CONTRIBUTORS
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Bill Brewer is Susan Stebbing Professor of Philosophy at King’s College London.
John Campbell is Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy at the
University of California, Berkeley.
Sam Coleman is Reader in Philosophy at the University of Hertfordshire.
Katalin Farkas is Professor of Philosophy at the Central European University.
Richard Fumerton is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Iowa.
Alex Grzankowski is Lecturer in Philosophy at Birkbeck College, University of
London.
Jonathan Knowles is Professor of Philosophy at the Norwegian University of
Science & Technology (N.T.N.U).
Joseph Levine is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts,
Amherst.
M. G. F. Martin is Wilde Professor of Mental Philosophy at the University of
Oxford and Mills Adjunct Professor of Philosophy at the University of California,
Berkeley.
Anders Nes is Associate Profosser of Philosophy at the Inland Norway University of
Applied Sciences
Jessica Pepp is Researcher in Philosophy at Uppsala University.
Thomas Raleigh is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the United Arab Emirates
University.
David Woodruff Smith is Professor of Philosophy at the University of California,
Irvine.
Tom Stoneham is Professor of Philosophy at the University of York
Michael Tye is the Dallas TACA Centennial Professor in Liberal Arts at the
University of Texas at Austin.
1
[[This is an uncorrected draft. Please do not please do not quote or cite this version!]
Introduction: The Recent Renaissance Of Acquaintance
Thomas Raleigh, United Arab Emirates University
1. Introduction
That there is a distinctively philosophical usage of the term ‘acquaintance’ is, of
course, due primarily to the influence of Bertrand Russell and in particular to the distinction
he famously drew between ‘knowledge by acquaintance’ and ‘knowledge by description’.
These phrases soon became part of the philosophical lexicon. For example, the Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society twice featured symposia on the question ‘Is there knowledge by
acquaintance?’, first in 19191 and then again in 19492. But then for much of the latter half of
the 20th Century, as Russell’s influence waned, the notion of acquaintance came to be viewed
with grave suspicion by many Anglophone philosophers. This was due in no small part to two
hugely influential criticisms of a broadly Russellian picture3: Wittgenstein’s (1953) ‘private
language argument’ and Sellars’ (1956) attack on the ‘Myth of the Given’. However, over the
last decade or two, the notion of ‘acquaintance’ has swung markedly back into fashion in
philosophy. The concept has, it seems, become respectable again. This volume gathers
together 13 new essays, illustrating the wide range of topics in philosophy of mind,
epistemology, philosophy of language and metaphysics, for which the concept of
acquaintance is nowadays being utilised4.
As ever in philosophy, this term of philosophical art has been used with a variety of
different meanings, for various different philosophical projects and purposes, by many
different philosophers. But as a first-pass characterisation of acquaintance that I hope most
parties could live with: acquaintance is a conscious mental relation that a subject can,
supposedly, bear to particular items or features that is, somehow, fundamentally different
from thinking a true thought about the item/feature in question. Rather than deploying
concepts to form a mental state that is (merely) about something, when we are acquainted
with something we are, in some sense, supposed to consciously confront that very thing itself.
I suspect that any attempt to further clarify the contrast with conceptual thought, or the
precise nature of the ‘conscious confrontation’, or to state the admissible categories of
1
Featuring G. E. Moore, C. D. Broad, G. Dawes Hicks and Beatrice Edgell.
Featuring the great legal philosopher H. L. A. Hart along with G. E. Hughes and J. N Findlay.
3
Though neither Wittgenstein nor Sellars explicitly single out Russell as their target, it is clear that
they are both criticizing a broadly Russellian, sense-data picture of experience.
4
See Wishon & Linsky (eds.), 2015 for an excellent recent collection of essays focusing on Russell’s
theory of knowledge by acquaintance at the time of Problems of Philosophy.
2
2
items/features that a subject can stand in the acquaintance relation to, is bound to step into
contested territory. However, I would venture to suggest that acquaintance could
illuminatingly be thought of as a way that the mind can supposedly be ‘directed’ at an object,
which fundamentally contrasts with the notion of ‘intentionality’ that comes down to us from
Brentano. For this latter, ‘quasi-relational’ notion does not require that the intentional object
of a mental state be something that actually exists – e.g. I can think about my Fairy
Godmother or about the present King of France – whereas acquaintance is supposed to be a
genuine relation, so which could only obtain between a subject and something actual5.
The plan for this introductory chapter then will be to briefly consider the Russellian
and pre-Russellian history of the concept, to consider a few questions and issues that the
notion of acquaintance raises, and finally to survey some of the main philosophical topics for
which ‘acquaintance’ has recently been invoked.
2. Historical background
Generations of budding Anglophone philosophers will have gained their first
exposure to the philosophical notion of acquaintance from Russell’s immensely popular book
The Problems of Philosophy (1912). Russell had earlier presented a paper to the Aristotelian
society in 1911, also entitled ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance & Knowledge by Description’,
which contains much of the same material that would make up chapter 5 of what he famously
called his ‘penny dreadful’ book. In fact, this distinction between two forms of knowledge
already appears at the beginning and end of his famous 1905 paper ‘On Denoting’. And a
mention of acquaintance occurs even earlier in his Principles of Mathematics (1903). It is
plausible that Russell’s notion of acquaintance was influenced by his teacher James Ward’s
notion of ‘presentation’, which was in turn arguably drawn from Kant’s notion of an
‘intuition’ (‘Anschauung’)6.
But although it was Russell’s influence which undoubtedly enshrined the distinction
as part of the standard terminology in ‘analytic’ philosophy, he was not the first Englishlanguage philosopher to use the word ‘acquaintance’ in this way. Passmore (1957) informs us
that John Grote, a moral philosopher and opponent of Utilitarianism, who held the
Knightbridge chair in philosophy at Cambridge, distinguishes between ‘knowledge of
5
Even this much is controversial – D W Smith (1989, this volume) develops a notion of acquaintance
in terms of intentionality, complete with modes of presentation. Mark Johnston (2004) holds we can, in
hallucinatory episodes, be acquainted with uninstantiated universals.
6
Ward, who was both a philosopher and a psychologist and advocated a form of panpsychism, held the
Chair of Mental Philosophy and Logic at Cambridge when Russell and Moore were students. See
Hellie, 2009, for the suggestion that Ward was drawing on Kant.
3
acquaintance’ and ‘knowledge–about’ in his 1865 work Exploratorio Philosophica7. And
William James, in his Principles of Psychology, from 1890, likewise uses the term
‘acquaintance’ when drawing a philosophical distinction between different kinds of
knowledge:
‘I know the color blue when I see it, and the flavor of a pear when I taste it; I know an
inch when I move my finger through it; a second of time, when I feel it pass; an effort
of attention when I make it; a difference between two things when I notice it; but about
the inner nature of these facts or what makes them what they are, I can say nothing at
all. I cannot impart acquaintance with them to any one who has not already made it
himself. I cannot describe them, make a blind man guess what blue is like, define to a
child a syllogism, or tell a philosopher in just what respect distance is just what it is, and
differs from other forms of relation. At most, I can say to my friends, Go to certain
places and act in certain ways, and these objects will probably come. (James, 1890, 221)
Of course, in many languages other than English, some such distinction is linguistically
marked by the existence of two different words – e.g. ‘savoir’ and ‘connaitre’ in French,
‘Kennen’ and ‘Wissen’ in German, ‘scire’ and ‘noscere’ in Latin – a linguistic fact that both
Grote and Russell adduced in support of drawing a similar distinction in English. In Germany,
at almost the same time as Grote, Helmholtz wrote in his 1868 paper ‘The Recent Progress of
the Theory of Vision’ about a distinction between ‘das Kennen’ and ‘das Wissen’ – the
former being ‘familiarity with phenomena’, the latter being “the knowledge of [phenomena]
which can be communicated by speech”. Unlike Russell, who held Knowledge by
Acquaintance to be more fundamental than Knowledge by Description, Helmholtz thought
that das Wissen was the more important and fundamental form of knowledge. For though he
allowed that das Kennen has ‘the highest degree of certainty and precision’, he thought, in
line with the passage quoted above from James, that it could not be expressed in words, even
to ourselves, and was thus unfit to be a basis for science. I cannot say whether William James
would have read Grote’s work, but he certainly did read and admire Helmholtz.
Whatever the precise origins of the philosophical practice of using the English word
‘acquaintance’ as we do, it seems immensely plausible that something like the same idea or
concept of an acquaintance relation has cropped up throughout the history of philosophy
under different labels. For example: Sosa (2003) suggests that the notion of
‘direct’/’unmediated’ cognitive contact that we find in chapter 5 of Problems of Philosophy,
7
John Grote is also credited with coining the term ‘relativism’. He is not to be confused with his
brother George Grote, also a philosopher, for whom the Grote chair in philosophy and logic at UCL
was named.
4
bears a close resemblance to the views of Leibniz, who Russell was reading avidly at the
time:
“Our direct awareness of our own existence and of our thoughts provides us with the
primary truths a posteriori, the primary truths of fact… there is no mediation between
the understanding and its objects.” (Leibniz, New Essays on Human Understanding,
1765, Book IV ch.9)
“We shall say that we have acquaintance with anything of which we are directly aware,
without the intermediary of any process of inference or any knowledge of truths.”
(Russell, 1912, 46)
In the same vein, Descartes’ foundationalist project would seem to be naturally
interpreted as being committed to some sort of especially secure and basic relation that one
bears to one’s own conscious states – see Richard Fumerton’s essay this volume. Brewer
(2011) points to Berkeley as an example of a philosopher whose theory of perceptual
experience depends on something like a basic notion of conscious acquaintance with minddependent objects – see also Stoneham (2002). McLear (2016) and Gomes (2017) have both
recently argued that Kant’s theory of perceptual experience is best interpreted in terms of an
acquaintance relation with features in the external environment. Woodruff-Smith (1989 and
this volume) employs the concept of acquaintance in his interpretation of Husserl – see also
Jansen (2014). Gideon Makin (2000) suggests that Russell’s acquaintance is really just the
very same relation that Frege called ‘grasping a sense’, though they disagreed over the objects
of the relation.
No doubt, many other similar precedents of something like the concept of an
acquaintance relation could be found throughout the history of philosophy – but that is, I
hope, enough history for present purposes.
3. Five Russellian Theses about Acquaintance
Russell’s distinction was explicitly epistemological, between two kinds of knowledge,
but Russell’s treatment of the distinction was also intimately bound up with claims both about
reference/language and also about the metaphysics of mind/consciousness. Russell, at least
around the time of Problems of Philosophy, had a number of commitments that may strike
acquaintance theorists nowadays as controversial or just plain wrong:
5
(i) Russell, at the time of ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance & Knowledge by
Description’ (KAKD) and Problems of Philosophy (PP), notoriously held that we are never
acquainted with familiar physical items in our shared environment – though it is important to
bear in mind that Russell insisted that sense-data are nevertheless mind-independent and
ontologically distinct from the subject’s conscious awareness of them.
