DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION
OF MIND
ABSTRACT. Dominance hierarchies are ubiquitous in the societies of human and nonhuman animals. Evidence from comparative, developmental, and cognitive psychological
investigations is presented that show how social dominance hierarchies shaped the evolution of the human mind, and hence, human social institutions. It is argued that the pressures
that arise from living in hierarchical social groups laid a foundation of fundamental concepts and cognitive strategies that are crucial to surviving in social dominance hierarchies.
These include recognizing and reasoning transitively about dominance relations, fast-track
learning of social norms (permissions, prohibitions, and obligations), detecting violations
of social norms (cheating), monitoring reciprocal obligations, and reading the intentions of
others.
1. INTRODUCTION
The problem of social coordination is one that any social species must
solve. Dominance hierarchies are the simplest and, by their very definition,
least equitable solution. In functional terms, dominance means that certain
individuals have priority of access to resources in competitive situations
(Clutton-Brock and Harvey 1976). In human socio-economic and socio
political systems, instances of dominance hierarchies include monopolies, monarchies, social stratification, caste and class systems, sexism, and
racism. In each case, social, political, and economic power falls disproportionately into the hands of some members of a society at the expense of
others.
Inequitable distribution of resources leads inevitably to social strife and
disharmony. Various attempts have been made throughout history to redistribute wealth and power (e.g., the Bolshevik Revolution, the Magna Carta,
legal codes, graduated tax laws, and even affirmative action) with varying
degrees of success. This striving for dominance and power plays itself out
not just in the global arena, but in everyday human relationships as well,
creating strife and conflict between parent and child, wife and husband,
colleagues, siblings, and friends.
It would be easy to dismiss dominance (and the conflict it produces)
in our social relationships and socio-political institutions as the inevitable
Synthese 122: 3–28, 2000.
© 2000 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
4
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
outcome of mixing individual differences with conflicts of interest. But
the ubiquity of this characteristic on local and global levels suggests otherwise. It suggests instead that dominance as a social reasoning strategy has
its fundamental roots in our cognitive architecture. Our social interactions
and institutions are shot through with dominance and the striving against
dominance because social dominance hierarchies constituted a crucible
in which cognitive and emotional functions were forged. These functions
include (but are not restricted to) a (sometimes regrettable) tendency to
conform and obey, and a (sometimes Machiavellian) capacity to forecast
the feelings, thoughts, plans, and actions of others.
In this paper, I will endeavor to demonstrate how social dominance
hierarchies shaped the evolution of the human mind, and, consequently,
human societies. I will show how survival pressures exerted by living with
conspecifics shaped a cognitive architecture imbued with the primitive deontic concepts of permission, prohibition, and obligation, the capacity for
violation (cheater) detection, and the capacity for hierarchically embedded
mental representations that enable outwitting and evasion of dominance
and social strictures through the use of deception and cooperative effort.
2. HOW NATURAL SELECTION WORKS
The cornerstone of evolutionary theory is natural selection, a theoretical
mechanism that works in the following way: Variation exists in the traits
of the members of most species, and some of this variation is heritable.
Because of their particular heritable attributes, some individuals will be
better able to cope with survival pressures than others within the same
environmental niche. These individuals will survive better or longer and
hence leave more living offspring than others in their species. The differential reproductive success of individuals based on their genetic differences
is called natural selection. The outcome of this process is that organisms
will evolve behavioral or other traits that promote individual reproductive success within a particular environmental niche, which is defined in
terms of the number of one’s offspring that live to reproduce themselves.
From an evolutionary standpoint, therefore, the fundamental problem that
an organism must solve is maximizing reproductive success.
In most species, there is a direct relationship between dominance rank
and reproductive success, with higher ranking members being less likely to
die of predation or starvation (Cheney and Seyfarth 1990, 33–4), and more
likely to leave living offspring (e.g., Bertram 1976; Bygott et al. 1979;
Dewsbury 1982; Clutton-Brock 1988; Ellis 1995; Fedigan 1983; Hausfater 1975; McCann 1981; Nishida 1983; Robinson 1982; Silk 1987; Tutin
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
5
1979; de Waal 1982; Watts and Stokes 1971). Among species in which
dominance rank is unstable, the level of reproductive success achieved by
any individual is directly related to the length of time during which the
individual is high ranking (Altmann et al. 1996). Maximizing reproductive
success, therefore, is intimately connected to maximizing one’s rank.
3. COGNITION IN NONHUMAN PRIMATES
Higher rank is not a simple matter of greater size. Dominance rank does
not correlate with size in many species (Smuts 1985; Walters and Seyfarth 1987). Instead, the evidence from primatology indicates that attaining
and maintaining a high-ranking position in a primate dominance hierarchy
depends on a collection of cognitive traits. These include:
•
•
•
•
•
Recognizing dominance relations
Fast track learning of social norms (i.e., permissions, prohibitions)
Detecting violations of social norms (cheaters)
Monitoring reciprocal obligations
Reading the intentions of others.
3.1. Dominance, Social Norms, and Violation Detection
To appreciate why these cognitive traits are crucial, one must first appreciate that, from a cognitive standpoint, a dominance hierarchy is a set of
implicit social norms. Social norms are prescriptive rules: They are rules
(implicit or explicit) that dictate which behaviors are permitted, obligated,
or prohibited. In dominance hierarchies, these social norms are reflected in
virtually every activity, including who is allowed to sit next to, play with,
share food with, groom, or mate with whom (Hall 1964; Aruguete 1994).
In order to avoid conflict in a social dominance hierarchy, individuals must
quickly learn what is permitted and what is forbidden them given their
rank.
Flouting these implicit social norms can have dire consequences. Indeed, Hall (1964) designated perceived violations of the “social code” as
the single most common cause of aggression in primate groups. Dominant
individuals typically take on the role of protecting this implicit “social
code”, aggressing against those who violate social norms and breaking
up disputes between lower-ranking individuals (see, e.g., Boehm 1992).
For example, high-ranking individuals often punish violations of social
norms as benign as grooming or sharing food with forbidden individuals
(de Waal 1992, 246–9). In order to preserve the social code, members of a
6
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
dominance hierarchy must be capable of detecting violations of the social
code. In other words, one must have the cognitive wherewithal to recognize
when someone is violating a social norm. This is particularly true if one
is to maintain a high-ranking position since violation detection is crucial
to ensuring that one maintains priority of access to resources (particularly
reproductive resources).
3.2. Dominance Status and Reciprocal Obligations
High-ranking positions are acquired and defended through the formation
of alliances, alliances that are based on reciprocal obligations (Chapais
1988 and 1992; Datta 1983a-b; Goodall 1986; Harcourt 1988; Harcourt
and Stewart 1987; Harcourt and de Waal 1992; Riss and Goodall 1977;
Seyfarth and Cheney 1984; Smuts 1985; Uehara et al. 1994; de Waal 1989;
1992). During contests of rank, individuals typically call for help, and nonkin allies are most likely to supply that help if the individual in question
has groomed them, shared food with them, or assisted them in agonistic
encounters in the past (Chapais 1992; Cheney and Seyfarth 1990, 67–
9; Prud’Homme and Chapais 1993; Seyfarth 1976; Seyfarth and Cheney
1984). These are reciprocal relationships in that the rate of intervention
by individual A on behalf of B is proportional to the rate of intervention of B on behalf of A (de Waal 1989; 1992). Furthermore, there is a
preference for forming alliances with high-ranking individuals, and highranking individuals (given the greater potential benefits that derive from
their interventions) need not reciprocate as often as subordinates in order
to maintain an alliance (Chapais 1992; Cheney 1983; Prud’Homme and
Chapais 1993).
3.3. Dominance Striving and the Problem of Other Minds
So far, we’ve seen that living within a social dominance hierarchy requires
recognizing what is permitted and forbidden given one’s rank, staying out
of trouble by conforming to social norms, forming strategic alliances based
on reciprocal obligations in order to improve and maintain one’s rank, and
maintaining social harmony and priority of access to resources by detecting and reacting to violations of social norms. These cognitive functions
produce dynamic societies in which there is a good deal of jockeying for
position, fission and fusion of coalitions and alliances, competition and
cooperative effort for mutual benefit. But among primates, at any rate, the
complexity of social life doesn’t end there because low-ranking individuals
use deception to improve their access to resources (Byrne 1995; Mitchell
1986; Whiten and Byrne 1988). For example, they conceal objects or behaviors from others by hiding them from view, acting quietly so as not
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
7
to attract attention, avoiding looking at a desirable object themselves, or
distracting attention away from the desired object or forbidden behaviors.
