Francesco Paolo Adorno
The Transhumanist
Movement
Contents
1 Introduction
1
2 The Transhumanist Movement
2.1 The Word
2.2 The People
2.3 The Organisations
2.4 Declarations
2.5 The Definitions of Transhumanism
References
13
13
15
26
30
33
37
3 Transhumanism Between Humanism
and the Posthuman
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Humanism
3.3 The Theories of the Posthuman
3.4 Is Transhumanism a Form of the Posthuman?
3.5 Is Transhumanism a Form of Humanism?
References
41
41
45
48
52
55
65
v
vi
Contents
4 Theory and Practice of Transhumanism
4.1 Enhancement
4.2 The Aims of Enhancement
4.3 What Needs to Be Enhanced?
4.4 Body Enhancement
4.5 Cognitive Enhancement
4.6 Moral Enhancement
4.7 The Search for Immortality
References
67
67
74
80
82
85
91
101
114
5 Problems of Transhumanism
5.1 Criticism of Enhancement
5.2 Therapy vs Enhancement
5.3 Medicine and Transhumanism
5.4 The Instrumentalisation of the Body
5.5 An Anthropology of Disability
5.6 Becoming a Cyborg
5.7 Legitimacy of Becoming a Cyborg
5.8 The Morality of Technology
References
121
121
129
136
141
146
153
158
165
170
6 Transhumanism and Biopolitics
6.1 Introduction
6.2 Biopolitics and Transhumanism
6.3 Biopolitics as Life Economics
6.4 The Economics, Morality and Politics
of Enhancement
6.5 Wellbeing Between Medicine and Politics
6.6 Enhancing to Manage and Govern
References
175
175
179
184
187
190
194
200
Bibliography
203
1
Introduction
As stated in the title, this book deals with the transhumanist movement.
It offers the reader not only a description of transhumanism but also and
above all an assessment of its underlying theory. In order to achieve this,
several notional choices have been made.
First, transhumanism is considered as a movement underpinned by
the concepts and theories expounded to a greater or a lesser extent by
all the authors discussed. Like every choice, this entailed a process of
selection and elimination: certain concepts were selected as the primary
focus while others were partially or totally excluded. This in turn meant
selecting the material to analyse, which was not restricted to concepts
and theories but also involved the elimination of some concrete facts. As
a result, the map of transhumanism presented in Chapter 2 is far from
complete. Transhumanism now encompasses such a spatially and temporally vast array of names, organisations, movements, trends, groups,
newspapers, fanzines, publications, conferences and meetings that it
would be impossible to take them all into account. This is not intended
as an apology but rather as an acknowledgement of responsibility for
a choice that is partly justified by the fact that, despite the limitless
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2021
F. P. Adorno, The Transhumanist Movement,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-82423-5_1
1
2
F. P. Adorno
material to study or summarise, most of the works on and from transhumanism are boringly repetitive and redundant. Whether it is Californian
biohackers working out of garages, Australian bio-artists, Oxford university researchers, Italian neo-futurists or French techno-socialists, the basic
ideas are broadly the same.
Second, it is worth recalling how in reality transhumanism acts on
two levels: a first level regards the direct enhancement of the human
body through the use of all kinds of prostheses that allow for a better
control of individual biological processes. The second level of development of transhumanism relates to an indirect enhancement of the human
body through a substantially uncontrollable increase in human intelligence which, according to its theorists, will lead to its replacement with
a still indefinable form of artificial intelligence. It is argued that the pace
of technological progress is so rapid that we will soon enter a phase
defined as “singularity” in which this acceleration, originating from weak
human capacities, will be such as to transform human nature in an irreversible and fundamentally unpredictable way. The brain, powerful as
it is, is limited in the same way that other parts of the human body
are, so despite all the creativity it possesses, it seems to have reached
its maximum expansion. Notwithstanding this, it has had the ability to
initiate a movement of technological progress that seems unstoppable
and that, above all, can transcend the biological limits of the human
organ, which it still is, creating higher forms of intelligence. Before the
end of the twenty-first century, our intelligence will be implemented on
a non-biological support billions of billions of times more powerful than
the biological support offered by neuronal matter, with consequences
that are completely inconceivable at the present stage of our knowledge.