Concerning the admissible objects of the acquaintance relation, Russell held that we
can only be acquainted with our current sense-data and mental states, plus some past sensedata and past mental states in memory, some universals and possibly also ‘the self’.
“We have acquaintance in sensation with the data of the outer senses, and in
introspection with the data of what may be called the inner sense—thoughts, feelings,
desires, etc.; we have acquaintance in memory with things which have been data either
of the outer senses or of the inner sense. Further, it is probable, though not certain, that
we have acquaintance with Self, as that which is aware of things or has desires towards
things.
In addition to our acquaintance with particular existing things, we also have
acquaintance with what we shall call universals, that is to say, general ideas, such as
whiteness, diversity, brotherhood, and so on…
It will be seen that among the objects with which we are acquainted are not included
physical objects (as opposed to sense-data), nor other people’s minds.” (Russell, 1912,
51)
However, Russell’s views on the possible objects of acquaintance had not always been so
restrictive. As Peter Hylton points out, in their correspondence from around 1900-1902 both
Russell and Moore thought that there was no restriction whatsoever on what we can be
acquainted with (see Hylton, 1990, chapter 4). Similarly in the preface to his 1903 Principles
of Mathematics, Russell holds that we can be acquainted with abstract logical/mathematical
items:
“The discussion of indefinable – which forms the chief part of philosophical logic – is
the endeavour to see clearly, and to make others see clearly, the entities concerned, in
order that the mind may have that kind of acquaintance with them which it has with
redness or the taste of a pineapple.” (Russell, 1903, xv)
Likewise, at the start of Chapter 3, Russell maintains that we can be acquainted with
inferential relations:
6
“…it is plain that where we validly infer one proposition from another, we do so in
virtue of a relation which holds between the two propositions whether we perceive it or
not: the mind, in fact, is as purely receptive in inference as common sense supposes it to
be in perception of sensible objects.” (Russell, 1903, p33)
(ii) Knowledge by Acquaintance is the more fundamental form of knowledge – all
Knowledge by Description ultimately depends on Knowledge by Acquaintance. At the start
of chapter 5 of problems of philosophy we are told:
“All our knowledge, both knowledge of things and knowledge of truths, rests upon
acquaintance as its foundation.” (Russell, 1912, 48)
It seems clear that one might be attracted to the notion of acquaintance and want to assign it
some kind of important epistemic role without going so far as to endorse Russell’s claim here
that all knowledge depends on acquaintance.
(iii) We can only understand propositions wholly made up of constituents we are
acquainted with. This principle seems to be first stated in print at the end of ‘On Denoting’:
“…in every proposition which we can apprehend (i.e. not only in those whose truth or
falsehood we can judge of, but in all that we can think about), all the constituents are
really entities with which we have immediate acquaintance.” (Russell, 1905, 492)
Russell re-asserted this principle in many later works, including both KAKD and PP:
“Every proposition which we can understand must be composed wholly of constituents
with which we are acquainted.” (PP, p58)
‘We must attach some meaning to the words we use, if we are to speak significantly and
not utter mere noise; and the meaning we attach to our words must be something with
which we are acquainted.’ (PP58)
‘The chief reason for supposing the principle true is that it seems scarcely possible to
believe that we can make a judgement or entertain a supposition without knowing what
it is that we are judging or supposing about.’ (KAKD 206)
A re-formulated version of this principle was later influentially championed by Gareth Evans,
in his “Varieties of Reference”, under the label ‘Russell’s Principle’
7
“…in order to be thinking about an object or to make a judgement about an object, one
must know which object is in question – one must know which object it is that one is
thinking about. (I call this principle Russell’s Principle…)” (Evans, 1982, 65)
(iv) When we are acquainted with a present sense-datum, we are perfectly/completely
acquainted with it; there is nothing we are missing, no ‘back side’ to a sense-datum.
“The particular shade of colour that I am seeing may have many things said about it -- I
may say that it is brown, that it is rather dark, and so on. But such statements, though
they make me know truths about the colour, do not make me know the colour itself any
better than I did before: so far a concerns knowledge of the colour itself, as opposed to
knowledge of truths about it, I know the colour perfectly and completely when I see it,
and no further knowledge of it itself is even theoretically possible. Thus the sense-data
which make up the appearance of my table are things with which I have acquaintance,
things immediately known to me just as they are.” (Russell, 1912, 47)
A corollary of this thesis is that, for Russell, there is no such thing as different ways or
manners of being acquainted with a present sense-datum, there is just the one simple/brute
acquaintance relation that can be borne contemporaneously to an item, which reveals it
perfectly and entirely as it is in itself. The specific phenomenology of an experience then is
determined entirely by the object side of the relation – the subject side cannot also contribute
to the phenomenology by being acquainted in this or that specific way or manner. However,
as Martin (this volume) points out, Russell did allow for different modes or manners of
acquaintance insofar as he allowed that we can also be acquainted with a past-sense-datum –
and here the object of acquaintance does not determine the phenomenology of the episode of
remembering, rather it is the accompanying imagery which determines the phenomenology.
Later, in his Analysis of Mind (1921), Russell came to reject this fourth thesis8, for by
that date he treats sense-data as identical with the ultimate physical constituents of reality
described by physics and so allowed that sense-data can have further
unperceived/unexperienced qualities and characteristics (and indeed can exist unperceived).
(v) Despite using the phrases ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance’, ‘Knowledge by
Description’, Russell thought that acquaintance is not just a means or source for getting
knowledge of a distinctive kind. He held that being acquainted with something is already in
itself a form of knowledge. To quote again from the passage at the start of chapter 5 of PP:
8
This move towards neutral monism arguably began even earlier, with his 1914 article ‘On the Nature
of Acquaintance’.
8
“…so far as concerns knowledge of the colour itself, as opposed to knowledge of truths
about it, I know the colour perfectly and completely when I see it, and no further
knowledge of it itself is even theoretically possible.” (Russell, 1912, 47).
Likewise in the previous chapter, Russell wrote:
‘Acquaintance with objects essentially consists in a relation between the mind and
something other than the mind; it is this that constitutes the mind’s power of knowing
things.” (Russell, 1912, 42, bold type added)
See Sam Coleman’s essay in this volume for contemporary endorsement of this idea that
acquaintance is itself a kind of Knowledge. However, I think that the way most theorists use
the term ‘acquaintance’ these days is to denote a relation of direct conscious awareness that
allows for a certain kind of knowledge or epistemic relation to an object but which does not in
itself count as a state of knowledge. I.e. it is possible to be acquainted with O and yet fail to
gain knowledge of any kind of O – one might be distracted or inattentive, one might be
deluded or crazy, one could be infected with some reasonable doubt about one’s ability to
form correct judgements.
******
More generally, I think its fair to say that most recent theorists who have appealed to
acquaintance would reject at least one, and quite possibly all five of these Russellian theses.
Certainly, none of these five theses are obviously entailed by the core characterisation of
acquaintance I gave above in section 1 – viz. a relation of conscious awareness that is
fundamentally distinct from thinking a true thought or forming an accurate judgement, in
which the mind has some kind of unmediated confrontation with some portion of reality.
4. Five Questions for Acquaintance Theorists
In this section, I briefly consider five important questions facing acquaintance
theorists.
(i) Firstly a methodological question: should we approach the relation of
acquaintance primarily as an epistemological topic – i.e. as a relation whose essential nature
we define in terms of its being a special source of knowledge or justification? Or should we
approach acquaintance primarily as a notion in the metaphysics of mind – i.e. as a relation
9
whose essential nature we define in psychological or phenomenological terms. In other
words: should we take the alleged existence of a special kind of epistemic relation as the
starting point for our philosophical investigations of acquaintance and only then go on to
consider what kind of mental metaphysics or mechanisms that would be required to allow for
that epistemic relation? Or do we start from the alleged existence of a special kind of
conscious state or relation, posited initially on introspective or phenomenological
grounds, and only latterly come to consider what epistemic or referential consequences might
flow from such a mental state/relation?
Of course, there is no need to treat these two different kinds of approaches to
acquaintance as mutually exclusive – after all, it is normal enough in philosophy that we
approach an issue or concept from various directions at the same time. Nevertheless, I think it
is worthwhile to register that there are these different starting points for thinking about
acquaintance and that different acquaintance theorists may have taken one or other route. For
example: in his influential work on acquaintance, John Campbell seems to be primarily
motivated by epistemological and referential concerns and this has led him to champion a
relational model of experience on which the mind is acquainted with external features. In
contrast, M. G. F. Martin seems to be motivated primarily by phenomenological
considerations to endorse a form of naïve-realism and he has been notably cautious about the
epistemological benefits, if any, that might result from adopting this acquaintance-based
model.
Or to take another example, a number of discussions of acquaintance in the literature
on singular thought/reference take their starting point to be the claim that there is some sort of
special relation one must have to an item in order to think a singular thought about it (or to
understand a singular term which refers to it) – with some theorists arguing for such a
requirement and others against it. The precise nature of the mental states or mechanisms
required for this relation is then a secondary question. It is not uncommon to read
philosophers arguing that there must be some such requirement, but who are happy to leave
its exact nature open at least for the time being. For example, Kent Bach writes:
‘A de re representation of a material object must be a percept or derive from a percept,
either one’s own or someone else’s.’ (Bach, 2010, 55)
But how much of an object has to be perceived? is it ok to have only seen a photo of it? What
about on TV? What if the object is covered under a thin blanket but you can make out its
rough shape and contours? Etc etc. Bach confesses he doesn’t really know – his hunch is to be
reasonably inclusive, but he draws a line at merely hearing a sound produced by the object.
But he’s also prepared to allow that the extent of singular thought is much more limited than
10
his intuitions suggest (see Bach 2010, 57-58). Its clear that Bach’s real interests here do not
lie in the precise nature of the perceptual link that allows for singular thought so much as just
establishing that there is some such constraint.
(ii) Secondly: is the acquaintance relation non-representational? Or is being
acquainted with an object just a distinctive kind – e.g. a non-conceptual or somehow sensory
kind – of representational state?
In general, those who are writing about acquaintance in the context of the traditional
problem of perception have assumed that it is a non-representational relation that stands in
opposition to the representational family of theories9. But when it comes to the literature on
the hard problem of consciousness this opposition between acquaintance and representation
become less clear. On the one hand Levine (2007) and Chalmers (2004, 2007) both hold that
we must acknowledge some kind of acquaintance relation to our own phenomenal
properties/features, but that this cannot be explained by appeal to a special kind of
phenomenal concept – i.e. to a special kind of representational vehicle. On the other hand,
Balog (2012) thinks that a special kind of concept – the phenomenal kind, which uses itself to
refer to itself – explains what acquaintance is. Being acquainted here then is treated as a
special sensory kind of conceptual representation. Paul Churchland (1989), who asserts that
“What Mary is missing is some form of ‘knowledge by acquaintance’” (Churchland, 1989,
71) provides a neuro-scientific story on which ‘acquaintance’ is cashed out as a ‘distributed
representation that is not remotely propositional or discursive’. Likewise, Bigelow &
Pargetter (1990, 2006), in providing a physicalist response to Jackson’s Mary, appeal to
acquaintance, which they understand in terms of a special kind of belief-representation. Earl
Conee, in yet another paper arguing that acquaintance holds the key to answering Jackson’s
Knowledge argument, is explicitly agnostic as to whether acquaintance is representational or
not:
“Perhaps awareness is experiential pure and unmediated; perhaps awareness of an
experienced quality is mediated by some particularly transparent sensory form of
representation. What matters for the present account is that experiencing a quality is the
most direct way to apprehend the quality. That much seems beyond reasonable doubt.”
