Fall 2019
237
Ecocide or Environmental
Self-Destruction?
Sandra Baquedano Jer*
The anthropocentric destruction of nature can be viewed as a form of self-destruction, which
affects individuals and also the human species. It entails active destruction of the natural
surroundings that are vital for the preservation of the planet’s biodiversity. But should
ecocide, or environmental self-destruction of the life of certain species, be considered an
“interruption” to the life of such species, or it is part of their natural life course? Are ecocide
and environmental destruction identical, or substantively different, phenomena? Prevention
of the death of biotic species, and of the massive destruction of abiotic species, constitutes
the ultimate challenge for both environmental and animal ethics. Modern mass extinction
of species can be understood as a form of speciesism, and the prevention of such extinction is the most urgent challenge for any ethics centered on the recognition of the value, or
rights, of nonhuman species.
ETYMOLOGY AND DERIVATION OF THE TERM
ECOCIDE: A TERM COINED IN WARTIME
The term ecocide only emerged in common usage a few decades ago. However,
its origins involve a dual history: the use of the word itself and its associated
problematic. In other words, the phenomenon of individual and environmental
self-destruction dates back to prehistoric times. The term now used to refer to this
was coined in the context of armed conflict, emerging in the mid-twentieth century,
the era of Western wars with Southeast Asia.
From the prefix eco- (in Greek, oikos), which denotes “home” or “household,”
and is the root from which the words ecology and economy are both derived, the
concept of ecocide was originally used to denote all such practices adopted in
wartime that turned the environment into a military objective. The dynamics of
ecocide triggers environmental disasters, forced migration, and the death or mass
destruction of both human and nonhuman beings.
Notable scholars and commentators, from a range of different conceptual starting points and premises, have described essentially similar situations, emphasising
the devastating impacts upon affected societies. These impacts are felt in abrupt
decline in levels of human population, and in disintegration of the social basis that
sustains political organization, economic complexity, and norms of civility across
the vast territories that human beings colonize or dominate in this way. The legacies of these extreme situations live on well beyond the lifespan of the generation
that first created them.
* Facultad de Filosofía y Humanidades, Universidad de Chile, Av. Capitán Ignacio Carrera Pinto
1025, Ñuñoa, Santiago, Chile; email:
[email protected].
237
238
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 41
The devastating effects of herbicides and defoliants used as chemical weapons
in Vietnam drove Arthur Galston, a biologist, and at the time chair of the Department of Botany at Yale University, to coin the term ecocide. A group of scientists
and academics brought attention to its meaning to denounce the environmental
and humanitarian catastrophe that had followed in the wake of Operation Ranch
Hand.1
The defoliation of jungles and woodlands, and destruction of crops, were adopted
as military strategies by the United States, and routinely deployed in Vietnam,
including its borders with Laos and Cambodia. The targets were Vietcong insurgents, but also local peasant communities. The aim was to starve them out and
deny them any forest cover that could potentially serve as a hideout, using hunger
and contamination to force rural populations to migrate towards towns and cities
controlled by U.S. forces.
Between 1962 and 1971, the U.S. Air Force sprayed more than eighty million liters
of herbicide and defoliants in the region, most of it sourced from Dow Chemical
and Monsanto. Twenty million gallons of Agent Orange were dumped in a single
year (1966).2 Official sources in Vietnam estimate that around two million human
victims, and three million hectares of land, were contaminated by the toxins. Still
today, there are thousands of children born to parents affected by chemicals known
to cause damage to DNA that produce birth defects or develop early childhood
cancers.3
The use of herbicides as a tactic of war took a longlasting toll on human health,
and also devastated the future of thousands of square kilometers of jungle and
arable land pulverized by so-called “Rainbow Herbicides” (including Agent
Orange). These legacies added weight to the idea that the Vietnam War had been
a theater of ecocide, in contravention of international law.4 A group of intellectuals, environmentalists, and pacifists of the day took up the anti-ecocide cause,
conscious that ecocide was part of a much broader spectrum of war crimes that
were being committed. At this point in this account it is helpful to pause and
1 See
Paul Frederick Cecil, Herbicidal Warfare: The Ranch Hand Project in Vietnam (New York:
Praeger, 1986).
