Forthcoming in Inquiry.
Grounding Nonexistence
Daniel Muñoz
Monash University
Contingent negative existentials give rise to a notorious paradox. I
formulate a version in terms of metaphysical grounding: nonexistence
can’t be fundamental, but nothing can ground it. I then argue for a new
solution, expanding on work by Kit Fine. The key idea is that negative
existentials are contingently zero-grounded—that is to say, they are
grounded, but not by anything, and only in the right conditions. If this
is correct, it follows that grounding cannot be an internal relation, and
that no complete account of reality can be purely fundamental.
Introduction
We are the only creatures who think and talk with ‘not’ and its equivalents (Horn 2001: xiii, Altmann
1967: 353–55); a grasp of negation is as distinctively human as walking upright. So it is remarkable
that negation—something we naturally master within a year of our baby steps (Horn 2001: 161)—
has struck so many grown-up philosophers as delusive and dispensable. In the ancient West,
Parmenidies ‘sought to banish all negative thought’ from philosophy (Horn 2001: 50). Russell would
later declare: ‘The world can be described without the word “not”’ (1948: 520). Negation is at best a
nifty shorthand, on this view, not a way to get at fundamental reality.
But like outrunning one’s shadow, metaphysics without negation is tricky business. One
problem is that, according to some writers, like the ancient Indian philosopher Vātsyāyana, the
positive depends on the negative: ‘That which is not is the means of apprehending that which is’ (as
cited by Randle 1930: 331, Horn 2001: 86). A simpler point is that we can’t fully describe the world
unless we give both its positive contents and negative limits: we need ‘Here’s this!’ and ‘That’s it!’
We have ourselves a paradox—an age-old, cross-cultural, metaphysical dilemma. We can’t
live with the negative, and we can’t live without it. But what exactly is the problem? No doubt there
are several tangled up here, but I won’t try to separate them out. Instead I want to take on a simple,
central form of the puzzle, which I will pose in the idiom of metaphysical grounding, with a focus
1
on contingent negative existentials like [There are no flying pigs] and [There are no ghosts].1
(Why grounding? Because it’s flexible and familiar (Schaffer 2009, Fine 2012, Bennett 2017).
Why negative existentials? Because facts with humdrum negative predicates, like ‘dead’ or ‘non-toxic’,
raise presupposition problems.2 Why not a singular fact, like [Pegasus doesn’t exist] or [There is no
such detective as Sherlock Holmes]? To avoid the referential riddles of empty names (Toms 1972: 7,
Braun 1993). Why contingent facts? Because necessary nonexistence, as in [There are no trilateral
squares], might be grounded anti-climactically in essences or laws (Rosen 2010: 119–120).)
Here is our spin on the paradox. What grounds the fact that there aren’t any ghosts? On the one
hand, it is natural to think that this fact must be grounded. There is something to Russell’s hunch
that the negative can’t be fundamental. But it is also natural to think that nothing could ground the
nonexistence of ghosts. After all, there are no fundamental negative facts there to ground it, and no
positive facts could ever guarantee it. This is so because any positive picture of the world, however
unspooky, is consistent with the possibility of there being further things—and those things could very
well be diaphanous particulars, out there haunting houses and saying ‘Boo!’. (What if a positive fact
does seem to rule out there being further things? Then it isn’t really positive!)
Our dilemma is that we apparently can’t have both: (1) that nonexistence must be grounded,
and (2) that nothing can ground it. I begin by presenting the full arguments for these claims (§§1–2),
before I show how they might be—surprisingly—consistent (§3). Nonexistence could be grounded
Let’s get this out of the way. Square brackets are used to denote facts: true structured
propositions. I assume that the positive/negative distinction is metaphysical (Russell 1918: 78-9,
Beall 2000, Molnar 2000: 72ff, Chalmers 2012: 151, Griffith 2015: fn. 11). And for the closest
paradox to mine, see Molnar (2000), whose puzzle is to figure out whether the following ideas could
be ‘co-tenable’: (1) The world is everything that exists; (2) Everything that exists is positive; (3) Some
negative claims about the world are true; (4) Every true claim about the world is made true by
something that exists. See Parsons 2006 for some criticism of Molnar’s setup.
2
Negative existentials are also notable for their prominence in recent literature. ‘No issue is
more hotly contested in truthmaker theory than the problem of negative truths, particularly those
truths that are about what does not exist’ (Asay and Baron 2013: 230).
1
2
precisely in the sense that that is grounded in nothing. This is possible because ‘grounded in
nothing’—if we can trust Fine (2012)—is ambiguous. It could mean that a fact is ungrounded (i.e.
fundamental, not grounded), or it could mean that the fact is zero-grounded: grounded in zero-many
things, as the empty set contains zero-many elements. My claim is that [There are no ghosts] is zerogrounded. I conclude with implications for the theory of grounding and for the negative more
generally. The main consequences are that grounding cannot be an internal relation (§4), and that
purely fundamental accounts of the world can’t be complete (§5).
In other contexts, zero-grounding doesn’t have such radical upshots. That is because zerogrounding is normally thought to hold only necessarily. Since the nonexistence of ghosts is contingent,
it can be grounded only contingently. So I argue that [There are no ghosts] is contingently zerogrounded—and this combination is what makes things radical.
To be sure, contingent zero-grounding sounds odd at first, a combination of two
controversial concepts. But it is the only way to reconcile our two intuitions about nonexistence:
that it’s grounded, and that nothing can ground it. Moreover, even if zero-grounding and contingent
grounding are controversial, they aren’t gimmicks. Contingent grounding has been used in accounts
of universal generalizations (Barceló Aspeitia 2015, Skiles 2015), normative reasons (Dancy 1981,
2004, Bader 2016), and the mind-body problem (Leuenberger 2008).3 Zero-grounding features in
accounts of the grounds of mathematics (Donaldson 2017), of identity (Schumener 2017: §3.3), and
of non-factive grounding facts (Litland 2017). Anyone drawn to these applications has a reason to
take contingent zero-grounding seriously. The same goes for anyone—philosophers, linguists,
whoever—seeking clues to the elusive nature of the negative.
3
See also Briggs 2012 and Barceló Aspeitia 2015 on contingent truthmaking.
3
1. Nonexistence is Grounded
Our paradox has the shape of a dilemma. On the one hand, [There are no ghosts] needs to be
grounded; on the other, nothing seems fit to be the ground. To most philosophers, these claims
sound flatly inconsistent, and so most accounts of negative existential facts give up one claim or the
other. I want to argue that this is move is seriously costly; there are good arguments for both claims.
