1
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory
Reasoning
The goal of this book is to shed light on metaphysical necessity and the broader class of
modal properties to which it belongs. This choice of topic requires little justification or
explanation. Since the work of Kripke, Lewis, and others ushered in the modal turn in
analytic philosophy, modality has become one of the most active areas of research in
metaphysics and modal notions have been central to philosophical theorizing across the
board—from the foundations of logic to moral theory. In view of this trend, it is an
important enterprise to gain a clear philosophical understanding of modality, not least in
order to determine whether it can bear the weight that so much of recent philosophical
practice has placed on it. And yet, while much illuminating work has been done on the
formal properties of necessity and its connections to other properties, a deep
understanding of its nature has largely eluded us, or so I will argue. The first aim of this
book is to plug this gap by offering a new account of what necessity is.
The second goal is to explain why human beings have modal thoughts at all. What is
the point of reflecting on unrealized alternatives to actuality—which of our interests and
concerns does it address? This second objective can be pursued in close connection with
the first. An account of the nature of modality can take inspiration from a hypothesis
about the cognitive and linguistic practices of everyday life in which modal thinking
originated, while ideas about the nature of modality can in turn suggest an account of the
purpose of modal thinking. That is the strategy pursued in this book.
I will argue that to understand modality we need to reconceptualize its relationship to
causation and other forms of explanation such as grounding, a relation that connects
metaphysically fundamental facts to non-fundamental ones. While many philosophers
have tried to give modal analyses of causation and explanation, often in counterfactual
terms, I will argue that we obtain a more plausible, explanatorily powerful and unified
theory if we regard explanation as more fundamental than modality. The function of
modal thought is to facilitate a common type of thought experiment—counterfactual
reasoning—that allows us to investigate explanatory connections and which is closely
related to the controlled experiments of empirical science. Necessity is defined in terms
of explanation, and modal facts often reflect underlying facts about explanatory
Boris Kment, Modality and Explanatory Reasoning, Oxford University Press,
2014, Chapter 1.
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
2
relationships. The study of modal facts is important for philosophy, not because these
facts are of much metaphysical interest in their own right, but largely because they
provide evidence about explanatory connections.
In the remainder of this chapter I will give a brief and highly selective sketch of the
position I am going to defend, before giving some advice to those who wish to read only
selected parts of this book.
1.1 The Nature of Modality
When asked to set aside sophisticated philosophical theories and give an intuitive
characterization of necessity, we may say something like this: a proposition is necessary
if its truth is in some sense very secure, invariable, or unconditional. The task of
analyzing necessity can be approached by trying to cash out the idea of security, invariability, or unconditionality in non-metaphorical terms. I will argue in Chapter 2 that it is
the same notion that we use when we ask of a certain proposition how easily it could have
failed to be true. The less easily the proposition could have failed to be true, the more
secure its truth.
To get a better handle on claims about how easily something could have been the case,
it is useful to consider how we ordinarily support such a claim. When talking about a
soccer game, we may say: “The game ended in a draw, but our team could easily have
won. If the goalkeeper had stood two inches further to the right two minutes before the
end, the other team would not have scored their goal.” In less favorable circumstances,
we may say instead, “Our team couldn’t easily have won. They would have beaten their
opponents only if they had started to train much earlier, had recruited Mary and Bob, and
had done a million other things differently.” How easily our team could have won
depends on how great a departure from actuality is required for them to win. If they win
in some scenarios that are only minimally different from the way things in fact are, then
we can say that they could easily have won. We can say the opposite if all scenarios
where they win depart very significantly from actuality. More generally, for any true
proposition P, how easily P could have failed to be true depends on how great a departure
from actuality is required for P not to be true. The greater the departure required, the
more secure P’s truth.
It is often assumed that necessity and possibility are all-or-nothing matters. But how
easily a proposition could have failed to be true is clearly a matter of degree, and I will
argue on that basis that we should think of necessity and possibility themselves as coming
in degrees. To say that P could more easily have been true than Q is to say that P has a
higher degree of possibility than Q.
Talk about degrees of possibility is ubiquitous in ordinary life, but the idioms we use
are not always overtly modal. You are running to catch the train, but the doors close on
you before you can jump in, causing you to sigh in frustration “I almost made it.” Your
3
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
utterance expresses the thought that you could easily have caught the train: a minimal
departure from actuality—the doors closing half a second later—is all that was necessary.
Similarly, in a sentence like “Smith got closer to winning than Jones,” we compare two
unrealized scenarios—Smith’s winning and Jones’s winning—by their proximity to
actuality. I think that such comparisons also underlie counterfactual judgments like “If I
had pressed this button, there would have been an explosion.” For on the best known
view of counterfactuals, which I accept, the conditional is true just in case some buttonpressing scenarios where an explosion takes place depart less from actuality than any
button-pressing scenarios without explosion.1
The idea that necessity can be explained in terms of closeness of non-actual scenarios
to actuality is likely to meet with protest, since the very property of being a non-actual
situation is often thought to be modal. Many philosophers, when they hear “non-actual
situations” or “alternatives to actuality,” think of unactualized metaphysically possible
situations or unactualized ways things could have been. From their point of view, any
attempt to analyze modality in terms of a closeness ordering of non- actualized situations
will seem blatantly circular. However, I think that it is a mistake to identify the space of
unactualized scenarios with the class of metaphysically possible scenarios. Consider
counterfactual conditionals as an example. Roughly speaking, a counterfactual is true just
in case its consequent is true at the closest worlds where its antecedent holds. On the
assumption that all worlds are metaphysically possible, this account yields the dubious
consequence that all counterfactuals with metaphysically impossible antecedents are
vacuously true (since there are no antecedent-worlds), irrespective of the specific
contents of their antecedents and consequents. But that seems very implausible. It’s
metaphysically impossible for Hillary Clinton to be Antonin Scalia’s daughter. But that
doesn’t trivialize the question how Clinton’s views would differ if Scalia were her father.
Similarly, it is metaphysically impossible for there to be no numbers. And yet, in
discussing whether mathematical facts contribute to explaining physical events, we may
ask—non-trivially, it seems—whether these events would unfold any differently if
numbers didn’t exist.2 Since this problem arises from disallowing worlds where
That’s the “standard” account of counterfactuals, as proposed by Stalnaker (1968, 1984: ch. 8) and Lewis
(1973a, 1986c).
2
The first example is unlikely to worry anti-haecceitist counterpart theorists like David Lewis (1968, 1971,
1986e: ch. 4; for discussions of different versions of the theory, see, e.g., Forbes 1982, 1987, 1990;
Ramachandran 1989, 1990a, 1990b; Fara and Williamson 2005; Kment 2012). Their view entails that the
truth-values of de re modal claims can change with contextual variations in the extension of the counterpart
relation. In most contexts, we operate with a counterpart relation that makes it is true to say that Clinton
could not have been Scalia’s daughter. That accounts for our impression that this proposition is impossible.