2 See Philip Jones Griffiths, Agent Orange: Collateral Damage in Vietnam (London: Trolley Books,
2004).
3 See Arnold Schecter, Le Cao Dai, Olaf Päpke, Joelle Prange, John D. Constable, Muneaki Matsuda,
Vu Duc Thao, and Amanda L. Piskac, “Recent Dioxin Contamination From Agent Orange in Residents
of a Southern Vietnam City,” Journal of Occupational and Environmental Medicine 43 (2001): 435–43;
J. L. Collins et al., Medical Problems of South Vietnam (Corinth: Black Mountain Press, 1967); N. Thi
Bình et al., Victims of Agent Orange/Dioxin in Vietnam—The Expectations (Hanoi: Research Centre
for Gender, Family, and Environment in Development, Proceedings of the International Scientific
Conference, 2006); Hugh Warwick, “Agente Naranja: el Envenenamiento de Vietnam,” The Ecologist
28 (1998): 17–18.
4 See David Zierler, The Invention of Ecocide: Agent Orange, Vietnam, and the Scientists Who
Changed the Way We Think About Environment (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 2011), p. 14.
Fall 2019
ECOCIDE OR ENVIRONMENTAL SELF-DESTRUCTION?
239
consider whether, and how, the concept of ecocide can plausibly be extrapolated
beyond its original wartime frame of reference.
THE INDIRECT INTENTION IN DYNAMICS OF
SELF-DESTRUCTION: THE ENVIRONMENTAL PROBLEM
Ecocide is the phenomenon that reveals in the most tragic way how so-called
development really has been a bad development. Its successes, far from leading
humankind down the path of environmental progress, have produced backsliding of
humanity’s instrumental self-knowledge about nature and its value. The complexity
of ecocide is bound iogether with other self-destructive and interconnected global
dynamics. Consider, for example, consumerism and human overpopulation. Both
phenomena have a burdening effect on Earth, reducing the planet’s effectiveness
in absorbing human waste,5 which in turn impacts climate change, creating problems of water scarcity, water management, contamination, deforestation, erosion,
salinization, soil fertility and, ultimately, wars resulting from control over natural
resources.6
Nature in relation to the human being, has become a shared space acted upon
by a range of different living beings, but in which one single species has managed
to impose its dominance over the rest, due to its particular biological capacity for
reasoning. Nature has been reified from within.
The power to create language; cultivate philosophy, art, and science; build
civilizations that have lasted for millennia; and construct magnificent works of
technology, also proves itself capable of destroying the environment that it inherited. The subordination of technical-scientific power to the dominant economic
system, overpopulation, industrialized wars, global climate change, and growing
consumerism have led to a present-day situation that is not only destructive, but
self-destructive. This self-destruction underlies a speciesist reification of nature,
causing the anthropogenic destruction of habitats, and mass species extinction.
As distinct from duty, the responsibility toward other living beings and to degraded
environments implies protecting the quality of life generated by relationships between
humans, and also nonhuman species. The greater the power of the inflicted damage,
the greater the responsibility of protecting what has been harmed. In spite of this
increase in responsibility, the reach and scope of technical-scientific capacity
has grown at a pace that has far outstripped the historical capacity of these same
dynamics to create a countervailing balance, in the form of a sense of responsibility toward the resulting disproportionate consequences. Ecocide is the clearest
signal of dissociation in this equation because this same proceeding has generated
an intentional destruction of the environment weakening those societies immersed
5 See Giovanni Sartori and Gianni Mazzoleni, La Tierra Explota (Madrid: Editorial Taurus, 2003),
pp. 125–30.
