The Recurrence of Acoustics in Levinas
Roberto Wu
Levinas Studies, Volume 10, 2015, pp. 115-136 (Article)
Published by Philosophy Documentation Center
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/lev.2016.0005
For additional information about this article
https://muse.jhu.edu/article/638980
Access provided by UFSC-Universidade Federal de Santa Catarina (30 Oct 2018 17:31 GMT)
The Recurrence of
Acoustics in Levinas
Roberto Wu
D
espite Levinas’s emphasis on the oral dimension of the encounter with the other, notions
such as hearing and listening are far from
receiving univocal accounts in his reflections. Yet, Jacques Derrida seems to find clear evidence of their relevance, affirming that
“Levinas places sound above light,”1 which is interpreted as the
affirmation of “the transcendence of hearing (l’entendre) in relation
to seeing (voir).”2 Nevertheless, the second movement of this interpretation inevitably evokes some confusion, for the priority of the
sound over light/seeing does not necessarily imply the priority of
hearing. Levinas’s accounts of hearing (entendre/audition),3 listening,
and/or hearkening (écouter) fluctuate throughout his philosophical
production, and, despite some occasional discussion, they remain
secondary compared with speech (parole), as in Totality and
Infinity,4 on which Derrida bases most of his analysis.5 It is only in
Otherwise than Being that they will be more systematically employed,
which does not imply, however, a weakening of the priority
of speech.
Without contesting the primordiality of speech over hearing,
listening, and audition, we aim, however, to investigate the purview of these last concepts by linking Levinas’s early account of
115
116
Lev ina s St u d i e s 1 0
acoustics with the description available in Otherwise than Being. This
involves: (1) examining how hearing, listening, and audition relate
to sound (and silence) in his discussion of the there is (il y a), and
(2) discussing the integration between these concepts with the acoustic
account of Otherwise than Being, in which terms like resonance and
echo are decisive. By means of this, we make visible some important
moments related to acoustics: (1) the resonance of essence, (2) the echo
of the otherwise, (3) the resonance of the “mute murmuring” of the il
y a, and (4) the “forgotten voices” of a tradition apart from ontology.
C REATION OF S ILENCE AND THE O VERFLOWING S OUND
In the little essay, “The Transcendence of Words: On Michel Leiris’s
Biffures,” published in 1949 and thus contemporaneous to Existence
and Existents (1947), “Reality and Its Shadow” (1948), and “Is Ontology Fundamental?” (1951), Levinas takes Leiris’s work as the motif
upon which the themes of hearing and living-world are developed. The
reference to these other texts is not arbitrary and scrutinizes that which
Gerald L. Bruns calls “aesthetics of materiality.”6 Leiris’s surrealism
seems to evoke a kinship with Levinas’s analysis of the there is (il y a)
in Existence and Existents. In opposition to Husserl’s and Heidegger’s
versions of phenomenology, which conceive of being from the angle
of givenness (Sinngebung), Levinas insists that the materiality of being
remains impenetrable despite the attempts of rendering meaning by
means of understanding. Therefore, the il y a expressly counteracts
the intelligibility provided by understanding, which articulates meaning, horizon, and light: “Behind the luminosity of forms, by which
beings already relate to our ‘inside,’ matter [matière] is the very fact
of the there is. . . .” (EE 57; ellipsis in original, translation modified /
DEE 92). Refractory to the advances of light, the il y a bespeaks the
anonymity that depersonalizes and makes indeterminate human existence, as, for example, in the experience of insomnia: “Wakefulness is
anonymous. It is not that there is my vigilance in the night; in insomnia
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
117
it is the night itself that watches. It watches. In this anonymous nightwatch where I am completely exposed to being all the thoughts which
occupy my insomnia are suspended on nothing” (66/111). The night
adumbrates the impersonality of the il y a, the fact that there is “an
absolutely unavoidable presence” (58/94), which is not an object, but
a verb that renders an event in its impersonal form (“It watches” — Ça
veille). Then, Levinas introduces a description that is important not
just for the economy of Existence and Existents, but also for his ulterior
philosophy, for it anticipates fundamental characteristics of Otherwise
than Being: “There is no discourse [discours]. Nothing responds to
us, but this silence; the voice of this silence is heard [entendue] and
frightens like the silence of those infinite spaces Pascal speaks of ” (58;
translation modified/95).
It is precisely the voice of the silence that comes from this presence
of absence that Levinas refers to, although implicitly, in his essay on
Michel Leiris. First of all, there is a form of art based on the primacy of
vision, in which a being appears as world, and which “makes beauty in
nature, calming it, appeasing it” (OS 147 / LTM 1093). Nevertheless,
Levinas warns, “All the arts, even the sonorous ones, create silence,”
and silence can be, “at times of the bad conscience, oppressive or
frightening” (147/1093). This description can hardly be dissociated
from the above quotation of Existence and Existents,7 but Levinas
also proposes the necessity of relating with this silence, a “need for
critique,” that is, the kind of relation that perceives the uneasiness
that underlies the “peace of the beautiful” (147/1093) and is aware
of the fact that silence is not mere absence, but the announcement of
the il y a.8 The silence that even sonorous arts create anticipates the
subject matter of the “resonance of silence” in Otherwise than Being.
Particularly significant is that Levinas extends the scope of silence to
all forms of art, for all of them are capable of reflecting the primordial
experience that insomnia and horror inflict.