This second-level transhumanism presents a difference, along with an
analogy, with first-level transhumanism that explains why we will not
deal with it directly. The difference is that, on the one hand, singularity is a largely predictive theory that focuses on the long-term effects of
progress in artificial intelligence and that, at least in the terms in which
it is presented, are far in the future. On the other hand, the problems
posed by the development of artificial intelligence go far beyond what has
been discussed in a specifically transhumanist context. The analogy is the
particularly negative representation of human biology, proposed by both
1 Introduction
3
these groups of transhumanists, even though they can be distinguished
and isolated. At the bottom of all the branches of transhumanism, there
is the belief that human biological processes—the living as such, not
to mention natural life—have too many limitations, too many obstacles, that make no sense and that can now be eliminated without any
difficulty. Starting from this common diagnosis, “biological” and “singular” transhumanists focus on two different but parallel ways of achieving
the same goal which consists of imagining the humanity of the future.
That means that the issues discussed are essentially the same, but the
means on which to act to produce and think of a posthuman humanity
are diverging. For “biological” transhumanists, it is the human body
in its diversity and materiality; for “singular” transhumanists, it is the
brain that has the evident characteristic of being a biological part of
the human body, but it also has the specificity of producing intangible
objects such as thoughts, emotions and feelings. The reasons why I prefer
to avoid discussing issues related to singularity starting from artificial
intelligence are, hopefully, understandable: from the more concretely
biological perspective, focusing on singularity would have been redundant with respect to our problems; from the more specifically cognitive
perspective, such a focus would have led us to discuss problems that are
largely beyond the transhumanist perspective.
With virtually no facts, few names and a great deal of theory, the
assessment of a movement cannot be a mere repetition of the almost
identical claims its authors make all around the globe. It must not be
limited to merely highlighting the implicitly introduced and employed
concepts, the more or less implicit justification strategies and the more
or less skilfully exploited historical references in order to gain the reader’s
approval. Instead, it must also shift through all the theoretical material,
evaluate it and point out any inconsistencies, issues, logical and theoretical errors, inaccuracies, misstatements and the more or less questionable
approximations that it allegedly identifies in its theoretical corpus and,
above all, it must consider any resulting practical and theoretical consequences. Despite an equidistance in principle, this book is far from
proposing an apology for transhumanism, which the shelves of bookstores and libraries are full of. On the contrary, after a first reading, it
will appear as excessively negative and critical of transhumanism. The
4
F. P. Adorno
fact is that the author is a philosopher who is convinced that the role
of his discipline is above all to criticise, to problematise and to show
the more or less evident implications of concepts, theories and movements to eliminate unreasonable prejudices, while also offering readers
some arguments to rationally justify a choice for or against the theses
of the transhumanists. Consequently, a point of view was chosen which
is this: a comprehensive critique of transhumanism will be developed
through the analysis and articulation of a series of arguments that tend,
as mentioned, to highlight the shortcomings and criticalities of the topic;
if the reader considers that these arguments are valid then his or her
rejection of transhumanism will be justified by a solid and substantial
reasoning and not only by the dread of transformations and changes,
the fear of the new, or by a prejudice favourable to the status quo. If,
on the other hand, these arguments are considered weak, inconsistent,
inconclusive or useless, the reader will be reinforced in his or her positive
conception of transhumanism.
