Intra-Party Democracy: A Functionalist Account
Samuel Bagg, University of Oxford
Udit Bhatia, University of Sheffield
NB: This is the final pre-publication draft of an article that has been published at the Journal of
Political Philosophy. Please cite the published version. Email me for a copy, or if you have access
through your institution, you can download it here: doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12270
Abstract: This paper articulates a functionalist account of intra-party democracy (IPD). Like
realist critics, we insist that IPD practices be evaluated on the basis of whether they facilitate
resistance to domination and capture at the level of the polity as a whole, and therefore accept
certain realist worries about IPD. Yet realists neglect the possibility that wealthy interests could
control the political agenda by capturing all viable parties simultaneously—and that mass-facing
IPD could counter this threat of oligarchic agenda capture. Taking this as the key function of IPD
within broader democratic systems, we conclude that inclusionary party reform is less urgent in
more flexible party systems, where dissenters are better able to resist this threat from within the
framework of inter-party competition. Regardless of the context, meanwhile, we also conclude
that mass-facing IPD practices should aim at enabling ordinary members and supporters of a party
to resist agenda capture by oligarchic interests. Though we stop short of defending any particular
set of reforms, we reject the emphasis of recent IPD advocates on individualized forms of
deliberative participation, in favor of a more oppositional and collectively-oriented approach—on
the grounds that the latter is more likely to encourage the development of effective institutions of
countervailing power.
Key Words: political parties, democratic theory, countervailing power, organizing, deliberation
Author Bios: Samuel Bagg is Postdoctoral Prize Research Fellow in Politics at Nuffield College,
Oxford (
[email protected]). Udit Bhatia is Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of
Sheffield.
Acknowledgments: For feedback and discussion, the authors are very grateful to Pierre-Etienne
Vandamme, participants in the 2020 REDEM workshop on representative democracy, and several
anonymous reviewers.
§I. Introduction
The organization of political parties presents a serious puzzle for democratic theory. On the
one hand, nearly everyone recognizes their essential role in supporting collective decision-making
and popular accountability. On the other hand, many parties are internally undemocratic, inviting
precious little input from ordinary members and supporters. Indeed, political parties have often
been accused of entrenching various interests and blocking democratic progress.
In response, many demand the internal democratization of parties. According to “isomorphic”
approaches, more specifically, party platforms should reflect the views of their core members and
supporters, realizing the same democratic ideals of deliberation, public reason, and participation
demanded of the polity itself.1 On this account, indeed, mass-facing forms of intra-party
democracy (henceforth IPD) are a clear requirement of democratic legitimacy: the only remaining
“puzzle” is how to implement them.
Yet others criticize this isomorphic approach as naïve. If democracy is really about the benefits
of inter-party competition—as democratic realists like Schumpeter have argued—then strong and
centralized parties may be its very essence.2 From their “systemic” perspective, indeed,
democratizing parties could actually weaken democracy writ large, by undermining the ability of
party elites to compete effectively against rivals.3 Properly conceived, in other words, democratic
ideals make no demand for mass-facing IPD to begin with—again leaving no genuine puzzle.
Martin Ebeling and Fabio Wolkenstein, “Exercising Deliberative Agency in Deliberative Systems,” Political Studies
66, no. 3 (2018): 635–50; Jan Teorell, “A Deliberative Defence of Intra-Party Democracy,” Party Politics 5, no. 3
(1999): 363–82; Jonathan White and Lea Ypi, The Meaning of Partisanship (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016).
2
Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (New York: Harper, 1942).See also Elmer Eric
Schattschneider, Party Government (New York: Farrar and Reinhart, 1942); Ian Shapiro, Politics against Domination
(Cambridge: Belknap, 2016); Samuel Bagg, “The Power of the Multitude: Answering Epistemic Challenges to
Democracy,” American Political Science Review 112, no. 4 (2018): 891–904.
3
Frances McCall Rosenbluth and Ian Shapiro, Responsible Parties: Saving Democracy from Itself (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2018).
1
1
Rejecting both views as overly simplistic, we develop a functionalist account of mass-facing
IPD. To begin with, we endorse the systemic evaluative approach favored by realist critics, and
we share their concern that intra-party conflict could undermine inter-party competition. We also
recognize, however, that certain forms of mass-facing IPD may perform a critical democratic role
within certain contexts—namely, preventing wealthy elites from controlling the agenda through
influence over the leaders of all viable parties—which actually enhances inter-party competition.
Rather than offering universal praise or censure, we hold that the democratic value of any massfacing IPD practice hinges on its tendency to facilitate resistance to oligarchic agenda capture.
Adopting this functionalist account has important consequences for the way we think about
intra-party democracy. First, the desirability of inclusionary party reform will vary by context,
depending on whether its function is already duplicated by other elements of the political system.
In particular, oligarchic capture of any given party is less threatening to broader democratic goals
when internal dissenters can relatively easily found new parties. Under more rigid party systems
where this is more difficult, by contrast, party reform within existing parties will be more urgent.
No matter the context, second, certain IPD practices will perform this anti-oligarchic function
better than others. As certain recent advocates have insisted, not all forms of mass-facing IPD face
the same challenges as the aggregative practices criticized by realists. Where these “revisionists”
favor deliberative forms of participation, however, our functionalist account suggests a focus on
building organized forms of collective countervailing power instead. While this goal overlaps at
times with that of enabling deliberative self-expression, our account also diverges from revisionist
approaches in several ways. For one, the function of mass-facing IPD might be fulfilled equally
well—if not better—by tight integration with external mass organizations such as labor unions,
rather than internal practices designed by party elites. Regardless of its institutional location, more
2
broadly, the goal of mass participation should not be individual self-expression but the creation of
countervailing organizational capacity through solidarity, social ties, and habits of collective
action. These, we argue, are the best tools ordinary people have in fighting oligarchic capture of
parties.
§II. A functionalist approach to intra-party democracy: preliminary arguments
We define “intra-party democracy” as any practice that limits the centralized discretionary
control exercised by top-level party leaders, by opening decision-making processes to input from
wider circles of party stakeholders. In this article, more specifically, we focus largely on massfacing practices that invite participation from ordinary party members and supporters.4 We also
support elite-facing forms of IPD, which constrain top-level leaders by empowering mid-level
elites such as backbenchers, party officials, and local or regional politicians. Since these practices
are endorsed by nearly everyone involved, however, we devote most of our attention in what
follows to the more contentious questions surrounding mass-facing IPD.5
A. An isomorphic approach: commonsense arguments for intra-party democracy
Many commonsense arguments for mass-facing IPD share the same basic structure. It is widely
believed, first, that the legitimacy of representative democracy hinges on a secure principal-agent
4
Perhaps most commonly, this means leadership selection through primary elections open to all supporters (as in the
US) or intra-party elections open to dues-paying members (as in the UK Labour Party). Rank-and-file supporters
might also participate in candidate selection through primaries, open lists and preference rankings, or recall
mechanisms between elections. (See Jonathan White and Lea Ypi, “Reselection and Deselection in the Political Party,”
in The Politics of Recall Elections, ed. Yanina Welp and Laurence Whitehead (Palgrave MacMillan, 2020), 179–99.)
Finally, ordinary people may contribute to platform construction through participation in local branch deliberations
or larger party congresses, as suggested by Enrico Biale and Valeria Ottonelli, “Intra-Party Deliberation and Reflexive
Control within a Deliberative System,” Political Theory 47, no. 4 (2019): 500–526; Fabio Wolkenstein, “A
Deliberative Model of Intra-Party Democracy,” Journal of Political Philosophy 24, no. 3 (2016): 297–320. As we
argue below, the goals of mass-facing IPD can also be served by integrating external mass-membership organizations
into party decision-making procedures, and this strategy also belongs in this category.
5
Matteo Bonotti, Partisanship and Political Liberalism in Diverse Societies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017),
27.
