A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
Leslie Allan
Published online: 9 November 2015
Copyright © 2015 Leslie Allan
The author contends that classifying theories in the field of meta-ethics along a single
dimension misses important nuances in each theory. With the increased sophistication
and complexity of meta-ethical analyses in the modern era, the traditional
cognitivist–non-cognitivist and realist–anti-realist categories no longer function
adequately. The author categorizes the various meta-ethical theories along three
dimensions. These dimensions focus on the linguistic analysis offered by each theory, its
metaphysical commitments and its degree of normative tolerance.
To cite this essay:
Allan, Leslie 2015. A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories, URL =
<http://www.RationalRealm.com/philosophy/ethics/taxonomy-meta-ethical-theories.html>
To link to this essay:
www.RationalRealm.com/philosophy/ethics/taxonomy-meta-ethical-theories.html
Follow this and additional essays at: www.RationalRealm.com
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial
or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sublicensing, systematic supply,
or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms and conditions of access
and use can be found at www.RationalRealm.com/policies/tos.html
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
1. Introduction
The aim with this typology is to present a classification of meta-ethical theories. Such
a classification helps students new to philosophy to see at a glance the range of views in the
field. It also assists professional philosophers and others interested in the field to explore
the relationships between theories and the nuances of each view.
Such a classification is notoriously difficult and there is no widespread agreement
amongst philosophers how this is to be achieved. This difficulty largely arises because each
meta-ethical theory answers questions in multiple areas of enquiry. Firstly, many theories
seek to provide a linguistic analysis of the ethical terms used in ordinary discourse. They
endeavour to provide an account of the meanings of ethical words such as ‘good’ and
‘right’. Secondly, such theories try to give some account of the psychological and social
functions of ethics and of moral discourse. Thirdly, these theories strive to give an
epistemological account of moral judgements: how we come to know moral truths and the
logical relationships between moral judgements and natural descriptions of the world and
of us. The problem of classification is made all the more difficult as some leading
proponents of particular theories do not address all of these questions or answer them in
unclear and ambiguous ways.
I have found it most useful to classify all of the major meta-ethical theories along
three dimensions. Along the Cognitivism–Non-cognitivism dimension are classified theories
according to whether they regard moral utterances as being truth-apt in the same way that
ordinary descriptive sentences bear truth or falsity. On the Realism–Anti-realism dimension
is shown the extent to which meta-ethical theories take morality to be about a
mind-independent realm. The third categorization along the Monism–Pluralism scale places
meta-ethical theories according to how tolerant they are of competing normative
frameworks.
Many moral philosophers divide meta-ethical theories into Objectivist and
Subjectivist types and then conflate this classification with either the
Cognitivism–Non-cognitivism divide or the Realism–Anti-realism divide. Classifying theories
this way misses an important characteristic and can be misleading. Subjectivism (in the
narrow sense of the view that equates moral judgements with psychological reports of
mental states) is a case in point. Without dispute, Subjectivism is a Cognitivist meta-ethic.
However, classifying it under Objectivism for this reason is both confusing and misleading.
Consider also Ideal Observer and Divine Command Theories. Both these theories
ascribe moral judgments to a single mind with preferences and so may be considered
Subjectivist (in the sense of ‘partial’). On the other hand, the preferences of this being are
held to be epistemically privileged and obligatory for all moral agents and so may be
considered Objectivist (in the sense of being ‘universalist’).
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
2
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
2. Meta-ethical Theory Dimensions
2.1 Linguistic Analysis
What do ethical terms such as ‘good’ and ‘right’ mean and how do these terms
function in ordinary moral discourse? This aspect of moral language is encapsulated in the
Cognitivism–Non-cognitivism dimension. This dimension characterises the extent to which
the meta-ethical theory ascribes propositional weight to moral utterances. Cognitivists see
moral utterances as having a robust truth value in much the same way as ordinary
propositions or statements, such as, ‘Ontario is the capital city of Canada’. For Cognitivists,
moral utterances are essentially about beliefs. In this sense, Cognitivism can be seen as
synonymous with Descriptivism. For Non-cognitivists, on the other hand, moral utterances
are not propositional in nature at all. Non-cognitivist positions lend greater weight to moral
utterances being expressions of attitudes, exhortations, commands or commitments.
