Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
DOI 10.1007/s10516-013-9227-2
ORIGINAL PAPER
The Irrationality of Physicalism
Pat Lewtas
Received: 15 September 2013 / Accepted: 3 December 2013 / Published online: 15 December 2013
Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013
Abstract This paper argues, not that physicalism is wrong, but that it is irrational.
The paper defines standards of rationality, both metaphysical and epistemological,
that physicalism necessarily inherits from science. Then it assesses physicalist
efforts to naturalize consciousness in light of these. It concludes that physicalism
allows its metaphysics to outrun its epistemology, in defiance of applicable standards, revealing a fundamental incoherence in the doctrine. The paper also briefly
reviews other naturalization programs, to claim that physicalism, unlike the sciences, hasn’t proved fruitful.
Keywords Physicalism Rationality Epistemic norms Consciousness
Naturalization programs
Consider three important mind–body theories: physicalism, emergentism and
panpsychism. Physicalism holds that all concrete entities are either basic physical
entities or nothing over and above basic physical entities.1,2 This means that all
higher-level concrete entities, including conscious properties, (at least token) reduce
to basic physical entities at the bottom level. Every kind of physicalism cleaves, one
way or another, to this core claim.3 Emergentism holds that all higher-level concrete
objects and most higher-level concrete properties work this way. However, some
1
This paper uses ‘‘entity’’ as a label for an existent of any kind. Objects, properties, events, processes,
causes, etc. all count as entities.
2
A basic entity is a basic building block not composed of anything else. Non-basic entities are composed
of basic entities.
3
See Lewtas (forthcoming a) for more about the doctrine, including a more detailed formulation of it.
P. Lewtas (&)
Department of Philosophy, American University of Beirut, Beirut, Lebanon
e-mail:
[email protected]
123
314
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
higher-level concrete properties, such as conscious properties, don’t reduce to
bottom-level entities. Although complex, these higher-level properties nevertheless
count as basic entities. They emerge—they pop into existence out of nothing
(without being built of anything, much less anything pre-existing)—upon the
tokening of suitably structured non-basic physical entities.4 Panpsychism holds,
with physicalism, that all higher-level concrete entities (at least token) reduce to
basic bottom-level entities. And it denies, with emergentism, that conscious
properties reduce to anything non-conscious. It therefore claims that higher-level
conscious properties (at least token) reduce to basic conscious properties at the
bottom level. The most reasonable kind of panpsychism attributes these basic
conscious properties to basic physical objects.5
Focus for a moment on panpsychism. Panpsychism issues from a steadfastly
rationalist outlook, rooted in (at least) a moderately strong principle of sufficient
reason applied across the board. Panpsychism therefore spurns both metaphysical
and epistemological gaps. It insists that all higher-level entities reduce, and reduce
intelligibly, to bottom-level entities. It parts with emergentism because emergentism
allows higher-level entities that don’t reduce to bottom-level entities. And it parts
with physicalism because, as panpsychists see it, physicalism allows higher-level
entities that reduce, but not intelligibly, to bottom-level entities.6 Because
panpsychism holds metaphysics and epistemology to the same reductive standard,
it keeps metaphysical and epistemological explanations from drifting apart. In each
case a good explanation shows how higher-level entities are either composites, or
straightforward results, of basic bottom-level entities. (This paper uses the results
relation—results from, results in—as an umbrella catching the ways one concrete
entity can be nothing over and above other entities. The relation thus covers
relations like identity, composition, realization, etc. So, for example, the physicalist
says, but the emergentist denies, that consciousness results from basic physical
entities. And we might agree that a diachronic effect results from its cause when the
effect is nothing but a reorganization of the entities present beforehand.)
Emergentism, unlike panpsychism, doesn’t issue from a principle of sufficient
reason applied across the board. Emergentism tolerates emergent properties that,
while triggered by suitable physical entities, don’t result from anything, much less
their triggering bases. Although an emergent emerges lawfully, the relevant natural
law merely records the unbroken pattern between (the coming into existence of the)
emergent and (the tokening of the) triggering base. It remains a brute fact that a
token base occasions a token emergent. And it remains a brute coincidence that
4
For more on emergentism, as well as a critique of it, see Lewtas (2013a).
5
Thus we have ‘‘mind dust’’ panpsychism, the kind put forward by James (1890/1950) and Strawson
(2006), and debated by Nagel (1979) and Van Cleve (1990). See Lewtas (2013b) and Lewtas
(forthcoming b) for more about this view. Some panpsychists—Russellian panpsychists—go on to reduce
(so-called) basic physical entities to basic conscious properties (with the result that basic conscious
properties aren’t instantiated by basic physical entities, but rather supply their underlying categorical
grounds). See Lewtas (forthcoming c) for a critique of Russellian panpsychism.
6
Other philosophers share this assessment, including most non-physicalists and even some physicalists
(namely a posteriori physicalists, Chalmers’ Type-B materialists, but not, of course, a priori physicalists,
Chalmers’ Type-A physicalists; see Chalmers 2003).
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
315
every such base occasions, not only an emergent, but also the same kind of
emergent.7 Still, emergentism, like panpsychism, keeps its metaphysics and
epistemology in step. The emergentist naturally enough declines to explain
processes (such as property emergence) and patterns (such as the covariation
between emergent and triggering base) that happen without reason or cause.8 But
neither does he posit entities that result from other entities, pursuant to reasons and/
or causes, in ways he can’t explain. His metaphysic doesn’t outrun his
epistemology.
This paper argues that physicalist metaphysics does outrun physicalist epistemology, in a way that casts doubt on the rationality of physicalism as an explanatory
theory, and therefore also as a metaphysical and ontological theory. It argues, that
is, that physicalism is irrational in ways that panpsychism, and even emergentism,
aren’t. The paper focuses on the much-discussed case of consciousness. Physicalism
tells us that consciousness results from physical entities, yet can’t explain how. This
paper doesn’t claim that this makes physicalism wrong (although many of its
arguments inevitably tend that way). It maintains, rather, that it makes physicalism
irrational. The paper defends this claim by setting forth standards of rationality that,
it argues, physicalism must adhere to. Then it shows how physicalism fails to meet
them. Sometimes the paper makes general arguments. Sometimes it looks at specific
authors as exemplars of physicalist views, then argues, or in some cases suggests,
that the point at hand applies more widely. The paper therefore doesn’t prove its
case—whatever, in this context, that might mean. But it hopes to make its case
credible enough to give the physicalist pause.
1 Method and Overview
Philosophy has spawned huge literatures about rationality, each featuring a
cacophony of competing theories. Nowhere do we find consensus, whether about the
nature of rationality, the rationality of agents, the rationality of decisions, the
rationality of inferences, the rationality of beliefs, or the rationality of systems of
beliefs. This paper would therefore sink into quicksand if it asked, in the abstract,
what makes a theory or collective world-view rational and then applied the results to
physicalism. The paper therefore pursues a different and three-step approach. First,
it shows that the practises and findings of science generate norms of rationality that
apply to scientific theories and argumentation. Second, it shows that physicalism
necessarily inherits these norms given the particular relation it bears to science. And
third, it shows that physicalism inevitably and systematically violates these norms.
The paper thus contends that physicalism suffers from incoherence between itself,
as a theory, and standards of theory-rationality inseparable from it. The first two
7
See Lewtas (2013a) for further defence of this claim.
8
The physical base counts as a Human cause of the emergent, because it stands in an appropriate formal
relation to it [constant conjunction, counterfactual dependence, perfect correlation, condition necessary
and sufficient (or merely sufficient), etc.]. But it doesn’t count as a non-Human cause, where we
understand non-Human causation as requiring that the natures of the causally related entities result in the
causal relation between them. Put crudely, a non-Human cause actively brings its effect about.
123
316
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
steps of the argument unfold in Sects. 2 and 3. Sections 4 through 10 develop the
third step. Section 4 introduces the problem consciousness poses for physicalism.
Section 5 addresses those physicalists—a priori physicalists—who deny the reality
of the explanatory gap (between consciousness and the physical) even as an
epistemic matter. Section 6 deals with physicalists who acknowledge the epistemic
reality of the gap, but hold out hope that some scientific or conceptual breakthrough
will bridge it. Sections 7 through 9 speak to physicalists—the a posteriori
physicalists—who accept the gap as an epistemic reality here to stay, but
nonetheless deny it metaphysical import. Section 10 asks whether physicalism has
led to fruitful research programs. Finally, Sect. 11 ties the paper’s arguments
together.
2 Physicalism, Science and Rationality
Physicalism does metaphysics by proxy. It delegates the task of exploring the world
to the science departments down the hall. It passes the torch on metaphysics because
it passes the torch on epistemology. After comparing the successes of science to the
failures of other approaches (including, notably, a priori philosophy), physicalism
judges the scientific method the best way—maybe the only way—of learning about
the concrete world. Overall, physicalism accepts that science has been at it long
enough, and gotten good enough, that we can—and should—trust its findings, in
outline at least. We might say that physicalism consecrates science as philosophically basic and physics as scientifically basic.9
It follows that physicalism loses its moorings if it distances itself from the
methods and findings of science. Unless its concrete metaphysic adopts the scientific
image more or less as science gives it to us, physicalism becomes underspecified
and indeterminate, telling us little about the world. It has specific metaphysical
content, after all, only when it takes science to have gotten it largely right. And
insofar as physicalism makes metaphysical claims over and above these borrowings,
or relies on non-scientific methods in its own independent investigations of concrete
reality, it undercuts its warrant. For that warrant rests significantly on the success of
science.
Physicalism therefore, and necessarily, inherits much from science. We can
divide these into metaphysical and epistemological bequests. They act, for reasons
given below, as constraints on the practise of science, and therefore as standards of
rationality for science. They become standards of rationality for physicalism given
the intimate relation physicalism bears to science. It follows that physicalism
undermines itself insofar as it runs afoul of these standards.