Chapter 4 sets out a detailed overview of the concepts and practices of transhumanism, starting from what appears to be its pivotal
concept: enhancement. This is a word used frequently and inaccurately
in everyday language, as indicated by the existence of various synonyms,
and whose scope indicates such embedded practices that there seems no
point in further analysing its meaning. After all, who does not work or
act to improve themselves? Who does not seek to better themselves from
every point of view? Trivialising enhancement in this way—unintentionally perhaps but certainly without sparing a second thought—obviously
means that it can be excluded ipso facto from any kind of debate or,
worse, delegitimised. What sense would it make to criticise the enhancement proposed by transhumanists if almost all human actions aim at
self-improvement? All this would achieve is a paradoxical questioning of
human history. Yet things may not be as clear-cut as they first appear,
because transhumanist enhancement differs somewhat from humanity’s
thirst for improvement and gives rise to concerns that have never been
raised before. Concentrating on the purpose of human actions, which
are always invariably geared towards improving an individual’s condition,
distracts attention from the means by which these are to be achieved and
hinders the proper assessment of their validity because it reduces the gap
1 Introduction
5
between the traditional and biotechnological enhancement proposed by
transhumanists. The use of biotechnology is legitimised by novel assumptions and could produce revolutionary effects, such as the achievement
of immortality. It remains to be seen just how desirable this and the
other enhancements proposed and propagated by transhumanism are
and whether the enhancement of certain faculties or the creation of new
capabilities can be considered truly positive achievements. Indeed, as
transhumanism’s promises are fulfilled, doubts arise over enhancement
in general as a practice involving biotechnological means as well as its
specific applications in the search for clear results.
However, it is not only this allegedly extraordinary biotechnological
enhancement that is problematic, but also the desire to remove it from
procedures of moral legitimation, which should be all the more necessary when their effects appear at first sight so outlandish. Intuitively,
apart from the specific arguments used to explain, justify and support
the various forms of enhancement, transhumanism employs a specific
strategy to legitimise its theories, affirming the full consistency and continuity of its proposals with movements, knowledge, beliefs and concepts
traditionally rooted in the theoretical framework of modernity. Basically,
transhumanists claim that they are the worthy and orthodox continuation of all the humanists, enlighteners and scientists who have worked
for the advancement of humanity. Transhumanism is not an innovative project but one that aims only to accept the consequences of the
very movement of modernity through technological progress. Its insistent reference to such notions as progress, humanity and humanism, and
even the very name of the movement itself, rightly restores the meaning
of this continuity. Transhumanism claims to be nothing other than the
orthodox extension of humanism with a view to becoming its crowning
achievement: a group of theories and ideas to explain the very premise
of the historical self-narration of our world of material progress.
However, the narrative proposed by transhumanism is too smooth,
too flat, to be accepted without detailed analysis. Chapter 3 will investigate its alleged continuity with humanism, a claim that transhumanists
frequently make in order to take their “rightful” place among the various
schools of thought engaging more or less critically with different forms of
6
F. P. Adorno
humanism. This has resulted in a somewhat problematic image of transhumanism: while it may initially seem fallacious to establish a continuity
with humanism, in reality there are certainly valid reasons for considering transhumanism as its fulfilment. This conclusion, which is not
devoid of ambiguity, can also be attributed to difficulties in defining
the key concepts of humanism present in all the authors, thinkers,
philosophers and scientists who consider themselves to be humanists.
Notwithstanding the uncertainties shrouding the issue, the fact remains
that the transhumanists’ claim that they are the continuers and heirs of
enlightenment and humanism does have a certain legitimacy.
Chapter 5 delves further into the essential principles of transhumanism and assesses its legitimation on the basis of its continuity with
traditional practices and theories in order to focus on one of its fundamental features. Transhumanism argues that, as there is no fundamental
difference between enhancement practices and medical therapies aiming
to restore good health, the rejection of biotechnological enhancement
should paradoxically lead to the same attitude being adopted towards
medical therapies. Since such a conclusion is literally inconceivable, transhumanists then argue that just as therapeutic interventions are regarded
as essential, the same should hold for enhancement interventions. Here
too, an excessively linear and superficial rationale fuels the suspicion
that such inconsistent and discontinuous reasoning should somehow be
exposed, first by making this analogy between the aims of therapy and
enhancement less straightforward, and second by pointing out the consequences it might have on people’s daily lives. If every therapy is basically
an enhancement and if every enhancement has a therapeutic aim, the
dissemination and pervasiveness of enhancement could be symptomatic
of a view of human life as not simply a succession of illnesses and diseases
but as a disease itself; one might then wonder if survival might not lie in
pathologising everyday existence.