For example:
The unit was resting. An adult female (Hamadryas baboon) spent twenty minutes in gradually shifting in a seating position over a distance of about 2 metres to a place behind a rock
about 50 cm high where she began to groom a subadult follower of the unit – an interaction
not tolerated by the adult male. As I was observing from a cliff slightly above the unit, I
could judge that the adult male leader could, from his resting position, see the tail, back
and crown of the female’s head, but not her front, arms and face; the subadult male sat
in a bent position while being groomed and was also invisible to the leader. (Observed by
Kummer, reported by Whiten and Byrne 1988)
Often a low-ranking male (chimpanzee) will sit with his upper arm resting on his knee
and his hand loosely hanging down so that a female in front of him can see his erect
penis, but apes on the side cannot see it. This inconspicuous form of concealment occurs
together with quick glances at dominant males. Needless to say, the subordinate always
uses the hand on the body side which is tuned towards the dominants. (Observed by de
Waal, reported by Whiten and Byrne 1988.)
One day, some time after the group (of chimpanzees) had been fed, Figan suddenly spotted
a banana that had been overlooked – but Goliath was resting directly underneath it. After
no more than a quick glance from the fruit to Goliath, Figan moved away and sat on the
other side of the tent so that he could no longer see the fruit. Fifteen minutes later, when
Goliath got up and left, Figan, without a moment’s hesitation, went over and collected the
banana. (Observed by Goodall, reported by Whiten and Byrne 1988.)
S (gorilla) looks up into Hypericum tree and spies a nearly obscured clump of Lanranthus
vine. Without looking at those behind her, she sits down by the side of the trail and begins
to intently self-groom until the others have passed her and all are out of sight some 15 foot
[sic] ahead. Only then did S stop ‘selfgrooming’ to rapidly climb into the tree, break off
the vine clump and descend with it to the trail to hastily feed on it before running to catch
up with the group. (Observed by Fossey, reported by White and Byrne 1988).
As is apparent, most of these deceptions allow lower-ranking individuals
to flout social norms without getting caught. This can have enormous beneficial consequences for the deceiver. Through deception, subordinates
garner a larger share of resources through deception, and form alliances
with forbidden individuals through surreptitious food sharing or grooming,
alliances that can be called upon during contests of rank. More importantly,
deception can be used to improve one’s access to reproductive opportunities, and hence, reproductive success. Gagneux et al. (1997) report that over
50% of the offspring born to female chimpanzees in their study group were
fathered by males from other troops. The females in question had surreptitiously disappeared around the times of their estrus and reappeared a few
days later. During these times, they had apparently engaged in clandestine
matings. Not surprisingly, then, dominants are ever vigilant to potential
deceptions, and develop strategies for counteracting them:
8
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
One chimp was alone in the feeding area and was going to be fed bananas. A metal box
was opened from a distance. Just at the moment when the box was opened, another chimp
approached at the border of the clearing. The first chimp quickly closed the metal box
and walked away several metres, sat down and looked around as if nothing happened. The
second chimp left the feeding area again, but as soon as he was out of sight, he hid behind a
tree and peered at the individual in the feeding area. As soon as that individual approached
and opened the metal box again, the hiding individual approached, replaced the other, and
ate the bananas. (Observed by Plooij, reported by Whiten and Byrne 1988.)
Belle, accordingly stopped uncovering the food if Rock was close. She sat on it until Rock
left. Rock, however, soon learned this, and when she sat in one place for more than a
few seconds, he came over, shoved her aside, searched her sitting place, and got the food.
Belle next stopped going all the way (to the food). Rock, however, countered by steadily
expanding the area of his search through the grass near where Belle had sat. Eventually,
Belle sat farther and farther away, waiting until Rock looked in the opposite direction
before she moved toward the food at all, and Rock in turn seemed to look away until Belle
started to move somewhere. On some occasions Rock started to wander off, only to wheel
around suddenly precisely as Belle was about to uncover some food . . . on a few trials, she
actually started off a trial by leading the group in the opposite direction from the food, and
then, while Rock was engaged in his search, she doubled back rapidly and got some food.
(Menzel 1974)
That deception occurs in the daily interactions of primate societies is
uncontroversial. Its interpretation, however, is not. The controversy concerns whether or not deceptions like these require mental representation
on the part of the participants, and if so, the minimum complexity of the
mental representation required to execute them. More to the point, the
crucial question is: To what extent are other species capable of reflecting
on their own internal states and the internal states of others?
Nature is replete with instances of deception, and most require no mental representation at all (e.g., the hawk moth flicks open its hind wings in
response to looming objects displaying spots on its hind wings that look
like the eyes of a large hawk). Some deception, however, is more difficult
to explain without appealing to a capacity for mental representation. Consider, for example, the cases of misdirected attention, which are difficult to
explain unless the deceiver were capable of higher-order intentional states
such as
I want (you to believe (that I stopped to groom myself))
or
I want (you to believe (that I know (the food is over there))
Krebs and Dawkins (1984) referred to the capacity to forecast the behavior of others (as in the case of Belle and Rock) as mind reading (although
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
9
they meant this in strictly behavioral terms and made no commitment to
mental representation). The competitive advantage conferred by such a capacity is obviously enormous – unless those you compete with also possess
the same capacity. Achieving dominance in such a society is extremely
difficult, and it is probably because of this “mindreading” capability that
hierarchies in some species can be notoriously unstable.
But the capacity to reflect on your own mental states and to appreciate (however minimally) the internal states of others confers other, less
malevolent advantages as well. The ability to anticipate others’ actions
also enables coordinated cooperative effort, such as seen in the cooperative hunting of lionesses and chimpanzees. In laboratory studies, common
chimpanzees have been shown capable of taking either role in a cooperative task when they’ve only been explicitly taught one of the roles,
suggesting that they appreciate what a partner needs to know in order for
both to succeed in a joint task (Povinelli 1994). They also deliberately
teach their offspring skills, such as nut cracking and (in the case of signing
chimps) sign language, exaggerating their movements to allow their offspring ample time to observe, and ensuring that their offspring are in fact
watching their actions while they are being demonstrated (Boesch 1991;
also see Caro and Hauser 1992). There is also evidence of compassion,
distress, and caring toward others, suggesting a capacity to appreciate the
feelings of others (see de Waal 1996 for numerous examples).
To summarize, primate social interactions are far more complex than
simple contests of strength. Instead, these interactions depend on a cluster
of important and primitive cognitive functions. The most primitive and
fundamental of these are (a) recognizing individuals and (b) making rank
and kinship discriminations through transitive inference. Without these
functions, one cannot monitor one’s history with other individuals, form
alliances, avoid conflict, and so on. Just as important, however, are (c)
recognizing/learning what is permitted and what is forbidden given one’s
rank, (d) forming reciprocal obligations based on resource sharing, (e)
monitoring reciprocity, (f) detecting violations of social norms (i.e., cheating), and (g) reading the intentions of others. Without a cognitive function
that allows one to quickly learn what is forbidden and what is permitted
given one’s rank, subordinates risk incurring the wrath of their higherranking conspecifics, a situation that can (and does) result in ostracism and
even death. Without a cognitive function that allows one to grasp the structure of an obligation, fruitful alliances cannot be formed and maintained
that allow one to move up in rank. Without a violation detection function,
highranking individuals cannot monopolize resources, cannot maintain
fruitful alliances, and cannot preserve the peace. In this basic mix, there is
10
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
also a capacity, however rudimentary, for reading the intentions of others
through an appreciation of their internal mental and emotional states. Unlike the basic cognitive functions required for dominance and social norm
reasoning, the interpretation of the data on this capacity is extremely controversial. Without the capacity to read the intentions of others, however,
the cooperative effort and higher-order deception seen among some social
mammals (particularly the great apes) would be virtually impossible.
These, I argue, constitute basic and early emerging cognitive functions
in social mammals, and they are shot through with the dynamics of dominance. What one is permitted or forbidden to do depends on one’s rank.
The rate at which one must reciprocate (and, hence, what counts as reciprocity) depends on one’s rank. And whether or not one must be vigilant
in detecting social norm violations depends on one’s rank.