(Conee, 1994, 145)
9
There are by now various hybrid theories in the literature that combine relational and representational
elements – e.g. Kennedy (2013), Logue (2014), Nanay (2016), Langsam (2011). But these are hybrid
theories precisely insofar as they combine a non-representational relation of acquaintance with the
external world together with the notion of representational content. Thus these hybrid theorists are still
treating acquaintance as a non-representational relation, even if it is somehow combined into a larger
state with a different representational component. See also Bengson et al (2011) for a ‘dual component’
theory of experience that also combines relational and representational elements.
11
For many epistemologists the point of appealing to an acquaintance relation is to
account for non-inferential justification of beliefs, or for a special kind of foundational
epistemic security – which in itself does not obviously require one to take a stand on whether
the relation essentially involves representational content. A number of recent defenders of
traditional foundationalist epistemologies – e.g. Fumerton (1995, this volume), Bonjour
(2003) Fales (1996), all maintain that an episode of acquaintance can involve propositional
content in the following way10. In order to generate justification for a belief, one needs to be
acquainted not only with a fact but also with: (i) a corresponding proposition (about that fact),
and, (ii) the relation of correspondence that obtains between the fact and the proposition.
However, it is important to distinguish the idea that the object of the acquaintance relation is
something representational – such as a thought or propositional content from the idea that the
acquaintance relation itself is a form of representation.
(iii) Thirdly, what sort of things are we (supposedly) acquainted with? What are the
possible objects of acquaintance?
We have already briefly discussed Russell’s views on the possible objects of
acquaintance in section 3, above. It is clear enough that any appeal to (or argument against)
some notion of acquaintance needs to consider some of the following sorts of questions: Are
we supposed to be acquainted with mind-independent features out in the environment? Or are
we only ever acquainted with mental or inner features? Or are we perhaps sometimes
acquainted with the outer, sometimes with the inner? Or are we sometimes acquainted with
both kinds of features in a single experience? E.g. Wishon (2012) argues that in perception
we are simultaneously acquainted with external objects and also with sensory properties of
our on experience. Should we treat the objects of acquaintance for each of the sensemodalities along the same lines, or might it be that, say, vision acquaints us with external
features whilst, say, taste or smell acquaint us with something inner? Are we acquainted with
our own consciousness? Or our own self? E.g. Duncan (2015) argues that we are acquainted
with ourselves. Can we be acquainted with acquaintance itself? (Fales (1996) suggests that we
can be acquainted with given-ness.)
As well as the inner vs outer axis, we can also ask about the metaphysical structure of
whatever it is we are acquainted with: Are we acquainted with something (whether inner or
outer) like a fact or state of affairs? E.g. Fumerton (1995) and Bonjour (2003) both endorse
the idea that we can be acquainted not only with a fact and with a thought but also with the
10
Notice, the idea is that acquaintance can inolve propositional content, not that it always or
essentially does so. E.g. Fumerton explicitly allows that one can be acquainted with a fact in a way that
does not involve propositional content. Many thanks to an anonymous reviewer for Oxford University
Press for helpful discussion on this point.
12
‘fit’ between the fact and the thought. Or are we acquainted just with the particulars
themselves? Or can we also be acquainted with token property instances?
Assuming we are somehow or other acquainted with properties, we are obviously
bound to ask which properties we can be acquainted with in experience – just as
representational theorists are obliged to answer a parallel question as to which properties can
be represented in experience. For example: are we only visually acquainted with 2-d shape
and colour properties, or can we also be acquainted with other properties – e.g. 3-dimensional
shape and depth, perhaps temporal properties, perhaps relations such as identity over time,
causation, meaning properties, perhaps the emotions of other people, etc. And if we think the
objects of acquaintance are always ‘inner’, we then face the question of whether these inner
items can possess the same properties of shape and colour that we standardly ascribe to
environmental items, or whether they instead possess distinct phenomenal properties –
shape*, colour*.
(iv) Fourthly, another important issue to consider is whether it is possible to stand in
multiple different acquaintance relations to the one same object of acquaintance – i.e. can
there be different ways or modes or manners of being acquainted with the very same thing?
We have already seen Russell in PP insist that when one is acquainted with a sensedatum, one is perfectly acquainted with it – there is, as it were, no back side or hidden aspect
to a sense-datum. And it seems that both Moore and Russell around this time held that
whenever there is a phenomenological difference between two experiences this is always to
be accounted for by a difference in the object side of the relation – see for example Moore’s
(1903) famous discussion of the apparent diaphaneity of experience. (However, it should be
bourn in mind that Moore eventually concluded that one can in fact attend to the act of
consciousness itself, as opposed to the object, though it requires a rather special act of
attention. It should also be remembered that whilst Russell held there was only one way to be
acquainted with a present sense-datum, he did allow that one could also be acquainted with it
in a different way, via memory, once the sense-datum was past – see M G F Martin’s essay
in this volume.)
I think this understanding of the acquaintance relation lives on in the literature on
consciousness. For example: Chalmers (1996, 2007), Nida-Rumelin (2007), Goff (2011,
2015) all claim that when one is acquainted with a phenomenal property – such as pain or
red-looking-ness – one is thereby provided with knowledge of the essence of that property (or
at least part of the essence). (Compare Bill Brewer’s essay in this volume, in which he
defends the thesis of ‘revelation’; idea that conscious acquaintance with a property can
provide knowledge of the nature of that property.)
However, in the literature on perception and naïve-realism we find John Campbell
(2002, 2007) arguing that acquaintance is a 3-place relation, whose relata include not just the
13
subject and the object but also a ‘viewpoint’. (see also Kennedy (2007)). Similarly Bill Fish
(2009) allows that the nature and functioning of the subject’s visual system can contribute to
the phenomenology of conscious acquaintance. More generally, if an acquaintance theorist
holds that we can be acquainted with environmental features, they are going to have to deal
with perceptual relativity, the changing appearances of an unchanging environmental object.
And so then it seems one has to allow for different ways or manners of being acquainted with
the same one item (see Raleigh (forthcoming) for further discussion of this point.)
One issue that then arises if one does allow for different manners or modes of
acquaintance is the following: how do these modes of acquaintance differ from the orthodox
representational notion of a mode of presentation or Fregean sense? You might worry here
that once different modes of acquaintance are allowed we begin to lose the contrast between
an acquaintance theory and a representational account of experience that treats the alleged
contents of experience along Fregean lines. For now on both stories the perceptual experience
is directed at an external object or scene, but this external target is presented to the subject via
a distinctive mode or manner of presentation. A first thought here might be that
representational modes of presentation do not require any actual existing object that the
subject is presented with – the object can be merely intentional. Whereas acquaintance is
genuine relation that requires both relata to actually exist for the relation to be instantiated.
However, if you think, as McDowell (1982) and Evans (1982) long ago urged, that there can
be special object-dependent, non-descriptive singular modes of presentation, then this
dimension of contrast may be lost.
Another obvious way to draw a contrast between the two approaches is to insist that
manners/modes of acquaintance are not assessable as true or false, whereas Fregean modes of
presentation are. However, not all representational theorists think of the content of experience
as having truth conditions – e.g. Tim Crane (2009) insists that experiential content can be
accurate/inaccurate but not true/false, since it is not propositional. And likewise, not all naïverealists/acquaintance theorists deny that experiences are assessable as true/false – it is
common to read people with naïve-realist sympathies, e.g. Martin (2002, 2004), continuing to
use the term ‘veridical’ as applied to experience itself.
A different possible dimension of contrast here is that on the orthodox Fregean
account, sense determines reference – that is for any mode of presentation there is a unique
(though possibly non-existent) intentional object. So we never find the same mode of
presentation presenting different referents on different occasions (though perhaps the same
mode of presentation can sometimes succeed in referring and sometimes fail). Whereas an
acquaintance theorist can, and I think should, allow that a manner/mode of acquaintance –
comprising the various factors both external and internal that contribute to the
phenomenology of the experience, e.g. perspective, lighting, condition of one’s eyes etc – can
14
be held constant over different occasions and yet acquaint the subject with numerically
different items. If I swap one visually indistinguishable item for another and keep the viewing
conditions identical, the mode or manner of acquaintance remains the same though the object
of acquaintance has changed. Of course this dimension of contrast would also be lost if the
representational theorist is prepared to abandon the orthodox Fregean doctrine that sense
determines reference.
Mark Johnston (2011), whilst arguing in favour of a relational view of perception,
briefly discusses the contrast with Fregean senses:
‘In an ASE [attentive sensory episode] the target is presented in a certain manner, and
the target may or may not conform to its manner of presentation. Hence these manners
of presentation are not Fregean senses, which determine something as their referent
when and only when the referent satisfies the sense. A target can be presented in an
ASE in an illusory fashion and yet the ASE may thereby allow its subject to makes his
or her first demonstrative reference to the target, and so have the target as a topic of
thought and talk.’ (Johnston, 2011, 173)
‘The best model of the relation between manner of presentation and target in an ASE is
given by ‘the theory of appearing’ where the manner of presentation just is the target
presenting-in-a-certain-manner.’ (ibid. 174)
In contrast, Levine (2001) assimilates acquaintance to a special kind of mode of presentation
– i.e. a phenomenal concept:
‘our conception, or mode of presentation of property like redness is substantive and
determinate in a way that the modes of presentation of other sorts properties are not.
When I think of what it is to be reddish, the reddishness itself is somehow included in
the thought; its present to me. This is what I mean by saying it has a ‘substantive’ mode
of presentation. In fact, it seems the right way to look at it is that reddishness itself is
serving as its own mode of presentation. By saying that the conception is ‘determinate’,
I mean that reddishness presents itself as a specific quality, identifiable in its own right,
not merely by its relation to other qualities.
……the mode of presentation of cathood [in contrast] lacks substance and determinacy.’
(Levine, 2001, 8)
And in a footnote he adds:
15
‘The contrast I’m after between modes of presentation of qualitative properties and
other properties (or objects) is perhaps captured in Russell’s (1959) distinction between
‘knowledge by acquaintance’ and ‘knowledge by description’. We are acquainted with
the contents of experience, but not with anything else.’ (ibid.,179 endnote 8)
(v) Finally, can acquaintance be further analysed and/or naturalized?