3
relationship between elected officials and ordinary citizens.6 Yet in practice, politicians often
appear to serve wealthy elites and other concentrated interests, rather than the people at large7—
and the mediation of political parties has long been blamed for facilitating this process of capture.8
In response, reformers have often sought to limit parties’ role by enabling people to vote directly
on legislation, through mechanisms such as initiatives and referendums.9 Recognizing that parties
are inescapable in modern politics, however, many have also sought to democratize parties
themselves, through mass-facing IPD, in the hope that broader participation in party governance
could restore the principal-agent relationship between ordinary citizens and public officials.10
We characterize this normative logic as isomorphic, in that it aims to democratize parties in
roughly the same ways—and for roughly the same reasons—as the political system writ large. And
whenever inclusionary party reforms are proposed, a version of this isomorphic logic is nearly
always present. Because it is so widely accepted in several countries, meanwhile, many party
leaders have also come to see such reforms as a strategic move that will endear them to voters and
help them win elections. For instance, primaries became central to leadership selection in both
major US parties after the tumultuous 1968 election, when the Democrats concluded that engaging
ordinary supporters could heal divisions and renew broad investment in the party in the wake of a
devastating loss. (The Republicans, not to be outdone, followed suit).11 As traditional European
6
See, e.g., Thomas Christiano, The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory (Boulder, CO:
Westview Press, 1996); Eric Beerbohm, In Our Name: The Ethics of Democracy (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 2012).
7
See, e.g., Martin Gilens and Benjamin I. Page, “Testing Theories of American Politics: Elites, Interest Groups, and
Average Citizens,” Perspectives on Politics 12, no. 03 (2014): 564–81.
8
For an overview, see Nancy Rosenblum, On the Side of the Angels: An Appreciation of Parties and Partisanship
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010), 165–209.
9
Rosenblum, 254–315.
10
See Eric Lawrence, Todd Donovan, and Shaun Bowler, “The Adoption of Direct Primaries in the United States,”
Party Politics 19, no. 1 (2013): 3–18.
11
For an overview, see Russell Muirhead, The Promise of Party in a Polarized Age (Cambridge, Massachusetts:
Harvard University Press, 2014), 146–72.
4
parties have shed their social base and lost ground to novel challengers in recent years, similarly,
they have increasingly turned to various forms of IPD in an effort to regain mass allegiance and
investment.12
B. A systemic perspective: realist objections to the commonsense view
At first blush, these intuitive arguments for IPD appear quite plausible. Empirical support,
however, is mixed at best—and many realist critics doubt that they provide a solid justification for
mass-facing IPD. According to Rosenbluth and Shapiro, for instance, the most important impact
of the post-1968 reforms in the United States has been to accelerate polarization.13 This, in turn,
has only amplified distrust of politicians and disaffection with politics—precisely the trends that
internal democratization was supposed to reverse. Similarly, they claim, recent democratizing
reforms have only accelerated the decline of traditional European parties. Given that we cannot
know what would have happened if these reforms had not been implemented, such causal claims
are difficult to evaluate. Nevertheless, these correlations are not encouraging for IPD advocates.
Meanwhile, the principal-agent model of representation that motivates many of their more
theoretical claims is widely regarded as empirically inaccurate and normatively misleading. To
start with, most of our political opinions appear to reflect our social and partisan identities, rather
than a genuinely independent process of reasoning and will-formation.14 This is not merely a
contingent result of bad policies or a lack of civic virtue: given the vast number of issues parties
must address, even the best-informed must rely on cues from specialized elites. Thus, political
Piero Ignazi, “The Four Knights of Intra-Party Democracy: A Rescue for Party Delegitimation,” Party Politics 26,
no. 1 (2020): 9–20; Rosenbluth and Shapiro, Responsible Parties.
13
Rosenbluth and Shapiro, Responsible Parties.
14
Christopher H. Achen and Larry M. Bartels, Democracy for Realists: Why Elections Do Not Produce Responsive
Government (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2016); Milton Lodge and Charles S. Taber, The Rationalizing
Voter (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013); Lilliana Mason, Uncivil Agreement: How Politics
Became Our Identity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018); Samuel Bagg, “Can Deliberation Neutralise
Power?,” European Journal of Political Theory 17, no. 3 (2018): 257–79.
12
5
parties could never serve purely as the “agents” of the voters they purport to represent. Rather,
party elites will always have significant discretion in shaping the party platform—and, in turn,
many of the views of the “principals” from whom they are supposed to take their orders.15 As such,
few contemporary theorists of representation retain a pure principal-agent model as the ideal.16
Given a realistic appraisal of the dynamics of mass politics in contemporary democracies, in
fact, many political scientists worry that mass-facing IPD is likely to exacerbate the problems of
elite capture that it is ostensibly intended to resolve. Richard Katz and Peter Mair, for instance,
argue that engaging the broader membership in platform construction only strengthens the power
of top-level leaders.17 Compared to mid-level elites, ordinary members typically have less capacity
for independent organization, and are less likely to resist the influence of the most visible popular
figures. Like nearly all participants in debates about party reform, therefore, Katz and Mair agree
that elite-facing IPD is crucial for preventing entrenchment, capture, and “cartelization” among
top-level leaders. What they suggest, however, is that mass-facing IPD can undermine these goals;
essentially handing power back to the most well-known top-level leaders.
Relatedly, many critics also charge that mass-facing IPD empowers vocal minorities who value
“ideological purity” over electoral competitiveness.18 If top-level leaders must cater to the
idiosyncratic preferences of the most active and enthusiastic participants in intra-party procedures,
party platforms will reliably shift to the extremes. If granted the discretion to maximize their vote
For an extended version of this argument, see Chapter 2 (“Beyond Policy Responsiveness”) of Samuel Bagg, The
Dispersion of Power: A Critical Realist Theory of Democracy, forthcoming with Oxford University Press.
16
Lisa Disch, “Toward a Mobilization Conception of Democratic Representation,” American Political Science Review
105, no. 1 (2011): 100–114; Andrew Sabl, “The Two Cultures of Democratic Theory: Responsiveness, Democratic
Quality, and the Empirical-Normative Divide,” Perspectives on Politics 13, no. 2 (2015): 345–65.
17
Richard S. Katz and Peter Mair, “The Cartel Party Thesis: A Restatement,” Perspectives on Politics 7, no. 4 (2009):
759. See also Jonathan Hopkin, “Bringing the Members Back in?: Democratizing Candidate Selection in Britain and
Spain,” Party Politics 7, no. 3 (2001): 343–61.
18
Richard S. Katz and William P. Cross, “Problematizing Intra-Party Democracy,” in The Challenges of Intra-Party
Democracy, ed. William P. Cross and Richard S. Katz (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 171.
15
6
share in the general population, by contrast, they are more likely to appeal to the median voter,
yielding greater systemic stability and overall responsiveness.
From a systemic perspective, after all, parties’ main task is not to enact the preferences of their
core supporters, but to pursue and wield power in the public interest. Whether pitching a platform
on the campaign, pursuing a coherent agenda in government, or uniting opposition to incumbent
abuses, top-level party leaders must maintain a diverse coalition long enough to take collective
action in service of common goals. As such, they must articulate a political vision that is at once
reasonably specific, broadly attractive, and emotionally salient—a difficult balance to strike. In
order to perform their democratic functions effectively, therefore, party leaders need significant
discretion over policy, messaging, and strategy. From the voters’ perspective, meanwhile, a system
of strong and centralized parties simplifies electoral choices, enabling ordinary people without
much specialized knowledge to exercise their political agency with maximal reliability.19
Rather than broadly enhancing political agency, realists charge, mass-facing IPD benefits
highly active and informed voters at the expense of most others. By proliferating ambiguity and
complexity within the political system, it fractures the public’s limited attention and attenuates its
ability to hold leaders accountable. Far from limiting the influence of wealthy elites, Rosenbluth
and Shapiro surmise, “weakening party control over decisions, candidates, and leadership selection
creates only the illusion of more grassroots democracy. In reality, it empowers intense minorities
19
Some have read skeptical arguments about voter competence—i.e., that voters are largely uninformed and
powerfully influenced by social identity—as evidence against Rosenbluth and Shapiro’s view. See, e.g., Peter
Giraudo, “The Case for Democratic Intra-Party Selection” (American Political Science Association, Los Angeles
(online), 2020). Yet even resolute skeptics like Achen and Bartels only argue that accountability is difficult; not that
it is entirely impossible: on the margins, incumbent performance and other programmatic factors may still make a
difference. If voters really behave as skeptics claim, indeed, that is all the more reason to sharpen the stakes of their
choices as much as possible.