6 See Vandana Shiva, Las Guerras del Agua (Barcelona: Icaria, 2004), pp. 55–119.
240
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 41
in this bad development.7 Self-destructive environmental dynamics, on the other hand,
refer to habits with a conscious tendency to damage or wreak significant destruction on
the human ecosystem and biodiversity on Earth, without there necessarily being any
direct intention to cause such effects.8 Mere awareness of how the actions of each person
contribute to the speciesist reification of nature is not sufficient to avert the continuation
of destructive practices, which cause global degradation and the mass death of species.
BACKGROUND EXTINCTION VERSUS
MASS EXTINCTION OF SPECIES
While many relationship forms exist between different cultural groups and nature,
sources suggest that many societies have been known to inflict hostile treatment
toward other living beings since time immemorial; and have also overexploited
the vast zones of the Earth they went about settling.9 The particularly alarming
factor of the current situation, however, lies in the fact that in recent decades, the
expanded reach of human actions has created what is by far the most serious scenario of environmental degradation and anthropogenic extermination in recorded
history: “Homo sapiens is poised to become the greatest catastrophic agent since a
giant asteroid collided with the Earth sixty-five million years ago, wiping out half
the world’s species in a geological instant.”10
Based on fossil records, paleobiologists tend, in general terms, to draw a distinction between two types of extinction rates: background extinction, and mass
extinction. Background extinction tends to take place through a continuous process,
after a long period during which both the species and its ecological niche manage
to endure without substantial changes. By contrast, mass extinction events, on the
other hand, in the words of Stephen Gould, “must, by four criteria, be reinterpreted
as ruptures, not the high points of continua. They are more frequent, more rapid,
more profound (in numbers and habitats eliminated) and have effects more different
than those of normal times.”11
Numerous scientists claim that current levels of mass extinction are comparable
only with the three most recent of the mass extinction events that occurred in the
0 7 See Vandana Shiva, Abrazar la Vida. Mujer, Ecología y Desarrollo (Madrid: Editorial Horas y
Horas, 2004), p. 21. 0
0 8 This type of self-destructive dynamic comes under criticism from biocultural ethics, which define
that a good, integral, and righteous life must consider living habits in relation to the well-being of
the group of (human and nonhuman) co-inhabitants within their shared habitats. See Ricardo Rozzi,
“Biocultural Ethics: Recovering the Vital Links Between the Inhabitants, Their Habits, and Habitats,”
Environmental Ethics 43 (2012): 27–50.
09 See Jared Diamond, Collapse, How Societies Choose to Fail or Succeed (Barcelona: Editorial
Debate, 2008), pp. 1–23.
10 Richard Leakey and Roger Levin, The Sixth Extinction: Patterns of Life and the Future of Humankind (New York: Doubleday, 1995), p. 221.
11 Stephen Jay Gould, The Flamingo’s Smile: Reflections in Natural History (New York: W. W.
Norton and Co., 1985), pp. 231–32.
Fall 2019
ECOCIDE OR ENVIRONMENTAL SELF-DESTRUCTION?
241
remote geological past. The difference lies in the fact that the present wave is an
anthropogenic one.12 The first of these three, around 250 million years ago, signalled the end of the Permian period (the sixth and final period of the Paleozoic
era). It is believed that it may have been caused by climate change and a variation
in sea levels, as a product of the fusion of the large continental land masses. This
event, together with the later separation of the continents from their tectonic plate,
is estimated to have extinguished ninety percent of the species, ushering in the end
of an evolutionary history of over 200 million years of the Paleozoic era. The next
significant mass extinction took place around 200 million years ago. The causes
were multiple and complex, stretching over hundreds of centuries, although two
principal triggering events were a meteor impact—which left a crater of more than
100 kilometers in diameter—and a series of eruptions of major lava flows, all on top
of dramatic climate change. The combination proved fatal to a good proportion of
all living beings. The third and final of the three most recent previous mass extinction events happened about sixty-five million years ago, and ended the lifespan of
the dinosaurs and thousands of other species. On this occasion, climate change,
variation in sea levels, and, above all, the collision of a giant asteroid with Earth
caused fire to break out across a large part of the earth’s surface, setting in motion
titanic ocean waves. Millions of tons of rubble and poisonous gases were thrown
up into the atmosphere, darkening the skies and rendering the life of more than
half the planet’s species unviable.13 After the disappearance of the dinosaurs, many
of the surviving species grew in number, and multiplied to a significant degree.