The metaphysical bequests are fourfold.
(1) Metaphysical rationalism Physicalism adopts science’s necessary working
assumption that the world, at bottom, makes sense. Underneath the complexity and
apparent chaos lies order. Here the physicalist takes the world to obey, or at least to
9
Most any physicalist text supports these claims. See Armstrong (1999) and Heil (2003) for particularly
clear cases.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
317
cohere with, some (at least moderately) strong version of the principle of sufficient
reason (adjusted, perhaps, to make room for such things as quantum indeterminacy).
The scientist may, at the end of the day, have to stomach brute entities and/or
random or uncaused phenomena. But the more of these he tolerates, the less
adequate he will judge his model or theory of the world. Each brute posit will stand
out as a loose end—as a hint, maybe, of an underlying order his model or theory has
failed to probe, and therefore always (and however unfairly) as a reproach.10 The
scientific outlook, by its nature, thus drives scientists toward a ‘‘theory of
everything’’. In such a theory, non-basic entities sit at the ends of causal chains
beginning from, or atop compositional hierarchies resting on, basic entities rooted in
mathematical necessity.11 Physicalism commits itself to metaphysical rationalism
because, as we saw, physicalism necessarily takes the world as science conceives it
and gives it.
(2) Metaphysical reductivism Physicalism takes on board science’s reductive
outlook: the working hypothesis, or empirical inference, that all non-basic entities
are nothing over and above basic physical entities.12 Science presupposes, for
instance, that galaxies derive their properties from the basic entities that make them
up; it wouldn’t readily entertain the possibility that electrons derive their basic
properties from the galaxies that contain them. Everyday illustrations of metaphysical reductivism abound: scientists investigate complex systems by first tackling
their simpler parts (their simpler subsystems); and scientists move toward complex
theories about complex phenomena by first framing simpler theories explicitly
assuming away many of the complicating factors. Metaphysical reductivism gives
physicalism a bottom up rather than top down metaphysic.13 Note that metaphysical
reductivism is entailed by metaphysical rationalism. This too explains physicalism’s
commitment to it.
(3) Ontological naturalism Physicalism must limit its substantive ontology (at
least its concrete substantive ontology) to the entities acknowledged or required by
science. This limits it—as the paper will shortly argue—to (1) entities that causally
affect our senses, directly or indirectly, and (2) entities postulated in causal
explanation either of entities which affect our senses or of their effects on our
senses. Physicalism would lose all meaning if it tolerated non-natural concrete
entities.
10
Witness physicists’ unease with the brute empirical values in the Standard Model. They therefore hope
to uncover some rationale for these values. See Greene 2000.
11
Witness efforts by some string theorists to derive basic physical entities from logic and mathematics
alone (see Greene 2000).
12
Levine (2001), 81 considers this one of physicalism’s necessary core commitments. Science may one
day abandon reductivism, Levine allows. But then it will falsify today’s physicalism.
13
Some philosophers, of otherwise naturalistic bent, endorse monist views according to which all
concrete entities derive their ultimate reality, as well as their natures, from the whole, the cosmos, the
One, which these thinkers understand as a single all-encompassing entity (see, for example, Schaffer
2010). This paper doesn’t consider such philosophers physicalists. Although they look to science for the
detailed natures of the cosmos and its parts, they turn away from presuppositions deeply embedded in
science. To this extent, and despite appearances, they count as old-style metaphysicians rather than
contemporary physicalists.
123
318
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
(4) Non-basic mentality Physicalism draws the empirical inference that mentality
(including consciousness) is a non-basic feature of the world. It bases this on the
fact that physics has found no unambiguous evidence of basic or bottom-level
mentality (including consciousness)—imprecise and controversial talk about a role
for consciousness in the collapse of the quantum wave function aside. Science finds
clear evidence of mentality (including consciousness) only when special sciences
like biology and psychology study the structures and manifestations of complex
nervous systems.14
The epistemological bequests are more diverse. We can group these into primary
and secondary bequests. The primary bequests either express general scientific
norms or less basic principles that nevertheless play a big role in what follows.
There are four of these.
(1) Epistemological rationalism Physicalism must, like science, treat the study of
nature as a rational activity governed by publicly defensible norms dealing both
with collecting and assessing evidence and with deductive, inductive and abductive
inferences therefrom—the kinds of norms that underwrite collective, cumulative,
reproducible and empirically verifiable epistemic progress. The physicalist can’t
accept theories grounded, for example, in trance, revelation or mere authority,
unless he also justifies these theories in accordance with the usual scientific criteria.
For these other methods fall short of the relevant kind of rationality.15 This last
bequest isn’t unique to science and its heirs, of course. Science holds forth as but
one way of studying nature rationally.16 But science gives up everything if it
abandons its rationalist approach. And so, too, does physicalism, both as a
philosophy endorsing metaphysical and scientific realism and, more particularly, as
a philosophy piggybacking on science.
(2) Epistemic warrant Physicalism necessarily adopts scientific criteria for
assessing evidence and theories. Physicalism can’t very well defend its metaphysic
by enshrining the scientific method as the first and last word, and then hold theories,
including philosophical theories, to other, much less lower, epistemic standards.
(3) Epistemic trust Epistemological rationalism has a general consequence. We
must begin with appearances—the way the world seems—and take them at face
value unless we have specific, positive and persuasive reasons to believe them
misleading. Nothing else makes sense. If we dismissed appearances as such, then
the enterprise of knowing and understanding the world couldn’t get started. It
wouldn’t have anything to work with. And once begun, it couldn’t home in on a
14
This contingent empirical result becomes an essential feature of contemporary physicalism. If future
science discovered that electrons have consciousness, or that consciousness plays a basic role in the
collapse of the quantum wave function, then physicalism, today’s doctrine, would be falsified. See Levine
(2001), Stoljar (2001) and Wilson (2006) for physicalism’s necessary insistence on non-basic mentality.
15
The scientist can, of course, be promiscuous within the context of discovery so long as chaste within
the context of justification.
16
Thus Descartes and Leibniz, among many others, approached the world rationally through a priori
philosophy as well as science. See Chalmers (1996, 2012) for a generally non-empirical but nevertheless
rationalist engagement with the world.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
319
determinate theory. It wouldn’t have any way to mark off good theories from bad.17
This norm applies to any enterprise that accepts the existence of a mind-independent
world and explores it rationally.
(4) Metaphysical/epistemological parity Physicalism shouldn’t, because science
doesn’t and can’t, let its metaphysics run ahead of its epistemology. Science can’t
overreach because it extracts its metaphysics from, and ties it directly to, its
epistemology—as practised through the scientific method. Science dismisses
overreaching as unscientific, often using the epithet ‘‘mere metaphysics’’ for socalled scientific theories that lack (adequate) empirical warrant.18 And physicalism
can’t overreach because it takes its concrete metaphysics from an empirical
discipline. Note that metaphysical/epistemological parity follows from epistemic
warrant.
The following five secondary epistemological bequests express either particular
consequences of the primary bequests or else norms that play a smaller role in the
paper’s arguments.
(5) Parsimony Metaphysical/epistemological parity entails other norms. One such
prohibits theoretical posits that outrun data and evidence. Parsimony favors
hypotheses that posit the fewest (kinds of) entities lacking independent evidence
(that is, evidence beyond their explanatory force in the case at hand).19 Physicalists
often support their views about consciousness by applying parsimony to mind–body
correlations (see, for example, Smart 1959 and Hill 1991).
(6) Minimal warrant An even more particular consequence of metaphysical/
epistemological parity prohibits theoretical posits not backed by any evidence at all.
Einstein came to regret postulating the cosmological constant because, at the time
he proposed it, no evidence supported it.
(7) Global cognitive capacity Physicalism adopts the working assumption,
necessary to science, that we humans have what it takes to understand the world.
Science can back off locally—in the face of specific, positive and persuasive
reasons for a bounded incapacity (thus the ongoing study of our cognitive blind
spots and biases)—but can’t admit to global incapacity and either justify its
practises or put forth its findings as truth. It follows that physicalism can’t derive its
metaphysic from science and at the same time deny global cognitive capacity. Note
that global cognitive capacity follows, at least loosely, from epistemological
rationalism.
(8) Local cognitive capacity Although science can admit to local cognitive
incapacity, its commitment to global cognitive capacity obliges it to assume local
capacity in the absence of good reasons to the contrary. Such reasons must be
17
Paul (2012) argues that any metaphysics, and certainly naturalistic metaphysics (including especially
physicalism), must accept epistemic trust.
18
Thus Smolin (2007) dismisses string theory as metaphysics rather than science precisely because, in
his view, string theory outruns the evidence.
19
Different philosophers understand parsimony differently. This disagreement doesn’t matter here.
123
320
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
specific (they must only apply locally), positive (they must rest on empirical
evidence and should identify, not only local cognitive failures, but also the precise
mechanisms responsible for them), and persuasive (they must show that humans
can’t overcome or sidestep the relevant incapacities). Again, local cognitive
capacity follows from global cognitive capacity. And again, physicalism’s
commitment to global cognitive capacity in turn commits it to local cognitive
capacity.
(9) Fruitfulness Physicalism, like science, judges research programs by their
fruitfulness. Scientists abandon programs, however promising when launched, that
go nowhere. Fruitfulness follows, albeit loosely, from epistemological rationalism.
Science, of course, presupposes and adheres to other norms. Many of these
physicalism inherits too. But the thirteen listed above suffice for the arguments
made here.
3 The Nature of the Physical
We need to know more about both physicalism and science before we can fully
grasp the reach of the above bequests. Physicalism not only claims that high-level
entities are (at least token) identical to arrangements of basic physical entities. But
more, it must identify them with token basic physical entities as physics describes
them. Otherwise, as remarked before, physicalism undercuts its warrant and paints
too indeterminate a picture of the world. It follows that physicalism must understand
the physical in terms of physical theory, for nowhere else do we find the physical as
physics describes it.20
What, then, does physical theory say about the world? We note here what science
does, can do and must do. Science collects data through empirical means and then
systematizes, interprets and explains them. Data thus come to the scientist by way of
the senses. They do so directly, through the world’s causal effects on eyes, ears, etc.
