Globalization and
democratization in Brazil
an interpretation of Rawls's political liberalism
Nythamar de Oliveira*
As it was bluntly stated on the homepage of the Carnegie Council Program
on Justice and Global Economy, “[g]lobalization has become a buzzword for
the overarching economic, political, social, and cultural trends of the late
twentieth century. Considered from the perspective of social and economic
justice, however, globalization has had a mixed record of success, at best.”1
The mixed blessings of globalization came under attack on several occasions
such as the latest international summits in Europe and the Americas, and three
editions of the World Social Forum, held at Porto Alegre, Brazil, at the
____________
* A first draft of this paper was read at the Philosophisches Forum of the Universität Kassel, in a
seminar organized by Prof. Hans-Georg Flickinger in February 2003 and supported by the CAPESDAAD exchange program on “Social Movements and the Struggle for Citizenship Rights: A
Comparison between Brazil and Germany.”
1
Cf. http://www.carnegiecoumeil.org/themes/justice.html
Civitas, Porto Alegre, v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
40
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
threshold of this new century. From a Third World standpoint, it is not only the
opposition of labor and environmental activists that has made a strong
impression on public opinion, but an ever-growing anti-Davos unease through
the creation and fostering of alternative forums of public discussion that deal
with the complex phenomenon of globalization from a rather local perspective,
such as the civil society and its voluntary associations, unions, and nongovernmental organizations (NGOs). Although both unionists and NGOs in
Brazil tend to radically oppose what has been perceived as a neoliberal
imposition of globalization “from above” --global economy being reducible to
the interests of the G-7 and so-called developed nations--, workers’ and unionrelated organizations seek alternative economic ways to solve infrastructural
problems while educational, environmental, and most NGOs seem to be more
concerned about the moral transformations under way in our social, political
and economic institutions.2 Hence, what has been superficially identified with
an anti-globalization movement in Brazil refers us back to the broader question
of the normative grounds of democracy itself: “Why, after all, should we stand
up for democracy?” The shift from a 21-year military dictatorship to a full
constitutional democracy in Brazil was only inaugurated with the transfer of
power to a civilian president in 1985 and radicalized with the impeachment of
President-elect Collor in 1992, but democratization is still under way and has
indeed a long way to go, given the social inequalities, corruption, and
authoritarianism that haunt this nation. To the extent that those pathologies
have been tackled by globalization and the latter equated with the ongoing
democratization of institutions worldwide, the normative dimension of
globalization (“global justice”) can be said to translate the very challenges
faced by the Brazilian transition to democracy, particularly those taken up by
the civil society, social movements, and NGOs (“local action”). The main
problem of my research can be thus stated: “How can a political theory of
global justice account for local action within a political culture which is still in
the process of consolidating its constitutional-democratic institutions?” Starting
from liberal models of social democracy inspired by Immanuel Kant’s political
thought, such as the ones proposed by John Rawls and Jürgen Habermas,
without any partisan commitments to the different programs of the leftist
spectrum, I shall confine myself to what I term “the Brazilian reception of
Rawls’s political liberalism,” --in particular, to his contribution to a theory of
global justice (Pogge, 2000) and recent appropriations by Habermas and other
Rawlsian-inspired recasting of social democracy. It is my contention here that
the main challenge of global justice consists in making the normative
dimension of globalization work for the actual consolidation of democracy and
citizenship rights in the social, political, and economic institutions of so-called
____________
2
See Petersen and Souza, 2002; Sobottka, 2002.
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
41
emergent societies, such as Brazil. Hence, the comprehensive, global program
of claiming human rights locally, particularly in Brazil and developing
countries, reflects what in Rawlsian terms has been called an international
“reflective equilibrium” in the very putting into practice of the agendas of the
United Nations, the European Union, and hundreds of NGOs all over the
planet. Three main problems arise at the outset, corresponding to the three
main theses of my essay, namely: 1) Rawls’s political liberalism is more
defensible as a specifically political, freestanding conception of global justice,
as opposed to the cosmopolitan versions and comprehensive receptions of
“justice as fairness”; 2) since his later writings do not shift away from his
earlier theory of justice, but rather radicalize it and make it more defensible as
a noncomprehensive doctrine, the historical, sociocultural background of
societies that did not experience the full process of a bourgeois revolution or
liberal democracy do not have to follow any pregiven patterns of political
development but may always resort to the Rawlsian paradigm of an “original
position” at any given time, just as constitutional, administrative, and
institutional reforms bring into effect the appropriate changes to respond to the
ongoing claims of social movements, grassroots activism, human rights
militancy, and NGOs; 3) finally, the problem of an atomist-individualist
conception of self, supposedly inherent in Rawls’s liberal theory of justice, is
shown to give way to a more realistic view of human rights, allowing both for
non-Western, non-Eurocentric contributions and for a veritable, interactive coconstitution of citizenship and governance, on a local, national level and on a
global, international scenario, assured by the normative correlation of person
and society. The communitarian critique of liberalism can be thus shown to
have decisively contributed to making the liberal conception of constitutional
democracy even more defensible, as attest the latest writings by Rawls,
Habermas, and Bobbio, especially on the problem of juridification. In this
sense, I firmly believe that Rawls’s lasting contribution to political theory helps
us overcome the dialogue de sourds between those who insist on a minimum
state and those who inflate the social attributions of a centralized government.