7
at the expense of most voters, and it promotes the capture, corruption, and lack of responsiveness
that lead people to demand decentralizing control in the first place.”20
C. A revisionist alternative: rescuing intra-party democracy?
In our view, realist critics are right to be skeptical of the most common arguments for massfacing IPD. We also endorse their systemic evaluative perspective: whatever intrinsic value there
may be in popular control of parties as such, the democratic character of the political system as a
whole surely deserves priority over that of its component parts.21 For two reasons, however, we
reject the categorical dismissal of mass-facing IPD by realists like Rosenbluth and Shapiro.
First, their exclusive reliance on inter-party competition to advance democratic goals ignores
the possibility of elite collusion across party lines.22 In a common process known as “cartelization,”
for instance, the “major governing parties” in a polity “agree to maintain state party funding for
the opposition when in power,”23 and lower the costs of competition by adopting a set of “agreed
goals.”24 As such, they begin to compete on efficient management of the polity, rather than
ideological cleavages, and come to “increasingly resemble one another.”25 And while the specific
phenomenon of cartelization has emerged most clearly in certain European party systems over the
past few decades, elements of an elite governing consensus can be found in every democracy.
By employing their outsized leverage to influence the leaders of all viable parties at once, in
short, wealthy elites and other groups with concentrated interests and extensive resources can often
20
Rosenbluth and Shapiro, Responsible Parties, 21.
To be clear, this broadly instrumentalist approach to IPD does not entail instrumentalism about democracy itself:
after all, there are plenty of “intrinsic” reasons we might value accountability and oppose capture by narrow elites.
22
Emilee Chapman, “Against Responsible Parties” (American Political Science Association, Los Angeles (online),
2020).
23
Jonathan Hopkin, “The Problem with Party Finance: Theoretical Perspectives on the Funding of Party Politics,”
Party Politics 10, no. 6 (2004): 635.
24
Peter Mair and Richard S. Katz, “Party Organization, Party Democracy, and the Emergence of the Cartel Party,” in
Party System Change: Approaches and Interpretations, ed. Peter Mair (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 115.
25
Katz and Mair, “The Cartel Party Thesis,” 757.
21
8
keep certain threatening issues off the political agenda entirely. In particular, the phenomenon we
call “oligarchic agenda capture”—reflected in a governing consensus maintained by all viable
parties that protects the interests of extremely concentrated wealth—is strikingly resilient across
the democratic world.26 It thus illustrates a critical weak point of inter-party competition, which
appears to face special challenges in contesting this form of capture.
Second, realists like Rosenbluth and Shapiro are too quick to paint all forms of mass-facing
IPD with the same brush. Although they accept many realist criticisms of existing IPD practices,
for instance, Fabio Wolkenstein and other revisionist advocates of inclusionary party reform point
out that mass-facing IPD practices might be designed differently—transcending the simplistic
principal-agent model assumed by commonsense views, for instance, and avoiding the tendency
of plebiscitary methods to further strengthen top-level leaders.27 Rather than simply aggregating
the unreflective opinions of rank-and-file members via primaries and open lists, more specifically,
revisionist IPD advocates demand the proliferation of opportunities for egalitarian, open-ended
exchanges of reasons between ordinary people and party elites.28
26
Thomas Piketty, Capital and Ideology, trans. Arthur Goldhammer (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 2020); Jeffrey A.
Winters, Oligarchy (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011). Following Arlen “Aristotle and the
Problem of Oligarchic Harm: Insights for Democracy,” European Journal of Political Theory 18, no. 3 (2019): 394.,
we understand oligarchs as agents who “retain personal access to massive concentrated wealth” and “deploy their
wealth to achieve discretionary influence in the public domain.” As a class, oligarchs share “an overriding focus on
wealth and income preservation,” which cuts across their other interests (398), and which they protect successfully
within a range of political systems. In democracies, oligarchs pursue their interests via agenda capture as well as other
methods like campaign donations, lobbying, and bureaucratic capture Jeffrey A. Winters, “Wealth Defense and the
Complicity of Liberal Democracy,” in NOMOS LVIII: Wealth, ed. Jack Knight and Melissa Schwartzberg (New York:
NYU Press, 2017), 158–225.
27
Carlo Invernizzi-Accetti and Fabio Wolkenstein, “The Crisis of Party Democracy, Cognitive Mobilization, and the
Case for Making Parties More Deliberative,” American Political Science Review 111, no. 1 (2017): 97–109; Ebeling
and Wolkenstein, “Exercising Deliberative Agency in Deliberative Systems”; Fabio Wolkenstein, Rethinking Party
Reform (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019).
28
Fabio Wolkenstein, “Intra-Party Democracy beyond Aggregation,” Party Politics 24, no. 4 (2018): 323–34; Fabio
Wolkenstein, “Agents of Popular Sovereignty,” Political Theory 47, no. 3 (2019): 338–62.
9
D. A functionalist approach: beyond realism and revisionism
In our view, revisionists are right to insist that other models of mass-facing IPD may be less
vulnerable to certain of the worries realists have raised about practices that are currently in wide
use. More specifically, we endorse their emphasis on multi-level organizational structures as a way
of avoiding the plebiscitary tendencies of purely aggregative practices. Where revisionists retain
the isomorphic goal of ensuring that party platforms reflect the views of core supporters, however,
we focus resolutely on the systemic aims of inter-party competition, and therefore propose a more
precise role for mass-facing IPD: i.e., resisting the sort of oligarchic agenda capture that seems
especially resilient to the power-neutralizing discipline provided by inter-party competition. While
revisionist reforms may occasionally support this narrower goal, their anti-oligarchic tendencies
will be limited. Because they foster individual self-expression rather than collective power, indeed,
deliberative forums will often favor wealthier and better-organized interests.
What emerges from our discussion, then, is a functionalist account of intra-party democracy,
which seeks to evaluate mass-facing IPD practices with reference to their performance of a specific
role within a broader framework of inter-party competition. In what follows, we first expand on
that function: i.e., facilitating resistance to oligarchic agenda capture (§III). We then ask when
inclusionary party reform is most needed to serve this function—arguing that it is relatively less
urgent in more flexible party systems, where dissenters have other ways of challenging a governing
consensus (§IV). Finally, we ask what kinds of inclusionary party reform will fulfill this function
most effectively, concluding that the goal of resisting oligarchic agenda capture is best served by
practices that generate solidarity and organizational capacity among ordinary people (§V).
10
§III. The systemic function of mass-facing intra-party democracy: facilitating
resistance to oligarchic agenda capture
On the broadly realist view we have accepted here, the key aims of electoral competition are
to minimize domination and prevent the capture of state power by any particular faction or elite.29
To the extent that mass-facing IPD practices threaten these systemic aims by constraining toplevel party leaders, then, realist critics are right to be concerned. In dismissing all forms of massfacing IPD as harmful on balance, however, realists underestimate the danger that cross-party
collusion among wealthy elites will yield oligarchic agenda capture—as well as the potential for
certain inclusionary party reforms to obstruct this process. As we argue in this section, indeed, that
should be seen as the key democratic function of mass-facing IPD.
Realists like Rosenbluth and Shapiro typically rely on a combination of inter-party competition
and elite-facing IPD as the best formula for preventing systemic domination or capture. Most
basically, they claim, inter-party competition incentivizes parties to attract a majority coalition by
serving the interests of the median voter30—and in order to pursue this goal effectively, top-level
leaders need significant discretion.31 Some degree of elite-facing IPD is necessary, however, to
ensure that backbenchers can replace top-level leaders who turn out to be ineffective, corrupt, or
ideologically motivated, and therefore unable to achieve that goal.32 When these two conditions
are met, then, policy convergences can generally be supposed to reflect clear preferences among
the electorate at large, rather than the failure of party leaders to identify and cater to a potential
majority coalition.33
29
Adam Przeworski, Why Bother With Elections? (Cambridge: Polity, 2018); Shapiro, Politics against Domination;
Bagg, “The Power of the Multitude.”