It seems clear that a line must somehow be drawn to separate health
from illness and enhancement from therapy in order to define the limits
of normal existence, although this is no simple task. Normality and
health are those human conditions that do not need treatment and could
certainly be modified through enhancement, although this would differ
1 Introduction
7
considerably from therapy. Other arguments legitimising such enhancement interventions would then have to be defined, since they could
no longer be justified by therapeutic necessity. The alleged continuity
between therapy and enhancement, which is also justified by historical processes that have progressively modified the means and aims of
medicine, has an “ideological” impact with deleterious consequences, as
is pointed out in the final chapter.
The problematic nature of the transhumanists’ “continuist” strategy
also emerges clearly when discussing their anthropology. The central
figure of transhumanism is, of course, the cyborg: a being that is stronger,
more powerful and better than a “normal” human being from every point
of view because it has been hybridised with artificial systems that perform
the functions of worn out or inadequate organs or replace them, as in the
case of RoboCop or the Terminator. The cyborg is an extremely problematic figure as it seems to portray a new human being which, in the
eyes of transhumanism’s critics, deserves nothing but ruthless condemnation. Transhumanists and their supporters respond to this by stating
that person has always been a cyborg. Critics of the cyborgisation of
humanity do not accept that the human race has always been fundamentally hybrid, impure and naturally “contaminated” by the environment
in which it evolves and by the tools it conceives and creates. The transhumanists once again claim this should not be wondered at and that no
justification or legitimation is warranted: the human being becoming a
cyborg does not mark a discontinuity with the evolution of its true nature
because we are born cyborgs. Denying a discontinuity in the evolution of humanity aims once again to avoid all criticism of the human
enhancement that transhumanism supports, by normalising something
utterly outlandish. But exactly what is outlandish in the human being
that transhumanism proposes to create? What makes it appear so utterly
innovative? A first answer to this question can be found in the means
that are to be used for this purpose: biotechnologies. While the impact
of the biotechnological manipulation of humanity cannot be predicted,
there are at least two implications of the analyses conducted in Chapter 5
that deserve to be highlighted.
The first implication is that technology is not itself neutral towards
the consequences it produces. The use of new technologies in the field
8
F. P. Adorno
of biology, medicine and elsewhere has the power to change the relationship that people have with themselves, with other people, with their
environment and with the world. The problem thus shifts, and it is up
to the transhumanists to provide a fuller depiction of the type of world
that biotechnologies are likely to design. However, it is clearly not a
question of explaining whether or not human nature will be modified,
and in what way; for example whether we will have wings or whether
devices will be integrated into our bodies to allow us to breathe under
water or to survive in the vacuum of space. Instead, what is required
of transhumanists is that they explain how everyday activities, however
insignificant, will change as a result of humanity becoming a cyborg,
and what undesirable but inevitable effects there might be. Rather than
on the enhancement of human beings as such, it is on these alterations
that the discussion should focus.
A useful example is provided by the world of sport: there are
widespread appeals for anti-doping legislation to be withdrawn because
performance enhancement is allegedly within every sportsperson’s reach
and has been in use ever since competitive sport was invented. Enforcing
penalties for doping is like trying to empty the ocean with a spoon:
futile, costly and counter-productive. Transhumanists put forward the
same argument in this context as that used elsewhere: since doping has
always existed, no justification is warranted because it would be like justifying the very existence of competitive sport. At the very least, the burden
of proof should fall on those who oppose these centuries-old practices.
One might object, however, that the intentional or unintentional effects
of biotechnological or gene doping make it totally different from “traditional” doping based on corticoids, amphetamines and hormones. The
former intervenes directly, definitively and in depth, acting on the athlete
at a submolecular level. The transhumanists retort that even if this were
the case, the difference between the two doping techniques is quantitative, not qualitative. Clearly, the debate is far from over. One way out of
this impasse might be to introduce another aspect that could be defined
as practical assessment. Biotechnological doping alters more than just the
sportsperson’s performance and not only raises issues of fair play but also
and above all changes the way in which sport is perceived and played.