And they do so indirectly, through the world’s causal effects on scientific
instruments, which in turn affect eyes, ears, etc. It follows that the scientist can
gather data only about dispositional properties—tendencies to affect the senses thusand-so under such-and-such conditions. The scientist then explains his data by
postulating properties, or objects with properties, that would cause his data. Hence
he hypothesizes new dispositions, or, at most, objects construed solely in terms of
new and old dispositions. He can do no other. Hypotheses framed in terms of nondispositional properties would lack causal explanatory power and hold aloof from
empirical test. They might have metaphysical warrant. But they would lack
empirical, and thus scientific, warrant.
Physics, like any science, therefore portrays the entities in its domain, which
include the concrete world’s basic building blocks, as systems or structures of
dispositions—dispositions arranged in space and time and related one to another.
20
Lewtas (forthcoming a) defends this understanding of physicalism against alternatives. It also
canvasses the problems it faces and the solutions to them.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
321
Thus physics understands the electron as a more or less durable cluster or bundle of
basic dispositions to do thus-and-so under such-and-such circumstances. Physics,
and the rest of the sciences, with their reductive outlook, then treat non-basic
entities as composites or aggregates of basic physical entities. This makes non-basic
entities complex systems/structures of interacting dispositions. It follows that all
concrete entities, at least as science reveals them, consist solely of structures of
interacting and spatio-temporally located dispositions. Science and physics
therefore say nothing about any non-dispositional qualities which fit into or fill
out physical structure. They say nothing about any qualities which underlie, hold
together or ground physical dispositions. They say nothing about the intrinsic
nature, if any, of physical substance—what physical substance is like in itself, apart
from its powers to interact with or relate to other things.21 As empirical disciplines
they can’t. This means that physicalism, whose substantive metaphysics has warrant
only when it marches in step with the substantive conclusions of science, also
endorses a purely dispositional, and hence purely causal/functional, world
picture.22,23
4 The Problem of Consciousness
Trouble arises when physicalism confronts consciousness. We’ve seen that physicalism must construe consciousness as a non-basic feature of the world that,
metaphysically, (at least token) reduces to basic physical entities (this follows from
non-basic mentality together with metaphysical reductivism). But a physical
understanding of consciousness proves elusive. This is the notorious explanatory
gap, the (at least apparent) fact that we can’t see, and can’t see that we ever could see,
how basic physical entities could result in consciousness.24 Materialists have wrestled
with this problem, on and off, at least since the Greek atomists offered their first crude
reductions. Contemporary physicalists have attended intensively to it, for over half a
century now, without much success—a judgement warranted by the profusion of
mutually incompatible physicalist accounts, each endorsed by only a small minority of
physicalists, and none of which has significant empirical evidence in its favor.25
This puts physicalists in an uncomfortable position. Imagine a scientist intent on
reducing some high-level entity A to certain lower-level B-entities. Try as he might,
he can’t get the B-entities to account for the properties of A. (The B entities do shed
21
Many physicalists have reached this conclusion. See Lewtas (forthcoming a) for references as well as
further argument along these lines.
22
Here we understand ‘‘causal/functional’’ as we did above, and thus more widely than in mind–body
functionalism.
23
Some physicalists recognize, within the physical, not only dispositional reality, but also whatever nondispositional entities, if any, ground dispositional reality (see Maxwell 1978). This paper has given
reasons not to classify such views as instances of physicalism. Lewtas (forthcoming a) gives other
reasons.
24
See Levine (1983, 1993, 2001) for background on the explanatory gap.
25
See Levine (2001) for an overview and harsh assessment of physicalist efforts tackling consciousness
and the explanatory gap.
123
322
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
some light. Our scientist discovers that the key properties of A take somewhat
different forms as the B-entities vary. But he sees no way of explaining those key A
properties—either their existence or overall nature—in terms of B.) Surely our
scientist would abandon his quest, concluding that the A-entity stands over and
above the B-entities. His fellow scientists wouldn’t take him seriously if he didn’t.
His field would move on.
The physicalist has three choices here. He can deny the gap, claiming that we can
indeed see the the right kind of links between physical and conscious entities. He
can hold out hope that tomorrow’s better science or some conceptual breakthrough
will close the gap. Or he can accept the gap as a sorry fact of life, but of
epistemological and not metaphysical import. In this case, and in lieu of explaining
consciousness, the physicalist typically explains away his inability to explain
consciousness. He traces the gap to some source other than the non-physical nature
of consciousness. This paper looks at all three approaches.
5 Denying the Gap
Physicalists who deny the gap deny that consciousness poses an explanandum over
and above the causal/functional (understood broadly, as above).26 They thus
understand consciousness as a collection of causal activities/dispositions or causally
specified roles detectable, in principle, from the third-person perspective. They
therefore deny that consciousness has a non-causal/functional qualitative nature
uniquely accessible from the first-person perspective.27
Consider Pereboom (2011), for instance. Pereboom suggests that experience is
straightforwardly physical. However, its mode of presentation, the way it presents to
us, makes experience appear to have properties it in fact lacks. And here Pereboom
has in mind the very ‘‘phenomenal properties’’ that, when we compare them to
physical properties, give rise to the explanatory gap. Pereboom admits that the
following two claims seem intuitive to many:
(i) Both the physical and introspective modes of presentation represent a
phenomenal property as having a specific qualitative nature, and the
qualitative nature that the introspective mode of presentation represents the
phenomenal property as having is not included in the qualitative nature the
physical mode of presentation represents it as having. (13)
(ii) The introspective mode of presentation accurately represents the
qualitative nature of the phenomenal property. That is, the introspective
mode of presentation represents the phenomenal property as having a specific
qualitative nature, and the attribution of this nature to the phenomenal
property is correct. (13)
Pereboom accepts the truth of (i), but suggests, given what we know and can
rationally believe, that (ii) could turn out false. In other words, it remains
26
These are a priori physicalists, Chalmers’ Type-A materialists (see Chalmers 2003).
27
See Lycan (1996) and Tye (1995) for general support of such claims.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
323
an open possibility that introspective representation is inaccurate in the respect
that it represents phenomenal properties as having qualitative natures they do
not in fact have…. For example, upon seeing the red tomato, Mary [of
Jackson’s knowledge argument] introspectively represents the qualitative
nature of phenomenal redness in the what-it-is-like-to-sense-red way, and it is
an open possibility that her representing it in this way attributes to it a
qualitative nature that it actually lacks. (14)28
In this case, we can dismiss the explanatory gap as an illusion.
When Mary is in the room, she does not represent phenomenal states in the
characteristic introspective way, and she does not appear to have the
information required to represent the complete real natures of these
phenomenal states by deriving them from what she knows. But it is a serious
open possibility that by virtue of her physical knowledge she can nevertheless
accurately represent the complete real natures of these states. Phenomenal
properties of these states, in particular, might not have the qualitative natures
they are introspectively represented as having. Instead, the natures of these
properties might accurately be represented by way of Mary’s physical
knowledge. If this possibility is actual, then from her physical knowledge, she
can derive every truth about the real natures of phenomenal states. (24)
Pereboom confronts an obvious objection.
One may now ask whether the problem for a physicalist explanation of
consciousness has merely been shifted from accounting for phenomenal states
and their properties to accounting for their introspective phenomenal modes of
presentation. (26)
But he believes he has an answer.
In response, there is no less reason to think that the qualitative inaccuracy
hypothesis holds for introspective representations of phenomenal modes of
presentation than it does for introspective representations of first-order
phenomenal states…. The same point might be made for any further iteration
of introspective representations of introspective phenomenal modes of
presentation. (26)
Pereboom denies that this ‘‘engenders an unwelcome infinite regress’’ (26).
First of all, a mode of presentation can function as a way a subject represents
an introspective representation without that subject also representing the mode
of presentation itself. [Mary] might, in addition, represent this mode of
presentation, but this would be a distinct representation that is not
necessitated. If she did represent the mode of presentation, it could be by
28
Pereboom doesn’t insist that his qualitative inaccuracy hypothesis mirrors the truth of things. He
claims, more modestly, that it remains an open and rational epistemic possibility. He therefore puts it
forth, not as part of a mind–body theory, but as a device to blunt the force of anti-physicalist arguments,
like the knowledge and conceivability arguments, which rest, at the end of the day, on the explanatory
gap. This paper bypasses this subtlety.
123
324
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
way of a higher order introspective mode of presentation. However, it would
again not be necessitated that she also represents this higher order mode of
presentation. Furthermore, it’s plausible that when someone introspectively
represents a sensation of red by way of [an introspective mode of
presentation], she will normally, although not necessarily, also represent [that
introspective mode of presentation] by a higher order mode of presentation,
but only in unusual cases would she introspectively represent that higher order
mode of presentation. (26–27)
What’s going on here? At first it looks like Pereboom does shift the
explanandum—experience as experienced—from the phenomenal property itself
to our mode of presentation of it. In other words, it seems that he introduces a new
entity, the phenomenal property as it truly exists apart from our experience of it,
relabels the original experience an introspective mode of presentation, and then
explains the newly introduced and non-experiential entity rather than experience
itself (now relabelled an introspective mode of presentation). In this case Pereboom
would have changed the subject from the explanandum we care about to something
else, something that, at best, bears some relation to the explanandum we care about.