It is not uncommon to hear the relation of acquaintance being described as ‘brute’ or
‘simple’ – suggesting that in some sense it resists further illuminating analysis. For example,
here is Evan Fales:
‘the quality of being given is itself given; and moreover, that is itself something simple,
not analysable into constituents, in the way in which the content of what is given on a
particular occasion might be. As sentient beings, we apprehend, directly and
immediately, what it is to be directly and immediately confronted by a perceptual
experience…
If someone did not already have acquaintance with given-ness, it would be quite futile
to instruct him either by employing ostension or by saying such things as that the given
is itself given, just as it would be futile to direct the blind person to color sensations by
saying that they are visually sensed.’ (Fales, 1996, 147-8)
Likewise Richard Fumerton writes that Acquaintance:
“cannot be informatively subsumed under a genus, and…cannot be analyzed into any
less problematic concepts” (Fumerton, 1995, 76)
Of course, acquaintance is not meant to be simple or brute in the sense that fundamental
particles or forces might be said to be simple or brute. I take it that the idea here is that the
state or relation of being consciously acquainted with something cannot be further analysed or
explained as being constituted by other, simpler conscious or personal level mental acts or
states. And so I assume that neither Fumerton nor Fales mean to be suggesting here that the
supposed unanalysability or ineffability of acquaintance shows that the relation could not in
fact supervene on purely physical facts. Likewise, naïve-realist acquaintance theorists, will
presumably not want to deny that an episode of S being acquainted with O in some way
supervenes on or is constituted by some complex extended physical process of interaction, a
causal chain running from O to S, reflected light, sub-personal unconscious events in the
retina and brain, etc.
16
This might naturally lead one to wonder as to whether some kind of naturalising
project could or should be pursued along roughly the same lines as the various attempts to
naturalise representational content. I.e. just as many theorists have attempted to state the
conditions under which some physical or neural mechanism represents something, in terms
that do not take for granted any kind of representational notion – meaning, truth, reference
etc, so one might attempt to state the conditions under which a subject is acquainted with
something in temrs that do not take for granted anything like consciousness – e.g. attention, or
wake-fulness or ‘presence to mind’ etc. In the context of naïve-realist or relational version of
acquaintance, one might look towards Enactive/Embodied/Extended approaches in cognitive
science as natural allies when trying to give a naturalistic account of conscious acquaitnanc
with one’s surroundings. And indeed Alva Noe has described his own Enactivist position as
being ‘as naïve-realist as one could hope to be’ (Noe, 2008, 703).
Notice also that even if we accept that the state or relation of being acquainted cannot
be analysed into personal level constituents, nor that it can currently be given a reductive,
naturlised account, that does not mean that nothing interesting or illuminating can be said
about it. Compare: Williamson (2000) famously argued that Knowledge is not analysable and
should be taken as an epistemological primitive – but that does not mean that nothing
interesting can be said about it, nor that we cannot specify necessary or sufficient conditions
for knowledge. Indeed Williamson himself holds that S knows that p iff S’s evidence includes
the proposition p. And so it might be likewise for acquaintance – even if it is not analysable
or reducible into simpler components, we might still be able to say various interesting or
illuminating things about it.
5. Some Recent Acquaintance-Based Theorising
In this final section, I briefly survey some of the main uses to which the notion of
acquaintance has been put in the recent literature – including the essays in the present volume.
5.1 Acquaintance & Phenomenal Properties
On Russell’s original picture, we are acquainted with sense-data, which were
supposed on the one hand to be distinct from familiar objects such as tables and chairs, but on
the other hand were also supposed to be mind-independent and ontologically distinct from the
subject’s conscious awareness of them. If we abandon this Russellian notion of sense-data,
we might then think of acquaintance as a conscious relation to familiar objects and features in
the external environment, or we might think of acquaintance as a relation that one bears to
states or features of one’s own mind. A number of philosophers writing on the so-called
‘Hard Problem of Consciousness’, and in particular in the recent literature on phenomenal
17
Concepts, have had recourse to this latter ‘internalist’ conception of acquaintance. It is
noteworthy that both physicalists and non-physicalists have made appeals to acquaintance in
this regard.
In the literature initially generated by Frank Jackson’s (1982) celebrated “Mary”
example, there were some theorists – e.g. Bigelow & Pargetter (1990, 2006), Conee (2004) –
who suggested that what Mary gains when she leaves her Black and White environment is
Knowledge-by-Acquaintance of a phenomenal quality that she previously knew about only by
description. This acquaintance-based response to Jackson’s ‘Knowledge Argument’ can thus
be grouped alongside Lewis’ (1988) & Nemirov’s (1980, 1990) claim that Mary gains a new
ability – in both cases the form of the response is to allow that Mary does indeed learn
something but to deny that the knowledge in question is propositional knowledge of a fact.
And so the physicalist thesis that all facts are physical facts can supposedly be saved. More
recently, Michael Tye (2009) also endorsed an acquaintance-based response to the knowledge
argument – though in Tye & Grzankowski’s contribution to the present volume, they argue
that acquaintance is only part of the solution. Tye & Grzankowski hold that when Mary first
experiences red she does indeed gain non-propositional knowledge by acquaintance of a
simple sensible quality, but they point out that this non-propositional state cannot in itself
suffice for Mary’s epistemic progress. According to Tye & Grzankowski, knowledge of what
it is like to experience red (an instance of knowledge-wh) is propositional knowledge. Tye &
Grzankowski go on to argue that although non-propositional acquaintance cannot itself
constitute a propositional answer to the question ‘what is it like to experience red?’,
nevertheless acquaintance is vital to understanding Mary’s epistemic gain. Acquaintance with
the sensible quality in question is that upon which Mary bases her phenomenal knowledge. In
the context of the knowledge argument, a propositional answer to ‘what is like to experience
red?’ must be based in one’s own acquaintance in order to qualify as an appropriate answer.
This position stands in contrast to the phenomenal concept strategy, a strategy that might seek
to situate acquaintance in relation to the possession conditions of certain concepts. Since Tye
& Grzankowski do not believe that there are any phenomenal concepts, they argue that their
“epistemic basing” approach is the preferred way to get Mary’s new acquaintance with a
color into the story.
One obvious worry about the strategy of appealing to acquaintance as a way of
defending physicalism, is that this special relation of acquaintance that we can allegedly bear
to our own conscious states is, prima facie, just as mysterious and difficult to explain for a
physicalist as the ‘qualia’ of phenomenal red-ness with which we started. E.g. Gertler (1999)
argues that it is only property dualists, and not physicalists, who can give a story as to how we
can have this special form of access – acquaintance – with qualia.
18
Bigelow & Pargetter’s acquaintance-based response to Mary allows that she would
come to have a new belief as a result of being acquainted with phenomenal red-ness. By
individuating beliefs in this fine-grained way, Bigelow & Pargetter’s acquaintance-based
theory can be seen as presaging the later literature focusing on the ‘phenomenal concept
strategy’ response to Mary. Phenomenal concepts are meant to be a special way of thinking
about a phenomenal property that one can typically only acquire by having a conscious
experience featuring that very property – i.e. by being acquainted with the very property that
the concept is about. A defender of physicalism can then appeal to this special phenomenal
kind of concept in explanation of how Mary can gain new propositional knowledge of the
same old physical facts that she already knew couched in terms of neuro-scientific concepts.
This strategy relies then on slicing the propositional contents of knowledge-states
more finely than facts. A physicalist must insist that phenomenal properties are physical
properties and that facts about what it is like to experience these phenomenal properties are
just physical facts. The idea then is that Mary, who by hypothesis already knows all the
physical facts, can gain a new phenomenal concept when she actually experiences red for the
first time – and so she can re-conceptualize a physical fact about the brain using this new
phenomenal concept and thus gain new propositional knowledge of the same old fact. Of
course, for this appeal to phenomenal concepts to count as a physicalist strategy, one must be
able to give a purely physical account of what it is to acquire and deploy a phenomenal
concept. That is, one must be able to give an account of what it is to think of a putatively
neural property in a special, distinctively sensory way that does not just take for granted the
existence of a special phenomenal aspect to the property.
Many such theories, which attempt to spell out what is distinctive and special about
phenomenal concepts in physicalistically respectable terms, have been offered in the
literature. E.g. Lycan (1996), Perry (2001) and Ismael (2007) appeal to the idea that
phenomenal concepts are a kind of indexical or demonstrative concept; Loar (1990/1997) and
Levin (2007) claim that phenomenal concepts are recognitional concepts; Hawthorne (2002)
and Braddon-Mitchell (2003) suggest that phenomenal concepts are conditional concepts.
One important suggestion has been that phenomenal concepts are quotational concepts, which
use a conscious state or property as part of the phenomenal concept whose referent is that
very state or property – just as the device of quotation can embed a word as part of a larger
meta-linguistic term that refers to that very word, e.g. “chair” refers to the English word:
chair and is also partly constituted by it. Likewise then, the idea is that a token phenomenal
concept uses (and is partly constituted by) a token phenomenal property in order to refer to
that very property. This kind of approach has been pursued by Papineau (1993, 2002, 2007),
Balog (1999, 2012) and Melnyk (2002). Balog in particular has claimed that a quotational
account of phenomenal concepts can give a physicalist explanation of our acquaintance with
19
phenomenal properties – i.e. how phenomenal concepts provide/involve a grasp of the
phenomenal property’s essential phenomenal nature. Sam Coleman’s essay in this volume
also deploys the notion of quotation in order to give an explanation of our acquaintance with
phenomenal properties that is consistent with physicalism. (Though Coleman distinguishes
his Quotational Higher-Order Theory of Consciousness from Quotational theories of
phenomenal concepts.)
In contrast, a number of anti-physicalist theorists have claimed that recognising a
relation of conscious acquaintance is mandatory for a good account of consciousness and of
our especially intimate cognitive contact with it’s manifest phenomenal nature, but that
recognising such a relation is a problem for physicalism. Levine (2007) argued that the
phenomenal concept strategy as pursued in strictly physicalist terms, fails to account for the
special direct acquaintance we have with the phenomenal property. (Levine does not selfidentify as an anti-physicalist, but he does think that the need to account for conscious
acquaintance is a serious objection against physicalism.) See White 2007, Chalmers 2007 and
Nida-Rumelin (2007) for related criticisms of the phenomenal concept strategy. In his
contribution to the present volume, Joseph Levine argues that whilst a non-naturalistic
theory of conscious acquaintance is required to explain the especially direct and intimate
cognitive relation we have to our own consciousness, such a non-naturalistic theory cannot
explain some of the other epistemological and semantic roles of experience that a naturalistic
theory of acquaintance is well-placed to explain.
When theorising about the metaphysics of consciousness, one might naturally try to
start from uncontroversial claims about the manifest phenomenal appearance of experience to
the conscious subject’s reflective point of view. But what seems uncontroversial and manifest
to some philosophers may not seem nearly so obvious to others! For example, H. H. Price (in
an oft-quoted passage) wrote:
“When I see a tomato there is much that I can doubt. I can doubt whether it is a tomato
that I am seeing, and not a cleverly painted piece of wax. I can doubt whether there is
any material thing there at all. Perhaps what I took for a tomato was really a reflection;
perhaps I am even the victim of some hallucination. One thing however that I cannot
doubt: that there exists a red patch of a round and somewhat bulgy shape, standing out
from a background of other colour-patches… that something is red and round then and
there I cannot doubt…(Price, 1932, p.3)
But what seemed indubitable to Price – the existence of some actual red, round particular –
has been denied by many adverbial and representational theorists. Likewise, a number of
representational theorists have claimed that the representational nature of perceptual
20
experience is obvious or manifest – e.g. Byrne (2001) Siegel (2010) Horgan & Tienson
(2002) – though this will of course be disputed by their non-representational oppponents.
