Medicine Studies (2010) 2:151–160
DOI 10.1007/s12376-010-0053-1
EDITORIAL NOTE
Medical Imaging: Pictures, ‘‘as if’’ and the Power
of Evidence
Irmgard Müller • Heiner Fangerau
Received: 14 October 2010 / Accepted: 19 October 2010 / Published online: 23 November 2010
Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010
There is no doubt that we are living in a time of
iconography. Pictures and images surround us from
birth until death. Throughout our whole lives (and
even before birth and after death), we are the product
and the producer of a pure flood of images, which
determine our thinking, wishes and imagination. The
omnipresence of images is the result of a fundamental
shift during modernity in both the status and modalities of presentation procedures. The concomitant
increase in technical methods for image production
resulted in a new kind of knowledge formation
compared to premodern times. It is a specific element
of these modern and postmodern processes of
knowledge formation and dissemination that knowledge itself seems to be more dependent on the
possibilities of its illustration, demonstration and
presentation than on the matter or cause itself.
Nevertheless, regarding the ‘‘claim for truth’’, this
practice is not less unproblematic than knowl-
I. Müller
Universität Bochum, Bochum, Germany
e-mail:
[email protected]
H. Fangerau (&)
Institute of the History, Philosophy and Ethics
of Medicine, Universität Ulm, Frauensteige 6,
89075 Ulm, Germany
e-mail:
[email protected]
edge that comes along without any form of representation.1
Contemporary medical practices are impossible
without imaging techniques. Whereas in many disciplines, the history and philosophy of visual culture play
an important role (Lynch 2006), in medicine only single
aspects have been highlighted so far. One example is the
practice of neuroimaging (cf. (Dijck 2005)). The
‘‘Gestaltsehen’’ perspective has been highlighted (Burri
2008, 214), and the process of creating visual evidence
using complex combinations of numerical methods,
statistical procedures and visualization-algorithms has
been discussed previously (Schinzel 2006; Huber
2009). In line with this research, this special issue of
Medicine Studies focuses on the specific use of
visualizations, the transformation of observations and
data into images, the shift in medical viewing patterns
caused by new visualization techniques and the nomothetic function of visual discourse networks for
distinguishing the normal and the pathological.2
This thematic issue of Medicine Studies also intends
to stimulate further debates and research. For example,
we lack systematic studies regarding the transformation
1
The body of literature regarding the practice of visualization
is steadily increasing. An instructive bibliographical essay
review is offered by Monika Dommann (2004).
2
The articles of this special issue were presented and discussed
during an interdisciplinary conference on Medical Imaging in
Ulm, Germany organized among others by the radiologists Rethy
Chhem (IAEA Vienna) and Shih-Chang Wang (Sydney), the
philosopher Santago Sia (Dublin) and the authors of this editorial.
123
152
and modelling of medical data by evaluation, selection
and statistical processing, which are not only phenomena of the computer age but have existed long before.
From the existing literature and papers in this issue, it is
clear that questions regarding the validity of medical
images are of special interest: many modern visualization techniques do not refer to observable correlates but
to complex mathematical processing procedures, which
have caused a paradoxical phenomenon, since they
produce virtual images that do not exist as visible
entities (Adelmann et al. 2009). In the history of
medicine, analyses focusing on the epistemic status of a
‘‘reality’’ or ‘‘visibility’’ produced by measurement and
evaluation are a desideratum along with studies on the
evidentiary value of technically evoked images. Consequently, the topic of this editorial is the epistemological potential of images and artefacts in medicine. By
providing two examples from the history of medicine,
we will examine the claim of evidence put forward by
scientists with the help of visualizations. These visualizations are scientific pictures, which are the result of the
interaction of processing measured data, picture creation, amplification, reduction and human interpretation.
Paul Ehrlich’s Images
The first example involves Paul Ehrlich’s central
contribution to immunology—the side-chain theory.
Cambrosio, Jacobi and Keating have shown that the
development, reception and acceptance of Ehrlich’s
side-chain theory, which explained the immune
response as an antibody-receptor reaction, offers an
illuminating example of the role and function of
graphical images during the implementation of a
medical theory (Cambrosio et al. 1993). Ehrlich based
his side-chain theory on his earlier systematic studies
on the relationship between the chemical structures of
pharmaceuticals and their distribution in different
organs (Ehrlich 1901) and on the research for his
habilitation, in which he had examined the organism’s
need for oxygen (Ehrlich 1885).3 The underlying idea
of his working hypothesis can be summarized as
follows: living cells have side chains on their surfaces
similar to those of the benzene ring, which can link
with toxins (e.g., from bacteria) and make these toxins
3
On the history of the side-chain theory cf. (Silverstein 1989;
2002).
