Review: Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care: Engendering Social Justice and Social
Identities
Reviewed Work(s): Care, Gender, and Justice; Feminists Read Habermas: Gendering the
Subject of Discourse by Diemut Elisabet Bubeck and Johanna Meehan
Review by: Mechthild Nagel
Source: Social Theory and Practice , Summer 1997, Vol. 23, No. 2 (Summer 1997), pp.
307-326
Published by: Florida State University Department of Philosophy
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/23559186
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact
[email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Social Theory and
Practice
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care: Engendering Social
Justice and Social Identities
[Review of Diemut Elisabet Bubeck, Care, Gender, and Justice
(Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), ix + 281
pp., $49.95 cloth; and Johanna Meehan (ed.), Feminists Read
Habermas: Gendering the Subject of Discourse (New York and
London: Routledge, 1995), xi + 291 pp., $17.95 paper.]
Over thirty years ago, Betty Friedan's Feminine Mystique started
a revolt of a peculiar sort in the U.S.; her book was a catalyst for
white, middle-class women to reflect on their status as house
wives, which they had acquired through choice or societal expec
tations. They began to reject that status, despite the considerable
privileges that came along with it. Some of these women partici
pated in the "borning struggle" of the civil rights movement by
starting consciousness-raising groups and discussing their per
ceived sense of oppression as homeworkers; they rejected all the
(patriarchal, bourgeois) values associated with it. On the academic
front, Marxist feminists started to confront "women's work" in the
ensuing debate about the status of domestic labor, which thrived
especially in the U.K.
In the early 1980s, another liberal feminist author took up a
different sort of consciousness-raising within moral psychology.
Carol Gilligan's ground-breaking book In a Different Voice (1982)
suggests that it is an ethic of care, rather than appeals to justice
and rights, which determines girls' moral judgments; Gilligan
demanded that this "voice" be heard, not dismissed, in ethical
discussions. As a result, feminists across all disciplines, not just
feminist ethicists, took up the notion of "woman's way of knowing
and caring."
The feminist notion of care connotes compassion, attentiveness,
devotion to others' needs—values foregrounded in the feminist
Copyright 1997 by Social Theory and Practice, Vol. 23, No. 2 (Summer 1997)
307
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
308 Mechthild Nagel
ethic of care developed by Gilligan, Hill Col
Ruddick, and Tronto. Still, not all caring is u
always already good caring. Some moralists co
who grudgingly serves her child. Authentic
mothering, on the other hand, are uncritical
validation of such affectivity poses a challenge
deontological ethics of Rawls, Kohlberg, and
dismisses these affects as personal matters, irr
considerations. Feminist ethicists, by contra
deontologists for their ideological move of disc
private feelings and evaluations as "merely"
so-called good life and not to the realm of justic
In the 1990s, a sobering realization is taking p
the second shift (or even third shift) phenom
required a synthesis of the two ethical positi
justice. Feminists are again questioning t
housework and the sexual division of work. T
the importance of care without engaging in fal
and romanticization. The question is raised
theoretical framework has more to offer to social theorists: Is it
desirable to reject the concept of care and turn to a Habermasian
deontological ethic, or to return to a Marxian blending of social
justice and care?
Contemporary social-political thought, such as Habermas's and
Rawls's theories of justice, still sidesteps a sustained analysis of
gender issues.1 With respect to the early social critical theory of
Habermas, the feminists in Meehan's collection propose to repair
it so that it accounts for the gendered nature of the bourgeois public
and private sphere. Similarly, Habermas's later discourse ethics,
or theory of communicative action, is "gender-repaired" with the
inclusion of care or affective emotion. Meehan's contributors are
marked by what Rawls would call an "overlapping consensus":
they want to correct Habermas's social and ethical theories while
remaining loyal to his framework.
By contrast, Diemut Bubeck, in her book, critiques Rawls's
social justice theory, in particular his distribution paradigm, for its
inadequacy in accommodating feminist materialist concerns. She
thinks that this form of "repair" should be done within the
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 309
parameters of a materialist analysis and ultimately rejects Rawls's
liberal framework.
Both books share a concern with overcoming the misleading
disjuncture of justice and care. Of course it is tempting to entertain
the question of which project—if either—succeeds in this
endeavor; I will attempt to refrain from playing out one against
the other while conceding that Bubeck has the more persuasive
perspective. Instead, I will address three themes that pertain to
both discourse ethics and materialist feminist ethics: the politics
of intertwining justice and care, the interconnection of race,
ethnicity, and so on with gendered selves in these discourses, and
the political nature of care.