In his contribution to this volume M. G. F. Martin, considers whether there can be
a description of the manifest subjective ‘facts of appearance’, which remains entirely neutral
between the main rival competing metaphysical accounts of what grounds or determines those
subjective facts – and in particular which remains neutral between representational vs. nonrepresentational theories. Martin starts his essay by considering a disagreement between
different two sense-data theorists – Russell on the one hand, and John Foster on the other –
concerning how to explain the phenomenal difference between episodes of sensory perception
and episodes of sensory imagination and recollection. Whereas Russell sought to explain both
perceptual experiences and conscious imagery in terms of acquaintance with sense-data,
Foster proposed a ‘two-level’ account on which a relation of acquaintance with sense-data –
as occurs in perceptual experience – is the more basic explanatory level, and then conscious
imagining and remembering are to be explained in terms of a representation of the more basic
relational sensory type of episode. An important moral that Martin draws from this debate is
that Foster was correct to think that conscious episodes of imagining and remembering are
manifestly representational in a way that episodes of perceptual experience are not. And thus,
Martin argues, we should reject the idea that there can be description of the subjective facts
which remains neutral between representational and non-representational accounts of the
metaphysical grounds of those facts.
5.2 Acquaintance & Perception
The past couple of decades have witnessed a surge of interest in ‘Naïve-Realist’ or
‘Relational’ theories of perceptual experience, according to which we can be consciously
acquainted with items and features in the external environment. Theorists who explicitly use
the term ‘acquaintance’ in this Naïve-realist context include: Campbell (2009), Fish (2009),
Hellie (2010), Brewer (2011), Soteriou (2013). But even when the term ‘acquaintance’ is not
used – as in, for example, Travis (2004) Putnam (1999), Logue (2012a), Martin (2002, 2004),
the relation of direct conscious awareness that is theorised to hold between subject and
external object is very plausibly thought of as a variety of acquaintance relation.
This surge of interest in Naïve-realism has surely been in large part due to the
development of new ‘disjunctivist’ strategies for responding to the argument from
hallucination – a strategy that is standardly credited first to Hinton (1967, 1973) and then
developed by Snowden (1980, 1990) and McDowell (1982, 1994) and receives its state of the
art defence in the work of M. G. F. Martin (2004, 2006)
In its simplest form, the argument from hallucination moves from 2 premises to the
conclusion that Naïve-realism is false:
21
(1) Hallucinations are conscious episodes that are not essentially relational.
(2) (Common Kind Assumption): Hallucinations and perceptual experiences are the
same essential kind of conscious episodes.
Therefore:
(3) Perceptual experiences are conscious episodes that are not essentially relational.
The first premise has generally gone uncontested (though see Raleigh, 2014, Ali 2016; see
also Johnston (2004) for the claim that in a hallucination one is consciously related to an uninstantiated universal), as it plausibly seems to simply fall out from the definition of a
hallucination. The disjunctivist strategy is to deny (2), the common kind assumption, and to
insist instead that hallucinations and perceptions, even when ‘subjectively indiscriminable’
and/or involving the same neural processes, are fundamentally different kinds of experience.
And so a class of subjectively indiscriminable experiences is said to form a (merely)
disjunctive kind – e.g. an experience as of a yellow lemon is either a perception of a yellow
lemon or a hallucinatory episode that the subject cannot introspectively distinguish from a
perception of yellow lemon. But there is, according to disjunctivists, no
substantial/fundamental common conscious nature, other than this subjective
indiscriminability, that is shared by both disjuncts – though there may be merely neurological
similarities.
Against disjunctivism, Robinson (1985, 1994) emphasises the possibility that the
neural causes/processes involved in both a perception and a subjectively indiscriminable
hallucination might be exactly the same. The problem for a disjunctivist then is that once it is
admitted that this neural event/process suffices by itself to give rise to the hallucinatory
experience and to explain its phenomenology, it seems that in the perceptual case also the
presence of this same neural event/process should likewise suffice to give rise to an
experience of the same type as in the hallucinatory case. Which would seem to ‘screen-off’
the alleged acquaintance relation to the external scene from doing explanatory work vis-à-vis
the phenomenology of the perceptual experience.
In response, Martin (2004, 2006) argues that the disjunctivist should hold that there is
nothing more to the conscious phenomenal nature of a causally-matching hallucination than
its indiscriminability from some perceptual experience – i.e. it is this negative epistemic
condition which explains the phenomenal nature of the hallucination rather than vice-versa.
Martin holds that this ‘negative epistemic’ characterisation of the hallucinatory case avoids
the screening-off worry as such a characterisation is essentially parasitic upon the
phenomenal nature of the perceptual case – and so the alleged naïve-realist acquaintance
22
relation with external features can still have a constitutive explanatory role vis-à-vis the
phenomenology of the perceptual experience11.
Just as hallucinations pose a potential threat to the claim that in perceptual experience
we can be acquainted with the external environment, so likewise dreams – to the extent that
they too are supposed to be episodes with a similarly sensory phenomenal character – might
also be thought to potentially undermine ‘naïve-realist’ positions. Tom Stoneham’s essay in
this volume considers how a naïve-realist, acquaintance theorist should try to deal with
dreams. One possibility would be to adopt a form of disjunctivism – which whilst allowing
that dreams have some kind of phenomenal character, would insist that it is of a
fundamentally different kind to the phenomenal character of perceptual experience. Stoneham
considers this disjunctivist response to be viable but ‘requiring considerable confidence with
respect to metaphysics’ and so ‘a comparative weakness of the [naïve-realist] account’. His
essay thus explores an alternative non-disjunctive strategy when it comes dreams: deny that
dreams have phenomenal character at all. (Compare: Fish 2009 and Logue 2012b both make
parallel denials that hallucinations really have genuine sensory phenomenal character.) Whilst
this will presumably strike many readers as a counter-intuitive and radical proposal,
Stoneham argues that we lack any theory-neutral evidence that dreams really do possess
phenomenal character as opposed to a rival view that we confabulate reports and construct
false memories of dream phenomenology as a result of cultural influence and social pressures
to conform. And so, if one antecedently thought that acquaintance provides the best account
of normal perceptual experience, it would be legitimate to prefer the non-phenomenal theory
of dreams on the basis that it fits with this best account of perception.
As well as the various (disjunctivist or non-disjunctivist) strategies for defending the
view against arguments from illusion, hallucination or dreams, there are various positive
motivations for the ‘naïve-realist’ idea that we can be directly acquainted with external
features. In sections 5.3 and 5.4 below we will consider some of the epistemic and referential
virtues that such a view has been alleged to possess. But another important kind of motivation
is phenomenological – i.e. the idea that we need to appeal to acquaintance with external
features in order to do justice to the manifest phenomenology of experience. For example, in
a series of important and influential papers, M. G. F. Martin (1997, 1998, 2002, 2004, 2006)
has maintained that a naïve-realist theory, according to which we can be directly acquainted
with familiar mind-independent objects and features in our surroundings, provides the best
articulation of how perceptual experience seems to first-personal reflection. Martin (2002) has
11
See Fish (2009) for another presentation of the ‘negative epistemic’ account of
hallucinations. See Sturgeon (1998), Siegel (2004, 2008), Pautz (2011) for criticism of the
negative epistemic account.
23
also argued that naïve-realism also provides the best account of the phenomenology of
sensory imagining, such as visualising.
Another important (and perhaps somewhat unjustly neglected) example of
acquaintance-based theorising about perception, in which the motivation for appealing to
acquaintance is phenomenological, is D. W. Smith’s 1989 book ‘The Circle of Acquaintance’.
In his contribution to the present volume, Smith endorses the idea that in perception we
can be directly acquainted with familiar features in our external environment, but he
emphasises that in our everyday actions we can also gain a kind of acquaintance with the
objects in our surroundings. Moreover, perception and action are usually ‘intertwined’ to such
an extent that they form a unified sort of experience – ‘perception-cum-action’. In unfolding
what he takes to be the complex phenomenological and intentional structure of this kind of
experience, Smith suggests that acquaintance with the familiar features in our surroundings
should be understood in the ‘embodied’ terms first laid down by Husserl and by MerleauPonty, which have more recently inspired theorists such as Varela, Thompson & Rosch
(1991), Gallagher (2006, 2017) or Noe (2004, 2012).
This tradition of embodied and enactivist approaches to experience is also an
important inspiration for Jonathan Knowles’s contribution to this volume. Knowles takes
as his point of departure the recent debate between John Campbell and Quassim Cassam
(2014) over the relative explanatory merits of an acquaintance-based, ‘relational’ account of
experience vs. a representational account. He argues that Campbell’s acquaintance-based
view is correct to insist that the phenomenal character of sensory experience is (at least
partially) constituted by the external objects and features that we perceive. However, Knowles
argues that the relational view does not sufficiently acknowledge the subject’s contribution to
phenomenal character of experience. He thus advances what he takes to be a superior
alternative theory, ‘Phenomenological Externalism’, according to which the objects and
features that we are directly presented with in perceptual experience are part of a ‘world-forme’ or ‘world-for-us’. Knowles’s theory is thus appealing to something like the idea of an
‘Umwelt’ – a term that was due originally to the German biologist Jakob von Uexküll, and
which was an important influence on Husserl’s notion of a Lifeworld (Lebenswelt).
Knowles’s essay provides an extended discussion of how such a ‘world of experience’ relates
to the world as described by our best physical sciences.
Anders Nes’s essay in this volume also engages closely with the work of John
Campbell as well as with the work of John McDowell. Whilst McDowell can be classified as
a kind of disjunctivist about perceptual experience, insisting as he does that in ‘good cases’ of
normal perceptual experience we are ‘open to the world’ (McDowell 1994, 111), he does not
treat this direct perceptual awareness of our surroundings as a relation of acquaintance. This
is because McDowell, following in the footsteps of Sellars and of Kant, insists that perceptual
24
experience itself must already involve the operation of conceptual capacities if it is to be a
source of knowledge and justified belief. Whereas acquaintance is supposed precisely to
contrast with the sort of thoughts and attitudes that employ concepts. However, Nes suggests
that there can be significant convergence between the acquaintance-based, relational position
of Campbell and the conceptualist position of McDowell if we consider the crucial role, for
Campbell, of conscious attention. Nes argues that attention should be considered a conceptual
capacity, in the sense relevant for McDowell’s purposes, and thus claims that many of the
reasons Campbell provides to favour the relational account can be recast in conceptualistfriendly terms.