But Pereboom explicitly denies doing this. As he makes clear in the second last
passage, he doesn’t in fact shift experience out of the phenomenal property and into
an introspective mode of presentation of it. He doesn’t do this because he also shifts
experience out of the introspective mode of presentation and into a higher-order
introspective mode of presentation of that. This shifting iterates, he tells us in the
last passage, until we get to an introspective mode of presentation not itself
introspectively represented. This leaves us to wonder about the source of the
qualitative illusions that fill out experience as experienced and give rise to the
explanatory gap. If the chain of interations stops at an introspective mode of
presentation that we do experience, then, indeed, Pereboom has merely shifted the
explanandum in the way he denies. And in this case he has merely relabelled mental
entities without offering an explanation of experience as experienced. On the other
hand, if the chain of iterations ends with a mode of presentation that we don’t
experience, an unconscious mode of presentation if you will, then Pereboom
identifies an illusion we do experience with a mental state we don’t experience. And
this move, if we take the identification to heart, does away with the illusion we
experience, and with it experience as experienced. Pereboom seems to embrace this
result: he admits that his hypothesis ‘‘is eliminativist about primitive phenomenal
properties and those that are accurately introspectively represented, but not about
phenomenal properties themselves’’ (26). So, in the end, Pereboom explains
experience by getting rid of it.
How do Pereboom’s suggestions fare in light of the standards of rationality
sketched in Sect. 2? By eliminating experience as experienced, Pereboom denies
manifest data. But it never makes sense to deny data. One can deny interpretations
or explanations of data, and thereby, in very limited measure, explain away certain
aspects of them. But one can’t deny data altogether. Data themselves one starts with.
Nobody who seeks a rational understanding of the world can winnow out the data he
likes from the data that lead where he doesn’t want to go. Certainly no scientist can
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
325
turn his back on consistent, insistent and reproducible data, yet hope to model the
world truly. Pereboom therefore violates both epistemological rationalism (which
enjoins the physicalist to employ scientifically acceptable methods of enquiry) and
epistemic trust (which enjoins the physicalist to start with appearances and to take
them seriously unless he has good reasons not to).
Does Pereboom have good reasons to doubt the appearances? First and foremost,
does he have empirical reasons—that is, scientifically respectable and hence
physicalistically acceptable reasons? Pereboom concedes that he doesn’t, that
‘‘awareness of a discrepancy between the real nature of a phenomenal property and
the qualitative nature we introspectively represent it as having seldom, if ever,
arise[s]…’’ (23). He nevertheless tentatively presents two possible examples.29 The
first concerns a fraternity hazing, where a blindfolded student, told that a razor will
be drawn across his throat, instead has an icicle drawn across his throat. The student
briefly feels pain in place of cold. Pereboom suggests that the student ‘‘at first
misrepresents the qualitative features of the sensation of cold he actually has as
qualitative features of pain…’’ (22). The second example involves Pereboom’s
daughter, told by her dentist, right before he injects her with Novocain, that he will
sprinkle drops of cold water on her gum. Later she tells her dad that she didn’t much
like the drops of water but that they didn’t hurt. Pereboom proposes that ‘‘the
dentist’s suggestion…kept [his daughter] from introspectively representing the
qualitative features of the pain state she was actually in as qualitative features of
pain…’’ (23). In each case Pereboom acknowledges that he offers ‘‘a controversial
analysis but not an implausible one’’ (22). A critic might maintain that the frat
student in fact does experience pain, however briefly, and that Pereboom’s daughter
in fact never experiences pain, at all. But more to the point, Pereboom’s examples,
even interpreted his way, give no support to his hypothesis. Pereboom needs
examples where a subject experiences a phenomenal property without the
experience having any of the qualitative features we tend introspectively to
represent phenomenal properties as having. But Pereboom offers no such examples.
His examples instead feature subjects who experience one kind of ‘‘illusory’’
introspective mode of presentation in place of another. It seems, then, that
Pereboom adduces no empirical or scientific evidence in favor of his hypothesis.
What else motivates it? Pereboom frankly acknowledges advancing his
hypothesis to reconcile physicalism with the intuitive force of the knowledge and
conceivability arguments.30 In other words, the only real ‘‘evidence’’ for his
hypothesis is its capacity to save a theory. Here one thinks of Einstein’s reasons for
postulating a cosmological constant (to save the steady state theory of the universe
in face of his own predictions of an expanding universe) and Lorentz’s and
Fitzgerald’s reasons for postulating their transformation equations (to save the
aether theory of light in face of the null results of the Michaelson-Morley
experiment). In neither case did any empirical evidence directly support the
29
See 22–23.
30
See 3, 7 and 8. Thus ‘‘[m]y intention isn’t to work out the details of a positive argument for
physicalism but rather to assess the prospects for physicalism in the face of the strongest challenges to
it…’’ (7).
123
326
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
hypothesis (in fact, Lorentz’s and Fitzgerald’s equations went so far as to explain
away the lack of empirical support). We can therefore say that Pereboom’s
hypothesis violates parsimony (which enjoins the physicalist to avoid posits that
outrun data and evidence) and minimal warrant (which enjoins the physicalist to
avoid posits not backed by any evidence whatsoever). Since metaphysical/
epistemological parity (which enjoins the physicalist to keep his metaphysics in
step with his epistemology) entails parsimony and minimal warrant, Pereboom
violates metaphysical/epistemological parity too. And since epistemic warrant
(which enjoins the physicalist to assess all theories by scientific criteria) entails
metaphysical/epistemological parity, Pereboom also violates epistemic warrant.
Pereboom bases his hypothesis on the possibility that we systematically fail to
interpret our experiences as they really are. He thus proposes a local cognitive
incapacity. However, local cognitive capacity enjoins the physicalist to reject such
proposals barring good reasons to the contrary. Such reasons must be specific (they
must only apply locally), positive (they must rest on empirical evidence and should
identify, not only local cognitive failures, but also the precise mechanisms
responsible for them), and persuasive (they must show that humans can’t overcome
or sidestep the relevant incapacities). Pereboom offers no reasons to think his
hypothesis satisfies these conditions. His hypothesis therefore violates local
cognitive capacity.
Does the above critique generalize to others who deny the explanatory gap? It
certainly applies to those, like Pereboom, who write off the first-person perspective
as an illusion (see Rey 1983, for example). But other philosophers deny the gap in
different ways. Some purport to explain away the first-person perspective by
physically explaining other things, perhaps third-person reports of so-called firstperson states (Dennett 1991), perhaps alleged hidden physical properties of
phenomenal states (Armstrong 1999). Others dismiss the first-person perspective for
its place in an outmoded folk psychology (Churchland 1996). Consider first those
who would explain away the first-person perspective by physically explaining
something else. Armstrong (1999), for instance, claims that experience has hidden
depths inaccessible to experience. We would know experience as physical if only
we could access these depths.
I would…advance the idea…that everything in the world, everything, every
event, every property of things and events, every relation that things and
events have to each other, are each one of them an epistemological iceberg.
Our knowledge and rational belief about all these things, though real, is
selective and limited. If you take this view then it becomes much easier to
accept that the secondary qualities might have hidden depths to which we
cannot penetrate in perception. (129–130).31
This makes sense only if experience includes more than we experience. But it
doesn’t, of course. The thing we wish to understand is experience itself—the
31
Armstrong counts as a higher-order perception theorist: he believes consciousness results from a
perception-like awareness of other mental states. So ‘‘perception’’, at the end of the passage, effectively
means experience.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
327
property of experience as experienced. If, at the outset, we define experience as
experienced to include the unexperienced, then we change the subject, from
experience as experienced to an amalgam of experience and something else.32 We
thereby risk explaining the unexperienced something else instead of experience
itself. And Armstrong does exactly that: later in his (1999) he identifies experience
with the hidden physical nature of experience, and elsewhere he identifies
experience with physical properties/states which occupy a given functional role
(see his 1993). Experience as experienced drops from the picture. Dennett (1991)
makes similar moves. He changes the subject from experience itself to third-person
reports of first-person states, then physically explains those reports. This might
undermine the third-person warrant for the first-person perspective. But it leaves
untouched the first-person warrant, the phenomenon we set out to explain in the first
place. Besides, explaining third-person reports would explain first-person states only
if the third-person reports themselves explained first-person states. But if they did,
we wouldn’t need, in this context, explanations of those third-person reports. We
would already have at hand an explanation of experience.
Armstrong and Dennett change the subject and explain something other than they
claim to explain. They thereby lose sight of the explanandum of interest and ignore
the first-person data for it. They don’t deny that data outright, as Pereboom does.
But ignoring data comes to the same thing as denying data. Either way the theorist
builds his model in defiance of the evidence. It follows that philosophers who
change the subject violate both epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the
physicalist to employ scientifically acceptable methods of enquiry) and epistemic
trust (which enjoins the physicalist to start with appearances and to take them
seriously unless he has good reasons not to).
What about those, like Churchland, who who dismiss the first-person perspective
as a posit of a defunct folk psychology? These thinkers treat consciousness as a
theoretical object in an explanatory theory: as a hypothesis or explanans explaining
something else. But, in this context at least, the first-person perspective—
consciousness—doesn’t enter the scene as a theoretical posit in explanation of
something else. It stands as a basic datum, a ground-level appearance, something
each of us encounters through being what we are. It therefore counts as an
explanandum in its own right. Now, mistaking explanandum for explanans, in this
context, serves as an excuse to sidestep the first-person evidence for experience.
Why? Theoretical posits never have direct evidence in their favor. They sit too far
from our sensory interface with the world. We endorse them, or not, depending how
well they explain the phenomena we introduced them to account for. (When we do
acquire direct evidence for a theoretical posit, it thereby loses its status as a
theoretical object.) So labelling experience a theoretical posit deftly classes it with
entities for which we can’t have direct evidence. Philosophers like Churchland thus
commit two sins. They confuse explanandum for explanans. And, partly because of
that, they turn their backs on basic data. These thinkers therefore violate
32
If we define experience as experienced to include the unexperienced, then we also tumble into
incoherence, thereby violating epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the physicalist, at the very
least, to forswear outright contradiction).