Let’s start with the arguments for thinking that nonexistence must be grounded.
Intuitively, negative facts are not fundamental—or to put the point a bit more romantically:
‘There is implanted in the human breast an almost unquenchable desire to find some way of
avoiding the admission that negative facts are as ultimate as those that are positive’ (Russell 1956:
287).4 I can think of two ways to back up this majestic intuition. The first is that nonexistence facts
are ‘no extra work’.
If [There are no ghosts] is fundamental, then it can’t be grounded in or generated by other
features of the world. That means that on the day of creation, God had two jobs to do: first, bring
about the existence of positive things like people and planets, perhaps while fleshing them out with
positive properties like shape and colour, and second, bring about the nonexistence of ghosts. But
how could that be a second job? Taking a positively fleshed-out world and ‘making’ it ghostless
doesn’t require any ontological work—just don’t add ghosts! Ghostlessness and the rest of
nonexistence ought to come for free given the positive facts, just as [p & q] is free given [p] and [q].5
Ghostlessness is ‘nothing over and above’ the positive facts about the non-ghosts, or as Armstrong
4
Doubts about fundamental negativity are all over the history of philosophy. For one early
example, see Saint Thomas Aquinas in his commentary on Aristotle’s De Interpretatione: ‘With respect
to the thing, the affirmative enunciation, which signifies to be, is prior to the negative, which
signifies not to be, as the having of something is naturally prior to the privation of it’ (book 1, lesson
13, in Oesterle 1962: 64; cited in Horn 2001: 47).
5
I am not the first to invoke the ‘What did God have to do?’ heuristic in a paper on negative
facts—see e.g. Saenz 2014: 92–3 and Parsons 2006: 592–3.
4
(2010: 80) puts it, ‘“No more” is not something more!’
On to the second reason why nonexistence had better be grounded: recombination. Since
fundamental facts don’t depend on one another, for any combination of the fundamental facts we
should expect to find a possible world where those are exactly the fundamental facts—fundamental
facts should be freely modally recombinable (Armstrong 1997: 196, Bennett 2011a: fn. 6). So if [There are
no ghosts] is fundamental, that means that ghosts’ nonexistence can be recombined with the
fundamental positive facts; so, there must be a possible world w* where the positive facts are the
same, but where ghostlessness is missing. But this is absurd: in order for w* to be positively like our
world, it would have to be ghostless. But for w* to lack ghostlessness, it would have to contain
ghosts! And of course, we can’t abide by any combination that includes positive facts like [Casper is
a ghost] along with [There are no ghosts]. Taken together, Free Modal Recombination and No Extra
Work seem clear and convincing.6
2. Nothing Grounds Nonexistence7
If [There are no ghosts] is grounded, what grounds it? Some say that the ground involves facts about
particular ordinary entities—either positive facts like [Ginger is human] or negative ones like [The
Eiffel Tower is not a ghost]. Others say that the ground is a rather hefty fact about the whole world
(Cheyne and Pigden 2006). Some even think the ground includes both.8
6
One objection to recombination is that it entails that fundamental properties can be had in
isolation. For example, if [Q1 has a mass m] and [Q1 has shape s] are fundamental, recombination
commits us to thinking that there is an odd world where Q1 has a mass but no shape (or any other
fundamental properties). This is ‘the problem of free mass’ (introduced as an argument against the
bundle theory; see Armstrong 1997: 99, Macdonald 1998). The best response, due to Schaffer 2003,
is that nearly all plausible ontologies are committed to free masses—so how bad could they be?
7
The arguments in this section were greatly improved by perceptive and incisive comments
from an anonymous referee at Inquiry. My warmest thanks.
8
For example, Kit Fine’s (2012) view is that [There are no ghosts] is grounded in [a is not a
5
But—intuition number two—none of these is fit to ground nonexistence. You can’t get
nothing from something. This one is also pretty appealing from the start:
Intuitively, what makes a sentence true such as ‘There are no Fs’ is a lack of Fs…it is just
confused to think that we must account for a lack by postulating the existence of something
else…. Such truths are true because certain things don’t exist, and it is wrong to try and
understand this in terms of the existence of something new. (Melia 2005: 69)9
Can we say anything to back up this intuition? I know of three arguments.
One (rough) argument has to do with subject matter: The idea is that [There are no ghosts]
can’t be even partially grounded in any positive fact about a particular entity, like [Ginger is a
human], because [There are no ghosts] is just about ghosts (if anything), not people and their species
(Cartwright 1960). Ginger’s being human, like any positive property of hers, is a ‘new’ subject
matter; and grounding explanations, like any good explanations, aren’t supposed to change the
subject.
This argument is meant to generalise to other possible grounds of nonexistence. If the
grounds are supposed to be negative facts, like [Ginger is not a ghost], these won’t mention new
properties. But they will still involve irrelevant particulars like Ginger, so they still change the subject
from the absence of ghosts. Nor would things be any better if we grounded nonexistence in a
massive positive fact, like [w is F], where w is the world and Fness is a maximally specific positive
property that accounts for the positive properties of w-inhabitants. If anything, [w is F] just changes
the subject even more, since the world includes Ginger and the other non-ghosts.10 Again, good
ghost], [b is not a ghost], etc., where a, b, etc. are all of the things, plus the totality fact: [All things
are identical either to a or to b or…]. More on the totality fact soon.
9
See also Raju (1941: 585): ‘[A negative judgment] cannot be true if there is nothing in reality
corresponding to its Not, and if there is something corresponding to its Not the judgment cannot be
negative’.
10
For a related point, about ‘irrelevance’, see Armstrong on truthmakers for ‘There are no
unicorns’ and ‘There are no centaurs’: ‘I do not deny that the whole world is a truthmaker for these
truths. But is it a minimal truthmaker? I don't think so. Huge swathes of the whole world are really
6
metaphysical explanations don’t change the subject. (They might home in on a more specific or
basic aspect of the subject matter, but sharpening focus is not the same as shifting it.) Whether we
use small facts or big ones, the problem remains: you can’t get nothing from something.
This argument is suggestive, but not decisive. Someone could resist by saying:
Maybe [Ginger is human] and [Ginger is not a ghost] have a different subject matter than
ghostlessness. But they aren’t irrelevant (pace Loss 2017: §3). If Ginger is human, she can’t be a
ghost. If she is a ghost, ghosts exist.11 So there is a rationale for saying that Ginger’s being
human, and her not being a ghost, could be part of the ground for [There are no ghosts].
This is a good challenge. We need something more careful.