5.3 Acquaintance & Reference
There is a widely (though not universally) accepted distinction between singular or de
re thoughts and descriptive or de dicto thoughts. The core intuition behind this distinction is
that one way of forming a thought about a particular object is by thinking of some descriptive
condition which that object (uniquely) satisfies. E.g. I may form a thought whose content
includes the descriptive condition: the current heaviest sumo wrestler, and by doing so my
thought will be about the particular individual (assuming there is one) who in fact uniquely
satisfies this condition – in this case, the Mongolian rikishi Ichinojo Takashi. But it seems
that at least sometimes one can think about a particular object in a more direct way – that is,
not via the satisfaction of some descriptive, conceptual condition but simply as that thing.
Granting that such direct, singular reference is sometimes possible, it is often assumed that
the item itself would then figure in the propositional content of the thought, in contrast to the
general, quantificational structure of a merely descriptive content.
There is then a question concerning the conditions under which one can make
singular reference to something and here it is often claimed that some kind of acquaintance
relation with the item in question is required (at least by somebody, somewhere, at some
time); though there is a whole spectrum of views on what counts as acquaintance, and there
are also those who deny that acquaintance is a necessary condition on singular reference at
all. (Jeshion 2010, Hawthorne & Manley 2012)
For example, Imogen Dickie (2010) has defined acquaintance as follows:
“A subject, S, is ‘acquainted’ with an object, o, iff S is in a position to think about o in
virtue of a perceptual link with o and without the use of any conceptual or descriptive
intermediary.” (Dickie, 2010, 213)
Dickie then goes on to argue that we can be acquainted with familiar physical objects in our
environment, as opposed to the idea that we can only be acquainted with mental items such as
25
‘sense-data’. Francois Recanati (2010) takes a slightly different approach, arguing that
acquaintance is a not a strictly necessary condition on singular thought, but rather that
acquaintance with a specific object is a normative /functional standard or constraint on
singular thought – i.e. singular thoughts ought to be tokened on the basis of acquaintance with
the referent for this is their proper purpose or functional role.
In her contribution to the present volume, Jessica Pepp argues that we should
distinguish more carefully between the claim that acquaintance is a necessary condition for a
thought to have singular propositional content and the claim that acquaintance is a necessary
condition for a thought to be about its object in a direct, ‘non-satisfactional’ way. Pepp
suggests that these two conditions can come apart and so even if it is false that acquaintance
is required for singular propositional content, it might yet be true that acquaintance is required
in order to think about an item in this special non-satisfactional manner
Another, related way in which acquaintance has been thought to be important to
reference is to allow for ostensive definitions of concepts/terms and so avoid a regress (or
loop) of merely verbal definitions. If we accept that at least some concepts are not to be
defined in terms of other concepts, then it seems we will need some other kind of nonconceptual relation to the referent. It is very natural to think that acquaintance with the
referent would be ideally suited to play this kind of role – see both Fumerton’s and Levine’s
contributions to this volume for further discussion.
This sort of concern about the ultimate basis for our grasp of reference was an
important motivation for John Campbell’s Reference and Consciousness (2002), a book
which played a seminal role in re-establishing the notion of acquaintance as part of the
mainstream conversation in analytic philosophy. Campbell famously argued that a nonconceptual, non-representational conscious relation to our surroundings – i.e. acquaintance –
is required to ground our knowledge of the reference of our concepts, especially our basic
demonstrative concepts. In later work, Campbell (2002a, 2005, 2009, 2011, Campbell &
Cassam 2014) has emphasized that conscious acquaintance with the external world is required
in order to answer what he calls ‘Berkeley’s Puzzle’:
‘Berkeley is trying to respect a principle about the relation between experience and
concepts that is both important and difficult to keep in place. This is what I will call the
explanatory role of experience. The principle is that concepts of individual physical
objects, and concepts of the observable characteristics of such objects, are made
available by our experience of the world. It is experience of the world that explains our
grasp of these concepts. The puzzle that Berkeley is addressing is that is hard to see how
our concepts of mind-independent objects could have been made available by
experience of them.’ (Campbell, 2002a)
26
Campbell’s claim is that experience cannot play the explanatory role we require of it – viz.,
giving us a conception of a mind-independent world of objects – unless we treat experience as
a non-representational relation of acquaintance. In other words acquaintance is supposedly
required to explain how it is we can even think about the mind-independent external features
of the world, let alone know anything about them. (See Cassam 2011, Campbell & Cassam
2014, Rey 2005 and Jonathan Knowles’ essay in this volume for critical responses to
Campbell.)
Another concern that was already present in Reference and Consciousness was to
understand our grasp not only of our own perceptually-based demonstratives, but also other
people’s perceptual demonstratives. And so we must consider cases of joint attention by two
different subjects to the same object. Campbell’s suggestion was that the nature of one’s
experience in such cases of joint attention is fundamentally different from cases of solitary
perceptual attention – indeed Campbell claimed we should take a ‘relational view’ of joint
attention:
‘Just as the object you see can be a constituent of your experience, so too it can be a
constituent of your experience that the other person is, with you, jointly attending to the
object.” (Campbell, 2002b, 161)
In his contribution to the present volume John Campbell revisits his argument for treating
experiences of joint attention as ‘primitive’. Drawing on empirical work by Michael
Tomasello, Campbell argues that the sort of acquaintance with external objects that is
required for a grasp of reference, and hence for communication, is grounded in very basic
joint-attentional activities that we engage in with our parents or caregivers in early infancy.
Campbell thus hopes to effect a rapprochement between the Wittgensteinian idea that shared,
public language is explanatorily prior to gaining full-blown propositional attitudes and the
core idea of Reference and Consciousness that it is perceptual acquaintance with objects and
features in our environment that explains our grasp of reference.
5.4 Acquaintance & Epistemology
Russell employed the notion of acquaintance as part of the project of foundationalist
epistemology which he saw himself as pursuing. One of the most ancient epistemological
dialectics is a concern with a potential regress of justifications – sometimes called ‘Agrippa’s
Trilemma’. Our beliefs stand in inferential relations (or at rather the contents of those beliefs
do). When the content of one belief entails the content of another, any justification for the
first belief is ‘transmitted’ to the second. (Likewise when the relation is not full entailment
27
but just probability raising, justification can be partially transmitted or bestowed . . .). But
while inferential relations can transmit justification it is not at all obvious, despite what
coherentists may claim, how they could create justification in the 1st place. An inferential
chain or structure could go around in a circle (or some more complicated web-like structure),
it could perhaps extend infinitely, or it can have a terminus – a belief that is not justified via
inferential relations. A foundationalist holds that there are such terminal nodes, which are
nevertheless justified non-inferentially. Some foundationalists in the past held that these
nodes were self-justifying. But the more normal foundational position, these days, is that
these terminal nodes are non-inferentially justified by something that is not a belief – viz, an
experience. If the experience is to provide a reason for belief that is not itself just a further
belief (not just another premise in a potential inference), then the experience must somehow
make something available to the subject in a way that is different from just having another
belief. And then one way to cash this out is that the subject is consciously acquainted with
something – where this episode of acquaintance can provide a reason for believing that p but
not by playing the role of a premise in an inference whose conclusion is p. Rather, the
experience is held to present or reveal the very things, the truth-makers, that the belief that p
is about (see Raleigh 2017 for further discussion of such non-inferential justification).
Recent theorists who have explicitly revived this traditional form of acquaintancebased foundationalism include: Moser (1989), Fumerton (1995, 2001), Bonjour (2003), Fales
(1996), Hassan (2011, 2013). In a similar vein, acquaintance has been appealed to in
epistemological discussions of self-knowledge, where it might be supposed to explain or
account for the distinctively secure status of knowledge of our mental states gained via
introspection. E.g. Brie Gertler (2011, 2012) has based her account of first person privileged
knowledge on the idea that we are acquainted with our own conscious mental states. This
revival of traditional, acquaintance-based foundationalism has faced various criticisms. For
example: Poston (2010) and Huemer (2007) argue that acquaintance cannot allow for fallibly
justified foundational beliefs. (See Fumerton 2010, Hassan 2013 for pro-acquantaince
responses.) Whilst Sosa (2003), Poston (2007) and Markie (2009) suggest that ‘speckled hen
cases’12 pose a problem for an acquaintance-based theories of justification. (See Bonjour
2003, Fumerton 2005 for responses.)
In Richard Fumerton’s essay for this volume, he continues to pursue his own
internalist foundational project in epistemology, a project that he explicitly connects with
Descartes’ employment of the ‘method of doubt’ to search for secure foundations for our
beliefs. Fumerton holds not only that we can be acquainted with conscious mental states of
affairs (facts) and with propositional contents (thoughts) but also with the correspondence
12
The example of a speckled hen is presented by Chisholm (1942), though Chisholm credits the idea
to Gilbert Ryle.
28
that can obtain between the fact and the thought such that the former is the truthmaker for the
latter. Fumerton claims that when we are acquainted with all three of these factors we would
have “strong or ideal” justification for believing the proposition in question. Fumerton argues
that such an account can deal with familiar ‘speckled hen’ type objections by denying that we
have genuine direct acquaintance with one or other of these three factors (fact, thought, or the
correspondence between them). He also argues that acquaintance can provide a unified
account of both empirical and a priori justification.
To be clear – one does not have to be an acquaintance theorist in order to accept that
there is non-inferential justification or in order to be a foundationalist. For example: Jim
Pryor (2000) has influentially argued in favour of the non-inferential justification of beliefs
by experience, but he does not make any sort of appeal to acquaintance (though he does think
that it is the distinctively ‘presentational’ phenomenology of perceptual experience which
allows it to provide defeasible, non-inferential justification for belief). More generally, one
could, prima facie, be a thoroughgoing representational theorist about experience, eschewing
all talk of acquaintance, and still maintain that a contentful, representational experience can
stand in a justificatory relation to a belief that is not an inferential relation.
A different kind of epistemic project for acquaintance, distinct from the
foundationalist project sketched above, is to explain how it is possible for us to gain
knowledge of the intrinsic, categorical nature of external mind-independent features – as
opposed to knowing merely that some or other intrinsic/categorical feature occupies a certain
position or role within a relational, theoretical structure. This ‘revelatory’ function for
acquaintance has in recent years been championed both by John Campbell (1993, 2005) and
Bill Brewer (2011)13. They have argued that acquaintance with the external world allows us to
avoid the sort of epistemic ‘Humility’ about the intrinsic nature of the external world that Rae
Langton (1998) and David Lewis (2009) suggested we are bound to be limited to – a position
that is very similar to epistemic structural realism in the philosophy of science (see, for
example, Maxwell 1968, Worrall 1989 – though it is arguable that Russell was already
endorsing something like structural realism in Problems of Philosophy). In his contribution
to the present volume, Bill Brewer argues that only an acquaintance-based account of visual
experience can explain such an experience’s ability to be a source of knowledge about the
intrinsic/categorical nature of mind-independent properties – e.g. a source of knowledge
about what it is for something to be round or square, red or blue etc. Brewer argues that two
main rival theories, resemblance-based or representational accounts, cannot account for how
experience can be a source of such knowledge. And so to the extent that we wish to avoid
embracing Humility and accept that experience is indeed a source of such ‘revelatory’
13
See also Dasgupta (2015) for another important recent work that appeals to the revelatory function
of acquaintance.