By resorting to a theory of global justice that avoids the pitfalls of both
neoliberalism and state socialism, an attempt is made at recasting Rawls’s idea
of public autonomy within a society whose democratic institutions are still in
the making. I am drawing on Rawls’s trilogy to account for the defense of
social democracy in Brazil and its insertion in the globalizing process without
subscribing to a neoliberal agenda or succumbing to the universalistcommunitarian dilemma.
Brazilian political theorists seem to oscillate between two main alternative
discourses on the democratization under way in post-military Latin America: a
“dialectical” one which places the task of democratization in the reconstitution
42
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
of types of mediation between the private sphere and the state (including
popular organizations as well as institutions for political citizenship),
suppressed or deformed by bureaucratic-military regimes, and an “analytical”
one which regardless of all atomization, depoliticization, and manipulation of
society by the authoritarian state and the former’s tactics of survival and
resistance through solidary forms of association, stresses the social foundations
of civil society. (Cohen and Arato, 1992, p. 48-58) While one model starts
from the fact of transition (from a military, authoritarian to a civilian,
democratic regime), the other finds its starting point and thrust in the very
equation of civil society and freedom. As Francisco Weffort put it, “we want a
civil society, we need to defend ourselves from the monstrous state in front of
us. This means that if [civil society] does not exist, we need to invent it. If it is
small, we need to enlarge it... In a word, we want civil society because we want
freedom.” ( Stepan, 1989, p. 349) Although Cohen and Arato succeed in
problematizing these and other related approaches, especially by pointing to the
danger of demobilization entailed in a reduction of civil society to the political
sphere, their analysis of Latin American democratization seems to take for
granted the conception of “transition,” even if distinguished from and
conjugated with “processes of initiation, consolidation, and completion.”
Leonardo Avritzer has shown that theories of transition fail to account for the
Brazilian process of democratization insofar as they leave unexplained “1) the
problem of political continuity that manifests itself in the survival of an
authoritarian political culture; and 2) the problems that emerge from the theory
of transition’s inability to incorporate an adequate theory of civil society.”
(1995, p. 243) In other words, democratization must address both the question
of a public, political culture and the question of a civil society likely to bring
about structural transformations, including the transfer of power and the free
coordination of action. As Avritzer puts it, “democratization has to involve in
some form the political system’s submission to rules of publicity and control by
civil society.” To be sure, this problematic underlies the very attempt by Cohen
and Arato to recast a theory of civil society, which they define “as a sphere of
social interaction between economy and state, composed above all of the
intimate sphere (esp. the family), the sphere of associations (esp. voluntary
associations), social movements, and forms of public communication.” (1992,
p. ix)
By resorting to Rawls’s political, liberal theory of justice, as well as to his
correlated views of deliberative democracy and public autonomy, I would like
to argue for an idea of public reason that subscribes both to an autonomous,
discursive self-understanding of the Brazilian ethos for local action (say, an
agenda created by and for the sake of Brazilian civil society, traditional and
alternative social movements) and to a freestanding concept of justice which is
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
43
inseparable from its universalizable, co-constitutive principles of liberty,
equality, reciprocity and publicity. Given the Brazilian Kant Renaissance in
ethics and political philosophy, following the Marxist and Hegelian-inspired
liberationist movements of the 70’s and 80’s (of which liberation theologian
Leonardo Boff, the late educator Paulo Freire, and the President-elect, Luiz
Inácio Lula da Silva, were among the most important exponents), the
conjugation of freedom and equality, peace and justice, toleration and
participation, autonomy and solidarity, have become more and more appealing
for the construction of a Third Way that avoids the pitfalls of the Cold War
binary logic of exclusion. Even as one differentiates between “liberation” in a
broader social, philosophical use and in a strictly theological use --say, between
Latin American “liberation theology” and various conceptions of social
liberation--, the ideals of cosmopolitan democracy and global justice do
authorize a conception of liberation that refers not only to the social, historical
phenomenon comprising both catholic and protestant grassroots movements in
Latin American, but also to black movements, feminist movements, indigenous,
Palestinian, Irish, African, and many other ethnic, human-rights and base
movements from developed and Third World countries alike that claim to some
form of social, political emancipation. In effect, what was named “liberation
philosophy” in Latin America emerged out of the same social, political
concerns and philosophical presuppositions that characterized the theological
movement, which was ecumenical and global from its very beginnings in its
radical intent to reform anew the Church, as attest the early writings of Rubem
Alves, Gustavo Gutiérrez, and Leonardo Boff. From a philosophicaltheological standpoint, the term “liberation” cannot be separated from its
correlated terms “liberty” and “freedom” --and it is in this very etymological,
conceptual vicinity that we should recast the radical project of social justice vis
à vis its political liberal roots. It is my contention here that the challenges posed
by liberationist thought could not and still cannot be met by the reappropriation
of Marxist analysis alone, insofar as its properly ethical, political thrust is
compromised by a totalitarian conception of human autonomy and selfliberation. I propose instead that the reformulation of political liberalism and