But when someone raises the question of how Clinton’s views would have been different if she had been
Scalia’s daughter, then we shift to a different counterpart relation in order to give the speaker some chance
of making a non-trivial claim. That is to say, we move to a context in which it is true to say that Clinton
could have been Scalia’s daughter and in which there is a non-trivial answer to the question of what her
political views would have been in that case. That explains the impression that the question is a substantive
one. Both impressions can be accommodated within the counterpart-theoretical framework. I have argued
elsewhere that there are strong reasons for rejecting anti-haecceitist counterpart theory (Kment 2012). In
1
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
4
impossible propositions are true, the obvious remedy—suggested and developed by a
number of philosophers—is to lift this restriction. Instead of appealing to possible worlds,
we can formulate the account in terms of worlds more generally, including both possible
and impossible worlds. Worlds are simply ways for reality to be, and they include both
ways reality could have been and ways reality couldn’t have been.3
In Chapters 4 and 5 I try to show that worlds can be defined non-modally as classes of
propositions that describe reality in logically consistent and maximally detailed ways.
This framework can be used to sharpen the account of modality sketched above. One
world, called the “actual world” or “actuality,” has the special distinction of being a
wholly correct description of reality. Other worlds differ from actuality to varying
degrees. The degree of possibility of a proposition P is determined by how close the
closest P-worlds are to actuality: the closer these worlds, the more easily P could have
been true. The class of all worlds within a certain distance from actuality may be called a
“sphere” around the actual world. The ordering of unactualized worlds by their closeness
to actuality generates a system of nested spheres. For each sphere there is a grade of
necessity that attaches to just those propositions that are true at every world in that
sphere, as well as a grade of possibility attaching to all propositions that are true at some
world in the sphere. The larger the sphere, the greater the associated grade of necessity.
One specific sphere, described in more detail below, corresponds to metaphysical
necessity: the metaphysical necessities are the propositions that hold at every world in
that sphere. Another, smaller sphere corresponds to nomic necessity, a form of necessity
associated with the laws of nature. Other spheres give us yet further grades of necessity,
some of them lower than nomic necessity, some intermediate between nomic and
metaphysical necessity, and some greater than metaphysical necessity.
I will argue in Chapters 2 and 3 that this theory does a good job of capturing our core
beliefs about what necessity is, and that it illuminates various features of modality and
modal discourse. To complete the analysis of modality, we need to give an account of the
rules that determine the ordering of worlds by their closeness to actuality. Different
worlds differ from or resemble actuality in different respects, and a theory of the closeness ordering needs to specify how much weight attaches to these different similarities
and differences. It is a common observation that we employ different standards of
closeness in different contexts. However, following David Lewis, I believe that there is a
specific set of rules about the weights of different similarities and differences that applies
in most contexts. Metaphysical and nomic necessity, as well as the other modal properties
and relations discussed in this book, are defined in terms of the standards of closeness
any case, counterpart theory doesn’t help with the second example of seemingly non-trivial
counterpossibles: the counterfactual about the non-existence of mathematical entities.
3
For uses of impossible worlds in accounting for counterfactuals with impossible antecedents, see, e.g.,
Routley (1989), Read (1995), Mares and Fuhrmann (1995), Mares (1997), Nolan (1997), Zalta (1997). See
Williamson (2007: 171–5) for an argument against non-trivial truth-values for counterpossibles. For replies
to these arguments, see Brogaard and Salerno (2007a, 2007b, 2013). Also see Baker (2007). For some arguments against impossible worlds, see Stalnaker (1996).
5
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
determined by this set of rules. I hold that a theory of these standards needs to appeal to
the relation of explanation. Before describing what motivates this claim, I need to say
more about how I conceive of explanation.
1.2 Modality and Explanation
1.2.1 Explanation
To say that x explains y is to say that x is the reason why y obtains, or that y is due to x.
Explanation in this sense is a metaphysical relation, not an epistemic one.4,5 A cause
partly explains its effect, but x can also partly explain y without being a cause of y. My
first example of such non-causal explanation will stay fairly close to the causal case. I
hold that effects are typically explained not by their causes alone, but by these together
with certain facts about the laws of nature. The coffee cup falls, hits the floor, and breaks
into a million pieces. Why did it happen? In part, it’s because you pushed the cup off the
table and because you have a planet under your kitchen floor. But another part of the
reason is that there is a law of nature to the effect that any two massive bodies attract
each other with a certain force. It’s partly because that is a natural law that the planet
attracted the cup.6 This is an example of non-causal explanation: the fact that a certain
law is in force partly explains certain goings-on but it doesn’t cause them.
My second example of non-causal explanation is the relation often called “grounding,” which I will discuss in Chapter 6. Grounding is the kind of explanatory connection
described in statements like the following:
What makes 28 a perfect number is the fact that it is a positive integer equal to the
sum of its proper positive divisors.
This particle is a hydrogen atom because (in virtue of the fact that) it is composed
of one proton and one electron in such-and-such configuration.
I will argue that there is a far-reaching structural analogy between causation and grounding. Just as earlier states of the universe typically give rise to later ones by causing them,
metaphysically more fundamental facts give rise to less fundamental ones by grounding
them. Certain general metaphysical principles, which I will call “laws of metaphysics,”
play essentially the same role in grounding as the natural laws do in causation. The
metaphysical laws include the essential truths, in a broadly Aristotelian sense of that
Compare Wesley Salmon’s distinction between ontic, epistemic, and modal senses of “explanation”
(Salmon 1984). My use of “explanation” is closest to what Salmon called “ontic explanation.”
5
I will also occasionally use “explanation” in other senses, e.g. in the sense of “account of why x obtains,”
and I will similarly use “explain” in the sense of “provide an account of why x obtains.” This is the sense in
which I will be using the term when I speak of a theory’s power to explain certain data, or of inference to
the best explanation. The context will always disambiguate.
6
I am simplifying by pretending that Newtonian physics is true.
4
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
6
term. To a first approximation, the essential truths about a property state what it is to have
that property. For instance, the essential truths about the property of being a gold atom
lay down that to be a gold atom is to be an atom with atomic number 79. Metaphysically
non-fundamental facts are explained by their grounds together with facts about the
metaphysical laws. For example, a is a gold atom because a is an atom with atomic
number 79 and because that’s what it is to be a gold atom.7
Grounding and causation are closely intertwined. In many cases, X causes Z by
causing some fact Y that in turn grounds Z. For example, I hold that if the mental is
grounded in the physical, then that’s how physical occurrences cause mental ones. You
sip your coffee, which brings about the occurrence of certain brain events, which in turn
grounds a taste sensation. The explanation of the sensation involves the sipping, the
natural laws that connect it to the fact that the brain events occur and the metaphysical
laws connecting that fact to the sensation. The example illustrates how natural and
metaphysical laws can both figure in the causal explanation of a fact.
My view of laws and explanation is anti-Humean. What the laws are isn’t determined
by the patterns that prevail in the universe; on the contrary, it’s the fact that certain laws
are in force that explains the patterns. In my view, the implausibility of the Humean
approach and its various problems more than outweigh its benefits, but I won’t argue for
that claim in this book. The debate about the virtues and vices of Humeanism has been
raging on for many years, and I have little new to add. In any case, a proper evaluation of
the approach would require another book. A dispute as fundamental as this should
perhaps be decided partly in light of how theoretically fruitful the opposing approaches
are. This book can be viewed in part as an attempt to contribute to this assessment. For I
hope to show that a plausible, unified, and highly explanatory account of the nature of
modality and of the purpose of modal thinking can be built on an anti-Humean basis.
