PART1
WELFARE
STATE
Hitotsubashi Journal of Social Studies 33 (2001), pp.37‑43.
C The Hitotsubashi Academy
THE WELFARE STATE INTO THE TWENTY‑FIRST CENTURY
CHRIS PIERSON
Even for its severest critics, almost above all for these critics, the coming of the welfare
state was one of the key transformations of the twentieth century world. In a century marked
by dramatic and sometimes violent change, news of which became ever more instantaneously
transmittable around the globe, the mundane and incremental growth of welfare states often
went under‑reported, at least until the 1970s when the welfare state emerged rather suddenly
as prime suspect in the faltering of the West's 'thirty glorious years' of uninterrupted economic
growth. Yet, however incrementally realised, the growth of welfare states was one of the key
secular trends of the twentieth century. Changes in governments' social expenditure gives us
one very simple indicator of the scale of this transformation. In 1900, Germany and
Switzerland were probably the only states in which social expenditure exceeded three per cent
of GDP. At the end of the period of its most rapid expansion in 1975, average social spending
in the major OECD countries was 22 per cent of a vastly increased GDP (though with Japan
something of an outlier at 13.7%). Expenditure continued to grow, though less rapidly, in the
years of welfare austerity after 1975 with the average spend on social protection in the
European Union, for example, standing at 26.5 per cent in the mid‑1990s. Of course, spending
is only one aspect of the changes associated with growth of the welfare state. Changes of public
expenditure upon this scale bring with them a wholesale transformation in the pattern and
incidence of taxation and a reconstruction of patterns of employment (both by sector and by
gender). They help, by turns, to foster and to mitigate changing patterns of family formation.
In time, these changes lead to new constellations of political (and industrial) interests that
both support (and mobilise against) particular forms of social protection. A society which
employs more university professors than miners may not have progressed but it has certainly
changed! (Figures drawn from Pierson, 1998).
From the Olympian perspective of a new century we can now identify perhaps three key
periods in welfare state development in the most developed economies after 1945 (or, a little
more modestly and accurately, three characteristic phases in the attempts of academic
commentators to make sense of welfare state developments in the last half‑century). Broadly
speaking, the earliest period belongs to the social democratic advocates of expanding social
citizenship (even if this principle was always quite imperfectly realised in practice). At its
simplest, the expectation was that societies of increasing affluence could afford to mitigate
poverty and at the same time to extend the range and quality of social and public services
provided to all its citizens outside the logic of the marketplace (the process later christened
'decommodification'; see Esping‑Andersen, 1990). For parties of the reformist left this
aspiration became a crucial element in a modernised progressive politics. Although a few
voices were consistently raised against this general orientation (most consistently and intelli‑
gently, of course, that of Friedrich Hayek), a sort of grudging consensus emerged around the
38
HITOTSUBASHI JOURNAJ
OF SOCIAL STUDIES
[ July
parameters of this notionally social democratic regime (Hayek, 1944).
As the economic difficulties of the early and mid‑1970s kicked in, in the Anglophone
world at least, what had become a rather tired consensus seemed to vanish almost overnight in
the face of the simple certainties of a revivified neo‑liberalism, whose one‑line account of the
difficulties of Western societies and economies was 'too much (welfare) state, too little
market'. But even in what was widely regarded as the spiritual homeland of the New Right ‑
Mrs. Thatcher's Britain ‑ welfare expenditures (and the overall tax take) continued to creep
upwards and, despite the apocalyptic visions of both advocates and opponents, the welfare
state corpse stubbornly refused to lie down (Pierson, 1994). There were certainly important
changes. Initially, there was a pronounced reduction in the pace of welfare expenditure growth
(in the face of rapidly growing need) and some relocation of spending effort (though very
rarely did these changes spill over into a real fall in overall social spending). Entitlement
tended to become more contingent (especially for the able‑bodied working age population),
co‑funding expanded and the delivery of services moved (some way) from the traditional
patterns of public administration towards semi‑autonomous agencies. At some point, between
Mitterand's about turn in France in 1981/2 and the austerity measures of Sweden's social
democrats in the early 1990s, the citizenship welfare state yielded to a much more cost‑
conscious, employment‑focussed and contingent welfare regime.
