Academia.eduAcademia.edu

The General Will

The General Will Jean-Jacques Rousseau is a philosopher who is widely known for his concept of "the general will." Rousseau emphasizes the importance of this general will throughout his philosophies, as he believes it to be the will of a political organism, which he sees as an entity with a life of its own. He makes it seem as though a political state can be compared to a body. Just as a body is unified, though it has various parts that have particular functions, a political state also has a will which looks to its general well-being.

Emily Owens 211426905 1 PHIL 2923 Monday March 5, 2012 Question no. 2 The General Will Jean-Jacques Rousseau is a philosopher who is widely known for his concept of ‘the general will.” Rousseau emphasizes the importance of this general will throughout his philosophies, as he believes it to be the will of a political organism, which he sees as an entity with a life of its own. He makes it seem as though a political state can be compared to a body. Just as a body is unified, though it has various parts that have particular functions, a political state also has a will which looks to its general well-being. However, a conflict arises when we ask ourselves how this general will can be determined, and we are faced with two possible options offered by Rousseau that seem to be rather contradictory. On one hand, he argues that the general will allows for individual diversity and freedom but it also encourages the well-being of the whole, therefore conflicting with the particular interests of individuals. This creates tension between the belief of a general will of the assembled people, and a general will supposedly always tending toward public utility. There are a few examples offered by Rousseau, and other authors that have studied his work, that help us draw a conclusion about how to determine the general will. These examples, along with real life instances can help to prove that the two aspects of his view can be reconciled because they are mutually agreeable. Rousseau argues that “in order for the general will to be truly general it must come 2 from all and apply to all” (The Social Contract, 1762). In order for it to be applied, Rousseau argues that the law must be general in application and universal in scope. For this to be true, however, it has to be the case that the situation of citizens is substantially similar to one another. That being said, the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010) helps us distinguish that this isn’t always the case. It explains that in a state where citizens enjoy a wide diversity of lifestyles and occupations, or where there is a great deal of cultural diversity, or where there is a high degree of economic inequality, it will not generally be the case that the impact of the laws will be the same for everyone. From this we can assume that in such cases it will often not be true that a citizen can occupy the standpoint of the general will merely by imagining the impact of general and universal laws on his or her own case. This is seen through the example of the separatist movement in Quebec, Canada. The separatist groups have made their desire to leave the country very clear, which led to the popular belief that Quebec is a population who are all determined to see this accomplished. But just because one group of people is very vocal and prominent in the lobbying world, does this mean that the entire population of Quebec wants the same thing, or that this is the best thing for the population? Well, frankly, it doesn’t. This was shown through the referendum that yielded the results determined by the people of Quebec for Quebec to remain part of Canada. Because of the different lifestyles and cultures within Quebec, different people wanted different things. This proves there can be more than one popular general will among different groups in a population, and there might even be more than one that tends toward public utility, but any one of these general wills are not focused on what is best for the population as a 3 whole. Rousseau explains this by stating that “in such a case the body of society is really divided into other bodies, the members of which acquire a general will, which is good and just with respect to these new bodies, but unjust and bad with regard to the whole, from which each is thus dismembered” (Discourse on Political Economy, 1755). The object of the general will is always abstract, or for lack of a better term, general. It can set up rules, social classes, or even a monarchial government, but it can never specify the particular individuals who are subject to the rules, members of the classes, or the rulers in the government. James J. Delaney (2005) explains that this is in keeping with the idea that the general will speaks to the good of the society as a whole. It is not to be confused with the collection of individual wills which would put their own needs, or the needs of particular factions, above those of the general public. This leads to a related point. Rousseau argues that there is an important distinction to be made between the general will and the collection of individual wills. In order for the general will to be determined, it must accommodate the interests of the entire population as one large assembly, not as a sum of separate assemblies. He further explains the divide between the will of the Assembly and the will of the public when he claims that there is often a great deal of difference between the will of all and the general will. The latter looks only to the common interest; the former considers private interest and is only a sum of private wills. But take away from these same wills the pluses and minuses that cancel each other out, and the remaining sum of the differences is the general will (Social Contract, IV, 146). 4 This point can be understood by considering that if citizens were ignorant of the groups to which they would belong, they would inevitably make decisions that would be to the advantage of the society as a whole, and thus be in accordance with the general will. James J. Delaney (2005) tells us that with the conflict between the general and individual wills in mind, Rousseau articulates three maxims which supply the basis for a politically virtuous state: (1) Follow the general will in every action; (2) Ensure that every particular will is in accordance with the general will; and (3) Public needs must be satisfied. Citizens follow these maxims when there is a sense of equality among them, and when they develop a genuine respect for law. Rousseau claims that when laws are in accordance with the general will, good citizens will respect and love both the state and their fellow citizens. Therefore, citizens will see the intrinsic value in the law, even in cases in which it may conflict with their individual wills. We still need to answer the question, however, as to how the general will is in fact determined. The answer to this question is through an assembly that represents the public utility. Rousseau (1755) offers an answer when he questions, must the whole nation be assembled together at every unforeseen event? Certainly not. It ought the less to be assembled, because it is by no means certain that its decision would be the expression of the general will; besides, the method would be impractible in a great people, and is hardly ever necessary where the government is well-intentioned” (Discourse on Political Economy, III, i). 5 This is where we can merge together Rousseau’s two different concepts into one basic idea: democracy. Rousseau tells us that in a democracy “each of us puts his person and all his power in common under the supreme direction of the general will, and, in our corporate capacity, we receive each member as an indivisible part of the whole" (1786, I, vi). Within this agreement, we elect an assembly to carry out the proceedings of our general will, which is decided on by means of a majority vote. By doing so, we are assuming that “equity is guaranteed [to us] by the fact that each person necessarily submits himself to the will he imposes on others” (The Social Contract, 1762, II). The assembly is, therefore, a representation of the public, guaranteeing us with equity so that we will want to follow the law, as earlier stated. Rousseau reaffirms that “the rulers well know that the general will is always on the side which is most favourable to the public interest, that is to say, most equitable; so that it is needful only to act justly, to be certain of following the general will” (The Social Contract, 1762, III, i). With a democracy, we are afforded with an assembly that wills a general will that is “always right and tends toward the public utility” (The Social Contract, 1762, II, iii). 6 References Delaney, J. (2005). Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseau/#SH4b Rousseau, J. (1755). A Discourse on the Political Economy. The Basic Political Writings. Vol III. Rousseau, J. (1762). On the Social Contract. . The Basic Political Writings. Vol IV. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (2010). Jean Jacques Rousseau. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rousseau/#IdeGenWil