The Constitution of Social Practices
Practices – specific, recurrent types of human action and activity – are perhaps
the most fundamental “building blocks” of social reality. This book argues that
the detailed empirical study of practices is essential to effective social-scientific
inquiry. It develops a philosophical infrastructure for understanding human practices, and argues that practice theory should be the analytical centrepiece of social
theory and the philosophy of the social sciences.
What would social scientists’ research look like if they took these insights
seriously? To answer this question, the book offers an analytical framework to
guide empirical research on practices in different times and places. The author
explores how practices can be identified, characterised and explained, how they
function in concrete contexts and how they might change over time and space.
The Constitution of Social Practices lies at the intersection of philosophy,
social theory, cultural theory and the social sciences. It is essential reading for
scholars in social theory and the philosophy of social science, as well as the broad
range of researchers and students across the social sciences and humanities whose
work stands to benefit from serious consideration of practices.
Kevin McMillan is Associate Professor in the School of Political Studies at the
University of Ottawa, Canada.
Philosophy and Method in the Social Sciences
Series Editor
Phil Hutchinson, Manchester Metropolitan University, UK
Engaging with the recent resurgence of interest in methodological and philosophical
issues in the human and social sciences, this series provides an outlet for work
that demonstrates both the intellectual import of philosophical and methodological debates within the social sciences and their direct relevance to questions of
politics, ethics or policy. Philosophy and Method in the Social Sciences welcomes
work from sociologists, geographers, philosophers, anthropologists, criminologists and political scientists with broad interest across academic disciplines, that
scrutinises contemporary perspectives within the human and social sciences and
explores their import for today’s social questions.
https://www.routledge.com/Philosophy-and-Method-in-the-Social-Sciences/
book-series/ASHSER1373
Titles in this series
Wittgenstein among the Sciences
Wittgensteinian Investigations into the ‘Scientiic Method’
Rupert Read, Edited by Simon Summers
(Ashgate, 2012)
Clarity and Confusion in Social Theory
Taking Concepts Seriously
Leonidas Tsilipakos
(Ashgate, 2015)
Evolution, Human Behaviour and Morality
The Legacy of Westermarck
Edited by Olli Lagerspetz, with Jan Antfolk, Ylva Gustafsson and Camilla
Kronqvist
The Constitution of Social Practices
Kevin McMillan
The Constitution of Social
Practices
Kevin McMillan
First published 2018
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
2018 Kevin McMillan
The right of Kevin McMillan to be identiied as author of this work has been
asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright,
Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in
any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing
from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identiication and explanation
without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Names: McMillan, Kevin, author.
Title: The constitution of social practices / Kevin McMillan.
Description: 1st Edition. | New York : Routledge, 2018. | Series: Philosophy
and method in the social sciences | Includes bibliographical
references and index.
Identiiers: LCCN 2017019485| ISBN 9781138894617 (hardback) |
ISBN 9781315179902 (ebook)
Subjects: LCSH: Social sciences—Philosophy.
Classiication: LCC H61 .M4823 2018 | DDC 300.1—dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017019485
ISBN: 978-1-138-89461-7 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-1-315-17990-2 (ebk)