An Olympic Games 100-m final contested by athletes with physical
1 Introduction
9
or chemical prosthetics and by genetically modified or cloned athletes
would call into question the current concept of “the Olympic 100-m
final”. Given the above forms of doping, it is probably the variations of
this concept and others of the same type and not those concerning doping
and its effects that need to be properly evaluated.
The second implication that deserves scrutiny is the unintentional
shift in outlook on human nature that the spread of enhancement
interventions will inevitably produce. The trivialisation of enhancement,
which is nothing more than the trivialisation of improvement therapies, will produce a pathologisation of existence (as will be discussed
in Chapter 6) with absolutely unprecedented moral and political consequences. It would be reductive to see transhumanist anthropology as
being entirely centred on the cyborg or, rather, it would be a mistake
to view the cyborg as the image of an augmented, upgraded human.
Indeed, there is another side to the cyborg, for example in the case
of the athlete Oscar Pistorius, who is a fragile, vulnerable, diminished
and disabled man. It is because human beings are deficient or impaired
that they need enhancement. Under the triumphant optimism of transhumanist technophilia there lies the sad and compassionate image of a
man constantly in need of care and therapy, improvements and support
without which his existence would be considerably worse than it is.
Contrary to popular belief, transhumanism treats people as if they were
disabled and in need of improvement therapies throughout their lives.
It proposes a generalised therapeutic solution, whose explicit aim is to
restore or attribute faculties capable of improving individual wellbeing
through increased freedom of movement and greater control over our
body. However, the view that humanity is fundamentally inadequate
or in a state of virtual deficiency risks triggering a pathologisation of
existence: a process in which all the imperfections of the human body
become defects to be eliminated, disabilities to be remedied and diseases
to be treated.
The moral and political consequences of transhumanist anthropology
and of the equivalence between therapies and enhancement are detailed
in Chapter 6. This final chapter follows a theoretical argument based on
an assumption external to transhumanism in order to abandon the sterile
discussions on the possible negative (or positive) effects of enhancement.
10
F. P. Adorno
These typically prove fruitless and ultimately hinder an overall assessment
of transhumanism not only as a movement promoting individualism and
competitiveness in the Western world and thereby revolutionising individual lives, but also as a theory producing more concrete and direct
effects. The assumption on which transhumanism is here interpreted is
that contemporary politics is centred on the biological life of human
beings, which has been the mainstay of power since the seventeenth
century. This means that the government of individuals, that is all those
practices that aim to make individuals perform a certain type of action
and adopt specific behaviour patterns with a view to ensuring adherence to a certain vision of morality, is nowadays achieved through life
processes.
From the purely moral point of view, transhumanist imperatives pressure individuals into taking responsibility for their own health and
activity, establishing a moral code entirely centred on their behaviour and
attitudes. Politically, this would result in a deconstruction of traditional
political thought, which would then be entirely modelled on biopolitical imperatives that in no way resemble traditional ones. In other
words, this diminished and vulnerable conception of the human being
would task politics with the management, strengthening and improvement of people’s biological life, the consequences of which would be just
as important as those previously mentioned with regard to enhancement.
Contemporary biopolitics eliminates the gap between the biological
processes supporting mere individual existence and the way in which
people try to live their lives, inspired by values, concepts and moral and
political judgements.
The result achieved by confusing these and reducing the one to the
other is the power to manage and govern people’s lives through the orientation imposed on the management of life processes. In other words,
the life of individuals is governed through the control and management
of human biological needs. Biopolitics thus comprises two factors: the
governance and the manipulation of human biology, that is the framework within which the creation of individual life must necessarily take
place. More precisely, by establishing itself in relation to this biological element, the lifestyle of individuals would be completely managed
1 Introduction
11
and controlled by external forces and thus hetero-directed. If transhumanism were internal to this strategy of government, which adopts and
updates its working procedures, then our view of these theories and
their proposed enhancement would change completely. Transhumanism,
which comes across as a theory that promotes and seeks to fulfil even
the most repressed and undeclared human desires, would merely supply
yet another means of dominating individual lives to those who seek and
know how to use it. Beneath the liberation of bodily forces lurks the
danger of an even more ruthless and direct control of people through
their bodies.