123
I. Müller, H. Fangerau
innoxious. Since the receptiveness of an organism for
toxins depended on these ‘‘protoplasm groups’’, he
named them receptors. Ehrlich imagined the process
of ‘‘detoxification’’ as a chemical reaction similar to
the neutralization of an acid by a base.
According to Ehrlich’s experimentally supported
view, each receptor could only react with specific
agents depending on its chemical structure. The toxins
had to fit in the receptor like a key in a lock, an analogy
that was coined by the chemist Emil Fischer in 1894 to
describe the stereochemical anchoring of enzymesubstrate-binding (Fischer 1894). Ehrlich used this
stereochemical conception as an explanation for the
antitoxin doctrine he developed while studying diphtheria toxin and diphtheria antitoxin. He attributed
specific groups of atoms to both reacting agents (toxin
and antitoxin) in the process of detoxification. He
assumed that the toxin consisted of two chemically
different parts. One part of the toxin, which linked to
the side-chain of the cell’s protoplasm,4 was called the
haptophore group, and the second part carrying the
poison was called the toxophore group (Ehrlich 1904).
If the haptophore group bound to the cell’s receptor,
then the receptor switched off. Ehrlich theorized that
the cell tried to repair this defect by regenerating and
releasing the same specific group of molecules in
excess to replenish their circulation in the blood. Now,
the receptors as antibodies could intercept and render
the intruding toxins harmless.
Ehrlich formulated this audacious and complex
explanation of the mysterious processes of immunity
in 1897 after performing experiments in animals with
ricin and antiricin (Ehrlich 1897a, b). At first, his
theory was disputed. Ehrlich himself encountered
repeated difficulties because the results of his animal
experiments were instable. In a letter to his cousin
Carl Weigert, a professor of pathology in Frankfurt,
Ehrlich lamented at the end of December 1896: ‘‘Here
everything is fluctuating and it is, as if one tried to
build a palace in the swamps. After all it eventually
works, but it costs a dreadful lot of animals, anger and
boredom’’ (Heymann 1928).5 In their correspondence,
4
Ehrlich at first followed the terminology of benzole chemistry and called the binding groups of the cell protoplasmatic
‘‘side chains’’. Later he used the term ‘‘receptor’’, because the
term ‘‘side chain’’ insinuated far too simple concepts regarding
their structure. Cf. (Ehrlich and Morgenroth 1904).
5
This and all of the following translations from German by HF.
Medical Imaging
Ehrlich expressed admiration for Weigert for his
mastery of staining techniques, and Weigert critically
commented on Ehrlich’s experiments. This correspondence also reveals the first graphical representation of the events Ehrlich assumed were taking place
on the cellular level. In 1898, Ehrlich cursorily
sketched the processes to foster understanding of his
theory, and he commented on his picture not without
self-mockery with the concomitant question ‘‘beautiful representations?’’ (‘‘Schöne Figuren?’’) (Fig. 1).
Ehrlich’s sketch shows that he considered the
binding of toxins by the cell’s protoplasm as analogous to the physiological nutrition of the cell. Soon
after, Ehrlich explicitly stated that there was a
similarity between toxins and food molecules when
he declared: ‘‘The toxins, as highly complicated
products of herbal and animal cells, share certain
153
haptophore groups with food molecules and are
consequently anchored by appropriate receptors of
the protoplasm as well’’ (Ehrlich and Morgenroth
1904).
Ehrlich’s ambiguous signature ‘‘beautiful representations’’ was chosen by Cambrosio, Jacobi and
Keating in a similar translation as the title for their
‘‘beautiful pictures’’ essay mentioned above (Cambrosio et al. 1993). In this essay, they examined how
Ehrlich developed diagrams from his first sketch to
implement his hypothesis. Our following remarks are
based on their findings.
Two years after his sketch of the ‘‘beautiful
representations’’ in his letter to Weigert, Ehrlich
published the first diagrams to depict his theory of
immunity. These images were added to the printed
version of an invited lecture Ehrlich gave in London
Fig. 1 Letter of Paul
Ehrlich with ,,Schönen
Figuren‘‘. First sketch of the
side chain theory in a letter
from Paul Ehrlich to Carl
Weigert. In: Paul Heymann,
Zur Geschichte der
Seitenkettentheorie Paul
Ehrlichs. Klinische
Wochenschrift 7 (1928).
