Kazi, S., & Galanaki, E. (2020). Piagetian theory of cognitive development. Entry in
the Encyclopedia of Child and Adolescent Development (S. Hupp & J. D. Jewell,
Chief Eds.). New York, NY: Wiley. doi: 10.1002/9781119171492.wecad364
Piagetian Theory of Cognitive Development
Smaragda Kazi1 and Evangelia Galanaki2
1 Panteion University of Social and Political Sciences, Greece
2 National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, Greece
Traditionally, cognitive development (see Studying Cognitive Development in
School-Aged Children) focuses on two questions: What changes are observed
throughout development in terms of depth of understanding, robustness of
reasoning and the ability to solve problems, and the differential accumulation and
effectiveness of knowledge acquisition? And how and why do changes occur? Jean
Piaget (see Piaget’s Theory), major founder of and pioneer in the field of cognitive
development for many years, was the first scholar to give substantive answers to these
questions.
To fully comprehend his view on cognitive development, one must be aware of
Piaget’s scientific origins. Piaget was a biologist, interested in the study of
epistemology (the nature and origins of knowledge) through psychological
methods, which he explored in Binet’s psychometric laboratory in Paris. These three
scientific fields contributed to the formulation of his theory.
Piaget’s biological background is obvious in his basic definition of intelligence
(see also Intelligence): “Every response, whether it be an act directed towards the
outside world or an act internalized as thought, takes the form of an adaptation or,
better, of a re-adaptation” (Piaget, 1950, p. 3). According to his definition,
“adaptation must be described as an equilibrium between the action of the
organism on the environment and vice versa” (Piaget, 1950, pp. 6–7). He, thus,
1
defined intelligence as “the state of equilibrium towards which tend all the
successive adaptations of a sensorimotor and cognitive nature, as well as all
assimilatory and accommodatory interactions between the organism and the
environment” (Piaget, 1950, p. 10). Through the construction, expansion, and
integration of mental structures, the individual not only acts (mentally and
behaviorally) following the principles of logic, but also becomes more and more able
to accurately predict future events (Piaget, 1971).
Piaget’s epistemological interests are reflected in his proposition that human
beings gradually construct a more refined, solid, and logically robust representation
of the inner and outer worlds (Piaget, 1977). The epistemological background of his
theory is present in the concepts that are important in the philosophy of knowledge.
Reasoning and logic, and the basic categories of reason, such as quality, quantity,
causality, space, and time, were the subjects of his research for decades (Piaget,
1928, 1929/1979, 1930, 1952a; Piaget & Inhelder, 1956). A reader familiar with
epistemology will be able to identify Kant’s categories of reason in Piaget’s thought.
Finally, Piaget’s psychological background is reflected in the introduction of his
unique clinical method. When he was testing his theory by administrating carefully
designed tasks, Piaget was interested not only in the correctness of the answers but,
more importantly, in the reasoning that had led to the specific answer. In this way,
his theory was cross-validated, since the reasoning level would place the individual
in one of the proposed stages of development.
1. From Concrete to Formal Thought
It may be argued that the attainment of Piagetian formal thought, between 12
and 15 years of age, surpasses the accomplishments, and also the limitations, of the
previous stage, that is, concrete thought, which is attained between 7 and 11 years
of age. Both concrete and formal thought are operational, as opposed to the earlier
Piagetian stages. The sensorimotor stage and the preoperational stage of thought
involve representations but not integrated mental operations. An operation is a type
of action or manipulation, applied either physically to objects or internally to
categories or propositions (as in the case of formal logic). Put another way, an
operation is a means that facilitates problem solving through the organization and
selective use of mentally transformed data about the world. There is a crucial
difference between a simple action and an operation in that the latter is an
internalized, reversible action, which is bound up with other operations in an
integrated structure.