Fossil records of anatomically modern human beings, have them dating back some
130,000 years, whereas studies on the origins of modern human beings in Africa
trace them back around some 200,000 years.14
Although today there is a fervent discussion surrounding the causes, intensity, and
extension of anthropogenic extinctions, there are many authors who maintain that
many of the larger sized animal species that survived the ice ages ended up becoming extinct toward the end of the last glacial period due to the hunting capabilities
of humans.15 It is true that the diversification and extinction rates vary during the
Cenozoic (post-dinosaur), Mesozoic, and Paleozoic eras, but what is relevant here
is that with the arrival of humans begins an unprecedented (anthropogenic) catastrophe in the Earth’s biodiversity triggering a mass extinction, caused this time by
man. Many authors maintain that it dates back millennia, drastically intensifying
in modern times: “In most cases, the megafauna extinctions began shortly after
the first arrival of prehistoric humans. . . . Of all continents, the megafauna mass
12 See Franz Broswimmer, Ecocide. A Short History of the Mass Extinction of Species (London:
Pluto Press, 2002), pp. 1–3.
13 See Richard Leakey and Roger Levin, Nuestros Orígenes (Barcelona: Crítica, 2015), p. 279.
14 See Broswimmer, Ecocide. p. 20.
15 See Jared Diamond, El Tercer Chimpancé (Barcelona: Random House Mondadori, Debate, 2014),
p. 74.
242
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 41
extinction data are clearest for North America, where seventy species (ninety-five
per cent of the megafauna) disappeared about 11,000 to 14,000 years ago. This is
exactly the time when North America was colonized by humans, and their arrival
and skill as hunters at that time are documented by the appearance of artifacts.
In some cases, accurate dating methods have shown that certain species became
extinct at exactly the times that humans arrived.”16
ANTHROPOGENIC EXTINCTION
AND ANIMAL SPECIESISM
Background extinction is part of a slow, natural process, unlike the current mass
extinction, that is taking place on an accelerated timescale as a result of multiple
anthropogenic causes. The extension of the ethical field to include nonhuman living beings must, therefore, be considered one of the greatest challenges facing both
environmental and animal ethics. The main shared obstacle is, at root, the problem
of speciesism. This particular form of discrimination is derived from a belief in the
superiority of one species over others, a belief that, moreover, advocates for the segregation of species or groups, to the detriment of those which are thereby rendered
vulnerable.17
Explicit use of the term speciesism has until now been mainly limited to references toward nonhuman animals. This bias calls for the extension of antispeciesism
to vegetable species, even in cases where this variant of discrimination is less
evident. This need is particularly apparent from an ecocentric point of view when
we consider that each species constitutes a whole that is distinct from the sum of
the individual beings of which it is composed. From the biocultural ethics perspective, it also becomes clear how certain groups within our species seek and obtain
material and superficial privileges in the world, in ways that impose costs in the
form of a profound global deterioration of the system within which other species
exist.18
Biotic and abiotic system destruction is predicated on a hermeneutic that degrades
the world not only biologically, but also spiritually. The irreversibility of extinction implies a definitive loss to humanity of certain living beings. This constitutes
both a moral, as well as an intellectual impoverishment, as the absence of those
other living beings makes the Earth a more desolate place in which the speciesist
culture has taken hold and become consolidated over the course of thousands of
years. Even when speciesism is understood from the animal sphere perspective,
16
Broswimmer, Ecocide. pp. 24–25.
See Richard Ryder, “Experiments on Animals,” in Animals, Men and Morals, ed. Richard Ryder
(London: Victor Gollancz, 1971), p. 79.
18 See Ricardo Rozzi, “Implications of the Biocultural Ethic for Earth Stewardship,” in Earth
Stewardship: Linking Ecology and Ethics in Theory and Practice, ed. Ricardo Rozzi et al. (Dordrecht:
Springer, 2015), pp. 113–36.