1.2.2 The Direction of Analysis
The connection of modality to causation and explanation is perhaps clearest when we use
counterfactuals to answer questions about explanatory relationships. If you want to know
whether Fred’s tactless remark on Friday caused his fight with Susie on Sunday, then the
natural question to ask is whether they would have fought without the remark. If the
answer is “no”—if the fight counterfactually depends on the remark—then you can infer
that the remark caused the fight. Similarly, if it can be shown that life wouldn’t have
developed if the value of some physical constant had been outside a certain range, then
that supports the claim that the existence of life is explained in part by the fact that the
value was within that range. Counterfactuals guide our judgments about explanatory
relationships. This observation has motivated analyses of causation and explanation in
I don’t claim that the foregoing constitutes an exhaustive list of all kinds of non-causal explanation. But
the cases I mentioned above are the only ones that will concern me in this book.
7
7
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
counterfactual terms. For a counterfactual analysis gives a straightforward account of the
connection between counterfactuals and judgments about explanation: Explanatory
relationships consist (at least partly) in certain patterns of counterfactual dependencies.
To ask whether X partly explains Y is (at least in part) to ask whether certain
counterfactuals hold.
There is, however, an obvious problem that besets any attempt to motivate an analysis
of D in terms of C by appealing to a seemingly correct inference from a claim about C to
another that is about D. If the inference is valid, then so is its contrapositive. But that
inference leads from a claim about D to one that is about C. We could take the first
inference to motivate an analysis of D in terms of C. But we could equally well take the
second inference to support an analysis of C in terms of D.
This observation can be applied to the present topic. Just as we can often infer that A
partly explains E if we know that E counterfactually depends on A, we can often infer
that E is counterfactually independent of A if we know that there is no explanatory
connection. Moreover, just as beliefs about explanatory relationships are often guided by
counterfactual judgments in accordance with the former inference, so counterfactual
judgments are often informed by prior beliefs about explanation in accordance with the
latter. The second phenomenon is amply illustrated by examples in the recent literature
on counterfactuals.8 Here is a variant of an example due to Dorothy Edgington (2003). As
you are about to watch an indeterministic lottery draw on television, someone offers to
sell you ticket number 17. You decline. As luck would have it, ticket number 17 wins. It
seems true to say “If you had bought the ticket, you would have won.” But this
presupposes that
If you had bought ticket number 17, that ticket would still have won.
Now suppose that the company that is organizing the draw has two qualitatively indistinguishable lottery machines that give the same chance to every possible outcome. They
used machine A in the draw, but could have used machine B instead. Consider:
If a different machine had been used in the draw, 17 would still have won.
That seems false. If a different machine had been used, then 17 might still have won, or
some other number might have won. It is not true that 17 would still have won. In the first
case, we hold the outcome of the lottery draw fixed, in the second we don’t. It seems very
plausible that this difference is due to underlying causal judgments. Your decision
whether to buy the ticket is not causally connected to the outcome of the draw (or so we
believe). That’s why the outcome can be held fixed when we are thinking about what
would have happened if you had made a different decision. By contrast, the use of a
particular lottery machine is part of the causal history of the outcome. Hence, which
machine is used makes a difference to the causal history of the result. That’s why the
8
Examples similar to the one that follows are discussed in Adams (1975: ch. IV, sct. 8, in particular pp.
132–3.), Tichý (1976), and Slote (1978).
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
8
outcome of the draw cannot be held fixed in the second case. In these examples, we are
drawing on prior causal judgments to decide whether certain facts can be held fixed—i.e.,
whether they would still have obtained if the antecedent had been true, or in other words,
whether they are counterfactually independent of the antecedent.
Just as our counterfactual judgments are often informed by pre-existing causal beliefs,
they frequently draw on prior judgments about non-causal explanation, as a second
example will illustrate. In most cases of ordinary-life counterfactual reasoning, we can
hold fixed the fact that material objects conform to the law of gravitation (call that law
“G”). For example, we accept that
If I were to suspend my pencil in the air and then release it, it would fall to the
ground.
But there are also cases where we can’t hold fixed the fact that events conform to G. For
instance, the following conditional doesn’t sound true:
If G weren’t a law of nature, events would still conform to G.
It seems plausible that this difference is due to certain underlying facts about explanatory
relationships: at the actual world the fact that G is a law of nature explains the fact that
events conform to G. By contrast, what I do with my pencil is not explanatorily relevant
to whether events conform to this law.
Examples like these might motivate the thought that counterfactuals should be analyzed in terms of explanation rather than the other way around.9 So far, then, there is no
reason for preferring one direction of analysis to the other. The only way to decide
between them is to look at the two options in more detail in order to determine which of
them can better account for the complex relationship between counterfactuals and explanation. It is well known that counterfactual analyses of causation and explanation face
considerable problems at this point. Counterfactual dependence is neither necessary nor
sufficient for the existence of an explanatory relationship, and decades of sustained effort
have failed to yield a counterfactual analysis that isn’t subject to clear counterexamples.
There is plenty of motivation for trying out a theory that rests on the opposite order of
analysis. Such an account will appeal to explanation to explain the standards of closeness
to actuality that figure in the analysis of counterfactuals (and of possibility and necessity
claims).10 I will aim to show in the course of this book that this approach can give a better
account of the data. A brief summary of my theory is given in the next section.
9
See Mårtensson (1999), Edgington (2003), Bennett (2003: ch. 15), Hiddleston (2005), and Wasserman
(2006) for causal analyses of counterfactuals motivated by examples like the above lottery case, and see
Kment (2006a) for an analysis in terms of (causal and non-causal) explanation.
10
It is a good question whether explanation itself is definable or should be taken as fundamental. I will
remain neutral on this issue. My account is consistent both with primitivism about explanation and with the
view that explanation can be analyzed (perhaps in terms of the relation of nomic determination discussed in
Chapter 10).
9
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
1.2.3 Closeness to Actuality
Chapters 7–9 will discuss a variety of modal data and will offer an account of the
standards of closeness that explains them. Simplifying somewhat, we can say that the
comparative closeness to actuality of two worlds is determined by weighing the similarities that the first world has to actuality against those that the second world has to
actuality. Not all similarities carry weight—some count for nothing. Of the similarities
that are relevant, some count for more than others. The first part of my theory distinguishes the relevant similarities from the irrelevant ones. The second part specifies the
relative weights of different kinds of relevant similarities.
The explanatory criterion of relevance. Suppose that fact f obtains at the actual world
and also at world w. Then that similarity carries non-zero weight just in case all parts of
f’s actual explanatory history obtain at w as well—including f’s actual causes and
grounds, and the facts about the laws that partly explain f at the actual world. The lottery
example of section 1.2.2 illustrates this. In the first version of the case, we are wondering
whether you would have won if you had bought the ticket. Antecedent-worlds where the
outcome of the draw is the same as in actuality are closer than those where the outcome is
different. Match in the outcome of the draw carries non-zero weight because all elements
of the actual explanatory history of the outcome are present at the closest antecedentworlds. Matters are different when it comes to the second version of the example, where
we consider the question whether the same ticket would have won if the other machine
had been used. In this case, some parts of the actual explanatory history of the outcome
fail to obtain at the closest antecedent-worlds, and it is therefore irrelevant to the position
of such a world in the closeness ordering whether the lottery draw has the same outcome
as in actuality.