According to Piaget, during concrete thought (Piaget, 1952b, 1954; Piaget &
Inhelder, 1969) two types of transformations are present. The first, inversion, is the
understanding that a transformation is reversible when it produces complete
compensation. For example, the child realizes that changes in one dimension are
counterbalanced by changes in another dimension. In terms of structure, a
transformation is reversible when its reverse results in its cancellation. For example,
the child realizes that a change may be canceled out by actually or mentally
reversing the steps and returning to the original state. In this case, the child realizes
that the product of a direct operation (e.g., adding) and its inverse operation (e.g.,
subtracting what was added before) is nil (0).
The second transformation, reciprocity, is focused on identity. For example, a
child in the stage of concrete thought, when asked to put rods in order of increasing
size, first chooses the smallest one, then the smallest of the ones left, and so on.
These choices show that the child knows that a rod is at the same time smaller than
those not yet placed in the arrangement (i.e., descending seriation, from the biggest
to the smallest) and bigger than the ones that have already been arranged (i.e.,
ascending seriation, from the smallest to the biggest). Thus, a reversible
composition of the relation smaller than and bigger than is present in the child’s
thought. The composition of these reversible relations allows the child to conclude
that A is bigger than C (without being shown these two rods together) if shown that “A
is bigger than B” and “B is bigger than C.”
A composition of reversible actions is observed during concrete thought in
class-inclusion tests. Here, the presence of a mental structure that groups various
inferences related to the data is observed. In concrete thought, the child can
3
compose the operation A + A<prime> = B (e.g., both roses and daisies are flowers)
with the operation B − A<prime> = A (the number of roses is what is left after
subtracting the number of daisies from the total number of flowers).
What, then, is the difference between the stages of concrete and formal
thought? According to Piaget, the answer lies on the difference in the structural
integration between concrete and formal operations: “the range of available
operations can be described in terms of a limited number of interdependent
structures. The structures found and the way in which they are integrated depends
on the stage of development considered; each set of structures can be related to a
particular group of logical forms” (Inhelder & Piaget, 1955/1958, p. xiv, emphasis
original). During the concrete stage, operations are based on a grouping structure,
depending on the logic of classes (for class-inclusion operations, based on the form
of reversibility of inversion or negation) and the logic of relations (for serial
ordering, based on the form of reversibility or reciprocity).
Thus, although inversion and reciprocity are present during concrete thought,
there is no general structure to integrate transformations by inversion and
transformations by reciprocity into a single system. This system emerges in the
logic of the adolescent, which shows that the two forms of concrete operational
reversibility are coordinated into a single system, that is, the inversion of the
reciprocal or the reciprocation of the inverse. Here the original identity or the
reciprocal interrelations of an object (or category or proportion) can be inversed or
an inversed object (or category or proportion) can acquire a different identity (or
can be characterized by different reciprocal interrelations).
Attainment of the above structure leads to the realization that (1) the apparent
properties of a specific object (category or proposition) is just one tangible
combination of its inherent properties, among other (real or imagined) equally
probable combinatory versions of the same properties; (2) it is possible to grasp all
the instances that may result from the combinations of the absence and/or the
presence of these inherent properties; (3) in this way, any object (category and
proposition), stripped from its real physical properties, may then be conceived as
an abstract entity; and (4) finally, it is possible to combine these abstract entities so
as to construct mental/abstract realities which can still be imagined, regardless of
whether or not they can possibly exist.
Thus, whereas concrete operations provide the means for structuring the
immediately present reality, formal thought leads to the conception of both the real
and the possible. In accordance with this, during the formal stage, the adolescent’s
logic becomes propositional. Thus, another striking difference between concrete and
formal operations, apart from the integration of operations, is that the latter are
performed on propositions (i.e., statements referring to reality) rather than directly
on reality (Inhelder & Piaget, 1955/1958).
The propositions on which formal operations are performed are conceived by
the adolescent as variables, which are hypothesized to be either the cause or the
result of changes in the (inner or outer) environment. In this way, formal thought
results in a segmentation of reality into continuously transformed propositions (e.g.,
in the form “if…, then…”). Also, during formal thought, the adolescent can
consider simultaneously more than one single relation or variable at a time.