17
Fall 2019
ECOCIDE OR ENVIRONMENTAL SELF-DESTRUCTION?
243
it can be seen that speciesism, and anthropogenic extinction of species, are parts
of the same problem. This problem, which still lacks a solution, nonetheless has a
history.19
THE ANAMNESIS OF SPECIESISM IN
MODERN ANTHROPOGENIC EXTINCTION
The types of anthropogenic depredation that possibly led to the extinction of
megafauna were associated with methods as crude as simply surrounding large
animals and herding them over a precipice. This and other types of archaic practices had become common by the end of the Quaternary in various parts of the
world. Franz Broswimmer emphasizes the fact that physical anthropologists and
palaeontologists alike strongly defend the thesis that the mass extinction of megafauna was not necessarily caused by extra-human factors, but by the massification
of hunting by humans, and that this “preindustrial” form of ecocide can now be
amplified into a “global ecocide.”20 Whether or not this affirmation is valid, all time
periods have seen the repetition of a common pattern: in many of the places that
were colonized by human populations, many populations of vegetable and animal
species entered into a precipitate process of extinction. In more recent times, for
example between the fourteenth and eighteenth centuries, modern trading in furs led
to the extirpation of certain animals from the areas in which they were exploited.
In another example, technological developments in the eighteenth century set in
motion the commercial hunting of cetaceans. A few decades later, whale hunting on
an excessively industrial scale led to a sharp decline in populations, placing whales
at risk of extinction.21 A common modus operandi was repeated: a commercially
desirable species would be discovered, and intensively hunted to the point where
local stocks were exhausted. New populations were then sought out in alternative
locations, only to be subjected, if found, to the same cycle of extermination.
From the ecocide concept perspective, this manner of relating to other species
appears to place human groups at the center of their own universe, one which turns
on an egotistical axis of indifference, and in accordance with a pattern within which
speciesism, reification, pillage, and destruction have been the rule rather than the
exception. The potentially fatal novel aspect resides in the impact of the sheer
reach that these self-destructive dynamics have acquired in the present day. Their
cumulative effects are the inevitable corollary of the anthropogenic disorder that
has caused humans to be responsible for mass extermination of species and the
destruction of biotic and abiotic systems.
Jarred Diamond alludes to other thinkers that have managed to extrapolate from
19 See J. Baird Callicott. “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair,” Environmental Ethics 2 (1980):
311–38.
20 See Broswimmer, Ecocide, pp. 34–35.
21 Ibid., pp.121–22.
244
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 41
the various stages of life, the trajectory that human civilizations have followed, and
may still follow, over time: “Writers find it tempting to draw analogies between those
trajectories of human societies and the trajectories of individual human lives—to
talk of a society's birth, growth, peak, senescence, and death—and to assume that
the long period of senescence that most of us traverse between our peak years and
our deaths also applies to societies.”22
This evolution, however, should not cause us to downplay the incidence of humans
in ecocide and the environmental self-destruction complex. The damage that people
inflict on their surroundings can lead to a long period of decline before societies
finally die. Alternatively, the kinds of problems I have described can culminate in
extreme situations leading to a collapse in society, as was the case for the human
population of Easter Island in the sixteenth century and in the case of the ecological
lessons learnt from the demise of the reindeer population of St. Matthew Island in
the twentieth century.23 In each case, a population—one human and one nonhuman—upon reaching exorbitant numbers and exceeding the carrying capacity of
their respective island, collapsed. While not all now-vanished societies came to
quite such a tragic end, the threat of world ecocide does contemplate the possibility that the fate suffered by past populations, decimated by specific environmental
problems, may be a sign of things to come for the globalized world. The risk of
such an outcome has undoubtedly been radically increased by the multiple factors
discussed above.