social democracy may help us carry out the project of social justice through the
democratization of social, economic, and political institutions in emergent
societies, in Latin America and elsewhere. (de Oliveira, 2002) While Christian
approaches to philosophy seemed reluctant to take liberal democracy seriously
in most Third World countries, political philosophy in Europe and North
America failed to respond to the challenges of Neo-Marxist thought until the
publication of Rawls’s A Theory of Justice in 1971, the same year major
liberation theologians launched their manifestoes against the neoliberal
doctrine of development (desarollo) imposed “from above.” Just as the Roman
Catholic Church played a decisive role during the Old and New Republic
44
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
regimes in alliance with the ruling elites (respectively known as the
institutionalization of oligarchy, 1889-1930, and populism, 1930-1964),
significant segments of the Brazilian Church took sides with the poor and social
movements that defied the authoritarianism of the military period (1964-1985)
and consolidated the democratizing process after the 1988 Constitution. The
rise of the third sector, its integration with social movements and NGOs’
response to the challenges of globalization have paved the way for a new
conception of sustainable development and social responsibility, as the state
reforms and the participatory engagement of civil society point today to an
ever-growing awareness of active citizenship that goes beyond revolution and
philanthropy (Krischke, 2001; Sobottka, 2002). It is against this social
historical background that I should like to place some reflections on the
recasting of political liberalism.
Kant’s theory of justice and his ideal of global peace have been
appropriated by Rawls in such a pervasive way that for many social and
political thinkers it has become the sought-for key to strike a much desirable
balance between the radical changes advocated by the left (esp. social
movements such as the landless, sem-terra, who fight for a nationwide land
reform) and the consolidation of individual rights claimed by the right (esp.
judicial reviews, trade liberalization, and state reforms). Just as Marx and
Hegel dominated the Brazilian academic political debate in the 70s and 80s,
Hobbes and Kant have been rediscovered in the 90s, following the critique of
the reception of liberalism in Brazil and the collapse of historical socialism in
Eastern Europe. I firmly believe that this Brazilian reception of authors such as
Rawls and Habermas has succeeded in at least pointing to the possibility of a
philosophy of praxis that does not sacrifice the individual and the pluralism of
reasonable ends. Hence both Habermas’s and Rawls’s procedural projects of
democracy have been largely debated in Brazil, and a post-Kantian critique of
modern subjectivity has also found a great reception among Brazilians in
various analyses of social and political exclusion.3 As Anthony Pereira put it so
well, we must avoid reducing Brazil’s democratization to one of the two
extremes: the resurrection of a unified civil society against a despotic state (an
extreme society-centered argument) and a controlled liberalization “from
above” by agents within the state (state-centered account). (1997, p. 3) In this
sense, Rawls and Habermas are representative of the main insights into the
political-theoretical problematic that might be termed the “unfinished project of
democratization in Brazil.” For both Habermas’s and Rawls’s procedural
theories of justice and democracy have been largely debated in Brazil, with a
____________
3
The Kant Renaissance and the Rawls-Habermas reception in Brazil were largely debated at the
International Symposia on Justice held in 1997, 2000 and 2003.
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
45
view to calling into question the aporias of the so-called liberal-communitarian
debate in ethics and political philosophy, by proposing local practices of
individuation through a socialization that cuts across ethnic, gender, and
cultural identities, far beyond liberal theories of minority rights. It remains to
be seen how any critique of democratization and globalization may contribute
to the autonomous construction of civil society without reducing the
differentiation between state and economy to a merely strategic, instrumental
device. In Habermasian terms, strategic conceptions of power fail to grasp the
communicative grounds of social action, just as Rawls’s political liberalism
unmasks the shortcomings of both utilitarian and rational choice models to
account for the Brazilian challenges of bringing out “ethics in politics.”
As one re-examines Rawls’s and Habermas’s contributions to modern
political theory, in particular, their recasting of the Kantian universalizable
principle of autonomy and its political implications, one cannot fail to notice
how public reason lies at the heart of democratizing processes and is decisive
to the survival of constitutionally-grounded institutions in this new century.
Both Rawls and Habermas have critically appropriated Kant’s cognitivist,
universalist and emancipatory conception of moral autonomy so as to attempt
at an original understanding of publicity and political culture. Kant can thus be
said to stand as the arbiter between Rawls and Habermas –als Schiedsrichter
zwischen Rawls und Habermas, to paraphrase an article by the young Marx-just as Locke’s “liberal individualism” and Rousseau’s “popular sovereignty”
had been previously judged and arbitrated by Kant’s political philosophy of
justice.4 Like Rawls, Habermas shows that normativity must go beyond a
merely conventional level of morality and require the structural transformation
of legal and economic-administrative institutions so as to make possible the
very co-existence of democratic differentiated interests. Kant’s deontological
ethics is thus opposed to both utilitarian and eudaimonistic views of morality
and politics, as it serves to construct a nonmetaphysical, political conception of
justice (Rawls’s “political autonomy”) and an intersubjective conception of
autonomy (Habermas’s “discourse theory of morality and law”). Both Rawls
and Habermas start from a critical standpoint regarding Kant’s fact of reason so
as to account for the principle of autonomy in moral and political reasoning.