But, as stated by Inhelder and Piaget (1955/1958, p. xxii), “formal thought is
more than verbal reasoning, or else, propositional logic. It also entails a series of
operational schemata which appear along with it; these include combinatorial
operations, propositions, double systems of reference, a schema of mechanical
equilibrium (equality between action and reaction), multiplicative probabilities,
correlations, etc.” Thus, according to the authors, any reference only to the specific
operations of propositional logic is not sufficient for understanding the
development of formal thought. In the general Piagetian view of development,
integration is a key concept for fully understanding the transition between stages.
In the case of the transition from concrete to formal thought, Piaget refers to
“integrated structures” on which the specific operations of propositional logic are
based, and specifically their integration into a combinatorial system or a structured
whole (Inhelder & Piaget, 1955/1958).
The structured whole has the following properties: (1) It allows composition, that
5
is, not only the assimilation of the facts in the form of propositions but, more
importantly, their arrangement according to all the possible combinations. (2) By
applying reversibility and complete compensation, the adolescent is able to create
successive situations where each possible explanation, which has already been
constructed and held in mind, is then systematically checked for its truth or fallacy.
Thus, according to Piaget (Inhelder & Piaget, 1955/1958), the development of formal
thought is simultaneously moving toward a construction of wholes (i.e., integration
of the parts or elements through composition) and a finer and detailed
discrimination of the parts that comprise the whole (i.e., apart from being integrated,
the parts are clearly separable from each other, through reversibility and
compensation).
An example that illustrates this is when children are shown several rods of
different lengths, thicknesses, and materials, and are asked to propose a pair of rods
that would constitute a fair test of the hypothesis “Long rods bend more than short
rods.” During the stage of concrete thought, a child would test pairs of rods of
different length and, by trial and error, find a pair of rods, regardless of their material
or thickness, that would certify the hypothesis. In contrast, a formal thinker, who
would be able to think propositionally and abstractly, would realize that if, ideally,
there were two rods that differ only in their length then their comparison would lead
to the undeniable conclusion that flexibility can be ascribed only to length. But, in
reality, rods have more properties than just their length (e.g., material).
The next possible mental act that would assimilate or resemble these ideal,
imagined rods would be to negate or cancel out all the other properties of the rods.
Thus, all possible variables are checked and are either rejected or accepted as
logical causes of the effect observed. As already mentioned, Piaget (Inhelder &
Piaget, 1955/1958) believed that this type of reasoning, whereby all relevant
dimensions are tested through successive, systematic trials by keeping stable all
others except the one that is being manipulated in order to ascertain its possible
causal role, can be achieved only if inversion and reciprocity are integrated to such
an extent that the thinker can understand their equivalence.
Therefore, an adolescent or an adult, faced with a cause–effect problem,
would first come up with a model where all possible variations are included, thus
taking into consideration a priori the length of the rods, their material (e.g., wood,
steel, or plastic), and their thickness. That is, all propositions (or possible
explanations) are already internally stated and combined, before the actual testing of
the hypotheses takes place. In the statement posed (“Long rods bend more than short
rods”), the only way to negate and cancel out the effects of the other properties
would be to make them the same, thereby still affecting flexibility but to the same
degree (e.g., comparing two rods made of the same material and of the same
thickness, differing only in length). Only by controlling for these intervening
properties can any observed difference in the flexibility of the rods be attributed to
their differences in length.
Formal thinkers, though, would not stop their experimentation at this point.
Since the propositional operations function as a whole, which is internally
structured, they would elaborate more on the question as to whether flexibility can
be ascribed only to length. They would proceed with controlling whether the
material (e.g., wood or steel) affects the flexibility, controlling, this time, for length
and thickness, or whether the thickness exerts any effect, controlling for length and
material. The end product would be a synthesis where all properties and their
combinations are tested, and the conclusion would reflect the systematicity with
which all properties were controlled for (e.g., “It is true that longer rods bend more
easily than shorter rods, provided that they are equally thick and made of the same
material, but also that steel rods bend more easily than wooden rods of the same
length and thickness”).