30
Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper, 1957).
31
Shapiro, Politics against Domination. See also Samuel Bagg and Isak Tranvik, “An Adversarial Ethics for
Campaigns and Elections,” Perspectives on Politics 17, no. 4 (2019): 973–87.
32
Ian Shapiro, “What Are Parties For?” (American Political Science Association, Los Angeles (online), 2020).
33
Rosenbluth and Shapiro, Responsible Parties, 39.
11
As critics have pointed out, however, Downsian convergence models “exclude the possibility
of influence by money or interest groups and maximize the apparent power of ordinary voters, by
making a series of highly restrictive and quite implausible assumptions.”34 Like the principal-agent
model often criticized by realists, for one, such models also presume that party elites primarily
respond to constituents’ pre-existing preferences, when in fact they often have a large role in
shaping the views of rank-and-file supporters. More broadly, median-voter models also presume
that voters are representative of the population, and that they vote based on an accurate
understanding of each party’s platform. Yet oligarchic elites often wield their outsized material
power to shape both the composition of the electorate and the terms of public discourse to their
advantage—thereby enabling parties to win elections without serving the median voter.
Compared to their resilient need to curry favor with wealthy elites, indeed, the incentives of
party leaders to serve the diffuse interests of poorly informed, poorly organized, and poorly
resourced constituents may be quite weak. On most issues, after all, ordinary people tend to adopt
the positions of their preferred party.35 By contrast, well-informed, well-organized, and wellresourced elites have little trouble discerning and pursuing their interests through pressure on
officials. On certain issues, of course, the views of ordinary people may be more recalcitrant,
forcing party leaders to disappoint wealthy donors in order to remain electorally competitive.36
Given the public’s finite and fractured attention, however, only a tiny minority of issues can be
salient at any time—and on others, wealthy interests remain privileged.37 In fact, parties may
Jeffrey A. Winters and Benjamin I. Page, “Oligarchy in the United States?,” Perspectives on Politics 7, no. 4 (2009):
742.
35
Achen and Bartels, Democracy for Realists.
36
Mark Smith, American Business and Political Power: Public Opinion, Elections, and Democracy (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2000); David Vogel, “Political Science and the Study of Corporate Power: A Dissent
from the New Conventional Wisdom,” British Journal of Political Science 17, no. 4 (1987): 385–408.
37
See especially Pepper D. Culpepper, Quiet Politics and Business Power: Corporate Control in Europe and Japan
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010). Oligarchic capture is especially pronounced—and welldocumented—in the US Larry M. Bartels, Unequal Democracy: The Political Economy of the New Gilded Age
34
12
converge on oligarch-friendly positions without any concerted effort by wealthy actors, due simply
to leaders’ “individual calculations of the vote-producing impact of money.”38 To the extent that
mid-level elites face these same incentives, meanwhile, they are no more likely to resist oligarchic
influence—and where their power lacks independent grounding in a popular base, those who do
dissent can easily be disciplined or removed by top-level leaders. While it is a crucial element of
multi-level IPD structures, therefore, elite-facing IPD is insufficient on its own to resist oligarchic
agenda capture.
We recognize that the extent of oligarchic influence varies across different contexts, and that
our account of its prevalence and severity may be somewhat controversial. We note, however, that
the general problem of oligarchic capture is a key concern for nearly all contemporary democratic
theorists—including all of the major participants in debates about IPD. And while realists like
Rosenbluth and Shapiro appear insensitive to the specific threat of agenda capture, via influence
over party leaders, this too is a very widespread concern, which has long motivated calls for massfacing IPD. Given the suggestive evidence already presented, and our broader aims in the paper,
then, we assume going forward that collusion across party lines in support of wealthy interests is
at least a plausible threat—and one that inter-party competition cannot address on its own.
If that is right, meanwhile, then certain realist concerns about mass-facing IPD are also likely
overstated. The demands imposed by ideologically motivated factions certainly limit the flexibility
of top-level leaders, and in some cases this will prevent them from satisfying the median voter and
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009); Martin Gilens, Affluence and Influence: Economic Inequality and
Political Power in America (Princeton University Press, 2012); Martin Gilens and Benjamin I. Page, “Testing Theories
of American Politics: Elites, Interest Groups, and Average Citizens,” Perspectives on Politics 12, no. 03 (2014): 564–
81; Winters and Page, “Oligarchy in the United States?”, but scholars have found similar results across the democratic
world Nathalie Giger, Jan Rosset, and Julian Bernauer, “The Poor Political Representation of the Poor in a
Comparative Perspective,” Representation 48, no. 1 (2012): 47–61; Noam Lupu and Zach Warner, “Affluence and
Congruence: Unequal Representation Around the World,” Journal of Politics, 2020.
38
Winters and Page, “Oligarchy in the United States?,” 743.
13
appealing to the broadest possible electorate. In other cases, however, these ideological demands
may serve to pry those leaders from the clutches of wealthy donors. Indeed, if these demands have
hitherto been suppressed because they threaten oligarchic interests, and not because majorities of
ordinary people oppose them, the success of such factions could even broaden the party’s electoral
appeal. If so, mass-facing IPD would advance systemic democratic goals—and that possibility is
what animates our functionalist account of mass-facing IPD. In at least some cases, it seems, party
reform that limits the flexibility of top-level leaders carries potential benefits for democracy as
well as potential costs—even from the systemic evaluative perspective accepted by realists.
To be clear: we do not claim that all mass-facing IPD practices will always facilitate resistance
to oligarchic agenda capture. On the contrary, we are sympathetic to realist concerns that certain
inclusionary party reforms, in certain contexts, may make capture more likely. On a systemic
approach that grants priority to the demands of vigorous inter-party competition, indeed, we think
that a stance of pro tanto caution towards decentralizing party reforms—rather than the pro tanto
enthusiasm offered by isomorphic approaches—is probably warranted. Our claim, rather, is that
some forms of mass-facing IPD, in some contexts, can facilitate resistance to oligarchic agenda
capture—and that because this threat is especially resilient to the effects of inter-party competition,
our pro tanto caution may be defeated in those cases. Rather than presenting mass-facing IPD as
a generic democratic good, therefore, we see its value as conditioned by the contextual urgency of
resisting oligarchic agenda capture, and the effectiveness of particular practices in doing so. We
turn now to the two central questions that emerge from this functionalist account: i.e., when is
party reform most needed, and what kinds will best advance the systemic goals of democracy?
14
§IV. When is inclusionary party reform democracy-enhancing? The role of party
system rigidity
In brief, our answer to the first of these questions is that the urgency of mass-facing IPD varies
with the rigidity of the party system: i.e., the difficulty of pursuing political change through new
parties. Many factors affect rigidity—including cultural familiarity with party creation, as well as
inequality and polarization39—but the most important is surely the electoral system. Briefly,
single-member districts with plurality rule (SMD) tend to generate rigid duopolies—or stable,
regionally
differentiated
oligopolies—while
multi-member
districts
with
proportional
representation (PR) typically yield more flexible multi-party systems.40
For our purposes, the key point is that parties in a rigid system entrench themselves in various
ways; in part by making it difficult for new parties to gain traction.41 To prevent oligarchs from
imposing a favorable governing consensus by capturing the leadership of these entrenched parties,
therefore, dissenting factions must be able to contest oligarchic influence within each party. In
more flexible party systems, by contrast, dissenting factions from outside the existing political elite
are better able to contest oligarchic agenda capture by founding new parties, so the need for
internal channels of dissent and contestation is comparatively less urgent.
Sean Goff and Daniel J. Lee, “Prospects for Third Party Electoral Success in a Polarized Era,” American Politics
Research 47, no. 6 (2019): 1324–44.