123
328
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the physicalist to employ scientifically
acceptable methods of enquiry) and epistemic trust (which enjoins the physicalist to
start with appearances and to take them seriously unless he has good reason not to).
In sum, this paper provisionally concludes—what seems intuitively plausible in
any case—that anyone who denies the explanatory gap must thereby, and without
sufficient reason, deny consistent, insistent, reproducible, bedrock data and also a
legitimate concrete explanandum. And this means violating key norms of scientific
and physicalistic rationality.
6 Hoping to Close the Gap
Physicalists from our second group look to a scientific or conceptual breakthrough
to lay bare the links between physical and conscious entities (see Churchland 1988
and, oddly enough, Nagel 1974). But these thinkers lose sight of the fact that the
explanatory gap points, not just to our inability today to see such links, but also to
our inability to see even the possibility of such links. What grounds this (at least
apparent) impossibility? Two facts. (1) Our phenomenal concepts differ from, and
apparently refer to different kinds of entities than, the causal/functional concepts
that fill out our physicalistic picture of the world. They do this because
consciousness presents as having a qualitative nature beyond the causal/functional.
Braddon-Mitchell & Jackson (2007) describes this presentational fact:
Intuitively, phenomenal nature is intrinsic. The perceived redness of a sunset
is a feature of how the experience is here and now; you cannot capture its
nature by talking of its similarities and differences, and of what causes it, and
of what it causes. It is as intrinsic as squareness. But then perceived redness in
particular, and color experience in general, cannot be captured in functional
terms, in terms of causal relations. (131)
(2) Our scientific concepts can’t reach beyond the causal/functional because they
necessarily refer to causally effective entities construed merely as such. This
follows from the Sect. 3 arguments about what science does, can do and must do.
What possible conceptual or scientific breakthroughs does this leave? Not (1) that
consciousness, appearances to the contrary, lacks qualitative nature. As argued in
Sect. 5, neither science nor philosophy can reinterpret the appearance of qualitative
experience as anything other than qualitative experience without thereby denying,
outright, the data given in experience. And no rational enquiry can deny bedrock
data. And not (2) that the physical, as science reveals it, includes non-causal/
functional qualitative aspects. First, even if such aspects exist as a matter of
metaphysical fact, science will never access them, because, for reasons canvassed in
Sect. 3, science can only detect, study and postulate causal/functional entities.
Second, if future science nevertheless somehow does discover or postulate noncausal/functional qualitative entities, it would thereby falsify today’s physicalism.
Today’s physicalism limits its metaphysic to the kinds of entities discoverable by
the empirical scientific method. And this method can only detect, study, postulate
and acknowledge causes and effects understood as such. Science will therefore take
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
329
us beyond the causal/functional only if it shelves the scientific method for, or
supplements it with, some other method of enquiry (trance, intuition, revelation,
consensus?). But if it does that, it will leave today’s physicalism behind. Third, the
kinds of revolutionary posits that might underwrite conceptual links between
consciousness and the physical seem likely to run afoul of non-basic mentality.
Think of posits like conscious electrons, conscious categorical grounds underlying
physical dispositions, or a basic role for consciousness in the collapse of the
quantum wave function. Any of these might close the explanatory gap. But at the
cost of disproving physicalism.
In sum, hopes for a scientific or conceptual breakthrough come down to one of
three things. (1) Denying the data tomorrow rather than denying them today, even
though we can’t ever deny data. This violates epistemic warrant (which enjoins
the physicalist to hold metaphysical doctrines to the same standards to which
scientists hold scientific theories) and epistemic trust (which enjoins the
physicalist to start with appearances and to take them seriously barring good
reasons to the contrary). (2) Putting faith in the impossible—in the shape of an
identity (token or otherwise) between, on the one hand, something essentially
non-causal/functional (because given to us, as data, in a form at least apparently
over and above the causal/functional) and, on the other hand, something
essentially causal/functional (because construed solely in terms of causal
relations). This violates epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the physicalist
to explore nature using publicly defensible standards of rational enquiry) and
epistemic trust. (3) Trusting to an unlikely and perhaps impossible scientific
revolution that would falsify physicalism even if it happened. This violates
epistemological rationalism and, in all probability, non-basic mentality (which
would straightforwardly falsify physicalism).
On top of this, there is something fishy about begging off debate about one’s pet
metaphysic in hopes of salvation tomorrow. ‘‘My theory faces problems; I can’t
answer them; the criticisms seem ironclad; but I needn’t worry because someday
someone will find the knockdown reply I don’t have now.’’ This dodge works for a
while, but wears thin as the wait grows long. Physicalists have reissued their
promissory note time and again for over half a century, during which scientific
knowledge has doubled roughly every 15 years. Unless the physicalist gives reasons
to expect a breakthrough—specific, positive and persuasive reasons more finegrained than the general march of science—then his trust in the future amounts to a
refusal to engage in rational enquiry today. And this, of course, violates
epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the scientist and physicalist to engage
in rational enquiry and nothing but).33
33
This isn’t merely the counsel of impatience. It doesn’t mean, for instance, that we should give up
trying to cure cancer because we’ve fallen short for well-nigh 60 years. We don’t have a cure, but we
readily see the shape a cure might take. Physicalists have wrestled with consciousness for just as long yet
haven’t made intelligible even the possibility of a physicalistic explanation.
123
330
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
7 Explaining Away the Gap using Metaphysics
Physicalists of the third kind accept the explanatory gap as a principled epistemic
barrier but deny it metaphysical significance.34 Consciousness is nothing over and
above the physical even though we don’t, and won’t ever, see how. These
physicalists explain away the gap by explaining our inability to see illuminating
links between physical and conscious entities. They thereby trace the source of our
handicap to something other than the non-physical nature of consciousness. This
strategy can’t prove that consciousness is physical, of course. But, if successful, it
could blunt any motivation to think otherwise. Thus Levine (2001), whom this paper
soon examines more closely, thinks the explanatory gap ‘‘is a very deep problem’’
(92), and impossible to bridge given our current and even future conceptual tools
(94), with the consequence that there is ‘‘an important sense in which we can’t
understand how [physicalism] could be true’’ (68). And yet he ‘‘stop[s] short of
endorsing the metaphysical anti-materialist conclusion’’ (39).
The physicalist has two options here. He can make the metaphysical claim that
ontological links hold between consciousness and the physical even though
intelligible links don’t. We don’t see illuminating links because, as a brute matter of
metaphysical fact, none exists.35 On the other hand, the physicalist can make an
epistemological claim. The ontological links between consciousness and the
physical shed just as much explanatory light, in principle, as the ontological links
between, say, water and H2O. However, something about us—some cognitive
failing, perhaps—blinds us to it.36 We look at Levine (2001) because he pursues
both approaches.
Consider the metaphysical claim first. Here the physicalist postulates brute
identities or brute (or strong37) metaphysical necessities. These come down to the
same thing, seen as identities when viewed metaphysically and seen as necessities
when viewed modally. If A and B stand in a relationship of brute identity, then A
equals B, but nothing—nothing metaphysically real—grounds an epistemically
intelligible connection between them. Thus the non-identity of A and B won’t seem
impossible no matter how much we know about A and B. By the same token, if A
and B instance a brute metaphysical necessity, then their non-identity remains
logically possible, and therefore a priori conceivable, but is nonetheless not
metaphysically possible. Here the metaphysical impossibility runs deeper than the
weak metaphysical impossibility defended by Kripke. Where Kripke merely
34
These are Chalmers’ Type-B materialists, much the majority (see Chalmers 2003). See, for example,
Hill (1991), Loar (1997) and Levine (2001).
35
Few physicalists embrace this strategy in print, although Chalmers (1996, 2010) claims that many
favour it in personal communication and many more are committed to it. We’ll see that Levine (2001)
toys with it without definitively endorsing or rejecting it.
36
Many physicalists adopt this approach. See, for example, McGinn (1989) and Papineau (2007).
37
Different philosophers use different terms. Chalmers (1996, 2003, 2010) speaks of strong metaphysical
necessities. Levine (2001) talks about brute metaphysical necessities (partly because he distinguishes
strong metaphysical necessities, which he deems barely acceptable, from brute metaphysical necessities,
which, in most passages, he deems unacceptable). See ahead for citations.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
331
constrains the way we can describe a possible world, brute metaphysical necessities
constrain the space of possible worlds.
Levine (2001) offers the following characterization of brute identities/necessities
and highlights some of their shortcomings.
[I]f we judge a situation metaphysically necessary, then we must have
available a representation of that situation relative to which it is conceptually
necessary. Another way to put the point is this: I deny the existence of ‘‘brute
necessities,’’ metaphysical necessities that transcend logic (where semantic
constraints on concepts are understood to be part of logic in the relevant
sense). If, for some alleged metaphysically necessary situation, there were no
description of it relative to which it was conceptually necessary—no
description of it (not just none that we can think of, but none at all) that
manifested either formal validity or semantic/conceptual necessity—it would
be hard to understand what could ground the metaphysical necessity. At the
very least, I don’t see how we could be in a position to judge that the situation
in question was metaphysically necessary. (41–42).
The…alternative [the postulation of brute identities/necessities]…just smacks
of metaphysical extravagance. It’s certainly not the case that we need appeal
to this sort of brute necessity in order to make sense of any of our other modal
claims, such as that water necessarily contains hydrogen. Furthermore, I don’t
see how we could ever be in a position to actually embrace any particular
realization thesis [such as one claiming that a given conscious property is
identical to, or is realized by, a given physical property] unless we had the
requisite realization theory [such as one showing how the physical property is
identical to, or realizes, the conscious property]…. (45)
Let’s work through the problems Levine notes. First, he questions our epistemic
right to embrace any mind–body identity/necessity in the absence of a relevant
realization theory. But if we had a realization theory, then we would understand why
the identity/necessity holds, in which case it couldn’t be brute. Levine here gets at
the utter lack of evidence for brute identities/necessities. Chalmers (2003) sharpens
the point by observing that no possible evidence could support them. We can’t know
them a priori because, by hypothesis, they constrain the space of worlds
independently of logical and hence conceptual possibility/impossibility. And we
can’t know them a posteriori because we have a posteriori access only to the actual
world, not the space of possible worlds. It seems, then, that brute identities/
necessities violate minimal warrant (which enjoins the physicalist not to postulate
entities unsupported by evidence), parsimony (which enjoins the physicalist not to
postulate entities that outrun the evidence) and epistemic warrant (which enjoins the
physicalist to hold his own theoretical posits to the same standards scientists hold
theirs).