Typeset in Times New Roman
by Swales & Willis Ltd, Exeter, Devon, UK
For Jas, Soren & Josha
Contents
List of figures
ix
Introduction
1
1 A “cultural” approach to social science 2
2 Practice theory today 4
3 Core ontological commitments 8
4 Sketch of the argument 10
5 Of philosophy and social science 14
1 What are practices?
20
1 Actions under a description 22
2 Looping effects 28
3 Historical constitution 30
2 Knowledge
36
1 Knowledgeable practices 36
2 Conceptualising knowledge 40
3 Retroactive redescription
61
1 The validity of retroactive redescription 64
2 The effects of retroactive redescription 68
3 Functional concepts and typological classiication 73
4 What is at stake? 78
4 Identification and context
1 Identifying practices “in all their speciicity” 85
2 Relations and relational properties 88
3 Criteria of identiication 92
85
viii Contents
5 Specificity and generalisation
103
1 Functions 103
2 Implications for generalisation, explanation
and description 111
3 Patchwork holism 118
6 Possibility and capacities
123
1 Possibility 123
2 Capacities 131
7 Constitutive relations and constitutive theory
145
1 Constitutive theory 145
2 Constitutive relations 146
3 Stability and change 152
Conclusion
157
1 Culture and action in the social sciences 158
2 Some beneits of studying practices 162
Works cited
Index
174
190
Figures
2.1
2.2
2.3
3.1
3.2
6.1
8.1
Are relations among concepts “internal relations”?
“Foucault’s fork”
The sincerity of discourse and the psychoanalytic stance
The signiicance of actors’ categories
The difference (“explicit”) concepts make
Observing intentional actions
“Individualism” and social explanation
44
50
53
63
65
133
166
Introduction
Thinkers once spoke of ‘structures’, ‘systems’, ‘meaning’, ‘life world’,
‘events’ and ‘actions’ when naming the primary generic social thing.
Today, many theorists would accord ‘practices’ a comparable honour.
Theodore Schatzki, “Practice Theory”
So begins the introduction to a much-cited volume advocating a “practice turn” in
contemporary social theory (Schatzki, Knorr Cetina and von Savigny 2001: 1). I
think these anonymous theorists are on the right track. Human practices are a fundamental constituent – arguably “the” fundamental constituent – of social reality.
This book attempts to develop the implications of this observation for the social
sciences. It therefore seeks to demonstrate the considerable potential fertility –
both theoretical and empirical – of a research programme centred on historical
practices. It suggests that the empirical social sciences and humanities would reap
considerable rewards from paying more systematic attention to practices as an
object of analysis.
In some quarters, a claim like this is likely to meet something of a paradoxical
response: some are liable to see it as rather obscure, others as utterly trite. This
book seeks to show that it is neither. For the puzzled reader, it proposes an original, systematic framework for how we might conceptualise, theorise, identify and
study human practices. For the jaded reader – the one who wonders what social
scientists have been studying for the past century if not human behaviour, and
considers “practice-talk” a hazy and contrived redescription of something wellstudied and entirely familiar – it offers a detailed discussion of the distinctiveness
and relative merits of the practice approach as conceived in these pages. To both
readers, and to others besides, it offers analysis and illustration of the approach’s
conceptual, epistemological and methodological implications, and of the speciic
beneits social scientists and historians might expect to gain from adopting it.
This book thus represents one effort to provide a methodical response to some
of the elementary questions raised by David Stern in his survey of the “practical
turn” in social theory and the social sciences:
2
Introduction
What is “practice theory”? The best short answer is that it is any theory that
treats practice as a fundamental category, or takes practices as its point of
departure. Naturally, this answer leads to further questions. What is meant by
“practices” here? What is involved in taking practices as a point of departure
or a fundamental category, and what does that commitment amount to? And
what is the point of the contrast between a practice-based theory and one that
starts elsewhere?
(Stern 2003: 185)
These are important questions, and they deserve a clear and relected response. In
answering them, this book aims to promote and contribute to “practice theory” –
to the lively and burgeoning literature of the past two decades applying an analytical emphasis on practices to the empirical and theoretical study of the social
sciences.1 But its ambitions are not limited to supplying an application, synthesis
or reinement of existing “practice theory”, for it aims to strike out in a rather new
direction, and to build a coherent and original theory of practices from the ground
up. The differences begin already with the irst step of the argument, for this book
starts from a somewhat idiosyncratic conception of what practices are in the irst
place. From this point of entry, it constructs an interlocking series of arguments
about the basic nature of practices and about the implications of this nature for
their effective empirical investigation. Thus, this book hopes to lay certain philosophical, theoretical and methodological foundations for substantive empirical
research on the practices of human social life.