A feminist who dares to engage with Habermas's critical theory
other than in negative, abstract critique inevitably has to respond
defensively to the question, "Why read Habermas?" "Forget
Habermas" seems a radical posture to entertain, when Marx,
Freud, and Foucault have been made palatable to feminist taste
buds through disciple or "bandita" methods. For example,
Freudian feminists are disciples, while post-Freudian feminists are
banditas. It seems to me that most of the feminist theorists in
Meehan's collection are disciples; for example, Jean Cohen avers
that Habermas's latest work (Facticity and Validity, 1994) shows
his commitment to accommodate feminist concerns and has
corrected his earlier "gender blindness" (p. 81, n. 1). Jane Braaten
seems at first to use the bandita method, as she re-uses or re-tools
the concept of "communicative thinking"; in the end, she too
suggests that Habermas's framework can be stretched to address
gender concerns.
What is Habermas's discursive theory of ethics? In a sweeping
and playful gesture, Seyla Benhabib locates it thus: "Discourse
ethics is situated somewhere between liberalism and communi
tarianism, Kantian universalism and Hegelian Sittlichkeit."
More precisely, discourse or communicative ethics attempts to
break with a (Kantian) monological conception of the moral self
and advocates a democratic proceduralism for establishing
universally acceptable norms. Yet Habermas appeals to an abstract
rather than substantive moral rationality to ensure the truth claim,
the principle of justification, for his ethics, and thus remains within
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
310 Mechthild Nagel
the Kantian tradition—and in opposition to fem
care. His approach is also Hegelian, insofar as h
concept of autonomy is necessary but not
communicative ethics. For him, recognition of
"generalized other," is key to understanding
concerns dealing with justice (and solidarity).
Feminists who have taken to critical so
particularly to Habermas's theory of communi
as all of the authors of Meehan's anthology pro
are rethinking what it means to articulate a rela
identity that is not blind to gender oppression.
the meaning of "we,"3 and confront the politi
feminists who are squarely labelled as uncrit
"difference," of fragmented and fractured selve
These Habermasian feminist theorists share a concern for
seeking the conditions of possibility of consensus in a post
conventional world. They focus on the role that women play as
political agents in the public sphere and analyze the relationship
of justice and care vis-à-vis "the concrete other."
In evaluating these claims, it is essential to ask whether
Habermas's theory is commensurable with feminist praxis. Does
it take into account "different voices," different social identities?
But first, I want to look at a feminist use of his colonization theory
vis-à-vis the application of social care.
In her article in Meehan's book, "Critical Social Theory and
Feminist Critiques: The Debate with Jiirgen Habermas," Jean
Cohen problematically characterizes care in the context of child
care commodification, or in Habermas's jargon, "colonization of
the life-world." Cohen balks at Nancy Fraser's suggestion (cf.
Fraser's article "What's Critical About Critical Theory?") that the
family be treated as an economic system, because it fails to take
psychological factors, such as identity formations, into account.
Also, Cohen is horrified at the idea of treating childcare like any
other kind of social labor, since this seems to totally commodify
nurturing (65). Indulging in alarmist gestures on this point, she
writes: "... when organizational or economic requirements
outweigh the communicative tasks of nurturing and teaching, they
subvert the raison d'être of the institutions and have pathological
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 311
consequences (unnurtured and untaught children)" (66). The
commodification of childcare thus stands in the way of committed
selfless care and pedagogy.
Cohen's argument does not take into consideration positive
effects of institutional procedures, for example, grievance
procedures, which protect the rights of workers. A general strike
of teachers might negatively affect students' education, yet it will
inevitably raise the students' consciousness about class struggle
and social justice issues. Even if care providers do not excercise
their right to strike, Cohen's analysis implies that daycare workers
and teachers (K through 12) should not be represented by unions,
because collective bargaining agreements unnecessarily
contribute to a climate where teachers see themselves exploited
and thus tend to alienate them from their caring work. I think it is
a mistake to romanticize the child-centered service mostly done
by women; instead one ought to take note of the ideological uses
of care, which Fraser—following Carole Pateman's materialist
analysis—seems to acknowledge in her article. This case
highlights the need to understand feminized practices of caring
and serving practices in the context of social justice, and not
simply as a "personal," private affair.
Returning to the question of whether Habermas's theory is
commensurable with feminist praxis, let us consider "Women and
the 'Public Use of Reason'," Marie Fleming's essay in Meehan's
book. She brings up another critique of Habermas's (and, I might
add, Cohen's) conservative tendencies. As he worries about the
"colonization of the life-world," Habermas warns us against
bringing legalities into the (communicative) realm of the
life-world, the family, and the school (132). Yet Fleming avers that
Habermas is also concerned about the danger of limiting freedom
through more juridification (133). This is certainly a point well
taken with respect to legislating "community standards" for
offensive art, pornography, and so on. Ironically, radical feminists
seem to have joined forces with family-values/moral-majority
interest groups. On the other hand, I contend that Habermas's idea
of (negative) freedom from "internal colonization" (i.e., freedom
from unnecessary legal restraints) is inadequate. It romanticizes
nurturing by cheering for the preservation of the sanctity and
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
312 Mechthild Nagel
purity of unregulated socialization within fam
Experience suggests that unless they are pushed
institutions rarely fight sexism, heterosexism,
oppression.