Next, Levinas shifts from the discussion of silence to a consideration of the sound as such, through the perspective of its disjunction
118
Lev ina s St u d i e s 1 0
with vision, by means of a correlation between sound and excess. He
writes, “There is in fact in sound — and in consciousness understood
as hearing [audition] — a shattering of the always complete world
of vision and art. Sound is all repercussion, outburst, scandal. While
in vision a form espouses a content and soothes it, sound is like the
sensible quality overflowing [débordement] its limits, the incapacity of
form to hold its content — a true rent in the fabric of the world — that
by which the world that is here prolongs a dimension inconvertible
into vision” (OS 147–48/ LTM 1093).
Likewise, a few years after this essay, Levinas will warn us of the
limitations of vision and light, as in “Is Ontology Fundamental?”
and, with a more detailed account, in Totality and Infinity, by taking
them as the key components of the dynamic of sameness. Nevertheless, even in this article of 1949 it is already possible to see how the
horizon of vision is “shattered,” whether in its character of containment and limitation or in its feature of calming and making nature
peaceful, because sound “overflows” and exceeds a “form,” being
therefore “repercussion, outburst, scandal.” Levinas describes the
surpassing feature of sound in terms of symbol: “the sound is symbol
par excellence — a reaching beyond the given” (OS 148/LTM 1093).
In “Meaning and Sense,” Levinas explains that “A symbol is not
the abridgement of a real presence that would preexist it; it would
give more than any receptivity for the world could ever receive”
(CPP 83/SS 133). A symbol entails an insurmountable gap between
orders separated by an excess; therefore, it does not belong to the
economy of collateral relations that encompasses the given. Music
incarnates the essential feature that underlies every form of art, namely,
the movement of going beyond what is given. Levinas performs in
“Reality and Its Shadow” the recurrent gesture of identifying understanding and knowledge with the given, a horizon that art attempts
to surpass and disrupt: “Does not the function of art lie in not understanding? . . . Art does not know a particular type of reality; it contrasts
with knowledge. It is the very event of obscuring, a descent of the
night, an invasion of shadow” (CPP 3/RO 773).
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
119
At least in one important aspect, the analysis of art in “Reality and Its
Shadow” has more affinity with Existence and Existents than with “The
Transcendence of Words”: the former presents the impersonality that
art, but especially music, sets forth, while the latter explicitly attaches
music with the word (mot) and the verb (verbe). In “Reality and Its
Shadow,” the concept of image appears from the outset as opposed
to “concept,” because conceptuality, to Levinas, implies grasping,
understanding, and power over the object. Thenceforth, he conducts
his interpretation of art based on a reversal, in choosing image over
concept, passivity over power: “An image marks a hold over us rather
than our initiative, a fundamental passivity” (CPP 3/RO 774). Taking into consideration the above analysis of sound, it is not surprising
thus that he affirms that “an image is musical” (3/774), whereas neither image is strictly conceived as optics, as far as Levinas dismantles
and reverses what this implies, nor are music and sound restricted to
usual theories of acoustics. Assuredly this statement anticipates much
of the “listening eye,” which will appear more than 30 years later in
Otherwise than Being.
While deepening the passivity implicated by the experience of art,
Levinas asserts the uniqueness of the rhythm. He refuses its definition
as “an inner law of the poetic order,” stating rather that experiencing it implies some kind of mutual participation: “our consenting to
them is inverted into a participation. Their entry into us is one with
our entry into them” (CPP 4/RO 774). By means of the analysis of
rhythm, Levinas takes up again in another domain the issue of the
depersonalization of the subject that he has undertaken in Existence
and Existents. In his analysis of insomnia, Levinas portrays the il y a
as the unavoidable presence of absence, in the face of which no one
is sure if one is the watcher or the one who is watched, and vigilance
turns out to be an impersonal event without subject. Something similar
occurs with rhythm, for “consent, assumption, initiative or freedom”
are terms that reveal themselves to be inadequate to a situation in which
someone is “caught up and carried away by it” (4/775). The subject
is thus depersonalized: “It is so not even despite itself, for in rhythm
120
Le v ina s St u d i e s 1 0
there is no longer a oneself, but rather a sort of passage from oneself to
anonymity” (4/775). In this anonymity, consciousness and unconsciousness compose a phantasmagorical landscape, as in a “waking
dream,” even if it is more adequate to characterize it as “a sphere situated outside of the conscious and the unconscious” (4/775).9 Levinas
concludes this moment of his argument by underscoring the uniqueness
of his conceptions of rhythm and music, as well as anticipating the
theme of the resonance that will play a key role in Otherwise than Being:
Then we must detach them from the arts of sound where they are ordinarily envisioned exclusively, and draw them out into a general aesthetic
category. Rhythm certainly does have its privileged locus in music, for
the musician’s element realizes the pure deconceptualization of reality.
Sound is the quality most detached from an object. Its relation with
the substance from which it emanates is not inscribed in its quality.
It resounds impersonally. [Il résonne impersonnellement] Even its timbre,
a trace of its belonging to an object, is submerged in its quality, and does
not retain the structure of a relation. Hence in listening [en écoutant] we
do not apprehend a “something,” but are without concepts: musicality
belongs to sound naturally. (CPP 4–5/RO 776)
Deconceptualization refers to the capacity of sound to engender a
disruption of subjectivity. Levinas suggests that its overflowing capacity
precludes it from being integrated within the horizon of conceptual
meaning articulated by vision and understanding. The excess that
belongs to the sound finds a parallel with the surplus of non-sense
over sense that the il y a delivers; in this sense, to listen means to be
“exposed” to that which resounds impersonally. This conception of
sound returns in Levinas’s later works, as in Otherwise than Being,
although with some important modifications that cannot be easily
harmonized with the account we have just presented.