29
knowledge about the external world’s intrinsic nature, we have reason to embrace an
acquaintance-based theory of experience.
A rather more specific epistemological topic in which acquaintance has recently
figured concerns aesthetic knowledge and judgement. Richard Wollheim (1980) proposed an
acquaintance principle according to which it is impossible to gain certain kinds of aesthetic
knowledge about O unless one is acquainted with O itself: ‘judgments of aesthetic value...
must be based on first-hand experience of their objects’ (Wollheim , 1980, 233). A number of
theorists have argued that Wollheim’s formulation is too strong for it would rule out making
judgements about a work’s aesthetic value based on a reproduction or photograph (see e.g.
Livingston 2003, Hopkns 2006). Nevertheless, many philosophers have maintained that
Wollheim’s acquaintance principle points to something correct about aesthetic judgement and
have tried to provide improved reformulations – see e.g. Budd (2003), Todd (2004),
Konigsberg (2012), Robson (2013, 2017), Sauchelli (2016) for further discussion.
It is commonplace to draw a distinction between knowing-that and knowing-how –
i.e. between factual and practical knowledge. Acquaintance raises the prospect that there may
be a third important kind of knowledge, which we might call objectual knowledge. We will
then naturally wonder whether one or other of these kinds of knowledge reduces to or
depends on one of the others. In the case of knowing-that and knowing-how, this question has
generated a very large literature (see Stanley & Williamson 2001, Stanley 2010 for recent
influential discussion; see Fantl 2009 for a useful survey article). And as mentioned already,
in section 3 above, Russell held that knowledge of an object by acquaintance was a
fundamentally different kind of knowledge, to knowing a truth about an object – indeed
Russell held that knowledge-by-acquaintance was the more fundamental kind. Katalin
Farkas, in her contribution to this volume, considers whether objectual knowledge forms a
genuine, irreducibly distinct kind of knowledge. Farkas argues that our everyday, natural
language talk of ‘knowing things’ does not express such a distinctive kind of objectual
knowledge with its own special, uniform nature. Indeed, Farkas suggests that at least some of
our familiar talk of ‘knowing things’ refers to relations that should not be classified as
knowledge at all. However, Farkas concludes that a distinctively philosophical notion of
acquaintance with one’s own conscious experience might allow us to carve out a narrower but
genuinely unified, sui generis category of objectual knowledge.
******
Whilst the foregoing survey of recent acquaintance-based theorising has by no means
been exhaustive, I hope that it will, like the essays gathered here, provide a sense of the rich
variety of topics for which the notion of acquaintance is currently being employed.
30
References
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Ali, R. (2016) ‘Does Hallucinating Involve Perceiving?’, Philosophical Studies 175
(3): 601-627
Bach, K. (2010) “Getting a Thing into Thought”, in Robin Jeshion (ed.), New Essays
on Singular Thought. Oxford University Press.
Balog, K. (1999) ‘Conceivability, Possibility, and the Mind-Body Problem’,
Philosophical Review 108 (4): 497-528
Balog, K. (2012) ‘Acquaintance and the mind-body problem’, in Simone Gozzano &
Christopher S. Hill (eds.), New Perspectives on Type Identity: The Mental and the
Physical, Cambridge University Press
Bengson, J., Grube, E. & Korman, D. (2011) ‘A New Framework for Conceptualism’
Noûs 45 (1): 167-189.
Bigelow, J. & Pargetter, R. (1990) ‘Acquaintance with Qualia’, Theoria 61 (3): 129147.
Bigelow & Pargetter (2006) ‘Re-Acquaintance with Qualia’, Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 84 (3): 353-378.
Bonjour, L. (2003) “A Version of Internalist Foundationalism,” in L. BonJour and E.
Sosa, Epistemic Justification: Internalism vs. Externalism, Foundations vs. Virtues,
Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2003) ‘Qualia and analytical conditionals’, Journal of
Philosophy 100(3): 111-135.
Brewer, B. (2011) Perception and its Objects, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Budd, M. (2003) ‘The Acquaintance Principle’, British Journal of Aesthetics 43
(4):386-392.
Byrne, A. (2001) “Intentionalism Defended”, Philosophical Review, 110: 199–240
Campbell, J. (1993) ‘A Simple View of Colour’, in John J. Haldane & C. Wright
(eds.), Reality: Representation and Projection, Oxford University Press.
Campbell, J. (2002a) Reference and Consciousness, Oxford: Oxford University Press
Campbell, J. (2002b) “Berkeley's Puzzle”, in Conceivability and Possibility, Tamar
Szabo Gendler and John O'Leary Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press
Campbell, J. (2005) “Précis of Reference and Consciousness, and Replies to Neil
Manson and Georges Rey”, Philosophical Studies, 126: 103–114, 145–153, 155–162
Campbell, J. (2007) ‘The Metaphysics of Perception’, Philosophical Issues 17 (1): 1–
15.
Campbell, J. (2009) ‘Consciousness and Reference’ in McLaughlin & Beckermann
(eds.) Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: OUP.
Campbell, J. (2011) “Relational vs. Kantian Responses to Berkeley's Puzzle”, in
Understanding Perception, Causation and Objectivity, N. Eilan, H. Lerman and J.
Roessler (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Campbell, J. & Cassam, Q. (2014) Berkeley’s Puzzle, Oxford: OUP.
Chalmers, D. (1996) The Conscious Mind, Oxford: OUP.
Chalmers, D. (2004) ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Knowledge Argument’, in Peter
Ludlow, Yujin Nagasawa & Daniel Stoljar (eds.), There's Something About Mary:
Essays on Phenomenal Consciousness and Frank Jackson's Knowledge Argument,
MIT Press
Chalmers, D. (2007) Phenomenal Concepts and the Explanatory Gap’, in Torin Alter
& Sven Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New
Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism, Oxford University Press.
31
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Chisholm, R. (1942) ‘The Problem of the Speckled Hen’, Mind 51(204): 368-373.
Churchland, P. (1989) ‘Knowing Qualia: A Reply to Jackson’ in Churchland, P. A
Neurocomputational Perspective, MIT Press
Conee, E. (1994) ‘Phenomenal Knowledge’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72:
136-150.
Crane, T. (2009) “Is Perception a Propositional Attitude?”, Philosophical Quarterly,
59: 452–69.
Dasgupta, S. (2015) ‘Inexpressible Ignorance’, Philosophical Review, 124(4): 441480.
Dickie, I. (2010) ‘We Are Acquainted with Ordinary Things’, in Robin Jeshion (ed.),
New Essays on Singular Thought, Oxford University Press.
Duncan, M. (2015) ‘We Are Acquainted with Ourselves’, Philosophical Studies 172
(9):2531-2549
Evans, G. (1982) The Varieties of Reference, Oxford University Press.
Fales, E. (1996) A Defense of the Given, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Fantl, J. (2009) “Knowing-How and Knowing-That,” Philosophy Compass, 3(3):
451–70.
Fish, W. (2009) Perception, Hallucination, and Illusion, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Fumerton, R. (1995) Metaepistemology and Skepticism, Lanham, MD: Rowman and
Littlefield.
Fumerton, R. (2001) “Classical Foundationalism,” in M. De Paul (ed.), Resurrecting
Old-Fashioned Foundationalism, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Fumerton, R. (2005) “Speckled Hens and Objects of Acquaintance,” Philosophical
Perspectives, 19: 121–138.
Fumerton, R. (2010) “Poston on Similarity and Acquaintance,” Philosophical
Studies, 147: 379–86.
Gallagher, S. (2006) How the Body Shapes the Mind, Oxford: OUP.
Gallagher, S. (2017) Enactivist Interventions: Rethinking the Mind, Oxford: OUP
Gertler, B. (1999) ‘A Defense of the Knowledge Argument’, Philosophical Studies
93 (3): 317-336.
Gertler, B. (2011) Self-Knowledge, New York: Routledge.
Gertler, B (2012) “Renewed Acquaintance,” in Declan Smithies and Daniel Stoljar
(eds.), Introspection and Consciousness, 93–128. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goff, P. (2011) 'A posteriori physicalists get our phenomenal concepts wrong',
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89: 2, 191-209
Goff, P. (2015) ‘Real acquaintance and physicalism,’ in P. Coates & S. Coleman
(Eds.) Phenomenal Qualities: Sense, Perception, and Consciousness, Oxford
University Press
Gomes, A. (2017) ‘Naïve Realism in Kantian Phrase’, Mind 126(502): 529-578.
Grote, J. (1865) Exploratorio Philosophica
Hart, H. L. A. et al (1949) ‘Symposium: Is there knowledge by acquaintance?’,
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume) 23(1): 69 – 128.
Hasan, A. (2011) “Classical Foundationalism and Bergmann's Dilemma for
Internalism,” Journal of Philosophical Research, 36: 391–410
Hasan, A. (2013) “Phenomenal Conservatism, Classical Foundationalism, and
Internalist Justification,” Philosophical Studies, 162: 119–141
Hawthorne, J. (2002) ‘Advice for Physicalists’, Philosophical Studies 109 (1): 17–52.
Hawthorne, J. & Manley, D. (2012) The Reference Book, Oxford: OUP.
Hellie, B. (2009) ‘Acquaintance’, in Tim Bayne, Axel Cleeremans & Patrick Wilken
(eds.), Oxford Companion to Consciousness, Oxford University Press.
Hellie, B. (2010) ‘An Externalist's Guide to Inner Experience’, in Bence Nanay (ed.),
Perceiving the World, Oxford University Press
32
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Helmholtz, H. (1868 [1995]) ‘The Recent Progress of the Theory of Vision’ in
Science and Culture: Popular and Philosophical Essays, ed. David Cahan, Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press.
Hinton, J. M., 1967, “Visual Experiences”, Mind, 76: 217–227.
Hinton, J. M., 1973, Experiences: An Inquiry into Some Ambiguities, Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Hopkins, R. (2006) ‘How to Form Aesthetic Belief: Interpreting the Acquaintance
Principle’ Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics 3.3: 85–99
Horgan, T. & Tienson, J. (2002) ‘The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the
Phenomenology of Intentionality’, in David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind:
Classical and Contemporary Readings, OUP.
Huemer, M. (2007) “Compassionate Phenomenal Conservatism,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 74 (1): 30–55.
Hylton, P. (1990) Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy,
Oxford University Press.
Ismael, J. (2007) The Situated Self, Oxford: OUP.
Jackson, F. (1982) ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly 32 (April): 127136
James, W. (1890) Principles of Psychology, New York: Henry Holt and Company.
Jansen, J. (2014) ‘Taking a Transcendental Stance: Anti-Representationalism and
Direct Realism in Kant and Husserl’, in (eds.) Faustino Fabbianelli & Sebastian Luft
Husserl und die Klassische Deutsche Philosophie, Springer.