So here is a second line of argument, which I endorse. The facts that are generally taken to
ground nonexistence are relevant to it, we can grant, but not as grounds. They play a different role.
The fact that Ginger is a human (or non-ghost) isn’t part of what makes the world ghostless; it
merely represents a failure to prevent it from being ghostless. (Forgive the triple negative.) There is an
analogy here with causation. If my plant dies from lack of water, we wouldn’t say that its death was
caused by anyone and everyone who could have intervened. The Queen of England, though she
could have swooped in to water my plant, didn’t cause it to die. She merely failed to prevent its
death (Sartorio 2004). That is how I think of Ginger and ghostlessness. Her being human isn’t even
part of the ground for [There are no ghosts]. It merely fails to ground [There are ghosts], and so fails
to rule out [There are no ghosts].12
Some might still be skeptical. Isn’t Ginger’s being human, rather than ghostly, in some sense
‘counting in favor’ of the world’s being ghostless? Isn’t it a bit precious to say that this favoring falls
short of grounding? If the skeptics are intent on finding grounds for nonexistence, they admittedly
irrelevant to the non-existence of these animals’ (2010: 85, emphasis original).
11
But see Yablo (ms.) for an argument that negative existentials are about all the positive things.
12
As I will later put it, [Ginger is not a ghost] is the absence of a ‘disabling condition’ (§5).
7
have a decent case for saying that [Ginger is human] is up to the job.
I think this skeptical view is harder to maintain, however, when we look at a fuller range of
examples, since there can be cases where nothing seems to ‘count in favor’ of a negative existential.
One example is a perfectly empty world, totally devoid of objects.13 It’s true here that there are no
ghosts—but there are no positive facts, or even negative facts about positive things, to favor that
negative existential. There are also other cases. Imagine a tiny world with three particles, α, β, and γ,
where the following negative existential contingently holds: [There are no more than three particles].
Does any property of those particles ‘count in favor’ of the negative existential? I don’t think so. If
anything, the positive facts [α is a particle] and [There are at least three particles] count against the
negative existential. Even if [There are no ghosts] can be grounded in particular facts, like [Ginger is
not a ghost], this strategy doesn’t generalise.
The second argument, then, has some force. We can grant that Ginger’s being a non-ghostly
human is relevant to ghostlessness without awarding it the status of a ground. It represents instead a
missed opportunity to prevent ghostlessness, a lack of disruption rather than the presence of a
generator.
My last argument against there being grounds of nonexistence is that it is hard to find a
ground that can necessitate it, and it is widely held that grounds must necessitate the truth of what they
ground—a principle known as:
Necessitation
If a set of facts S grounds B, then it is necessary that if all the facts in S are the case, so is B.14
I myself don’t accept this principle. But those who do, I think, are going to have trouble finding
13
Saenz (2014) discusses such a case at length. (There is some debate over whether an empty
world is possible. Baldwin (1996) argues that it is; Coggins (2010, Chapter 4) argues that it isn’t.)
14
Necessitation is the ‘default view among proponents of grounding’ (Bliss and Trogdon 2014:
§5), endorsed by Correia 2005, Witmer et al. 2005, deRosset 2010, Rosen 2010, Audi 2012a, 2012b,
Trogdon 2013, and Dasgupta 2014.
8
grounds for nonexistence.
Consider what happens if we try to ground [There are no ghosts] in the individual-level facts
about the (non-ghostly) particulars: the XXs (which include all of the actual things, none of which
are ghosts). Among these individual-level facts will be facts like [Ginger is a human], or like [The
Eiffel Tower is not a ghost]. But no matter how many such facts we list out, they won’t rule out the
possibility of ghosts. That is because it is consistent with any such set of facts that there be a further
object y, not among the XXs, such that y is a ghost.
I know of two ways to respond to this argument. One is to appeal to Necessitism, the
controversial view that there can be no contingent beings, no change in what exists from world to
world: necessarily, everything exists necessarily.15 Given Necessitism, the facts about individuals
among the XXs will necessitate [There are no ghosts], since there couldn’t possibly be any other
individuals—and so no other potential ghosts!
I want to grant that Necessitists have a decent grounding story for [There are no ghosts]. To
some extent, they simply get out of the puzzle, and that is a mark in favor of their view. But they
have trouble grounding a certain bigger fact: the totality fact, which says that there are no more things
besides the ones there actually are. It too is a negative existential: [There exists no y that isn’t among
the XXs], where the XXs are all of the actual things. What are the grounds for this fact? What facts
ground the fact that there aren’t any more things? Necessitists can point to some relevant
necessitating facts—all facts of the form [a is among the XXs]. But this answer doesn’t seem like a
good explanation. We are asking why there aren’t further things besides these, the ones there are. It is
not satisfying to be told: ‘Well, none of these is a further thing!’ The effectiveness of this answer
presupposes the very totality fact that we are trying to explain.
15
For recent defenses of Necessitism, see Williamson 2013 and Goodman 2016. See also Linsky
and Zalta 1994, 1996 (whose view is similar, but who officially believe in contingent objects).
9
Now we move to the standard way of finding necessitating grounds of nonexistence, which
is to go beyond facts about individuals and appeal directly to a big fact, like the totality fact, that
concerns the state of the whole world. The hope is that the big fact will (maybe with help from the
individual-level facts) rule out the possibility of there being further things.
The same song is played in different keys. Cheyne and Pigden (2006) would ground [There
are no ghosts] in a massive fact that they would ‘roughly characterize’ as the world as it actually is.
Schaffer (2010) would ground [There are no ghosts] in the world’s (contingently) being the only
fundamental thing. Cameron (2008) would ground it in the existence of the world, which he takes to
be essentially a world, and so essentially not part of a bigger world with ghosts in it. Armstrong (1997,
2004, 2010) and Fine (2012) would partially ground it in a kind of totality fact, a fact saying that all
things are among the XXs (where the XXs are all of the actual things).16
But these proposals, despite their differences, confront the same Big Dilemma: is the ‘big
fact’ positive or negative? If positive, it can’t necessitate nonexistence. If negative, even partly, then
it will itself amount to a negative existential that holds without grounds. We should slow down a bit
to work through this Dilemma in detail.