The arguments of this book are intended to have a very wide-ranging scope.
They suggest that, done well and done carefully, the systematic analysis of historical practices has much to contribute to virtually all substantive realms and topics
in the social sciences and humanities. At its best, such analysis will prompt new
questions, provide new perspectives, suggest new connections, encourage new
conceptualisations of phenomena, stimulate new avenues of research and draw
attention to new and previously unnoticed phenomena in social-scientiic inquiry.
One of the aims of this book is to show, through argument and example, how such
broad and diverse consequences might be expected to follow.
1 A “cultural” approach to social science
In its emphasis on practices, this book attempts to promote the possibility, power
and signiicance of a broadly “cultural” approach to the social sciences. I do not
mean to hang much on the word itself. “Culture” is a vague, multifarious and
contested term, and is not one that features prominently in my own work. (Like
some anthropologists, I would rather stick to the adjective and typically avoid the
nominal form.)2 Here I use it instead as a loose, generic and convenient way to
refer to a diverse family of approaches to the study of the social world. Speaking
very generally, these heterogeneous approaches tend to be variously sensitive,
inter alia, to the symbolic, ideological, representational, discursive, practical,
ritualistic, identitarian, relexive, normative, affective, aesthetic, unconscious,
Introduction 3
quotidian, conventional, artefactual, relational, interactional, contextual and
constitutive dimensions of social life. (Elsewhere in the book I occasionally make
generic reference to “cultural phenomena”; it is elements such as these that are
broadly intended.) These approaches are centrally interested, that is, in patterns in
the action and in the materially manifest forms of thought of people in particular
times and places.3
Without denying the signiicance of other emphases, this book suggests that
the relationship between human practices and human knowledge ought to be the
analytical centrepiece of “cultural” approaches to the social sciences. Again without dismissing alternatives, it also argues that “cultural” approaches, understood
in this sense, are not just one option among others in the social sciences; they are
analytically essential to the study of social phenomena in general. It advances a
series of arguments in support of this position, along with a detailed investigation
of the broad nature and implications of the practice–knowledge relationship.
Many, though not all, “cultural” approaches to social research position themselves outside of the traditional epistemological conventions of the social sciences.4
It is customary within the social sciences to group these conventions under the
label of “positivism”. This label is extremely vague and problematic, and on any
careful construal almost certainly false; for familiarity and brevity, on the other
hand, it has no going rival. I accept it therefore for the purposes of briely characterising this book’s epistemological stance, which is resolutely non-positivist,
indeed probably anti-positivist, in the aforementioned sense of that term. That is
to say that it straightforwardly rejects, among other things, the presumed necessity
and/or superiority of the hypothetico-deductive model of theory construction and
evaluation in the social sciences; the methodological and epistemological unity
of the natural and social sciences; the fundamental underlying unity of principles,
of inferential standards and of the logic of inquiry in qualitative and quantitative research; the search for “law-like”, uniform causal generalisations (whether
deterministic or probabilistic in nature); and the understanding of social causality
on the broad model – if not necessarily the speciic terms – of statistical inference.
There are social scientists who might construe any position that eschews commitments such as these as an intrinsic rejection of “the social-science enterprise”.5
Such claims can only rest on an extremely narrow and arbitrary conception of
social science. This book is in part an effort to demonstrate not just the possibility
but the great power of a far broader conception of social-scientiic inquiry. It is
a conception which retains, indeed insists on, a strong commitment to analytical
rigour.6 In this respect, this book aligns itself with a growing literature in the heterodox social sciences which places a heavy emphasis on conceptual, analytical
and methodological issues (e.g. Martin 2011; Hall 1999; Topper 2005; Reed 2011;
Packer 2010; Biernacki 2012; Toomela and Valsiner 2010). Rigour of thought
and analysis is certainly no proprietary possession of “positivist” social science.