p. 1307
123
154
for the Royal Society (Ehrlich 1900). In this paper,
two images appeared for the first time, which in the
following years were modified, refined and combined
to larger complexes. As the levels of the single
components’ abstraction increased, the specificity of
the functions they represented grew. When the sidechain theory was applied to explain haematolysis,
both the receptor apparatuses and the number of
assumed immune bodies were duplicated. Ehrlich
conceptualized that an amboceptor circulated in the
blood with two different haptophoric groups, which
acted as an intermediate between the erythrocytes and
complement (Ehrlich and Morgenroth 1900). Soon
Ehrlich’s scheme did not only operate with receptors
of a first, second or third order, but it also included
manifold complements, toxoids, toxonoids, toxons,
complementoids, epitoxoids and nutriceptors.6
At first, Ehrlich abstained from giving chemical
definitions or clear statements regarding the chemical
existence or non-existence of these agents. In his
London lecture, he emphasized that his figures were
hypothetical in character. He explicitly declared that
his diagrams should be looked at without any
morphological considerations. Ehrlich emphasized
that they were only a pictorial method of displaying
and explaining his views about the metabolism of the
cell and the way that toxins and antitoxins acted
during immunization.
Despite of Ehrlich’s introductory remarks concerning the visualization of his theory of immunization in which he saw nothing more than ‘‘the clearly
arranged abstraction of an experience gained from an
extraordinary large number of exact experiments’’
(Ehrlich 1904, V), his diagrams did not fail to have an
impact. They suggested and provoked the impression
of a real fact. In particular, the ostensive visualization
of the single components, which resembled living
organisms, seemed to confirm the belief that he had
been able to unravel the mystery of life. Ehrlich
presented structures with tentacles stemming from the
protoplasm to represent the associations of polyps.
His images resembled for example those of polyps
and medusae published by Gegenbaur (Gegenbaur
1854). Later, Ehrlich also used analogies from
botany. The visitors to his institute, who had wished
to see cell receptors through his microscope, were
6
See the compilation by Schatiloff (Schatiloff 1908, 9ff).
123
I. Müller, H. Fangerau
deeply disappointed when they were only shown
these symbols instead of reality (Cambrosio et al.
1993).
Ehrlich’s theory was rapidly disseminated not only
because of the analogies in his graphical representations, but also due to his illustrative textual presentation. By extensively using metaphors and analogies,
Ehrlich intensified the impression that he was
describing reactions of real, existing chemical bodies,
which anchored and captured toxins like fishing rods
and snapped poisonous elements up with the help of
their tentacles.7 Ehrlich received admiration, but also
faced some severe criticism for his images. The
French bacteriologist Jules Bordet vehemently
attacked Ehrlich. Bordet had described non-specific
serum components—the so called alexines, which
correspond with today’s complement system, and in
1919, Bordet received the Nobel Prize for his
immunological research. Bordet accused Ehrlich of
having achieved the acceptance of his theory only
with the help of popular illustrations in the mould of
children’s’ picture books (Christ and Tauber 1997).
In Bordet’s view, Ehrlich had put forward his theory
only with visual definitions without caring for the
ontological status of the assumed substances. Bordet
himself strictly abstained from using any pictorial
representation and advocated textual presentation. He
considered textual presentation the more adequate
and precise method of putting forward a theory.
Similarly, other scientists argued that the diagrams
were too imprecise to represent the complexity of the
protoplasm and the reactions between protein
7
As an example may serve Ehrlich‘s essay on the theory of
lysin’s actions, in which he described the assimilation of giant
molecules in the cell (Ehrlich 1899): ,,In sehr zweckmäßiger
Weise wird solches erreicht werden können, wenn der Fangarm
des Protoplasmas zu gleicher Zeit als Träger einer fermentativen Gruppe diese sofort in nahe räumliche Beziehung zu der
zu verdauenden und zu assimilierenden Beute bringt. Derartige
zweckmäßige Einrichtungen, dass der Fangapparat zugleich
verdauende Wirkung ausübt, finden wir ja in der ganzen Reihe
der verdauenden höheren Pflanzen in der verschiedensten Art
und Form. So sezernieren die Tentakeln der Drosera, also
Fangarme im allergröbsten Sinne, die das gefangene Object
umgeben, eine Flüssigkeit, die stark verdauende Wirkung
ausübt. […] Wir nehmen also an, dass bei der Ergreifung dieser
[Toxine] und anderer hochcomplicirter Körper Seitenketten
besonderer Art vorhanden sind, die ausser dem fangenden
Complex noch einen anderen Complex enthalten, der durch
Fixation geeigneter Fermente Verdauungswirkung auslösen
kann. […]’’.
Medical Imaging
molecules and chemical atoms that were taking place
on the invisible level.
Indeed, Ehrlich had aimed for this vagueness and
indefiniteness in his representations. He was sure that
the single components of his side-chain theory were
not really existing entities. They were obviously
unreal and could be identified only by their assumed
effects. Their factual existence, however, was unproven and unprovable. The components could only be
discerned through consistently repeated experimental
events, which happened as if Ehrlich’s assumptions
were correct. Thus, the single components of the sidechain theory were scientific fiction, not a copy of
reality (Dworetzky 1914).