Conversely, in “The Transcendence of Words,” the indeterminateness that is characteristic of his descriptions of the il y a, and related
to the impersonal and to anonymity, is put aside in favor of the verbal
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
121
sound: “If, however, sound can appear as a phenomenon, as here, it is
because its function of transcendence only asserts itself in the verbal
sound. The sounds and noises of nature are words [mots] that disappoint us. To really hear [entendre] a sound is to hear a word [mot]. Pure
sound is verb [verbe]” (OS 148; translation modified / LTM 1093).
This passage is categorical: verb is the grounding of sound; even noises
are conceived in terms of words. According to Levinas, there is a decay
of speaking in contemporary philosophy and sociology, in which occurs
“a disdain for the word” (148/1093). In face of this, he emphasizes
how important is the speaking word and gives us the example of
Robinson Crusoe’s meeting with Man Friday, which is more expressive than his other ties with civilization, such as his artificial utensils
or the preservation of “his morality” (148/1093). Levinas describes
this event as that “in which a man who speaks replaces the ineffable
sadness of echoes [la tristesse inexprimable de l’écho]” (148/1093).
This observation makes room for his claim that “social relation — the
real presence of the other [l’autre] — matters” (148/1093–94), a
presence that “is fulfilled in hearing [l’audition]” inasmuch as the
word uttered by the other plays a “transcendent role” in which “verb
refuses to become flesh” (148/1094). The “privilege of the living
word [mot vivant], destined to be heard [l’audition]” (149/1094),
opposes to the conception of language based on signs, for the latter
fails to give an account of speaking as an event; rather, language as a
system of signs privileges the writing as being its substance, which,
according to Levinas, produces “disfigured words, ‘frozen words’”
(149/1094). In contrast to frozen words of documents and vestiges
(vestiges), Levinas conceives the speaking from the perspective of an
encounter with the other, in the sense of an interruption: “To speak
is to interrupt my existence as a subject, a master, but to interrupt it
without offering myself as spectacle, leaving me simultaneously object
and subject. My voice brings the element in which that dialectical situation is accomplished concretely” (149/1094).
122
Le v ina s St u d i e s 1 0
T HE E CHO OF S AYING
The ubiquity of themes related to acoustics in Otherwise than Being
suggests some sort of retrieval of matters that we have just addressed,
especially the overflowing character of sound, the link between image
and sound, silence, and the il y a. Unlike Totality and Infinity, Other
wise than Being is deliberately expressed through acoustic concepts:
resonance, echo, voice, inaudible, listening eye, hearing, silence, and
so on.
The priority of speaking over hearing, already enacted in Totality and
Infinity, is maintained in Otherwise than Being, but the latter unfolds
the discussion on language stressing the distinction between saying
and said. This priority appears in Otherwise than Being on different
occasions, as, for example, in the formulation “obedience precedes any
listening [écoute] to the command” (OB 148; translation modified/
AQE 232), which instead of subordinating obedience to listening, or
even establishing an equivalence between them, affirms the primacy and
independence of the former from the latter. As in Totality and Infinity,
in which the speech of the other determines a command to which I
must respond, Levinas maintains in Otherwise than Being the dignity
and the absolute priority of this speech from any acoustical apprehension. This can be developed at least into two directions. First, Levinas
explains this priority by means of the theme of creation, in which the
creature has already received a command even before he or she begins
to understand: “But in creation, what is called to being answers to a
call that could not have reached it since, brought out of nothingness,
it obeyed before hearing [d’entendre] the order” (113/179), for in a
sense being is already a response to creation. Second, this priority corresponds to the constitutive anachronism of the fractured encounter
with the other: “‘Before they call, I will answer,’ the formula is to be
understood literally. In approaching the other I am always late for
the meeting” (150/235). These statements express the idiosyncrasy
of Levinas’s ethics, in which obedience precedes understanding, as
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
123
responsibility comes before commitment — a gesture that he calls “the
passing itself of the Infinite” (150/235). This idea also appears in the
following assertion: “The neighbor strikes me before striking me, as
though [comme si] I had heard [entendu] before he spoke” (88/141).
The expression “comme si” should not be overlooked, for it indicates
an analogical treatment of the term entendre that prevents a contradiction with the above formulation of the pre-original anachronism.
The obedience to the command precedes any uttering of sounds and
consequently any hearing in this sense. The anachronism between
obedience and hearing elicits the theme of the immemorial past, which
comes to us not as presence, but as trace and echo. With regard to the
issue of the neighbor, Levinas writes, “In proximity is heard [s’entend]
a command come as though from an immemorial past [comme d’un
passé immémorial ], which was never present, began in no freedom.