Indeed, this book hopes to show that sustained rigorous relection can demonstrate
the profound implausibility – or, at the very least, the wholly optional status –
of many of the underlying conceptual, ontological, epistemological and methodological assumptions of conventional social-scientiic research. An inlexible
4
Introduction
commitment to a particular construal of rigour and a particular image of precision
can lead to theorising that is often, in actual fact, neither rigorous nor precise in
its characterisation and explanation of the varied phenomena of the social world.
It is my aim to develop these relections and arguments in a clear, systematic and
compelling fashion that is accessible to both a mainstream and non-mainstream
social-science audience. I also aim to demonstrate in an intuitively plausible fashion what, concretely, is at stake in the issues explored in these pages, particularly
for empirical research. I aim, in other words, to show readers exactly why they
should care about these issues, whatever their persuasion.
I expect that this book may encounter a different sort of scepticism from certain
readers of a more heterodox stripe. These readers may well wonder what the point
is, and whether I am not laboriously reinventing the wheel (in an alien and forced
analytical vocabulary and style, no less). Some may think this is time wasted
resurrecting old, and unproductive, debates; others will believe these debates to
have been long settled – in favour of the home team, no doubt. They might also
believe that all of my substantive arguments and conclusions are already relected
in existing or current work in social theory and heterodox social science. All of
the social-scientiic disciplines have had their own pitched epistemological and
methodological battles or underground resistance movements; I will not even try
to canvas them here. I will leave ultimate judgements about novelty and relevance
in the hands of the reader. All I can ask is that the sceptic read the arguments carefully and in full before deciding.
2 Practice theory today
This book will directly set out to develop an original account of the nature and
signiicance of practices in the social world. It will not systematically compare
this account with the existing literature in practice theory, nor will the existing
literature be subject to detailed review and critical assessment.7 Nevertheless, it
is worth making a few generic points about today’s practice theory at the outset
in order to highlight some aspects of what is analytically at stake in these pages.
The distinctive character of the account of practices presented here can be
traced to its very point of departure: to its conception of what practices are in the
irst place. In this regard an important point about the understanding of “practice” in the existing literature should be noted. One way of formulating this point
might be to observe that practice theorists have typically been interested more in
“practice”, in the abstract singular and without an article, than in “practices” –
than in the speciic kinds of things that people do and have done, the diverse
concrete activities in which they engage.8 To date, practice scholars have tended
to conceive of practice in terms of habitual or customary performance based on
skills acquired through experience, training or routine performance, and embodied in “tacit knowledge” or know-how.9 This conception thus draws in part on
the familiar opposition between practice and theory – i.e. rational, relective,
“calculative” thought – drawn in everyday language. Thus practice theorists have
stressed the habitual, tacit, non-calculative, non-representational, unspoken and
Introduction 5
“everyday” dimensions of human action.10 They have presented practice as a
matter of customary or competent activity based on skills acquired through experience, training and routine performance. For these scholars, practice is that broad
domain of human action that is familiar to the point where it becomes “second
nature” and quasi-automatic, performed without much in the way of deliberate
relection. It is the product of inarticulate skills, practical knowledge and knowhow (not “know-that”), of a “practical sense”, a “feel for the game”.
Thus in world politics, for instance, the performance of practices of international summitry may be held to rely on often unarticulated and unrelected
background knowledge, such as the “very speciic and skilful way for state oficials to subtly take a little distance from the consensus forged for the oficial
communiqué”. Generic practices of strategic bargaining à la Thomas Schelling
(1960; 1966) likewise require background skills of effective communication
and signalling – of threats, resolve/commitment, correct incentives, etc. – and of
being able to walk the ine line between brinkmanship and disaster. Moreover, the
communicative practices themselves, as well as their recognition and interpretation, operate almost entirely in the realm of the tacit, given that in the relevant
situations, explicit “talk is cheap” (Adler and Pouliot 2011: 7–8). The behaviour of diplomats – e.g. copying budgets, updating protocols, handling a senior
promotion – is shaped by their juggling of at least three distinct, often contradictory, unspoken “scripts”: those of the bureaucrat, the hero, and the mediator
(Neumann 2005). Background tacit knowledge is required for those who witness
as much as those who engage in practices. Thus Charles de Gaulle’s ostentatious
1963 veto of British membership in the European Common Market relected a
tacit “tradition of great-power lèse-majesté which was quite recognisable even to
avowed ‘pro-Europeans’, much as they may have deplored it” (Navari 2011: 10).