Start with Cheyne and Pigden, whose ‘big fact’ is clearly meant to be positive. (Their title:
‘Negative Truths from Positive Facts’!) Why think the big positive fact can necessitate the
nonexistence of, say, unicorns? Because there can’t be unicorns without a change in how the world
actually is, which is precisely what the big fact is meant to capture. They write:
the (first order) way the universe actually is (a very large and complex fact, but a positive fact
nonetheless) makes it true that there are no unicorns. For (on the assumption that there are
no unicorns) the universe would have to be a different way for unicorns to exist…the
existence of the actual configuration of the universe necessitates or makes true the
proposition that there are no unicorns. (Cheyne and Pigden 2006: 257)
16
Armstrong is a truthmaker theorist, but we can imagine a ground-theoretic version of his view.
(Same for Cameron, Cheyne, and Pigden.) I also ignore that Amstrong’s totality facts (or ‘totality
states of affairs’) totalise the first-order states of affairs, not the objects (1997: 134, 198; 2010: 78).
10
The problem with this view is simple and familiar (Parsons 2006: 594, Armstrong 2006: 267). Let ‘P’
denote the big, actually comprehensive positive fact. P is intuitively consistent with the presence of
further positive facts, which might involve unicorns—just imagine adding to our world w another
chunk of spacetime populated by one-horned equines. This new world w* would differ from ours in
what the positive facts are. But the big actual positive fact, P, would be present and unchanged in w*. It
would just fail to be the biggest positive fact. This crucial ambiguity is concealed by Cheyne and
Pigden’s phrase ‘how the world actually is’. If ‘how the world actually is’ is just P, then it’s positive,
but it can’t necessitate [There are no unicorns]. If ‘how the world actually is’ includes the fact that P
exhausts the positive facts, then it can necessitate, but it’s no longer purely positive. Unlike P itself, it
is a negative fact that there are no positives beyond P.
The second option is that the big fact is negative. Armstrong explicitly takes this route: for
him, the big totality fact is a negative existential.17, 18 The obvious problem with this is that negative
existentials are exactly what we are trying to ground: [The XXs total the things] ends up being
equivalent to [There is no y that is not among the XXs]. So even if Armstrong succeeds in reducing
the nonexistence of ghosts—indeed, reducing the nonexistences of all kinds of contingent beings—
to one big negative existential, this only gets us less fundamental nonexistence, which means we still
Totality facts ‘involve negation—they could be called “no more” states of affairs’ (Armstrong
2010: 75). Note that I have ignored Armstrong’s distinction between ‘limits’ and ‘absences’. He uses
‘limit’ to refer to universal generalizations, ‘at most’ claims, and ‘no more’ claims (2010: 74-81). He
reserves ‘absence’ for ‘there are no’ claims, i.e. negative existentials like ‘There are no unicorns’
(2010: 82–87). In my view, universal generalizations are sharply distinct from the others, since they
aren’t negative existentials; they are grounded contingently in their instances, not zero-grounded. ‘At
most’ facts, meanwhile, are paradigm negative existentials, with ‘There are no’ facts as a limiting
case: [There are no Fs] = [There are at most zero Fs].
18
Another option is that the totality fact is a universal generalization: [Every object x is among
the XXs], where the XXs are all of the actual objects. As Fine (2012: §7) and Skiles (2015: §4.2)
argue, this can’t work given Necessitation, since universal generalizations would themselves need to
be grounded in their instances plus the totality fact. (The instances alone don’t necessitate.)
17
11
have one big case where we disrespect the ‘no extra work’ point and recombination.
A final possibility is that the ‘big fact’ isn’t the sum of ordinary positive facts, nor a normal
negative, but instead sui generis: it is fundamental, positive, and yet powerful enough to exclude
further positive facts. This proposal is ad hoc; it violates recombination; and it makes the totality fact
count as ‘extra work’ when it ought to come for free. Still, I think this is the best option for anyone
seeking grounds for nonexistence. We will revisit this view in §5.19
I conclude that there are real problems for the proposed grounds for nonexistence. We are
therefore in a paradoxical pickle. Nonexistence has to be grounded, and yet nothing is fit to ground
it. Now it is finally time to see if these claims could be reconciled.
3. Ex Nihilo, Nihil Fit
If nonexistence is ungrounded, then it takes more ontological work than it ought to, and invites
illicit modal recombinations. But if we ground nonexistence in some facts, then we risk mistaking a
failure of prevention for a success in creation, and we can’t hold on to the idea that grounding is a
necessary relation (unless we go Necessitist, or find some way out of the Big Dilemma).
The only option left, it would seem, is that nonexistence is grounded in nothing. Can we
make sense of this idea?
There is something intuitive about it. ‘Negative truths, many think, are not true because of
19
What about Schaffer and Cameron? Do their proposed grounds count as negative and yet
necessitating? One formidable objection, due to Griffith (2012), is that these authors propose
grounding negatives in properties that are border-sensitive, and intuitively, the instantiation of such
properties is partly grounded in negative facts about what is going on outside of an object. Schaffer’s
(2010: §IV) view is that [There are no ghosts] is true in virtue of the world’s being the unique
fundament, which for him depends on the world’s being all there is, which is intuitively dependent
on there not being more to it. Cameron’s (2008) view is that [There are no ghosts] depends on the
existence of the world, which is essentially the biggest thing there is, but intuitively being the biggest
depends on there not being further, larger things.
12
what there is but because of what there isn’t’ (Cameron 2018: 345). But Cameron warns against
interpreting this claim in an ontological way, as grounding the negative in the existence of lacks or
absences. To explain ‘There are no Fs’ in terms of ‘a lack of Fs’ is ‘simply disingenuous when one
doesn’t believe in absences, or things that don’t exist…. Better…to just come clean and say…that
these claims are simply not grounded by anything!’ (2018: 351). I agree.20 ‘Grounded in nothing’
can’t just mean a negative ground. We need grounding without any grounds.
The key, I think, is zero-grounding. Recall that, for Fine, ‘being grounded in nothing’ is
ambiguous between being ungrounded and being zero-grounded. An ungrounded fact obtains
without being grounded at all; it’s fundamental. A zero-grounded fact is indeed grounded, but in
zero-many facts. How does that work? What on earth is zero-grounding?
Fine’s key analogy is with sets. The empty set is generated by the same process as impure
sets, but while the impure sets come from certain urelements, the empty set comes ex nihilo.
Any non-empty set {a, b, ...} is generated (via the ‘set-builder’) from its members a, b, ....
The empty set {} is also generated from its members, though in this case there is a zero
number of members from which it is generated. An urelement such as Socrates, on the other
hand, is ungenerated; there is no number of objects - not even a zero number - from which
it may be generated. Thus ‘generated from nothing’ is ambiguous between being generated
from a zero number of objects and there being nothing - not even a zero plurality of objects
- from which it is generated; and the empty set will be generated from nothing in the one
sense and an urelement from nothing in the other sense.