Why should dominance play such a large role? Essentially, because
it was there first. Dominance is ubiquitous among social species, and in
many, size does matter. But if wit can out-maneuver brawn, then there is
an evolutionary pressure to be brainy. Dominance hierarchies constituted
the social context for the evolution of these basic cognitive functions, functions that are crucial for out-competing brawn in contests of rank, and for
maintaining a stable social environment.
4. SOCIAL COGNITION IN HUMAN PRIMATES
Pope Edwards (1982, 276) described the social order in preliterate human
societies as “cooperation and reciprocal obligations within a hierarchical
structure of authority relationships”. It is as good a description of most
human societies and social institutions as any. Human cognition, then, was
(and still is) subject to the same types of selective pressures as other social
mammals during evolution, bigger brains notwithstanding. And so it is not
surprising to find evidence of a human biological preparedness to develop
cognitive functions for classes of problems that are critical to survival in a
social dominance hierarchy. As we saw earlier, these functions include
•
•
•
•
•
Recognizing dominance relations
Fast track learning of social norms (permissions and prohibitions)
Detecting violations of social norms (cheaters)
Monitoring reciprocal obligations (social exchange reasoning)
Reading the intentions of others (theory of mind reasoning).
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
11
4.1. Dominance Effects in Human Social, Emotional, and Cognitive
Functions
Dominance hierarchies are apparent in the play groups of preschool
children (Hold-Cavell and Borsutsky 1986; Keating and Heltman 1994;
LaFreniere and Charlesworth 1980; Rubin and Caplan 1992; Smith 1988),
even among children as young as two years of age (Frankel and Arbel
1980). In fact, social dominance is the earliest stable dimension of peer
group social organization (Strayer and Trudel 1984). Children as young as
four years of age can reliably report the hierarchical structure of dominance
relations in their play groups, a task that depends at least implicitly on the
use of transitive inference; in contrast, content-free transitive reasoning
does not reliably emerge until the 6th or 7th year of life, suggesting a
distinction between domain-specific and general reasoning versions of this
type of reasoning competence that emerge at different developmental rates
(Smith 1988).
Consideration of relative rank also modifies physiological stress indices., such as blood pressure, heart-rate, and cortisol levels. Retaliating
against an aggressor causes these indices to return to normal – but
only when retaliating against a lower-status target; if a victim retaliates against a higher-status aggressor, his or her stress indices remain at
their frustration-induced elevated levels. (Hokanson 1961; Hokanson and
Shetler 1961).
Countless studies in social psychology have also revealed a distressing
human tendency to conform, comply, and submit to authority (dominant
individuals) – even malevolent authority. Perhaps the most famous examples of this are the Milgram experiments (Milgram 1974). Sixtyfive
percent of the subjects participating in these studies obeyed a malevolent
authority’s orders to deliver a potentially fatal electric shock to an innocent
victim. (In fact, no shocks were delivered and the “victim” was a confederate of the experimenter, but the subjects were not made aware of these
facts until after they agreed or refused to obey the order.)
Dominance appears to be written deeply into our physiological, social,
and cognitive functions. It emerges early as a defining trait of individuals
(personality) and hence produces a propensity for human social groups to
organize themselves hierarchically, and for the majority of individuals to
displace responsibility for their actions by obeying authority. So large a
part does it play in our social lives that it also shapes and modifies our
cognitive strategies and physiological responses.
12
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
4.2. Social Norm Reasoning
Philosophical treatments of reasoning have long appreciated the need to
distinguish between practical reasoning and theoretical reasoning, a need
that has recently also emerged in psychological models of reasoning (e.g.,
Manktelow and Over 1991; 1995; Cummins 1996b–c; 1997; 1998a, b;
1999, in press; Oaksford and Chater 1992). The goal of practical reasoning
is determining a prudent course of action. Typically, this means determining what one is permitted, obligated, or forbidden to do. Deontic logics
have been proposed to aid in developing normative models of this type of
reasoning, logics that have as their primitive operators permission, obligation, and (in some cases) prohibition (Hilpinen 1971; 1981). These are the
core operators that are needed to do the job. Practical, or deontic, reasoning
is distinct from discursive or theoretical reasoning in which the reasoner is
required to determine the epistemic status (truth) of a description of a state
of affairs. Here, one is not concerned with choosing a prudent course of
action. Instead, one is concerned with what is entailed by given facts.
This distinction appears not just in normative models of reasoning, but
in everyday reasoning as well. For nearly three decades, psychologists
have noted that when reasoning about prescriptive rules (social norms), we
spontaneously look for possible violations of the rule, that is, we look to
see who might be breaking the rule (Cheng and Holyoak 1985; 1989; Cosmides 1989; Griggs and Cox, 1982; Cummins 1996a, b; Johnson-Laird,
et al. 1972; Manktelow and Over 1991; 1995). This extremely cogent
and crucial reasoning strategy seems to be triggered almost exclusively
by problems with deontic content, particularly permissions, obligations,
prohibitions, promises, and warnings. Violation detection is rarely found
in everyday theoretical reasoning.
The most striking examples of this effect have been reported using the
Wason Card Selection Task. As a simple example, imagine someone tells
you something odd about a mutual friend of yours, namely:
If John stays overnight at his cabin, then he always comes home
with a sack of garbage. (If < p >, then < q >)
As proof, your friend has kept tabs on John, writing down his activities
everyday for the past three months and storing the information in a computer file. The file contains information about where John went and what
he had with him when he returned. These include
• Information about what John brought home when he stayed overnight
at his cabin (p)
• Information about what John brought home when he stayed overnight
elsewhere (∼ p)
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
13
• Information about where John had gone when he returned with a sack
of garbage (q)
• Information about where John had gone when he returned without a
sack of garbage (∼ q).
Which occasions would you like to inspect in order to make sure your
friend is right? The typical choices on theoretical (or truth-testing) problems like this is p and q, that is, “stayed overnight at his cabin” and “came
home with a sack of garbage”.
Now imagine that John’s cabin is in a wildlife preserve, and it is
required that all overnight visitors take their garbage out with them in order protect the environment and discourage scavenging. Which occasions
would you like to inspect in order to make sure John obeyed the rule?
The typical answer on deontic problems like this is p and ∼ q (“stayed
overnight at his cabin” and “returned without a sack of garbage”).
When reasoning about the truth of a conditional statement, people
spontaneously seek to confirm that the antecedent (p) and the consequent
(q) did in fact occur together. When reasoning about obedience to prescriptive rules (social norms), people instead spontaneously look for
possible rule violations. This is true whether the final query biases search in
favor of verification (as in the example above) or violation detection (e.g.,
“. . . in order to find out whether your friend was wrong” and “. . . in order
to make sure John isn’t breaking the rule”). But consider this: In the truthtesting case, had you inspected the occasions in which John came home
without a bag of garbage and discovered that he’d been to his cabin, this
would have provided incontrovertible proof that the statement was false.
Yet it does not occur to us to look for potential violations of the statement
in the truth-testing case. The need only seems apparent in the deontic case.
This is what I refer to as the deontic effect (Cummins, 1994b, c; 1998a, b;
1999 in press).
The deontic effect does not appear just in the reasoning of adults. It
has been observed in children as young as three years of age, making it
one of the earliest emerging reasoning functions (Cummins 1996a). Children spontaneously adopt a violation detection strategy when attempting to
determine whether or not a social rule is being followed, but not when attempting to determine whether a conditional utterance is true or false. The
magnitude of this effect is equivalent to the magnitude found in the adult
literature. Furthermore, children also find it easier to recognize instances
of cheating than instances that prove a rule false (Harris and Nuñez 1996).
Although the deontic effect has been observed in numerous experiments over the course of thirty years (see Cummins (1996b) for a review),
its interpretation is not without controversy. Some have argued that the de-
14
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
ontic effect simply shows that embedding reasoning problems in contents
with which people are reasonably familiar improves performance (e.g.,
Griggs and Cox 1982; Johnson-Laird et al. 1972). Others have argued that
we induce reasoning schemas for frequently occurring, highly important
classes of situations (such as permissions), and the deontic effect reflects
evocation of these class-specific schemas (Cheng and Holyoak 1985; 1989;
Holyoak and Cheng 1995). Still others have argued that the deontic effect
reflects the evocation of innate, genetic algorithms for cheater detection
that evolved in response to pressure to reason about social exchange, which
is defined as cooperative effort for mutual benefit (Cosmides 1989; Cosmides and Tooby 1992; 1994; Gigerenzer and Hug 1992). The deontic
effect also has been explained as the inevitable outcome of a search for
counterexamples to reasoner-constructed mental models, a process that
is sensitive to subjective utility (Manktelow and Over 1991; 1995). And,
finally, some researchers have argued that the shift in selection patterns
on the truth-testing and deontic versions of the Wason task indicates that
people view these tasks in terms of optimal data selection, and shift their
strategies from maximizing expected information gain on the truth-testing
version to maximizing expected utility on the deontic version (Oaksford
and Chater 1992).