The gravitation example can be given a similar treatment. In the second version of this
case, where we were wondering what would be the case if G weren’t a law, antecedentworlds that conform to G aren’t closer than those that don’t. The explanatory criterion of
relevance explains this finding: at the actual world events conform to G because G is a
law. But G isn’t a law at a world where the antecedent is true. Therefore, even if such a
world conforms to G, that isn’t a closeness-relevant similarity. Matters are different in the
first version of the example. At the closest worlds, where I release my pencil in mid-air,
G is still a law. Hence, other things being equal, such worlds are closer to actuality if
their events conform to G than if they don’t.
The weight of relevant similarities.11 The explanatory criterion of relevance specifies
the conditions under which a similarity carries non-zero weight, but it doesn’t tell us how
much weight it carries when these conditions are satisfied. The second part of my theory
addresses that question. Of all the similarities that meet the explanatory criterion of relevance, similarities in the metaphysical laws are the weightiest. To simplify somewhat,
11
What follows is a simplified statement of my account of the relative weights of different similarities. The
full view will be given in Chapter 8.
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
10
any world with the same laws of metaphysics as actuality is closer to actuality than any
world where these laws are different, no matter how closely the second world matches
actuality in other respects. Worlds that have the same metaphysical laws therefore form a
sphere around actuality. The second most important criterion is match in natural laws.
Worlds with the same metaphysical and natural laws as actuality are closer than worlds
that don’t meet this condition. They form a second, smaller sphere within the first sphere.
Similarities between the histories of two worlds matter to the closeness ordering as well,
although to a lesser degree. For each sphere, there is a grade of necessity that attaches to
the propositions that hold at every world in that sphere. Metaphysical necessity is the
grade corresponding to the sphere of worlds with the same metaphysical laws as actuality, while nomic necessity is the grade connected to the sphere of worlds that match actuality in all laws (metaphysical and natural).
In the second half of the book I will try to show that this account affords an attractive
and unified explanation of a variety of data about modality and its connection to
explanation. Moreover, it can serve as the basis of a plausible account of the function of
modal thought.
1.3 The Function of Modal Thought
My discussion of the purpose of modal thinking will start from the above observation that
counterfactual beliefs often guide judgments about explanatory relationships. In Chapters
10–12 I will aim to explain how counterfactual reasoning can serve this function, and I
will argue that modal thinking developed at least in part because of its utility for
evaluating explanatory claims. The brief summary that follows will focus on my account
of counterfactual reasoning under determinism. Indeterministic cases will be discussed in
Chapter 12.
I hold that the use of counterfactual reasoning to assess explanatory claims is an
extension of a very common procedure for investigating causal relationships that John
Stuart Mill called “the method of difference.”12 Consider a humble example of this
method. Your laptop is plugged in but the battery, though nearly depleted, is not
charging. To find out whether the problem is due to a battery defect, a malfunctioning
adapter, or a dead outlet, you vary one factor at a time while holding the others fixed. For
example, using the same battery and adapter, you plug into a different outlet. If the
battery starts charging, you conclude that the issue was caused by an outlet problem.
Scenario 1: A B C D
E
Scenario 2: Ā B C D
Ē
Idealizing somewhat and focusing on deterministic contexts, we can give the following simplified and schematic description of the method of difference. The agent
12
Mill (1956: bk. III, ch. VIII, sct. 2).
11
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
observes a scenario where A is present, accompanied by the surrounding conditions B–D,
and where E obtains a moment later. She also observes a second situation where A is
absent but which matches the first scenario in containing B–D. This time, E does not
occur. If she believes that in the first scenario no factors other than A–D were causally
relevant to the presence of E, then she can take her observations to support the claim that
A is a cause of E in the first scenario. Sophisticated versions of this procedure are applied
in scientific experiments. (In these cases, Scenario 1 is the “experimental condition,”
Scenario 2 is the “control condition,” and B–D are the background factors that the
experimenters are controlling for.) However, my discussion will largely focus on
everyday uses of the method.
I will argue that ordinary-life applications of the method of difference rest on an
assumption that I will call the determination idea. When applied to causation under
determinism, the determination idea amounts to the assumption that (to simplify
somewhat) E’s causes and the laws involved in E’s explanation together determine that E
obtains. The determination idea provides a straightforward explanation of how the
method of difference works. Since B–D obtain in Scenario 2 but E doesn’t, the agent can
conclude that B–D and the laws don’t determine E. But by the determination idea, the
factors that caused E in Scenario 1 and the laws must together determine E. So, B–D
can’t include all of the causes of E in Scenario 1. Given the assumption that A–D do
include all of these causes, it follows that A must be a cause of E.
The determination idea, which will be spelled out in non-modal terms in Chapter 10,
is not an analysis of causation. It merely states a condition that is necessary, though not
sufficient, under determinism for certain factors to include all of E’s causes: these factors
and the laws involved in E’s explanation must together determine E. Other versions of
the idea apply to probabilistic causation and to grounding, as will be discussed in later
chapters. While I think that the determination idea is plausible and that some objections
to it are misguided, it is not of critical importance for my purposes whether the idea
should be regarded as true in light of our best philosophical and scientific theories. My
reconstruction of everyday applications of the method of difference requires only the
premise that the determination idea is commonly used in ordinary explanatory thinking,
at least as a working assumption. Chapter 10 will provide further support for this claim.
The method of difference is limited in scope. If we have observed A followed by E,
and we want to show that A was a cause of E, we have to find or create another situation
where A doesn’t obtain but which otherwise matches the scenario we have observed in all
relevant ways. That is often impossible in practice. And the method is useless when our
goal is to find out not what caused E, but which laws were involved in E’s explanation.
For the laws never vary between different scenarios that actually obtain. If my
reconstruction of Mill’s method is on the right track, however, then there is a straightforward extension of it that remedies these shortcomings. On my account, the sole
function of Scenario 2 is to show that B–D and the laws don’t determine E. But given a
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
12
realistic amount of background knowledge about the laws, we can show the same by
mental simulation. We represent to ourselves an unactualized scenario where B–D obtain
but A doesn’t, and where history then unfolds in accordance with the actual laws. If E
fails to obtain in this situation, then B–D and the laws don’t determine E. Using the
determination idea, we can again infer that B–D don’t include all causes of E in the actual
scenario. Given our background assumption that A–D do include all of E’s actual causes,
we can conclude that A is actually a cause of E. The mental simulation I described is a
simplified version of the reasoning by which we determine whether E depends
counterfactually on A: we imagine a scenario where A is absent, holding fixed various
other facts that actually obtain (B–D and the laws), and we then determine whether E
obtains in that situation. The situation imagined serves the same purpose as Scenario 2
(the “control condition”) in the method of difference, and by holding fixed the right facts
we achieve the same as by controlling for background conditions in an experiment. The
same type of mental simulation can also be used to show that a certain law L is involved
in explaining E, only in that case we need to imagine a scenario where L isn’t a law but
where other relevant factors are the same as they actually are.
Chapter 11 will explain why a sophisticated version of counterfactual reasoning
requires a closeness ordering of unrealized scenarios that is governed by the specific
standards described in Chapters 8 and 9. Roughly speaking, this ordering gives us an easy
way of deciding, for any fact A, which unrealized scenarios we need to consider if we
want to test whether A partly explains a certain other fact: of all scenarios where A is
absent, we should consider those that are closest to actuality in the ordering. The
background facts that we need to hold fixed are just those that obtain in these scenarios.