Second, Levine condemns brute identities/necessities as metaphysically extravagant, reminding us that we don’t need them to explain any other identities (such as
the identity of water and H2O). Here, perhaps, Levine implies that postulating such
identities/necessities violates parsimony (which enjoins the physicalist not to
123
332
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
postulate entities that outrun the evidence). Perhaps he also worries that the
restrictions on possible worlds imposed by brute identities/necessities seem
mysteriously non-natural, and hence not the kinds of entities a physicalist ontology
can readily accommodate (and thus violations of ontological naturalism). After all,
what concrete physical entities could ground such modal properties? How could
such modal properties figure in, or be required by, concrete causal relations—which
relations, Sect. 3 argued, exhaust the nature of the physical world as given by
science and as taken up by physicalism?
Third, Levine wonders what could ground brute identities/necessities. We can
strengthen this concern by noting that brute identities/necessities seem not only
mysterious, but also incoherent. How can property A (a conscious property) and
property B (a physical property) stand in a relationship of identity where nothing
about A and nothing about B make this intelligible—and yet where, by hypothesis,
the unintelligibility results from the metaphysics and not merely from epistemology? If A and B really are the same thing—if we have just one thing rather than two
things somehow related—then we have a single thing with a single set of properties.
Now, if the apparent bruteness doesn’t result from epistemological factors, then we
don’t cognize the single property A/B as property A through one subset of its
properties and as property B through another subset of its properties. Nor do we
cognize A/B as A through a subset of its properties plus a set S1 of properties it
doesn’t in fact have, and as B through another (possibly identical) subset of its
properties plus a different set S2 of properties it doesn’t in fact have. We instead
cognize A/B as A and as B through cognizing the very same properties. More, we
cognize A and B in the very same way, since the bruteness, again by hypothesis,
doesn’t spring from epistemological factors. But then how can the identity/necessity
be brute—and therefore unintelligible in principle? How can it fail to be
straightforwardly intelligible? Here we have violations of metaphysical rationalism
(which enjoins the physicalist to postulate entities that make sense) and
epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the physicalist to employ rational
methods of enquiry, and which therefore proscribes incoherent posits).
Brute identities/necessities have other shortcomings, ones Levine doesn’t
mention. First, for the identity/necessity to seem contingent, the ‘‘two relata’’ must
appear not to share all their properties. But we must take this appearance at face
value barring good reasons—specific, positive and persuasive reasons—for judging
it misleading. But we noted above that no direct evidence supports brute identities/
necessities. This rules out good reasons for dismissing the appearance that the ‘‘two
relata’’ differ. Thus we have violations of epistemic trust (which enjoins the
physicalist to take appearances seriously) and hence also epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the physicalist to employ scientifically acceptable methods and
standards of enquiry).
Second, brute identities/necessities hold only at high levels of organizational
complexity—almost surely at the level(s) of the conscious properties and the
complex physical entities (at least token) identical to them. After all, if the brute
identity/necessity resulted from bottom-level entities and/or bottom-level identities/
necessities, then we could, in principle, understand it in terms of them. And in this
case the higher-level identity/necessity wouldn’t, and in principle couldn’t, seem
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
333
contingent. But this means the identity/necessity can’t (at least token) reduce to
basic physical entities. And this violates metaphysical reductivism (which commits
the physicalist to a bottom-up metaphysic) as well as, perhaps, ontological
naturalism (because an entity that doesn’t reduce to basic physical entities has
dubious claims to being natural).
Third, brute identities/necessities, postulated in ad hoc defence of a theory
but otherwise lacking direct evidence in their favor, stand on a par with
Einstein’s cosmological constant and the physical processes proposed by
Lorentz and Fitzgerald. More, and much like the Lorentz and Fitzgerald
equations, brute identities/necessities outrun not only the evidence, but also all
possible evidence, since they explain, and thus explain away, their empirical
and conceptual invisibility. It follows that brute identities/necessities violate
minimal warrant (which enjoins the physicalist to postulate only entities
supported by evidence), parsimony (which enjoins the physicalist not to
postulate entities which outrun the evidence) and hence metaphysical/
epistemological parity (which enjoins the physicalist not to let his metaphysics
outstrip his epistemology).
For all this, Levine seems, at the end of the day, to endorse brute identities/
necessities. Not because he wants to, or likes them, but because his physicalism
leaves him no choice. Levine says the following after making his case for the reality
and intractability of the explanatory gap.
First, to avoid commitment to brute metaphysical necessity, I argued that for a
situation to be metaphysically impossible, it must be that there is a
representation of it relative to which the situation is also conceptually
impossible. Second, in order to meet this requirement we would need a
realization theory that in the end is based on some identification of the target
property so that a redescription of it enables the relevant conceptual necessity
to be expressed. (90)
But this is exactly what an unbridgeable explanatory gap rules out. It follows that
Levine can’t avoid commitment to brute identities/necessities.38 He thus makes all
the irrational moves he warns against. And so does any physicalist who discounts
the explanatory gap for these kinds of metaphysical reasons. This matters, because
brute identities/necessities stand as the only obvious metaphysical way to defuse the
gap while acknowledging its epistemic reality.
38
The case is a little more nuanced than these arguments suggest. Levine distinguishes between (to use
his jargon) brute metaphysical necessities and strong metaphysical necessities (55, 59). Then he argues
that strong metaphysical necessities, while carrying heavy theoretical costs, don’t offend the canons of
good philosophy as badly as do brute metaphysical necessities (58–60). Finally, he denies that his kind of
physicalism need subscribe to strong metaphysical necessities anyway (55). For two reasons this paper
doesn’t accept Levine’s pleas of innocence. First, it finds his distinction between strong and brute
metaphysical necessities elusive. Second, it judges that Levine commits himself to brute identities/
necessities notwithstanding his words to the contrary. Here the paper would repeat the argument made in
the text, this time taking into account technicalities in Levine’s presentation glossed over above.
123
334
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
8 Explaining Away the Gap using Epistemology I
Physicalists who accept the gap as here to stay also explain it away epistemologically. They claim that the ontological links between consciousness and the physical
do shed explanatory light, at least in principle. But some cognitive handicap on our
part blinds us to it. These physicalists trace the gap to some form our concepts can’t
help but take, or to some cognitive faculty responsible for that form. They thereby
deny local cognitive capacity. This paper looks at several versions of the strategy.39
Perhaps most widely followed is the phenomenal concept strategy, also known as
concept or conceptual dualism.40 This holds that our concepts cut the world more
finely than the properties that fill it out. Thus two disparate concepts, with no a
priori connection between them, can home in on the same referent.
Most concept dualists claim that, although our phenomenal concepts do refer to
physical entities, they have special features that hide their referents’ physical
natures from us. It makes sense for the concept dualist to say this. He can’t very well
allow that our physical concepts fail to represent their referents’ natures completely
and accurately (subject to gaps or mistakes at the edges, of course). For then he
undercuts his warrant for physicalism—which, we have seen, rests significantly on
the claim that empirical science yields a complete and accurate account of the world
(subject, again, to gaps or mistakes at the edges). Concept dualism therefore
pressures the physicalist to blame phenomenal concepts for the explanatory gap.
Concept dualists commonly understand our physical concepts as involving
‘‘thick’’ or descriptive modes of presentation. Thus the concept of an electron
attributes the properties physics tells us electrons have. As Levine (2001) puts it,
‘‘[most] materialists are willing to grant a cognitively substantive, or ‘‘thick’’ mode
of presentation for concepts/terms like ‘‘water’’ – an ascriptive mode that describes
water’s causal role…’’ (83).41 And concept dualists commonly understand our
phenomenal concepts as involving ‘‘thin’’ or merely demonstrative modes of
presentation. The concept of an experience thus has no more cognitive content than,
for example, ‘‘that thing over there’’ or ‘‘things like that’’ taken independently of the
entities ostended.
[According to most physicalists] qualitative concepts are essentially ‘‘blind’’
demonstratives. They are pointers we aim at our internal states with very little
substantive conception of what sort of thing we’re pointing at – demonstrative
arrows shot blindly that refer to whatever they hit. (Levine 2001, 84)
Our phenomenal concepts therefore reveal nothing (or at least very little) about the
natures their referents have. This explains why brain state 77 seems only
contingently related to pain. Our concept ‘‘brain state 77’’ spells out a determinate
nature whereas our concept ‘‘pain’’ leaves its referent’s nature wholly up in the air.
39
The paper can’t look at all of them. New ones pop up all the time. Think of poor Hercules, lopping off
the Hydra’s heads, only to have two heads spring forth from each severed stump.
40
See Alter & Walter (2007) for papers pursuing and criticizing this strategy.
41
Levine understands modes of presentation as ways entities, or referents, present to us. ‘‘One must
distinguish between concepts and properties. Concepts are, roughly, modes of presentation of properties
(as well as objects)’’ (46).
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
335
Levine, a concept dualist himself, turns this strategy on its head. He considers
most concepts, including, especially, our physical concepts, as ‘‘non-ascriptive’’—
as lacking descriptive or other cognitive content and as relating to their referents
only by referring to them (rather than, say, by describing them).