Semi-cognitivism straddles the middle ground, maintaining that the central meaning of
moral terms is affective, but allowing some propositional content to moral utterances.
In this dimension, Cognitivism is further divided into three types. Naturalism is the
view that moral facts are exhaustively facts about the natural world. Conversely,
Non-naturalists regard moral properties as non-natural properties of things and events.
Lastly, Relativists translate statements about moral properties into statements about the
preferences of a privileged individual or the group to which the speaker belongs.
2.2 Metaphysical Commitments
To what do ethical terms refer? Do they refer to natural properties of things and
events or do they refer to non-natural or supernatural entities? This aspect of meta-ethical
analysis is captured in the Realism–Anti-realism dimension. Realist positions view moral
values and rules existing in a mind-independent realm, ontologically separate from the
judgements and preferences of particular individuals or groups. Anti-realist proponents, on
the other hand, see moral values and rules as being inextricably embedded within and the
manifestations of human or super-human judgements and preferences. This dimension
mirrors the realist–instrumentalist divide in epistemology and tells another side of the story
compared with the Cognitivism–Non-cognitivism dimension. Quasi-realism strikes an
intermediate position between Realism and Anti-realism. On this view, speakers are
regarded as identifying their moral judgements with some objective feature of reality, while
at the same time maintaining that the affective aspect of moral judgements remains central
to their meaning.
Note that on the Realism–Anti-realism dimension, Realism is not synonymous with
Cognitivism. Subjectivism, for example, attributes robust truth values to moral utterances
(Cognitivist) while regarding moral judgements as reports of the speaker’s preferences
(Anti-realist). On this dimension also, Realist positions are subdivided into Naturalist and
Non-naturalist variants, while the Anti-realism group contains within it a sub-group of
Relativist theories.
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
3
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
2.3 Normative Freedom
How epistemically tolerant is the meta-ethical theory to competing normative
ethical systems? Does the meta-ethical theory allow in-principle for one and only one
epistemically correct normative framework or does it allow epistemic legitimacy to more
than one set of normative judgements? This aspect of normative tolerance is displayed on
the Monism–Pluralism dimension.
Note that this question of tolerance is not a question about the standpoint of a
typical moral agent engaging in normative discourse. It is not a question about how many
normative systems a moral agent subscribing to that meta-ethical view recognizes as
genuine competitors. It is a question about the tolerance level of the proponent of that
meta-ethical view qua meta-ethicist. One way to imagine the Monism–Pluralism dimension
is to consider the special case of a world in which only ideal moral agents existed. (The
properties of an ‘ideal’ moral agent are specified by the meta-ethical theory in question.) In
this world, consider how many normative theories would be accepted by moral agents as
normatively correct. Meta-ethical views that entail that only one normative theory is correct
are, according to this characterization, Monist. Those that entail more than one are
regarded here as Pluralist.
To illustrate this way of classifying meta-ethical views, consider Intuitionism. As a
group, Intuitionists argue for a variety of competing normative systems. Which normative
system a particular Intuitionist proposes depends on how that particular Intuitionist thinks
they sense non-natural moral properties. However, even given this plurality of competing
systems, Intuitionists agree that there is only one normatively correct system of values and
obligations. It is in this sense that I am categorizing them as meta-ethical Monists.
Now contrast Intuitionism with Prescriptivism. Like Intuitionists, Prescriptivists as a
group also recognize a variety of competing normative systems. For a Prescriptivist,
however, in a world consisting entirely of ideal moral agents, there would remain a
multiplicity of normative judgements as moral agents will differ in the prescriptions that
they would want to universalize. For a Prescriptivist, ‘Shut all doors’ is just as epistemically
legitimate a normative position as ‘Keep all doors open’. Prescriptivism, in this sense, is
Pluralist.
This categorization splits the Relativist group into those variants that have a single
moral adjudicator and those that have a multiplicity of adjudicators. Surveying this
dimension tells a richer story compared with just looking at the
Cognitivism–Non-cognitivism dimension or the simplistic Objectivism–Subjectivism
dichotomy.
There is some ambiguity in deciding where to place Existentialism on this dimension.