2. Characteristics of Formal Thought
All specific characteristics of formal thought derive from the propositional
logic, the structured whole, and the integration of inversion and reciprocity into an
integrated system. Five main abilities emerge from the attainment of these:
A formal thinker has the ability to conceive both the possible and the
7
real, for example, “What if there were rods whose only property would be
length and nothing else?” On the contrary, a concretely thinking child
conceives the real and works toward the possible.
Formal thought is hypothetico-deductive. An adolescent becomes
capable of forming hypotheses that would explain cause–effect relations
and also of deducing their truth. On the contrary, a concretely thinking child,
although able to form hypotheses based on reality, lacks the ability to design
experimentation that would lead them to complete deductions.
Formal thought is combinatory. This enables the construction of
mental models that control all possible variables and their combination as
causes and then, through the control-of-variables strategy, to the extraction
of valid conclusions. A concretely thinking child does not seem to be able
to conceive of all the possible combinations and their experimentation is
random and incomplete.
A formal thinker can discriminate between the robustness of a
conclusion and the reality per se. Where the premises do not coincide with
reality, they can decide on the validity of the conclusion, based on the
application of logical rules. A child, however, is still bound to reality and will
thus reject valid conclusions in case they derive from invalid premises.
The formal stage involves reflective thinking. Adolescents are
capable of thinking about their thoughts and ideas, critically analyzing them,
and systematizing them in a deliberate construction of theories.
3. Universality of Formal Thought
Piaget (Inhelder & Piaget, 1955/1958) believed that formal thought was the
last stage of equilibrium, preparing the adolescent to efficiently enter and to adapt
to the adult world. There is no doubt that human development, as conceived by
Piaget, was very influential. There is also no doubt that the experiments he designed
were appropriate for capturing the transformation of thought and the transitions
from one stage to the next. Despite the recognition that Piaget’s theory received,
some serious doubts were raised, grounded in robust empirical data, about the
universal attainment of formal thought. When Piagetian experimental testing for
the acquisition of formal thought were replicated, the results were disappointing,
in that more than half of the population of adolescents and adults failed to operate
as formal thinkers. In addition, formal reasoning did not appear to be a generalized
ability in all subject areas (Markovits & Barrouillet, 2002), and, although
application of formal operations was not spontaneous for some participants,
appropriate questions or probing led them to exhibit formal thinking (Stone & Day,
1978), or their performance was advanced when people were collaborating within
groups rather than working individually (Dimant & Bearison, 1991).
An explanation for these data may derive from Piaget’s background as a
biologist, an epistemologist, and a clinician. Perhaps his biological background misled
him in terms of the generalizability of formal operations. Piaget conceived of
intelligence as an adaptation mechanism, which, once attained, is bound to be applied
to every aspect of an individual’s environment. Although Piaget was aware that in
concrete thought the attained operations were not applied in perfect synchronicity (i.e.,
they show a decalage, or time lag, in attainment), the overall picture was that gradually
the concrete operations would be steadily used across all domains. Furthermore, given
that his data robustly verified the expected shift to all the previous stages he had
conceived (from sensorimotor to preoperational to concrete thought), it seems perfectly
logical and consistent to have assumed that the upcoming shift from concrete to formal
thought would also apply to all individuals.
As stated later by Piaget himself (1972), and as confirmed by the crossvalidation of his view, formal thought is definitely not a generally applicable way
of thinking, but is bound to certain areas of expertise. In this way, the same person
may spontaneously answer as a formal thinker when deciphering relations in a
certain domain of thought but as a concrete thinker in another domain, where his
or her accumulated knowledge and expertise is limited. This is an interesting
finding, which goes far beyond the actual intraindividual differentiation of
9
performance. It contributes to the mainstream question about the unity and/or the
modularity of the mind, not only on the level of performance (Karmiloff-Smith,
1995) but on the neuropsychological level (for an overview, see Demetriou &
Spanoudis, 2018). The finding is also relevant to the observed interindividual
differences in cognitive development, an area that was not elaborated in the Piagetian
theory.