[Physical concepts] are ‘‘presentationally thin’’ in the sense that their modes of
presentation either contain nothing of cognitive significance beyond the bare
representation of the property in question, or contain representations of other
properties that are presentationally thin as well. (8)
[So] there is very little, if anything, like conceptual content, or cognitive
significance, over and above the actual symbols of the relevant representations
and their referents. (53)
Levine understands phenomenal concepts, on the other hand, as ‘‘ascriptive’’—as
having thick modes of presentation that attribute to conscious entities all the
richness we experience from the first person perspective.
[O]ur conception, or the mode of presentation of a property like reddishness is
substantive and determinate in a way that the modes of presentation of other
sorts of properties are not. When I think of what it is to be reddish, the
reddishness itself is somehow included in the thought; it’s present to me. This
is what I mean by saying it has a ‘‘substantive’’ mode of presentation. In fact,
it seems the right way to look at it is that reddishness itself is serving as its
own mode of presentation. By saying that the conception is ‘‘determinate,’’ I
mean that reddishness presents itself as a specific quality, identifiable in its
own right, not merely by its relation to other qualities. (8)
Levine purports to undermine anti-physicalist arguments, not, as most concept
dualists do, by pointing to shortcomings in our phenomenal concepts, but instead by
trimming back the a priori. ‘‘Because I am very sympathetic to the Quinean attack
on the analytic/synthetic distinction I would like as much as possible to reduce the a
priori to logical form’’ (42). Given that our concepts ‘‘the watery stuff’’, ‘‘H2O’’, and
‘‘brain state 77’’ lack descriptive content, but our concept ‘‘pain’’ drips with it, the
referents of the first three vary across possible worlds (since they can refer to
anything) whereas the referent of the fourth stays the same. But then ‘‘zombieH2O’’—H2O that isn’t watery stuff—is just as conceivable as is an instance of brain
state 77 that isn’t a pain (since we can imagine a world where ‘‘H2O’’ refers to
giraffes and ‘‘watery stuff’’ refers to triangles). But we all agree that zombie-H2O
lies beyond the metaphysical pale. It follows, Levine concludes, that ‘‘no antimaterialist metaphysical consequences follow from the conceptual possibility of
zombies. The materialist has no more to fear from mindless zombies than she has to
fear from zombie-H2O’’ (54).
Levine nonetheless takes the explanatory gap seriously. He points out that it
endures even after we beef up our thin physical concepts with the thick background
knowledge we acquire a posteriori about their referents. Thus the referent of our
concept ‘‘brain state 77’’, as understood in the full light of science, fails to explain
the referent of our concept ‘‘pain’’, as understood from the first-person perspective.
123
336
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
In cases…such as ‘‘water = H2O’’, while there is no a priori route from the
‘‘H2O’’-described facts to the ‘‘water’’-described facts, still there is the definite
sense that when all the chemical facts are in, the whole story has been told….
[N]o sensible question about how H2O could be water remains…. However,
with the proposed identification of reddishness with a physical or functional
property…a substantive question does remain…. (91)
These and other instances of concept dualism all make the same kinds of moves.
Physicalism comes across data it can’t digest. But the concept dualist finds cause to
explain away these data as misleading appearances generated by conceptual
distortion or blindness. He thus denies local cognitive capacity and, to that extent,
trims back our overall cognitive rationality. Now, we’ve seen that the physicalist
must presume local cognitive capacity unless he has specific, positive and
persuasive reasons to the contrary. But the concept dualist has no such reasons. In
fact, he advances his conceptual alibi, not because the evidence demands it, but
solely to safeguard physicalism. Two facts point this way. (1) We find no consensus
among physicalists about whether such incapacities exist. Nor do we find any
consensus among concept dualists about what these incapacities are. Each
philosopher cooks up his own pet conceptual mechanism, and none of these
proposals garners much support from other thinkers.42 We see this most clearly with
Levine’s idiosyncratic concept dualism, which rests on an understanding of physical
and phenomenal concepts precisely the opposite of that endorsed by most
physicalists. But the other concept dualists bear it out too. Thus Loar (1997)
understands phenomenal concepts as recognitional concepts; Papineau (2007)
understands them as quotational concepts; Block (2007) understands them as a
different and incompatible kind of quotational concept; and Perry (2001)
understands them as indexical concepts. (2) Concept dualists consistently adduce
philosophical arguments instead of citing scientific facts. Thus Levine attends to the
nature and reach of the a priori, the theory of concepts, the epistemic status of both
confirmation theory and the theory of reference (62), and the nature of phenomenal
concepts as introspectively revealed. The same goes for Loar, Papineau, Block and
Perry, although the paper won’t support this claim textually. It thus seems that
concept dualist hypotheses don’t enjoy empirical backing. And yet these hypotheses
fall within the domain of cognitive psychology, dealing, as they do, with the
contingent nature of our information gathering and processing systems. So the
concept dualist defends his philosophical theory against basic data by practising
armchair (and largely a priori) science. This violates epistemic warrant (which
enjoins the physicalist to hold philosophical theories to the same standards to which
scientists hold scientific theories). We can compare concept dualism with Freudian
psychology, infamous for diagnosing criticisms of it as symptoms of the psychopathological mechanisms postulated by it. Furthermore, because concept dualism
postulates cognitive incapacities only to save physicalism, it violates minimal
warrant (which enjoins the physicalist to postulate only those entities that enjoy
evidential support) and epistemological rationalism (which enjoins the physicalist
42
See the essays in Alter & Walter (2007), the works cited there, and the discussions in Levine (2001) of
other concept dualists.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
337
to study nature in accordance with publicly defensible norms about collecting and
assessing evidence).
9 Explaining Away the Gap using Epistemology II
Colin McGinn (1989) postulates a cognitive shortcoming—call it M—that keeps us
from grasping the straightforwardly physical nature of consciousness. McGinn says
we know that a physical psychophysical link obtains—call this P—because we
know that physicalism holds true. He then canvasses the only cognitive avenues
through which, he claims, we might hope to grasp P—introspection and empirical
neuroscience. Introspection won’t lead us to P because it doesn’t reveal
consciousness as depending on neural processes. And empirical neuroscience
won’t lead us to P because, McGinn argues, scientific concepts are essentially
perceptual, perceptual concepts are essentially spatial, and spatial concepts have no
grip on consciousness. Hence M.
McGinn makes the same moves as concept dualists—he postulates a contingent
cognitive mechanism solely to proof physicalism against basic data, then supports
his hypothesis with philosophical argument rather than empirical evidence. But
McGinn goes one step further. He does the very thing the theist does when pressed
about the problem of evil. He insists that the apparently fatal problem besetting his
metaphysic, a problem he can’t answer, does have an answer, but one that lies safely
outside the reach of human thought. The theist, under duress, assures us that God
works in mysterious ways, that our finite minds can’t expect to grasp his infinite
design. McGinn, a physicalist in a corner, assures us that P would reveal the
straightforwardly physical nature of consciousness if only it didn’t lie beyond our
cognitive competence. But just as the physicalist scorns the theist’s dodge, so we
might scorn McGinn’s. We can’t prove him wrong, of course, any more than we can
disprove the theist. Who knows what wonders lurk where human minds will never
go? But both McGinn and the theist, by seeking refuge in the unknowable and
incomprehensible, opt out of rational enquiry. Where the scientist and the
philosopher aim to understand the world through rational thought, McGinn and
the theist do something else.43 And this something else violates epistemological
rationalism.
10 Physicalism and Fruitfulness
The physicalist embraces science because it works. And science, for its part, judges
scientific theories and research programs by whether and to what extent they
work—in a word, by their fruitfulness. Some of these theories and research
43
We can read McGinn more charitably, of course—not as arguing for physicalism, but as exploring
what must follow about us from the truth of physicalism coupled with our inability to see its truth. But
even this kinder reading reveals metaphysical hubris. Compare McGinn with the creationist, who,
confronted with the fossil record, suggests that God brought forth the world six thousand years ago with
fossils in place.
123
338
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
programs, like the theory of evolution by natural selection and the research program
of evolutionary biology, deliver the goods and flourish. Others, like the caloric
theory of heat and the program of phrenology, don’t deliver and fall by the wayside.
Is physicalism delivering the goods? Does it make progress on the problems it
tackles, resolving one after another, making ever more of the world intelligible in
light of its central claims? It seems not. Physicalism may not, in fact, have had any
major successes at all. We’ve seen how it spins its wheels with consciousness. It
also spins its wheels in other domains.44
This paper obviously can’t delve deeply into each research program physicalism
spawns. Instead it skims lightly over the surface, summarizing the state of play,
noting problems, and drawing a few very tentative conclusions. In a word, this
section aims to suggest more than to argue.
Physicalists have struggled to naturalize norms. However, despite much labor,
they have yet to field a theory with much plausibility, let alone one that enjoys much
support, even among physicalists.45 Every effort seems to miss the should-ness,
ought-ness, binding-ness—the normative-ness—that sets norms apart.
Physicalists freely admit that indexical facts don’t reduce to physical facts.46
Most believe that this doesn’t threaten physicalism. But physicalism claims that all
concrete entities are either physical or nothing over and above the physical. It would
seem to follow that (1) indexical facts don’t exist (contrary to appearances as well as
the beliefs of most physicalists); (2) indexical facts count as facts about abstract
entities rather than concrete entities (which makes little sense, especially on a
physicalist ontology); or (3) physicalism is false.
Physicalism has difficulty accommodating modality, not least because possibilities and necessities don’t readily reduce to actual concrete physical entities.47 This
has led some physicalists to expunge modality from their ontologies.48 It has also
motivated most physicalists to seek accounts of causation that shun entities like
necessary connections.49 But if necessary connections don’t obtain, in some form at
least, then causal relations can’t reduce to their causal relata. They must instead
stand over and above the entities that figure in them. Hence the claim, shared by
most physicalists, that causal relations and laws of nature hold contingently.50 But
this seems to turn causal laws, from epistemological artifacts recording the causal
capacities of concrete entities, into metaphysical actors with causal clout in their
own right. But how can laws push concrete physical entities around? And how can
the physicalist naturalize causal laws that don’t reduce to—that aren’t even
grounded in—the concrete physical entities that figure in them? No good answers lie
44
See Nagel (2012) for an extended argument to this effect.