As mentioned before, our standards of closeness accord great weight to similarities in the
natural laws, and even greater importance to match in the laws of metaphysics. Whenever
possible, we should hold fixed which metaphysical laws are in force, and if possible, we
should also hold fixed what the natural laws are. (I will argue that the rationale for these
rules is closely connected to the distinctive explanatory roles of the metaphysical and
natural laws.) The purpose of our various modal notions, including those of metaphysical
and nomic necessity, consists in the fact that they make it easier to apply these rules of
counterfactual reasoning.
Since comparative closeness to actuality is defined in terms of explanation, we typically need to have some explanatory knowledge already before we can conduct counterfactual reasoning to establish a claim about explanation. But there is no circularity.
The explanatory knowledge needed to establish the relevant counterfactual differs from
the explanatory knowledge we acquire as a result of the process. Counterfactuals, and
modal claims more generally, mediate inferences from old items of knowledge about
explanation to new ones. This view explains the phenomenon, mentioned in section 1.2.2,
that we commonly draw inferences in both directions, from explanatory claims to
counterfactuals and vice versa. Both kinds of inference are usually involved in establish-
13
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
ing a claim about explanation through counterfactual reasoning. But inferences in the two
directions differ in one important way. Most counterfactuals are made true in part by
patterns of explanatory relationships, and that’s why beliefs about such patterns are
typically required as premises in establishing that one fact counterfactually depends on
another. By contrast, the further inferential step from the counterfactual dependence to
the explanatory conclusion isn’t underwritten by a similar constitutive connection—
counterfactual dependencies aren’t part of what explanatory relationships consist in. The
inference rests instead on the determination idea, as explained above.
My account explains why counterfactual reasoning is a reliable method of testing
causal and other explanatory claims across a wide range of circumstances. But I will
argue in Chapter 12 that the view also predicts and explains why the method doesn’t
work in certain other cases, like those of causal overdetermination and preemption. These
are the examples that have dogged counterfactual accounts of causation. My theory can
account for them.
I don’t pretend that my account of the role of counterfactuals in explanatory reasoning
gives us the whole story about why we have modal thoughts. There is no doubt that
modal thinking serves other purposes as well. To assess the safety record of a nuclear
power plant, we may try to find out how close the plant came to an accident at various
points in the past. When making practical decisions, we often determine the likely
consequences of a possible action by asking what would happen if we were to perform
it.13 Beliefs about the proximity of unrealized scenarios also have a powerful and welldocumented influence on our evaluative judgments and emotions.14 Whether you react to
an event with joy or with disappointment doesn’t depend solely on your perception of its
intrinsic pleasantness or desirability. It is equally determined by how the outcome
compares to others that could easily have come about. It seems probable that in such
cases modal judgments play an adaptive role in regulating emotion and motivation.
Modal thinking was most likely molded by a variety of functional pressures. I won’t aim
to do more in this book than to give an account of one of its uses that seems to be of
particular interest to philosophy.15,16
13
See Gibbard and Harper (1978) and Lewis (1981), among others.
See, e.g., Medvec, Madey, and Gilovich (1995).
15
Why, then, does my discussion of the genealogy of modal thinking focus on its role in explanatory
reasoning? The reason is twofold. Firstly, it is one of my chief aims to argue that explanation is more fundamental than modality. To support this order of explanation, it is important to show that it gives us a better
account of the role of counterfactuals in explanatory reasoning than the opposite direction of analysis.
Secondly, by studying how modal thought figures in reasoning about explanation, we are likely to shed
light on the functions of a larger range of modal notions than by investigating other uses of modal thinking.
When we use counterfactuals in decision making, our attention seems to be restricted to worlds that differ
mostly in what decisions we make, but which are otherwise pretty much like actuality. Similarly, in cases
where we respond emotionally to the thought that things could easily have turned out better or worse than
they did at time t, we typically consider only scenarios where the laws are the same as they actually are and
where history unfolds the same way until shortly before t. Such uses of modal thinking don’t require us to
14
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
14
1.4 Modality in Metaphysics
During the last couple of decades, modality has played a central role in metaphysical
theories about numerous topics. For example, many philosophers have defined an essential feature of an object as a property it must have if it exists. Others have tried to give an
account of truth-making in terms of a modal relationship between worldly entities and
true claims. Various relations of supervenience have been used in an attempt to capture
theses of the forms The B-facts are nothing over and above the A-facts, The A-facts are
more fundamental than the B-facts, or All facts are ultimately A-facts. Counterfactual
conditionals have been put to heavy work in several areas of metaphysics as well. And
there are many more examples. These developments made it natural to think of the
exploration of modal facts as one of the chief occupations of the metaphysician.
More recently, this idea has come in for criticism. Not that there aren’t important
connections between metaphysical theses on the one hand and modal claims on the other.
If understood a certain way, the claim that the A-facts are more fundamental than the Bfacts arguably entails a substantive supervenience thesis. From the claim that x is
essentially P, it follows that x must be P if it exists. And perhaps the thesis that x is a
truth-maker of P entails that x’s existence necessitates P’s truth (or something along these
lines). The problem is that in all of these cases the entailment seems to hold only in one
direction—from the metaphysical claim to the modal one. The supervenience of the Bfacts on the A-facts alone doesn’t entail that the A-facts are more fundamental than the
B-facts in any interesting sense; a necessary property of a thing needn’t be essential to it,
and P’s truth-makers may not be the only entities whose existence necessitates P’s truth.
There is therefore no obvious way of formulating modal claims that are equivalent to the
ask how very remote scenarios are ordered by their relative proximity to actuality, and they consequently
don’t require us to distinguish between the different degrees of necessity that correspond to spheres large
enough to include such remote scenarios. Therefore, to the extent that such high degrees of necessity figure
in our thinking, that fact cannot be explained by appeal to the role of modal thinking in decision making or
in regulating one’s emotions.
By contrast, there is no general limit on the remoteness of scenarios that we can usefully consider when
we apply counterfactual reasoning to test explanatory claims. For instance, when we investigate the
explanatory role of a certain fact about the metaphysical laws, the closest worlds where that fact fails to
obtain may be very far away from actuality. In such cases, we have a use for notions that distinguish
between different degrees at the upper end of the necessity scale.
16
A complete account of the various functions of modal thought would have to take into account the
findings of the considerable psychological literature on counterfactual thinking. See, for example, Au
(1992), Boninger, Gleicher, and Strathman (1994), Byrne (1997, 2002), Costello and McCarthy (1999),
Einhorn and Hogarth (1986), Ginsberg (1986), Hilton and Slugoski (1986), Johnson (1986), Kahneman and
Varey (1990), Mandel, Hilton, and Catellani (2005), Reilly (1983), Roese (1994), Roese and Olson (1993,
1995a, 1995b, 1995c), Sherman and McConnell (1996), Shultz and Mendelson (1975), Wells and Gavinski
(1989).
15
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
metaphysical theses at issue, let alone modal claims that capture the intended contents of
these theses.