The concerns motivating this approach are important ones. The practice turn
has usefully drawn attention to core aspects of human action largely ignored or
undertheorised in conventional approaches to social science. These include the
“unconscious” and “subconscious”, “instinctive”, habitual and “corporeal” dimensions of action and knowledge. They also include the variety of capacities and skills
which undergird different types of action. Practice theory has drawn attention to
the qualitatively distinct nature, the signiicance and the ubiquity of know-how as
a type of knowledge. Sometimes it has been accompanied by renewed attention
to people’s agency, creativity and active resistance to entrenched, overt forms of
order and power. It has contributed to growing attention (in various quarters) to
the role of affect and emotion in social behaviour. It has also emphasised the oftneglected “everyday” aspects of social and political life.11
There are, however, a number of serious analytical dificulties that aflict
explanatory accounts based on such a conception of practice(s). Some of these
problems have been set out crisply and incisively by Nigel Pleasants, Theodore
Schatzki and Stephen Turner, among others (Pleasants 1996; 1999: chs 4–5;
Schatzki 1990; 1997; Turner 1994; 2002: 31–2, 45–7).12 (The relative neglect
among practice scholars of Schatzki’s vigorous arguments against conceptions
of practice that appeal to tacit knowledge and tacit rules is particularly striking.
6
Introduction
As an editor of the seminal multidisciplinary volume of practice theory cited in
the epigraph, and author of three of the only book-length practice accounts to
date, his is one name known to all advocates of the practice turn in the social
sciences and humanities.)
One key issue is the explanatory ambition of these accounts. It may be that
identifying, conceptualising and characterising action and behaviour come across
as fairly uninteresting, and largely atheoretical, exercises – preliminaries, perhaps, to social-scientiic investigation, and not ends in themselves. Even scholars
who eschew mainstream epistemic practices may nonetheless share a widespread,
if perhaps largely unconscious, assumption in the social sciences: that as social
phenomena, action and behaviour are more or less uncomplicated and straightforward to identify, describe and classify – unlike, perhaps, motives, intentions,
ideas, norms, culture, discourse, functions, structures, institutions and so on. (That
such an assumption may cross epistemological lines might help explain why a
social-scientiic focus on “mere” behavioural regularities seems to strike so many
“non-positivist” scholars as narrow and analytically regressive.)13 Challenging
this assumption is one aim of this book. The book thus stresses the profound
importance and interest, but also the profound complexity, of effectively characterising human behaviour for social-scientiic research. My personal sense is that
there is little that is straightforward about identifying generic forms of human
behaviour for the purposes of general explanation. This applies even to those
forms of behaviour we are inclined to ind extremely familiar.