40
Maurice Duverger, Political Parties (London: Meuthen Press, 1954). Of course, these tendencies are mediated by
many other factors. Regional differences can produce multiple parties at the national level, while barriers to ballot
access—in the US, for instance—reinforce a two-party system. Similarly, details like the minimum viable vote share
can lead to variation among PR systems (with higher thresholds for entry generating greater rigidity). In addition,
many systems employ a hybrid model mixing elements of SMD with elements of PR. For simplicity, we bracket this
diversity here. See Karen E. Ferree, G. Bingham Powell, and Ethan Scheiner, “Context, Electoral Rules, and Party
Systems,” Annual Review of Political Science 17, no. 1 (2014): 421–39.
41
The existence of many diverse parties gives voters more “exit” options, and is often a sign of a flexible party system.
Yet multiparty systems can still become entrenched, making it easier for oligarchs to capture all parties
simultaneously. Even in an apparently static duopoly, meanwhile, the credible threat of new party formation could
induce party leaders to reject oligarchic demands. As such, the true variable of interest for us is the difficulty of
pursuing political change by founding new parties, rather than the number of existing parties as such.
39
15
From the perspective of resisting oligarchic agenda capture, in other words, mass-facing IPD
and a flexible party system can be understood as partial substitutes. Wherever it is especially
difficult to challenge the governing consensus upheld by all existing parties—either by contesting
party platforms or founding new parties—oligarchic elites with outsized access to covert, backchannel influence will face little institutional opposition in capturing the political agenda. So long
as dissenting factions have at least one of these institutional avenues available to them, however,
the risk of agenda capture will be notably reduced. Where mass-facing IPD gives ordinary voters
agency over the agenda through their voice within their parties, a flexible party system empowers
voters through their choice between parties—i.e., through meaningful exit options.42 Either way,
party leaders have somewhat stronger incentives not to accede to oligarchic demands.
This insight allows us to cast doubt on the model hailed as ideally democratic by Rosenbluth
and Shapiro: centralized parties combined with a rigid party system. The closest approximation of
this ideal type in real world, they claim, is the Westminster model—especially as it functioned in
the mid-20th century UK. And in their view, the UK’s high social spending during that period
demonstrates that societies employing this model are sufficiently capable of resisting oligarchic
domination. As we explore below, however, it is misleading to depict mid-century UK parties as
fully centralized. In particular, the Labour Party may have had relatively few channels for directly
incorporating popular input, but like many other social democratic parties in that era, it was tightly
integrated with strong social organizations that did have such channels for mass engagement:
namely, trade unions. Despite their flaws, many unions were at least minimally accountable to a
Mark Warren, “Voting with Your Feet: Exit-Based Empowerment in Democratic Theory,” The American Political
Science Review 105, no. 4 (2011): 683–701.
42
16
large base of engaged members with a strong collective identity, which helped them—and the
Labour Party whose platform they shaped—resist oligarchic demands.43
A better example of the consequences of combining a rigid party system with centralized party
control, we claim, is provided by contemporary India. For several years, India’s electoral landscape
challenged Duveger’s law by presenting a multi-party democracy despite a First-Past-the-Post
system. This was, as observers noted, due to the presence of various regional parties that exercised
an influence on coalition government at the national level. 44 Recent years, however, have seen a
decline in the competition posed by such regional parties in general elections, and consequently
their ability to exercise electoral influence or bargaining power on the national scene.45 Thanks to
extreme anti-defection laws,46 meanwhile—among many other institutional and cultural factors—
the top-level leaders of India’s major parties control some of the most centralized party structures
in the democratic world.47 As such, dissenting factions have no viable institutional means—either
by reforming existing parties or creating new ones—to contest a governing consensus that
increasingly seems to favor the wealthiest elites.48
43
D. W. Rawson, “The Life-Span of Labour Parties,” Political Studies 17, no. 3 (1969): 313–33; Paul Webb and Tim
Bale, “No Place Else To Go: The Labour Party and the Trade Unions in the UK,” in Left-of-Centre Parties and Trade
Unions in the Twenty-First Century (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017).
44
See, for instance, Adam Ziegfeld, Why Regional Parties? Clientelism, Elites and the Indian Party System (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 2016).
45
For more on this trend and the reduction of the “effective number of parties” in recent elections, see Milan Vaishnav
and Jamie Hintson. India’s Fourth Party System (Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace,
2019).
46
The 52nd amendment to the Indian Constitution entails that legislators who defy their parties may lose not only their
party membership but also their place in parliament. For discussion, see Udit Bhatia, “Cracking the Whip: The
Deliberative Costs of Strict Party Discipline,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 23,
no. 2 (2020): 254–79.
47
Eswaran Sridharan, “The Shifting Party Balance,” Journal of Democracy 28, no. 3 (2017): 76–85; Udit Bhatia,
“What’s the Party Like? The Status of the Political Party in Anti-Defection Jurisdictions,” Law and Philosophy 40,
no. 3 (2021): 330–33.
48
In recent years, for instance, “substantial growth in the power of business groups in Indian politics” has been
accompanied by “a noticeable convergence in the economic programs of India’s major political parties, the BJP and
the Congress.” Christophe Jaffrelot, Atul Kohli, and Kanta Murali, “Conclusion,” in Business and Politics in India,
ed. Christophe Jaffrelot, Atul Kohli, and Kanta Murali, Modern South Asia (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019),
284. See also Aseema Sinha and Andrew Wyatt, “The Spectral Presence of Business in India’s 2019 Election,” Studies
in Indian Politics 7, no. 2 (2019): 247–61; Eswaran Sridharan, “Parties, the Party System and Collective Action for
17
Of course, we can hardly claim to offer a comprehensive account of oligarchic capture in
India—or anywhere else, for that matter. After all, wealthy elites have outsized influence in all
democracies, including those incorporating mass-facing IPD and flexible party systems. In the first
instance, rather, our aim is simply to suggest that oligarchic agenda capture in India could be
mitigated by increasing the flexibility of the party system, or—more realistically, perhaps—by
implementing certain inclusionary party reforms. More broadly, our aim is to demonstrate that the
model preferred by Rosenbluth and Shapiro is not ideally democratic. Given that it features neither
mass-facing IPD nor a flexible party system, dissenting factions within their model have few
institutional resources for challenging an oligarch-friendly governing consensus. As in India,
therefore, the democratic character of such systems could typically be enhanced—albeit only on
the margins—through certain well-designed inclusionary reforms to internal party governance.
It might seem to follow from the preceding discussion that the optimal democratic structure
would feature both a flexible party system and (certain effective forms of) mass-facing IPD. We
reject this inference, however. Despite their blind spots, realists like Rosenbluth and Shapiro are
right to worry that weaker and more decentralized parties may have more trouble presenting a clear
platform, implementing a coherent set of policies, and coordinating opposition to incumbent abuse.
Given the vagueness of key terms and the array of other potentially confounding factors involved,
such sweeping theoretical claims are difficult to verify empirically, and it is not our aim here to
defend them systematically. As noted, however, we find these realist concerns about the systemic
effects of inclusionary reforms plausible enough to warrant a stance of pro tanto caution.
What we have argued in this section, then, is that this pro tanto caution is relatively easier to
defeat in rigid party systems. We do not suggest that it is always defeated; nor that caution is never
State Funding of Elections: A Comparative Perspective on Possible Options,” in India’s Political Parties, ed. Peter
Ronald deSouza and Eswaran Sridharan (New Dehli: Sage, 2006), 311–40.
18
defeated in flexible systems. Some inclusionary reforms may be generally counterproductive—
and therefore unwise to pursue, even in rigid party systems—while others may be quite effective
at resisting oligarchic agenda capture across a range of circumstances, and thus democratically
valuable even in flexible systems. In the next section, indeed, we examine the differential effects
of different kinds of mass-facing IPD practices. Despite our best predictive efforts, however, any
proposed reform always carries risks and rewards. Our point in this section is simply that when
dissenters have no alternative institutional avenues for challenging a governing consensus that may
have been imposed by oligarchs, the urgency of finding a solution is greater, and that may shift
the balance in favor of reform. Because flexible party systems ensure that dissenters have
alternative institutional avenues for challenging oligarchic agenda capture, by contrast, proposals
for inclusionary party reform must meet a higher bar within such systems.
