Peter Bornedal
RECONSTRUCTING NIETZSCHE’S EPISTEMOLOGY
WITHIN THE POSITIVIST AND PRAGMATIC TRADITIONS
Today we possess science precisely to the extent that we have decided
to accept the testimony of the senses – as we still sharpen them, arm
them, and learn to think them through. The rest is miscarriage and
non-yet-science.
Nietzsche: Götzendämmerung1
1. The Thing-in-itself and the True-Apparent Distinction
Nietzsche criticizes the „thing-in-itself‟ and the „true-apparent distinction‟
throughout his work. However, the „thing-in-itself‟ changes value from
being understood as a „hidden‟ thing to being understood as a
substantial, homogeneous, distinct, and independent „thing.‟
„Perspectivism‟ as epistemological doctrine emerges as the logical
consequence of the latter criticism of the thing as distinctly and
substantially „in-itself.‟
1.1. Nietzsche‟s Epistemology in Analytic Readings
In various often highly complex arguments, we sometimes detect in
Analytic critique an urgency to restore the „thing-in-itself‟ and the „trueapparent‟ distinction to Nietzsche‟s epistemology. The analytic
commentator is frequently reading Nietzsche‟s perspectivism as
paradoxical or inconsistent in two different directions, logically and
ontologically.
Ad 1. Logically, one reads Nietzsche‟s remarks on „perspectivism‟ as
meta-statements on knowledge, understood as universal all-inclusive
propositions of the form, „all knowledge is perspectival,‟ and from here
1
Nietzsche: GD, Die „Vernunft‟ in der Philosophie 3, KSA 6, p. 75. References
to Nietzsche‟s work conform to usual standard. KSA: Sämtliche Werke
Kritische Studienausgabe. Ed. G. Colli & M. Montinari. Berlin/New York (W.
de Gruyter), 1967-77. FW: Die fröhliche Wissenschaft, KSA 3. GD:
Götzendämmerung, KSA 6. GM: Zur Genealogie der Moral, KSA 5. JGB:
Jenseits von Gut und Böse, KSA 5. NF: Nachgelassende Fragmente, KSA 7-14.
WL: Über Wahrheit und Lüge in aussermoralischen Sinne, KSA 1. WM: Der
Wille zur Macht. Stuttgart (Kröner Verlag), 1996.
2
the logician extracts the Liar Paradox.2 If the sentence says that „all
knowledge is perspectival,‟ the sentence includes itself as perspectival
and is therefore not truly true, and it must follow that „Perspectivism‟ as
creed defeats itself. This typically impels the commentator to inquire
whether Nietzsche can want to express such a paradox, while it gives the
commentator the opportunity to suggest logically more satisfying
alternatives to the purported paradox.
Ad 2. Ontologically, perspectivism is seen as constituting a problem,
since it allows the object-world to dissipate into perspectives and as such
seems to defend that our sensible knowledge is „only‟ perspectival or
„only‟ interpretation, not factual. If our seeing is perspectival, the
objectivity of the world as an independent reality (subject-, mind-,
language-, and theory-independent) is at stake, since one has allowed
interpretations, interests, and contexts to determine objects in their being.
The analytic-rationalist reader tends to object to Nietzsche‟s perceived
introduction of relativism, skepticism, or idealism on the supposedly
strong counter-argument that if everything is „our perspective,‟ we
necessarily must presuppose an objective world, which is there to be seen
from „different angles.‟3 If we ask what comes first, the „object‟ or the
„different angles‟ from where we see it, the sound answer gives itself, „the
object.‟ As such, perspectivism can only be an epiphenomenon,
reconfirming the solid existence of an independent and real world.
After this fundamental rebuttal of Nietzsche‟s epistemological
position, we then notice that analytic commentary often starts a rescuing
operation meant to save Nietzsche from his alleged inconsistencies; we
notice that within an overall destructive critique, benevolent intentions (or
„charitable readings‟) usually are more common than malevolent. As the
point of departure, one always attempts to repair the supposed paradox of
perspectivism as it is perceived to lead us to all the dangerous „isms‟ –
2
3
On the paradox, see e.g., Dowden, Bradley: “Liar Paraodox” in: Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy or Russell, Bertrand. Logic and Knowledge:
Essays 1901-1950, ed. by Robert C. Marsh, George Allen & Unwin Ltd.
(1956).
We find such arguments in for example M. Clark: Nietzsche on Truth and
Philosophy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991; cf. p. 136-139) or
in B. Leiter: Nietzsche on Morality (London, Routledge, 2002) & Leiter:
“Perspectivism in Nietzsche‟s Genealogy of Morals,” in Nietzsche, Genealogy,
Morality (ed. R. Schacht. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994); p.
344. For objections to the approach, see e.g., Lightbody, B.: “Nietzsche,
Perspectivism, Anti-realism: An Inconsistent Triad”; in The European Legacy,
Vol. 15/4, 2010, and C. Cox: Nietzsche: Naturalism and Interpretation.
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999).
3
skepticism, relativism, or idealism – as such jeopardizing serious
epistemic commitment to a „real‟ and „true‟ world.