It is not clear whether what follows is a gradual, generalized collapse or if
industrial civilization—with its tendency to ruin its surroundings—will decay
into an abrupt end. What is certain, however, is that in either case, the scenarios
for quality of life, whether they be ecocidal or self-destructive, are both sure to
produce degrading, intolerable situations and realities. This situation has already
been faced, of course, by numerous species, but has simply remained invisible to
humans blinkered by speciesism. The avoidance of such a fate is undoubtedly the
most pressing challenge for all environmental and animal ethics.
ANTISPECIESIST DISJUNCTURES BETWEEN
ENVIRONMENTAL AND ANIMAL ETHIC
As soon as a range of speciesist practices were massified and made more acute
through technical-industrial development and the rise of a particular dominant
economic ideology, human beings began to exploit and systematically eliminate
innumerable species from the face of the Earth, spurred on by a host of myths.24
Acquisition of the power to eliminate other species from nature gave rise to the
22
Jared Diamond, Collapse (New York: Penguin Group, 2005), p. 6.
See William R. Catton, Rebasados (México City: Editorial Océano, 2010), pp. 249–50.
24 See Vandana Shiva, Cosecha Robada. El Secuestro del Suministro Mundial de Alimentos (Buenos
Aires: Editorial Paidós, 2009), pp. 15–33.
23
Fall 2019
ECOCIDE OR ENVIRONMENTAL SELF-DESTRUCTION?
245
notion of a responsibility to protect those same species, in a setting that allowed
for their conservation. In this context, some philosophical schools of thought accordingly focused their attention on the survival of species and ecosystem integrity,
while others placed more emphasis on the need to end cruelty toward animals,
making common cause with movements, that for exemple, fight for animal rights
or for the abolition of property rights over animals. Both philosophical schools
of thought concur, however, in a critique of the human being’s conception as the
only being in the world that conceives of itself as an end within itself, and never
as a mean: that is, treating all other species as a mere mean, available to be pressed
into service, while never regarding itself in the same way. Hans Jonas has posited
that every living being should be considered an end within itself, with an intrinsic
value requiring no ulterior justification. From Jonas’ perspective, humans enjoy no
particular advantage over other species, because their “ontological dignity” resides
only in their unique capacity to be custodian and guardian of the others. On this
basis, one can argue that the prototype of responsibility is the intrahuman model
of relationships that can be nonreciprocal, and essentially unilateral.25
Various regions of the world have established protected areas, in a more or less
conscious effort to compensate for the self-destructive tendencies discussed in this
paper by halting the all-out deterioration of the Earth’s surface caused by extractive
industries. Are conservation projects exempt from all speciesist practices? Recognized
park areas have sprung up to preserve particularly spectacular scenic beauty, found in
places that people often must pay in order to visit. This enterprise, however, has no
direct bearing on what such visitors do to favor or oppose the causes that lie behind
the initiatives. There is no doubt that some tourists, captivated by the sight of unique
natural beauty, are in a stronger position to develop a greater awareness towards becoming altruistically involved in causes promoting the protection of unspoilt areas.
Nevertheless, conservationism, even of vast areas, is not immune from any vestige of
speciesism, when, for example, it selects areas and landscapes for conservation based
on their unique appeal to Western aesthetic notions of beauty, while ignoring pastures,
ravines, valleys, or wetlands that may be important for other reasons.26 Nonetheless,
it would be absurd to deny all legitimacy to these projects and conservation areas that
proceed from this aesthetic fascination. Systems of national parks have undoubtedly
helped to protect biodiversity and preserve the beauty of unique landscapes against
the depredations of global anthropogenic destruction. However, it is worth drawing
attention, through this example, the high and profound complexity of speciesism that
sometimes derive to the extreme of confronting environmental with animal ethics.
The search for beauty in practice has been a motivating factor behind many
ecological and animal protection initiatives. The point is that it cannot in itself
25 See Hans Jonas, Das Prinzip Verantwortung (Frankfurt: Editorial Suhrkamp Taschenbuch, 2003),
pp. 177-78.
26 See Adrian Monjeau, “Guns and Roses: Violencia y Belleza en la Relación Hombre-naturaleza,”
Cuadernos de Ética 24, no. 37 (2009): 1–11.