§V. What kinds of inclusionary party reform are democracy-enhancing? The
importance of organized collective power
The second major consequence of adopting a functionalist approach is to shift the kinds of
mass-facing IPD practices we understand as most likely to enhance democracy. Like revisionists,
to begin with, we think that party leaders may be held accountable through broad participation by
rank-and-file supporters in local institutions that are linked to the decisions of top-level leaders
through multiple levels of organization. Beyond that, however, the orientation to inclusionary party
reform that we propose diverges in several key respects from revisionists’ deliberative approach.
A. Revisionist and functionalist approaches: key differences
Given the systemic evaluative perspective we adopt, for one, the point of including a wider
group of stakeholders is not to ensure that the party platform reflects their views in any general
sense. If the primary role of parties is to compete for votes from diverse groups of citizens in inter-
19
party elections, then each party’s top-level leaders must enjoy significant discretion in shaping its
platform—and its strongest supporters are not the only constituency whose views are appropriately
considered in that process. In our view, therefore, the relatively narrow aim of mass-facing IPD is
simply to provide some degree of resistance against a specific threat that inter-party competition
is distinctively ill-equipped to address—i.e., oligarchic agenda capture—by ensuring that
dissenters have at least some tools at their disposal for contesting the influence of wealthy elites.
Similarly, the reason to engage large numbers of ordinary citizens—in addition to various midlevel elites and other stakeholder representatives—is not that this will satisfy their postmaterialist
demands for individualized self-expression, and thereby strengthen their commitment to the
collective aims of the party as such. Mass participation is necessary, rather, because it protects the
integrity of elite-facing IPD, which in practice carries much of the burden of resisting oligarchic
agenda capture. One the one hand, it ensures that some mid-level elites have independent sources
of power in a mass base, such that dissenters cannot simply be replaced by top-level leaders. In
the absence of any dissenting mid-level elites, on the other hand, its role is again to ensure that
dissenters among the broader population of members and supporters have at least some
institutional channels through which to oppose oligarchic agenda capture.
Beyond simply providing institutional forums within which citizens could contest oligarchic
influence, finally, we argue that mass-facing IPD practices must be designed to maximize the
likelihood that oligarchs will actually encounter significant resistance in their attempts to influence
the party’s agenda. On our account of the mechanisms of oligarchic agenda capture, recall, its
pervasiveness is largely attributable to wealthy elites’ superior ability to coordinate in defense of
shared interests. A key realist criticism of aggregative IPD practices, meanwhile, is that they
weaken the complex forms of intermediation and organization provided by many mid-level
20
elites—instead fostering direct, plebiscitary connections between disorganized individuals and
prominent top-level leaders. As such, we argue that inclusionary party reform must aim to facilitate
potent forms of countervailing organization among ordinary people, which could counterbalance
the pressures that are reliably exerted on party leaders by well-organized and wealthy elites.
Assuming that the most effective strategies will vary substantially by context, we stop short of
prescribing any particular practices as optimally democratic or universally required for this antioligarchic end. Drawing on the experience of social democratic parties tightly integrated with the
labor movement, however, this final section illustrates the limitations of deliberative approaches
and outlines a more promising orientation for inclusionary party reform. Although revisionists’
emphasis on layered, multi-level organizational structures is a step in the right direction, we argue
that their exclusive reliance on deliberative modes of engagement between party elites and rankand-file members or supporters fails to address underlying problems of disorganization and
individualization. Instead of proliferating opportunities for individual self-expression within the
party, we conclude that efforts to democratize political parties should aim to strengthen social ties,
solidarity, and habits of collective action among ordinary people—and that these imperatives need
not be pursued entirely within existing party hierarchies.
B. Organized collective power: achievements and challenges
Our point of departure is the widespread historical observation that many of the parties which
have consistently resisted oligarchic agenda capture have been integrated with independent massmembership organizations such as labor unions.49 Of course, revisionists’ turn to deliberation is at
49
John S. Ahlquist, “Labor Unions, Political Representation, and Economic Inequality,” Annual Reviews in Political
Science 20 (2017): 409–32; Colin Crouch, Post-Democracy (Malden, MA: Polity, 2004); Richard Freeman and James
L. Medoff, What Do Unions Do? (New York: Basic Books, 1984); Jane McAlevey, A Collective Bargain: Unions,
Organizing, and the Fight for Democracy (New York: Harper Collins, 2020); Wolfgang Streeck and Anke Hassel,
“Trade Unions as Political Actors,” in International Handbook of Trade Unions, ed. John T. Addison and Claus
Schnabel (Edward Elgar, 2003), 335–65.
21
least partly motivated by their pessimism about the prospects of reviving this kind of organized
collective power, given the declining strength of labor and related trends, and we acknowledge
that contemporary conditions present serious challenges for this model. In our view, however, the
resurgence of some such countervailing organizations—albeit, perhaps, in novel or unfamiliar
forms—is both possible and urgently necessary. As Steven Klein has recently argued in this
journal, that is, democracy requires organized collective power.50
In brief, the key challenge is that the alliance between labor unions and social democratic
parties—once a robust source of opposition to oligarchic interests—has disintegrated along with
the labor movement itself.51 For one, globalization and other changes have gradually eroded the
“cohesive social environments that helped structure the original growth of mass parties”—
including trade unions, social clubs, and so on—as well as the collective class-based identities that
were once supported by these organizations.52 Relatedly, the left-right dimension that once reliably
structured political contestation around economic issues has increasingly been complicated by a
cross-cutting “cosmopolitan–communitarian” dimension, further obstructing the organization of
parties around consistent opposition to oligarchic interests.53
At least partly in response to this marked decline in class consciousness and conflict over issues
of economic redistribution, revisionist advocates of mass-facing IPD have argued that our efforts
Steven Klein, “Democracy Requires Organized Collective Power,” Journal of Political Philosophy, 2021.
Sheri Berman and Maria Snegovaya, “Populism and the Decline of Social Democracy,” Journal of Democracy 30,
no. 3 (2019): 5–19; Jacob S. Hacker and Paul Pierson, Winner-Take-All Politics: How Washington Made the Rich
Richer--and Turned Its Back on the Middle Class (New York: Simon & Schuster, 2011); Stephanie L. Mudge, Leftism
Reinvented: Western Parties from Socialism to Neoliberalism (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2018).
52
Wolfgang Streeck, “The Politics of Exit,” New Left Review, 2014, 123. See also Gabriel Winant, “We Live in a
Society,” N+1, December 12, 2020, https://nplusonemag.com/online-only/online-only/we-live-in-a-society/.
53
Simon Bornschier, “The New Cultural Divide and the Two-Dimensional Political Space in Western Europe,” West
European Politics 33, no. 3 (2010): 419–44; Pradeep K. Chhibber and Rahul Verma, Ideology and Identity: The
Changing Party Systems of India (Oxford University Press, 2018); Michael Zürn and Pieter de Wilde, “Debating
Globalization: Cosmopolitanism and Communitarianism as Political Ideologies,” Journal of Political Ideologies 21,
no. 3 (2016): 280–301.
50
51
22
to deepen democracy should pivot to more individualized and deliberative forms of inclusionary
party reform. In particular, Invernizzi-Accetti and Wolkenstein take their cue from recent claims
that citizens of advanced democracies are increasingly motivated to participate in politics by the
opportunities for self-expression it affords.54 Unfortunately, they observe, these “postmaterialist”
demands cannot be satisfied by aggregative procedures, whose appeal is grounded rather in
collective identification and the pursuit of common aims. To secure wider participation, therefore,
contemporary political parties must institutionalize discussion within local branches and other
empowered deliberative forums.
