Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium Vol. 2 No. 1 (2017)
The Violence of Democracy
Prem Kumar Vijayan
Hindu College, University of Delhi
Abstract: This paper seeks to examine the relation between democracy and violence. It will
first offer an historical overview of the emergence of democracy in relation to three major political
events: the English civil war from 1640-1660; the American war of independence and the
drafting of the Bill of Rights; and the French Revolution. It will propose that, apart from the
fact that each of these struggles was marked by large-scale and protracted violence, they also
shared a common discourse – the discourse of rights, understood proprietorially. The paper will
argue that the emergence of democracy as articulated through this discourse of proprietorial rights
was, in turn, closely related to the emergence of the contemporary form of the nation-state, and
that, consequently, it is founded on a paradox: the discourse of the nation (or nationalism) has
been historically an exclusivist one, while the discourse of democracy seeks, by definition, to be
inclusive. It will argue that the colonial moment served on the one hand, to disseminate the
discourses of nationalism and democracy; while on the other, it complicated the paradoxical
relation between them further, when the discourse of rights (integral to both) often emphasized
community rights over individual rights, at least in colonial South Asia. The contours of
community, then and since, have been overwhelmingly determined by the personal law system
and the communal patriarchates. Given that, this paper will argue that the tensions between the
exclusivism of such communalisms and the inclusivism of the democratic discourse leads
inevitably to the production of cultures of violence. It will conclude by questioning the
sustainability of a rights-based understanding of democracy.
Keywords: democracy, communal identify, violence, individual and civil
rights, minorities, citizenship
Introduction
This paper intends to explore the dynamics between violence and democracy.1
It is often said that ‘democracy’ as a term has been applied and invoked in
relation to so many different political forms and practices that its actual
analytical usability is almost nil. Nevertheless, as I will argue in this paper,
however ‘democracy’ is conceived of, all its various, even contradictory
formulations share a widely held, ‘commonsensical’, even somewhat simplistic
© The Author(s)/psags/kairostext.in
CONTACT Prem Kumar Vijayan
[email protected]
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
84
premise: that violence and democracy are antithetical to each other. This
premise is often articulated in platitudes, e.g., that “there is no place for
violence in a democratic society” – that reflect certain assumptions about both
violence and democracy – such as that violence is inherently irrational, and
democracy inherently rational; or the Weberian thesis that the state is defined
by its monopoly over legitimate force, which implies that any violence by a
non-state actor is necessarily illegitimate; and so on.2 This paper aims to engage
with some of those assumptions – why they are made, what purpose they serve,
their political implications – in the course of examining the dynamic noted
above. It will argue that this almost universal premise, that democracy and
violence are antithetical to each other, is actually an integral element of a larger
culture of violence. That culture generates this premise as both critique and
defence of itself – the critique is the defence, insofar as the critique distances
itself (the critiquing society) from itself (the critiqued society). The paper will
then examine how this plays out in the context of India.
The Idea of Democracy
The history of democracy as we, in the post-colonial present, have inherited it,
is indelibly marked by what is commonly referred to as the ‘west’. Put another
way, ‘democracy’ is an idea that has its historical roots in ancient Greece,
subsequently to resurface millennia later, as part of the process of nation-state
formation in Western Europe and North America, from the seventeenth
century onward. The question of whether or not there were other democratic
political formations and/or practices elsewhere in the world during this time is
of little more than academic interest, since the pertinent template for us today,
is the Euro-American form noted above, and which I will elaborate on briefly
below. This form has disseminated through the globe largely through the
process of colonisation but also through other means – revolutionary, adoptive,
adaptive, even through (paradoxically) imperial/militaristic intervention, as for
instance with the ‘Democratic Republic of Congo’. As I noted above, this
evolutionary process has been studied and discoursed on by a host of scholars
from every hue of the political and ideological spectrum, and needs little
reiteration (see for instance, von Holdt 2014; Schwarzmantel 2010; Keane
2004). Here, I wish to dwell briefly on the relation between democracy,
violence, the discourse of rights and the notion of the nation.
The emergence of the discourse of democracy in modern times can be
traced back to three major political events: the English civil war from 16401660; the American war of independence and the drafting of the Bill of Rights;
and the French Revolution. Each of these epochal events was fundamentally
transformative of the political and social domains they occurred in – but they
are related in other, more significant ways too. First, they were all marked by
bloody and prolonged violence, ending with some form of democratisation of
the polity (albeit of varying stability and to varying degrees) – a point we will
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
85
return to shortly. Second, they all centred on a discourse of individual and civil
rights which, for the first time, sought to establish rights as belonging to the
individual subjects of a state, and not just to a privileged few within it, or to the
state itself in relation to its subjects. Intrinsic to this were the prior history of the
Reformation (dating back to the early sixteenth century) and the gradual delinking of the Church from the State (from about the middle of the seventeenth
century); but as important was the casting of these rights in a language of
proprietorship – as inalienable possessions of the individual (male) subject (see
MacPherson 1962).3
The language of proprietorship is particularly significant because it
indexes the changed and changing composition of the relevant societies. This
changing composition may be summed up (albeit rather baldly) as the gradual
and increasing presence in economic and political power of the mercantile and
professional classes, who were accruing and consolidating private capital from
outside the traditional feudal elites (Jha 2012). The requirement of statutory
protection through legal rights for this capital acquisition and accumulation was
however not just at the level of the individual subject. The imperial conquest
and colonial policies that were initiated in this period served the interests of
precisely these emergent classes, for whom it then became necessary to try to
control and direct the formulation and administration of these policies – in
other words, to have a real say in governance. It is at this point (around the
early eighteenth century) that the discourse of rights begins to turn into an
instrument for demanding and ensuring democratic participatory governance –
i.e. collective governance through public debate and consensus rather than
through individual or privileged fiat. It is thus not coincidental that the ideation
of the nation-state as a coherent collective with common interests emerges in
this period as the ideology of nationalism. It is not coincidental that the modern
nation-state as an effect of these interests is chartered in and through the
language of democracy.