Examples like this have motivated some philosophers to question the central role that
modality has played in metaphysical theories in the wake of the modal turn, and to hold
that that role should instead be given to (for example) grounding, essence, or
fundamentality. Maybe the best way of spelling out the idea that the A-facts are more
fundamental than the B-facts is in terms of grounding, and perhaps the distinctive feature
of the essential truths about a thing is their special explanatory role. Similarly, the truthmaker of a true claim P may be thought of as some entity whose existence (partly)
grounds the truth of P.17
I think that my account underwrites this shift of focus from the modal to the explanatory domain. On my view, modal facts aren’t metaphysically deep or fundamental in any
sense. They concern a relation of comparative closeness between certain complex classes
(the worlds) that is of no special metaphysical importance. We are ordinarily thinking
about this closeness ordering only because such thoughts serve useful functions like that
of mediating inferences between beliefs about explanatory relationships. Facts about
explanatory relationships, and facts about essence and the metaphysical laws, are more
fundamental than modal facts and are therefore better suited to form part of the subject
matter of metaphysics. At the same time, my theory makes it unsurprising that modal
considerations have figured so prominently in many philosophical debates whose
ultimate concern is with explanation. For it entails that some modal facts, e.g. certain
counterfactual dependencies and supervenience relationships, reflect important
explanatory connections (such as grounding relationships). Other modal facts reflect facts
about the essences of things or about the metaphysical laws, and the latter facts are of
interest because of their central explanatory role. Modal facts therefore constitute
important data. For example, a hypothesis about essence, grounding, or fundamentality
can be evaluated in part by its consistency with the relevant modal data and its ability to
explain them. In these cases, modal facts are not themselves the ultimate objects of
investigation. They are of interest solely in their role as evidence. I suspect that that is the
main way in which modal facts are important in metaphysics. (I will briefly consider
some of these implications of my account in section 7.2, and I say a little more about
them elsewhere, but it will remain a task for the future to develop them in detail.18)
17
For relevant discussions of supervenience, see Horgan (1993), Wilson (2005), Stoljar (2009), Dasgupta
(ms-b); for discussions of truth-making, see Restall (1996), Rodriguez-Pereyra (2006); for a discussion of
essence, see Fine (1994). For skepticism about the shift of focus to facts about metaphysical forms of
explanation, see Hofweber (2009).
18
See Kment (forthcoming).
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
16
1.5 The Question of Reduction
My account analyzes modality in terms of several properties and relations that have often
been taken to be modal (the most important ones are listed and briefly discussed below).
While I myself don’t believe that they are modal and therefore take my account of
modality to be reductive, it is beyond the scope of this book to argue for this conclusion
in detail. If I am wrong about this, then my account is non-reductive and it could no
longer be taken to show how modal facts are grounded in non-modal facts alone. But the
loss would be moderate, provided that the account traces what Peter Strawson (1992: 19)
called a “wide, revealing, and illuminating circle.” I think that the theory would still shed
light on questions about the interrelations between different modal properties, the way in
which modal facts are connected to facts about explanatory relations, and the function of
modal thought.
Essence and laws. It was common for a long time to define essentialist locutions in
modal terms.19 On this account, a is essentially F just in case it is impossible for a to exist
without being F. However, Kit Fine (1994) has argued, quite convincingly in my view,
that this characterization doesn’t adequately capture the essence–accident distinction. As
Fine points out, it is a necessary feature of the number 2 to be a member of the set {2}
and a necessary property of {2} to have 2 as a member. But while having 2 as an element
is part of what it is to be {2}, being a member of {2} is not part of what it is to be 2. The
distinction between essential and accidental truths about an object cuts more finely than
any modal distinction. Moreover, as we will consider in more detail from Chapter 7
onwards, it can be made plausible that modal facts are often explained by facts about the
essences of things. I think that these findings make it more promising to give an account
of modality in terms of essence than to pursue to the opposite order of analysis. The
discussion in the second half of this book is intended to provide further support for this
view.
The distinction between essence and accident is sometimes treated as obscure and
mysterious. I am not sure what to make of this charge. If the complaint is that talk of
essence is esoteric and removed from ordinary thought, then I think that it rests on a false
assumption. Essentialist idioms seem to be used frequently in everyday life, e.g. when we
talk about what makes a piece of music punk, what it is to be courageous, or what
happiness or justice consist in. Admittedly, there are different possible interpretations of
such utterances, but in each case it is easy to imagine a perfectly ordinary context in
which we can plausibly take them to express essentialist claims. Perhaps the worry is that
essence eludes our philosophical understanding. While I will argue that essence is
irreducible and indefinable in a sense to be explained, I think that we can gain a better
19
Fine (1994: 3) mentions Mill (1956: bk. I, ch. VI, sct. 2) and Moore (1922: 293, 302) as proponents of
this conception. Also see Kripke (1980), Plantinga (1974: chs. IV–V), and Forbes (1985: 96–100).
17
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
understanding of essence by describing its metaphysical role—in particular its role in
explanation. That is one of the topics of Chapter 6.
I regard the essential truths as a type of law, and I think that much of what I said in the
previous two paragraphs also applies, mutatis mutandis, to other kinds of (natural and
metaphysical) laws. The laws have distinctive modal features: they support counterfactuals and are associated with special forms of necessity. But I hope to make it
plausible that that is so because necessity and counterfactual dependence are defined in
terms of laws, not the other way around.20
Propositions. The entities I call “propositions” are the primary bearers of modal
properties and form the raw material for the construction of worlds. We can describe
these entities, at least to a first approximation, as structured complexes that represent
reality as meeting certain conditions. They are similar to Russellian propositions in being
constructed from the entities they are about (i.e., from the entities involved in the
conditions that they represent reality as satisfying).21 At the same time, they are like
sentences inasmuch as their representational features depend in a systematic way on what
their constituents are and on the ways these constituents are put together. This makes it
tempting to talk about them as if there were sentences and to use the rich resources of our
syntactic and semantic vocabulary to give a compositional account of how their
representational properties are determined. It is harmless to yield to this temptation (as I
will do when formulating my theory of propositions in Chapters 4 and 5), as long as we
bear in mind that semantic claims about propositions need not be taken literally, but can
be understood as exploiting a mere analogy to sentences.
Chapters 4 and 5 will present a non-modal theory of propositions as class-theoretic
constructions. I call the entities defined by this account “propositions” in part because of
their resemblance to Russellian propositions and in part for lack of a better term. But I
don’t mean to imply that the structured complexes that figure in my account can play the
full theoretical role of propositions. For example, I don’t claim that they can plausibly be
regarded as the contents of sentences (relative to contexts) or as the objects of attitudes
like belief or hope.22 (In fact, while I will continue to describe these complexes as having
representational features, that is not an essential part of my theory. What is essential is
merely that each complex is connected to a certain condition on reality. The precise
nature of that connection ultimately doesn’t matter. Instead of describing the complexes
as propositions that represent reality as meeting certain conditions, we could decide to
Is there a workable non-modal analysis of lawhood? I don’t know that there isn’t, but find the available
candidates not very satisfying. Perhaps the best option is to regard lawhood as fundamental (see Maudlin
2007: ch. 1).
21
For a well-developed account of propositions along Russellian lines, see Soames (1987, 1989).
22
See King, Soames, and Speaks (2014) for discussion of the question whether structured complexes like
those that figure in my theory can play the theoretical role of propositions.