This way of the neighbor is a face” (88/141). To hear a command,
as is asserted here, does not represent an inconsistency with the thesis
of the anachronism above presented, for Levinas is not advocating
in this last sentence a dependency of the command on hearing, but
rather remarking that if and when one hears the command, one attends
something that cannot be described as a presence, for the pre-original
whence of this command refers to an immemorial past, and, because
of this, this particular hearing is described in the mode of as though.10
As with the proximity of the neighbor, also the relation with the third
party, the illeity (illéité) consists in an order that has already addressed
me before any hearing, “It is the coming of the order to which I am
subjected before hearing it [l’entendre], or which I hear [j’entends] in
my own saying” (150/234–35). This sentence thus presents the very
core of the idea of “the other in the same” (105/167), which means,
on the one hand, that “the saying that comes to me is my own word”
(150/235), and, on the other hand, that one’s subjectivity is based
on “an anarchic plot” (105/167). In the dynamic of substitution I am
the one who is responsible for the other, but obeying this command
differs from responding to orders given in the present; rather, it means
124
Le v ina s St u d i e s 1 0
that this saying is anarchically inscribed in me: “It is the pure trace of
a ‘wandering cause,’ inscribed in me” (150/235).11
A whole acoustic terminology stems from the pre-original anachronism. Inasmuch as saying refuses contemporaneity with the said,
the unheard (inouï) indicates the priority of the command situated on
the level of saying, to which one has been already addressed, and the
impossibility of coincidence between the ethical and the ontological:
“Then, the trace of saying, which has never been present, obliges me;
the responsibility for the other, never assumed, binds me; a command
never heard [jamais entendu] is obeyed” (OB 168/AQE 261). The
expression “ambiguity of inspiration” designates the anarchic obedience for-the-other (pourl’autre) and simultaneously the authorship
of having receiving and assumed this command inscribed in me, “this
unheard-of obligation [inouïe obligation]” (148–49/232). Anachronism and ambiguity are not to be suppressed in this case, for they attest
“a diachronic ambivalence which ethics makes possible” (149/232).
In refusing a primordial role to any apprehension, the unheard reveals
the very heart of the Levinasian account of ethics, inasmuch as it radicalizes the disjunction between ethics and ontology. “The unheard-of
saying [le dire inouï] is enigmatically in the anarchic response, in my
responsibility for the other” (149/232).
Far from indicating that concepts such as hearing and listening are
excluded from the internal logic of Otherwise than Being, the anachronism itself ascribes distinctive roles to them, for what is at stake here
is not the perception of some present sound, but the retention of the
echo of a saying that resounds in one’s ears. The said receives, therefore,
a more robust account in this book; instead of being merely a negative demarcation of the apophantic discourse, the said also evokes the
saying that resonates in it. “The said, contesting the abdication of the
saying that everywhere occurs in this said, thus maintains the diachrony
in which, holding its breath, the spirit hears the echo [entend l’écho]
of the otherwise” (OB 44/AQE 76). The “unsayable saying [le Dire
indicible]” exceeds the said and is irreducible to predicative relations,
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
125
although in a manner in which it “lends itself to the said” (44/76)
without being absorbed for or diluted in the latter, whereas “the saying
is both an affirmation and a retraction of the said.” (44/75). While
keeping itself in face of the said and simultaneously in the said, the
unsayable saying lets itself be reduced,12 a reduction that is energized
by “the ethical interruption of essence,” and which exceeds mere presence or manifestation, for “the breathless spirit retains a fading echo
[écho]” in “the ambiguity or the enigma of the transcendent” (44/76).
In and through the said, essence encompasses two different possibilities: either it assumes the verbal character resounding in the said,
or it becomes petrified in the noun: “in the said, the essence that
resounds [résonne] is on the verge of becoming a noun” (OB 41/AQE
71). Essence, in the verbal sense, “resounds [résonne] in the prose
of predicative propositions” (41/71). To say that essence resounds
in the said is to say that it vibrates within the said or temporalizes.
Conversely, there is the latent risk of apophansis itself muffling the
resonance, and consequently forcing the verb to become mere noun:
“This resonance [Résonance] is always ready to congeal into nouns,
where being will be congealed into a copula and the Sachverhalt
‘nominalized’” (47/79). The resonance of the verb “is collected into
an entity by the noun,” and, accordingly, “to be thenceforth designates
instead of resounding” (42/73). More accurately, the double direction
of the essence engenders an internal amphibology in which predicative propositions transition from one extreme possibility to another;
therefore, an “amphibology of the logos” (amphibologie du logos), which
corresponds to an “amphibology of being and entities” (de l’être et de
l’étant) (43/74), takes place. “The said as a verb is essence or temporalization. Or, more exactly, the logos enters into the amphibology in
which being and entities can be understood and identified, in which
a noun can resound as a verb and a verb of an apophansis can be
nominalized” (42/72). At first sight, this amphibology leads us to an
identification of the essence with the appearance and manifestation of
the said, but, more than “making being understood,” temporalization
126
Lev ina s St u d i e s 1 0
likewise makes “its essence vibrate [vibrer]” (35/61); in so doing, the
saying places itself on the hither side of being (l’en deçà de l’être), as
the possibility of ethical interruption of the essence.
The term echo reveals itself as being fitted perfectly to Levinas’s purposes. On the one hand, it refers to the anarchic saying that is always
prior to understanding and hearing, and, on the other hand, it bespeaks
the passivity of being accused: “The metaphor of a sound that would
be audible only in its echo meant to approach this way of presenting
one’s passivity as an underside without a right side” (OB 106/AQE
167). Only from the perspective of “a passivity more passive than all
passivity” (15/30), that is, from the ethical standpoint of vulnerability and exposure, in which one is addressed in the accusative, may a
comparison with echo in terms of recurrence of one’s responsibility
for others become intelligible. The recurrence of persecution is “prior
to all reflection, prior to every positing, an indebtedness before any
loan, not assumed, anarchical, subjectivity of a bottomless passivity,
made out of assignation, like the echo of a sound [l’écho d’un son] that
would precede the resonance [résonance] of this sound” (111/175).