(Beiner and Booth, 1993) While Rawls seeks to recast the principle of
universalizability as a procedural test for maxims, Habermas reformulates
Kantian proceduralism in intersubjective, communicative terms. Unlike Rawls,
however, Habermas explicitly embraces Hegel’s critique of Kant in his
____________
4
Cf. “Luther als Schiedsrichter zwischen Strauβ und Feuerbach”, originally published in the
“Anekdota zur neuesten deutschen Philosophie und Publicistik”, Band II, 1884, in K. Marx and F.
Engels, Werke (Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1976), vol. 1, p. 26ff.
46
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
reconstruction of the latter’s proceduralism. Although I cannot recast the
Rawls-Habermas debate here, it is my contention that the Brazilian reception of
these authors can help us situating the pros and cons of both views as we seek
to justify, in nonmetaphysical terms, the normative grounds of democratization
in relation to the complex phenomenon of globalization. Hence both Rawls and
Habermas seem to be caught in the same aporia of reformulating the Kantian
conception of autonomy to account for the moral foundations of the political
(and hence of a liberal republicanism) without its metaphysical
presuppositions. (de Oliveira, 2000) For Kant, the essential character of law is
universality and the person who acts from duty attends to the universality of her
principle, i.e., one only acts on a maxim that she could will to be a universal
law (categorical imperative). While Habermas seeks to maintain both the
observer’s and the participant’s standpoints in a dual conception of society as
system and lifeworld, Rawls recasts his theory of justice within the framework
of an overlapping consensus whereby the reasonable pluralism of our liberal
democracies accommodate competing, comprehensive doctrines (moral,
religious, ideological). ( Pogge, 1989) Rawls proposes thus a public criterion of
justice for judging feasible institutional structures for a society in moral terms,
by endorsing the principles of equal liberty, fair equality of opportunities and
difference within a procedural device of representation (“original position”,
behind the “veil of ignorance”). (Rawls, 1993, p. 5f.; 1971, §§ 11, 14, 39)
The principles of justice can be fairly recast in a social-democratic model
that favors an egalitarian approach to public policies and a liberal defense of
human rights, pluralism, participatory citizenship, and social responsibility.
(Rawls, 1996; 2001) Such is the point of intersection of communitarian and
liberal accounts of a true democratic ethos. The recent debate opposing
Rawls’s political liberalism and Habermas’s deliberative democracy, besides
problematizing the taken-for-granted oppositions between universalism and
communitarianism, social contract and natural rights, has served also to enrich
our modern understanding of political culture. Rawls’s shift from the 1971
account of justice as fairness towards the later reformulations leading to his
1993 volume on political liberalism does indeed address this problem, inherent
in a hypothetical, contractarian procedure. Rawls’s theory of justice can thus
help us reconstruct modern civil society as the institutional component of a
postconventional democracy. Rawls’s earlier conception of deliberative
democracy and his later conception of a public political culture that promotes
justice in reflective equilibrium attest to civil society’s democratizing thrust in
a pluralist world. Although Rawls and Habermas can be identified as
“procedural universalists” as they resort to a normative, universalizable
conception of Kantian-inspired, public practical reason to justify the integration
and differentiation of institutions such as the family, civil society, state,
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
47
governmental and nongovernmental organizations, they disagree not only in
their procedural schemes (devices of representation) but also in their political
intent. While Rawls seeks to rescue the democratic radicalness of Rousseau’s
general will in its alliance with Lockean, toleration-oriented liberalism,
Habermas sets out to overcome the fin-de-siècle crisis of democracy, especially
the legitimation crisis that characterizes modern state, without falling back into
the aporias of a critique of ideology or falling prey to relativism, skepticism,
and historicism. Both thinkers have thrown a new light on the normative
grounds of social criticism, by reformulating the conception of social life forms
(political culture and lifeworld) and the conception of a free, moral person
(sense of justice and conceptions of the good). Both Rawls and Habermas
reappropriate Kant’s distinction between right/law and ethics, as they recast the
conception of a public normativity regulated by rational discursivity, shared by
all parties and guiding human, autonomous action in pluralist democracies.
Political questions are thus procedurally discussed according to devices of
representation (e.g., Rawls’s “original position” and Habermas’s “ideal speech
situation”) and grounded in a moral, normative and universalizable
argumentative construction. While Rawls’s political liberalism anchors in the
conception of a public political culture the “overlapping consensus” which
accounts for the contractarian, binding coexistence of reasonable,
comprehensive doctrines in social cooperation, Habermas seeks to articulate
the question of normativity with the social, political question of
institutionalization, in the very conception of an integrated model
differentiating the systemic world of institutions (defined by the ability to
respond to functional demands of the social milieu) from the lifeworld
(Lebenswelt, i.e. forms of cultural, societal and personal reproduction which
are integrated through norms consensually accepted by all participants).