This brings us to the third point of similarities in the three cases noted
above, which is in essence a paradox: unlike earlier mobilisations under the sign
of collective identity – say for instance Anglo-Saxon resistance to Norman
conquest in the early part of the second millennium, or internecine conflicts
between the Gothic tribes, some centuries later – the ideology of nationalism
was founded on a notion of abstract, universal and anonymous equality, but
within a defined and identified collective. It is important to understand this
development clearly: what we are witnessing in these epochal moments is the
articulation and implementation of the paradoxical idea that democracy can
(and should) be exclusive. For instance, the Commonwealth established by
Cromwell through the English Civil War was never intended as extending to a
true commonwealth of all English subjects, let alone non-English ones; the
American Declaration of Independence explicitly claimed ‘unalienable rights’
on the principle that ‘all men [sic] are equal’, but the Bill of Rights and the
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
86
Constitution that followed would nevertheless guarantee these only to
Americans (and, in practice, further excluded blacks, women and the ‘original’
aboriginal Americans); the French Revolution could turn into the Reign of
Terror precisely because ‘liberty’, ‘equality’ and ‘fraternity’ – the last in
particular a most telling term, bespeaking an exclusively male and national
collective, and in this sense already undoing the intent of the first two terms –
were not available to those determined as being outside the national collective.
Thus, (assuming that inclusiveness is a characteristic of democracy) the very
important principle of determining who to include and conversely, of who to
exclude (with equal attention to both) is then not a function of the democratic
ideal per se but a product of its articulation in and through the ideation of the
nation.
Some clarifications are required before we proceed. In one sense,
democracy has historically always contained this paradox: from the exclusivity
of the citizenship that was required to participate in democracy in ancient
Greece, to the instances noted above, to the blatant irony of the National
Democratic Socialist Party of ante-bellum Germany, to the ‘special’ status of
Kashmir in the Indian political system – the instances abound – democracy has
always been limited and/or exclusive. To remark on it here is then not so much
to suggest a particularly new perspective, as to focus on some historical
consequences of the flow of its dynamics, specifically its intimate evolutionary
association with two processes: the emergent discourse of rights and the more
contemporary ideation of the nation-state. Indeed, this particular conjunction
hinges on the question, ‘Who is entitled to the nation-state, and why?’, a
question that emerged in the transition from feudalism to capitalism in the
European context, precisely because the nation and the state were themselves emerging
as resources to be claimed – i.e., as contested forms of capital. Thus, in the discourse of
‘rights’ that underlies the discourse of ‘democratisation’ in this context, ‘rights’
too are conceptualised as a form of legal capital, to be acquired by the
claimants, not given automatically. In other words, when democracy is invoked
within the architectonics of the modern nation-state, (a) its fundamental
proposition of equal, participatory and consensual governance for all citizens,4
is its political and ideological justification, and yet (b) its application is
determined by the cultural logics – customs, beliefs, sentiments, mythologies,
rituals – of nationalism; and (c) its historically inherent principles of exclusivity
then serve to generate a contestational politics of identity (intra- and/or interstate).
The second clarification is related to possible defences of democracy,
along the following lines: (a) that there cannot be any other practice of
democracy but in and through the exclusivist structure of the nation-state; yet
conversely (b), that the ideal democratic system that would be truly inclusive,
universal and egalitarian cannot exist within the global dispensation of separate
nation-states. Again, (c) that democracy by definition is a form of rule, and
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
87
therefore has to be executed, implemented and maintained through institutions
of administration – i.e., a state, which is by definition an exclusive body within
a given society; yet (d) that, because it is the function of states to maintain
economic, social and territorial control, they cannot extend democratic rights
to individuals or groups that threaten this function, and therefore democracy
cannot be blamed as flawed for what is essentially an issue of state function. It is
evident that these are all related arguments, each with some degree of
legitimacy – the degree being set by the extent to which they also contradict
each other. To my mind, the contradictoriness is itself a sign of the problematic
history of democracy, and may be summed up simply as stemming from the
attempt to realise an abstract universal ideal within the contingencies of
historical circumstance. Hence the frequent qualification of democracy into its
varieties – revolutionary, socialist, liberal, capitalist, nationalist, representative,
etc. These qualifications then become the implicit and/or explicit principle of
exclusion.