As the century moved towards a close, the welfare state as an object of analysis both for
policy‑makers and academic commentators appeared to have changed again. Amongst aca‑
demics, attention increasingly shifted away from competing ideologies of welfare towards an
understanding of welfare processes under the rubric of, and with the tools appropriate to,
'normal politics'. At least in part because more ideological explanations (often derived from
neo‑Marxist or New Right foundations) fitted so poorly with our increasingly detailed
knowledge of what had happened to actually‑existing welfare regimes over the preceding
twenty years, the 'new politics of welfare' tends to be written in the language of a more
empirical political science or political economy ‑ a language variously of rational choices,
interests, institutions and inertia (Pierson, 1996). What these surveys tended to show was that,
whilst there was real and across time substantial change in patterns of welfare state develop‑
ment, this process was driven less by ideology than by the accumulation of underlying social
and economic transformations (with demographic change and globalization being the most
frequently invoked). Nor were all these changes unambiguously in one direction. Whilst most
commentators focussed upon the squeeze that globalization placed upon public expenditure,
others saw it having precisely the opposite effect (Garrett, 1998;Garrett, 1999).
Amongst political practitioners attitudes to the welfare state have shifted perhaps even
more decisively (since these views are not always tempered in the same ways by empirical
evidence). Indeed, having once been cited as that which most decisively distinguished the
post‑war constitutional left from the constitutional right, attitudes to the welfare state no
longer define a clear‑cut ideological division. Whilst those on what remains of the left favour
a little more redistribution and those on the right rather more selective targeting (and more
space for private sector alternatives) a broad swathe of centrist political opinion represents the
'problem' of the welfare state as essentially 'technical'. (Although this co‑exists strangely with
an aspiration to 're‑moralise' some welfare issues.) Democratic publics are thought still to
want good quality public services (in education and health care, for example) and an
undergirding system of income maintenance (for those, perhaps a decreasing number, who are
200 1 J
THE WELFARE STATE INTO
TH E
TWENTY‑FIRST CENTURY
39
thought to deserve it) but they are reluctant to will (any additional) means to secure these
desirable ends. Political elites and those who furnish them with policy advice have come to see
social policy increasingly as the handmaid of economic policy and to operate with an
essentially binary division of welfare expenditure into 'social investment' (good) and 'social
costs' (less good). Generally the ambition has been to shift resources towards 'investment'
(education, training, preventive health care) and to minimise (or reallocate) 'costs' (income
transfers, especially amongst the working‑age population). The lexicon of welfare has been
suitably re‑written. The problem of poverty (reflecting inadequate incomes and to be addressed
through redistribution) is increasingly recast as a problem of social exclusion (whose solution
lies in enabling participation and extending 'real opportunities'). For those of working (and
pre‑working) age, a right to employment (at one time more or less underwritten by the state)
gives way to employability (a personal responsibility for the client to be 'work‑ready'). The
polarity of mutual obligation between state and citizen is reversed (from a state responsibility
for the well being of the unemployed citizen to the responsibility of those without jobs to
enhance their employability as a condition of the state's support). In other areas (such as the
provision of pensions and other elements of what has been social insurance), the aspiration is
to encourage self‑funding (or some public/private mix) amongst those citizens who can aiford
it. Increasingly, political parties contest an ever more crowded political centre ground by
oifering to better each other in maximising efficiency (in both public and private sectors),
increasing employability (with a galaxy of assorted sticks and carrots) and thus increasing the
fruits of economic growth out of which an enhancement of public services can be more or less
painlessly reconciled with expanding private consumption (ironically, an echo of the 'win‑win'
device of 'classical' social democracy).
Just such an agenda appears increasingly as the collective common sense of the interna‑
tional policy‑making community ‑ housed in agencies such as the OECD and the World
Bank. It can also be found in the more directly political context of advocacy of a Third Way.