In addition, the area of expertise may not be necessarily related to formal
schooling or education. This connects to the second dimension of Piaget’s
background, the epistemological one. Piaget’s theory was greatly influenced by the
Kantian concepts of reasoning and logic and the basic categories of reason such as
quality, quantity, causality, space, and time. Here a gap appears between science
and real life. It seems that the “Piagetian human being” and the adult world that
Piaget conceived were almost purely scientific. But is this the case in the real world?
The answer is definitely no. Given that, it is not a surprise that an individual may
fail to apply formal operations, when tested with experiments that are inspired
mainly by the world of science. Familiarity, thus, would play an enormous role in
the quality of the answers given by the participants. In accordance, there are
numerous studies (coming especially from the conceptual change paradigm)
showing that the acquisition of any scientific knowledge is a slow process,
characterized by conflicts and misconceptions (see Vosniadou, 2013, for further
elaboration). It has also been shown that analytic thinking and the application of
appropriate strategies may not be attributed to age or growing per se, but mostly to
the systematic and long-term teaching of the scientific knowledge. From this angle,
the conflicting results on the universality of the formal thought may be more easily
interpreted, bearing in mind interindividual differences in familiarity with the
testing context, the amount of teaching, the accumulation of relevant knowledge,
and, most importantly, differentiation between real life and science.
The third dimension concerns the clinical methodology that Piaget adopted.
Piaget was interested in the spontaneous intelligence of the child and the
adolescent. This method was fascinating because it permitted a robust validation of
his theory, by allowing the individual to unfold the operations that they apply.
However, two reservations emerge: Were the participants motivated enough to try
their best during testing? And why was the possible difference between
spontaneous answers and answers produced after appropriate probing not of any
value to Piaget? As far as motivation is concerned, there is no doubt that
methodology plays a crucial role in the quality of the answers provided by
participants. When someone is not interested in the setting of an experimental
condition, finds no value in engaging with it, or, even worse, is repulsed by it, it is
more than certain that there will be a remarkable divergence between attained and
observed performance.
As far as probing is concerned, focusing on the spontaneous answers has its
own merit, but it also leads to two equally interesting questions. The first is: Given
that the application of formal operations can be probed, is it also possible that
formal thought can be taught at an earlier age than that stated by Piaget? Answers
to this question are contradictory. Yes, it can be taught but not completely or
efficiently enough, since taught formal operations cannot be generalized to other
domains than the ones in which training took place. The second question is: How
logical are we as human beings in real-life conditions? In his lab, Piaget did not help
his participants to perform at their optimum level, and this tactic certainly led to an
underestimation of their cognitive abilities. But, even if he would, would that
change how people think, act, and make decisions in their everyday life? For
example, when a person is faced with a personal dilemma, the chances are that they
would not be helped (or be willing to be helped) to make the best possible choice
by someone who has already attained the formal level of reasoning. Thus, probing
would have been (and is) extremely informative on a theoretical level but, given that
Piaget’s main focus was on the equilibrium between the individual and their
environment, it makes perfect sense that he did not allow for any kind of probing
when designing or administrating his tasks for children and adolescents.
3. Conclusions
11
Piaget conceived of development as a process of four distinct qualitative
stages. He attributed cognitive change to the mechanisms of assimilation,
accommodation, and equilibrium, and to the integration of mental operations into
organized structures that differ at every consecutive stage in their complexity and
their efficiency at minimizing the conflicts between already acquired knowledge and
the situations at hand. He claimed that the attainment of abilities developed in each
stage was universal and holistic (with the exception of formal thought, which
maintained its universality but was constrained by individuals’ areas of expertise).