By analogy, a zero-grounded fact is grounded in zero-many facts, and a fundamental positive fact is
not grounded at all.21 If this makes sense, it’s exactly what we wanted: nonexistence facts are no
extra ontological work, but they’re not grounded in anything.
20
Cameron raises his objection against Melia, whose view we saw in §2, above. For a similar
objection, see Bennett (2011b: 188ff) and Griffith (2015: fn. 8), who object to Merricks’ (2007: xii)
proposal that negative existentials ‘depend on the world’ in a ‘trivial’ way, on the ground that
Merricks doesn’t explain the difference between substantive and trivial dependence.
21
Fine (2012: 47–8) also leans on the metaphor of a ‘machine’ that manufactures sets; for more
on the idea of sets as generated by a process, see Boolos 1971.
13
Still, the set analogy might not be enough. Can we say more about what zero-grounding is
supposed to be? We might try other analogies. Here are two from Jonathan Schaffer.22 First: initial
causal conditions (uncaused) vs. ex nihilo causal outcomes (caused, but not by anything). The
distinction is between events that come out of nowhere (a butterfly pops ex nihilo from the aether)
vs. events that aren’t effects at all, and simply lie at the start of a causal chain. The uncaused starting
conditions are like the ungrounded fundamental level, and the ex nihilo outcomes are like the zerogrounded facts. Second: premises in a deductive argument (underived) vs. tautologies (derived, but
not from anything). Premises ‘follow from nothing’ in the sense that they don’t follow at all, but are
simply written at the start. Tautologies follow in the sense that they are derived from the set of zeromany premises.23
So let’s suppose that zero-grounding makes sense, and that [There are no ghosts] really is
zero-grounded. We aren’t done yet. For we face a tricky question. If nothingness suffices in our
world to generate [There are no ghosts], why doesn’t it always suffice? Think about the empty set:
because it’s generated from nothing, there’s no way to stop it from existing; it exists at all possible
worlds. Why shouldn’t the same be true for [There are no ghosts]? Why isn’t it necessarily true? The
answer can’t be that the grounds of [There are no ghosts] are present in one world but removed in
the other. There were never any grounds to be taken away.
The key here, I think, is that grounds aren’t the only facts that might be difference-makers. If
grounding is contingent, then besides grounds, there might also be the presence and absence of
In ‘Beyond Fundamentality’, presented at Metaphysical Mayhem in 2017.
In fact, this second analogy may be more than illustrative. If grounding involves a metaphysical
kind of explanation, and explanations are arguments, we can distinguish grounds from zero-grounds
in terms of zero- vs. many-premised metaphysical arguments. Jon Litland develops this idea en route to a
rigorous account of zero-grounding: ‘The seemingly mysterious distinction between being ungrounded
and being zero-grounded is a special case of the familiar distinction between not being derivable and
being derivable from the empty collection of premisses’ (Litland 2017: 280, emphasis original).
22
23
14
disabling conditions—reasons why a certain would-be ground turned out not to be a ground in a certain
case (Dancy 2004). For example, we might say [All ravens are black] is, when true, grounded
contingently in facts like [Rae is black], where Rae is a raven (Skiles 2015). But there could be
disablers of the form [Roy is white], where Roy is also a raven. Another example: [I promised to
help] might fail to ground [I ought to help] if disabled by [My promise was made under duress]
(Dancy 2004: Chapter 3).
Back to nonexistence: here is how disabling might help us. In our world, the generation of
[There are no ghosts] from nothing goes through, but in other worlds, it’s disabled by facts of the
form [x is a ghost]. For example, if Casper is a ghost, then [Casper is a ghost] disables the zerogrounding of [There are no ghosts]. In our world, however, no one is a ghost, and so there are many
lacks of disablers—such as [Ginger is a human]—which I earlier described as failures of prevention.24
So here is my solution. On pain of paradox, contingent nonexistence has to be grounded,
but in nothing. Zero-grounding lets us ground facts in nothing, but seems unsuited for grounding
contingent facts, since there would have to be an explanation for why the zero-grounding works in
some cases but not in others, and clearly such an explanation can’t come from variation in the
ground. But we can explain this variation if we accept contingent grounding, giving up
Necessitation. We can say that zero-grounding works by default but fails around disablers. The
disablers of contingent negative existentials (like [There are no ghosts]) are counterinstances (like
[Casper is a ghost]).
The core idea is that contingent negative existentials are contingently zero-grounded: they’re
24
Why all this talk about lacks of disablers? What about enablers, i.e. reasons why some would-be
ground was sufficient for the grounded fact? (Skow 2016: 109.) I am hesitant to say ‘enabling’
because I don’t think there will always be enabling conditions for the zero-ground, in the sense of
background conditions that, together with the ground, necessitate the grounded fact’s obtaining.
What fact could suffice for the totality fact besides the totality fact itself, or something that depends
on it, like a big universal generalization?
15
grounded automatically but not inexorably. There are some subtly different ways we might get at this
idea. We could say that negative existentials are grounded by default (Horty 2012, Lance & Little
2008), that they’re grounded ceteris absentibus (Leuenberger 2008), or that they’re true because they
have no falsemakers (Lewis 2001). I will not consider these other possibilities, because I think the
core idea can be put just fine in terms of contingent zero-grounding.25
4. Generality and Internality
We have a new solution to our paradox of grounding nonexistence. What follows?
First, the contingent zero-ground account points us toward a fresh and general take on the
numinous split between positive and negative. By default, positive facts don’t obtain. They can only
make it into reality with some ontological elbow grease: [There are ghosts] requires an instance of
the form [x is a ghost], and [Rose is red] requires Rose to have the property of redness. But negative
facts obtain by default, and it takes metaphysical muscle to strip them out of reality: [There are no
ghosts] obtains unless there is a disabler of the form [x is a ghost], and [Rose is not red] obtains
unless blocked by Rose’s sanguine hues. For negative facts, obtaining is the default, and failure to
obtain is the exception. For positive facts, the opposite is true. (Maybe this is behind our amazement
that there is something rather than nothing.) This might not be the whole story for the
positive/negative distinction.26 But it is a nice clue.
Second, our account of nonexistence also meshes with another instance of contingent
grounding. Skiles (2015) argues that accidental universal generalizations, like [All humans are under
150 years of age], are fully and contingently grounded in their instances. This view seems already
For Lewis (2001: 610), the basis for ‘There are no ghosts’ involves ghosts only at other
possible worlds. My objection should be clear by now: I say the basis involves nothing, period.