In addition, Habermas's rationalistic tenden
embodied intersubjectivity is problematic for al
Meehan's anthology. They critique his relianc
controversial differentiation of justice and the g
preference for abstract moral reason over substa
Jane Braaten, in particular, reveals Habermas's K
which cannot simply be spirited away to make
ethics work for feminists.
What are the implications of Habermas's
rationality for theory and practice? Jane Braaten
with feminist understandings of substantiv
community and solidarity, to formulate "
thinking." This notion displaces to some extent H
of communicative rationality, which is not base
ideals (139). Braaten finds Habermas's ideal of co
in exploring the notion of solidarity among dive
(141). Yet consensus has little relevance as a st
feminist collective action; it is often motivated t
of compassion for the plight of an individual memb
the role of experience, not appeals to univer
determines communicative action (143).
In a related critique, Braaten argues that Evely
Helen Longino's studies of the social sciences
character of epistemology have convincingly sho
social, substantive ideals that inform knowledg
progress, and not the isolated ahistorical Cartesia
of knowledge (151). Braaten concludes with the
feminist communicative thinking begin with the
how oppression works and how one can resi
hegemonic institutions. By addressing this conc
beyond communicative theory and its worry abo
However, she agrees with Habermas that "[c
thinking cannot (and need not) ignore questions
happen to be formal or general." She argues tha
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 313
wary of claiming that women's experiences are simply
generalizable. Yet, "[r]emembering and synthesizing from
women's stories also creates the bonds of solidarity ... Though
we find each other's stories sometimes overwhelmingly unlike our
own, our knowledge of them creates the possibility of mutual
support" (157). It seems to me that caring is a "substantive" ideal;
as such it is clearly meant to be included in her ideal of
communicative thinking. But she provides examples that avoid a
mere romantic appropriation of care, as does Cohen. Braaten's
account also avoids casting a (substantive) principle of care
against an (abstract) principle of justice. Even though Braaten
insists that she has not repudiated Habermas's theory, I take her
feminist proposal for communicative thinking to be a determinate
negation (rather than a merely abstract negation) of Habermas's
communicative rationality, since it foregrounds substantive, not
formal, principles.
Bringing forward another limited critique of Habermas, Simone
Chambers takes up the question of the primacy of formalism in
her analysis of the discursive politics of a feminist peace and
justice affinity group. Unlike Braaten, Chambers hesitates to
critique Habermas's model. She is attentive to the praxis of
successful discourse as outlined by the activists' resource
handbook, in which they draw on Gilligan's ethic of care.
Habermas's discourse ethics with its emphasis on abstract
formalism and correct proceduralism seems undesirable to these
activists. Nevertheless, their approach shares proceduralist aspects
with Habermas's discourse ethics, by privileging consensus
formation over disagreements, conflicts, and difference (170). She
also notes the pitfalls of the drive towards group consensus and
agrees with Habermas's critique of a communitarian ethos,
unsuited to modem pluralist democracies (176). But we need to
ask whether Habermas is really immune from that critique himself.
After all, communicative ethics is a consensus-driven discourse
that tends to silence difference.
In her essay, Seyla Benhabib also points out striking similarities
between Gilligan and Habermas regarding the necessary
interaction between care or solidarity and justice (192). Yet she
focuses on disagreements between their ethical theories and seeks
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
314 Mechthild Nagel
to forge a third perspective combining the care pe
universalist perspective. In her critique of the
addresses the "woman's question," Benhabib cla
has insufficient reasons for rejecting a univers
Habermas's or Kohlberg's (183). On the ot
formalistic ethics could benefit from Gilligan
approach, important for a postconventional eth
for combining (impartial) justice and (contex
states cogently that we need both a deontologic
our actions and a contextualized moral concern for others: "The
generalized other of the justice perspective is always also a
concrete other" (192). Care is not merely a personal but also a
moral issue, a position that neither Habermas nor Kohlberg would
endorse. In the end Benhabib advocates a feminist critical theory
with "the right mix of justice and care"—requiring the subject to
integrate both autonomy and solidarity. Furthermore, she proposes
(in contrast to Nietzschean, Marxist, and postmodern identity
notions) an intersubjective yet coherent self-identity—a self that
is constituted and reconstructed through the web of others'
narratives (200).