In addition, Piaget focused on the development of logical mathematical
thought, and of specific areas of reasoning (such as causality, time, and space).
Furthermore, he introduced a clinical method to reveal the child’s stage of
reasoning. Finally, he conceived of intelligence as the human’s tool for adaptation
and considered formal thought to be the last stage in human development which
would ensure that no more disturbances would be encountered in our adaptation to
the adult world and that equilibrium would henceforth be stabilized.
Hundreds of thousands of pages have been written on each of these
propositions, either in favor of or criticizing the Piagetian view of development.
For example, the very existence of stages is greatly disputed. The mechanisms of
cognitive change proposed by Piaget have also been an area of controversy, with
scholars from different traditions proposing alternative stages and/or mechanisms
of cognitive development, and emphasizing, for example, the attainment of
appropriate strategies in reasoning and problem solving, conceptual changes, or the
development of core cognitive abilities, such as speed of processing, executive
functions (see Executive Functioning in Children), and memory (see Working
Memory Development). Another area of dispute concerns the adequacy of the
Piagetian holistic mechanisms of cognitive change to explain the whole range of
human development, especially intra- and interindividual differences (see also
Siegler & Alibali, 2005).
The Piagetian methodological clinical approach has also been received with
skepticism. It has been shown that, as a method, it could not always reveal the
participant’s actual reasoning abilities, since intervening factors (such as
familiarity, memory span, motivation, misinterpretation of the requirements of the
tasks) often led to an underestimation of the participant’s performance (as in
Sinnott, 1975).
Furthermore, conceiving of the infant, the child, and the adolescent as potential
experimenters, with the end product being the attainment of a logical–
mathematical mind, has also been greatly disputed, because performance in real-life
settings may differ substantially from that in experimental settings.
Accordingly, a number of theorists have claimed that the strict logical
reasoning of an adolescent, in reality, may lead to maladaptation rather than
adaptation. Whereas for a scientist the attainment of a strict methodological
approach is a prerequisite, adaptive functioning as a member of a society requires
flexibility and recognition that there are situations where, by the very nature of
our interactions with others in various social settings, there are not “right” or
“wrong” conclusions, as there are in strict experimentation. Most of the situations
we are dealing with are multivariate and conflicting, so that we have to gradually
admit that nothing around us is either black or white, an acceptance that leads us
to the acquisition of postformal thought. Postformal thought entails the conclusion
that, in reality, we are constantly solving problems within a gray area, where our
decisions are best made when balancing costs and benefits (see Labouvie-Vief, 2006).
Another stream of research posits that humans continue to develop cognitively
throughout the lifespan (e.g., Moshman, 1998; Schaie, 1978; see also Transition from
Adolescence to Emerging Adulthood).
These points do not, in any way, undermine the great contribution of Piaget.
Even if developmental psychologists disagree with some or with all of the Piagetian
postulates, they would have to agree that Piagetian theory was one of the most
influential theories in the history of science, providing an initial ground for the
formulation of the theories to come. As a final note, Piaget continued to influence the
course of developmental psychology, as the ancestor of a prominent group of neoPiagetian theorists (such as Case, 1992; Demetriou, Shayer, & Efklides, 1992;
13
Demetriou & Spanoudis, 2018; Fischer, 1980; Halford, 1993; Pascual-Leone, 1970).
SEE ALSO: Intelligence; Piaget’s Theory; Studying Cognitive Development in
School-Aged Children; Theories of Adolescent Development: Overview; Transition
From Adolescence to Emerging Adulthood
References
Case, R. (1992). The mind’s staircase: Exploring the conceptual underpinnings of
children’s thought and knowledge. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Demetriou, A., Shayer, M., & Efklides, A. (1992). Neo-Piagetian theories of cognitive
development: Implications and applications to education. London, UK:
Routledge.
Demetriou, A., & Spanoudis, G. (2018). Growing minds: A developmental theory of
intelligence, brain, and education. London, UK: Routledge.