Whatever the reasons, there is a clear pattern in the practice turn. To this point,
speciic empirical practices, and their particular features and interrelations, have
not been the object of primary theoretical interest. When they do receive attention, it is typically derivative. They are examined because, and to the extent that,
these activities are thought to exhibit features held to be typical of “practice”
in general – for instance, a certain tacit, unrelective, intuitive, skilful, nonrepresentational, commonsensical or habitual quality. These shared qualities, and
not the speciic details of the speciic activities (in and of) themselves, are the
main object of attention. Moreover, what is supposed to be theoretically interesting about these practices is that they embody, or are symptoms of, certain
other types of phenomena which are held to underlie and to structure, guide and
produce them: dispositions, tacit knowledge, tacit (or constitutive) rules, norms,
principles, codes, formulae, habits, habitus, conventions, standards of correctness,
attitudes, scripts, schemes, cognitive schemata, and so forth.14
The result is somewhat ironic for an approach that purports to privilege
practice. Practice scholars have often done little to systematically identify and
theorise, with close precision, the actual activities of social life themselves. For
much of this work “practices” has, in a sense, functioned as an odd placeholder
term. Use of the concept is supposed to signal a certain interest in materiality –
as against, typically, the alleged non-materiality of discourse and texts. Yet in
practice, scholarship citing it tends to remark only incidentally or in an ad hoc
fashion on the concrete things people actually do. The real theoretical attention
is in fact devoted to those entities which are alleged to cause (or “constitute”)
Introduction 7
and explain people’s actions. Sometimes the terms “practice” and “practices” are
actually used to refer to these underlying phenomena,15 and not the activities they
supposedly produce. Other scholars seem to slide arbitrarily between the one and
the other when referring to “practices”.
I will not engage in a systematic critique of existing practice theory here.
These problematic features aren’t at any rate unique to it; they are characteristic
of the treatment of the “cultural” realm in the social sciences more generally. Two
in particular may be noted. One concerns the way the explanatory relationship
between action and the proposed underlying cultural phenomenon is conceived.
This relationship is seen either as an instance of garden-variety causality, or, more
intriguingly, as a “constitutive” relation. The former view is simplistic, unrealistic
and exceedingly narrow. The latter is more promising, but typically left extremely
vague and undertheorised by its advocates. On those rare occasions that it is given
lesh, it very often turns out to be construed as a softer form of determination in
social life than causality, a kind of “causality-lite”. Its broad epistemic aims and
form are similar to those of traditional causal explanation of human behaviour: to
account for the occurrence of speciic actions on speciic occasions. In this book, I
argue that this is the wrong thing to ask of “cultural” theories of the social world.
In Chapter 7, I endorse the appeal to constitutive relations, but argue that these
should be conceptualised in a rather distinctive fashion.
The other aspect common to these approaches to practice – and to “cultural”
accounts more broadly – is the nature of the “explanans”, the cultural phenomena
alleged to do the explaining. Examples include (tacit) rules, norms, principles, dispositions, tacit knowledge, habits, habitus, conventions, scripts, hexis, standards,
codes, (unspoken) formulae, attitudes, schemes, schemata and tendencies. Each
of these has a venerable pedigree in the social sciences. And despite non-trivial
differences among them, they form something of a family. They all represent hidden entities that are supposed to exist in addition to, to underlie, and to infuse and
generate the manifest actions they are cited to explain.
Though some of them have certain limited uses, I consider them generally to
be rather suspect and occult analytical objects. In most cases one can reasonably
doubt whether any coherent entities corresponding to these categories actually
exist. One can also question the explanatory logic and power of such entities, and
indeed argue that there is little to nothing that positing such entities adds to a careful description of the activities themselves. Just as corrosively, a powerful case
can be made that not only are allegedly ubiquitous objects like tacit social rules,
norms and behavioural dispositions not needed to make sense of human behaviour, but that they could not fulil this role even if they were. What’s more, one
might plausibly argue that the analytical dependence actually runs in the opposite
direction from the one imagined: that the identiication and characterisation of
“norms”, “dispositions” and “tacit rules” that allegedly explain practices, and the
impression of their explanatory power, fundamentally rely on the theorist’s prior
grasp of features of the practices themselves – and, at their most effective, often
simply restate or redescribe those features. In the place of pseudo-explainers like
these, I will recommend sustained attention to that very behaviour, to the actual
8
Introduction
practices themselves, as well as to their constitutive relationship with knowledge
in its material and discursive forms. A close examination of concrete practices
and knowledge will help produce not only more accurate and useful description,
conceptualisation and characterisation but also more successful (constitutive and
even causal) explanation.