Ehrlich treated his visual representations as if the
assumed structures really existed, and he used them as
heuristic tools to structure further experiments and to
generate new knowledge. He did not use them as
explications of causes or to make specific postulations
regarding their appearance. For Ehrlich, the value of
his images materialized in a constructive alternativism,
in their status of images that represented his side-chain
theory ‘‘as if’’ its postulated elements existed in real.
Their power as a model was achieved through their
plausibility and the sensation of evidence they emanated at first sight. However, the ‘‘epistemic power of
representativeness’’, using Sybille Kraemer’s (Krämer
2009, 12) terminology, turned out to be fallacious,
since it did not lead to the actual chemical reality.8
Ehrlich’s visualizations reminded his viewers of
living organisms and could be related to well-known
examples, such as the old conception of the body as an
organism that is ready to battle hostile agents. This
immediacy secured his pictures and the theory they
represented a lasting impact, which was independent
of their real ontological status. Ludwik Fleck coined
the terms ‘‘collective thought style’’ and ‘‘thought
coercion’’ to describe this type of directed perception,
which goes hand in hand with an according theoretical
and factual processing of what is perceived (Fleck
8
Ehrlich himself closed his introduction into the side-chain
theory stressing the heuristic power of the combination of
single research results and the principles of his theory: ,,Die
unübersehbare Fülle der Einzelthatsachen läßt sich ohne
Zwang in die hier kurz dargestellten Prinzipien [der Seitenkettentheorie] einordnen, die zugleich heuristische Kraft genug
bewähren, um ihrerseits wieder zur Auffindung zahlreicher
neuer experimenteller Thatsachen zu führen’’(Ehrlich and
Morgenroth 1904).
155
1980). With regard to Ehrlich, one might postulate
that ‘‘vision coercion’’ and diagrammatic coercion
could explain the evidentiary power of his images.
A glance into a modern immunology textbook
reveals that the immunological diagrams put forward
by Ehrlich to visualize unknown immune system
events still claim validity. Furthermore, they still
appear to encapsulate and reproduce real structures
(e.g. Murphy and Travers 2009).
Imaging Sperms and Concepts of Embryological
Development
A second illustrative example of this general principle of filtering an observer’s perception is the debate
that occurred during the 17th and 18th centuries
among reproductive biologists. Here again, theoretical conceptions evoked observations and illustrations, which retroacted with the underlying idea. At
the time, few questions preoccupied scientists as
much as those involving human development, and
few debates challenged the existing metaphysical
world order to such an extent as these questions.
In 1651, William Harvey published his observation
that embryonic development originated from the egg,
which led to a scientific dispute (Harvey 1651). His
dictum ‘‘omne vivum ex ovo’’ challenged the classic
doctrine of spontaneous generation of living beings
from inorganic material (Fig. 2). Since Harvey was
unable to describe the role of sperm in generation, his
dictum also challenged the validity of the theory that
female and male sperm contributed equally to human
development. No matter how hard Harvey tried, he
could not detect any sperm in the uteri of his dissected
research animals (Goltz 1986). He concluded that
male sperm stimulated the egg through an immaterial
‘‘aura seminalis’’ (cf. Schurig 1720), a theory, which
did not convince his contemporaries. Although Harvey was highly regarded as a scientific authority, since
he had described the circulation of blood, his tenets on
human development were severely criticized.
Scientists began intensive investigations into the
field of human development. After 20 years of thorough research, it caused a sensation when the first
spermatozoa were sighted under the microscope. The
spermatozoa were pictured as small animalcula—real
creatures with heads and tails. The paradox powers
postulated by Harvey seemed to have materialized.
123
156
Fig. 2 Detail of the frontispiece of: William Harvey, Excercitationes de generatione animalium. London 1651, Jupiter is
holding a box with the inscription ,,Ex ovo omnia’’. The picture
demonstrates the programmatic direction of the book, in which
Harvey tries to prove the development of every living creature
from the egg (p. 409: ,,Ovum esse primordium commune
omnibus animalibus‘‘)
The first image of this mysterious animal appeared on
the margins of a writing of the Dutch physicist Nicolas
Hartsoeker (1656–1725) to Christian Huyghens
(Huyghens 1899, 58–61). Hartsoeker reported in his
letter and in print (Hartsoeker 1678, 355–366) that he
had observed uncountable small creatures, which
resembled small eels or tadpoles in a cockerel’s sperm
under the microscope. Sixteen years later, he reprinted
his spermatic animals in a book on optics with the
remark that human sperm looked the same (Hartsoeker
1694, 227). He added that each sperm included a
female and a male exemplar, which was inserted into
the egg in order to grow and to be nurtured here. To
emphasize this textually presented idea, he added a
microscopic view showing a spermatic animal that
appeared as a cowering homunculus. The long tail
housed the allantoic vein to allow for placental nidation. However, Hartsoeker was very careful regarding
the real existence of these embryological beings. Only
later, when he copied this picture in other works, the
original explanatory function of the image was blended
with empirical observations. It became ‘‘real’’.