But I want to ask, what narratives are to be considered legiti
mate? How are different voices recognized and represented, es
pecially in the context of a white supremacist society? Benhabib
shares Habermas's optimistic Enlightenment project that fails to
acknowledge its adherence to the logic of identity, that is, "dif
ference" always already succumbs to identitarian thinking. Thus
Benhabib lacks a social-political framework or a narrative that
could address issues of fairness, of distribution of (public) care
among groups of people differentiated by gender, class, caste, eth
nicity, and so on. To my mind, it does not suffice to allude to the
conception of a coherent self who is vaguely connected to others.
While Benhabib insists on an undefined "right mix" of care with
justice, Jodi Dean advocates a "progressive Gilligan reading" of
contextualized (i.e., gendered) care givers and takers (207). She
critiques Habermas's stage theory, with its preconventional,
conventional, and postconventional levels, that underscores
Kohlberg's moral system.
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 315
Dean claims that it is also necessary to revise discourse ethics
so that it can include the concerns of women (208), because
Habermas's own analysis is not concerned with the gendered
nature of authority. She notes that in his ethics, recognition (of the
other as subject) is only treated either as competition or
cooperation, with competition in the ascendant; one argument,
even in a supposedly coercion-free environment, must "win out."
Empathy is neglected as a "personal," not moral, intuition so that
it plays no constitutive role in recognizing the other. Dean chides
Habermas for bringing in "empathy 'from behind'."
As a corrective move, she puts forth the category of connection
—that is, that empathy and attachedness are constitutive elements
of intersubjective relationships—to revise his ethics (220). She
also suggests that one has to overcome "role recognition in favor
of the mutual recognition of subjects deserving equal respect"
(222) to answer the question of how such ethics works at a
postconventional level for both men and women. Dean, like
Benhabib, questions the concept of mutually respectful, reciprocal
relationships at the postconventional level, relationships between
the observer and the generalized other; she asserts that the latter
has to be thought of as multiple others, not as the other (224).
To return to my initial question about accounting for
differences, Benhabib and Dean answer that Habermas's discourse
ethics offers a recipe to feminists that successfully addresses the
concerns of "different voices" and identities.
To my mind, the question remains of how we engage in this
Utopian "leap" towards postconventional, undistorted, rational
value judgments. Is it enough to postulate a "critical distance" to
ensure that we do not get trapped in conventional hypocrisies and
prejudices? Communicative, critical practice has to be concep
tualized differently, so that it does not get entangled in a methodo
logical solipsism. Reason ought to be subservient to our
human-practical needs and not be appealed to in isolation of them.
Habermas's postconventional perspective ignores our irrational,
distorted emotions as well as our care-free play, risk-taking, which
contribute to our daily moral decision-making.
As Dean notes, one cannot simply bring "care" into Habermas's
ethics as an afterthought. Undoubtedly, a Habermasian ethicist
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
316 Mechthild Nagel
could respond that the problems I mention are not
for his discourse ethics, because they addre
conventional level. However, I contend that the
between conventional and postconventional stag
to obscure the methodological solipsism at wo
appeal to my own rational capacity to sort out u
judgments and find my account simply confirm
(rational) self. As Dean points out, discourse eth
recipes that tell the moral agent which venue o
making to follow on the postconventional level.
fall-back position seems to be this: What cou
judgment, which needs to be weeded out in discu
seems to be predicated on the Kantian "neutral"
of a coherent, self-interested, and monological s
The ethic of care also relies on a modernis
intersubjectively posited, relational selves. It is
way that indicates a limited understanding of l
Most Gilligan feminists have in mind a care that
filtered, virtually free of distorted sentiments;
"care" for dependents, for the sick, is unquestion
ask: Are carers obliged to be serving their ablewho are abusers? Can practicing "authentic" car
of abusiveness? Neither theories of justification
care provide adequate answers for such question
Let me now turn to another problem of th
dimension of discourse ethics. One of the under
entertained in Meehan's anthology is that of how t
additive approach, that is, one that simply adds a
that erase the gendered (and raced) first-world s
discourse ethics. If Habermas's account is gende
it be repaired to deal seriously with sexism, het
interlocking oppressions of sexism, racism, and
Allison Weir, in Meehan's book, delineates coge
of a relatively coherent self, even taking into acc
self-identification, such as Gloria Anzaldúa's sel
a Catholic-raised, lesbian Chicana who is trying
her borderland experience (265). Braaten, too, g
analysis of the differing positionality of the li
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 317
activists. Nevertheless, the discussion of race (and imperialism)
is marginal. To be sure, this anthology is subtitled "Gendering the
Subject of Discourse." Yet their lack of attention to race and racism
ought to be troubling to the contributors, since surely none of the
contributors wants to commit Habermas's error of draping the
subject in a universal—that is, white (fe)male—masquerade.