Jeshion, R. (2010) ‘Singular Thought: Acquaintance, Semantic Instrumentalism, and
Cognitivism’, in Jeshion (ed.) New Essays on Singular Thought, Oxford: OUP.
Johnston, M. (2004) “The Obscure Object of Hallucination”, Philosophical Studies,
103: 113–83
Johnston, M. (2011) ‘On a neglected epistemic virtue’, Philosophical Issues 21(1):
165-218.
Kennedy, M. (2007) ‘Visual Awareness of Properties’, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 75(2): 298–325.
Kennedy, M. (2013) ‘Explanation in Good and Bad Experiential Cases’ in Fiona
Macpherson & Dimitris Platchias (eds.), Hallucination: Philosophy and Psychology,
MIT Press.
Konigsberg, A. (2012) ‘The Acquaintance Principle, Aesthetic Autonomy, and
Aesthetic Appreciation’, British Journal of Aesthetics 52 (2): 153-168.
Langsam, H. (2011) The Wonder of Consciousness: Understanding the Mind
Through Philosophical Reflection, MIT Press.
Langton, R. (1998) Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves,
Oxford: OUP
Leibniz, G. (1765) New Essays on Human Understanding, Langley (trans.)
Cambridge University Press.
Levin, J (2007) “What is a phenomenal concept?” in T. Alter & S. Walter (eds.),
Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge. New Essays on Consciousness
and Physicalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Levine, J. (2001) Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness, Oxford University
Press.
Levine, J. (2007) “Phenomenal Concepts and the Materialist Constraint,” in T. Alter
& S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge. New Essays
on Consciousness and Physicalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lewis, D. (1988) “What Experience Teaches”, Proceedings of the Russellian Society,
13: 29–57.
Lewis, D. (2009) ‘Ramseyan Humility’. In D. Braddon-Mitchell and R. Nola (eds.),
Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism. Cambridge, Mass: MIT.
33
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Livingston, P. (2003) ‘On an Apparent Truism in Aesthetics’, Journal of Aesthetics
43(3): 260-278
Loar, B. (1990/1997) “Phenomenal States” (Revised Version), in The Nature of
Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, N. Block, O. Flanagan, G. Güzeldere (eds.),
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Logue, H. (2012a) ‘Why Naive Realism?’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
112 (2pt2): 211-237. 2012.
Logue, H. (2012b) ‘What should the naïve realist say about total hallucinations?’
Philosophical Perspectives 26 (1): 173-199.
Logue, H. (2014) ‘Experiential Content and Naive Realism: A Reconciliation’ in
Berit Brogaard (ed.), Does Perception Have Content?, Oxford University Press.
Lycan, W. (1996) Consciousness and Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Makin, G. (2000) The Metaphysicians of Meaning: Russell and Frege on Sense and
Denotation, London: Routledge.
Markie, P. (2009) “Classical Foundationalism and Speckled Hens,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 79 (1): 190–206
Martin, M. G. F. (1997) “The Reality of Appearances”, in Thought and Ontology, M.
Sainsbury (ed.), Milan: Franco Angeli, pp. 77–96.
Martin, M. G. F. (1998) “Setting Things Before the Mind”, in Contemporary Issues
in the Philosophy of Mind, A. O'Hear (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Martin, M. G. F. (2002) “The Transparency of Experience”, Mind and Language, 17:
376–425.
Martin, M. G. F. (2004) “The Limits of Self-Awareness”, Philosophical Studies, 120:
37–89.
Martin, M. G. F. (2006) “On Being Alienated”, in Perceptual Experience, Tamar S.
Gendler and John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press
Maxwell, G. (1968) ‘Scientific methodology and the causal theory of perception’, in
I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Problems in the philosophy of science. Amsterdam:
North-Holland Publishing Company.
McDowell, J. (1982) “Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge”, Proceedings of the
British Academy, 68: 455–79.
McDowell, J. (1994) Mind and World, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
McLear, C. (2016) ‘Kant on Perceptual Content’, Mind 125 (497):95-144.
Melnyk, A. (2002) Papineau on the Intuition of Distinctness’ SWIF Philosophy of
Mind 4(1).
Moore, G. E. (1903) ‘The Refutation of Idealism’ Mind 12 (48):433-453.
Moore, G. E. et al (1919) ‘Symposium: Is there knowledge by acquaintance?’,
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume) 2 (1):159 – 220
Moser, P. (1989) Knowledge and Evidence, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nanay, B. (2016) ‘Philosophy of perception – A road-map with many bypass roads’,
in Bence Nanay (eds.) Current Controversies in Philosophy of Perception, London:
Routledge.
Nemirov, L. (1980) “Review of Thomas Nagel, Mortal Questions,” Philosophical
Review 89: 473–477.
Nemirov, L. (1990) “Physicalism and the Cognitive Role of Acquaintance,” in Lycan
(ed.) Mind and Cognition, Oxford: Blackwell.
Nida-Rumelin, M. (2007) “Grasping phenomenal properties,” in T. Alter & S. Walter
(eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge. New Essays on
Consciousness and Physicalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Noe, A. (2004) Action in Perception, MIT Press.
Noe, A. (2008) ‘Reply to Campbell, Martin and Kelly’, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, Vol. 76, No. 3: 691-706
Noe, A. (2012) Varieties of Presence, Harvard University Press
34
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Papineau, D. (1993) Philosophical Naturalism, Oxford: Blackwell, 1993
Papineau, D. (2002) Thinking about Consciousness, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Papineau, D. (2007) “Phenomenal and perceptual concepts,” in T. Alter & S. Walter
(eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge. New Essays on
Consciousness and Physicalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Passmore, J. (1957) A Hundred Years of Philosophy, New York: Basic Books.
Pautz, A. (2011) “Can Disjunctivists Explain our Access to the Sensible World?”,
Philosophical Issues, 21: 384–433.
Perry, J. (2001) Knowledge, Possibility and Consciousness, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Poston, T. (2007) “Acquaintance and the Problem of the Speckled Hen,”
Philosophical Studies, 132: 331–346.
Poston, T. (2010) “Similarity and Acquaintance,” Philosophical Studies, 147: 369–
378.
Price, H. H. (1932) Perception. London: Methuen.
Pryor, J. (2000) ‘The Skeptic and the Dogmatist’, Noûs 34 (4): 517–549.
Putnam, H. (1999) The Threefold Cord, New York: Columbia University Press.
Raleigh, T. (2014) “A New Approach to ‘Perfect’ Hallucinations”, Journal of
Consciousness Studies 21 (11-12): 81-110.
Raleigh, T. (2017) “Against an Inferentialist Dogma”, Synthese 194 (4): 1397-1421
Raleigh, T. (forthcoming) “Visual Acquaintance, Action and The Explanatory Gap”,
Synthese.
Recanati, F. (2010) ‘Singular Thought: In Defense of Acquaintance’, in Robin
Jeshion (ed.), New Essays on Singular Thought, Oxford University Press.
Rey, G. (2005) ‘Explanation, not Experience: Commentary on John Campbell,
Reference and Consciousness’, Philosophical Studies 126 (1): 131-143.
Robinson, H. (1985) “The General Form of the Argument for Berkeleian Idealism”,
In Essays on Berkeley: A Tercentennial Celebration, J. Foster and H. Robinson
(eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Robinson, H. (1994) Perception, London: Routledge.
Robson, J. (2013) ‘Appreciating the Acquaintance Principle: A Reply to Konigsberg’
British Journal of Aesthetics 53 (2): 237-245. 2013
Robson, J. (2017) ‘Is perception the canonical route to aesthetic judgement?’,
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 1-12. 2017
Russell, B. (1903) ‘Principles of Mathematics’, Cambridge University Press
Russell, B. (1905) ‘On Denoting’ Mind, 14: 479–493
Russell, B. (1911) ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance & Knowledge by Description’,
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11: 108–128
Russell, B. (1912) Problems of Philosophy, London: Williams and Norgate
Russell, B. (1914) ‘On the Nature of Acquaintance’, Monist, 24: 1–16, 161–187,
435–453
Russell, B. (1921) Analysis of Mind, London: George Allen and Unwin.
Sauchelli, A. (2016) ‘The Acquaintance Principle, Aesthetic Judgments, and
Conceptual Art’ Journal of Aesthetic Education 50 (1): 1-15.
Sellars, W. (1956) ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind’ in Minnesota Studies in
the Philosophy of Science, vol. I, H. Feigl & M. Scriven (eds.), Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press.
Siegel, S. (2004) “Indiscriminability and the Phenomenal”, Philosophical Studies,
120: 90–112
Siegel, S. (2008) “The Epistemic Conception of Hallucination”, in Disjunctivism:
Perception, Action, Knowledge, Fiona Macpherson and Adrian Haddock (eds.),
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
35
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Siegel, S. (2010) The Contents of Visual Experience, New York: Oxford University
Press
Snowdon, P. F., (1980) “Perception, Vision and Causation”, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, New Series, 81: 175–92.
Snowdon, P. F. (1990) “The Objects of Perceptual Experience”, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes, 64: 121–150.
Sosa, E. (2003) “Beyond Internal Foundations to External Virtues,” in L. BonJour
and E. Sosa, Epistemic Justification: Internalism vs. Externalism, Foundations vs.
Virtues, Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Soteriou, M. (2013) The Mind’s Construction: The Ontology of Mind and Mental
Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press
Stanley, J. (2010) Know How, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stanley, J. & Williamson, T. (2001) “Knowing How,” The Journal of Philosophy,
98(8): 411–44.
Stoneham, T. (2002) Berkeley's World: An Examination of the Three Dialogues,
Oxford: OUP.
Sturgeon, S. (1998) “Visual Experience”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
New Series, 98: 179–200
Todd, C. (2004) ‘Quasi-Realism, Acquaintance, and the Normative Claims of
Aesthetic Judgement’, British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (3):277-296.
Travis, C. (2004) “The Silence of the Senses”, Mind, 113(449): 57–94
Tye, M. (2009) Consciousness Revisited: Materialism without Phenomenal Concepts,
MIT Press.
Varela, F., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991) The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science
and Human Experience, MIT Press.
White, S. (2007) “Property Dualism, Phenomenal Concepts, and the Semantic
Premise,” in T. Alter & S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal
Knowledge. New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Williamson, T. (2000) Knowledge and Its Limits, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wishon, D. (2012) ‘Perceptual Aquaintance and Informational Content’ in Miguens
& Preyer (eds.), Consciousness and Subjectivity, Ontos Verlag
Wishon, D. & Linksy, L. (eds.) (2015) Acquaintance, Knowledge, and Logic: New
Essays on Bertrand Russell's The Problems of Philosophy, Center for the Study of
Language and Information Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations, G.E.M. Anscombe and R.
Rhees (eds.), G.E.M. Anscombe (trans.), Oxford: Blackwell.
Wollheim, R. (1980) Art and Its Objects (2nd ed.) Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press,
Woodruff-Smith, D. (1989) The Circle of Acquaintance, Cambridge University Press
Worrall, J. (1989) ‘Structural realism: The best of both worlds?’, in D. Papineau
(Ed.), The philosophy of science, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
36