20
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
18
say that the complexes are conditions on reality, although that would be a less convenient
form of expression.)23
Logical truth and entailment. My account of modality will appeal extensively to the
property of being a logical truth and the relation of logical entailment. (I will always use
“entailment,” “consequence,” “follow from,” etc. for logical entailment, not for the
weaker relation of metaphysical necessitation, and “consistency” for logical consistency,
not for metaphysical possibility.) I have no account of logical truth to offer. I am
somewhat attracted to the idea that the logical truths are those claims whose truth is in
some sense due to their logical forms, and given the aforementioned analogies between
sentences and propositions, this way of thinking about logic could be applied to
propositions as well as to sentences. But it doesn’t go very far in illuminating logical
truth. It leaves open the question of what logical form is and what it means to say that a
proposition owes its truth to its logical form, and I am not sure how these questions
should be answered. While I don’t think that there are strong reasons for thinking that
logical truth needs to be explained in modal terms, I won’t delve into this complex and
controversial issue. For even if it turns out that a general account of logical truth has to
appeal to modality, that wouldn’t frustrate the reductive aspirations of my project. We
could define a non-modal syntactic property that is coextensive with logical truth over the
domain of propositions and could then cast my analysis in terms of this property rather
than the property of logical truth.
1.6 A Guide for Selective Readers
The remainder of this book can be divided into the five parts described below. Each of
these is either self-contained or has a self-contained portion that can serve as an introduction to the respective part of my theory. It is recommended to read Chapter 1 before
turning to other parts of the book, as that will give the reader a mental framework that
might make it easier to assimilate the material of later chapters.
The analysis of modality. This part of the book comprises Chapters 2, 3, and 7.
Chapters 2 and 3 give an outline of the analysis of modality I will develop, provide some
initial motivation for it, highlight a number of its distinctive features, and discuss how it
can explain various data about modality. Combined with section 1.1, Chapters 2 and 3
form a self-contained unit that introduces my approach to modality. (It’s also possible to
read only section 1.1 and Chapter 2 to get an even briefer but less complete introduction
to my theory.) My accounts of metaphysical and nomic necessity are given in Chapter 7
and will presuppose some of the results of Chapter 6.
Of course, conditions in the relevant sense aren’t individuated modally (by necessary equivalence), but
much more finely than that. For example, the condition that two and two make four is not the same as the
condition that water (if it exists) has chemical structure H2O, despite the fact that the two conditions are
necessarily equivalent.
23
19
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
A theory of worlds. Chapters 4 and 5 present my account of worlds. I will defend the
thesis that facts about worlds are metaphysically contingent along a number of dimensions: Many worlds are contingent existents and some worlds (including some that are
very close to actuality) even fail to exist at themselves—if they had been actualized, then
they wouldn’t have existed. Which propositions are true at a given world w can also vary
between different possible worlds where w exists. Finally, the very property of being a
world is a contingent feature of many worlds: some worlds could have been non-maximal
situations rather than worlds. These results have noteworthy implications for our
understanding of actualization and iterated modality. Chapters 4 and 5 don’t presuppose
familiarity with earlier parts of the book (except in their respective final sections, which
can be skipped by readers only interested in the theory of worlds). To get an overview of
my approach to worlds it’s possible to read Chapter 4 by itself, although the account
presented there faces some problems that are only addressed in Chapter 5. Readers more
interested in the general approach to modality than in the account of worlds can skip
Chapters 4 and 5, except that they may want to take a brief look at section 4.3, which
introduces some logical principles that are occasionally applied in later chapters.
Essence, laws, and grounding. Chapter 6 presents the working account of essence,
grounding, and metaphysical fundamentality that I will use in my theory of modality and
counterfactual reasoning. This chapter can be read on its own, but it is important to bear
in mind that in this book my interest in essence and grounding is subsidiary to the main
goal of illuminating modality and its connection to explanation. Consequently, my aim in
Chapter 6 is not to develop a comprehensive theory of essentiality and grounding, but
only to give a rough working account. Many central questions in this area of metaphysics
will be left unanswered.
Counterfactuals and closeness to actuality. Chapters 8 and 9 form a fairly selfcontained part of the book that develops an analysis of comparative closeness to actuality
and a theory of counterfactuals. Chapter 8 states and motivates my view and can be read
on its own. Chapter 9 makes the account more precise and modifies it slightly, before
responding to a number of objections.
The function of modal thought. Chapters 10–12 present my theory of the purpose of
modal thinking. Chapter 10 explains the general approach I take in this part of the book
in an informal way and doesn’t require knowledge of the previous chapters. The more
detailed development of the theory in Chapters 11 and 12 will rely on the results of
Chapter 8. To a lesser extent, Chapter 11 will also draw on the material of Chapters 2 and
6, while section 12.3.2 will use findings from section 9.2. Readers who have read
Chapters 1 and 8 and sections 6.1.1, 6.2, and 6.4 and who have glanced over the rest of
Chapter 6 should have no difficulty following the gist of Chapter 11 and most of Chapter
12.
Readers who want more information about where to find what are advised to look at
the introductions to the individual chapters (or in the case of Chapter 10, at the intro-
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
20
duction together with section 10.1), which give brief overviews of the respective chapter
contents.
References
Adams, E. (1975), The Logic of Conditionals. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Au, T. (1992), “Counterfactual reasoning,” Semin & Fiedler (1992): 194-213.
Audi, P. (2012a), “A clarification and defence of the notion of grounding”. In
Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, ed. by F.
Correia and B. Schnieder. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Audi, P. (2012b), “Grounding: towards a theory of the in-virtue-of relation,” Journal of
Philosophy 109, pp. 685-711.
Baker, A. 2007, “A Counter on Counterpossibles”, The Reasoner 1, 7-8.
Bennett, J. (2003) A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals. Oxford: Clarendon.
Boninger, D., F. Gleicher, and A. Strathman (1994), “Counterfactual Thinking: From
what might have been to what may be,” Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 67: 297-307.
Brogaard, B. & J. Salerno 2007, “Why Counterpossibles are Non-Trivial”, The Reasoner
1, 5-6.
——. 2013, “Remarks on Counterpossibles”, Synthèse 190: 639–60.
Byrne, R. (1997), “Cognitive Processes in Counterfactual Thinking About What Might
Have Been,” in Medin (1997).
——. (2002) “Mental Models and Counterfactual Thoughts About What Might Have
Been,” Trends in Cognitive Science 6: 426–431.
Costello, T. and J. McCarthy (1999), “Useful Counterfactuals,” Linköping Electronic
Articles in Computer and Information Science, 3(2),
http://www.ep.liu.se/ea/cis/1999/002/ .
Daly, C. (2012), “Scepticism about grounding.” In Metaphysical Grounding:
Understanding the Structure of Reality, eds. F. Correia and B. Schnieder.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dasgupta, S. ms, “The Possibility of Physicalism”
Edgington, D. (2003) “Counterfactuals and the Benefit of Hindsight,” in Dowe and
Noordhof (2003), 12-27.
——. (2011). “Causation First: Why Causation is Prior to
Counterfactuals.” In Hoerl, C., T. McCormack and S. Beck, eds., Understanding
Counterfactuals, Understanding Causation: Issues in Philosophy and Psychology.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 230–241
21
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
Einhorn, H. and R. Hogarth (1986), “Judging probable causes,” Psychological Bulletin,
99: 3-19.
Fara, M. and T. Williamson (2005), “Counterparts and Actuality,” Mind 115.
Fine, K. (1994), “Essence and Modality,” Philosophical Perspectives 8, pp. 1-16
——. (2012a), “The pure logic of ground”, Review of Symbolic Logic
——. (2012b), “A guide to ground”. In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the
Structure of Reality, eds. F. Correia and B. Schnieder. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Forbes, G. (1982), “Canonical Counterpart Theory,” Analysis 42: 33-7.
——. (1985), The Metaphysics of Modality, Oxford (Clarendon)
——. (1987), “Free and Classical Counterparts: Response to Lewis,” Analysis 47: 14752.