Concretely, I want to question whether the "generalized other" in
its feminist expanded version is always already a raced subject as
well as a gendered subject (and Dean and Meehan convincingly
"fill in" the missing subject formations in this context). Despite
the emphasis on substantive rationality, on the importance of the
particular, contextualized, gendered subject positions, I would
have found it helpful if the processes of racialization, of the
intersectionality of race and gender, had been addressed and not
simply posed as an "added-on" problem.
Perhaps we have reached the discursive limits of Habermas's
discourse ethics with respect to the topic of race and racism; one
indication might be his use of terms such as "colonization thesis,"
which for him simply denotes the process of increasing
commodification in the life-world (already lamented by Guy
Debord's Situationist Internationale in the 1960s). To my
knowledge, critical race theory has not made use of Habermas's
reflections on juridification to advance its penetrating critique of
Anglo-American legal institutions.
In their discussions of relational feminist approaches to social
identity, the Habermasian theorists foreground affective care,
albeit critically, and discuss its usefulness for a feminist discourse
ethics. However, they tend to focus on normative moral claims,
independent of the economic reality that agents find themselves
in. To the credit of Diemut Bubeck, her account of care begins with
a discussion of women's work.
Bubeck takes a materialist feminist perspective which is an
oddity in ethic-of-care discussions. "Women's work" is a technical
term that is used in a descriptive sense, not as an essentializing
move. As an instructive guiding thread throughout her book,
Bubeck uses (in)famous statistics of the U.N. that effectively
dramatize the appalling economic inequalities women experience
globally. Women receive only one-tenth of the world's income and
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
318 Mechthild Nagel
own less than one-hundredth of the world's pro
they do seventy-five per cent of the wo
consideration of care is motivated by a desire
socioeconomic distribution of benefits and burd
a number of social justice theorists have been
have, for the most part, only marginally dis
division of labor. In contrasting her account of
the mainstream ones, Bubeck states resolutely:
women's work as care... is my final and positiv
challenge of showing how women are unjustly
While many feminist theorists (including
recently argued for a synthesis of "care" a
Bubeck's decisive thesis that in fact to see ju
opposites is wrong, "that the choice between c
false choice" (13). Equally misguided are fem
celebrate care as a liberatory notion while co
rights. (Yet, she also notes correctly that there are
that have little to do with care and are in direct
Habermas's theory, which foregrounds abstract
substantive reason, seems to me—and to the contributors to
Meehan's collection—to be a case of such false choice.
Bubeck starts her analysis by critiquing two conflicting
Marxian theories of work: (a) the problem of necessary versus
abundant labor and (b) the dialectic of labor. The first theory is
gender-blind, since it assumes that all work can be reduced or
abolished. This leaves open for speculation the question of what
Marx would do with certain unfree labor that is irreducible and
typically women's work—unless, of course, one might stipulate,
that for Marx, rearing children is a kind of play.
Bubeck has a sterner vision in mind and conjures up a
cyborg-like scenario that confirms Jean Cohen's horror of
increasing bureaucratization: "Thus imagine a society in which
sick, old-aged, and disabled people are put into fully automated
hospitals and asylums, and where children are brought up by
robots" (28). Marx, as Bubeck notes critically, is not only unaware
of the problem of how to minimize "women's work," but he is also
silent as to how to address minimization of necessary labor for
racial minorities in an advanced industrial society (32). Necessary
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 319
labor may very well be minimized for the (racial, ethnic) majority,
but what distributive safeguards does Marx put in place so that
minorities are not left to bear the brunt of labor that cannot be
reduced?
The second theory, the dialectic of labor, gives an account of
the changing relationships of workers under different modes of
production. In the first phase, workers identify "slavishly" with
their work, with their craft. In the second phase, under capitalism,
workers become alienated from their product, yet at the same time
"free" themselves from natural, slavish identification with their
work. Finally, under communism, workers come to consciously
realize themselves in their work (36-37). This account is also
clearly gendered, as Bubeck notes. While it is conceivable to
include women's work in the division of labor and in dialectical
stage theory, Marx does not mention anywhere a "slavish" rela
tionship of women or that their work could be sublated (41). If the
dialectical progression were to be applied to their work, women
would cease to be naturally designated carers and nurturers and
could choose to be hunters, shepherds, and critics (43).
Since Marx's dialectic of labor fails to include women's work,
Bubeck turns to the analyses of Second Wave Marxist feminists.