Dimant, R. J., & Bearison, D. J. (1991). Development of formal reasoning during
successive peer interactions. Developmental Psychology, 27, 277–284.
doi:10.1037/0012-1649.27.2.277
Fischer, K. W. (1980). A theory of cognitive development: The control and
construction of hierarchies of skills. Psychological Review, 87, 477–531.
doi:10.1037/0033-295X.87.6.477
Halford, G. S. (1993). Children’s understanding: The development of mental models.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Inhelder, B., & Piaget, J. (1955/1958). The growth of logical thinking from childhood
to adolescence: An essay on the construction of formal operational structures.
New York, NY: Basic Books.
Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1995). Beyond modularity: A developmental perspective on
cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Labouvie-Vief, G. (2006). Emerging structures of adult thought. In J. J. Arnett & J. L.
Tanner (Eds.), Emerging adults in America: Coming of age in the 21st century
(pp.
59–84).
Washington,
DC:
American
Psychological
Association.
doi:10.1037/11381-003
Markovits, H., & Barrouillet, P. (2002). The development of conditional reasoning: A
mental
model
account.
Developmental
Review,
22,
5–36.
doi:10.1006/drev.2000.0533
Moshman, D. (1998). Cognitive development beyond childhood. In W. Damon (Series
Ed.) & D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 2.
Cognition, perception, and language (5th ed., pp. 947–978). New York, NY:
Wiley.
Pascual-Leone, J. (1970). A mathematical model for the transition rule in Piaget’s
developmental stages. Acta Psychologica, 32, 301–345. doi:10.1016/0001-6918
(70)90108-3
Piaget, J. (1928). Judgment and reasoning in the child. London, UK: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Piaget, J. (1929/1979). The child’s conception of the world. New York, NY: Harcourt,
Brace.
Piaget, J. (1930). The child’s conception of physical causality. New York, NY:
Harcourt, Brace.
Piaget, J. (1950). The psychology of intelligence. London, UK: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Piaget, J. (1952a). The child’s conception of number. London, UK: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Piaget, J. (1952b). The origins of intelligence in children. New York, NY: International
Universities Press.
Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in the child. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Piaget, J. (1971). Biology and knowledge: An essay on the relations between organic
15
regulations and cognitive processes. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Piaget, J. (1972). Intellectual evolution from adolescence to adulthood. Human
Development, 15, 1–12. doi:10.1159/000271225
Piaget, J. (1977). The development of thought: Equilibration of cognitive structures.
New York, NY: Viking Press.
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1956). The child’s conception of space. London, UK:
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1969). The psychology of the child. New York, NY: Basic
Books.
Schaie, K. W. (1978). Toward a stage theory of adult cognitive development.
International Journal of Aging and Human Development, 8, 129–138.
doi:10.2190/1TEA-M6PK-28A0-49HV
Siegler, R. S., & Alibali, M. W. (2005). Children’s thinking (4th ed.). Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice Hall.
Sinnott, J. D. (1975). Everyday thinking and Piagetian operativity in adults. Human
Development, 18, 430–443. doi:10.1159/000271504
Stone, C. A., & Day, M. C. (1978). Levels of availability of a formal operational
strategy. Child Development, 49, 1054–1065. doi:10.2307/1128745
Vosniadou, S. (2013). Conceptual change in learning and instruction: The
framework theory approach. In S. Vosniadou (Ed.), International handbook
of research on conceptual change (2nd ed., pp. 11–30). New York, NY:
Routledge.
Further Reading
Demetriou, A., & Spanoudis, G. (2018). Growing minds: A developmental theory of
intelligence, brain, and education. London, UK: Routledge.
Flavell, J. H. (1963). The developmental psychology of Jean Piaget. New York,
NY: Van Nostrand.
Piaget, J. (1950). The psychology of intelligence. London, UK: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Piaget, J. (1970). Piaget’s theory. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.), Carmichael’s handbook of
child psychology (pp. 703–732). New York, NY: Wiley.
17