There is a third clarification I seek to make before proceeding. The
paradox drawn attention to in the argument above seems to suggest an
underlying, even inbuilt contradiction in the concept of democracy, especially
when it is sought to be realised within a specific historical context. Further,
there is an implicit suggestion, particularly in the instances I have offered, that
democracy is dogged by violence precisely because of this contradiction – that,
in other words, rather than serving to end violence, every attempt to realise
democracy within the political form of the nation-state seems to serve only to
perpetuate violence in one form or another. This is an important consideration;
but in order to address it fully, it is necessary to return to our narrative of
democracy itself, to understand the concept and its dynamics fully before we
interrogate its logical and historical feasibility. In order to do so, I will turn now
to the specific paths that democracy has adopted in the South Asian – primarily
the Indian – context.
Indian ‘Democracy’: Origins
The language of democracy, its attendant discourses of rights and the idea of a
national community that can claim those rights, were all introduced into the
South Asian region through the colonial encounter. One of the most powerful
transformations of South Asian polity and society wrought by this encounter
was the complete overhaul of cognitions of the separations of space, of the
meanings of public and private spaces, and their juxtaposition in political terms.
Sudipta Kaviraj has noted how the state in pre-colonial India was never as
central to the lives of its subjects as it came to be under and after colonisation
(1999, 142ff). Prior to the interventions of the colonial state, the dynamic
between the public and the personal was arguably much more localised,
determined largely by the organisation of power and hierarchies, both
geographically (at the respective levels of the village, province, kingdom, etc. in
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
88
specific regions) and communally (in terms of the specific, locally available
relations between castes and religious communities), and between these
communities and the particular dispensations of the local (princely or nawabi)
state (Kaviraj 1999; Dumont 1970; Heesterman 1985). It would not be
inaccurate to characterise this organisation of the flow of power as held and
maintained by the codes of a cultural regime, rather than an administrative
bureaucracy. In contrast, the political dispensation evolving in the West that we
briefly sketched earlier, and that was introduced into the subcontinent by the
British from the eighteenth century onward, was already fundamentally
inscribed by the emergent discourses of liberal individualism, secularisation and
the public-private dichotomisation of the social and political realms (Kaviraj
1999; Taylor 1993; Fox-Genovese 1991; Horwitz 1982), embedded in and
shaped by the structures of an administrative bureaucracy, and the dynamics of
an evolving capitalist economy. This political dispensation was an early form of
what was to emerge as liberal democracy in Britain. By the time the British
government began to exercise direct administrative power in India – i.e. from
1858 onward – this political dispensation was already emerging as liberal
democracy in Britain, containing some crucial constituent elements like
elections to a parliament, representational governance, political parties,
inalienable rights, equality before the law (at least notionally), etc.
Many of these ideas began to permeate into the colonies of the empire,
partly through native intellectuals and leaders who had studied the colonial
master and began interrogating empire in the same language of rights that had
facilitated it in the first place – but, in some ways more significantly, also
through British imperial administrative policies themselves. For instance, the
British administration, as part of the pragmatics of establishing political and
administrative hegemony, began a process of identifying communities in
religious terms, the differences established through separate personal laws
drawn up in consultation with the respective communal elites, thereby also
separating these personal laws from public or civil and contractual laws (Mani
1987; Newbigin 2009). In effect, the entire cultural bureaucracy referred to
above was codified in the form of the personal laws of each community; and
since these laws mostly concerned women and property, it was effectively also
the codification of the individual communal patriarchal cultures into a
multiplicity of communal patriarchates. In essence, the personal laws
guaranteed the rights of the communal patriarchate to govern the community.
The principle of inclusion/exclusion which was central to the formation of the
communal patriarchates, thus became integral to the codification of personal
laws too – but paradoxically, as part of a move towards a more representative (and hence
more democratic) system of governance.
Community organisations (and sometimes individuals) could seek
modifications in these laws or fresh legislation, provided they could
demonstrate either communal authority, and/or numerical support, as
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
89
representing their community. The goal was limited representative
participation in governance – getting the native elite to rule the communities of
India on their behalf – by allowing communal patriarchies a degree of power
over their communities in return for the same communal elites mediating for
the British with their respective communities (Zavos 2000; Guha 1989; Aloysius
1999). While the idea of representative participation in the colonial
administration never did really take hold – because of the limited scope of the
proffered participation, as well as of opposition to the principle of separate
communal electorates – the concomitant ideas of communal representation and
collective public action in a ‘neutral’ public space of debate, discussion and
dissent proved enormously popular and quickly grew and spread across the
country. This is not to suggest that imperial governance was itself democratic –
it was far from it – but that the constituent discourses of democracy took firm
hold on South Asian soil, (a) as a (probably completely unanticipated) byproduct of the administrative measures of the British; and (b) not by
overcoming and/or replacing the older, feudal patriarchates, but paradoxically,
by reinforcing them through codifying them into personal law.
Fundamentally related to this process was the evolution of nationalist
discourses. Even as the discourse of rights began to enter into political play in
the organisation of the indigenous elites, it took shape as communal rights
rather than as individual rights, as in the case of Europe. Although the notion
of the nation emerged in Europe as being in essence defined along racial,
ethnic, religious and/or linguistic lines, especially as Romantic nationalism, it
also had to engage with the other emergent discourse of the nation – that of a
community of individuals with a common history, common interests, and with
equal and absolute rights and obligations in relation to the state. Most
significantly, this community was conceived of as constituted, in principle, by
equal individuals – or more specifically, of individuals who were in principle
equal before the state. In contrast, in the subcontinent it took shape through
communal identities along religious and caste lines, with community rights
forming the basis of representation in the political system. These communities
were constituted of individuals steeped in unequal relations, both within the
communities and in relation to the state. This is not to imply that inequalities
did not exist in Europe, or even on a lesser scale; they did, but were just
organised differently – only, the difference in question was the monumental one
of colonialism. The permeation of the discourse of rights in the Indian context
was therefore shaped by the necessities and vicissitudes of colonial
confrontations, between communities themselves, as well as between
communities and the colonial state.
The nature of the public-personal dichotomy was thus qualitatively
different in the Indian context, marked not by secularisation and the demands
of liberal capitalism, but by the extension and entrenchment of upper caste,
upper class patriarchies into communal patriarchies. The aim was as much to
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
90
construct and consolidate communal identity as to gradually secure hegemonic
control, through the very process of communal representational politics, over
the public sphere of economic, industrial, bureaucratic and professional
modernisation that was also under way under colonialism – in fact, the first was
perceived as a necessary condition for the second. The efflorescence of religious
reform organisations and caste organisations from the late nineteenth century
onward (see Zavos 2000), laying claim to rights and privileges on behalf of the
communities they allegedly represented, indicates the extent to which the
nationalist discourse in the subcontinent was actually fragmented into multiple
nationalisms. While the mainstream nationalist movement led by the Indian
National Congress (INC) tried hard to at least officially maintain a secular, noncommunal nationalist spirit, in fact its leadership and upper echelons were
overwhelmingly constituted of upper caste Hindus, many of them strongly
traditionalist, and as many openly sympathetic to, if not direct votaries of,
Hindu nationalism. This was the single most important reason for the
formation of the Muslim League as well as of lower caste mobilisations by BR
Ambedkar and others, who felt with some justification that the INC was
democratic only in form, and not in substance (see Vijayan 2012).
The implications of this process are of some significance. In the entire
development of the democratic discourse and its concomitant nationalist
discourses, the issue of rights was a highly charged and fraught one. For
instance, women’s rights to education, property, even life (in the case of upper
caste widows), were bitterly fought over between reformers and traditionalists,
indexing the extent to which individual rights and what were understood as the
cultural rights of the community could become deeply conflictual. However, it
is worth noting that there was no extended industrial capitalist economy as in
Europe (specifically Britain) that was even more exploitative of its female labour
than of males, leading to women mobilising for and demanding their civil and
economic rights (Fox-Genovese 1991; Cockburn 1992). Rather, whatever
reforms were achieved were not only confined to a very small number of upper
caste women, nor in response to women mobilising and demanding their rights
on a large scale, but were undertaken by sections of upper caste patriarchy in
response to perceptions of ‘Hinduism’ as a decadent, corrupted religion that
severely ill-treated its women – in other words, as a sign of the modernisation of
the community. Lower caste claims to basic civil rights too were similarly
bitterly fought over, leading to the famous stand-off between Gandhi and
Ambedkar over separate electorates, which the latter eventually was pressurised
into conceding, in the face of Gandhi’s fast unto death (Aloysius 1999). In both
instances, the cultural paramountcy of the (upper caste male) community was
clearly – and forcefully, even violently – established over the rights and claims
of the (lower caste and/or female) individual – even as this paramountcy was
articulated in the exact same language of rights. Evidently then, the discourse of rights
did not emanate out of this socio-historical dynamic, but was instead
transplanted and ‘translated’ into meeting the specific demands of an intense
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
91
colonial struggle for power. I am not here engaging with the question of the
importance or validity of the discourse of rights (a complex question in itself)
but simply highlighting its peculiar evolutionary path in the subcontinent; in
what follows I will attempt to briefly chart this course of transplantation and its
consequences.
Indian ‘Democracy’: Cultural Contours
After 1947, a major objective of the newly independent nation-state, headed by
Jawaharlal Nehru, was modernisation – not just in industry, technology and the
economy, but in its social and civic life – a cultural modernisation, if you wish,
most evident in the state’s official, emphatic promotion of ‘a scientific temper’
(Chatterjee, 1993 [1986], 131ff). As such, the new state sought to present itself
to the international community as a multi-ethnic, multi-religious and yet
secular nation, a nation whose conceptions of nationality and citizenship did
not depend on religion, language, caste or gender, but one that guaranteed the
rights of all its various citizens on the ‘rational’ basis of the doctrine of universal
and fundamental rights that it had inherited from the British. It was important
to present itself as a nation that would not be torn apart by sub-national and/or
ethnic and/or communal conflicts, because it officially and statutorily
maintained the sovereignty of the principle of universal rights for all its citizens.
This was done through the adoption and implementation of constitutional
electoral democracy, modelled almost wholly after the British Westminster
form. The motive however was not just some form of national vanity, the
ostentatious political announcement of an arriviste to democratic modernity: the
nationalist elite, under the leadership of Jawaharlal Nehru and Vallabhai Patel,
recognised the importance of national unity for development and economic
growth, and Nehru at least genuinely believed that this could be best achieved
through an accommodative and inclusive political system – i.e. through the
adoption of liberal democracy. That is, social and economic modernity could
only be achieved through adopting a modern political system (Khilnani 1997).
However, as we have seen, the chosen system was itself the product of a
particular historical dynamic, which had not – and could never be, in the same
terms – played out in the subcontinent. In its ‘translation’ into the socio-cultural
discourses of the subcontinent, it was consequently consistently marked by a
three-way tension between the sanctity of individual rights and the safeguarding
of community rights, both in relation to the claim to rights of other
communities, however all these were interpreted. This was particularly true of
religious communities, as indexed by the extended controversy over the passage
of the Hindu Code Bill in the 1950s (Sinha 2012); but it was also true of
linguistic communities, as witnessed by the massive and violent controversy
over what was seen as the ‘imposition’ of Hindi as the national language, in the
1950s and early 1960s; and it was again the case with issues of caste and
gender, as with the continuing controversy over reservations for lower castes, in
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
92
governmental, administrative and public sector occupations, and for women in
parliament.
It has been argued that, in a context of widespread and increasingly
disproportionate disparity in the distribution of wealth and resources, the
allocations of and entitlements to the same would necessarily be contested
fiercely, state interventions to even out these disparities (through affirmative
action policies for instance) would necessarily evoke hostility (Hardgrave and
Kochanek 2008, 8-10; Sastry 2009). 5 Whether or not this is the case, the
argument does serve to draw our attention to the fact that in the subcontinent,
the invoking of the principles of democracy by contesting claimants to them,
has been done, not as a consequence of their (assumed or real) violation(s) per
se, but as the redress for (assumed or real) violation(s) of community rights, thus
inexorably drawing the discourse of democracy into a politics of identity, rather
than into the politics of inequality, injustice or oppression. That is, ‘democracy’,
in the case of India, has increasingly come to signify the equality of
communities, rather than individuals, in relation to the state.
Democracy ‘Lost in Translation’?
In one sense, this was perhaps inevitable, given that democratic ideas and
concepts in the subcontinent took hold on a terrain that was already multiethnic, multi-linguistic and multi-religious. In contrast, the discourse of
democratic politics in Europe was deployed to protect and promote the
interests of emergent, and consequently relatively homogeneous middle classes
with more or less common socio-economic interests and concerns. 6 The
nationalist leadership in India had in fact hoped that the democratic process
would help to overcome the problem of heterogeneity, by instituting citizenship
as the national identity over and above other identities – but this was not to be.
This is not to suggest that the discourse of individual civil rights does not exist
or is not operational in the Indian socio-polity, which is therefore completely at
the mercy of communalist discourses: Rajeev Bhargava (2002) has rightly taken
issue with Sunil Khilnani and others for implicitly or explicitly arguing this. But
it is nevertheless true that individual civil rights usually come into force only in
matters of civil and contractual law, and are frequently subverted and/or
subsumed by the processes, if not the claims, of community rights. The case of
Shah Bano is one well-known instance of this (A.M. 2003); but it was
foregrounded most dramatically in the farcical process of investigation and
prosecution that was undertaken by the Gujarat government following the
communal carnage of 2002, when, in case after case, every principle of natural
justice and equality before the law that is fundamental to the democratic
process was openly flouted, in the Hindu nationalist government’s bid to
protect the Hindu perpetrators of the violence against Muslims.7 It illustrated
explicitly the extent to which perceived and alleged community rights may be
openly asserted even when they are patently against constitutional law.
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
93
This is an important point, because it opens out some of the tangled knots
surrounding the issue of democratic rights in the Indian subcontinent. In the
appropriation of the language of rights to entire communities – by treating the
community as the most significant social unit rather than the individual – a
singular and crucial slippage has occurred which persistently obstructs the
democratic process. The electoral process perpetuates and encourages this
treatment, in the campaign methodology of cultivating ‘vote-banks’ or
constituencies by political parties. In this, the issues and concerns of individual
communities, invariably framed in the language of rights, take shape as
affecting them because of who they are, rather than just and rectifiable issues in
their own right: the causes of the wrongs (assumed, alleged or real) became
more important than the wrongs themselves. The matter is complicated by
issues like affirmative action policies which sought, and continue to seek, to
rectify the consequences of centuries of oppression and exploitation (whether
on caste or gender lines) through positive discrimination. This is an apparently
paradoxical application of the doctrine of rights, but only if we assume
universal equality to begin with – which is not, and has never been the case
historically. It is important to note that the doctrine of rights at the heart of the
concept of democracy makes this assumption, which is one of the problems of
its application in contexts with somewhat extreme states of social and economic
disparity. In such contexts, with the advantage of hindsight, it seems almost
inevitable that the historically oppressed and marginalised sections would
appropriate the language of rights as collectives, reinforcing their claims
through the strength of numbers, rather than as individuals. It seems almost
inevitable that political parties would resort to vote-bank politics – in many
instances, in fact, explicitly organise around issues of community identity – in
‘translating’ the discourse of rights to meet perceived community needs, rather
than issues in general.
Further, it is clearly noticeable that this process of community
appropriation of the language of rights is not dependent on which specific
community undertakes the appropriation, but is part of the general ‘translation’
of the discourse of rights into the subcontinent. While community identities,
along with their substantive constituents, grow, change and morph into other
identities over long periods and in different contexts, the process of
appropriation continues irrespective of these changes. The outstanding
example of this is the gradual process of fragmentation of the larger political
parties into smaller, more locally oriented parties, with more clearly defined
constituencies, each using the same language of rights to articulate its individual
agenda. This is particularly true of the seventies, the late eighties and the late
nineties, with the Congress-I regaining lost ground briefly in the intervening
periods. It is evident again in the establishment of coalition politics at the centre
in the eighties, while the constituent parties of the coalition remained locked in
rivalry in the states, thus indicating the extent to which identity politics could be
malleable, even manipulable, in the complex dynamics of representative
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
94
electoral democracy. It is also indicative of the perpetual incompleteness of the
triangular dynamic of identity politics – democracy – nation-state, insofar as the
viability and stability of democracy depends on the equilibrium arrived at
between the autonomy of the state and the rights of the nation (constituted of
these multiple communities and their cultural identities) as well as the rights of
the individual (the abstract subject of the state). To reformulate the triangle
more accurately then, democracy relies on the equilibrium between statecommunity-individual.
However, as noted above, the second of these terms, ‘community’, is shaped by
the communal patriarchate of personal law. This implies that as long as
communities proclaim the supremacy of community rights over universal and
fundamental individual rights, and assert these even in the face of contravening
civil laws, the discourse of rights will remain a fraught, and indeed perilous, one
for democracy. There has long been an awareness of this; there have been
repeated attempts to legislatively prevent it by proposing a uniform civil code,
with which to replace the multiple personal laws that, in some ways, manifest
the country’s heterogeneity in legal terms. This has however never managed
any degree of success so far, partly because of alarmist visions of a uniform civil
code infringing on the rights of individual communities, and partly because it
would undercut the very basis of power of the various communal patriarchies.
Consequently no political party has the will to promote the issue in any serious
way – with the ironical exception of the Hindu nationalist Bharatiya Janata
Party (BJP), which seeks essentially to impose the Hindu civil code as the
uniform civil code of the country. As importantly, the severe economic
inequalities and disparities that mark social relations, within and between
communities, raises serious doubts about the viability of a uniform civil code
functioning as an instrument of democratisation.
The Illusions of Rights-Based ‘Democracy’
By now it should be clear that the discourse of ‘democracy’, at least in
postcolonial India, is founded on the sanctity of (communal rather than
individual) ‘rights’: thus, there are constitutionally guaranteed fundamental
rights, civil rights and democratic rights, which nevertheless can run foul of the
communal rights guaranteed through personal laws. This discourse of
‘democracy’ will be, and is, at its weakest in two seemingly opposite but actually
almost identical scenarios: the first is, when individual communities in a multicommunity nation-state proclaim their customary rights as above and prior to
those constitutionally guaranteed by the nation-state. In this case, the triangle
state-community-individual falls apart because of the complete disavowal (of
the validity) of the discourse of universal rights that is supposed to be
guaranteed by the ‘democratic’ state. 8 The second is, when a particular
communal identity aspires and attempts to represent the nation itself,
narrowing the gap between community identity and national identity,
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
95
proclaiming the (alleged) needs of a specific community as the needs of the
national community, and replacing the discourse of universal rights guaranteed
by the nation-state with the notion of rights – such as they are – enshrined in
that community’s customs and traditions. Such is the case with Hindu
nationalism, which seeks to collapse the triangle of state-community-individual
into the single dimension of the Hindu nation-state.
In a multi-ethnic, multi-religious, multi-lingual context, characterised,
most importantly, by highly levels of economic inequality, the survival of this
kind of ‘rights’-based ‘democracy’ depends on the stability of the triangle noted
above – on the continued maintenance of a tension between the identity of the
state and the multiple identities that constitute its heterogeneity (on the one
hand), as well as with its individual subjects (on the other). In an ideal
democratic socio-polity, this tension would manifest as the ceaseless
negotiations between individuals, community identities and the nation-state
within the terms of the inviolability of fundamental rights and the supremacy of
national civil and democratic rights. In actual practice, it invariably takes form
either as the violent assertion of community rights – of which we have already
listed several instances earlier – or the punitive violence of the state, in its
imposition of what it sees as its right to maintain the law (or sometimes both,
when the state is dominated by the majority community, as happened in
Gujarat in 2002). Evidently then, because this particular conception of
‘democracy’ (which also happens to be the most pervasive and hegemonic
understanding of it), is founded on the principle of ‘equality of rights’, rather
than on say, the principle of the ‘equitable distribution of resources and
opportunities’, it is most vulnerable to collapse when the rights claimed are
equally ‘right’ or legitimate, and equally contested – often violently.
It must be noted, parenthetically, that we are here defining violence as
not just an event attached to a discourse but a discursive event in itself, with
discursive and actual consequences. The implications of such an understanding
of violence are, inevitably, far-reaching, raising questions about the violation of
rights inherent in an exclusivist conception of the nation-state, of citizenship, of
the maintenance of national borders, consequently of the legitimacy of armed
forces, and of the earlier-mentioned right of the state to perpetrate violence,
and so on – but this is not the space to go into a detailed discussion of these
issues. In what follows therefore, I will merely indicate some of the directions in
which these arguments will lead us.
Let us return now to the point we had noted earlier in the paper – that
historically democracy appears to perpetuate violence rather than end it. It is
clear that within the contradictory logics of the nation-state – as being a right
that can be claimed, as well as being itself a claimant of rights; and as being
simultaneously inclusive and exclusive – the dynamic of democracy will always
be a limited and fraught one. The nation-state as the site of the playing out of
identities is always vulnerable to being appropriated by any one or more of
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
96
those identities, and consequently of becoming ipso facto a claimant to the
discourse of rights. It is when the state thus appropriates the discourse of rights
and functions as an actor within the dynamic of democracy – when the state
claims rights of an equal or superior order to those of its subjects – that its
‘democratic’ credentials begin to implode. The question here is not whether the
state as a political entity should not or cannot claim (or have) rights, but
whether ‘democracy’ as a practice should, or even can, be viably founded on a
discourse of ‘rights’. As we have seen, when it is, it is immediately rendered
vulnerable to its own ironies and contradictions, becomes prey to its own
principle of inclusion/ exclusion, and hence unleashes the very violence that it
is supposed to keep in check.
Conclusion
There are issues that arise out of the preceding arguments that, for reasons of
space, I have left untouched, to be addressed in future work. For instance, in
the scenario of multiplying identities as a possible strengthening of democracy
that I have noted above, the very important question arises of the relation
between this process of multiplication and market forces that encourage
multiplicity as essential to (consumer) choice: rather than enable democracy,
would not such a process then render it even more subservient to the market by
encouraging the commoditisation of identity, thereby initiating a fresh process
of social, political and economic disparity? There is no easy answer, partly
because it is a question addressed to a hypothetical situation; but hypothetically
speaking then, an intensification of identity politics is also likely to result in an
increase in alliance politics, intra- and inter-nationally – and evidence of the
latter is already increasing globally, in the formation of political blocs centred
around economic interests: the European Union, ASEAN, SAARC, the G-8,
even the World Social Forum, etc. Likely, even this identity politics will then
become more and more defined by the economic interests fundamental to those
identities, than by issues of, for instance, communal grievance. But these can
only be tentative speculative remarks on what is essentially a project in itself.
What is clear is that the idea of the nation-state – which is the dominant
form of the state today – as an entity designed to cater to the needs, rights and
privileges of a specific people, exclusively, is an idea that is no longer consonant
with the principles of democracy (however understood) – if it ever was. Ideally,
the state should only serve as the facilitator and executor of the democratic
discourse, and not become yet another claimant of rights within (or without) its
terms. But the strength of the Weberian thesis – that the state is defined by its
monopoly on legitimate force – indicates the extent to which we tacitly grant
the state the right to perpetrate violence, as if (a) because it is perpetrated by the
state it is automatically legitimate (which in one sense it is, because the
legitimacy or illegitimacy of any violence is ultimately decided by the state); and
(b) the state and the nation are separate entities, with the state imagined as the
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
97
agent authorised to preside over the nation. In actual fact, of course, the state is
neither separate from the nation, nor does it possess a subjectivity and agency
that is autonomous of the nation. In actual fact, the state is no more than the
institutional technology – the apparatus, in Althusser’s words (Althusser 1984
[1971]) – through which (national) power is exercised by the dominant
community of the nation. And since the dominant community of the nation is,
as we have seen, drawn and defined by its patriarchate, the exercise of power as
‘legitimate force’ by the state is, in effect, no more than the legitimation of the
violences committed by that patriarchate (Gabriel & Vijayan 2012, 304). To rephrase an old Marxian prophecy then, true democracy will arrive not with the
withering away of the state, but with the disintegration of the (patriarchal
cultures of violence of the) nation.
Notes
Karl von Holdt (2014) has attempted a similar examination of the relationship between
democracy and violence in the South African context, and offered a theory of ‘violent
democracy’ as a way to understand how democracies work in contexts of deep inequality
and ethnic strife. My arguments below have some points of agreement with his, but move in
a different direction, as will shortly become evident.
2 This would of course apply to all states, not just ‘democratic’ ones; but the fact that it applies
to ‘democratic’ states too does not detract from the implication that ‘democracy’ and
violence are antithetical. It only implies that violence is antithetical to other forms of
governance too, besides the ‘democratic.’
3 While women’s rights were already being sought and contested for by early activists like
Mary Wollstonecraft, the subject of the state as the possessor of rights was to remain of
masculine gender and upper class origin, by law and convention, till the late nineteenth
century.
4 This can be obtained in the currently hegemonic understanding of ‘democracy’ articulated
in a document like the Inter-Parliamentary Union's Democracy: Its Principles and Achievements
(Union, 1998)
5 See Rudolp and Rudolph (1987), Corbridge and Harris (2000), Pavan Verma (2002), for
different perspectives on this argument.
6 See Barro (1999). It is also of considerable interest that we may be witnessing a reverse flow
of the impact of multi-cultural contexts on the operations of democracy, in the growing
tendency toward identity politics in Western societies – but this is not the space to elaborate
on that.