In our view, however, revisionists’ acquiescence to perceived demands for individualized selfexpression is premature, and their exclusive focus on deliberative solutions is at best a distraction.55
Collective forms of anti-oligarchic power can be revived, we insist—both by fostering new
solidarities, along new lines, and by contesting the policies that undermined labor’s strength in the
first place. Indeed, we claim, they must be: individualized forms of deliberative participation will
always be inadequate to address oligarchic agenda capture, and in some cases may be harmful.
C. Deliberative forums and organized collective power
Let us begin by considering the best-case scenario for deliberative party reforms. On the model
proposed by Wolkenstein and other revisionists, intra-party forums would have substantial power,
rather than playing a merely consultative role. They would also be structured in egalitarian ways—
using facilitation techniques that can minimize the dominance of privileged voices, for instance56—
Invernizzi-Accetti and Wolkenstein, “The Crisis of Party Democracy, Cognitive Mobilization, and the Case for
Making Parties More Deliberative.” See, e.g., Ronald Inglehart and Christian Welzel, Modernization, Cultural
Change, and Democracy: The Human Development Sequence (Cambridge University Press, 2005); Pippa Norris,
Democratic Phoenix: Reinventing Political Activism (Cambridge University Press, 2002).
55
For further context, see Bagg, “Can Deliberation Neutralise Power?”
56
As described, for instance, in Afsoun Afsahi, “Gender Difference in Willingness and Capacity for Deliberation,”
Social Politics: International Studies in Gender, State & Society, 2020.
54
23
rather than being manipulated by party elites to serve their own ends. In such ideal conditions, we
concede, deliberative reforms would likely advance certain democratic goals—giving participants
a greater sense of political efficacy, for instance, and even enabling contestation of the agenda.
Still, deliberative forums could realistically engage only a tiny minority of the party’s voters,
and participants would almost certainly be unrepresentative of that larger group. The power given
to any particular branch or forum, meanwhile, will necessarily be bounded by their small scale and
local scope—constraints imposed by the demand to remain both deliberative and inclusive. In
order to initiate party-wide changes in a coherent anti-oligarchic direction, therefore—rather than
a cacophony of conflicting local imperatives that party elites could readily ignore—ordinary party
members would need to unify around a specific set of demands, and successfully advance them
over the objections of party leaders in a multitude of different branches and forums.
It is not impossible to imagine groups of ordinary people taking just this kind of coordinated
collective action in opposition to oligarchic agenda capture, and revisionists might therefore claim
that their model can accommodate the sort of countervailing power we recommend. On the one
hand, however, such a concerted strategic effort would seem to betray the open-ended spirit that
is central to most justifications of deliberation. On the other hand, it would also rely on substantial
solidarity and collective organization: i.e., precisely those elements of countervailing power that
revisionists have notably failed to discuss. To the extent that deliberative forums can accommodate
or even encourage coordinated collective action by organized groups of rank-and-file members,
therefore, we conclude that they can facilitate resistance to oligarchic agenda capture. Given that
other intra-party decision-making procedures could also accommodate such coordinated action,
however, deliberative forums are less essential to anti-oligarchic resistance than the organizations
24
through which collective action is coordinated in the first place. Even in the best-case scenario, it
seems, revisionists’ exclusive focus on the former over the latter is misplaced.
Once we relax the idealizing assumption that party elites will act in good faith, meanwhile—
rather than using their control over the structure of deliberative forums to insulate their agenda
from serious challenges—there is even less cause for enthusiasm about deliberative approaches.
Revisionists often rely on a largely undefended assumption that deliberative exchanges between
citizens and elites are “likely to be a much more effective mechanism to check the power of the
leadership over the base than merely voting on their proposals.”57 In doing so, they ignore the
substantial evidence that elites often employ the tools of participatory inclusion very strategically,
in ways that entrench and legitimize their power58—and neglect the strong possibility that
opportunistic party leaders would use intra-party deliberation in similar ways.
D. Organized collective power: contemporary prospects
For all these reasons, then, we think revisionists are overly optimistic about deliberative party
reforms. At the same time, we argue, they are also overly pessimistic about the prospects of more
organized and collectively-oriented forms of participation. Though Invernizzi-Accetti and
Wolkenstein are right to reckon with the declining salience of class conflict and the apparent
increase in demand for individualized forms of participation, for instance, they are wrong to see
these trends as inevitable and irreversible. Their account frames the transition from collective
solidarity to individualized self-expression as a natural consequence of growing material security
Invernizzi-Accetti and Wolkenstein, “The Crisis of Party Democracy, Cognitive Mobilization, and the Case for
Making Parties More Deliberative,” 103.
58
Gianpaolo Baiocchi and Ernesto Ganuza, Popular Democracy: The Paradox of Participation (Stanford University
Press, 2016); Jaskiran K. Dhillon, Prairie Rising: Indigenous Youth, Decolonization, and the Politics of Intervention
(Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2017); Caroline W. Lee, Do-It-Yourself Democracy: The Rise of the Public
Engagement Industry (Oxford University Press, 2014); Albert Weale, The Will of the People: A Modern Myth
(Cambridge: Polity, 2018). For further discussion, see Chapter 3 (“Beyond Participatory Inclusion”) in Samuel Bagg,
The Dispersion of Power: A Critical Realist Theory of Democracy (Oxford University Press, Forthcoming)
57
25
and other global economic trends, rather than as a contingent result of specific political choices. It
therefore obscures the very deliberate efforts of oligarchic elites to dismantle the socio-legal
foundations of labor unions and other sources of countervailing power.59
The declining power of labor cannot be attributed solely to government policies aimed directly
at that result. Yet even many apparently unrelated economic trends—including the expansion of
“workplace fissuring” and the “gig economy,” as well as broader forces such as globalization and
automation—have thrived at least partly because they undermine workers’ organizational capacity,
and thus serve the shared interests of elites around the globe.60 And if the declining power of unions
and other organs of countervailing power is partly a result of policy choices, then a more
“promotive stance” could mitigate this decline, thereby reviving our capacity to resist oligarchic
capture.61
Even absent state support, meanwhile, shifts in the strategic orientation of union leaders and
party elites—amidst changing economic and cultural conditions—could also initiate a revival of
working-class movements. Clearly, there is no consensus about which organizing tactics are most
effective, and no strategy is appropriate for every context. Nevertheless, several recent analyses
have converged on the insight that, despite their relatively high costs to members, confrontational
and participatory approaches often yield the most enduring increases in membership.62 As many
59
For a classic account, see David Harvey, A Brief History of Neoliberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).
McAlevey, A Collective Bargain; Quinn Slobodian, Globalists: The End of Empire and the Birth of Neoliberalism
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2018).
61
Martin O’Neill and Stuart White, “Trade Unions and Political Equality,” in Philosophical Foundations of Labour
Law, ed. Hugh Collins, Gillian Lester, and Virginia Mantouvalou (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018). See also
Kate Andrias and Benjamin I. Sachs, “Constructing Countervailing Power: Law and Organizing in an Era of Political
Inequality,” Yale Law Journal 130, no. 3 (2021 2020): 546–635.
62
Jane McAlevey, No Shortcuts: Organizing for Power in the New Gilded Age (New York: Oxford University Press,
2016); Jeffrey Stout, Blessed Are the Organized: Grassroots Democracy in America (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 2012); Deva R. Woodly, Reckoning: #BlackLivesMatter and the Democratic Necessity of Social Movements
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021). For further discussion, see Chapter 8 (“Organizing for Power: An Agenda
for Democratic Action”) in Samuel Bagg, The Dispersion of Power: A Critical Realist Theory of Democracy (Oxford
University Press, Forthcoming)
60
26
effective organizers have long argued, in short, the experience of achieving concrete victories
through collective struggle can be transformative—especially when it involves participation in
mass collective action such as a strike.63 In particular, successful collective struggles can exert a
powerful influence on participants’ identities, generating the sort of solidarity and sustained
commitment to collective action that is necessary to support lasting, effective institutions of
countervailing power.