Therefore, it is by the normativity inherent in a given public political culture
and lifeworld that social life is actualized, calibrated and balanced at the very
level of political institutions. Both Rawls and Habermas succeed in showing
that normativity must supersede a merely conventional stage of morality and
demand the structural transformation of legal and economic-administrative
institutions so as to make possible the coexistence of differentiated, democratic
interests. While the theory of communicative reason claims to provide us with
the foundations of meaning, reference, and truth or validity for both theoretical
and practical reason, Rawls’s theory of public reason is confined to the political
conception of justice, particularly addressed to the basic structure of society,
understood as a liberal-democratic unified system of social cooperation
between moral, free persons. Hence “public reason” in Rawls cannot be simply
equated with Habermas’s “public sphere.” Although both attend to the
intersubjective constitution of the social world, we must keep their differences
in their conception of publicity–which Rawls formulates in terms of both a
48
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
political culture and a background culture. Grosso modo, the Brazilian
reception of these authors’ conception of political culture has been very
positive, although Rawls’s contractarianism has been perceived as inadequate
for a society so far from being well ordered, whose concrete mechanisms of
exclusion seem to prohibit any idealized view of social contract. Even though
Rawls’s liberalism is explicitly qualified as “political,” in contrast with
economic neoliberalism, its has fallen prey to the charges of historicism (i.e.
that the historical conditions allowing for the emergence of a democratic,
public political culture are hard to be conceived in a nonliberal society unless
one resorts to an idealized, suprahistorical model). Because of its original
affiliation with the Frankfurt School and the critique of ideology, the
Habermasian model of a critical theory of society seems thus more fruitful for
the analysis of Brazilian democratization. Since Habermas views modernity as
a complex, rational integration of moral, political, and aesthetic culture against
the background of differentiated, public spheres of action (state, market,
culture), his conception of societal modernization seems to allow for a better
understanding of democratization and the emergence of Brazilian civil society.
As Avritzer remarks,
Processes of modernization encompass deep transformations in the forms of
organization at the everyday life level due to the introduction of impersonal forms
of coordination of social action. These transformations have one main impact on
society: they change century-old social practices and lead to the loss of control over
one’s everyday life. Forms of limitation on the impersonal coordination of
economic action became the solution found within modernity to offset the loss of
freedom at this level. Authoritarianism in Brazil was part of a project of systemic
modernization which introduced impersonal forms of action coordination without
allowing for the emergence of forms of citizenship which could offset this
interference with traditional forms of everyday life organization. (1996, p. 245)
It is, to my mind, at this very intersection of human social nature and
citizenship that the conception of a public political culture should be
formulated. Of course, the concept of political culture is very complex and has
been the object of more than sixty-five definitions. According to Stephen
Chilton (1991), nine criteria for the conceptualization of political culture arise
from comparitive studies in political behavior, culture, and sociology:
supramembership, sharedness, behavioral, postbehavioral, unrestricted
applicability, nonreductionism, comparability, objective testability. I am
adopting here a succint definition, proposed by Charles Taylor (1985, p. 52),
according to whom political culture is “the intersubjective and common
meaning embedded in political actors’ practices.” Any radical critique of power
would go even further and link authoritarian modernization to normalizing
techniques that might help us account for the persistence of subjugating forms
of social control, not only from above and centralized power, but everywhere
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
49
and at all levels of social networks. Ironically enough, Avritzer concludes, in
the same text, “thus power and knowledge were utilized throughout a process in
which state and market actors attempted to create a modern society without
acknowledging social actors’ identity as members of economic, civil, and
political society.” (1996, p. 248) Habermas and Rawls ultimately agree on the
self-determination of the modern philosopher who can no longer remain
indifferent to the political, historical events of her own times.
In order to articulate a reconstruction of “a differentiated, pluralist, and
modern civil society” with “a political culture mature enough to accept the
promise and risks of liberal and democratic citizenship,” Cohen and Arato
carefully investigate liberal, communitarian, and radical concepts of democratic
state and society. In particular, they explicitly embrace Habermas’s critical
theory, as an alternative view to Rawls’s political liberalism, so as to
“accommodate the negative phenomena associated with modern civil society”
in alternative postmodernist criticisms. Habermas’s conception of deliberative,
participatory democracy is thus endorsed as a more adequate model than the
ones proposed by both liberals and communitarians to be linked to the
normative grounds of a theory of civil society that accounts for both civil
disobedience and social movements. However, as pointed out by feminist
critics such as Seyla Benhabib (1992) and Nancy Fraser (1998), Habermas
tends to undermine the intersubjective basis of his own theory either by
confining its publicity to a historically, socially determined identity (European
male) or by mimicking the other of a supposedly communicative reason in the
functionalist colonization of marginal lifeworlds. Together with the question of
normativity, the problem of the self was the punctum dolens of the RawlsHabermas debate and remains far from a satisfactory thematization, especially
from the standpoint of those who are underrepresented in such debates. Hence
the appeal of a radical critique of liberal reason to so-called “peripheral”
societies, as the Neo-Marxist, economic metaphor of the 1970s still serves to
characterize the political, cultural “dependency” of Latin America vis à vis
global neoliberalism. In effect, it is in the post-ideological vacuum in the
aftermath of the Cold War that liberals, communitarians, and radicals have
attempted to rethink and redefine the role and limits of the state and civil
society in Brazil, with a view to avoiding extremes in either direction.