The immemorial past implies a surplus that refuses its identification
as a theme in the said, which does not only imply the impossibility of
the saying to be completely absorbed by the said, but also demands a
redirection of one’s attention toward the echo of an anarchic bygone.
When referring to the amphibology of being and entities, Levinas points
out the disjunction between the possibility of “assembling the dispersion of duration into nouns and propositions,” which consequently
“lets being and entities be heard [laisse entendre]” through the resonance of essence, and the possibility of surprising “the echo [l’écho]
of the saying [in the said], whose signification cannot be assembled”
(27/48).
The impact of the diachrony of transcendence into synchronic
time resembles the movement of breathing, which is conceived
as “transcendence in the form of opening up [déclaustration]”
to the other (OB 181/AQE 278). The diachrony of breathing,
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
127
“a diachrony without synthesis” that resembles the very dynamic
of the “truth” (183/281), refers to the “movement from here to
yonder” (180/276), an “exile in oneself ” (182/279) that encompasses an inspiration that is “without a stopping point” and an expiration that is “without return” (182/279). Levinas goes on to say,
“In human breathing, in its everyday equality, perhaps we have to
already hear [entendre] the breathlessness of an inspiration that paralyzes essence, that transpierces it with an inspiration by the other, an
inspiration that is already expiration, that ‘rends the soul’! It is the
longest breath there is, spirit” (181–82/278). Levinas tarries alongside
the subject matter of “restlessness of respiration” (182/279) to draw
attention to the instant that separates inspiration and expiration, in
which the spirit holds its breath and by so doing hears the echo of the
otherwise. What is then heard in this contraction of the natural movement of breathing? Levinas explicitly affirms the ethical relevance of this
hearing for the diachrony of the-one-for-the-other (l’unpourl’autre
ellemême), a hearing of the resonance of silence.13 The temporalization
of the said in which essence vibrates “lets the pre-original saying be
heard [laisse entendre], answers to transcendence, to a dia-chrony, to
the irreducible divergency that opens here between the non-present
and every representable divergency, which in its own way . . . makes a
sign to the responsible one” (10–11/24–25).
I L Y A AND THE R ESONANCE OF S ILENCE
Levinas’s description of the “rustling” of the il y a as being a necessary condition for the possibility of substitution has never been so clear
as in this passage of Otherwise than Being: “To support [emphasis in
French edition] without compensation, the excessive or disheartening
hubbub [l’écoeurant remueménage] and encumberment [encombre
ment] of the there is [il y a] is needed” (OB 164/AQE 255), whereas
it awakens the ego “from its imperialist dream” (164/256). Nonetheless, this necessary condition is plainly insufficient to perform by
128
Le v ina s St u d i e s 1 0
itself the entire movement toward the beyond being, for it is only the
encounter with the other that evidences the complete powerlessness
of one’s self-assurance within the scope of the same.14
Levinas has already conceived art as that which creates silence,
and stressed the oppressive and frightening character of this silence,
in “The Transcendence of Words.” One learns from Existence and
Existents that silence refers to the il y a, to the voice of silence that
impersonally accompanies every instant of one’s existence, as the silence
of the infinite spaces described by Pascal. Some important displacements, however, are to be considered, regarding the relation between
the il y a and silence in Otherwise than Being. In this later work,
silence refers most of the time to the resonance of essence. The “resonance of silence,” of which the “listening eye” is aware, cannot be identified anymore with the silence of the il y a of Existence and Existents,
although there are some undeniable affinities. In Otherwise than Being,
it corresponds to the amphibology of being and entities and therefore
to the amphibology of language in its double reference to verbs and
nouns: “Here language does not double up the being of entities,
but exposes the silent resonance of the essence” (OB 40/AQE 70).
In “The Question of Subjectivity,” among other texts, Levinas
addresses the sense in which the resonance of silence connects with
Heidegger: “In its reign of being, being is language — and it is a silent
language or the voice of silence, Läute der Stille. (In this way, without realizing it, Heidegger would have ‘Judaized’ the Greeks!) This
voice of silence is that which is heard by the poet, who transposes it
into human language” (GDT 151/DMT 173).15 Levinas clarifies that
the expression “resonance of silence” refers to Heidegger’s Läute/
Geläut der Stille.16 To employ Levinas’s terminology, this expression
means the precedence of the said over communication, a said that can
be brought to manifestation and intelligibility by the hearing of the
poet. Nevertheless, Levinas warns, in so doing it also excludes any
possibility of diachrony that resonates in this silence. In what sense
could this emphasis on the “voice”17 of silence have “Judaized” the
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
129
Greeks, as Levinas claims? The contrast that Martin Jay offers between
these two traditions is helpful: “If the Jews could begin their most
heartfelt prayer, ‘Hear, O Israel,’ the Greek philosophers were in effect
urging, ‘See, O Hellas.’”18
In Otherwise than Being, the resonance of silence does not refer
anymore, in an exclusive way, to the presence of absence in the middle
of the night that oppresses the insomniac, but to the fact that essence
vibrates in the said. The “eye that listens” (oeil qui écoute) does not
capture an object in the light; instead, this expression adumbrates
the exposure of the eye to the unbearable silence that resounds,
to the “saying that does not say a word” (OB 151/AQE 236).
Time and the essence it unfolds by manifesting entities, identified in the themes of statements or narratives, resound as a silence
[résonnent comme un silence] without becoming themes themselves.
They can, to be sure, be named in a theme, but this naming does
not reduce to definitive silence the mute resonance [la résonance
sourde], the murmur of silence [le bourdonnement du silence], in which
essence is identified as an entity. Once again for the “listening eye” a
silence resounds [un silence résonne] about what had been muffled, the
silence of the parceling out of being, by which entities in their identities
are illuminated and show themselves (OB 38/AQE 67).