Yet the Anglo-American domestic labor debate reveals to Bubeck
that Marxist theory is ill-equipped to understand and measure
women's work in particular, because by focusing on the aspect of
production (of use values), it fails to grasp the care dimension of
women's activities (64). However, I would argue that Miriam
Greenspan's notion of the "labor of relatedness" and Ann
Ferguson's account of sex-affective production is commensurable
with Bubeck's materialist theory of care, since they also address
explicitly the exploitative nature of domestic production, that is,
of the extraction of surplus labor.6 While the domestic labor debate
started out to theorize women's domestic work and women's
oppression by men, these feminist demands were, as Bubeck
convincingly shows, systematically derailed by the functionalist
Marxist position, for example, by the claim that the capitalists
benefit from women's housework (78). The problem with this
"benefit" position is that it sidesteps the issues of how men, not
just capitalists, benefit from women's unpaid labor and why
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
320 Mechthild Nagel
women tend to do this kind of work. It fails t
explanation of how capitalists actually benef
housework by paying a family wage and ign
capitalists do not necessarily even pay a family
The insights to be learned from this functionalis
avoid fitting women's work into the Marxist fr
Marxist analytic concepts can be used as tools a
Despite her own materialist penchant, Bubeck
irreverent with Marx and the Marxist tradition—more bandita
like—than the feminists in Meehan's collection are with
Habermas, since all of them profess to stay put within the
framework of discourse ethics.
Bubeck rejects simplistic exploitation stories, which often
overlook the material status of exploited and exploiter. She gives
a functionalist definition, saying that those whose labor burdens
exceed their benefits are exploited (92). But what measures does
one apply? A utilitarian calculus? How do caring and charity work
get measured? Bubeck concedes that burden and benefits are not
easily assessed, especially when a person occupies both positions
(enjoying privilege and being exploited) in different circum
stances. Therefore it seems to me that it is futile to base such a
definition on material status, especially since Bubeck does not
comment on who is doing the "counting" (of beneficial and
burdensome shares).7
So what kind of ethic of care is liberating? Bubeck avoids
prescribing a particular meta-ethical theory, but seems to lean
towards a utilitarian greatest-happiness model, emphasizing
minimization of harm. Noddings's "myopic model" assumes the
existence of a sharp distinction between "law and justice" on the
one side and "receptiveness, relatedness, and attentiveness" on the
other side. In upholding her ethic of care, Noddings simply and
completely rejects considerations of justice. Bubeck realizes that
it is difficult to imagine that an ethic of care could indeed allow
for distributive justice to work within it. She avers that one simply
needs to avoid a romantic and repressive ethic of care. So rather
than outright rejecting an ethic of care, Bubeck is interested in
expanding a Gilligan and Noddings model that takes women's
different positionalities into account.
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 321
In her reworking of the ethic of care, she is interested in
decentering previous models that focus on the agent alone and not
on her effects. Instead of endorsing a subj ectivist model, she favors
an objective one, which looks at both private and public care.
Public care is beneficial because it is impersonal, or rather could
be impersonal, and thus could help relieve a mother's chores, guilt
ridden anxieties, and so on. Bubeck contrasts her advocacy for
public care with Noddings's appreciation for proximity and
relatedness of care. Noddings apparently affirms an agent's choice
to prefer caring for a bigoted relative rather than becoming active
in a progressive cause. Bubeck uses Noddings's problematic
example to stress the need to use care in a less personalized, more
public setting (220). Public care (e.g., in a hospital emergency
room) needs to adhere to principles of justice; one key issue is to
avoid the appearance of favoritism, of tending to one's own kin
first. Yet, this does not require that public care has to be devoid of
personal attentiveness.
Even though many ethic-of-care theorists focus on the agent,
the care-giver, they still fail to ask the pertinent question: Why is
it that women still do the bulk of care, across race and class
boundaries? Bubeck gives an account of a revised Marxist feminist
"exploitation story" that looks critically at the ideological con
struction of women's care, "the circle of care," which proves to be
an abyss from which women cannot escape (181).
Bubeck disagrees with those Marxists who claim that it is
primarily the capitalist who benefits from women's household
work; she also finds limiting feminists who argue that it is
husbands who benefit. Rather it is all men who benefit from
women's unpaid work; we need to look at this work, more
specifically, as care, in which women engage and are exploited.
Hence, care is most of all an exploitative practice; this is why
Bubeck is less sympathetic to feminist accounts, particularly that
of Noddings, who ignores that evaluation and thus reinscribes the
oppressive function of care (184).