246
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 41
overcome the many levels and manifestations of speciesism when it is informed by
aesthetic norms that can themselves become discriminatory when applied to select
certain species over others. Those not favored may be displaced or even eliminated
from some protected areas as a result. For example, species likely to be singled
out include pandas, dolphins, or huemules (a species of Andean deer) rather than
“ugly” insects, such as cockroaches, beetles, or spiders. These and other selection
criteria are open to critical reflection in regards to the meaning and extent of varying degrees of speciesism.27 Despite these limitations, it is undeniable that caring
for, and valuing, the quality of life of nonhuman species represents at least a move
toward antispeciesist motivations, even when it still proves difficult to fully apply.
BEYOND ANTI-SPECIESIST DISJUNCTURES BETWEEN
ENVIRONMENTAL AND ANIMAL ETHICS:
THE SHARED CHALLENGE
Mere attentiveness to the ability of non-human species to feel pain and suffering
does not automatically spell the end of epistemic and ethical anthropocentrism, as
speciesism implies a perception of the world that treats other species as the property
of humanity, and behaves abusively toward them. However, such attentiveness
does allow us to gain a sense of the breadth of the spectrum of speciesist problems
against which both environmental and animal ethics are forced to struggle. It also
allows us to consider these challenges as an essentially philosophical, and not
merely biological, matter.
Human beings, alone among the species, are responsible for the current condition of the planet, because their condition as sapiens could have permitted them to
avoid setting in motion a chain of events that has led to a possibly ecocidal scenario,
or to the infinite number of environmentally self-destructive dynamics that have
undeniably marked human beings’ speciesist role in Earth’s history.
The environmental problems that put the lives of various species at risk constitute
ever more visible evidence of the need to address ecocidal and self-destructive human tendencies. Homo sapiens is inextricably caught up in these same tendencies,
whether as perpetrators or as victims, as powerful members of the human species
also prey on their own. Any effort to prevent a fatal outcome turns on a need to
understand the problem of speciesism, from within an identity that transcends a
person’s gender, race, origins, ideology, and culture. A common consciousness of
ethics is required, one that attributes at least the same importance to the care and
protection of extra-human relationships as it does to intrahuman ones, and that is
also conscious of the stubborn persistence of speciesism, even within practices that
attempt to combat against it.
27 See Sandra Baquedano, “Conservacionismo en Eras de Especismo,” Luna Azul 41 (2015): 240–53.
Fall 2019
ECOCIDE OR ENVIRONMENTAL SELF-DESTRUCTION?
247
Environmental and animal ethics share a common desire to avoid disastrous
levels of large-scale mortality and destruction; this goes for both biotic and abiotic
species. The prevention of such destruction is one conscious motivation behind
antispeciesism, as it is focused on the value and rights of other species.28
The absence of an ethic capable of stretching beyond humanity means that
anthropocentric cultural or mental schemas eventually turn against themselves.
Scholars are increasingly able to identify and describe certain self-harming behaviors in other species29 or ecosystems.30 The anamnesis of speciesism in the
modern anthropogenic extinction shows that in global terms, these dynamics have
had a similarly (self-) harmful impact on the basis that sustain life on Earth. Global
losses have ensued in the form of the destruction and self-destruction of species.
Human beings are capable of both causing and being caught up in this same (self-)
destruction, for multiple anthropogenic reasons.
28 On the irreconcilable issues existing between both ethics, see Óscar Horta, “The Ethics of the
Ecology of Fear against the Nonspeciesist Paradigm: A Shift in the Aims of Intervention in Nature,”
in Between the Species 13 (2010): 163–87; Catia Faria, “Muerte Entre las Flores: El Conflicto Entre el
Ecologismo y la Defensa de los Animales no Humanos,” in Viento Sur 125 (2012): 67–76.
29 See Vitus Drosher, Überlebensformel: Wie Tiere Umweltgefahren meistern: Können Tiere Selbstmord begehen? (Münich: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1987).
30 See Catton, Rebasados; Diamond, Colapse.