In its best known formulation (Giddens, 1998; Giddens, 2000) the Third Way set outs to
describe a new politics (of welfare amongst others) that is 'beyond' the older and exhausted
alternatives of neo‑liberal right and 'classical' social democracy ‑ thus opening up the
possibility of a 'renewed' social democracy. For Giddens, the 'classical' social democratic
welfare state was the radical politics of a 'simpler', Iess 'refiexive' modernity and the welfare
state an appropriate mechanism for dealing with external (rather than manufactured) uncer‑
tainty. Reflexive modernity generates a quite new set of circumstances and requires a much
greater emphasis upon the active involvement of citizens (as individuals, families or groups) in
making their own welfare arrangements in a process of active engagement with the state. In
this context, Giddens calls for a new emphasis upon hfe politics ‑ a politics which is about 'how
(as individuals and as collective humanity) we should live in a world where what used to be
fixed either by nature or tradition is now subject to human decisions' ‑ and generative politics ‑
a politics which 'exists in the space that links the state to refiexive mobilization in the society
at large .. a politics which allows individuals and groups to make things happen, rather than
have things happen to them' (Giddens, 1994, p. 15).
From this follows Giddens's commitment to the idea ofpositive welfare: welfare as the
creative, bottom‑up, self‑activity of citizens and their voluntary associations pursuing greater
autonomy and happiness in a 'reflexive engagement with expert systems' (Giddens, 1994, p.
153). Traditional welfare states treated risks as external (as misfortunes, such as ill health or
40
HITOTSUBASHI JOURNAL OF SOCIAL STUDIES
[ July
unemployment, which just happen to people) and its citizens as passive recipients of the state's
largesse. They also operated with a set of assumptions about people's lifestyles (full‑time
lifelong employment for men, childrearing in stable heterosexual marriages for women) which
just do not square with the ways we (choose to) Iive now. Increasingly, so Giddens argues, we
have to recognise that social contingencies, such as ill health, are often the product of
individuals' perverse behaviour or neglect (as in the case of smoking or obesity). Remedies lie
not just in the hands of the state but in individuals, families and groups exercising 'lifestyle
responsibility' (and making themselves happier in the process), often, though not necessarily,
in partnership with the state. Given the greater diversity and changeability in individuals' Iives
(in terms of employment, marital status, household composition and so on) we need welfare
arrangements which foster apolitics ofsecond chances (Giddens, 1994, p. 172). Giddens insists
that existing 'passive' welfare states can create demoralising patterns of welfare dependency
and social exclusion arguing, for example, that retirement at 65 is an arbitrary imposition of
inactivity upon a (growing) group of the population which is generally healthy and keen to be
economically active (Giddens, 1994; Giddens, 2000, pp. 39‑40). What is needed is a welfare
regime which is empowering, which provides the opportunities (and sometimes the resources)
which will enable individuals to take responsibility for their own well‑being.
The welfare state that emerges from these changes is enabling or facilitating rather than
providing. Globalization requires that states should focus upon the 'competitiveness' of their
increasingly exposed economies ‑ above all, raising the productivity of its domestic labour
supply (justifying expenditure upon education and training). If standards of living are to be
protected in an increasingly competitive global marketplace, developed economies have to
secure a productivity premium. They have to be able to develop a workforce which is
multi‑skilled, fiexible, adaptable and 'clever' ‑ or they will find themselves engaged in a battle
to provide cheap labour which they cannot win. Demographic changes (above all the ageing
of the population) reinforce this imperative for greater productivity and require that states
seek to displace social costs (i.e. the income maintenance of the elderly) upon citizens
themselves. Increasingly there is an attempt to redefine the role of the welfare state for the
elderly in terms of the guarantee of incomes (and thus selective intervention) rather than
universal provision on the basis of a shared citizenship. Overall this suggests a future in which
welfare states focus upon social investment rather than social costs. Welfare states should be
enabling rather than providing, customised rather than generic, smaller but smarter.