26
It might be that some zero-grounded facts are positive, e.g. the fact that I is numerically
identical to myself (Schumener 2017: §3.3). If so, zero-groundedness doesn’t guarantee negativity.
25
16
committed to contingent zero-ground. Consider how it would treat a universal generalization that is
vacuously true, but only contingently so, like ‘All flying pigs are pink’. This truth corresponds to the
following fact: [∀x ∈ {y: y is a flying pig}, x is pink], which will be contingently grounded its
instances—which are zero in number! The fan of contingent ground, I suggest, should think of all
generalizations as grounded (fully and exclusively) in their instances; the only thing that makes
negative existentials special is that, like vacuously true universal generalizations, they don’t have any
instances. Thus we have a unified way to ground general facts.
(Or rather: we have a promising idea. We won’t have a general account until we also have a
view of which facts count as negative. No doubt a full view is out of reach for now, but why don’t
we look at some key cases? Suppose [p] is positive and consider [¬¬p]. Is that a negative fact? Surely
yes, if our test is ‘Does it have a negation?’ But perhaps no, if our test is ‘Does it obtain by default?’
Here, I think the thing to say is that negation flips polarity. [φ] is a positive fact iff [¬φ] is negative. So
[¬¬p] is positive; its negations cancel out. What about a contingent fact [p & ¬q], where [¬q] is
negative and [p] positive? This seems to me only partly negative. Next, consider general facts like [All
cats meow], [Most dogs woof], and [Exactly one koala plays kazoo]. Are they positive or negative?
These strike me as mixed polarity, too (assuming that the predicates involved are positive).27 There
are also interesting problems raised by nested and negated determiners. Facts with these aren’t
always tricky: [Some cats love some dogs] is positive, and [No cat loves any dogs] is negative. But
what about, say, [¬∃x∀y y = x]? (Nothing is identical to everything—i.e. it’s not the case that there is
exactly one thing?) What about [Something loves most things]? We don’t have any algorithm to say
27
But what grounds these facts? Briefly: (1) [There is exactly one F] is fully grounded in [There is
at least one F], [There is at most one F]—the latter of which is negative and zero-grounded; (2) [At
least half of Fs are G] is fully grounded in each set of instances, [a is F], [b is F], etc., where a, b, etc.
are at least half of the Fs; this grounding is enabled by [a, b, … are at least half of the Fs].
17
when a complex fact is positive or negative, and we don’t have any useful ground-theoretic
categories within the catchall of ‘mixed polarity facts’. There remains a lot of work to be done.)28
Third, the contingent zero-ground account of nonexistence suggests an analogous view in
the theory of truthmaking: perhaps <There are no ghosts> is contingently made true by zero-many
things.29 If so, we have an exception to truthmaker maximalism, the idea that all truths have a
truthmaker. Some argue that it would be ad hoc to make exceptions for maximalism when it comes
to negative existentials (Armstrong 2004: 70, Cameron 2008: 411, Dodd 2007: 394, Merricks 2007:
40-3, Saenz 2014: 83-4). While these arguments have weight, I believe that they work best against the
view that <There are no ghosts> isn’t made true at all. My conjecture is that this proposition is made
true, but not by anything.30
Finally, and perhaps most interestingly, contingent zero-grounding falsifies another popular
principle, beyond Necessitation:
Internality
If a set of facts S grounds B, then it is necessary that if all the facts in S are the case and B is
the case, then S grounds B.31
If ‘positive’ and ‘negative’ are too coarse for the distinctions we need, what properties should
we call on? One hunch is that we might consider the monotonicity of the determiners involved in
general facts (see Barwise and Cooper 1981: 184–7). Upward monotonicity is a clue that a fact is
positive (as in ‘Some Fs are G’); downward monotonicity suggests negativity (as in ‘no Fs are G’’);
and no monotonicity suggests a mixture (as in ‘Exactly two Fs are G’).
29
I assume, following Rodriguez-Pereyra (2006: 186), that truthmakers may be entities of any
ontological type—object, property, state of affairs, fact, etc.—and that the entities made true are
propositions. (Also, ‘<P>’ refers to the proposition that P.)
30
Let me give a quick objection to Griffith’s (2015) ingenious account, on which the
truthmakers for a negative existential are (roughly) the actual things that could have made it false.
Griffith’s view leaves some negative truths without truthmakers. Consider <There exists nothing
made from ectoplasm>. Nothing actual could have made this false, because no actual things could
have been made from ectoplasm (since the material objects have their non-ectoplasmic origins
essentially, and the nonmaterial objects are essentially nonmaterial). Another counterexample is
<There is no stuff causally isolated from A>, where A is all of the actual stuff.
31
Internality is endorsed in Bennett 2011a, Rosen 2010, Audi 2012, and Bernstein 2016.
Leuenberger (2014), Litland (2015), and Baron-Schmitt (ms.) give counterexamples very unlike the
example I am about to give, which I owe to Jon Litland.
28
18
The idea here is that, given the presence of the grounded fact, grounds always necessitate that they are
the grounds. Internality is consistent with the examples we’ve seen, but consider B = [(There are no
ghosts) ∨ (there are flying pigs)]. This fact is actually contingently zero-grounded. But in another
world v, where there are ghosts and flying pigs, B is grounded in [There are flying pigs]. So, B and the
zero-ground are not enough to necessitate that B is zero-grounded. They are present at v, but there,
the ground is positive and porcine.
5. Incompleteness
If nonexistence is contingently zero-grounded, as I have argued, then grounding cannot be an
internal relation. I conclude with another, even more radical consequence.
Our account of nonexistence entails the incompleteness of the fundamental: the
fundamental facts don’t necessitate the rest.32 No set of facts can be complete without fixing the
limits of what there is—it’s not enough to say what is there and what it’s like, unless we can ensure
that there is nothing else. But ‘There is nothing else’ is a contingent, zero-grounded negative
existential—it’s not fundamental, and isn’t necessitated by anything that is. That makes the
fundamental level incomplete. Not all facts flow from it, because it doesn’t include its own limits.
Possible objection: this is a disaster. Completeness is as plausible as it gets when it comes to
principles of grounding. Reject it, and your view doesn’t just sound false, if not inscrutable. Any
respectable conception of fundamentality needs its basic level to be complete.
My response: completeness is good and true in one sense, false and undesirable in another.
The completeness principle—that the totality of facts is necessitated by the fundamental facts—is
really ambiguous between these:
This isn’t the only way to use ‘completeness’, but it is a perfectly familiar use; see Sider 2011:
Chapter 7.