Brian Schroeder interprets the listening eye as follows: “For Levinas, the metaphor of the listening eye indicates the approach to move
beyond the hegemonic image, paradoxically dehierarchizing the relation between the terms visual/aural, sight/sound, seeing/hearing,
while maintaining the ethical superiority of the Other.”19 In a sense,
this procedure of “dehierarchizing” extends itself to other concepts of
Levinas’s philosophy in order to compose a language of the transcendence. This procedure is necessary to disrupt the system of references
that we are familiar with, while twisting meanings in order to free
new possibilities of addressing alterity. Therefore, the primary role of
presenting the awkward expression “eye that listens” has less to do
with vision or audition than with our expectations of these concepts;
130
Le v ina s St u d i e s 1 0
in other words, Levinas is undoubtedly less concerned with a theory
of vision or audition than with a displacing of these terms in order to
achieve a space of transcendence, because to him it is not a matter of
how a subject can apprehend words and sounds, but rather of how a
radical displacement of one’s existence is implicated by the encounter with the other. This can be explored in at least two ways. Firstly,
the “eye that listens” has paradoxically the same function as Plato’s
judge presented in the Gorgias, the one “divested ‘of eyes and ears’ ”
(OB 190/AQE 250),20 for both criticize the limitation of the sameness provided by the senses in ethical demands. Secondly, seeing and
hearing/listening are disconnected from their usual role in theories of
perception to deliver instead a function similar to that of the caress, for
the latter, as a fulfillment of proximity, opposes the perceiving mode
of touch. When Levinas states, “In every vision contact is announced:
sight and hearing caress the visible and the audible. Contact is not
an openness upon being, but an exposure of being” (80/128), he
is enabling the possibility of thinking the listening eye as performing
something entirely different from the traditional functions ascribed
to seeing and hearing in ontology. In which way does the listening
eye expose itself if not in the sense of allowing one to be stroked by
the echo of the saying? As well as caress, the listening eye engenders
proximity as proximity,21 as exposedness to the other, in which “grasping” becomes “being grasped” (75/121).
If the resonance of silence is thus attached to the vibration of the
essence within the said, how is the il y a described in Otherwise than
Being? Although there is some coherence with his previous works,
where Levinas has engaged it as rustling ( frôlement) or as “the muffled
rustling of the nothingness” (le sourd bruissement du néant) (TI 146/
TeI 156),22 the il y a is rather addressed in Otherwise than Being as a
modification of the essence, insofar as the “imperturbable essence”
turns “as in insomnia, from this neutrality and equality into monotony,
anonymity, insignificance, into an incessant buzzing [bourdonne
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
131
ment] that nothing can now stop and which absorbs all signification”
(OB 163/AQE 253–54). “Essence stretching on indefinitely (. . .) is
the horrifying there is,” affirms Levinas, punctuating simultaneously
the detachment or “subtraction” of the subject from the essence
(163/254): “It is the incessant buzzing [l’incessant bourdonnement]
that fills each silence, where the subject detaches itself from essence
and posits itself as a subject in face of its objectivity” (163/254). This
“incessant buzzing,” or “intolerable rumble” (bourdonnement intolé
rable) (163/254), fills the silence that resounds in the essence with a
“surplus of non-sense over sense” (164/255): “The rumbling of the
there is [bourdonnement de l’il y a] is the nonsense in which essence
turns, and in which thus turns the justice issued out of signification”
(163/254). Thenceforth, “to find itself again in essence” (163/254)
requires from the subject something other than a reversal of nonsense into sense again, whereas every sense is continually dissolved
into nullity for the il y a — only the diachronic substitution for the
other completely achieves that which il y a partially performs: in the
diachrony, the subject awakened to passivity fulfills the radical passivity
of the for-the-other.
These elements should also be considered in Levinas’s account of art.
He underscores the borderline position of art as follows: “Through art
essence and temporality begin to resound with poetry or song. And the
search for new forms, from which all art lives, keeps awake everywhere
the verbs that are on the verge of lapsing into substantives” (OB 40/
AQE 70). Art resounds in a way that prevents verbs from becoming
nouns, by keeping them awake. It is thus the resonance of silence that
resounds in art, the silence that art itself creates, which involves two
ideas that can be conjoined: in Existence and Existents, silence is linked
to the very experience of depersonalization, and in “The Reality and Its
Shadow” Levinas explains how one is impelled toward anonymity and
impersonality by means of art.23 In a sense, art keeps awake the verb in
creating the conditions by which one may experience impersonality,
132
Lev ina s St u d i e s 1 0
and this always means to bring silence to the fore: “As an impersonal
going on, an incessant splashing [incessant clapotis], a mute murmuring
[sourd bruissement], as there is, does not essence swallow up the signification that will give light to it? Is not the insistence of this impersonal
noise [bruit impersonnel] the threat of an end of the world felt in our
days?” (140/219). The silence does not draw attention to itself unless
something befalls, as when one is overwhelmed by insomnia, or when
the work of art ostensively imposes the “mute murmuring” upon the
spectator or listener. It is appropriate to speak of this silence, then, in
terms of deafness, as inattentiveness to the resonance of essence: “But
it does so in isolation: every work of art is in this sense exotic, without
a world, essence in dissemination. To fail to recognize the said properly
socalled (relative as it may be) in the predicative propositions which
every artwork — plastic, sonorous or poetic — awakens and makes
resound [résonner] in the form of exegesis is to show oneself to be as
profoundly deaf [surdité aussi profonde] as in the deafness of hearing
[n’entendre] only nouns in language” (41/71).