——. (1990), “Counterparts, Logic and Metaphysics: Reply to Ramachandran,”
Analysis 50: 167-173.
Gibbard, A. and Harper, W. (1978), “Counterfactuals and Two Kinds of Expected
Utility,” in C. Hooker, J. Leach, and E. McClennen (eds.), Foundations and
Applications of Decision Theory, Dordrecht: Reidel, 125‐62.
Ginsberg, M. (1986), “Counterfactuals,” Artificial Intelligence 30: 35–79.
Hiddleston, E. (2005) “A Causal Theory of Counterfactuals.” Nous 39: 632-657.
Hofweber, T. 2009. “Ambitious, yet modest, metaphysics,” In Metametaphysics: New
Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, ed. by Chalmers, D., D. Manley and R.
Wasserman, 260–89. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Horgan, T. (1993), “From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands
of a Material World,” Mind 102, pp. 555-586.
Johnson, J. (1986), “The Knowledge of What Might Have Been: Affective and
attributional consequences of near outcomes,” Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin 12: 51-62.
Kahneman, D., and C. Varey (1990), “Propensities and counterfactuals: The loser that
almost won,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59: 1101-1110.
King,
Jeffrey C., "Structured Propositions", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/propositions-structured/>.
King, Jeffrey, S. Soames and J. Speaks (2014). New Thinking about Propositions. Oxford
University Press.
Kment, B. (2006), “Counterfactuals and Explanation.” Mind 115: 261-310.
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
22
——. (2012), “Haecceitism, Chance and Counterfactuals.” Philosophical Review
121: 573-609
——. (forthcoming) “Modality, Metaphysics, and Method,” to appear in C. Daly
(ed.), The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods, Palgrave/Macmillan.
Kripke, S. (1980), Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, Mass. (Harvard UP)
Lewis, D. (1968), “Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic,” Journal of
Philosophy 65: 113-26.
——. (1971), “Counterparts of Persons and Their Bodies,” Journal of Philosophy 68:
203-211.
——. (1973), Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
——. (1981), “Causal decision theory,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59: 5-30.
——. (1986a) “Counterfactual Dependence and Time’s Arrow,” in Lewis (1986a), 32–
66.
——. (1986b), On the plurality of worlds, Oxford (Blackwell)
Mandel, D., D. Hilton, and P. Catellani (eds.) (2005), The Psychology of Counterfactual
Thinking, International Series in Social Psychology.
Mares, E. (1997), “Who's Afraid of Impossible Worlds?”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal
Logic 38: 516-526.
Mares, E. and A. Fuhrmann (1995), “A Relevant Theory of Conditionals,” Journal of
Philosophical Logic 24: 645-65.
Mårtensson, J. (1999) Subjunctive Conditionals and Time. Acta Universitatis
Gothoburgiensis.
Medvec, Victoria H., Scott F. Madey and T. Gilovich (1995). “When Less Is More:
Counterfactual Thinking and Satisfaction Among Olympic Medalists.” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 69: 603–610.
Mill, J. S. (1956) A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. London/New
York: Longmans, Green.
Moore, G. E. (1922), “External and Internal Relations,” in: Philosophical Studies,
London (Routledge and Kegan), pp. 276-309.
Nolan, D. (1997), “Impossible Worlds: A modest approach,” Notre Dame Journal of
Formal Logic 38: 535-73.
Ramachandran, M. (1989), “An Alternative Translation Scheme for Counterpart Theory,”
Analysis 49: 131-41.
——. (1990a), “Contingent Identity in Counterpart Theory,” Analysis 50: 163-66.
——. (1990b), “Unsuccessful Revisions of CCT,” Analysis 50: 173-77.
Read, S. (1995), Thinking about Logic, Oxford: Oxford UP.
23
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
Reilly, J. (1983), “What are conditionals for?”, Papers and Reports in Child Language
Development 22.
Restall, G. 1996, “Truthmakers, entailment and necessity”, Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 74: 331–40.
Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. 2006. Truthmaking, entailment, and the conjunction thesis. Mind
115: 957–81.
Roese, N. (1994), :The Functional Basis of Counterfactual Thinking,” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 66: 805–818.
Roese, N. and J. Olson (1993), “The Structure of Counterfactual Thought,” Personality
and Social Psychology Bulletin 19: 312-319.
——. (eds.) (1995a) What Might Have Been: The Social Psychology of Counterfactual
Thinking, Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
——. (1995b), “Counterfactual Thinking: A Critical Overview,” in Roese & Olson
(1995a).
——. (1995c), “Functions of Counterfactual Thinking,” in Roese & Olson (1995a).
Rosen, G. (1990), “Modal Fictionalism,” Mind 99, pp. 327-54.
——. (2010), “Metaphysical dependence: grounding and reduction”, in Modality:
Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, eds. B. Hale and A. Hoffmann, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 109–135.
Routley, R. (1989), “Philosophical and Linguistic Inroads: Multiply Intensional Relevant
Logics,” in Norman & Sylvan (1989), Ch. 19.
Salerno, J & B. Brogaard (forthcoming), “Williamson on Counterpossibles”, The
Reasoner.
Salmon, W. (1984), “Scientific Explanation: Three General Conceptions,” in Asquith &
Kitcher (2004): 293-305.
Schaffer, J. (2009), “On What Grounds What,” in Chalmer et al. (2009), pp. 347-83.
Sherman, S., and A. McConnell (1996), “The role of counterfactual thinking in
reasoning,” Applied Cognitive Psychology 10: 433-444.
Shultz, T. & R. Mendelson (1975), “The use of covariation as a principle of causal
Analysis,” ChildDevelopment 46: 394-399.
Sider, T. 2011. Writing the Book of the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Slote, M. (1978) “Time in Counterfactuals.” Philosophical Review 87: 3–27.
Soames, Scott. (1989). “Semantics and Semantic Competence.” Philosophical
Perspectives, 3, Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory, Ridgeview Publishing
Company, Atascadero, CA, pp. 575–596.
Spirtes, P., C. Glymour, and R. Scheines (2000), Causation, Prediction, and Search, 2nd
Synopsis: Modality and Explanatory Reasoning
24
edition, Boston: MIT Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1968) “A Theory of Conditionals.” Studies in Logical Theory, American
Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series 2. Oxford: Blackwell, 98–112.
——. (1984), Inquiry, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
——. (1996), “Impossibilities”, Philosophical Topics, 24: 193–204.
Stoljar D. (2009), “Physicalism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009
Edition), ed. E. Zalta.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/physicalism/.
Strawson, P. F. (1992). Analysis and Metaphysics. Oxford University Press. London.
Tichý, P. (1976) “A counterexample to the Stalnaker-Lewis analysis of counterfactuals.”
Philosophical Studies 29: 271–273.
Wasserman, R. (2006) “The Future Similarity Objection Revisited.” Synthese 150: 57-67.
Wells, G. and I. Gavinski (1989), “Mental simulation and causality,” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 56: 161 - 169.
Williamson, T. (2007). The Philosophy of Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Wilson, J. ms, “No Work for a Theory of Grounding”
Witmer, D. G., W. Butchard, and K. Trogdon. 2005. “Intrinsicality Without Naturalness”.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70: 326–50.
Zalta, E. (1997), “A Classically-Based Theory of Impossible Worlds,” Notre Dame
Journal of Formal Logic 38: 640-660.