Even more spectacular was the image of a spermatic
animal published by the secretary of the Academy of
Montpellier Francois Plantade under the anagram
Dalenpatius. Dalenpatius claimed to have observed the
moult of a spermatozoon under the microscope
(Dalenpatius [=Francois Plantade] 1699–1700). As
123
I. Müller, H. Fangerau
proof, he added an image of a moulting homunculus
whose head, breast, arms and legs were still mantled
with an outer skin. The credibility of this report was
highly questioned. The French physician Jean Astruc
could only interpret the image as a satire put forward
by Dalenpatius to ridicule preformationists who
believed that the forms of living beings preexisted in
miniature versions (Astruc 1740, 1002f.). Nevertheless, the image had a lasting effect. It suited preformationism so perfectly that in 1721, the Italian
biologist Antonio Vallisneri did not hesitate to include
a reproduction of these animalcules in a table of known
spermatozoons (Vallisneri 1721, Table I, Figure 7–9
and pp. 6–7), (Fig. 3).
No matter how unusual these fantastic images
might appear to us today, when they were published
in the 17th century they seemed to fit the expectations
of biologists who were using microscopes to visualize
the invisible. For instance, in Francesco Redi’s
representations of fish worms, he attributed them
with a human shape (Redi 1684, Table 23). Another
example of this effect is Joblot’s descriptions of the
organisms he observed in an extraction of anemones
(Joblot 1718, p. 58, Table 56, Figure 12). He
described that the back of one six-legged animal
was covered with a mask resembling a human face
(Fig. 4). Perhaps Joblot was ridiculing microscopic
representation practices, but the basis of this image
may have been more credible. Modern representations of hydrachnidia still have some similarities to
Jablot’s image (Kaestner 1969, 777f.).
Although the pioneer of microscopic research and
sperm visualization Antonj van Leeuwenhoek
rejected and criticized these exaggerated visual interpretations (van Leeuwenhoek 1719, 82–94), he contributed his own interpretations of microscopic
images. In many works, Leeuwenhoek described
vivid, visible structures and vessels inside the animalcula (van Leeuwenhoek 1678, Table 13). He also
promoted the idea that organisms and their body parts
were preformed in the spermatic animals. His visualizations helped to fix and implement the preformistic ideas (Vallisneri 1721, Table I).9 Leeuwenhoek’s
9
Vallisneri combines images of spermatic animals following
the descriptions of Leeuwenhoek, Nicolas Andry and
Dalenpatius. He adds the comment that it is impossible to
neglect the factual existence of the imaged animals (una cosa
di fatto) facing so many prominent witnesses.
Medical Imaging
157
Fig. 3 Plate displaying
different spermatic animals
(vermi spermatici): Fig. II,
III, IV and V following A.
van Leeuwenhoek;—Fig.
VI (salt crystals in the
spermatic animal), VII, VIII
und IX following
Dalenpatius;—Fig. X, XI
and XII following N. Andry
(De la génération des vers
dans le corps de l’homme,
1701, Table 3, Fig. 12, 13,
14);—Fig. XIII Spermatic
animals of a rabbit in
motion, observed under the
microscope by Vallisneri.
Antonio Vallisneri: Istoria
della generazione
dell’uomo, e degli animali,
se sia da’vermicelli
spermatici, o dalle uova.
Venedig 1721, Plate I
authority as the inventor of the microscope strengthened the validity of his exposures, and his less
dramatic visualizations convinced with ostensive
precision. These images were carried from handbook
to handbook: Even 150 years later, the impact of
Leeuwenhoek’s images lasted on. In 1821, Prevost
and Dumas described the origin of sperm in the
testicles, which contradicted the prevailing idea that
spermatozoa could be classified as independent
organisms (Prévost and Dumas 1821–1822,
Table 1–2). Nevertheless, their illustrations referred
to Leuwenhoek. The idea that spermatozoa were
organisms was bound to contemporary thinking to
such an extent that in 1837, the physiologist Gustav
Valentin described the mouth, anus, stomach and
early stages of evolutionary development in bear
sperm (Valentin 1837, Table 24).