32
19
Completeness (de re)
The set of fundamental facts S is such that all the actual facts are necessitated by S.
Completeness (de dicto)
All actual facts are necessitated by the set of fundamental facts—i.e. by what’s fundamental.
The difference is crucial. The fundamental facts are complete de dicto if there can’t be a change in
total facts without a change in what the fundamental facts are. Completeness de re says instead that, if S is
the set of fundamental facts, there can’t be a change in total facts from the actual world without a
change in S—those particular facts.
In my view, the fundamental facts are not complete de re. There is a possible world w+ where
all the actual fundamental facts are present (and fundamental) along with new fundamental facts—
extra quarks, bonus events, alien properties, etc. (A way to think about this: w+ has a duplicate of
the actual world as a proper part.) That much is entailed by two plausible ideas: that all fundamental
facts are positive, and that no set of positive facts can rule out there being further positive things.
But notice that w+ is not a problem for completeness de dicto. The actual world and w+ are the same
when it comes to the actual fundamental facts (all present at both), but there is a change in which facts
are fundamental (w+ has extras).
So I suggest that the fundamental level is incomplete only de re, and that this shouldn’t
trouble us. It would be a disaster if we had to say that the basic facts are incomplete de dicto—but we
don’t, so we are safe.
Still, isn’t there something deeply right about de re completeness? Don’t we think that some
elite set of the facts has got to fix the others? Sure. But it’s not the ungrounded facts alone: it’s them
plus the zero-grounded facts. Even we can embrace the truer, weaker de re principle:
Weak Completeness (de re)
The set of fundamental or zero-grounded facts S+ is such that all the actual facts are
necessitated by S+.
In other words: if S+ is the union of the set of fundamental facts and the set of zero-grounded facts,
20
then there can be no world can differ from the actual world unless it differs in respect of some fact
in S+. Sounds about right to me. Any world with the same limits and contents as ours has to be
numerically the same.33
By now, I hope, incompleteness won’t seem so unthinkable. If we think some negative
existentials are contingently zero-grounded, we do have to give up (strong) completeness de re, but
we can accept its de dicto cousin and weakened counterpart. How much more completeness do we
really need? ‘Yet more’, I can imagine some philosophers saying. ‘Disambiguate as much as you
want: I know exactly which principle I can’t live without, and it’s completeness de re. I believe it
come what may—and I accept no substitutes.’
I don’t have any objection to this position, except what I have said already: we need
incompleteness de re to get contingent zero-ground, and we need contingent zero-ground to solve
our paradox. But a friend of completeness could struggle through the paradox some other way.
Perhaps the best option: take the totality fact to be sui generis and fundamental, then deny that it can
be freely modally recombined with the (other) positive facts. The deep choice, then, is between
recombination and completeness. And this reflects an even deeper choice between two pictures of
the fundamental. Are the fundamental facts the ones that fully and elegantly account for the rest? (In
Lewis’s (1986) phrase, do they account for everything ‘completely and without redundancy’? See also
Wilson 2012: 1.) If so, then completeness de re is a must. But there is another picture that privileges
recombination—fundamentality as independence. The idea here is that no fundamental fact depends on
anything else; that is why we are free to remove one, without replacement, and make ourselves a
new possible world. Depending on which picture we prefer, we will take negative existentials as
either zero-grounded or grounded in totality.
33
Why reject weak completeness de re? Perhaps to keep robust emergence (Wilson 2014: 544).
21
So my argument is itself, in a way, incomplete. By zero-grounding negative existentials, I’ve
tried to reconcile three ideas: (1) that the fundamental facts can recombine; (2) that the fundamental
positive facts can’t recombine with negative existentials; and (3) that negative existentials have no
grounds. The resulting view rules out completeness (in its strong de re form). But while, as I’ve
argued, this conclusion may be less radical than it sounds, still you might reject it, simply by insisting
that completeness is a fixed point, and recombination isn’t. Stalemate.34
All that being said, I hope to have made progress by showing how completeness could well be
false: perhaps the way the world is depends not just on its fundamental filling, but also on its zerogrounded boundaries. No story is complete without ‘The End’—but is ‘The End’ itself really part of
the story?35
Though I still have the ‘no extra work’ intuition on my side—and the problem of free mass
against me (see fn. 6, above).
35
This paper began as I was leaving UT Austin for MIT, and I have been receiving helpful
comments ever since. My warmest thanks to David Balcarras, Bernhard Salow, Jack Spencer, Steve
Yablo, Brad Skow, Jon Litland, Agustín Rayo, Alex Skiles, Josh Dever, David Sosa, Galen Strawson,
Ross Cameron, Karen Bennett, Daniel Stoljar, Ted Sider, Amie Thomasson, Damian Melamedoff,
Kat Hintikka, Jonah Nagashima, Ginger Schultheis, Quinn White, Eddy Chen, Jonathan Dancy, an
extraordinarily helpful referee at Inquiry (whose comments improved the introduction, framing, and
arguments), and audiences at the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference and MIT’s
MATTI reading group. Sincere apologies to anyone I have left out. This project began with
indispensable help from the Rapoport-King Thesis Scholarship; I owe special thanks to Robert D.
King and Audre and Bernard Rapoport. Finally, I would like to thank Nathaniel Baron-Schmitt for
his invaluable insights and encouragement over the years; without him, this paper would likely have
been boring—or worse: nonexistent.
34
22
REFERENCES
Altmann, S.A., 1967. Structure of social communication. In S.A. Altmann (ed.), Social Communication
Among Primates, 325–362. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Armstrong, D. M., 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———2004. Truth and Truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———2006. Reply to Cheyne and Pigden. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (2): 267–268.
———2010. Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Asay, J., and Baron, S., 2013. Unstable truthmaking. Thought 1: 230–238.
Audi, P., 2012a. A clarification and defense of the notion of grounding. In Correia and Schneider
2012: 101–121.
Audi, P., 2012b. Grounding: toward a theory of the in-virtue-of relation. Journal of Philosophy 109:
685–711.
Bader, R., 2016. Conditions, modifiers, and holism. In Lord and Maguire 2016: 27–55.
Baldwin, T., 1996. There might be nothing. Analysis 56: 231-238.
Barceló Aspeitia, A.A., 2015. Making quantified truths true. In Torza A. (ed), Quantifiers, Quantifiers,
and Quantifiers: Themes in Logic, Metaphysics, and Language. Synthese Library (Studies in
Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science), vol 373. Springer, Cham.
Baron-Schmitt, N., ms. Contingent grounding.