45
See Miller (2013) for an overview of physicalist meta-ethical thinking.
46
See, for example, Perry (1979).
47
Lewis (1986) reduces possibilities to concrete actualities, but only at prohibitive ontological cost!
48
See, for example, Quine (1961).
49
Most physicalists adopt a broadly Human account of causation. See Mackie (1980) and Lewis (1983)
for examples.
50
Humans about causation are committed to the contingency of both causal relations and laws of nature.
See Lewtas (2013a) and Lewtas (forthcoming d) for more about this.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
339
to hand, certainly none that should please the physicalist. The physicalist thus seems
faced with a dilemma. If he recognizes modal entities, his physicalism comes under
pressure because these entities don’t readily reduce to actual physical entities. But if
he disavows modal entities, he seems forced to reify causal laws, a move which also
strains his physicalism.
Physicalism also has trouble with meaning, whether construed as sense (very
roughly, what a thinker or language user grasps) or in terms of reference/intentionality
(very roughly, the relation that holds between the thought or expression and the entity
the thought or expression is about). Physicalist attempts to naturalize sense run into
problems of under-determination of theory by all available and even possible data,
where attributions of sense play the role of theory and all possible physical facts play
the role of data. Thus Quine and Kripke’s Wittgenstein argue from idealized
epistemological access to all facts relevant to determinations of meaning, to
constitutive meaning skepticism, and finally to meaning nihilism.51 But we experience
linguistic and mental senses in our daily lives. More, our lives, as lived and
experienced, wouldn’t be possible if these senses didn’t exist.52 Similar problems arise
with intentionality and reference. The physicalist has at hand only one relation
naturalistic enough for the task of naturalizing them—causation. But causal relations,
understood as actual entities shorn of modal attributes, seem ill-suited to capture the
normativity of reference and intentionality. Thus, for example, causal/covariational
accounts of intentionality falter in their efforts to accommodate the possibility of
error.53 Teleological accounts, such as those offered in Dretske (1981) and Millikan
(1984), face similar difficulties. Many physicalists insist that it’s early days yet, and
that, in time, some causal account will bear fruit.54 But others hold out less hope.55
None of these laughably brief cartoons carries much weight, of course. But they
perhaps suggest that physicalism isn’t solving problems, isn’t advancing its research
programs, and isn’t contributing to knowledge the way science and physics do.
Physicalism, this paper proposes, has so far proved sterile and shows no sign of
getting on track. If this is right, then physicalism violates both epistemic warrant
(which enjoins the physicalist to hold philosophical theories to the same standards to
which scientists hold scientific theories) and fruitfulness (which enjoins the
physicalist to forsake research programs that don’t pan out).
11 Conclusion
It might not have turned out this way. Physicalism isn’t irrational from the outset.
But the doctrine ran into entities it couldn’t make sense of in light of its overarching
51
See Quine (1960) and Kripke (1982).
52
See Lewtas (forthcoming e) for further development of these points.
53
Here we have the problem of ruling out, as illegitimate, incorrect but actual word uses. Suppose
someone mistakenly uses ‘‘horse’’ to refer to a cow. How, on causal/covariational accounts, can his word
not, on that occasion at least, mean cow? Fodor (1987) discusses these kinds of issues at length.
54
Levine (2001) claims this.
55
See, for example, Lycan (2008).
123
340
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
metaphysic. This forced physicalists to make moves, and physicalism to take on
shapes, that conflict with the metaphysical and epistemological principles the
doctrine necessarily inherits from science. At bottom, science and philosophy are
ways of engaging rationally with a world itself necessarily taken to be rational (in
the sense of being orderly and thus, at least in principle, intelligible). Physicalism,
through contingent bad luck, found itself faced with a choice: between giving up its
core metaphysic and giving up standards of rationality essential to it. Physicalists
opted for the latter. Where science extends human knowledge, and feeds our hopes
for understanding more and more of the world, physicalism denies data, attributes
brute and mysterious features to the world, cuts back our rational and cognitive
capacities, insists on a metaphysic that outruns its epistemology, and embraces
dogmatism even unto faith.56
References
Alter T, Walter S (2007) Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge. Oxford University Press,
New York
Armstrong DM (1993) A materialist theory of the mind, 2nd edn. Routledge, London
Armstrong DM (1999) The mind–body problem. Westview, Boulder
Block N (2007) Max Black’s objection to mind–body identity. In: Alter T, Walter S (eds) Phenomenal
concepts and phenomenal knowledge. Oxford University Press, New York
Braddon-Mitchell D, Jackson F (2007) Philosophy of mind and cognition. Blackwell, Oxford
Chalmers D (1996) The conscious mind. Oxford University Press, New York
Chalmers D (2003) Consciousness and its place in nature. In: Stich S, Warfield T (eds) The Blackwell
guide to philosophy of mind. Blackwell, New York
Chalmers D (2010) The character of consciousness. Oxford University Press, New York
Chalmers D (2012) Constructing the world. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Churchland PS (1988) The significance of neuroscience for philosophy. Trends Neurosci 11:304–307
Churchland PM (1996) Matter and consciousness, Revised edn. The MIT Press, Cambridge
Dennett D (1991) Consciousness explained. Little, Brown, Boston
Dretske F (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. Bradford Books/MIT Press, Cambridge
Fodor J (1987) Psychosemantics: the problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. MIT Press,
Cambridge
Greene B (2000) The elegant universe. Vintage, New York
Heil J (2003) From an ontological point of view. Oxford University Press, New York
Hill C (1991) Sensations: a defense of type materialism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
James W (1890/1950) Principles of psychology. Dover Publications, New York
Kripke S (1982) Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Levine J (1983) Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pac Philos Q 64:354–361
Levine J (1993) On leaving out what it’s like. In: Davies M, Humphreys G (eds) Consciousness:
psychological and philosophical essays. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 121–136
Levine J (2001) Purple haze: the puzzle of consciousness. Oxford University Press, New York
Lewis D (1983) New work for a theory of universals. Austr J Philos 61:343–377
Lewis D (1986) On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell, Oxford
Lewtas P (2013a) Emergence and consciousness. Philos 88(4):527–553
Lewtas P (2013b) What it is like to be a quark. J Conscious Stud 20(9–10):39–64
Lewtas P (forthcoming a) Physicalism and the intrinsic nature of consciousness unpublished ms
Lewtas P (forthcoming b) Building minds: solving the combination problem unpublished ms
56
The author thanks Joe Viste for encouraging him to bring this paper’s arguments together in one place.
The paper would never have come about but for him.
123
Axiomathes (2014) 24:313–341
341
Lewtas P (forthcoming c) Russellian panpsychism: too good to be true? unpublished ms
Lewtas P (forthcoming d) How to make dualist interactionism work unpublished ms
Lewtas P (forthcoming e) Consciousness, qualia and cognition: why consciousness includes more than
qualia unpublished ms
Loar B (1997) Phenomenal states. In: Chalmers D (ed) Philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press,
New York
Lycan W (1996) Consciousness and experience. Bradford Books, Cambridge
Lycan W (2008) Phenomenal intentionalities. Am Philos Q 45(3):233–252
Mackie J (1980) The cement of the universe: a study of causation. Oxford University Press, New York
Maxwell G (1978) Rigid designators and mind–brain identity. In: Savage C (ed) Minnesota studies in the
philosophy of science, vol 9. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, p 1978
McGinn C (1989) Can we solve the mind–body problem? Mind 98(891):349–366
Miller A (2013) Contemporary metaethics: an introduction, 2nd edn. Polity Press, Cambridge
Millikan R (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories. Bradford Books/MIT Press,
Cambridge
Nagel T (1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philos Rev 4:435–450
Nagel, T. (1979). Panpsychism. In Mortal Questions. New York: Cambridge University Press
Nagel T (2012) Mind and cosmos. Oxford University Press, New York
Papineau D (2007) Phenomenal concepts and perceptual concepts. In: Alter T, Walter S (eds)
Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge. Oxford University Press, New York
Paul L (2012) Metaphysics as modelling: the handmaiden’s tale. Philos Stud 160:1–29
Pereboom D (2011) Consciousness and the prospects of physicalism. Oxford University Press, New York
Perry J (1979) The problem of the essential indexical. Nous 13:3–21
Perry J (2001) Knowledge, possibility and consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge
Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge
Quine WVO (1961) Reference and modality. In: Linsky L (ed) Reference and modality. Oxford
University Press, Oxford, p 1971
Rey G (1983) A reason for doubting the existence of consciousness. In: Davidson R, Shwartz G, Shapiro
D (eds) Consciousness and self-regulation, vol 3. Plenum Press, New York
Schaffer J (2010) Monism: the priority of the whole. Philos Rev 199(1):31–76
Smart JJC (1959) Sensations and brian processes. Philos Rev 68:141–156
Smolin L (2007) The trouble with physics: the rise of string theory, the fall of a science, and what comes
next. Mariner Books, Boston
Stoljar D (2001) Two conceptions of the physical. Philos Phenom Res 62:253–281
Strawson G (2006) Realistic monism: why physicalism entails panpsychism. In: Strawson G et al (eds)
Consciousness and its place in nature. Imprint Academic, Exeter
Tye M (1995) Ten problems of consciousness: a representational theory of the phenomenal mind.
Bradford Books, Cambridge
Van Cleve J (1990) Mind: dust or magic? Panpsychism or emergence? Philos Perspect 4:215–226
Wilson J (2006) On characterizing the physical. Philos Stud 131:61–99
123