Seeing Existentialism as promoting a single overriding normative principle—that of
‘authenticity’—leads to placing Existentialism in the Monism camp. Existentialism’s
liberalism in allowing for a multiplicity of ‘authentic’ ethical commitments, on the other
hand, appears to place it in the Pluralist camp. Here, I will draw a parallel between
Existentialism and naturalistic Utilitarianism, with its single overriding principle of
impartiality, and put Existentialism in the Monist camp.
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
4
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
3. Meta-ethical Theory Taxonomy
Linguistic Analysis
Cognitivism
Naturalism
Non-naturalism
Semi-cognitivism
Non-cognitivism
Relativism
Utilitarianism
Intuitionism
Cultural Relativism
Constructivism
Sophisticated Emotivism
Radical Emotivism
Neo-Aristotelianism
Rationalism
Subjectivism
Existentialism
Projectivism
Prescriptivism
Ideal Observer Theory
Revolutionary Fictionalism
Norm-expressivism
Divine Command Theory
Error Theory
Plan-expressivism
Metaphysical Commitments
Hermeneutic Fictionalism
Realism
Naturalism
Quasi-realism
Non-naturalism
Relativism
Utilitarianism
Intuitionism
Sophisticated Emotivism
Cultural Relativism
Radical Emotivism
Neo-Aristotelianism
Rationalism
Projectivism
Subjectivism
Prescriptivism
Norm-expressivism
Ideal Observer Theory
Constructivism
Plan-expressivism
Divine Command Theory
Existentialism
Hermeneutic Fictionalism
Revolutionary Fictionalism
Error Theory
Monism
Normative Freedom
Anti-realism
Pluralism
Utilitarianism
Rationalism
Radical Emotivism
Sophisticated Emotivism
Prescriptivism
Cultural Relativism
Neo-Aristotelianism
Projectivism
Subjectivism
Constructivism
Norm-expressivism
Existentialism
Existentialism
Plan-expressivism
Hermeneutic Fictionalism
Ideal Observer Theory
Revolutionary Fictionalism
Divine Command Theory
Error Theory
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
5
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
Below is a short description of each of the meta-ethical theories classified in the
above typology.
Utilitarianism:
A type of Naturalism that equates morality with facts about what promotes
the welfare or interests of sentient creatures. (J. S. Mill)
Neo-Aristotelianism:
A type of Naturalism that grounds ethics in facts about human nature and
evaluates living things as specimens of their kind. (G. E. M. Anscombe,
P. Foot, P. T. Geach)
Intuitionism:
A form of Non-naturalism that posits that moral qualities are not natural
qualities and that they are perceived directly by a moral sense. (M. Huemer,
G. W. Leibniz, H. J. McCloskey, G. E. Moore, W. D. Ross, H. Sidgwick)
Rationalism:
A form of Non-naturalism that postulates that universalized moral rules can
be deduced by reason alone as synthetic a priori principles. (M. Huemer,
I. Kant, C. Korsgaard)
Cultural Relativism:
A type of Relativism in which moral judgements are understood as the
speaker’s report of their social group’s accepted norms of behaviour.
(F. Boas, G. Harman, E. Westermarck, D. B. Wong)
Subjectivism:
A type of Relativism in which moral judgements are understood as the
speaker’s report of their psychological state of approving or preferring.
(D. Hume, Protagoras)
Ideal Observer
Theory:
A type of Relativism in which the standard for morality is determined by what
is preferred by an impartial ideal observer with perfect knowledge and
without cultural bias. (R. B. Brandt, R. Firth, D. Hume)
Divine Command
Theory:
A type of Relativism in which what is good is what God approves and what is
right is what God commands. (R. M. Adams, P. Copan, P. Quinn)
Existentialism:
The view that ethics is fundamentally grounded in the human freedom to
choose and the imperative to act authentically. (A. Camus, S. Kierkegaard,
J-P. Sartre)
Constructivism:
The view that moral principles are determined through an idealized process
of deliberation and agreement by rational agents. (D. Copp, T. Hobbes,
J. Rawls, T. M. Scanlon)
Radical Emotivism:
The view that moral utterances are simply exhortations of emotions,
attitudes or preferences with no descriptive content. (A. J. Ayer, B. Russell)
Sophisticated
Emotivism:
The view that moral utterances are centrally expressions of attitudes and
preferences while also peripherally describing the object of evaluation in
some way. (D. H. Monro, C. L. Stevenson)
Projectivism:
The view that moral utterances are projections of approval or disapproval as
a property onto an event or object. (S. Blackburn)
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
6
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
Norm-expressivism:
The view that normative judgments express the acceptance of systems of
rules dividing actions under naturalistic descriptions into those that are
forbidden, permitted and required. (A. Gibbard)
Plan-expressivism:
The view that normative judgments express the acceptance of plans to act in
a particular way, depending on the naturalistic circumstances of the speaker.