Barwise, J. and Cooper, R., 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and
Philosophy 4: 159–219.
Beall, J.C., 2000. Truthmakers for negative truths. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (2): 264–268.
Bennett, K., 2011a. By our bootstraps. Philosophical Perspectives 25 (1): 27-41.
———2011b. Truthmaking and case-making. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83 (1):187-195.
———2017. Making Things Up. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
23
Bernstein, S., 2016. Grounding is not causation, Philosophical Perspectives 30: 21-38.
Bliss, R. and Trogdon, K., 2014. Metaphysical grounding. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
(Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/grounding/>.
Boolos, G., 1971. The iterative conception of set. Journal of Philosophy 68 (8): 215-231.
Braun, D. 1993. Empty names. Noûs 27 (4): 449–469.
Briggs, R., 2012. Truthmaking without necessitation. Synthese 189 (1):11–28.
Cameron, R. P., 2008. How to be a truthmaker maximalist. Noûs 42 (3): 410–21.
———2018. Truthmakers. In Michael Glanzberg (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Truth. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Chalmers, D., 2012. Constructing the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cheyne, C. and Pigden, C., 2006. Negative truths from positive facts. Australasian Journal of Philosophy,
84: 249–265.
Chudnoff, E., ms. Grounding and entailment. Unpublished.
Coggins, G., 2010. Could There Have Been Nothing? Against Metaphysical Nihilism. London: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Correia, F., 2005. Existential Dependence and Cognate Notions. Munich: Philosophia.
Correia, F. and Schnieder, B. (eds.), 2012. Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dancy, J., 1981. On moral properties. Mind 90 (359): 367-385.
———2004. Ethics Without Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dasgupta, S., 2014. The possibility of physicalism. Journal of Philosophy 111 (9/10): 557–592.
deRosset, L., 2010. Getting priority straight. Philosophical Studies 149: 73–97.
Donaldson, T., 2017. The (metaphysical) foundations of arithmetic. Noûs 51 (4): 775–801.
24
Fine, K., 2012. Guide to ground. In Correia and Schneider 2012: 37–80.
Gillon, B. S., 1999. Negative facts in classical Indian philosophy. The Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Eds., Craig, E. and Craig, E. London: Routledge.
Goodman, J., 2016. An argument for necessitism. Philosophical Perspectives 30 (1): 160–182.
Griffith, A.M., 2012. On some alleged truthmakers for negatives. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (4):
301–308.
———2015. How negative truths are made true. Synthese 192 (1): 317–335.
Horn, L., 2001. A Natural History of Negation. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Horty, J., 2012. Reasons as Defaults. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lance, M. & Little, M., 2007. Where the laws are. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 2: 149–171.
Leuenberger, S., 2008. Ceteris absentibus physicalism. In D. W. Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in
Metaphysics. Oxford University Press 4–145.
———2014. Grounding and necessity. Inquiry 57 (2): 151–174.
Lewis, D., 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Wiley-Blackwell.
———2001. Truthmaking and difference-making. Noûs 35 (4): 602–615.
Linsky, B. and Zalta, E., 1994. In defense of the simplest quantified modal logic. Philosophical
Perspectives 8: 431–458.
———1996. In defense of the contingently nonconcrete. Philosophical Studies 84 (2–3): 283–294.
Litland, Jon 2015. Grounding, explanation, and the limit of internality. Philosophical Review, 124(4):
481-533.
———2017. Grounding ground. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 10, eds. Karen Bennett and
Dean Zimmerman: 279–316.
Lord, E. and Maguire, B. (eds.), 2016. Weighing Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Loss, R., 2017. Grounding, contingency, and transitivity. Ratio 30 (1): 1–14.
25
MacBride, F., 2016. Truthmakers. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition),
Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/truthmakers/>.
Macdonald, C., 1998. Tropes and other things. In S. Laurence and C. Macdonald (eds.), Contemporary
Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics, 329–350. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Molnar, G., 2000. Truth-makers for negative truths. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78: 72–85.
Oesterle, J., ed. and trans. 1962. Aristotle: On Interpretation. Commentary by Saint Thomas and Cajetan.
Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.
Parsons, J., 2006. Negative truths from positive facts? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (4): 591–
602.
Randle, H.N., 1930. Indian Logic in the Early Schools. London: Oxford University Press.
Raju, P.T., 1941. The reality of negation. Philosophical Review 50 (6): 585–601.
Rodriguez-Pereyra, G., 2006. Truthmakers. Philosophy Compass 1 (2): 186–200.
Rosen, G., 2010. Metaphysical dependence: grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffmann
(eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, 109–36. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Russell, B., 1918. The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. Reprinted in 1998. Peru: Open Court Publishing.
Originally printed 1918–1919 in The Monist 28: 495–527; 29: 190–222, 345–380.
———1956. Logic and Knowledge, R. C. Marsh (ed.). London: George Allen & Unwin.
Saenz, N. B., 2014. The world and truth about what is not. Philosophical Quarterly 64 (254):82–98.
Sartorio, C., 2004. How to be responsible for something without causing it. Philosophical Perspectives
18: 315–336.
Schaffer, J., 2003. The problem of free mass: must properties cluster? Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 66 (1): 125–138.
———2004. Two conceptions of sparse properties. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85: 92–102.
26
———2009. On what grounds what. In David Manley, David J. Chalmers & Ryan Wasserman
(eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, 347–383. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
———2010. The least discerning and most promiscuous truth-maker. Philosophical Quarterly, 60:
307–24.
Schumener, E., 2017. The metaphysics of identity: is identity fundamental? Philosophy Compass.
Sider, T., 2011. Writing the Book of the World. Oxford University Press.
Skiles, A., 2015. Against grounding necessitarianism. Erkenntnis 80 (4):717–751.
Skow, B., 2016. Reasons Why. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Williamson, T., 2013. Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wilson, J., 2012. Fundamental determinables. Philosophers’ Imprint 12 (4).
———2014. No work for a theory of grounding. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57:
5–6, 535–579.
Witmer, G., Butchard, W., and Trogdon, K., 2005. Intrinsicality without natural-ness. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 70: 326–350.
Yablo, S., 2004. Advertisement for a sketch of an outline of a proto-theory of causation. In Ned
Hall, L. A. Paul & John Collins (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press 119--137.
———ms. What ‘X does not exist’ says about we who do exist. Unpublished. URL =
<https://www.academia.edu/38017185/WHAT_X_DOES_NOT_EXIST_SAYS_ABOUT
_WE_WHO_DO_EXIST>.
27