This deafness may likewise be described as the incapability of hearing the resonance of silence, or the lack of awareness of the amphibology that leads to the pure identification of the saying with nouns.
Nevertheless, Levinas also refers to another dimension of deafness,
which concerns other traditions besides ontology,24 as when he criticizes the ontological approach “if one is deaf [sourd] to the petition
that sounds [résonne] in questioning and even under the apparent
silence of the thought that questions itself, everything in a question
will be oriented to truth, and will come from the essence of being”
(OB 26/AQE 48). Levinas evokes the voices that do not coincide
with those of ontology, “inflexions of forgotten voices [inflexions de
voix oubliées]” (26/48) that resound in the essence. He asks if “there
is not heard a voice [ne s’entend pas une voix] coming from horizons
at least as vast as those in which ontology is situated” in the “mute
murmuring” of the il y a (140/219). Finally, the moments of “forgot-
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
133
ten voices” and the “voice of silence” conjoin with the “voice of the
infinite,” as in this passage where Levinas relates the infinite with “the
beginninglessness of an anarchy and . . . the endlessness of obligation,”
which allows him to conclude, “In the absolute assignation of the subject the Infinite is enigmatically heard [s’entend]: before and beyond.
The extent and accent of the voice in which the Infinite is thus heard
[la portée et l’accent de la voix où l’Infini ainsi s’entend] will have
to be made clear” (140/219).
F INAL R EMARKS
Although some of the acoustic motifs that appear in Otherwise than
Being had been employed in previous works, it is noteworthy that
only when Levinas brings to the fore subjects such as the amphibology of saying and said, the immemorial past, and the diachrony of the
interruption, among others, are they able to play a more relevant role
in his philosophy. Levinas gives new directions to concepts that have
appeared before, such as the silence that, besides its well-known connection with the arousal of the il y a, is also systematically employed
to designate the amphibology of being and entities. On the other
hand, there is an expansion of the subjects of his thought by means of
acoustics, and terms like hearing and listening are not just occasionally
mentioned, as often happened in previous writings, but become crucial
to the argumentation. This is unmistakable in the presentation of the
main themes: the eye that listens to the resonance of essence, and the
hearing that is aware of the echo of the otherwise, the breathlessness
of an inspiration, the pre-original saying, the forgotten voices, the
infinite, and so on. In this sense, the ubiquity of acoustic terms does
not only express a radicalization of his critique of the visible, but takes
on and expands his early insight on the capacity of sound and audition
to overflow the limits of the sensible and the given, as sketched in his
aesthetics of materiality.
134
Lev ina s St u d i e s 1 0
Notes
Funding for this research was provided by CAPES-Brazil as a scholarship for
postdoctoral studies. The author thanks Chiara Pavan and Stephanie Rumpza for
their probing and helpful comments. In addition to the abbreviations at the front
of this volume, the following are also used: Emmanuel Levinas, “La realité et son
ombre” (RO), Les temps modernes 38 (1948): 769–89; Emmanuel Levinas, “La
signification et le sens” (SS), Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 69, no. 2 (1964):
125–56; Emmanuel Levinas, “La transcendance des mots: À propos des Biffures
de Michel Leiris” (LTM), Les temps modernes 44 (1949): 1090–95.
1. Derrida writes, “Respect, beyond grasp and contact, beyond touch, smell
and taste, can be only as desire, and metaphysical desire does not seek to consume, as do Hegelian desire or need. This is why Levinas places sound above
light.” Jacques Derrida, “Violence and Metaphysics: An Essay on the Thought
of Emmanuel Levinas,” in Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (London:
Routledge, 2005), 123–24.
2. Ibid., 124.
3. According to the circumstances, entendre may be translated as hearing or
understanding. Unless stated otherwise, the passages discussed here are always
related to hearing.
4. For the sake of brevity, we skip the analysis of entendre, écouter, and audi
tion in Totality and Infinity, since it involves an entirely different approach. We
will indicate, however, some related aspects throughout this article.
5. In this sense, Ricoeur’s interpretation of Levinas in Oneself as Another can
also give rise to misunderstandings: “the ‘appearing’ of the Other in the face of
the Other eludes vision, seeing forms, and even eludes listening voices [l’écoute des
voix]. In truth, the face does not appear; it is not a phenomenon; it is an epiphany”
Oneself as Another (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994), 189, translation
modified; original at Paul Ricoeur, Soimême comme un autre (Paris: Éditions du
Seuil, 1990), 221. It is true that the face-to-face eludes listening to the voice of
the other, inasmuch as the obedience of command is prior to listening/hearing.
Nevertheless, Levinas also places relevance in “the voice in which the Infinite is thus
heard” (OB 140), or in the “eye that listens” (30) to the voice and the resonance
of silence, or in the hearing of “forgotten voices” (26), as we will develop further.
6. Gerard L. Bruns, “The Concepts of Art and Poetry in Emmanuel Levinas’s
Writings,” in The Cambridge Companion to Levinas, ed. Simon Critchley and
Robert Bernasconi (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 207.
7. Or from this other passage of Existence and Existents: “For the insecurity
does not come from the things of the day world which the night conceals; it is
due just to the fact that nothing approaches, nothing comes, nothing threatens;
this silence, this tranquility, this void of sensations constitutes a mute, absolutely
indeterminate menace” (EE 59/DEE 96).