(A. Gibbard)
Prescriptivism:
The view that moral judgments are universal imperatives to act for any agent
in a similar circumstance to the one judged. (R. Carnap, R. M. Hare)
Hermeneutic
Fictionalism:
The view that moral agents typically pretend to ascribe mind-independent
moral properties to objects and events. (M. E. Kalderon, J. Woodbridge,
S. Yablo)
Revolutionary
Fictionalism:
The view that moral language should be reformed to continue the fiction in
which moral agents falsely ascribe mind-independent moral properties to
objects and events. (R. Joyce)
Error Theory:
The view that moral agents falsely ascribe mind-independent moral
properties to objects and events. (I. Hinckfuss, J. L. Mackie)
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
7
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
References
Allan, Leslie 2015. A Defence of Emotivism, URL =
<http://www.rationalrealm.com/philosophy/ethics/defence-emotivism.html>.
Ayer, A. J. 1971. Language, Truth and Logic, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Bagnoli, Carla 2015. Constructivism in Metaethics, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Spring 2015 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/constructivism-metaethics/>.
Bradley, F. H. 1962. Ethical Studies, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brandt, R. M. 1959. Ethical Theory, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
Chew, M. Y. 1998. A Taxonomy of Moral Realism, paper delivered at Twentieth World
Congress of Philosophy, Wolfson College, URL =
<https://www.bu.edu/wcp/MainTEth.htm> (Retrieved: September 22, 2015).
Foot, P., ed., 1977. Theories of Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Geach, P. T. 1965. Assertion, Philosophical Review 74/4: 449–65.
Hare, R. M. 1972. The Language of Morals, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harman, Gilbert 1977. The Nature of Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heathwood, Chris 2012. A Taxonomy of Metaethics, Ethical Theory, University of Colorado,
URL = <http://spot.colorado.edu/~heathwoo/phil3100SP12/taxonomyhandout.pdf>
(Retrieved: September 22, 2015).
Helm, Paul, ed., 1981. Divine Commands and Morality, New York: Oxford University Press.
Hume, David 1739 (1896). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Joyce, Richard 2015. Moral Anti-Realism, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015
Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/moral-anti-realism/>.
Lenman, James 2014. Moral Naturalism, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring
2014 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/naturalism-moral/>.
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
McCloskey, H. J. 1969. Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Mill, John Stuart 1861 (1962). Utilitarianism, ed. M. Warnock, Glasgow: Collins.
Monro, D. H. 1967. Empiricism and Ethics, London: Cambridge University Press.
Moore, G. E. 1903 (1965). Principia Ethica, London: Cambridge University Press.
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
8
Leslie Allan
A Taxonomy of Meta-ethical Theories
Rawls, John 1972. A Theory of Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ross, W. D. 1939. Foundations of Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Sayre-McCord, Geoff 2014. Metaethics, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer
2014 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/metaethics/>.
Sias, James 2015. Ethical Expressivism, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, URL =
<http://www.iep.utm.edu/eth-expr/> (Retrieved: September 22, 2015).
Stevenson, C. L. 1963. Facts and Values, London: Yale University Press.
Stevenson, C. L. 1976. Ethics and Language, London: Yale University Press.
Russell, B. 1935. Religion and Science, London: Thornton Butterworth.
Urmson, J. 0. 1968. The Emotive Theory of Ethics, London: Hutchinson.
van Roojen, Mark 2015. Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism, The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/moral-cognitivism/>.
Warnock, M. 1978. Ethics since 1900, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wellman, C. 1961. The Language of Ethics, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Wikipedia contributors 2015. Meta-ethics, Wikipedia, The Free Encyclopedia (2015, June 21),
URL = <https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Meta-ethics&oldid=667912961>
(Retrieved: September 22, 2015).
Downloaded from http://www.RationalRealm.com
9