Even if labor unions, social democratic parties, and the class-based identities that support them
are indeed in terminal decline, finally, other sources of countervailing power can be grounded in
other forms of collective identity, among other disempowered groups with shared interests. Efforts
to organize communities around common local concerns, for instance, have sometimes generated
enduring organizations with substantial countervailing power64—as have the efforts of
disadvantaged racial and ethnic groups to contest their shared oppression.65 While efforts to
organize tenants, debtors, and welfare beneficiaries have fewer successful models to draw upon,
shifting conditions may present new opportunities for building countervailing power among these
groups as well.66 Like labor unions, these other countervailing organizations most often achieve
broader political success by extracting concessions from left-leaning parties, thereby forcing
certain issues onto the agenda for inter-party competition. Yet that is not the only way to resist
oligarchic agenda capture: in some contexts, at least, well-organized groups of ordinary people
63
Saul Alinsky, Rules for Radicals: A Pragmatic Primer for Realistic Radicals (New York: Random House, 1971);
Robert Moses et al., “The Algebra Project: Organizing in the Spirit of Ella,” Harvard Educational Review 59, no. 4
(1989): 423–43; Charles M. Payne, I’ve Got the Light of Freedom: The Organizing Tradition and the Mississippi
Freedom Struggle (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995).
64
Vijay Phulwani, “The Poor Man’s Machiavelli: Saul Alinsky and the Morality of Power,” American Political
Science Review 110, no. 4 (2016): 863–75; Stout, Blessed Are the Organized.
65
Payne, I’ve Got the Light of Freedom; Woodly, Reckoning.
66
Andrias and Sachs, “Constructing Countervailing Power.”
27
could also pry open certain features of an oligarch-friendly governing consensus via internal
pressure on centrist or right-leaning parties.
E. Implications of the functionalist approach
As we have emphasized, it is beyond our scope to evaluate the prospects of any particular
approach to building organized collective power in any particular context—and we are especially
mindful to avoid universalizing the model adopted by 20th-century social democratic parties. One
important concrete implication of our approach does emerge quite clearly from our examination
of this historical model, however: namely, that the layers of organization linking mass participation
to top-level party leaders need not be located within the party structure. As with labor unions in
the social democratic party model, rather, a party might successfully resist oligarchic capture by
integrating independent organizations into its decision-making at certain critical junctures. As long
as those external organizations are accountable to a mass base of some kind, their democratic role
is functionally similar to that played by more paradigmatic IPD practices, and thus belongs to the
same category of democratic tools.67 Indeed, it may have advantages over internal party reforms.
Because they remain independent, for one, external organizations are both less likely to be coopted by top-level leaders, and better positioned to challenge those leaders without damaging their
ability to present and execute a coherent platform. Meanwhile, organizations with a social or
economic purpose other than partisan competition will likely attract more consistent participation,
outside of election campaigns, from a wider range of people. Even in an era of growing demand
for political self-expression, opportunities to debate finer points of policy and strategy are unlikely
For instance, Susan E. Scarrow and Thomas Poguntke argue that “linkage through collateral organizations is another
important aspect of intra-party democracy,” citing the British Labour Party as an especially “conspicuous” example
of this form of intra-party democracy. See their “Intra-Party Democracy and Representation: Necessity, Complement,
or Challenge?,” in The Oxford Handbook of Political Representation in Liberal Democracies, ed. Robert
Rohrschneider and Jacques Thomassen (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020), 328.
67
28
to appeal quite as broadly as the social bonds and other intrinsic benefits offered by organizations
with a more immediate social purpose, such as labor unions and community groups—not to
mention the social clubs and religious groups with which they are often intertwined.
That said, the advantages of entrusting some or all IPD functions to external organizations are
hardly decisive, and will vary by context. As such, we do not claim that mass-facing IPD must take
this form. Regardless of where it happens, the crucial point is to design mass-facing IPD practices
that generate regular, organized engagement—which, as we noted above, is the most reliable way
to generate the solidarity, social ties, and habits of collective action that can actually sustain
countervailing sources of power among ordinary people.68 And it is certainly conceivable that this
sort of engagement could be generated within the party. Given that nearly all contemporary
discussion centers on such internally-focused reforms, however, our insistence that external massmembership organizations could also fulfill the most important democratic function of mass-facing
IPD—so long as they are properly integrated into party decision-making—represents an important
intervention. Indeed, including this latter strategy in the category of mass-facing IPD allows us to
considerably shrink the apparent distance between realist critics and revisionist advocates.
On the one hand, realists like Rosenbluth and Shapiro often point to the “centralized” parties
that created social democracy in postwar Europe as evidence that mass-facing IPD is unnecessary
for resisting oligarchic capture. Because this account ignores the integration of those parties with
external organizations, however, this description is misleading. Most crucially, we have suggested,
it was their affiliation with mass-membership trade unions that allowed the UK Labour Party and
68
McAlevey, No Shortcuts; John S. Ahlquist and Margaret Levi, In the Interest of Others: Organizations and Social
Activism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2013); Hahrie Han, How Organizations Develop Activists: Civic
Associations and Leadership in the 21st Century (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014); Hahrie Han, “The
Organizational Roots of Political Activism: Field Experiments on Creating a Relational Context,” American Political
Science Review 110, no. 2 (2016): 296–307; Paul W. Speer and Hahrie Han, “Re-Engaging Social Relationships and
Collective Dimensions of Organizing to Revive Democratic Practice,” Journal of Social and Political Psychology 6,
no. 2 (2018): 745-758–758.
29
other European social democratic parties to resist certain forms of agenda capture during that
period.69 On the other hand, revisionists like Wolkenstein are clearly concerned with oligarchic
influence on party leaders, and would likely welcome the growth of organized collective power,
among ordinary people, as a counterweight. Yet their deliberative solutions are not well-suited to
fostering such countervailing power, and in limiting their horizon to internal party structures, they
ignore the strategies that have enjoyed the most success historically. By highlighting that certain
external organizations can fulfill the most crucial anti-oligarchic function of mass-facing IPD, our
functionalist account thus opens space for convergence among realists who are skeptical of internal
party reforms, and revisionists who insist that resisting oligarchic capture of party elites requires
some form of mass engagement.
§VI. Conclusion
This paper has articulated a functionalist account of intra-party democracy. To begin with, we
have adopted the systemic evaluative approach preferred by realist critics—insisting that massfacing IPD practices be evaluated on the basis of whether they facilitate resistance to domination
and capture at the level of the polity as a whole. In rejecting such practices altogether, however,
realists put too much faith in the tendency of inter-party competition to realize those goals—in
particular neglecting the possibility that wealthy interests could control the political agenda by
capturing all viable parties simultaneously. As revisionist advocates have insisted, meanwhile,
some forms of mass-facing IPD may hold more democratic promise than the plebiscitary practices
rightly criticized by realists. Where revisionists press for deliberative reforms, however—as a way
As Elin Haugsgjerd Allern and Tim Bale put it, this is regarded as “common wisdom” among students of political
parties, trade unions, and working class power more generally. See “The Relationship between Left-of-Centre Parties
and Trade Unions,” in Left-of-Centre Parties and Trade Unions in the Twenty-First Century (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2017).
69
30
of ensuring that parties reflect the views of rank-and-file members—our functionalist account
suggests a more specific aim, and a more targeted set of practices.
The key role of mass-facing IPD within a broader democratic system, we have argued, is to
counter the specific threat of oligarchic agenda capture. Our first conclusion, then, is that
inclusionary party reform is less urgent in more flexible party systems, where dissenters are better
able to resist this threat from within the framework of inter-party competition—i.e., by founding
new parties. Whatever the context, second, we conclude that mass-facing IPD practices should aim
at enabling ordinary members and supporters of a party to resist agenda capture by oligarchic
interests. Though we stop short of defending any particular set of reforms, we reject revisionists’
emphasis on individualized forms of deliberative participation, in favor of a more oppositional and
collectively-oriented approach—on the grounds that the latter is more likely to encourage the
development of effective institutions of countervailing power. Organizing collective power and
subsequently linking it to parties’ decision-making processes is undoubtedly a tall order. If we
hope to address oligarchic threats to democracy, however, there are no shortcuts to be found.
31