In all of this controversy, two things remain uncontroversial. The first
is that when reasoning about prescriptive social rules, people adopt a violation detection strategy. The second is that what counts as an efficacious
and rational strategy when reasoning about social rules is perfectly obvious: It’s clear even to three-year-olds. In contrast, what one ought to do
when testing a statement’s truth is the subject of controversy even among
scientists and philosophers of science (e.g., Duhem 1954; Earman 1992;
Horwich 1982; Lakatos 1970; Putnam 1974). One might ask, ‘Why?’ Why
is the deontic version of the task so much clearer and easier for human
primates to reason about while the truth-testing version is not? Why, in
fact, do people perform well on the deontic version of the task regardless
of general intellectual ability or level of education while performance on
the truth-testing version correlates positively with intelligence (Stanovich
and West in press)?
Even more crucial is the observation that consideration of relative social
rank strongly influences the likelihood that a violation detection strategy
will be evoked. Reasoners are far more likely to look for cheaters when
checking on individuals who are lower ranking than themselves (65%) than
when checking on individuals of equally high (20%), equally low (18%)
or higher rank (20%) than themselves (Cummins 1999). Social rank had
no effect on the likelihood of adopting a violation detection strategy in a
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
15
lie detection condition. (The percentage “p and not-q” responses ranged
from 15% to 18% across the rank manipulations in the lie detection task).
Similarly, Mealey and her colleagues found that subjects were far better at
remembering low-status cheaters than high-status cheaters or non-cheaters
of any rank (Mealey et al. 1996).
These seemingly disparate and confusing results can be readily understood from the perspective offered here: Violation detection is a basic
cognitive function that facilitates social regulation. It is a crucial function
for ensuring that implicit (or explicit) social norms are honored, and, more
particularly, that higher-ranking individuals can protect the status quo by
regulating the behavior of those over whom they have power or authority.
4.3. Monitoring Reciprocity
Reciprocity appears to be a primitive component of human cognitive architecture, at least in the social realm. Infants engage in turn-taking games
with caretakers within the first year of life (Vandell and Wilson 1987).
Preschoolers typically choose to help playmates who have helped them in
the past, and are more likely to share resources with those who have shared
with them in the past (Smith 1988).
Research on decision-making among adults also shows that reneging
on a promise to cooperate is reacted to more strongly and more negatively than competitive loss alone (Rabbie 1992; Weg and Smith 1993).
For example, Weg and Smith (1993) gave subjects the opportunity to win
money in transactions based on the Prisoner’s Dilemma. The subject’s task
was to decide whether to betray his or her collaborators and win a fixed
amount of money, or to trust them and possibly win more or less than
the fixed amount. Subjects showed a greater willingness to trust, and a
greater unwillingness to forgive betrayals of that trust, than would have
been predicted by rational choice theory.
These results are better accounted for by assuming that people are predisposed to engage in reciprocal obligation transactions, or, as Cosmides
and Tooby call it social exchange (Cosmides 1989; Cosmides and Tooby
1992; 1994). According to Social Exchange Theory, cheater detection is
part of a domain-specific mental algorithm – a mental module – that
evolved in humans in the Pleistocene in response to pressure to reason
about social exchange. Social exchange is defined in terms of reciprocal
altruism, that is, cooperative effort for mutual benefit. Cheater detection
is a crucial element of this theory because modeling in evolutionary biology has repeatedly shown that reciprocal altruism cannot emerge as an
evolutionarily stable strategy unless the participants are capable of detecting and excluding cheaters (e.g., Axelrod and Hamilton 1981). Curiously
16
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
cheating is defined in Social Exchange Theory not as failure to reciprocate
but instead as taking a benefit without paying a cost. Further, most of the
research done testing the theory has focused on detecting violations of
social norms (such as wearing a tattoo or eating a certain type of food
when one is not entitled to according to social conventions), which we
already know people are very good at. Other results have shown that cost
manipulations have little effect on cheater detection (Cheng and Holyoak
1989) but benefit manipulations do (Cosmides and Tooby 1992), and that
which violations are detected depends on whose perspective the reasoner
adopts during the reasoning process. For example, consider the promise
“If you mow my lawn, I’ll give you $5”. From the promisor’s perspective,
it is important to ensure that the lawn was mowed before the $5 was paid.
In the standard Wason task, this corresponds to selecting not-p and q, that
is, “didn’t mow the lawn” and “paid $5’. From the promisee’s perspective,
it is important to ensure that the $5 was paid once the lawn was mowed.
This corresponds to selecting p and not-q, that is, “mowed the lawn”, and
“didn’t pay $5”. Several studies have now reported that a switch in perspective on reciprocal obligation tasks results in just this type of switch in
selection patterns, suggesting that people are indeed very good at defecting
violations of reciprocal obligations (Gigerenzer and Hug 1992; Manktelow
and Over 1991; 1995; Politzer and Nguyan-Xuan 1991).
Cross-cultural work on reasoning shows similar results. An example
cited by Scribner (1975, 155) on syllogistic reasoning among the Kpelle
of West Africa amply illustrates the type of responses observed when using
categorical syllogisms to test theoretical reasoning:
(E:)
All Kpelle men are rice farmers. Mr Smith (this is a Western
name) is not a rice farmer. Is he a Kpelle man?
(S:)
I don’t know the man in person. I have not laid eyes on the man
himself.
(E:)
Just think about the statement.
(S:)
If I know him in person, I can answer that question, but since I
do not know him in person I cannot answer that question.
(E:)
Try and answer from your Kpelle sense.
(S:)
If you know a person, if a question comes up about him, you are
able to answer. But if you do not know a person, if a question
comes up about him, it’s hard for you to answer it.
As this excerpt shows, the reasoner does not seem to grasp the fact that
the dilemma can be resolved via reasoning. Instead, he is concerned with
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
17
retrieving and verifying facts, a strategy that does not fare well in this type
of task.
A very different picture emerges, however, when members of preliterate
cultures are asked to reason about moral dilemmas. One oft-cited study by
Harkness et al. (1981) on rural Kenyans (Kipsigis community) illustrates
the typical result observed in these studies. The dilemma in this excerpt
concerned whether a boy should obey his father and give him some money
he had earned himself when the father had promised the boy he could keep
it.
A child has to give you what you ask for just in the same way as when he asks for anything
you give it to him. Why then should he be selfish with what he has? A parent loves his child
and maybe hthe soni refused without knowing the need of helping his father. By showing
respect to one another, friendship between us is assured and as a result this will increase
the prosperity of our family.
As is apparent, the reasoner has little difficulty understanding what this
reasoning problem is all about. Furthermore, this protocol is full of references to reciprocity, and particularly reciprocal obligations. Interestingly,
however, just as in primate societies, what counts as reciprocal depends
on social status. In this study, when determining what was right or fair, all
subjects settled dilemmas in favor of the person with higher rank or status,
regardless of the merits of the case.
In short, there is ample evidence that reciprocity emerges early in
human development and is a universal characteristic of spontaneous,
untutored reasoning.
4.4. Human Reasoning and the Problem of Other Minds
As we saw in the section on nonhuman primates, detecting violations of
social norms and reading the intentions of others differ significantly in
terms of the computational commitments they require. Learning the social
norms of one’s group and detecting violations of them does not require
appreciating the internal states of others. Social norms and violation detection traffic in the realm of readily observable overt behavior. Reading the
intentions of others, however, can and often does require crossing the line
into the realm of the unobserved and private internal states of others. As
we saw, it can in fact require constructing hierarchically embedded mental
representations of the mental states of others. “Mind reading”, therefore,
requires greater representational and computational complexity than does
inducing social norms and detecting norm violations.
It should come as no surprise, then, that “mind reading” – a skill at
which humans excel compared to other species – emerges later during
development than does cheater detection – a skill we seem to have in
18
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
common with other social animals. In the developmental and comparative literatures, “mind reading” is called theory of mind reasoning, and it
comprises a number of separate subskills which develop at different ages.