(Krischke, 2001)
To my mind, the critical appropriation of liberal and communitarian models
in Brazil must take into account not only the empirical specificities of the
democratizing processs, but also the theoretical limitations of most attempts at
making sense of normativity within the social sciences. This can be particularly
perceived in the judiciary and legislative debates, as well as in the tremendous
challenges posed by sustainable development both to public policies and to the
50
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
regulation of small, socially responsible enterprises. Hans-Georg Flickinger
(1986) has convincingly pointed to the contradictions and shortcomings
inherent to the juridification of liberal democracy, of which Brazilian
democratization is no exception. Flickinger is particularly critical of the subtle,
oft-neglected tendency of democratic, political liberalism to evolve into a “total
institution,” increasing the social exclusion and making almost impossible to
believe in the effective success of social movements and grassroots claims, as
witness both the landless movements and the very starving, miserable victims
of famine in Northeastern Brazil (targeted by Lula’s ongoing Projeto Fome
Zero). Hence the apparent advantage of communitarian models over its liberal
counterparts, insofar as the public, social welfare is concerned. (Flickinger,
2003)
Although social movements, such as community-based (CEBs) and
liberationist grassroots movements in the seventies and the landless (sem-terra)
movement of the nineties, together with multi-party opposition and NGOs,
were decisive in bringing about radical transformations for democratization,
Brazilian society paradoxically remained until recently subordinate to the state,
even in their subtle reproduction of an authoritarian culture. Hence clientelism,
paternalism, corporativism, populism, demagogy and various forms of
corruption seem to betray a hegemonic political culture that survived and
permeated the military discourse on “modernization” and “development,” its
“liberationist” antagonists, and its “liberalizing” successors. The1988
constitution (Brazil’s fifth), the bureaucratic-administrative reforms and the
land reform under way, attest to this participatory democratic process which
has also called into question the agenda of political parties and politicians in
their interventions between civil society and state. Witness as well the political,
social changes brought about by the Workers’ Party (PT) on the local
experience of “participatory budget” (orçamento participativo) in several parts
of the country, but especially through the mayoral administration of the city of
Porto Alegre for four consecutive terms and the current federal government’s
efforts to carry out state administrative reforms.
To be sure, neither the more radical socialists nor moderate socialdemocrats were imune to the vices of authoritarianism, and the public opinion
has proved rather skeptical about the programmatic, social solutions offered by
different parties traditionally associated with the left, on the three levels of
municipal, state, and federal offices. And yet, criticism and skepticism point
also to some maturity in terms of political behavior. For an entire conception of
political development is at stake in these analyses that seek to evaluate how the
mass media, public opinion, and voters themselves concur to repudiate or
embrace certain values linked to political events. The fundamental concept of
public autonomy, so cherished by both Rawls and Habermas, has become one
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
51
of the touchstones of Brazilian political philosophy in the nineties and has been
brought to the fore through some of the most basic democratic notions such as
citizenship and deliberative participation. It is particularly important to recall
that, prior to the globalization awareness of the late nineties, a moralizing turn
was taking place in Brazilian politics as early as 1992, under the motto “ethics
in politics” culminating in the impeachment of an elected President.