This is not the only possible response to those changes that are said to make more
traditional forms of the welfare state unsustainable. For a really radical alternative ‑ one
which its supporters see as uniquely suited to the new circumstances of the twenty‑first century
e might turn to the advocates of a Citizen's Basic Income. Advocates of BI turn the issue
‑
of employment and participation on its head. The core initiative is to introduce for all citizens
an unconditional basic income:
an income paid by the government to each full member of society ( l) even if she is not
willing to work, (2) irrespective of being rich or poor, (3) whoever she lives with, and (4)
(Van Parijs, 1995, p. 35)
no matter which part of the country she lives in.
Advocates of a BI begin from some of the same social and economic changes as do more
mainstream advocates of reform. They too focus upon the changed world of work, but draw
quite opposite conclusions. The attempt to reconcile justice and efficiency under post‑war
welfare state regimes was built around progressive taxation, full employment, corporatist
200l]
THE WELFARE STATE INTO THE TWENTY‑FIRST CENTURY
41
industrial relations, massified semi‑skilled labour, Fordist labour processes and constrained
capital mobility. That world is gone. Where lifelong employment (and its attendant pensions
and social insurance rights) are much less certain, where relations between men and women
and between both and the world of formal employment are so changed, where marriage is
increasingly a serial experience, the old remedies are increasingly unworkable. The key
ambition of newer employment‑oriented social policies is to seek to reproduce a political
economy of full employment (though in an updated and gender‑neutral way). But this is
impossible. Jobs can only be created (with great difficulty) by 'fiexibilisation' ‑ Iowering wages
and conditions ‑ and stable careers or, a little less grandly, steady employment from 16 to 64
(which made many aspects of social insurance work) seem to have disappeared. Those who are
employed claim to have too much work, whilst those who cannot get a job have inadequate
incomes. This is perverse. Technology has rendered much work redundant and the aspiration
to grow our way to fuller employment comes up against real ecological limits. The problem is
not a shortage of work but the relationship between employment and income. To secure the
coupling of social justice to economic efficiency (and ecological sustainability) now means
partially disengaging income from employment ‑ and moving to the maximum‑sustainable
Basic Income for all citizens.
In the face of those who argue that with a BI no one would ever leave the beach,
supporters insist that a maximal BI would actually prove to be economically efficient (as well
as socially just). Critics insist that a BI set at even a quite modest level would undermine
incentives, discouraging the less skilled from entering the labour market and placing a fiscal
burden upon capital and more skilled workers which would encourage them to lessen their
effort or withdraw from the formal economy altogether. Supporters of a BI are generally
sanguine about these objections. At one level, they resist the idea that maximising growth and
employment are unqualified goods. Insisting that there is an ecological limit to 'justice through
growth', they encourage us to think of solutions that would involve both working and
consuming less. Philippe Van Parijs (1995), for example, argues that what we should be
seeking to maximise is not income but 'real freedom for all' (allowing individuals to choose as
freely as possible what it is they want to do with their lives). Supporters of BI argue further
that traditional accounts (and welfare states) have always privileged paid employment over
other forms of work (especially the unpaid labour of women within the household) which have
often been seen not to count as work at all. But even within a more traditional economic mode
of accounting, BI is said to be efficient. It allows individuals to take on work at very low wages
(because of the income support that BI would provide). It would allow workers to retrain
without excessive cost, to start new enterprises without undue personal risk. It would
encourage greater fiexibility in forms of work and easier movement between household and
employment. In general, a BI is said to deliver 'flexibility with security', a combination which
'completely overshadows' concerns about the disincentive effects of the new (and extensive)
tax regime upon which it would be based.