After Leeuwenhoek’s first description of sperm,
spermatogenesis became an important field of
research, and Harvey’s observation that the egg was
the starting point of reproduction was more or less
neglected. Only a few ovulists challenged the tenets
of the animalculists. It might be argued that Harvey’s
abandonment of images hindered the reception of his
findings. Except for its allegoric frontispiece, Harvey’s work did not contain any figures. Harvey
intentionally had abstained from using visualizations
as stated in his foreword (Harvey 1651, 10). He
distrusted images of any kind because he believed
they abstracted, generalized and distorted in contrast
to precise observations. Any image could only be a
false representation of its object. Harvey believed that
only own immediate observations were credible and
reliable.
Nevertheless, even if scientists of the 17th and
18th century agreed with Harvey’s statement regarding images, they still used visual representations.
Their critical use constituted a theory that was then
again backed by images. Last but not least, the
ovulists and animalculists agreed on one point. Both
followed the preformist tradition. Therefore, they
both tended to display homunculi in their respective
123
158
Fig. 4 Organisms found in an infusion of anemones described
by Joblot. ,,Tout le dessus de son corps est couvert d’un beau
masque bien formé, de figure humaine, parfaitement bien fait;
comme on en peut juger par ce dessein, où l’on voit six pattes
et une queuë, sortant de dessous ce masque, qui est couronné
d’une coëffure singuliere‘‘ (Part II, p. 57). Joblot, L.:
Descriptions et usages de plusieurs nouveaux microscopes,
tant simples que composez. Paris 1718, Taf. 6, Fig. 12
microscopic images, as can be viewed in a 1729
figure by the Dutch scientists Thomas Kerckring
(Kerckring 1729).
Conclusion
What can be concluded from these examples about
the practice of medical imaging and the evidentiary
power of pictures? Both examples show that scientific
images cannot only be seen as illustrations of
experimentally induced or morphological facts. They
are bound to scientific practice, the thought styles of a
thought collective, the cultures of popularizing
knowledge and the cultures of the public understanding of science. Additionally, they are of course
constituted by preexisting concepts. They represent
the observed objects as if they existed in reality—a
practice Immanuel Kant had considered to be not
only possible but theoretically and practically necessary when the existing concepts do not suffice to
provide explanation and understanding of the
123
I. Müller, H. Fangerau
unknown (kant 1783, §57, 58; Vaihinger 1911). On
this basis, the philosopher Hans Vaihinger established
his philosophy of ‘‘as if’’, a fictionalism, which would
see the aspect of ‘‘as if’’ in the two examples above
instead of empty fiction. As our examples reveal, the
‘‘as if’’ in these cases has its own theoretical and
practical value, which leads to theoretical and
practical consequences (Vaihinger 1911). Thus, the
evidence of ‘‘as if’’ images also lies in their power to
produce plausible consequences. In a Festschrift for
Vaihinger, the system biologist Ludwig von Bertalanffy commented on the meaning of Vaihinger’s
analogical factionalism stating that every interpretation of reality remains a ‘‘risky adventure of reason’’.
Either one should generally abstain from interpreting
the entity of any object or one should be aware of the
fact that these interpretations have the characteristics
of an analogy. There is no proof that the ‘‘real’’ world
has the same structure, as it is attributed by our own
experience, analogies and metaphors (Bertalanffy
1986, 86–87).
Established patterns and conventions of perception
shape the representation of these analogies in images.
They constitute on the one hand how knowledge is
displayed and on the other hand direct the formulation
and presentation of new knowledge. Only images
fitting these traditions can be trusted, and only these
images are attributed with some evidentiary power.
They are consciously false assumptions put forward for
the sake of their functional results. Whoever accepts
this character would agree with revisions. As the
philosopher Arnold Kowalewski argued, none of these
fictions would be privileged, and these (scientific)
assumptions—and thus their visual representations—
followed the ‘‘law of shifting ideas’’. Whenever the
philosophy of ‘‘as if’’ fictionalized certain ideas after
critical inquiry, it weakened its impact, but attracted
new followers. Consequently, it founded an ‘‘image
collective’’ (‘‘Ideengemeinschaft’’), a concept later
taken up by Ludwik Fleck as the ‘‘thought collective’’
(Kowalewski 1986, 230).
For the history of medical imaging, this theory
means that any illustrator has to adapt his visualizations to the vision coercions of the respective thought
collective. When illustrations are produced or signed
by authorities, this increases their evidentiary power.
Citations of these illustrations and re-citations of
patterns introduced by these authorities increase the
credibility of the respective images. Finally, by
Medical Imaging
reiteration and the solidification of a theory, the
original explanatory function of an image can be
transformed into an empirical observation. As a
consequence, the former ‘‘as if’’ status transcends
into an ‘‘it is’’ status, which might be deceptive but is
taken for reality. The image itself has become the
proof. There is no evidentiary power per se; there is
only a power of evidence, which is constituted by
those who produce medical images and negotiate
them with their recipients. Thus, the evidentiary
power of medical imaging depends on how convincingly the borderline between ‘‘as if’’ and ‘‘it is’’ is
transcended. The transition of this borderline is the
underlying story of the following papers, which
hopefully lead to fruitful further discussions in this
journal and beyond.