3 Core ontological commitments
Together, the arguments advanced in this book urge a particular image of socialscientiic inquiry, based upon what it takes to be core features of the ontology of
the social world. A few very general and abstract aspects of this image can be
speciied at the outset. One is the ineliminably historical nature of the social world
and of the phenomena therein. Practices are fundamentally historical phenomena,
which come into being, exist and disappear in a particular time and place. Our
epistemic practices – particularly our practices of conceptualising, characterising
and generalising about social phenomena – should therefore be oriented to, and
genuinely relect, this historicity. Second, and relatedly, practices are contingent
phenomena. There are few human practices of any moderate complexity that are
universal in any meaningful sense, and what might at irst appear to be subtle
or minor differences between practices can be of considerable signiicance for
social-scientiic inquiry. Most human practices did not, strictly speaking, have
to arise at all or take the form they did; most have required speciic conditions
for their existence, and have depended profoundly on elements of their historical
context for their very nature and persistence.
A third point follows from this: that human practices, and therefore virtually
all social phenomena, are deeply contextual things. They are in important part
constituted by speciic elements of their context, and cannot be fully identiied and
understood in analytic isolation from that context. This leads to a fourth point: if
contexts are fundamental to the very identity and existence of practices (and other
social phenomena), then we need to identify them with far greater speciicity than
they have hitherto been. We should proliferate the number of social phenomena we recognise, and seek to identify and distinguish them in their cultural and
historical speciicity. This has direct implications for social-scientiic conceptformation. In particular, the kinds of abstract, typologically oriented, functional
concepts typical of conventional social science will normally be profoundly inadequate to the (contextually varied) phenomena they seek to capture and describe.
Thence, too, a ifth point: the relationship between a practice and the key elements
of its context is constitutive in nature. This constitutive relationship helps us to
understand not only the existence but the speciic features and indeed the very
generality of a practice. Many of the central sorts of explanatory generalisations to
be made about practices will therefore be generalisations about constitutive relations and can best, perhaps only, be captured by constitutive theorising.
Yet this is not to deny the role, presence or indeed ubiquity of causality in
the social world. Many heterodox approaches to the social sciences have tended
to reject outright the relevance or even the possibility of causal inquiry into the
Introduction 9
social world. Others have accepted something of an intellectual division of labour,
effectively leaving causal inquiry to the “positivists”. Though I understand the
impulse behind the irst response, and indeed once felt it myself, I believe both to
be mistaken. What is fundamentally problematic, I believe, is not the existence,
extent or importance of social causality, but the particular monolithic conception
of causality presumed by mainstream social-scientiic inquiry. Countless variants
of this conception have been offered, but its core is remarkably stable, and it is so
widespread and so deeply entrenched, in our daily lives as much as in academic
research, that it has effectively become synonymous with causality tout court. It
is something along the lines of the motivating image behind statistical inference:
what might be called “correlation-plus” – uniformly regular covariance of the
occurrence of instances (or of the “values” of some attribute) of the explanans
and explanandum, plus some mysterious “extra” element, its identity endlessly
debated, that secures actual causal inluence from the one to the other. The covariance may be deterministic or stochastic in nature, but either way, it is uniform in
its regularity.
In my view, this conception is fundamentally inappropriate as a characterisation of virtually any actually existing form of social causality. It is ine, indeed
quite useful, to speak of causes and causings in the social world, so long as we
drop the assumption of uniform regularity and attend to the possibility of plural
and perhaps extremely diverse forms of social causality. In Chapter 6 we will
see one proposal for a generic way of characterising this irregularity and this
potential diversity. In Chapters 6 and 7, I present arguments that attempt to reconcile the simultaneous possibility in the social world of vast causal diversity and
contingency, on the one hand, and the manifest regularity and generality of social
phenomena, on the other. Again, these arguments underscore the signiicance and
autonomy of constitutive theory.
A inal word on pigeonholes, “-isms” and tribal allegiances. I am somewhat
wary of labels. No doubt they are necessary to some extent. On the other hand,
they too often function as shortcuts and indeed substitutes for critical thought.
They can allow scholars, particularly when confronted with the unfamiliar, to
peg and to typecast, and to trot out glib stock criticisms, without feeling any need
for careful engagement with arguments. Despite the diverse range of theoretical
approaches and philosophical positions on offer in the social sciences today, I’m
not sure that this work its very easily into any of them. One can’t realistically
expect, however, to escape assignment to more familiar categories. A little preemptive self-identiication, then, for whatever it’s worth.
Philosophically, this book is strongly inluenced by the work of the so-called
Stanford School in the history/philosophy of science. For a period during the
1980s, the Stanford philosophy department was home to a formidable group
of broadly like-minded thinkers: Ian Hacking, Nancy Cartwright, John Dupré,
Peter Galison, Margaret Morrison and Arnold Davidson. The subject matter of
this book relects one of their primary philosophical preoccupations: “One thing
that unites Stanford School practitioners is a strong respect for scientiic practice –
actual scientiic practice” (Hoefer 2008: 1; original emphasis). The names and
10
Introduction
arguments of Cartwright, Dupré and, above all, Hacking feature prominently
throughout this book. My intellectual debt to Hacking, speciically, extends far
beyond his work in the philosophy of science.16 The extent, moreover, to which
the remarkable oeuvre of Michel Foucault has inspired the arguments of this book
will also be obvious to many readers. Those for whom that name instantly evokes
certain prejudices and expectations should be forewarned: I often recognise little
of the Foucault I have read in the work of his followers, let alone his critics.17 In
addition to Foucault and the Stanford School, the twentieth century’s greatest analytic philosopher, Ludwig Wittgenstein, is a shadowy presence lurking in these
pages. The inluence of Elizabeth Anscombe, one of his ablest students, often
takes a more visible form.
That said, a list of “inluences” will rarely provide a good guide to someone’s
ideas. I have my points of difference with all of the aforementioned thinkers.
At any rate, authorial intention can’t, and perhaps shouldn’t try to, legislate the
meaning of a work. Little point, then, in further attempts to control the reader’s
interpretations. On to the argument.
4 Sketch of the argument
The irst chapter of this book begins with the obvious question: what exactly are
practices, anyway? I distinguish my own answer from some existing alternatives,
showing how my conception of practices differs from conceptions typical of practice scholarship in the social sciences and humanities. I essentially see practices
as the generalised form of actions of a particular type. It is therefore a conception
of practices that treats practices not as “hidden” or “tacit” phenomena underlying
action but as the activity itself – as phenomena that are all “on the surface”, as it
were. My conception might seem to bear a strong resemblance to the more conventional social-scientiic concept of “behavioural regularities”. This impression
is supericially correct, but there is a wide range of crucial differences that become
clear as the account unfolds.
Since practices are but the generalised form of actions, I argue that an account
of social practices might usefully begin by theorising action. I draw on the classic
account of action offered by philosopher Elizabeth Anscombe, and on the surprising twist on Anscombe’s argument introduced by Ian Hacking. Hacking’s twist
helps us in particular to understand the fundamental constitutive (and logical)
relationship between actions and concepts, where concepts represent descriptions
of actions or of their elements. It also helps us to see that this constitutive relationship is characterised by a constant “looping effect” between actions (practices)
and concepts, an effect that is fundamental to the dynamism of social reality.
This looping effect entails that human practices are intrinsically historical in their
nature and constitution over time. Because of this looping effect, practices have
a curious sort of ontological status that is somewhat unlike other, more familiar,
forms of generic phenomenon.
No practice exists in a vacuum; any practice is part of a broader realm of
activity with some degree of “internal” interconnectedness. The same is true