8. Similarly, horror also denotes a sonorous account: “The rustling [frôlement]
of the there is . . . is horror” (EE 60; emphasis and ellipses in original/DEE 98).
Ro b e r to Wu
Th e Re c urre n ce of Acousti c s
135
9. “The particular automatic character of a walk or a dance to music is a mode
of being where nothing is unconscious, but where consciousness, paralyzed in its
freedom, plays, totally absorbed in this playing” (CPP 4/RO 775).
10. By the same token, in “The Proximity of the Other” one finds again the
“as though/as if ” relating listening and obedience: “The fortheother arises in
the I like a commandment heard by him, as if obedience were a state of listening
for the prescription” (IR 213).
11. The accusative form is prior to the appearance in the said, insofar as passivity exposes the fact that oneself is not the cause of oneself, but a creature. “The
hypostasis is exposed as oneself in the accusative form, before appearing in the
said proper to knowing as the bearer of a name” (OB 106/AQE 167). Moreover,
according to Levinas, “The oneself cannot form itself; it is already formed with
absolute passivity” (104/165). These passages enable the interpretation of the idea
that “The ego is in itself like a sound that would resound in its own echo [comme
un son qui résonnerait dans son propre écho], the node of a wave which is not once
again consciousness” (103/162). Once again, it is important to underline the
word “like” (comme), because the vocabulary of resonance and echo does not fit
with the perspective of the consciousness that Levinas rejects in these passages.
The analogy that would result in a dismissal of the unity of consciousness in this
last passage will be strongly reiterated some lines afterwards: “Nothing here resembles self-consciousness” (103/163). Of interest to us here is that Levinas rejects
subjectivity as consciousness and enacts it as passivity; in so doing, he posits the
subject as the one who echoes a pre-original inscription within him/her as the one
assigned with responsibility: “The response which is responsibility, responsibility
for the neighbor that is incumbent, resounds in this passivity, this disinterestedness
of subjectivity, this sensibility” (14–15/30–31).
12. Reduction has the precise meaning of “going back to the hither side of
being” or “to the hither side of the said” (OB 45/AQE 76).
13. Levinas writes, “Transcendence owes it to itself to interrupt its own
demonstration. Its voice has to be silent as soon as one listens for its message”
(OB 152/AQE 238).
14. The encounter with the other involves a double character: on the one hand,
the other is the one whom I can wish to kill, but any attempt to carry out this task is
unfruitful — the face eludes and shows the limits of my powers; on the other hand, it
is the other who interrupts the unceasing cycle of having my enterprises undone by
the il y a, whereas he or she offers an alternative that remains outside the dynamic
of power that underlies the contending with the il y a. Levinas writes, “Everything
that claims to come from elsewhere, even the marvels of which essence [emphasis
in French edition] itself is capable, even the surprising possibilities of renewal by
technology and magic, even the perfections of gods peopling the heights of this
world, and their immortality and the immortality they promise mortals — all this
does not deaden the heartrending bustling of the there is recommencing behind
every negation. There is not a break in the business carried on by essence, not a
distraction. Only the meaning of the other is irrecusable, and forbids the reclusion
136
Le v ina s St u d i e s 1 0
and reentry into the shell of the self. A voice comes from the other shore. A voice
interrupts the saying of the already said” (OB 182–83/280).
15. A similar explanation is found in Otherwise than Being: “The said can indeed
be understood to be prior to communication and the intersubjective representation
of being. Being would have a signification, that is, would manifest itself as already
invoked in silent and nonhuman language, by the voices of silence [voix du silence],
in the Geläut der Stille, the language that speaks before men and harbors the esse
ipsum, the language which poetry puts into human words” (OB 135/AQE 211).
16. It is not possible to discuss here what this expression means to Heidegger
and in which sense Levinas’s reading is appropriate or not. See Martin Heidegger,
“Language,” in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New York:
Harper and Row, 1975).
17. Geläut der Stille is translated as “the peal of stillness” by Albert Hofstadter.
Although Heidegger refers to command (Geheiß ) and call (Ruf ) in this text, the
term “voice” that Levinas frequently employs does not appear in “Language.”
18. Martin Jay, Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in TwentiethCentury
French Thought (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 33. The difference between Christian and Jewish tradition is also relevant: “The word made
flesh in the Christian tradition was thus a falling away from the Jewish stress on
the voice and the ear” (556).
19. Brian Schroeder, “The Listening Eye: Nietzsche and Levinas,” in Emma
nuel Levinas: Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers, vol. 2, ed. Claire Katz
and Lisa Trout (London: Routledge, 2005), 279.
20. See Plato, Gorgias 523c–d.
21. “In this caress proximity signifies as proximity, and not as an experience
of proximity” (OB 80/AQE 128).
22. Sourd bruissement is also translated as “mute murmuring” in Otherwise
than Being, as we will see afterwards.
23. The silence of resonance presented in Otherwise than Being does not coincide with Levinas’s early account of silence in Existence and Existents. Among the
many discordances, it is noteworthy that the “voice of silence” with which one is
confronted while facing the il y a appears as “frightening” and “oppressive,” as an
unbearable silence that reproaches every attempt of the subject to render meaning
only by himself/herself. Conversely, this expression is defined in Otherwise than
Being as the very temporalization and vibration of the essence.
24. “Behind being and its monstration, there is now already heard the resonance [s’entend la résonance] of other significations forgotten in ontology, which
now solicit our inquiry” (OB 38/AQE 67).