Benhabib's discussion of the generalized versus concrete other
is portrayed by Bubeck as another extremist position. Bubeck
points out that justice cannot neatly be aligned with the generalized
other, and care with the concrete other (215), so that the issue, no
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
322 Mechthild Nagel
matter what, says Benhabib, is not to present the
and justice." Care is not always a proximate, per
as the case of public care shows. In fact em
hospitals is—and ought to be—completely
ministered, and relatedness or nepotism is u
That does not mean that personalized attention
public care, even if this is one's impression fr
care workers entangled in a web of bureauc
Rather than lamenting the impersonalized characte
one ought to reflect on the beneficial aspect
professional carers who are not related to the peop
are often better trained to take care of them th
This argument should allay Jean Cohen's fe
cratization of the life-world.
In Bubeck's careful analysis, "justice cum
mechanical adding up of principles, but is i
ferentiated. Thus she does not repeat the mistaken
of the ethic-of-care feminists, and has to be recko
critics (e.g., Habermas, Kohlberg) who dismiss
for being essentialist, "justice-blind," and s
problematic.
The strength of Bubeck's analysis lies in her c
of various models of ethic of care; she interrogate
the basis of whether they are useful in high
oppression, or whether in fact their heralding of
voice" furthers rather than subverts wome
Bubeck claims that Noddings's radically contex
care lends itself to that latter interpretation. In th
rejection of considerations of justice, ethic-o
overlook the problem of fair distribution, or the b
unremunerated "labor of love" that carers carry
With refreshingly unsentimental materialist
explores the benefits of being subjected to e
might create the conditions of refusal, of resis
who become aware of their situation might eng
opportunity, carers could very well turn into figh
the notion of "othermothering" comes to mind
standpoint theory and ethic of care to forge an Af
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 323
theory highlighting affinity or connectedness among women in
black communities. Care, in this context, rather than being
oppressive, is seen as a force of resistance.9
Some of the weaknesses of Bubeck's book have to do with the
commonality versus difference problem. Even though Bubeck
does not build her own exploitation story on the model of women
as wives, her attempt to see women as carers still draws on the
model of the nuclear family (in a white-dominated industrialized
country such as the U.K.), for instance, in the ethical dilemma
examples she poses. How differentiated is the generalized other,
one might ask with Benhabib? In her variability catalogue, she
mentions immigrants who "tend" to have larger family sizes and
rely on extended kin for caring practices. While I am not going to
dispute the facts that she seems to base this on, why assume that
the (white) nuclear family model she employs for her examples is
fact not fiction?
Another blind spot is her insistence that care is to be distributed
equally among "able-bodied" adults. Is she trying to establish
some objective measure of quality care? Surely, she cannot mean
to disqualify older children who care for their younger siblings and
other kin? Or differently-abled persons who want to take care of
themselves and their partners, children, and so on, but are forced
to live in an environment that discriminates against them, so that
they have to rely on other care-takers.
It may be too sweeping and reductivistic a charge to state that
all men benefit from female (maternal) care and don't participate
equally—and I am not just thinking of elderly men taking care of
their ailing wives.10 While Bubeck critiques Delphy and
Leonard's antiquated model of family relations and obligations
(123), there is also very little discussion of "queerie" family
settings in her own account. Can we only imagine gay men as
caricatures of female care behaviors, à la Torchsong Trilogy, where
one partner imitates/parodies the maternal side? There seems to
be more than simply the "good will of a husband" that is at stake
here (cf. 99).
The problem with talking about "care," theorizing care, is that
we have a commonsensical notion of it, and we may very well be
espousing fictional, stereotypical platitudes of "authentic care"
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
324 Mechthild Nagel
and leave very little room for mythic-tran
realistic portrayals of what real people do (mot
Medea, notwithstanding). Bubeck has taken up
mystification of care, particularly when care
service. Meeting a need for a dependent, for an in
function, whereas satisfying needs of someone
activity for himself is merely rendering a serv
A key challenge for the ethic-of-care theoris
an essentialist construction of a "woman's voice" that is not
necessarily a "victim's voice"; here Bubeck's insistence on talking
about the vulnerability of women as carers comes to mind (124).
If Foucault is right in suggesting that power also comes from
below, how can that be applied to women's resistance to care?
From antiquity on, a number of narratives about women's (mythic)
resistance to patriarchal, imperialist hegemony have recounted the
possibility of withholding reproduction—a birth-strike; rarely, if
ever, are there accounts of women's "care-strikes" except for the
truly monstrous mothers accounts, such as Euripides' Medea. Of
course, as with the fear of castration, these stories may reveal more
about male erotic anxieties than about women's actual threatening
initiatives.