(Rosenfield, 1992) It would be as naive to assume that those local political
events did not reflect global economic trends as the other way round. Above
all, and beyond all the empirical contingencies entailed by such analyses, a
representative democratic behavior means that democracy cannot ever be taken
for granted, and must be thus regarded as a dynamic process in which the
inclusive, pluralist claims of civil society condition and are conditioned by
complex forms of active, political participation. The democratization of
societies such as the Brazilian one coincides thus with the globalization of
economic systems and the changes within political structures that have been
gradually restoring (or establishing) the rule of law through constitutional
procedures as well as the call for a sustainable development and social
responsibility.5 Hence the resort to the Kantian idea of perpetual peace, recast
by both Rawls and Habermas, in an attempt to articulate state law and
international law in a globalized scenario. According to Kant, the abolition of
war is the ultimate goal of the system of law, within a cosmopolitan perspective
that brings about the constitutional stability of nations that subscribe to the
liberal principles of republican democracy. Just as state law and international
law bring about the rule of law (Rechtsstaat) within one particular nation and
among several nations, cosmopolitan law brings the state of nature to an end by
the institution of a universal federation of nations (Völkerbund). (Rawls, 2001)
Both Rawls and Habermas have addressed the challenge of global justice for
emergent societies that still face the Kantian predicament of an unsociable
sociability without the taken-for-granted human rights that characterize welfare
states and egalitarian, liberal democracies. The inhuman face of capitalism is
now, more than ever, unmasked in the exploitation and social exclusion of
women and children in many societies that provide cheap labor and raw
material for industrialized countries. In this sense, the challenge of
multiculturalism in Brazil provides us with theoretical perspectives on
ethnicities and social policies so as to account for the paradigm of a multiracial
society that responsibly deals with racial and social inequalities to be overcome
in the very process of democratization, even as democracy becomes the true
currency of globalization. Miscegenation, which turns out to be a distinctive
feature of Brazilian multiracial identity, is thus explored as a subversion of the
very myth of “racial democracy”, as accommodation gives way to
____________
5
In Brazil, Ethos Institute remains a national reference. Cf. the site: http://www.ethos.org.br
52
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
transformation in inter-racial relations. Comparative studies of US and
Brazilian slavery systems and racial ideologies have shown that although
segregation and miscegenation led to radically opposing outcomes (grosso
modo, the civil conquests of black movements in the US and the tacit
acceptance of “whitening” as a vehicle of social mobility for Afro-Brazilians),
the Brazilian experience of democracy ultimately demands an egalitarian
extension of freedom to all peoples of color that will or already constitute the
majority population. (Andrews, 1991) Afro-American transnational identity in
Latin American and Caribbean social groups turns out to be one of the greatest
examples of cultural resiliency in the world, but the same concept may as well
be extended to other ethnicities across Brazil, such as Latinos, Jews, Arabs, and
numerous native American peoples.
In conclusion, what is at stake is a political-theoretical problem, namely, the
attempt to account for both democratization and its undermining contradictions
in the process of the rationalization of complex forms of social life, as well as
to account for the fact that we did not have either a political-liberal nor a
nationwide revolutionary experience in Brazil. Moreover, anyone who sets out
to think “civil society”, “democracy” and “modernity” in Brazil has to face the
challenge of avoiding, on the one hand, the facile importation of European and
North-American categories uncritically applied to a Brazilian context, and the
aporetic, self-deceptive attempt to create ex nihilo, in the pseudo-originality of
reinventing the wheel. For the better or for the worse, we must always start in
medias res, from what we are: a racist, sexist, and elitist society with a
tremendous potential for self-overcoming and social transformation. Hence
both bureaucratic-administrative reforms and judicial reforms under way attest
to this participatory democratic process which has also called into question the
agenda of political parties and politicians in their interventions between civil
society and state. In effect, the very role of opposition in post-military Brazil
has been one of the targets of serious social criticism. As Roberto Mangabeira
Unger (1995, p. 240f) put it so well:
There are two ways that a transformative politics can be disparaged. One is to give
in entirely to the maxim that politics is the art of the possible. If you always respect
the limits of the possible and cultivate the image of the realist, you end up a
prisoner to the established system of interests and prejudices. This way is to submit,
as the majority of socialist and workers’ parties in the rich Western democracies
have done. They have tried to humanize the existing order rather than to remake it.
On the other hand, whoever loses touch with unyielding realities becomes
disoriented in the vacuum of loose utopias. This was the fate of sectarian and
revolutionary leftists throughout the course of the twentieth century. We have had
too few examples in the twentieth century of a left that, treading the narrow path
between these opposing dangers, has insisted upon testing the limits of the possible.
The PT [Brazilian Workers’ Party] has been one of these examples.
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
53
Without any pretensions to having solved or even addressed all the
problems raised by these debates between Habermasians and Rawlsians, or
lying at the transition from authoritarian Brazil to a democratic society, I have
outlined some thoughts on global justice and normativity which relate to a
broader problematic, namely, that of redefining the role and identity of civil
society in the unfinished project of “democratizing Brazil.” It is important thus
to stress that the question of “who we Brazilians are” –the question of
collective, national subjectivity thematized by Rawls and Habermas-- cannot
avoid the tension between what we have been, what we shall become, and what
we ought to be. For the question of collective self-identity lies at the heart of a
self-understanding of aesthetic, moral, and political culture --even beyond the
traditional conceptions of the nation-state. If we want to find the grounds for
the “self-reassurance” necessary to carry out a project of emancipation --in
Brazil as elsewhere-- the wholistic approach to reason and action must integrate
everyday social life, and this requires some commitment on the part of civil
society to reaching understanding about validity claims. This is perhaps the
secret utopia of the Habermasian fusion of the horizons of solidarity and
autonomy, between facts and norms, and undoubtedly the secret to his success
among social-democrats and the advocates of the Third Way in Brazil. If Rawls
fails to provide us with a substantiated account of the intersubjectively
constituted liberal culture that carries out the democratic ideals of his theory of
justice, Habermas reconceives “public autonomy” as “the availability of a
differentiated network of communicative arrangements for the discursive
formation of public opinion and will,” as a system of basic individual rights
“provides exactly the conditions under which the forms of communication
necessary for a politically autonomous constitution of law can be
institutionalized.” (1992, p. 134-5, 207-9) Brazilian citizens have certainly
been socialized into a rather corrupt political culture, so full of contradictions
and shortcomings when compared to the normative, regulative ideals of the
democratic yardstick. And yet, this making of a political culture is only
sustained to the extent that Brazilians also produce and reproduce such a
culture. The shift from a hypocritical “racial democracy” towards a societal,
pluralist democracy is the only way out of the “elitist liberalism” of both
military and civilian calls to modernize Brazil. Just as the aestheticist
regionalism and nationalism of the modernist movement of the 1920s gave way
to a technocratic, nationalist modernization in the 1950s and 1960s only to
highlight the oligarchic, hierarchical relations of power that made Brazil one of
the most socially unequal nations of the planet, a moral revolution from below
alone can secure the rule of law for all and call for a public, democratic
distribution of primary goods. If Brazil remains too far from a well ordered
society and public participation in the bargain processes is still remote from the
majority of the population, the political thrust of social movements and civil
54
Civitas – Revista de Ciências Sociais v. 4, nº 1, jan.-jun. 2004
disobedience meets a fortiori the normative criteria of a concept of democracy
that defies and transgresses any “power that be” for the sake of the people. That
the outcast in Brazil discover their own identity as citizens, rights-bearers or as
end-in-themselves only attests to the proximity between Rousseau and Kant in
both radical and liberal formulations of the volonté générale and the kingdom
of ends, between Habermas and Rawls. Hence a radical critique of state and
society is not necessarily opposed to the regulative ideals of a procedural
theory of justice. Whether politics is simply a continuation of the war of all
against all or a consensus-seeking overcoming of the state of nature, what is at
stake is precisely what is lacking (justice) and yet we seek by all reasonable
means to make it possible. In order to carry on our reflections on the limits of
the possible, Brazilian civil society must thus continually renew every critique
of its own identity, past and present, so as to allow for both freedom and justice
to flourish and radically transform itself.
References
George Reid Andrews, Black and White in São Paulo, Brazil, 1888-1988. University of
Wisconsin Press, 1991.
Leonardo Avritzer, “Transition to Democracy and Political Culture: An Analysis of the
Conflict between Civil and Political Society in Post-Authoritarian Brazil,”
Constellations 2/2 (1995): 242-267.
Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in
Contemporary Ethics. New York: Routledge, 1992.
Nancy Fraser, Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the “Postsocialist”
Condition. New York and London: Routledge, 1997.
Ronald Beiner and William J. Booth, eds., Kant and Political Philosophy: The
Contemporary Legacy. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1993.
Stephen Chilton, Grounding Political Development. Boulder: Lynne Rienner
Publishers, 1991.
Jean Cohen and Andrew Arato, Civil Society and Political Theory. Cambridge: MIT
Press, 1992.
Hans-Georg Flickinger, “The paradox of political liberalism: The juridification of
democracy” (in Portuguese) Filosofia Política 3 (1986): 117-129.
_____. Em nome da liberdade: Elementos da crítica ao liberalismo contemporâneo.
Porto Alegre: Edipucrs, 2003.
Jürgen Habermas, Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und
des demokratischen Rechtsstaats. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1992.
_____. “Morality and Ethical Life: Does Hegel’s Critique of Kant Apply to Discourse
Ethics?” (1983), reprinted in Beiner and Booth, 1993.
N. de Oliveira – Globalization and democratization in Brazil:...
55
Paulo Krischke, The Learning of Democracy in Latin America: Social Actors and
Cultural Change. Huntington: Nova Science, 2001.
Nythamar de Oliveira, Tractatus ethico-politicus. Porto Alegre: Edipucrs, 1999.
_____. “The Critique of Public Reason Revisited: Kant as Arbiter between Rawls and
Habermas,” Veritas, 44/4 (2000): 117-142.
_____. “Desconstruindo a Libertação: Teoria e Praxis, Teocomunicação 32/135 (2002):
155-178.
Anthony Pereira, The End of the Peasantry. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press,
1997.
Nokolai Petersen and Draiton G. Souza (eds.), Globalisierung und Gerechtigkeit. Porto
Alegre: Edipucrs, 2002.
Thomas Pogge, Realizing Rawls. Ithaca: Cornell, 1989.
_____. “The Moral Demands of Global Justice,” Dissent 47/4 (2000): 37-43.
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press, 1971.
_____. “Themes in Kant’s Moral Philosophy” (1983), reprinted in Beiner and Booth
1993.
_____. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia, 1996.
_____. The Law of Peoples. Harvard University Press, 2001.
Denis Rosenfield, A Ética na Política. São Paulo: Brasiliense, 1992.
Emil Sobottka (ed.) Organizações e Movimentos Sociais. Civitas 2/1 (2002).
Alfred Stepan, ed., Democratizing Brazil: Problems of Transition and Consolidation.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989.
Charles Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1985.
Roberto Mangabeira Unger, “The 3rd of October 1994 and the Future of Brazil’s
Workers’Party (PT)” Constellations 2/2 (1995): 224-241.
Texto recebido em 16.01.04 e aprovado em 30.03.04