References
Adelmann, R., J. Frercks, et al. 2009. Datenbilder. Zur digitalen Bildpraxis in den Naturwissenschaften. Bielefeld:
Transcript Verlag.
Astruc, J. 1740. De Morbis Venereis Libri novem. Paris: Editio
altera. Tomus II.
Bertalanffy, L. von. 1986. Vahingers Lehre von der analogischen Fiktion in ihrer Bedeutung für die Naturphilosophie.
In Die Philosophie des Als Ob und das Leben. Festschrift
zu Hans Vaihingers 80. Geburtstag, ed. A. Seidel, 82–91.
Aalen: Scientia.
Burri, R. 2008. Doing images. Zur Praxis medizinischer Bilder.
Bielefeld: Transcript
Cambrosio, A., D. Jacobi, et al. 1993. Ehrlich’s ,,beautiful
pictures’’ and the controversial beginnings of immunological imagery. Isis 84: 662–699.
Christ, E., and A. Tauber. 1997. Debating humoral immunity
and epistemology: The rivalry of the immunochemists
Jules Bordet and Paul Ehrlich. Journal of the History of
Biology 30: 321–356.
Dalenpatius [=Francois Plantade] 1699–1700. Extrait d0 une
Lettre de M. DALENPATIUS à l’Auteur de ces Nouvelles,
contenant une découverte curieuse, faite par le moyen du
Microscope. In: Nouvelles de la République des Lettres,
t. IV, pp 552–554.
Dijck, J.V. 2005. The transparent body: A cultural analysis of
medical imaging. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Dommann, M. 2004. Vom Bild zum Wissen: Eine
Bestandsaufnahme wissenschaftshistorischer Bildforschung.
Gesnerus 61: 77–89.
Dworetzky, A. 1914. Zur erkenntnistheoretischen Würdigung
der Ehrlichschen Seitenkettentheorie. Deutsche medizinische Wochenschrift 40: 1324–1326.
Ehrlich, P. 1885. Das Sauerstoff-Bedürfniss des Organismus.
Eine farbenanalytische Studie. Berlin: Hirschwald.
159
Ehrlich, P. 1897a. Die Wertbemessung des Diphterieheilserums und deren theoretische Grundlagen. Klinisches
Jahrbuch 6: 299–326.
Ehrlich, P. 1897b. Zur Kenntnis der Antitoxinwirkung. Fortschritte der Medicin 15(2): 41–43.
Ehrlich, P. 1899. Zur Theorie der Lysinwirkung. Berliner
Klinische Wochenschrift 36: 6–9.
Ehrlich, P. 1900. Croonian lecture: On immunity with special
reference to cell life. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London 66: 424–448.
Ehrlich, P. 1901. Über Toxine und Antitoxine. Therapie der
Gegenwart 42: 193–200.
Ehrlich, P. 1904. Vorwort. Gesammelte Arbeiten zur Immunitätsforschung. Berlin: Hirschwald.
Ehrlich, P., and J. Morgenroth. 1900. Ueber Hämolysine.
Vierte Mittheilung. Berliner klinische Wochenschrift 37:
681–687.
Ehrlich, P., and J. Morgenroth. 1904. Wirkung und Entstehung
der aktiven Stoffe im Serum nach der Seitenkettentheorie.
In Handbuch der pathogenen Mikroorganismen, Vo. 4,
ed. W. Kolle and A. Wassermann, 430–451. Jena: Gustav
Fischer Verlag.
Fischer, E. 1894. Einfluss der Configuration auf die Wirkung
der Enzyme. Berichte der deutschen chemischen Gesellschaft 27: 2985–2993.
Fleck, L. 1980. Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Einführung in die Lehre vom
Denkstil und Denkkollektiv. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
Gegenbaur, C. 1854. Zur Lehre vom Generationswechsel und
der Fortpflanzung bei Medusen und Polypen. Würzburg:
Stahel.
Goltz, D. 1986. Der leere Uterus. Zum Einfluss von Harveys
De generatione animalium auf die Lehren von der
Konzeption. Medizinhistorisches Journal 21: 242–268.
Hartsoeker, N. (1678). Extrait d’une lettre de M. Nicolas
Hartsoeker écrite à l’Auteur du Journal touchant la
maniere de faire les nouveaux Microscopes […]. Journal
des Scavans pour l’anne´e LXXVIII: 355–356.
Hartsoeker, N. 1694. Essay de dioptrique. Paris: Jean Anisson.
Harvey, W. 1651. Exercitationes de generatione animalium.
Amsterdam: Elzevir.
Heymann, B. 1928. Zur Geschichte der Seitenkettentheorie
Paul Ehrlichs. Klinische Wochenschrift 7: 1257–1260,
1305–1309.
Huber, L. 2009. Operationalisierung—Standardisierung—
Normalisierung. Die Produktion und Visualisierung von
Daten in der kognitiven Neurowissenschaft. Erkenntnis
und Kritik Zeitgenössische Positionen, ed. D. Dumbadze,
167–192. Bielfeld: Transcript.
Huyghens, C. 1899. Oeuvres Complètes Publiées par la Société
Hollandaise des Sciences, T. 8, Correspondance
1676–1684, Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, No. 2117,
pp. 58–61.
Joblot, L. 1718. Descriptions et usages de plusieurs nouveaux
microscopes, tant simples que composez. Paris: Jacques
Collombat.
Kaestner, A. 1969. Wirbellose. Lehrbuch der Speziellen Zoologie, Vol. 1, 774. Stuttgart: Gustav Fischer.
Kant, I. 1783. Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik. Riga: Hartknoch
123
160
Kerckring, T. 1729. Opera omnia anatomica; continentia spicilegium anatomicum ostogeniam foetuum […]. Leiden:
Theodor Haak und Samuel Luchthaus.
Kowalewski, A. 1986. Die Haupteigenschaften der Philosophie
des Als Ob. In Die Philosophie des Als Ob und das Leben.
Festschrift zu Hans Vaihingers 80. Geburtstag, ed.
A. Seidel, 227–235. Neudruck der Ausgabe Berlin 1932,
Aalen: Scientia.
Krämer, S. 2009. Bild, Schrift, Zahl. München: Fink.
van Leeuwenhoek, A. 1678. Observationes […] de Natis e
semine genitali Animalculis. Philosophical Transactions
of the Royal Society of London 142: 1040–1046 (Tab.
1013).
van Leeuwenhoek, A. 1719. Epistola 116 [1699]. Data Ad
Regiam Societatem Londinensem. In Epistolae ad Societatem Regiam Anglicam et alios illustres viros Seu
Continuatio mirandorum Arcanorum Naturae detectorum
[…], ed. A. v. Leeuwenhoek, 82–94. Leiden: Langerak.
Lynch, M. 2006. The production of scientific images: Vision
and re-vision in the history, philosophy, and sociology of
science. In Visual cultures of science: Rethinking representational practices in knowledge building and science
communication, ed. L. Pauwels, 26–40. Lebanon, NH:
Dartmouth College Press.
Murphy, K., Travers, P., and M. Walport. 2009. Janeway
Immunology, 7th ed. Heidelberg: Spectrum, Akademischer Verlag.
Prévost, J. L., and J. A. Dumas. 1821–1822. Sur les Animalcules spermatiques de divers Animaux. Me´moires de la
Socie´te´ de Physique et d0 Histoire Naturelle de Gene`ve 1 1:
180–207.
123
I. Müller, H. Fangerau
Redi, F. 1684. Osservazioni intorno agli animali viventi che si
trovano negli animali viventi. Florenz: Piero Matini, Tab.
23, Fig. 1a, b.
Schatiloff, P. 1908. Die Ehrlichsche Seitenkettentheorie.
Erläutert und bildlich dargestellt. Mit sechs Tafeln. Jena:
Verlag Gustav Fischer.
Schinzel, B. (2006). Wie Erkennbarkeit und visuelle Evidenz
für medizintechnische Bildgebung naturwissenschaftliche
Objektivität unterminieren. Bild und Einbildungskraft.
B. Hüppauf and C. Wulf. München, pp 354–370.
Schurig, M. 1720. Spermatologia Historico-Medica. Seminis
humani consideratio physico-medico-legalis […]. Johann
Beck: Frankfurt a. M.
Silverstein, A.M. 1989. A history of immunology. San Diego:
Academic Press.
Silverstein, A.M. 2002. Paul Ehrlich0 s receptor immunology,
the magnificent obsession. San Diego: Academic Press.
Vaihinger, H. 1911. Die Philosophie des Als Ob. System der
theoretischen, praktischen und religiösen Fiktionen der
Menschheit auf Grund eines idealistischen Positivismus.
Mit einem Anhang über Kant und Nietzsche. Berlin:
Reuther & Reichard
Valentin, G. 1837. Über die Spermatozoen der Bären. Nova
Acta Physico-Medica Academiae Caesareae LeopoldinoCarolinae Naturae Curiosorum 21: 239–244.
Vallisneri, A. 1721. Istoria della generazione dell0 uomo e degli
animali, se sia da0 vermicelli spermatici, o dalle uova.
Venedig: G. G. Hertz.