In conclusion, I want to return to Meehan's collection and ask:
What are the promises of Habermasian discourse ethics vis-à-vis
social justice? Despite the laudable efforts by this successor of the
Frankfurt School (of Horkheimer/Adorno) to provide us with a
model that does not merely reflect the Kantian monological
subject, and the considerable attempts of the feminists of
Meehan's collection to imbue the social self with gender (and other
voices), I am skeptical of whether Habermas's social theory, in
particular his postconventional ethics, supplants or sublates the
Marxian notion of ideology critique. Rather than questioning
Habermas's politics and commitment to social justice, all the
feminist authors are preoccupied with tearing down some of his
structuralist distinctions (e.g., life-world versus system,
justification versus application, abstract rationality versus
substantive reason, generalized other versus concrete other), to
make the master theory more amenable to their concerns about
solidarity, respect, and care.
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Critical Theory Meets the Ethic of Care 325
Yet, arguably, Hossenfelder's polemic gesture with respect to
the uses of a postmonological discourse ethics hits the mark and
puts into doubt the merits of such revisionist efforts: "Here, too,
the few have to lead the discourse on behalf of all (of us), and in
order to accomplish this credibly, they have to follow the criteria
of rationality. But then the detour via discourse is superfluous,
since one could simply follow those criteria."11 Despite fetishist
disavowals of the monological, solipsistic subject, the proposal to
add-and-stir-in the flavors of pluralism and the uncoerced force of
the better argument to the Kantian moral subject only reinforces
the monological, albeit pluralist monological character of the
Habermasian subject(s).
Even though I also remain skeptical about the political merits
of an ethic of care, Bubeck's materialist conception of it and her
Marxist use of ideology critique seem in the end to be more
promising than the proposal of a feminist user-friendly communi
cative rationality that could also somehow encompass care.13
Notes
1. Bubeck and Meehan thus continue the trend of revisionist interpretations in
feminist political theory; some other notable contributions to this field are
Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornell (eds.), Feminism as Critique (Minnea
polis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), and Mary L. Shanley and
Carole Pateman (eds.), Feminist Interpretations and Political Theory (Cam
bridge: Polity Press, 1991).
2. Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism
in Contemporary Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1992).
3. On the postmodem angle of the debate, see Andrew Cutrofello, "Must We
Say What 'We' Means? The Politics of Postmodernism," Social Theory and
Practice 19 (1993): 93-109.
4. On a more "interactive" debate between the two camps, see Seyla Benhabib,
Judith Butler, Drucilla Cornell, and Nancy Fraser, Feminist Contentions
(New York: Routledge, 1992).
5. On this topic, see Rainer Marten, Lebenskunst (München: Wilhelm Fink
Verlag, 1993), p. 50.
6. See Miriam Greenspan, A New Approach to Women and Therapy (New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1983); and Ann Ferguson, Blood at the Root: Mother
hood, Sexuality and Male Dominance (London: Pandora, 1987).
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
326 Mechthild Nagel
7. Nevertheless, Bubeck proceeds with her own "exploit
feminists such as Spelman for disavowing generalizati
one ought to clarify, is not Elizabeth Spelman's positio
that of postmodern feminists (e.g., Judith Butler), contr
mistakenly assumed. Spelman has merely raised the spe
generalizations, invoking an unreflected "speaking for
an arrogant claim of commonality in order to approp
Spelman, Inessential Woman (Boston, Beacon Press,
"Woman: The One and the Many." Delphy and Leo
women's exploitation is certainly guilty of such false
the other hand, as Bubeck's own account shows, it is p
"women" to speak on behalf of women, since, as Spelm
all claims about commonality are arrogant.
8. However, in reality, emergency care is far from bein
and impartially: practices of heterosexism, class bias, r
trism abound in U.S. hospitals.
9. See Patricia Hill Collins, Black Feminist Thought (New
1990); and Stanlie James and Abena Busia (eds.), Theor
nisms (New York: Routledge, 1993).
10. As Dagmar Ganssloser has argued in her discussion o
Jewish women survivors of Auschwitz, it is misleading
women practiced care, e.g., by creating "families" in the
strategy. Men also developed solidarity groups, even e
recipes as a strategy to combat a persistent hunge
"Schwarze Milch der Friihe: Überlebende berichten fib
sale in Auschwitz" (unpublished Master's thesis, Frankf
11. Malte Hossenfelder, "Überlegungen zu einer transzen
des kategorischen Imperativs," in Forum fur Philosop
(1988), p. 291; cited in Guido Lôhrer, Menschliche Wü
liche Geltung und metaphorische Grenze der praktisch
(Freiburg: Alber, 1995), p. 95.
12. Lôhrer, p. 456.
13. Many thanks to Roger Gottlieb and Mary Manke for the
earlier versions of the paper.
Mechthild Nagel
Department of Women s St
Mankato State Universi
[email protected].
This content downloaded from
24.59.96.164 on Sun, 12 May 2024 20:15:55 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms