New York County Clerk’s Index Nos. 162358/15 and 150149/16
Court of Appeals
STATE OF NEW YORK
>>>>
IN
RE
NONHUMAN RIGHTS PROJECT, INC.,
ON BEHALF OF TOMMY,
Petitioner-Appellant,
against
PATRICK C. LAVERY, individually and as an officer of
Circle L Trailer Sales, Inc., DIANE LAVERY,
and CIRCLE L TRAILER SALES, INC.,
Respondents-Respondents.
(Additional Caption on the Reverse)
PROPOSED BRIEF BY AMICI CURIAE PHILOSOPHERS
IN SUPPORT OF THE PETITIONER-APPELLANT
MARY JEAN MEZZINA, ESQ.
3434 Milburn Avenue
Baldwin, New York 11510
516-319-9239
Date Completed: February 23, 2018
Attorney for Amici Curiae Philosophers
Kristin Andrews (York University);
Gary Comstock (North Carolina State
University); G.K.D. Crozier (Laurentian
University); Sue Donaldson (Queen’s
University); Andrew Fenton (Dalhousie
University); Tyler M. John (Rutgers
University); L. Syd M Johnson (Michigan
Technological University); Robert Jones
(California State University, Chico); Will
Kymlicka (Queen’s University); Letitia
Meynell (Dalhousie University); Nathan
Nobis (Morehouse College); David PeñaGuzmán (California State University, San
Francisco); James Rocha (California State
University, Fresno); Bernard Rollin
(Colorado State); Jeffrey Sebo (New York
University); Adam Shriver (University of
British Columbia); Rebecca L. Walker (University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill)
IN
RE
NONHUMAN RIGHTS PROJECT, INC.,
ON BEHALF OF K IKO ,
Petitioner-Appellant.
against
CARMEN PRESTI, individually and as officer and director of The Primate
Sanctuary, Inc., CHRISTIE E. PRESTI, individually and as an officer and
director of The Primate Sanctuary, Inc., and THE PRIMATE SANCTUARY, INC.
Respondents.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Page
Table of Authorities ...................................................................................iii
I.
Interest of the Amici Curiae................................................................ 1
II. Summary of the Argument.................................................................. 2
1. Species Membership ...................................................................... 4
2. Social Contract ............................................................................... 5
3. Community Membership ............................................................... 5
4. Capacities ....................................................................................... 6
III. Argument ............................................................................................ 6
1.
Species Membership ...................................................................... 6
1.1 Species as a biological category ............................................... 8
1.2 The ‘Species Problem’ ............................................................. 10
1.3 Implications for human nature.............................................. 11
1.4 Conclusions regarding Species Membership......................... 13
2. A Social Contract Conception ...................................................... 14
2.1 Not all rights depend on the existence of a social
contract ................................................................................... 14
2.2 The social contract does not produce ‘persons’...................... 17
2.3 Personhood is not conditional on bearing duties
and responsibilities ................................................................ 19
2.4 Conclusions regarding the Social Contract ........................... 20
i
3. A Community Membership Conception ...................................... 21
3.1 The Wide view ........................................................................ 22
3.2 The Narrow view .................................................................... 25
3.3 Conclusions regarding Community Membership ................. 27
4. A Capacities Conception .............................................................. 28
4.1 Conditions of personhood ....................................................... 28
4.2 Personhood and autonomy ..................................................... 31
4.3 Why chimpanzee autonomy matters ..................................... 33
4.4 Conclusions regarding Capacities ......................................... 35
IV. Conclusion ......................................................................................... 36
ii
TABLE OF AUTHORITIES
Page(s)
Cases
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574) ................................................................. 1, 21
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574) ....................................................................... 3
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574) ....................................................................... 7
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574) ....................................................................... 7
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574) ..................................................................... 19
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574) ..................................................................... 22
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc v. Presti
(2015 NY Slip Op 00085) ..................................................................... 33
Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc v Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574) ....................................................................... 4
People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2014 NY Slip Op 08531) ..................................................................... 14
People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2014 NY Slip Op 08531) ..................................................................... 15
People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2014 NY Slip Op 08531) ..................................................................... 19
People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2014 NY Slip Op 08531) ..................................................................... 19
iii
Other Authorities
Rousseau 1762, Book 1, Chapter 1 .......................................................... 16
iv
New York County Clerk’s Index Nos. 162358/15; 150149/16
Court of Appeals
STATE OF NEW YORK
THE NONHUMAN RIGHTS PROJECT, INC., ON
BEHALF OF TOMMY,
THE NONHUMAN RIGHTS PROJECT, INC., ON
BEHALF OF KIKO,
Petitioner-Appellant,
—against—
PATRICK C. LAVERY, INDIVIDUALLY AND AS AN OFFICER
OF CIRCLE L TRAILER SALES, INC., DIANE LAVERY, AND
CIRCLE L TRAILER SALES, INC.,
CARMEN PRESTI, INDIVIDUALLY AND AS AN
OFFICER AND DIRECTOR OF THE PRIMATE SANCTUARY, INC.,
CHRISTIE E. PRESTI, INDIVIDUALLY AND AS AN OFFICER AND
DIRECTOR OF THE PRIMATE SANCTUARY, INC., AND
THE PRIMATE SANCTUARY, INC.,
Respondents-Respondents.
BRIEF OF AMICI CURIAE PHILOSOPHERS1 IN SUPPORT OF
PETITIONER-APPELLANT
Kristin Andrews (York University); Gary Comstock (North Carolina State
University); G.K.D. Crozier (Laurentian University); Sue Donaldson (Queen’s
University); Andrew Fenton (Dalhousie University); Tyler M. John (Rutgers
University); L. Syd M Johnson (Michigan Technological University); Robert Jones
(California State University, Chico); Will Kymlicka (Queen’s University); Letitia
Meynell (Dalhousie University); Nathan Nobis (Morehouse College); David PeñaGuzmán (California State University, San Francisco); James Rocha (California
State University, Fresno); Bernard Rollin (Colorado State); Jeffrey Sebo (New York
University); Adam Shriver (University of British Columbia); Rebecca L. Walker
(University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill).
1
I.
Interest of the Amici Curiae
We the undersigned submit this brief as philosophers with
expertise in animal ethics, animal political theory, the philosophy of
animal cognition and behavior, and the philosophy of biology in support
of the Nonhuman Rights Project’s efforts to secure habeas corpus relief
for the chimpanzees Kiko and Tommy.2 The Appellate Division, First
Department's ruling in Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v.
Lavery (2017 NY Slip Op 04574), declining to issue an order to show
cause seeking habeas corpus relief and their transfer to a primate
sanctuary, uses a number of incompatible conceptions of person which,
when properly understood, are either philosophically inadequate or in
fact compatible with Kiko and Tommy's personhood. The undersigned
have long-standing active interests in our duties to other animals and
reject arbitrary distinctions used to (rightly) protect humans while
denying adequate protections for other animals given their relevantly
similar vulnerabilities to harms and relevantly similar interests in
avoiding such harms. We submit this brief in our shared interest in
ensuring a more just co-existence with other animals who live in our
2
The authors thank Andrew Lopez for his invaluable research assistance.
1
communities. We strongly urge this Court, in keeping with the best
philosophical standards of rational judgment and ethical standards of
justice, to recognize that, as nonhuman persons, Kiko and Tommy
should be granted a writ of habeas corpus and their detainers should
have the burden of showing the lawful justification of their current
confinement.
II.
Summary of the Argument
The Nonhuman Rights Project (NhRP) is pursuing common law
writs of habeas corpus that challenge the lawfulness of the captivity of
chimpanzees Kiko and Tommy. As recently noted by the First
Department of the Appellate Division of the New York Supreme Court,
the NhRP’s goal is
to change the common-law status of at least some nonhuman
animals from mere ‘things,’ which lack the capacity to
possess any legal rights, to ‘persons,’ who possess such
fundamental rights as bodily integrity and bodily liberty,
and those other legal rights to which evolving standards of
morality, scientific discovery and human experience entitle
2
them (Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574)).
To date, the courts have decided against the NhRP, although
without fully addressing whether Kiko and Tommy are the sorts of
beings who can enjoy habeas corpus relief. As noted by the First
Department, the central issue is whether the concept of ‘personhood’
applies to chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). In denying writs of habeas
corpus for Kiko and Tommy the court does not contest the scientific
evidence of chimpanzee agential and psychological capacities that has
been presented by NhRP, nor the facts of the cases. They maintain,
rather, that the concept of ‘personhood’ cannot refer to nonhuman
beings.
We write as a diverse group of philosophers who share the
conviction that if the concept of ‘personhood’ is being employed by the
courts to determine whether to extend or deny the writs of habeas
corpus, they should employ a consistent and reasonable definition of
‘personhood’ and ‘persons.’ We believe that the previous judgements
offered by the Third, Fourth, and First Departments of the Appellate
3
Division of the New York Supreme Court applied inconsistent
definitions of ‘personhood.’
In this brief, we argue that there is a diversity of ways in which
humans (Homo sapiens) are ‘persons’ and there are no non-arbitrary
conceptions of ‘personhood’ that can include all humans and exclude all
nonhuman animals. To do so we describe and assess the four most
prominent conceptions of ‘personhood’ that can be found in the rulings
concerning Kiko and Tommy, with particular focus on the most recent
decision, Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc v Lavery (2017 NY Slip Op
04574):
1. Species Membership. This conception is arbitrary because it
picks out one level of biological taxonomic classification, Homo
sapiens, and confers moral worth and legal status on its
members. Various attempts in the literature to justify this
approach are self-defeating because they demonstrate that the
criteria defending the choice of a specific biological group are
actually doing the moral work, and these criteria invariably
leave out some humans or include some nonhuman animals.
This is because our species, like every other, is the product of
4
gradual evolutionary processes that create an array of
similarities between species and an array of differences within
them.
2. Social Contract. This conception has been misconstrued by
previous Courts as endowing personhood on contractors;
instead, social contracts make citizens out of persons. The
exclusion of an individual (or species) from the contract does
not strip that individual (or species) of personhood.
3. Community Membership. This conception rests on the idea
that personhood has a social dimension and is importantly
linked to membership in the human community. On a Wide
view, to be a person is to be embedded in social relationships of
interdependency, meaning, and community. Kiko and Tommy
clearly meet this criterion: we have made them a part of our
human community of persons. On a Narrow view, to be a
person requires not just social embedding, but also the
possession of certain psychological capacities, such as beliefs,
desires, emotions, rationality and autonomy. Again, these
5
capacities are reasonably ascribed to Kiko and Tommy. On
either view, they are members of our community.
4. Capacities. This conception, which is endorsed by the NhRP,
maintains that personhood rests on having certain capacities.
Autonomy is typically considered a capacity sufficient (though
not
necessary)
for
personhood.
Violations
of
autonomy
constitute a serious harm. The affidavits from primatologists
support our view that chimpanzees are autonomous beings,
entailing that Kiko and Tommy are persons.
Each of these different conceptions supports different reasoning
regarding personhood. The first, species membership, is morally weak
due to its arbitrary character. The other three, when properly
understood, entail that Kiko and Tommy can qualify as persons. On
these grounds we agree with the NhRP that it is unjust to deny Kiko
and Tommy habeas corpus relief.
III.
Argument
1.
Species Membership
The First Department offers a Species Membership argument for
denying the NhRP’s claim that Kiko and Tommy are entitled to habeas
6
relief when it argues that, while infants or comatose persons have legal
rights despite their inability to bear social and legal duties or
responsibilities, they are nonetheless “human beings, members of the
human community” (Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery
(2017 NY Slip Op 04574)). Further, the First Department argues that in
decisions under which nonhumans, such as corporations, have been
treated as ‘persons,’ the “laws are referenced to humans or individuals
in a human community” (Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v.
Lavery (2017 NY Slip Op 04574)). Thus, the First Department argues
that all and only members of the human species are recognized as
persons by the law, and exceptions can be justified solely on the basis of
some unspecified relation to members of that species.
In their appeal to species membership, the First Department is
using a biological classification to determine the proper scope of legal
rights and protections. Historically, U.S. law, and in particular the
ascription of rights and privileges, has been informed by biological
theories. The biological traits and classifications that have been
considered legally salient have changed significantly over time (e.g.,
race or sex), keeping pace with both scientific and moral progress, and
7
correcting some of the egregious errors of earlier scientific theories and
political regimes.
We endorse the idea that the biological sciences must inform legal
practice, but we maintain that species membership alone cannot
rationally be used to determine who is a person or a rights holder. The
concept of ‘personhood,’ with all its moral and legal weight, is not a
biological concept and cannot be meaningfully derived from the
biological category Homo sapiens. Moreover, species are not ‘natural
kinds’ with distinct essences; therefore, there is no method for
determining an underlying, biologically robust, and universal ‘human
nature’ upon which moral and legal rights can be thought to rest. Any
attempt to specify the essential features of ‘human nature’ either leaves
out a considerable number of humans—often the most vulnerable in our
society—or includes members of other species.
1.1 Species as a biological category
Species is only one level of biological classification that reflects
what is sometimes called the ‘Tree of Life.’ While chimpanzees (Pan
troglodytes) and humans (Homo sapiens) are different species and have
been placed in different genera (Homo and Pan, respectively), they
8
belong to the same family, Hominidae, and so share every level of
classification above (order, Primates; class, Mammalia; etc.). The basic
form of this system of classification was introduced by Carl Linnaeus in
1735. His system helped to bring order to the descriptive work of early
modern biologists who were endeavoring to discover and specify the
essential characteristics that made each organism a member of its kind.
The great insight of Charles Darwin (more than 100 years after
Linnaeus) was that the differences between species did not reflect the
existence of essential characteristics, but instead were the product of a
gradual process of natural selection. Darwin (1859) emphasized the
diversity of organic populations, due to a slow accumulation of changes
producing distinct varieties within a population and eventually new
species.
The gradualism of evolution suggests there are no species
essences, no set of properties both necessary and jointly sufficient for an
organism to be a member of a particular species. In other words, species
are not natural kinds, at least as natural kinds are commonly
understood. There are three central reasons for this:
9
1.
There is a great deal of similarity across species because all
organisms on the planet are more or less closely related to each
other; it is often the case that the more closely two species are
related, the more similar they tend to be.
2.
There tends to be a substantial degree of natural variation
among organisms within a particular species—a feature of
populations ‘exploited’ by natural selection.
3. Species change over time—they evolve—so even if all members
of a species shared some characteristic at one time, this would
probably not be true of all their descendants, and was definitely
not true of all their ancestors.
1.2 The ‘Species Problem’
These facts about the process of evolution and the character of
living organisms create a fundamental problem for scientists studying
the classification of organisms, referred to as the ‘Species Problem.’
Although evolutionary theory facilitates the grouping aspect of
classification, offering a principled criterion for grouping organisms
together—shared ancestry—it offers no clear criteria for the level at
which to rank them. Whether an ancestral grouping should be
10
considered a variety, subspecies, species, superspecies, subgenus, or
genus can be an open question. While, among sexual species,
interbreeding has often been used to define the boundaries of species
groups, this is controversial and leads to its own set of problems and
counterexamples (e.g., Neanderthals and our own species).
When understood as a biological classification, it is difficult to see
why species, or indeed any other taxonomic category, should bear any
moral weight. Certainly, there are capacities or relationships that may
typically be shared by the members of a particular species that are
morally relevant (as we discuss in Section 4), but then it is the
capacities that are doing the ethical work—not species. Species
membership is at best a heuristic that aids a superficial assessment of
moral status.
1.3 Implications for human nature
The use of the term ‘human nature’ typically implies the existence
of a core essence universally shared by all and only human beings;
however, the biological category Homo sapiens cannot offer a
sufficiently stable or consistent foundation for ‘human nature’ (Hull
1986).
11
The significant similarity between humans and our closest living
relatives might be difficult to see because our evolutionary proximity
has often been overlooked. In fact, chimpanzees are about as closely
related to humans as African elephants are to Indian elephants
(Langergraber et al. 2010; Rohland et al. 2010). This suggests that a
kind of prejudice might be responsible for our tendency to perceive our
species as radically distinct from others in the animal kingdom. Indeed,
a number of theorists (e.g., Diamond 1993, p. 97; Goodman et al. 1998;
Wildman et al. 2003) have argued that chimpanzees and bonobos (Pan
paniscus) ought to be reclassified, alongside humans, in the genus
Homo. This thought is not new; in the 18th century, Linnaeus wrote to
a colleague that his reasons for placing ‘Man’ in a distinct genus had
more to do with placating theologians than with the principles of
natural history (Frängsmyr et al. 1983, 172).
Using species membership to determine who has legal status
requires a justification of why species membership should be preferred
over genus membership, which we share with Neanderthals and other
hominins,
or
over
family
membership,
which
we
share
with
chimpanzees and the other great apes. After all, the lesson of
12
Darwinism is that there are no hard and fast distinctions among any of
the categories in the Tree of Life, but only a nested organizational
hierarchy.
1.4 Conclusions regarding Species Membership
Efforts to identify a set of diagnostic traits both universal and
unique to Homo sapiens invariably fail. Either they leave out some
humans, or they include members of other species. Using the biological
category Homo sapiens to define ‘personhood’ and to determine who has
legal status is arbitrary and makes little sense given what we know of
evolutionary processes and our evolutionary history.
The NhRP seeks to have Kiko and Tommy classified as persons
based on the capacities they share with other persons. If persons are
defined as ‘beings who possess certain capacities,’ and humans usually
possess those capacities, then being human can be used to predict with
a degree of accuracy that a particular individual will also have those
capacities, and be a person. But it is an arbitrary decision to include
species membership alone as a condition of personhood, and it fails to
satisfy a basic requirement of justice: that we treat like cases alike. It
13
picks out a single characteristic as the one that confers rights, without
providing any reason for thinking it has any relevance to rights.
2.
A Social Contract Conception
The Third Department, citing Cupp, argues that “Reciprocity
between rights and responsibilities stems from principles of social
contract, which inspired the ideals of freedom and democracy at the core
of the US system of government. Under this view, society extends rights
in exchange for an express or implied agreement from its members to
submit to social responsibilities. In other words, ‘rights [are] connected
to moral agency and the ability to accept societal responsibility in
exchange for [those] rights’” (People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project,
Inc. v. Lavery (2014 NY Slip Op 08531)).
The influential social contract theories that emerged in Europe in
the 17th and 18th centuries, and which inspired the language and
ideals found in the US Constitution, would disagree for at least three
reasons. These reasons are: (1) not all rights depend on the existence of
a social contract, (2) the social contract does not produce ‘persons,’ and
(3) personhood is not conditional on bearing duties and responsibilities.
2.1 Not all rights depend on the existence of a social
contract
14
Among the most influential of social contract philosophers are
Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who
maintain that all persons have ‘natural rights’ that they possess
independently of their willingness or ability to take on social
responsibilities (Hobbes 1651; Locke 1689, 1698; Rousseau 1762). These
rights, which we possess in the state of nature, include the right to
absolute freedom and liberty. Upon contracting with our fellows, we do
not become ‘persons’, but rather ‘citizens’; and we do not suddenly
acquire rights, but rather give up our natural rights, sometimes in
exchange for civil and legal rights.
The Third Department, citing Cupp, appears to advance an
argument that persons are those who have rights by virtue of their
capacity to bear responsibilities. They acquire those responsibilities the
moment they assent to an “express or implied” (People ex rel.
Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (2014 NY Slip Op 08531))
social contract. The social contract, according to this line of thought, is
the mechanism whereby persons take up societal duties and
responsibilities, receiving rights in exchange. But this is not how
political philosophers have understood the meaning of the social
15
contract historically or in contemporary times. In effect, the Third
Department, and in turn the First Department, has it backwards.
Rousseau explicitly rejected the idea that the social contract gives
rights to persons, proclaiming, “Man is born free, and everywhere he is
in chains” (Rousseau 1762, Book 1, Chapter 1). These chains, for
Rousseau, are self-imposed, forged by ourselves, when we give up our
natural rights and freedoms and place ourselves under the authority of
another. The social contract ‘chains’ us. We find a similar argument in
Hobbes. What we acquire with a social contract, according to Hobbes,
are law and morality, not rights. In fact, in the act of creating a social
contract, we give up nearly all of our rights, save one: the right to life.
And what we receive in exchange for giving up all these rights are not
new rights, but rather security in the form of the protection of the
sovereign.
Locke believed that we form societies to protect the institution of
private property. We make a compact to leave the state of nature and
form a society because we have a shared interest in protecting our
property, including our own bodies. In this transition from the state of
nature to the state of civil society, we gain some valuable things,
16
including laws, the executive power needed to enforce the laws, and
judges to adjudicate property disputes. But we lose our previously held
rights, including the right to protect ourselves by any means necessary
and punish those who transgress against our property.
We ought not understand the social contract, therefore, in terms of
the acquisition of rights, per se. Rather, we should think about it in
terms of the acquisition of a single duty: to obey the law.
2.2 The social contract does not produce ‘persons’
In the philosophies of Hobbes and Rousseau, with the advent of
the social contract we see the creation of an ‘artificial man’ (the
sovereign or Leviathan), not a ‘person.’ This artificial man is an
abstraction since no real person could be literally composed of the rights
and powers of others. Rousseau describes this ‘new person’ as a
collective created only by a truly democratic social contract. Locke
describes a ‘body politic’ to which contractors submit. The sole person
created by the social contract, while important, is a mere abstraction,
and by no interpretation an actual person.
The upshot of this is that social contracts create citizens, not
persons. Citizens are individuals who are subject to the laws authorized
17
by the contract. Notably, the U.S. Constitution mentions the term
‘persons’ fifty-seven times, but does not define it. The 14th Amendment,
however, distinguishes between persons and citizens. This is consistent
with social contract theory, which holds that only persons can bind
themselves through a contract and, in so doing, become citizens. While
persons do not depend on a social contract, the social contract depends
on persons who will be its ‘signatories.’
It follows from social contract theory that all contractors must be
persons, but not that all persons must necessarily be contractors. There
can be persons who are not contractors—either because they choose not
to contract (e.g., adults who opt for life in the state of nature) or because
they cannot contract (e.g., infants and some individuals with cognitive
disabilities).
Social contract philosophers have never claimed—not now, not in
the 17th century—that the social contract can endow personhood on any
being. The contract can only endow citizenship on persons who exist
prior to the contract and agree to it. If persons did not exist before the
contract, there would be no contract at all since only persons can
18
contract.
Personhood,
therefore,
must
be
presupposed
as
a
characteristic of contractors in social contract theories.
2.3 Personhood is not conditional on bearing duties
and responsibilities
The First Department, citing Cupp, claims that “nonhumans lack
sufficient responsibility to have any legal standing” (Matter of
Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (2017 NY Slip Op 04574)). The
Third Department has also argued that chimpanzees, unlike human
beings, “cannot bear any legal duties, submit to societal responsibilities
or be held legally accountable for their actions” (People ex rel.
Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (2014 NY Slip Op 08531)), and
thus cannot have legal rights. Further, citing Gray, it is stated that “the
legal meaning of a ‘person’ is ‘a subject of legal rights and duties’”
(People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (2014 NY Slip
Op 08531)).
In contrast, the NhRP has argued that an entity is a ‘person’ if she
can bear rights or responsibilities. The reason for this broader
understanding of ‘person’ is that not all persons can be held accountable
for their actions and bear societal duties. Infants, children, and those
19
found not guilty by reason of insanity cannot be held accountable and
cannot bear legal or societal duties. They are, nonetheless, persons.
The writ of habeas corpus challenges the status of ‘things’
currently ascribed to Kiko and Tommy. At issue in the cases of Kiko and
Tommy is not whether they can bear legal duties or be held legally
accountable for their actions, but rather whether they are persons and
have legal rights. Among individuals, only those who are persons can
have legal duties and responsibilities. Non-persons cannot. But the
personhood of chimpanzees cannot be conditional on bearing legal
duties and responsibilities, because being legally recognized as a person
is
and
must
be
logically
prior
to
bearing
legal
duties
and
responsibilities.
2.4 Conclusions regarding the Social Contract
While
legal
duties,
legal
accountability,
and
societal
responsibilities are acquired by citizens under social contracts, neither
the status of citizenship nor personhood depend on the ability to bear
those
duties
and
responsibilities.
Many
humans
who
are
uncontroversially legally recognized as persons and citizens cannot bear
those duties and responsibilities and cannot be held legally accountable
20
for their actions. Therefore, whether or not Kiko and Tommy can bear
legal duties and responsibilities, or be held legally accountable, is
irrelevant to their legal status as persons. Secondly, social contracts do
not create the rights associated with personhood. In agreeing to a social
contract, we give up our natural rights in exchange for other societal
benefits. Finally, social contract philosophers have consistently
maintained that social contracts do not make us persons, but rather
create citizens out of existing persons. Social Contract theory, therefore,
cannot and does not rule out the personhood of Kiko and Tommy.
3.
A Community Membership Conception
As already mentioned, the First Department in Lavery held that
the ability to acknowledge legal duties and responsibilities is required
for personhood, and entitlement to habeas relief. In response, NhRP
argued that this cannot be the right standard for personhood, since it
would imply that humans who cannot acknowledge such duties and
responsibilities, such as infants and comatose individuals, are not
persons. In addition to presenting a species conception of persons, the
First Department addressed this objection by asserting that such
21
individuals are members of “the human community” (Matter of
Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (2017 NY Slip Op 04574)).
One interpretation of ‘human community’ puts the exclusive
emphasis on ‘human,’ understood as a biological category, so that
‘human community’ is a synonym for ‘members of the species Homo
sapiens.’ This interpretation collapses into the species membership view
addressed in Section 1. A second interpretation puts the emphasis on
‘community,’ referring to membership in a community of which humans
are members. On this view, personhood is not grounded in discrete
traits or capacities of individuals; rather, personhood is something that
we achieve through development and recognition within a community of
persons. In Ubuntu philosophy, this is captured in the saying “a person
is a person through other people” (Eze, 2010, 190).
There are different ways of interpreting the idea of membership in
a community of persons. We discuss two such views below—which we
call Wide and Narrow—and show that on both of them, Kiko and
Tommy should be seen as members of a community of persons.
3.1 The Wide view
22
According to the Wide view, someone is a member of a community
of persons because they are embedded in interpersonal webs of
interdependency, trust, communication, and normative responsiveness
(i.e., our behavior is informed by various norms). Persons do not exist as
independent islands, floating free of each other.
On this view, children and individuals with cognitive disabilities
are clearly persons even if they cannot enter into contracts or bear
certain legal responsibilities. The fact that they have guardians for
certain legal purposes, far from disqualifying them from personhood,
confirms that they are members of these webs of social connection. We
all are dependent on others at some points in our lives, and
interdependent at all times. Infants depend on their parents and
caretakers to feed them, teach them a language, and help them to see
the world from others’ perspectives. Adolescents and some individuals
with cognitive disabilities may not have all of the capacities of mature,
developmentally typical adults, and may not have all of the moral
duties and citizenship responsibilities that come with them, but they
are embedded in the web of interpersonal relationships on which
personhood rests.
23
The Wide view recognizes the psychological reality that our
individual capacities and identities are formed in social interaction
(and, by implication, it recognizes the profound harm caused by
unlawful detention and denial of society). It also avoids the exclusionary
tendencies of conceptions of personhood that require high thresholds of
individual capacity. The Wide view has been endorsed in particular by
philosophers of disability, who emphasize that individuals with
cognitive disabilities, like everyone else, are persons because of their
embeddedness in social relations (Kittay 2005; Silvers and Francis
2015; Arneil and Hirschman 2016). Personhood rights help to ensure
that individuals are able to form and maintain appropriate social bonds,
while protecting individuals from the arbitrary power of others to
detain, confine, neglect, or isolate them.
Kiko and Tommy are embedded in interpersonal webs of
dependency, meaning, and care with other human persons, and so are
part of human communities. We have brought Kiko and Tommy into
our community and embedded them in social relationships, and so they
too should be protected when others exercise arbitrary power over those
social ties. Kiko and Tommy remain members of a community with
24
humans because, however inadequate their care, they are dependent on
their keepers for food, water and shelter, and, as evidenced by the
NhRP lawsuit and this brief, there are those who recognize them as
part of the community. The fact that Kiko and Tommy are
simultaneously the subject of instrumentalization and the subject of
legal advocacy shows that their membership is disputed. Recall,
however, that this has also been true for many humans seeking habeas
corpus relief. Indeed, this is one of the functions of habeas corpus: to
protect members of the community who are being treated as things.
In short, the Wide view accepts the link between personhood and
community, but denies that community membership is exclusive to
human beings, not least because we have in fact brought other
individuals, such as Kiko and Tommy, into our community. Rather, it is
available to any sentient individual who is embedded in the relevant
relationships of interdependency and who would suffer if excluded from
those relationships.
3.2 The Narrow view
One could adopt a less inclusive conception of community. On the
Narrow conception, ‘personhood-as-community-membership’ requires
25
persons to have traits that are more than sentience or vulnerability, but
less than the capacity to bear legal responsibilities. These traits may be
biological or psychological.
Biological
traits
are
physical
properties:
having
forty-six
chromosomes, for example, or having human parents. This would be a
return to the view that only members of the species Homo sapiens
qualify for personhood, and, as argued in Section 1, restriction of
personhood on the basis of species is arbitrary and unsupported by
biological science.
Psychological traits are mental capacities: having beliefs and
desires, for example, or emotions, autonomy, and rationality. We will
have more to say about such capacities in Section 4, where we will
discuss the psychological capacities sufficient for personhood.
The key point for our purposes is that, as will be shown in Section
4, this Narrow view will include Kiko and Tommy as persons. They are
clearly the kind of psychological beings found in our community. While
Kiko and Tommy are not members of the species Homo sapiens, they
are clearly relevantly similar to humans in the kind of psychological
beings they are, as it is reasonable to ascribe to them such psychological
26
traits as beliefs, rationality, desires, emotions of care, as well as the
capacity for autonomy.
3.3 Conclusions regarding Community Membership
The idea that personhood has a social dimension, and is
importantly linked to membership in the human community, is familiar
and plausible. However, we cannot simply assume that it excludes Kiko
and Tommy.
If one accepts either the Wide or Narrow view of human
community, Kiko and Tommy are persons. On the Wide view, to be a
person is to be embedded in social relationships of interdependency,
meaning, and community. Kiko and Tommy clearly meet this criterion:
we have made Tommy and Kiko part of our human community of
persons by embedding them within relations of care and intersubjective
response, and rendering them vulnerable to forms of exclusion from this
community. On the Narrow view, to be a person requires not just social
embedding, but also the possession of certain basic, powerful, and
familiar psychological capacities, such as beliefs, desires, emotions,
rationality, and autonomy. It is reasonable to think that Kiko and
Tommy have these capacities.
27
On either the Wide or Narrow view, Tommy and Kiko are
members of our community, and so are owed protection from the
arbitrary power of others to define their social conditions.
4.
A Capacities Conception
The rulings from the Third and First Departments do not dispute
the fundamental claim made by the NhRP that the capacity for
autonomy is sufficient (though not necessary) for personhood. To defend
the NhRP’s claim about autonomy, we provide a brief analysis of
personhood that is consistent and ensures that all those human beings
commonly regarded as persons remain so, but does not introduce ad hoc
exclusions of other beings who meet the criteria. If chimpanzees possess
the same relevant capacities that qualify humans as persons, then the
reasonable conclusion should be that chimpanzees are also persons.
4.1 Conditions of personhood
John Locke, already mentioned in Section 2, described what it is
to be a person this way: “a thinking intelligent being that has reason
and reflection and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing
in different times and places; which it does only by that consciousness
which is inseparable from thinking and...essential to it” (Locke 1689, II.
28
XXVII .9, p.280). Though Locke’s view is still influential, contemporary
philosophical discussions of personhood tend to provide a more explicit
breakdown of core capacities. Of those commonly listed, we find
reference to autonomy (minimally, to act voluntarily or to control our
behavior in light of our preferences or goals), emotions, linguistic
mastery, sentience (the capacity for conscious awareness, sensation,
pleasure, and pain), rationality, reflective self-awareness (that is, being
aware of ourselves as ‘selves’), and reciprocity (e.g., Andrews 2017;
DeGrazia 2007; Dennett 1988). There is no disputing the personhood of
individuals who possess all of these capacities. However, there is no
way to hold that possessing all of these properties is necessary for
personhood without excluding some humans who lack one or more of
these properties. Furthermore, most of these properties develop
gradually in humans, so possession of them is not a clear-cut matter.
Instead, to be a person one must have multiple personhood-making
properties, although which properties cannot be non-arbitrarily
specified. Conceiving personhood in this way means that there is no
defensible minimum threshold of capacities that can definitively draw a
29
line separating persons from near-persons or non-persons (DeGrazia
2007).
Both the Third and the First Department rulings acknowledge the
affidavits submitted by a number of respected primatologists in support
of the view that chimpanzees share many relevantly similar
characteristics
with
humans.
Self-awareness
is
mentioned
by
Christophe Boesch (Boesch Aff. 12), Tetsuro Matsuzawa (Matsuzawa
Aff. 15), and Matthias Osvath (Osvath Aff. 12). Evidence for this
includes chimpanzees’ mirror self-recognition and awareness of where
they fit into their social hierarchy (see de Waal 2016). There is growing
evidence that chimpanzees plan their foraging activities, as mentioned
by James Anderson (Anderson Aff. 16) and Osvath (Osvath Aff. 12),
that they have preferred community members or ‘friends,’ as mentioned
by Boesch (Boesch Aff. 17) and Jennifer Fugate (Fugate Aff. 14), and
even favored tools, as mentioned by Anderson (Anderson Aff. 16). These
observations, if correct, point to the presence of goals, desires to satisfy
goals, and preferences. That chimpanzees can delay gratification (refuse
a smaller reward and wait for a larger one), as mentioned by Osvath
(Osvath Aff. 14), suggests a capacity for voluntary behavior and self-
30
control. Given the evidence that chimpanzees are autonomous,
emotional, self-aware, sentient beings who have beliefs and desires,
chimpanzees fulfill the requirements for personhood on a capacities
conception.
4.2 Personhood and autonomy
The NhRP’s case is based on one particular capacity—autonomy—
and this is for good reason. For one, it is a capacity that philosophers
have historically associated with personhood. Immanuel Kant’s
conception of persons is framed in terms of autonomy, such that we can
be ends in ourselves. However, Kant’s conception of autonomy requires
a great deal of cognitive sophistication, as it requires the ability to
abstractly consider principles of action and judge them according to
prudential values or rationality (see Johnson and Cureton 2017). His
conception has been criticized given that few humans engage in
abstract reflection before every action, and yet we are still acting
autonomously (as opposed to acting under the influence of a mindaltering substance or acting because of a compulsion). On the Kantian
view humans are rarely autonomous, and young children and some
cognitively disabled humans would fail to be autonomous actors, despite
31
appearances to the contrary. To address this worry, the well-known US
bioethicist and philosopher, Tom Beauchamp, together with the
comparative psychologist, Victoria Wobber, have suggested that an act
is autonomous if an individual self-initiates an “action that is (1)
intentional, (2) adequately informed…and (3) free of controlling
influences” (Beauchamp and Wobber 2014). Beauchamp and Wobber
contend that chimpanzees fit their conception and the submitted
affidavits previously referenced provide evidence to this effect.
Chimpanzees can act intentionally (they can plan and act to achieve
goals), and so satisfy (1). They learn how to navigate quite complex
physical and social worlds, reflecting a “richly information-based and
socially sophisticated understanding of the world” (Beauchamp and
Wobber 2014), and so satisfy (2). Whether chimpanzees act free of
controlling influences will depend on their environment and the options
available to them, but there is no doubt that chimpanzees can so act
when they find themselves in contexts without autonomy-depriving
controlling influences.
A second reason to focus on autonomy is that it is a cluster
concept. As highlighted by Beauchamp and Wobber, it brings together
32
capacities to act intentionally (which assumes capacities to form goals
and direct one’s behavior) and to be adequately informed (which
assumes capacities to learn, to make inferences, and acquire knowledge
through rational processes), each of which requires sentience. This
means that an autonomous capacity requires other personhood
capacities, namely sentience and rationality. So understood, evidence of
autonomy is sufficient evidence of personhood. Thus, chimpanzees
qualify as persons on autonomy grounds alone.
4.3 Why chimpanzee autonomy matters
A final reason for the NhRP’s focus on autonomy is due to the
concept’s direct connection to ethics. Violating someone’s autonomy is
widely regarded as a harm. After all, autonomous individuals have a
basic interest in exercising their autonomy, and to violate it is to violate
a basic interest (Beauchamp and Childress 2001). This brings us to
another point of contention in the rulings handed down by the Fourth
and First Departments. The Fourth Department ruled, and the First
Department concurred, that “habeas corpus relief…is unavailable”
(Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc v. Presti (2015 NY Slip Op
00085)) to Kiko or Tommy because the NhRP is not seeking their
33
release from captivity but rather their relocation to a suitable
sanctuary. The judgment lumps together markedly different kinds of
captivity. Our discussion of autonomy provides a way to usefully
distinguish Kiko and Tommy’s current captive conditions from those
afforded them in sanctuary. Both Kiko and Tommy are currently
housed alone and in small enclosures. A sanctuary like Chimp Haven,
which resides on 200 acres, is currently home to over 200 chimpanzees.
Save the Chimps is currently home to 248 chimpanzees residing on
twelve three-acre islands. Should Kiko and Tommy be relocated to
sanctuaries such as these several things change: they will no longer be
housed alone, they will no longer be confined indoors, they will have
markedly more freedom to roam, explore, and forage, they will have the
opportunity to develop and exercise more typical chimpanzee social
capacities, all the while expanding their goals and preferences to reflect
the greater opportunities afforded them. In their current conditions of
captivity their interests in acting autonomously are profoundly violated.
A sanctuary such as Chimp Haven or Save the Chimps promises not
only much greater freedom, but a setting where chimpanzees’
autonomous capacities are respected.
34
4.4 Conclusions regarding Capacities
The NhRP is arguing that chimpanzees are persons under a
capacities approach to the concept of personhood. This reflects their
view that this concept of personhood is already enshrined in law and
that, as it stands, it applies to chimpanzees just as it does to humans.
Affidavits by numerous eminent primatologists have attested to the fact
that chimpanzees possess the relevant capacities to qualify as persons,
and the First and Third Departments have not disputed the facts
regarding chimpanzee capacities. Importantly, despite appeals to
considerations like being human or being a member of a human
community, that either have no relevance to personhood or are actually
friendly to chimpanzee personhood, previous courts have never disputed
the capacities account of personhood. They have, however, resisted the
conclusion that obviously follows from those facts, and from our
discussion above: that chimpanzees such as Kiko and Tommy qualify as
persons.
35
IV.
Conclusion
Of the four conceptions that have been employed by the courts,
Species Membership is arbitrary and must be rejected, while the other
three suggest that Kiko and Tommy are persons. This Court should
recognize that when criteria for personhood are reasonable and
consistently applied, Kiko and Tommy satisfy the criteria and are
entitled to habeas corpus relief.
36
February 20, 2018
Respectfully submitted,
__________________________________
Mary Jean Mezzina, Esq.
Attorney for Amici Curiae
Kristin Andrews (York University);
Gary Comstock (North Carolina State
University); G.K.D. Crozier (Laurentian
University); Sue Donaldson (Queen’s
University); Andrew Fenton (Dalhousie
University); Tyler M. John (Rutgers
University); L. Syd M Johnson (Michigan
Technological University); Robert Jones
(California State University, Chico); Will
Kymlicka (Queen’s University); Letitia
Meynell (Dalhousie University); Nathan
Nobis Morehouse College); David PeñaGuzmán (California State University, San
Francisco); James Rocha (California State
University, Fresno); Bernard Rollin
(Colorado State); Jeffrey Sebo (New York
University); Adam Shriver (University of
British Columbia); Rebecca L. Walker
(University of North Carolina at Chapel
Hill)
3434 Milburn Avenue
Baldwin, New York 11510
516-319-9239
37
Bibliography
Anderson, James R. (2013). Affidavit in support of chimpanzee
personhood. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (Nov. 20, 2013),
available at: https://www.nonhumanrights.org/content/uploads/Ex-4Anderson-Affidavit-Tommy-Case.pdf.
Andrews, Kristin (2017). “Life in a cage.” The Philosophers’ Magazine,
76: 72-77.
Arneil, Barbara; Hirschman, Nancy (eds.) (2016). Disability and
Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Beauchamp, Tom L.; Childress, James L. (2001). Principles of
Biomedical Ethics (5th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Beauchamp, Tom L.; Wobber, Victoria (2014). “Autonomy in
chimpanzees.” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 35(2): 117-132.
Boesch, Christophe (2013). Affidavit in support of chimpanzee
personhood. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (Nov. 19, 2013),
available at: https://www.nonhumanrights.org/content/uploads/Ex-5Boesch-Affidavit-Tommy-Case.pdf.
Curry, Andrew (2013). “Archeology: The milk revolution.” Nature, 500:
20-22. Available at: http://www.nature.com/news/archaeology-the-milkrevolution-1.13471.
Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species by means of Natural
Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life.
London: John Murray. Available at:
http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/1228.
de Waal, Frans (2016). Are We Smart Enough to Know How Smart
Animals Are? New York: W.W. Norton and Company, Inc.
DeGrazia, David (2007). “Human-animal chimeras: Human dignity,
moral status, and species prejudice.” Metaphilosophy, 38(2-3): 309-329.
38
Dennett, Daniel (1988). “Conditions of personhood.” In What Is a
Person? Michael F. Goodman (Ed.). New Jersey: Humana Press, pp.145167.
Diamond, Jared (1993). “The third chimpanzee.” In The Great Ape
Project: Equality Beyond Humanity, Paola Cavalieri and Peter Singer
(Eds.). New York: St. Martin’s, pp. 88-101.
Eze, Michael Onyebuchi (2010). Intellectual history in contemporary
South Africa. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Frängsmyr, Tore; Lindroth, Sten; Eriksson, Gunnar; Broberg, Gunnar
(1983). Linnaeus, the Man and His Work. Berkeley and Los Angeles:
University of California Press.
Fugate, Jennifer M.B. (2013). Affidavit in support of chimpanzee
personhood. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (Nov. 23, 2013),
available at: https://www.nonhumanrights.org/content/uploads/Ex-6Fugate-Affidavit-Tommy-Case.pdf.
Goodman, Morris; Porter, Calvin A.; Czelusniak, John; Page, Scott L.;
Schneider, Horacio; Shoshani, Jeheskel; Gunnell, Gregg; Groves, Colin
P. (1998). “Toward a phylogenetic classification of primates based on
DNA evidence complemented by fossil evidence.” Molecular
Phylogenetics and Evolution, 9(3): 585-598.
Hobbes, Thomas (1651). Leviathan, Or The Matter, Forme and Power of
a Common-Wealth Ecclesiasticall and Civil ,Edwin Curley (Ed.).
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1994. Original text available at:
https://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/3207.
Hull, David (1986). “On human nature,” PSA: Proceedings of the
Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Volume Two:
“Symposia and Invited Papers”: 3-13. Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam
(2017). “Kant's moral philosophy,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), available at:
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/kant-moral/.
39
Kittay, Eva Feder (2005). “At the margins of moral personhood.” Ethics,
116(1): 100-131.
Langergraber, K.E., Prüfer, K., Rowney, C., Boesch, C., Crockford, C.,
Fawcett, K., Inoue, E., Inoue-Muruyama, M., Mitani, J.C., Muller, M.N.
and Robbins, M.M., 2012. “Generation times in wild chimpanzees and
gorillas suggest earlier divergence times in great ape and human
evolution.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 109(39):
15716-15721. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1211740109.
Linnaeus, Carl (1735). Systema Naturæ per regna tria naturæ,
secundum classes, ordines, genera, species, cum characteribus,
differentiis, synonymis, locis (Translates from Latin as System of nature
through the three kingdoms of nature, according to classes, orders,
genera and species, with characters, differences, synonyms, places).
Available at: http://www.biodiversitylibrary.org/item/15373.
Locke, John (1689). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding,
Volume I. John Yolton (Ed.). London: Dent and Sons, 1965Original text
available at: https://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/10615.
Locke, John (1698). Second Treatise of Government. Hackett Publishing;
Indianapolis 1980. Original text available at:
http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/7370.
Matsuzawa, Tetsuro (2013). Affidavit in support of chimpanzee
personhood. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (Nov. 23, 2013),
available at: https://www.nonhumanrights.org/content/uploads/Ex-9Matsuzawa-Affidavit-Tommy-Case.pdf.
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (2017 NY Slip Op
04574).
Matter of Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc v. Presti (2015 NY Slip Op
00085).
40
Osvath, Matthias (2013). Affidavit in support of chimpanzee
personhood. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (Nov. 19, 2013),
available at: https://www.nonhumanrights.org/content/uploads/Ex-11Osvath-Affidavit-Tommy-Case.pdf.
People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery (2014 NY Slip Op
08531).
Rohland, Nadin; Reich, David; Mallick, Swapan; Meyer, Matthias;
Green, Richard E.; Georgiadis, Nicholas J.; Roca, Alfred L.; Hofreiter,
Michael (2010). “Genomic DNA sequences from mastodon and woolly
mammoth reveal deep speciation of forest and savanna elephants.”
PLOS Biology, 8(12). Available at:
http://journals.plos.org/plosbiology/article?id=10.1371/journal.pbio.1000
564.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1762). On The Social Contract, Or Principles
of Political Right in The Basic Political Writings, Donald A. Cress
(Trans. & Ed.) Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 2011. Original texts
available at: http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/author/1286.
Silvers, Anita; Francis, Leslie Pickering (2015). “Human and civil
models of rights: Healthy and ill disabled and access to health care.” In
Human Rights and Disability: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, JohnStewart Gordon, Johan-Christian Põder, and Holger Burckhart (Eds.).
New York: Routledge, pp. 132-153.
Wildman, Derek E.; Uddin, Monica; Liu, Guozhen; Grossman, Lawrence
I.; Goodman, Morris (2003). “Implications of natural selection in
shaping 99.4% nonsynonymous DNA identity between humans and
chimpanzees: Enlarging genus Homo” PNAS, 100(12): 7181-7188.
Available at: http://www.pnas.org/content/100/12/7181.
41
CERTIFICATE OF COMPLIANCE
Pursuant to 22 NYCRR § 500.13(c)
The foregoing brief was prepared on a computer. A proportionally spaced typeface
was used, as follows:
Name of typeface: Times New Roman
Point size:
14
Line spacing:
Double
The total number of words in the brief, inclusive of point headings and footnotes
and exclusive of the statement of the status of related litigation; the corporate
disclosure statement; the table of contents, the table of cases and authorities and
the statement of questions presented required by subsection (a) of this section; and
any addendum containing material required by § 500.1(h) is 6,500.
Dated:
February 22, 2018
___________________________
Mary Jean Mezzina, Esq.
3434 Milburn Avenue
Baldwin, New York 11510
(516) 319-9239
[email protected]