7 There are many other examples of such privileging of community rights over the law of the
land: the defensive outrage of upper caste Hindus in support of sati (widow self-immolation
on the husband’s pyre) cases like that of Roop Kanwar, in 1988; the repeated and
widespread attack on couples celebrating Valentine’s day; the regular demand for dress
codes for women in colleges and universities; attacks on Dalit villages and villagers perceived
to be challenging upper caste dominance or customs; and most tellingly, upper caste
mobilisation against reservations for lower castes under the banner, ‘Youth for Equality’.
8 This is best illustrated by the versions of Islamic orthodoxy that succeeded in overturning the
Supreme Court ruling on Shah Bano’s entitlements to maintenance. For a discussion of this
and other cases, see Zoya Hassan (1994).
1
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
98
Works Cited
Althusser, Louis. [1971] 1984. “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses.”
In Essays on Ideology, 1-60. London: Verso.
A.M. 2003. “The Shah Bano Legacy”. The Hindu, Op-Ed, August10.
http://www.thehindu.com/thehindu/2003/08/10/stories/2003081000
221500.htm
Aloysius, G. 1999. Nationalism without a Nation in India. Delhi: OUP.
Barro, Robert J. 1999. “Determinants of Democracy.” Journal of Political
Economy 107(S6): 158-183.
Bhargava Rajeev. 2002. “Liberal, Secular Democracy and Explanations of
Hindu Nationalism.” Commonwealth and Comparative Politics 40 (3): 72-96.
Chatterjee, Partha. [1986] 1993. Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A
Derivative Discourse? London: Zed Books.
Cockburn, Cynthia. 1992. “Technology, Production and Power.” In Inventing
Women: Science, Technology and Gender, edited by Gill Kirkup and Laurie
Smith. Milton Keynes: Polity Press.
Corbridge, Stuart and John Harris. 2000. Reinventing India. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Dumont, L. Homo Hierarchicus. 1970. Chicago, Chicago University Press.
Fox-Genovese, E. 1991. Feminism Without Illusions: A Critique of Individualism.
Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Gabriel, Karen and P K Vijayan. 2012. “Orientalism, Terrorism and Bombay
Cinema.” Journal of Postcolonial Writing 48(3): 299-310.
Guha, Ranajit. 1989. “Dominance without Hegemony and its Historiography”.
In Subaltern Studies VI, edited by Ranajit Guha, 210-309. Delhi: OUP.
Hardgrave, Robert and Stanley Kochanek. [2000] 2008. India: Government and
Politics in a Developing Nation. Boston: Thomson Wadsworth
Hassan, Zoya (Ed.). 1994. Forging Identities: Gender, Communities and the State in
India. New Delhi: Kali for Women.
Heesterman, J. C. 1985. The Inner Conflict of Tradition: Essays in Indian Ritual,
Kinship, and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Horwitz, Morton, J. 1982. “History of the Public/Private Distinction.”
University of Pennsylvania Law Review 130: 1423–1428.
Jha, Saumitra. 2012. “Financial Innovations and Political Development:
Evidence
from
Revolutionary
England.
http://economics.mit.edu/files/9676
Kaviraj, S. (Ed.). 1999. Politics in India. Oxford in India Readings in Sociology and
Social Anthropology. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Keane, John. 2004. Violence and Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Khilnani, S. 1997. The Idea of India. London: Hamish Hamilton.
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium
PREM KUMAR VIJAYAN
99
MacPherson, CB. 1962. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to
Locke, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mani, Lata. 1987. “Contentious Traditions: The Debate on Sati in Colonial
India,” Cultural Critique 7 (Autumn): 119-156
Newbigin, Eleanor. 2009. “The codification of personal law and secular
citizenship: Revisiting the history of law reform in late colonial India.”
The Indian Economic and Social History Review 46(1): 83–104. New Delhi:
SAGE.
Rudolph, L.I. and S.H. Rudolph. 1987. In Pursuit of Lakshmi: The Political
Economy of the Indian State. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Sastry, Mukul. 2009. “Reservation Policy in India: A Critical Evaluation.”
SSRN Electronic Journal. http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1406222
Schwartzmantel, John. 2010. “Democracy and violence: a theoretical
Overview”. Democratization 17(2): 217-234.
Sinha, Chitra. 2012. Debating Patriarchy: The Hindu Code Bill Controversy in India
(1941–1956). New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Taylor, Charles. 1993. “Modernity and the Rise of the Public Sphere.” In The
Tanner Lectures on Human Values, 14, edited by G. B. Peterson, 203-260.
Salt
Lake
City:
University
of
Utah.
https://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/t/Taylor93.pdf
Union, Inter-Parliamentary (Ed.). 1998. Democracy: Its Principles and Achievements.
Geneva:
Inter-Parliamentary
Union.
http://archive.ipu.org/PDF/publications/DEMOCRACY_PR_E.pdf
Varma, P.K. 2007. The Great Indian Middle Class. New Delhi: Penguin.
Vijayan, P.K. 2012. Making the Pitrubhumi: Manhood and the Hindu Nation. ISS PhD
Theses.
Erasmus
University
Rotterdam.
http://hdl.handle.net/1765/32246
von Holdt, Karl. 2014. “On Violent Democracy.” The Sociological Review 62(S2):
129–151.
Zavos, John. 2000. The Emergence of Hindu Nationalism in India. London: SAGE.
Kairos: A Journal of Critical Symposium