For example, infants as young as 10 weeks can distinguish among various
facial expressions (Haviland and Lelwica 1987), and even two year olds
can succeed at tasks that require them to grasp another’s goals, desires, or
preferences (e.g., Bartsch and Wellman 1989; Flavell et al. 1990; Melztoff
1995).
Reasoning about the content and truth values of others’ belief states,
however, proves more troubling to young children. For example, children
younger than about age 4 fail to take into account a speaker’s knowledge
when evaluating utterances, and simply label inaccurate statements as lies.
For example, if puppet A watches an event, then lies about it to puppet
B, who then innocently passes the inaccurate information on to puppet
C, children in this age group will call both A and B liars (Strichartz and
Burton 1990; Wimmer et al. 1984). It is not until about the 7th or 8th
year of life that consideration of what a speaker believed or knew reliably
appears in their judgments. (See Haugaard and Reppucci 1992; Bussey
1992 for reviews of this literature.)
Prior to about age 4, children also perform inconsistently on tasks that
require attributing false beliefs to others. In the standard false belief task,
children watch while a puppet hides a toy in location A and then leaves. A
second puppet then appears, finds the toy, and hides it in location B. The
child is then asked where the first puppet left the toy, where the toy is now,
and where the first puppet thinks the toy is. Prior to about age 4, children
answer the first two questions correctly, yet believe the first puppet thinks
the toy is in the current location (location B). Their behavior is typically
explained as a failure or inability to attribute false beliefs to others (see
Gopnik 1993; Leslie 1994; Perner 1991 for reviews of this literature.)
Although these tasks are seemingly very different, they share one very
important feature: They require appreciating the knowledge/belief states
of others. In the deception task, puppet A is guilty of lying because it
knew one thing but reported something inconsistent with that knowledge.
In contrast, puppet B wasn’t guilty of lying because it reported accurately
what it knew, but what it knew was contrary to fact. In the false belief task,
the first puppet can’t know that the toy was moved because it didn’t see
the toy get moved, so it believes something contrary to reality. In order
to perform these tasks, one must maintain several conflicting pieces of
knowledge – what is true, what puppet A believes to be true, and what
puppet B believes to be true. But in both tasks, young children seem to
focus almost exclusively on the first of these – what is currently true. They
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
19
find it difficult to reason well if they must take into account what others
saw, knew, or believe, particularly if that knowledge or belief is contrary
to fact.
Two broad classes of explanations have been offered to explain these
results. The first class includes discontinuity theories: They attribute the
change in performance in the third year of life to a radical change in the
nature of the child’s understanding of mental states, that is, a change in
competence, from a non-representational to a representational “theory of
mind” (Gopnik 1993; Perner 1991; Wellman 1990). Prior to this shift,
the child lacks a concept of false belief. The second class of explanations
include continuity theories: These theories frame false belief reasoning in
terms of conceptual competence. They propose that the concept of false
belief is part of an early emerging, domain-specific representational system, that becomes functional through the period from approximately 18 to
36 months. The shift that occurs from ages 3 to 4 is one of a change in
performance, not competence (Leslie 1994).
There are three additional facts about theory of mind reasoning that
need to be brought into this discussion. The first is that it is not until about
ages 5 to 7 that children can reliably perform tasks that require understanding statements that express second-order intentionality such as “John wants
his mother to think that . . . ” (Perner and Wimmer 1985). The second is
that children begin to pass the false belief task at the same time they begin
to pass counterfactual reasoning talks (Riggs et al. 1998). These results
suggest that it is not until children can construct and manipulate hierarchically embedded mental representations that they can reliably succeed in
cognitive tasks that depend on them. And as we saw earlier, creatures that
are capable of constructing such representations are also highly capable
of thwarting social norms and dominance through dint of guile. Which
brings us to the second fact: Theory of mind reasoning emerges earlier
in later borns than first borns (Jenkins and Astington 1996; Lewis et al.
1996; Perrier et al. 1994; Ruffman et al. 1998), which is readily predicted
by the theory of dominance presented here. One of the primary purposes of
deception is outwitting those who have power to constrain or inhibit your
behavior.
The capacity to represent others’ internal states, however, has other,
less Machiavellian, uses. It also allows for greater compassion, and social
codes based on something other than social norms. In short, it sets the stage
for the development (or evolution) of a code of morality, particularly one
based on harm to others. The capacity to appreciate others’ internal states
allows one to ground social codes in concepts such as suffering. Without
20
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
it, social codes must be grounded in rules that forbid, permit, or obligate
certain kinds of behavior.
This distinction between a social code grounded in prescriptive rules
and one grounded in appreciation of others’ internal states emerges early
in human development, and it is universally (cross-culturally) recognized.
Children as young as 2 12 years of age distinguish between social conventions and moral prescriptions (Hollos et al. 1986; Nucci et al. 1983).
Children treat moral rules as unconditional obligations toward others and
social conventions as context-specific rules based on authority and consensus. They judge moral transgressions in terms of harm done to others
and fairness (e.g., pain or injury incurred), and judge social rule violations in terms of social coordination factors (e.g., social sanctions against
breaking the rules). In one study, over 80% of preschoolers stated that conventional transgressions would be right if there were no rule pertaining to
the act (e.g., adopting a different form of dress, greeting, use of toys, etc),
but that moral transgressions would not be right even if there were no rule
pertaining to the behavior (e.g., hitting another child, stealing property).
This distinction appears to be universal, having been observed in a variety
of cultures both developmentally and in adult legal/social codes (Snarey
1985).
Moral dilemmas often arise when socially acceptable behavior is seen
by large enough segments of a society to violate basic moral rules. This
division lies at the foundation of classic as well as contemporary disputes
over slavery and animal rights, as these excerpts show:
In our opinion, if monkeys could read and otherwise use language properly, we could
not ethically use them as laboratory animals. A major justification for experimenting on
(or eating, or otherwise using) animals, at least as we see it, rests on a basic conception of
ethics: Rights only exist because there are complementary duties (e.g., see Frankena 1963).
For example, if you have a right to live, the rest of us have a duty not to kill you. Thus,
ethics is embedded in a community of responsible citizens who can perform the necessary
duties that allow rights to be conferred. If a monkey, or anything else, could understand
necessary duties, it would become a member of the community to which the rights apply.
However, monkeys cannot participate in such social contracts. (Kosslyn and Koenig 1995,
501)
Here, the justification for animal experimentation (and consequent suffering) rests on the deontic concepts of rights and duties, that is, on
permissions and obligations that are conferred upon members of a group.
This contrasts sharply with the following argument that appeals instead to
an appreciation of the internal states of others, particularly to their capacity
for suffering::
But is there any reason why we should be suffered to torment them? Not any that I can
see. Are there reasons why we should be suffered not to torment them? Yes, several. The
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
21
day has been, I grieve to say in many places it is not yet past, in which the greater part
of the species, under the denomination of slaves, have been treated by the law exactly
upon the same footing as, in England, for example, the inferior races of animals are still.
The day may come, when the rest of the animal creation may acquire those rights which
never could have been withholden from them but by the hand of tyranny. The French have
already discovered that the blackness of the skin is no reason why a human being should
be abandoned without redress to the caprice of a tormentor. It may come one day to be
recognized, that the number of the legs, the villosity of the skin, or the termination of the
os sacrum, are reasons equally insufficient for abandoning a sensitive being to the same
fate. What else is it that should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of reason, or,
perhaps, the faculty of discourse? . . . .the question is not, Can they reason, nor Can they
talk?, but can they suffer? (Bentham 1789; Chap.: 17, section 1, part 4, fn)
While the former argument appealed to rights, obligations, and social
norms, this argument appeals to victims’ internal states, particularly their
capacity for suffering. The developmental, comparative, and cognitive
research presented here suggests that these two types of reasoning are
fundamentally different because they rely on different concepts, and, perhaps, engage different reasoning strategies. The former depends on the
deontic concepts of permissions, prohibitions, and obligations and relates
to distinctly observable behavior. The second depends on internally representing, considering and perhaps even experiencing to some degree, the
mental and emotional states of others. Working out how to bridge these
two domains has been the goal of philosophers and legal scholars for millennia, and the difficulty of this task is apparent in the many disparate
schools of thought that have emerged as a result (e.g., deontology and
consequentialism). Perhaps these issues are so thorny not only because
of the social ramifications they carry but because they require the blending
of two fundamentally different types of cognition.
In summary, five cognitive functions that are crucial to survival in social dominance hierarchies are apparent in human reasoning performance.
These include recognizing dominance relations, cogent reasoning about
permissions, obligations, and prohibitions (social norms), violation detection, reciprocity, and “mind-reading”. All but the last of these emerge
early in development and color reasoning performance throughout the
lifespan. “Mind-reading” emerges later in development, and seems to depend on a complexity of mental representation that distinguishes humans
from many other species. The nature of this complexity seems to be a
capacity for forming deeply-embedded representations (of the type readily
seen in human communicative signals, i.e., language), and has as its consequence enabling an organism to distinguish between true representations
and counterfactuals that can serve as goals, suppositions, or representations
of the internal states of others.
22
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
5. WHY DOMINANCE IS NOT AN INEVITABLE SOCIAL OUTCOME
The theory of dominance presented here is NOT a theory of innate modules. Instead, it is a theory about cognitive functions jointly shaped by
innate predispositions and environmental inputs. When it comes to nativist theses about cognition, there is a temptation to ask which information
(rules, theories, etc.) is innate, and which is learned. An alternative explanation is that complex social animals do not inherit modules fully formed
but instead have a biological preparedness to develop them very quickly
for classes of problems that are critical to survival (Cummins and Cummins, in press). Biological preparedness as an explanans is more consistent
with contemporary neuroscience than are innate modules. The picture of
the brain that is emerging from decades of neuroscience research is one in
which precious little is fixed at birth. Instead, innate processing “biases”
are elicited or modified through interactions with the environment. Furthermore, biological preparedness comes in degrees, and is probably best
explained in terms of canalization (Ariew 1996; McKenzie and O’Farrell
1993; Waddington 1975). A trait is said to be more or less canalized as
its expression is more or less independent of environmental influence. A
combination of genetic and environmental factors cause development to
follow a particular pathway, and once begun, development is bound to
achieve a particular end-state.
This means that biology often puts strong constraints on what types
of knowledge or skills can or will be learned, but that the environment
plays a very large role in how and whether certain biological predispositions get expressed. I have argued here that humans (like most other
social mammals) have a propensity to form dominance hierarchies and
to use dominance-centered strategies for controlling social interactions.
I’ve also argued this is so because many of our basic cognitive functions
were forged in the crucible of dominance hierarchies and were crucial to
survival in these environments. Our evolutionary environment is reflected in our cognitive architecture, and that architecture in turn shapes the
nature of our social institutions. In their most benign form, hierarchies
reflect nothing more than leadership qualities among a few individuals.
In their more malevolent form, such hierarchies can constitute rigid and
profound socioeconomic stratification. From a socio-political perspective,
perhaps the most important contribution that cognitive psychologists can
make is to investigate which environmental contingencies trigger or hinder
the expression of these potentially destructive biological predispositions.
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
23
R EFERENCES
Altmann, J., S. C. Alberts, S. A. Haines, J. Dubach, P. Muruth, T. Coote, E. Geffen, D. J.
Cheesman, R. A. Mututua, S. N. Saiyalel, R. K. Wayne, R. C. Lacy, and M. W. Bruford:
1996, ‘Behavior Predicts Genetic Structure in a Wild Primate Group’, Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences 93, 5795–801.
Anew, A.: 1996, ‘Innateness and Canalization’, Philosophy of Science 63, S19–S27.
Aruguete, M.: 1994, ‘Cognition, Tradition, and the Explanation of Social Behavior in NonHuman Primates’, [Review of Social Processes and Mental Abilities in Non-Human
Primates]. American Journal of Primatology 33, 71–4.
Axelrod, R., and W. D. Hamilton: 1981, ‘The Evolution of Cooperation’, Science 211,
1390–6.
Bartsch, K. and H. M. Wellman: 1989, ‘Young Children’s Attribution of Action to Beliefs
and Desires’, Child Development 60, 946–64.
Bentham, J.: 1789, The Principles of Morals and Legislation, Prometheus Books, Buffalo,
N.Y.
Bertram, B. C. R.: 1976, ‘Kin Selection in Lions and Evolution’, in P. P. G. Bateson and R.
A. Hinde (eds), Growing Points in Ethology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
pp. 281–302.
Boehm, C.: 1992, ‘Segmentary “Warfare” and the Management of Conflict: Comparison of
East African Chimpanzees and Patrilineal-Patrilocal Humans’, in A. Harcourt and F. B.
M. de Waal (eds), Coalitions and Alliances in Humans and Other Animals, pp. 137–75,
Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Boesch, C.: 1991, ‘Teaching in Wild Chimpanzees’, Animal Behavior 41, 530–2.
Bygott, J. D., B. C. R. Bertram, and J. P. Hanby: 1979, ‘Male Lions in Large Coalitions
Gain Reproductive Advantage’, Nature 282, 839–41.
Byrne, R.: 1995, The Thinking Ape: Evolutionary Origins Of Intelligence, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Bussey, K.: 1992, ‘Children’s Lying and Truthfulness: Implications for Children’s Testimony’, in S. J. Ceci, M. De Simone Leichtman, and M. Putnick (eds), Cognitive and
Social Factors in Early Deception, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 89–110..
Caro, T. M. and M. D. Hauser: 1992, ‘Is There Teaching in Non-Human Animals?’,
Quarterly Review of Biology 67, 151–74.
Chapais, B.: 1988, ‘Rank Maintenance in Female Japanese Macaques: Experimental
Evidence For Social Dependency’, Behavior 104, 41–59.
Chapais, B.: 1992, ‘Role of Alliances in the Social Inheritance of Rank Among Female
Primates’, in A. Harcourt and F. B. M De Waal (eds), Cooperation in Contests in Animals
and Humans, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 29–60.
Cheney, D. L.: 1983, ‘Extra-Familial Alliances Among Vervet Monkeys’, in R. A. Hinde
(ed.), Primate Social Relationships, Blackwell, Oxford.
Cheney, D. L. and R. M. Seyfarth: 1990, How Monkeys See the World, University of
Chicago Press, Chicago.
Cheng, P. W. and K. J. Holyoak: 1985, ‘Pragmatic Reasoning Schemas’, Cognitive
Psychology 17, 391–416.
Cheng, P. W. and K. J. Holyoak: 1989, ‘On the Natural Selection of Reasoning Theories’,
Cognition 33, 285–313.
Clutton-Brock, T. H.: 1988, ‘Reproductive Success’, in T. H. Clutton-Brock (ed.), Reproductive Success, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
24
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
Clutton-Brock, T. H. and P. H. Harvey: 1976, ‘Evolutionary Rules and Primate Societies’,
in P. P. G. Bateson and R. A. Hinde (eds), Growing Points in Ethology, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, pp. 195–238.
Cosmides, L.: 1989, ‘The Logic of Social Exchange: Has Natural Selection Shaped How
Humans Reason? Studies With the Wason Selection Task’, Cognition 31, 187–276.
Cosmides, L. and J. Tooby: 1992, ‘Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange’, in J.
Barkow, L. Cosmides and J. Tooby (eds), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology
and the Generation of Culture, Oxford University Press, New York.
Cosmides, L. and J. Tooby: 1994, ‘Origins of Domain Specificity: The Evolution of
Functional Organization’, in L. A. Hirshfeld and S. Gelman (eds), Mapping the Mind:
Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture, pp. 85–116, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Cummins, D. D.: 1996(a), ‘Evidence of Deontic Reasoning in 3- and 4-Year-olds’, Memory
and Cognition 24, 823–9.
Cummins, D. D.: 1996(b), ‘Evidence for the Innateness of Deontic Reasoning’, Mind and
Language 11, 160–90.
Cummins, D. D.: 1996(c), ‘Dominance Hierarchies and the Evolution of Human Reasoning’, Minds and Machines 6, 463–80.
Cummins, D. D.: 1997, ‘Rationality: Biological, Psychology, and Normative Theories’,
Cahiers de Psychologie Cognitive (Current Psychology of Cognition) 16, 78–86.
Cummins, D. D.: 1998(a), ‘Social Norms and Other Minds: The Evolutionary Roots of
Higher Cognition’, in D. D. Cummins and C. A. Allen (eds), The Evolution of Mind,
Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 30–50.
Cummins, D. D.: 1998(b), ‘Can Humans Form Hierarchically Embedded Mental Representations?’ Commentary on R. W. Byrne and A. E. Russon ‘Learning By Imitation: A
Hierarchical Approach’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21, 687–8.
Cummins, D. D.: 1999, ‘Cheater Detection is Modified by Social Rank’, Evolution and
Human Behavior 20, 229–48.
Cummins, D. D.: in press, ‘Adaptive Cognitive Mechanisms: Reasoning about Social
Norms and Other Minds’, in R. Elio (ed.), Commonsense, Reasoning, and Rationality:
Vancouver Studies in Cognitive Science, Vol. 11, Oxford University Press, Oxford
Cummins, D. D. and R. C. Cummins: in press, ‘Biological Preparedness and Evolutionary
Explanation’, Cognition.
Datta, S. B.: 1983(a), ‘Relative Power and the Acquisition of Rank’, in R. A. Hinde (ed.),
Primate Social Relationships, Blackwell, Oxford,
Datta, S. B.: 1983(b), ‘Relative Power and the Maintenance of Rank’, in R. A. Hinde (ed.),
Primate Social Relationships, Blackwell, Oxford.
Dewsbury, D. A.: 1982, ‘Dominance Rank, Copulatory Behavior and Differential Reproduction’, Quarterly Review of Biology 57, 135–59.
Duhem, P.: 1954, The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, Princeton University Press,
Princeton, NJ (Original work published in 1914.)
Earman, J.: 1992, Bayes or Bust?, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Ellis, L.: 1995, ‘Dominance and Reproductive Success Among Nonhuman Animals: A
Cross-Species Comparison’, Ethology and Sociobiology 16, 257–333.
Fedigan, L.: 1983, ‘Dominance and Reproductive Success in Primates’, Yearbook of
Physical Anthropology 26, 91–129.
Flavell, J. H., E. R. Flavell, G. L. Green, and L. J. Moses: 1990, ‘Young Children"s
Understanding of Fact Beliefs Versus Value Beliefs’, Child Development 61, 915–28.
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
25
Frankel, D. G. and T. Arbel: 1980, ‘Group Formation by Two-Year-Olds’, International
Journal of Behavioral Development 3, 287–98.
Frankena, W. K.: 1963, Ethics, Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.
Gagneux, P., D. S. Woodruff, and C. Boesch: 1997, ‘Furtive Mating in Female Chimpanzees’, Nature 387, 358–69.
Goodall, J.: 1986, The Chimpanzees of Gombe, Belknap Press, Cambridge.
Gopnik, A.: 1993, ‘How We Know Our Minds: The Illusion of First-Person Knowledge of
Intentionality’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16, 1–15.
Griggs, R. A. and J. R. Cox: 1982, ‘The Elusive Thematic Materials Effect in Wason’s
Selection Task’, British Journal of Psychology 73, 407–20.
Hall, K. R. L.: 1964, ‘Aggression in Monkey and Ape Societies’, in J. Carthy and F. Ebling
(eds), The Natural History of Aggression, Academic Press, London, pp. 51–64.
Harcourt, A. H.: 1988, ‘Alliances in Contests and Social Intelligence’, in R. W. Byrne
and A. Whiten (eds), Machiavellian Intelligence, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp.
131–52.
Harcourt, A. H. and K. J. Stewart: 1987, ‘The Influence of Help in Contests on Dominance
Rank in Primates: Hints From Gorillas’, Animal Behaviour 35, 182–90.
Harcourt, A. H. and F. B. M. de Waal (eds), 1992, Coalitions and Alliances in Humans and
Other Animals, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Harkness, S., C. Pope Edwards, and C. M. Super: 1981, ‘Social Roles and Moral Reasoning: A Case Study in a Rural African Community’, Developmental Psychology 17,
595–603.
Harris, P. L.. and M. Nuñez: 1996, ‘Understanding of Permission Rules by Preschool
Children’, Child Development 67, 1572–91.
Haugaard, J. and N. D. Reppucci: 1992, ‘Children and the Truth’, in S. J. Ceci, M. De Simone Leichtman and M. Putnick (eds), Cognitive and Social Factors in Early Deception,
Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 29–46.
Hausfater, G.: 1975, ‘Dominance and Reproduction in Baboons (Papio Cynocephalus): A
Quantitative Analysis’, Contributions in Primatology 7, 1–150.
Haviland, J. M. and M. Lelivica: 1987, ‘The Induced Affect Response: 10 Week Old Infants’ Responses to Three Emotional Expressions’, Developmental Psychology 23,
97–104.
Hilpinen, R.: 1971, Deontic Logic: Introductory and Systematic Readings, Reidel/Kluwer,
Boston.
Hilpinen, R.: 1981, New Studies in Deontic Logic, Reidel/Kluwer, Boston.
Hokanson, J. E.: 1961, ‘The Effect of Frustration and Anxiety on Overt Aggression’,
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 62, 346–51.
Hokanson, J. E. and S. Shetler: 1961, ‘The Effect of Overt Aggression on Physiological
Arousal’, Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 63, 446–8.
Hold-Cavell, B. C. and D. Borsutzky: 1986, ‘Longitudinal Study of a Group of Preschool
Children’, Ethology and Sociobiology 7, 39–56.
Hollos, M., P. E. Leis and E. Turiel: 1986, ‘Social Reasoning in Ijo Children and Adolescents in Nigerian Communities’, Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 17, 352–74.
Holyoak, K. J. and P. W. Cheng: 1995, ‘Pragmatic Reasoning with a Point of View’, 1,
289–313.
Horwich, P.: 1982, Probability and Evidence, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Jenkins, J. and J. W. Astington: 1996, ‘Cognitive Factors and Family Structure Associated
with Theory of Mind Development in Young Children’, Developmental Psychology 32,
70–8.
26
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
Johnson-Laird, P. N., P. Legrenzi and M. S. Legrenzi: 1972, ‘Reasoning and a Sense of
Reality’, British Journal of Psychology 63, 395–400.
Keating, C. F. and K. R. Heltman: 1994, ‘Dominance and Deception in Children and
Adults: Are Leaders the Best Misleaders?’, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin
54, 312–21.
Kosslyn, S. M. and O. Koenig: 1995, Wet Mind: The New Cognitive Neuroscience, Free
Press, New York.
Krebs, J. R. and R. Dawkins: 1984, ‘Animal Signals: Mind-Reading and Manipulation’, in
J. R. Krebs and N. B. Davies (eds), Behavioral Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach, 2nd
ed., Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 380–402.
La Freniere, P. and W. R. Charlesworth: 1983, ‘Dominance, Attention, and Affiliation in
a Preschool Group: A Nine-Month Longitudinal Study’, Ethology and Sociobiology 4,
55–67.
Lakatos, I.: 1970, ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’,
in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, pp. 91–196.
Leslie, A. M.: 1994, ‘ToMM, ToBY, and Agency: Core Architecture and Domain Specificity’, in L. A. Hirshfeld and S. A. Gelman (eds), Mapping the Mind: Domain
Specificity in Cognition and Culture, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp.
119–48.
Lewis, C., N. Freeman, C. Kyriakidou, K. Maridaki-Kassotaki and D. Berridge: 1996, ‘Social Influences on False Belief Access: Specific Contagion or General Apprenticeship?’,
Child Development 67, 2930–47.
Manktelow, K. I. and D. E. Over: 1991, ‘Social Roles and Utilities in Reasoning With
Deontic Conditionals’, Cognition 39, 85–105.
Manktelow, K. I., and D. E. Over: 1995, ‘Deontic Reasoning’, in S. E. Newstead and J. St.
B. Evans (eds), Perspectives On Thinking and Reasoning, Erlbaum, Englewood Cliffs,
NJ.
McCann, T. S.: 1981, ‘Aggression and Sexual Activity of Male Southern Elephant Seals
(Mirounga Leonina)’, Journal of Zoology 195, 295–310.
McGuffin, P. and J. Scourfield: 1997, ‘A Father’s Imprint on His Daughter’s Thinking’,
Nature 387, 652–3.
McKenzie, J. A. and K. O’Farrell: 1993, ‘Modification of Developmental Instability and
Fitness: Malathion-Resistance in the Australian Sheep Blowfly’, Genetica 89, 67–76.
Mealey, L., C. Daood and M. Krage: 1996, ‘Enhanced Memory for Faces of Cheaters’,
Ethology and Sociobiology 17, 119–28.
Meltzoff, A. N.: 1995, ‘Understanding the Intentions of Others: Re-enactment of Intended
Acts by 18-month-old Children’, Developmental Psychology 31, 838–50.
Menzel, E. W.: 1974, ‘A Group of Chimpanzees in a 1-Acre Field: Leadership and Communication’, in A. M. Schrier and F. Stollnitz (eds), Behavior of Nonhuman Primates,
Academic Press, New York, pp. 83–153.
Milgram, S.: 1974. Obedience to Authority, Harper and Row, New York.
Mitchell, R. W.: 1986, ‘A Framework for Discussing Deception’, in R. W. Mitchell and N.
S. Thompson (eds), Deception: Perspectives on Human and Nonhuman Deceit, SUNY
Press, New York, pp. 3–40.
Nishida, T.: 1983, ‘Alpha Status and Agonistic Alliance in Wild Chimpanzees (Pan
Troglodytes Schweinfurthü)’, Primates 24, 318–336.
Nucci, L. P., E. Turiel and G. Encarnacion-Gawrych: 1983, ‘Children’s Social Interactions
and Social Concepts’, Journal of Cross Cultural Psychology 14, 469–87.
HOW THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT SHAPED THE EVOLUTION OF MIND
27
Oaksford, M. and N. Chater: 1994, ‘A Rational Analysis of the Selection Task As Optimal
Data Selection’, Psychological Review 101, 608–31
Perner, J.: 1991, Understanding the Representational Mind, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Perner, J., T. Ruthman and S. R. Leekam: 1994, ‘Theory of Mind is Contagious: You Catch
It from Your Sibs’, Child Development 65, 1228–38.
Perner, J. and H. Wimmer: 1985, ‘John Thinks That Mary Thinks That . . . : Attribution
of Second-Order Beliefs by 5–10-Year-Old Children’, Journal of Experimental Child
Psychology 38, 437–71.
Pope Edwards, C.: 1982, ‘Moral Development in Comparative Cultural Perspective’, in D.
A. Wagner and H. W. Stevenson (eds), Cultural Perspectives on Child Development, W.
H. Freeman, San Francisco.
Politzer, G. and A. Nguyen-Xuan: 1992, ‘Reasoning about Conditional Promises and
Warnings: Darwinian Algorithms, Mental Models, Relevance Judgments, or Pragmatic
Schemes?’, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 44A, 401–421.
Povinelli, D. J.: 1994, ‘What Chimpanzees (Might) Know about the Mind’, in R. W.
Wrangham, W. C. McGrew, F. B. M. de Waal and P. G. Heitne (eds), Chimpanzee
Cultures, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 285–300.
Prud’homme, J. and B. Chapais: 1993, ‘Aggressive Interventions and Matrilineal Dominance Relations in Semifree-Ranging Barbary Macaques’, Primates 34, 271–83.
Putnam, H.: 1974, ‘The ‘Corroboration’ of Theories’, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Vol. 1, Open Court, LaSalle, IL,.pp. 221–40.
Rabbie, J. M.: 1992, ‘The Effect of Intragroup Cooperation and Intergroup Competition on
In-Group and Out-Group Hostility’, in F. de Waal and A. H. Harcourt (eds), Coalitions
and Alliances in Humans and Other Animals, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 175–
208.
Riggs, K. J., D. M. Peterson, E. J. Robinson, and P. Mitchell: 1998, ‘Are Errors in False
Belief Tasks Symptomatic of a Broader Difficulty with Counterfactuality?’, Cognitive
Development 13, 73–90.
Riss, D. C. and J. Goodall: 1977, ‘The Recent Rise to the Alpha-Rank in a Population of
Free-Living Chimpanzees’, Folia Primatologica 27, 134–51.
Robinson, J. G.: 1982, ‘Intrasexual Competition and Mate Choice in Primates’, American
Journal of Primatology, 1 Supplement, 131–44.
Rubin, K. and R. J. Caplan: 1992, Peer Relationships in Childhood, Erlbaum, Englewood
Cliffs, NJ.
Ruffman, T., J. Perner, M. Naito, L. Parkin and W. C. Clements: 1998, ‘Older (But Not
Younger) Siblings Facilitate False Belief Understanding’, Developmental Psychology
34, 161–74.
Scribner, S.: 1975, ‘Recall of Classical Syllogisms: A Cross-Cultural Investigation of
Errors on Logical Problems’, in R. J. Falmagne (ed.), Reasoning: Representation and
Process in Children and Adults, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Seyfarth, R. M.: 1976, ‘Social Relationships among Adult Female Monkeys’, Animal
Behavior 24, 917–38.
Seyfarth, R. M. and D. L. Cheney: 1984, ‘Grooming, Alliances, and Reciprocal Altriusm
in Vervet Monkeys’, Nature 308, 541–3.
Silk, J. B.: 1987, ‘Social Behavior in Evolutionary Perspective’, in B. B. Smuts, D. L.
Cheney, R. M. Seyfarth, R. W. Wrangham and T. T. Struhsaker (eds), Primate Societies,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp. 318–29.
Smith, P. K.: 1988, ‘The Cognitive Demands of Children’s Social Interactions With Peers’,
in R. W. Byrne and A. Whiten (eds), Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise
28
DENISE DELLAROSA CUMMINS
and the Evolution of Intellect in Monkeys Apes and Humans, Oxford University Press,
Oxford, pp. 94–110.
Smuts, B.: 1985, Sex and Friendship in Baboons, Aldine Press, Hawthorne.
Snarey, J. R.: 1985, ‘Cross-Cultural Universality of Social-Moral Development: A Critical
Review of Kohlbergian Research’, Psychological Bulletin 97, 202–32.
Stanovich, K. E. and R. F. West, in press, ‘Cognitive Ability and Variation in Selection
Task Performance’, Thinking and Reasoning 4, 193–230.
Strayer, F. F. and M. Trudel: 1984, ‘Developmental Changes in the Nature and Function of
Social Dominance Among Young Children’, Ethology and Sociobiology 5, 279–95.
Strichartz, A. F. and R. V. Burton: 1990, ‘Lies and Truth: A Study in the Development of
the Concept’, Child Development 61, 211–20.
Tutin, C. E. G.: 1979, ‘Mating Patterns and Reproductive Strategies in a Community of
Wild Chimpanzees (Pan Troglodytes Schweinfurtü)’, Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology 6, 29–38.
Uehara, S., M. Hiraiwa-Hasegawa, K. Hosaka and M. Hamai: 1994, ‘The Fate of Defeated
Alpha Male Chimpanzees in Relation To Their Social Networks’, Primates 35, 49–55.
Vandell, L. and K. S. Wilson: (1987), ‘Infant’s Interactions With Mother, Sibling, and Peer:
Contrasts and Relations Between Interaction Systems’, Child Development 58, 176–86.
de Waal, F. B. M.: 1982, Chimpanzee Politics, Johns-Hopkins University Press, Baltimore.
de Waal, F. B. M.: 1989, ‘Food Sharing and Reciprocal Obligations among Chimpanzees’,
Journal of Human Evolution 18, 433–59.
de Waal, F. B. M.: 1992, ‘Coalitions As Part of Reciprocal Relations in the Arnhem Chimpanzee Colony’, in A. H. Harcourt and F. De Waal (eds), Coalitions and Alliances in
Humans and Other Animals, Oxford University, Oxford, pp. 233–58.
de Waal, F. B. M.: 1996, Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Waddington, C. H.: 1975, The Evolution of an Evolutionist, Cornell University Press,
Ithaca, NY.
Walters, J. R. and R. M. Seyfarth: 1987, ‘Conflict and Cooperation’, in B. B. Smuts, D. L.
Cheney, R. M. Seyfarth, R. W. Wrangham, and T. T. Struhsaker (eds), Primate Societies,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp. 306–17.
Watts, C. R. and A. W. Stokes: 1971, ‘The Social Order of Turkeys’, Scientific American
224, 112–8
Weg, E. and V. Smith: 1993, ‘On the Failure To Induce Meager Offers in Ultimatum
Games’, Journal of Economic Psychology 14, 17–32
Wellman, H. M.: 1990, The Child’s Theory of Mind, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Whiten, A. and R. W. Byrne: 1988, ‘The Manipulation of Attention in Primate Tactical
Deception’, in R. W. Byrne and A. Whiten (eds), Machiavellian Intelligence, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, pp. 211–24.
Wimmer, H., S. Gruber and J. Perner: 1984, ‘Young Children’s Conception of Lying:
Lexical Realism – Moral Subjectivism’, Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 37,
1–30.
Department of Philosophy
University of California-Davis
Davis CA 95616
E-mail:
[email protected]