Conclusion
I have confined my comments here to two quite differing responses to the challenges of the
new century's changing world of welfare. It seems clear that, for now at least, the future is
42
HITOTSUBASHI JOURNAL OF SOCIAL STUDIES
[ July
much more likely to belong to the advocacy of Giddens and the OECD than the supporters of
a Basic Income. Given this, it is important to record that the belief that the future shape of
welfare policy is unavoidably given by processes of globalisation and societal ageing has been
systematically overstated. Although it is an argument that cannot be developed here (see
Pierson, 2001), globalisation is an uneven process and societal ageing will vary substantially
amongst OECD states (consider, for example, the contrast between the UK and Japan). It is
not the absolute level of social expenditure but its relation to other aspects of government
policy (above all, taxation) that is crucial. Simply put, international investors tend to punish
not big spenders but persistent debtors (Swank, 1998). It also clear that even where the
challenge is pressing there are a range of options open to policy‑makers (Boix, 1998). At the
same time, we need to be sure that our overview is broad enough to capture all the significant
elements of any given social protection regime. Australia is an interesting case. Australia has
featured frequently in OECD and World Bank accounts of 'good' welfare regimes, Iargely
because it is comparatively inexpensive and strongly targeted. But, in fact, it is a country which
has managed historically to combine comparatively low levels of welfare expenditure with a
relatively low dispersion of incomes, Iargely through the judicial manipulation of labour
markets and wage arrangements.
Experience suggests that however severe may be the challenges of delivering welfare in the
new century, policy change is likely to be incremental (if cumulatively substantial). It will also
vary substantially from place to place. (The impact of globalisation varies significantly from
state to state and the same is true of the extent and consequences of demographic change) . At
least two aspects of the traditional welfare regime which have persisted through the recent
changes and into the new century look set to present a challenge in the longer term. First,
welfare states remain (despite the growth of international policy communities and the
experience of the European Union) essentially national institutions and principally the domain
of more developed (and affluent) states. Whatever happens to redistribution (whether of
resources or opportunities) within the more affluent states, one of the great challenges of the
new century will be to address the question of widening inequalities (and apparatuses of
redistribution) at the global level. Secondly, welfare states have always relied upon economic
growth to make their politics run. Whilst Giddens has brought an ecological sensibility into the
mainstream of welfare debate, it remains the case that welfare state solutions still rely upon
economic growth to finesse distributional issues. If global ecological problems are real
problems in the new century (and surely the disagreement is only over the location and extent
of the challenge) the attendant problem is to find solutions to the first issue (global inequality)
without a straightforward recourse to the growih option. Herein lie the really big challenges
for the politics of welfare in the twenty‑first century.
SCHOOL OF PoLmcs, UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM, UK
REFERENCES
Boix, C. 1998 Political Parties, Growth and Equality. Cambridge: CUP.
Esping‑Andersen, G. 1990 The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Cambridge: Polity.
Garrett, G. 1998 Partisan Politics in the Global Economy. Cambridge: CUP.
THE WELFARE STATE INTO THE TWENTY‑FIRST CENTURY
200 1 J
43
Garrett, G. 1999 Globalization and Government Spending Around the World. Working
Paper: (http://pantheon.yale.edu/ gmg8)
Giddens, A. 1994 Beyond Left and Right. Cambridge: Polity.
Giddens, A. 1998 The Third Way Cambridge: Polity.
Giddens, A. 2000 The Third Way and Its Critics. Cambridge: Polity.
Hayek, F. 1944 The Road to Serfdom. London: Routledge, Kegan Paul.
Pierson, C. 1998 Beyond the Welfare State, (Second edition). Cambridge: Polity.
Pierson, C. 2001 Hard Choices: Social Democracy in the 2lst Century. Cambridge: Polity.
Pierson, P. 1994 Dismantling the Welfare State? Reagan, Thatcher, and the politics of
retrenchment. Cambridge: CUP.
Pierson, P. 1996 'The New Politics of the Welfare State', World Politics, 48, 143‑79
Swank, D. 1998 'Funding the Welfare State: Globalization and the Taxation of Business in
Advanced Market Economies', Political Studies, 46 4, 671‑92
van Parijs, P. 1995 Real Freedom for All: What (if anything) can justify capitalism? Oxford:
OUP .