In this analytic-rationalist drive to restore things-in-themselves to
Nietzsche – not only in the form of substance and matter, but sometimes
also in the form of forces, causes, selves, or morals – one appears to
defend what H. Putnam has labeled „metaphysical realism‟ as a few
commentators have remarked,4 i.e., the defense of an objective mind-,
language-, and theory-independent world about which we form
knowledge as representation of that world as it is in-itself. In
philosophical elaboration of this view, the „correspondence theory of
truth‟ offers the most obvious account of the notion. Theories are
accordingly true or false depending on whether they fit or do not fit the
objectivity of things antedating them.
As I shall argue, the idea of this objective world is persistently
criticized throughout Nietzsche‟s work, from the early Wahrheit und Lüge
to the late Nachlaß material, while „perspectivism‟ emerges as his label
for an alternative epistemology.
I see a number of problems emerging from the analytic-rationalistic
approach that are avoided in one aligns oneself closer to Nietzsche‟s text
and intellectual context, one of them being that if one insists on the
objectivity of the object, while permitting „perspectivism‟ only as
subjective representations of the object, it remains unexplained how
knowledge of the supposedly solid and permanent world is produced
among subjects with different, competing, and often opposing beliefs. It
seems then that the proud display of epistemic commitment achieves the
opposite of what it intends, because it destabilizes knowledge in an even
more radical sense than what Nietzsche was intending. One ends up
defending a position that Mach would dismiss as „naïve subjectivism‟:
“Naïve subjectivism [construing] variant findings of one person under
variable conditions and of different persons as so many cases of
appearance in contrast with a hypothetical constant reality, is no longer
admissible.”5
4
5
The discussion has been addressed by Abel, G.: Interpretationswelten:
Gegenwartsphilosophie Jenseits von Essentialismus and Relativismus.
Frankfurt, Suhkamp Verlag, 1995. L. Anderson discusses the correspondence
theoretical interpretations of Nietzsche‟s perspectivism with reference to
Putnam in “Truth and Objectivity in Perspectivism”; Synthese 115, 1-32,
Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998.
Mach, E.: Knowledge and Error: Sketches on the Psychology of Enquiry
(Translation T. J. McGormack. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company,
1976 (German edition, 1905)), p. 6.
4
1.2. Different Aspects of the “Thing-in-Itself‟
In reconstructing Nietzsche‟s epistemology, we can hardly
overestimate the importance of his challenge to the notion of the „thingin-itself‟ and to the „true-apparent distinction.‟ It is a critical engagement
he reiterates from his earliest to his latest writings, although his early
views undergo a revision especially concerning the thing-in-itself.
We are able to discern three possible definitions of the always
criticized „thing‟: (1) It can be conceived as a hidden some-thing, as if it is
a substance or a lump of matter actually existing albeit not accessible forus. In this sense, the „thing‟ is both in-itself and hidden, but it is still
assumed to be present in its hiding (this seems to be the most common
and traditional interpretation, which Nietzsche is most obviously
addressing, in critical discussion, in the early WL). (2) It can be conceived
as a Grenzbegriff as according to F. A. Lange,6 indicating an unknown but
indeterminable realm not accessible to us given our biological speciesspecific perceptive-cognitive limitations as Homo Sapiens. The more
inaccessible the notion becomes, the more we must acknowledge
„appearances‟ as our only reality (cf. Lange). Furthermore, the emergence
of evolutionary biology as well as research in vision and sensation (made
by, e.g., H. von Helmholtz, Du Bois Raymond, G. Th. Fechner, and E.
Mach) can be seen as supporting this „naturalized‟ version of the „thingin-itself.‟ In this biological-physiological sense, we can conceive the
„thing‟ as that which is below Fechner‟s “thresholds.”7 Accordingly, we
happen to have a perceptive-cognitive apparatus imperfect in its
perception of detail and limited to perception above a certain sensational
threshold. That which we are incapable of perceiving below our
„threshold‟ (beyond a certain limit) is conceived as the „in-itself.‟ (3) The
thing-in-itself may finally be seen as that which we in commonsensical or
„pragmatic‟ perception without further ado understand as a „thing‟ before
we start analyzing or contemplating its properties, elements, relations,
contexts, or perspectives. In this sense, the thing is no longer understood
as in-itself as hidden, as inaccessible, or as below threshold, but rather as
an in-itself of the distinct, homogeneous, and unified object. A „thing‟ is
now our spontaneous cognitive abstraction, abbreviation, or interpretation
6
7
“Das „Ding an sich‟ ist ein bloßer Grenzbegriff.” Lange, Fr. A.: Geschichte des
Materialismus, Zweites Buch. Geschichte des Materialismus seit Kant, op. cit.
p. 50. See also Stack, G.: Lange and Nietzsche, op. cit., p. 217-18.
Cf. Fechner, G. Th.: Elements of Psychophysics. New York/Chicago, Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, 1966. Translated by H. Adler.
5
of complexes of relations and sense-data, which we necessarily carry out
when we perceive properly speaking, i.e., when we transform a world of
sensation-elements into simple and crude „objects.‟ In any of these three
aspects, the „thing‟ is in Nietzsche always that which is falsely regarded
as „true‟ contrary to that which is „apparent.‟
The last aspect has here our special attention, because when the „thingitself‟ changes value from its first to its third aspect, the issue is no longer
our ignorance about the „hidden,‟ but about the isolated and discrete. The
„thing-in-itself‟ becomes a „thing-as-it-is‟ falsely assuming a
homogeneous object with its self-evidently ascribed substantiality and
extension. This last aspect is the most pertinent in the discussion of
Nietzsche‟s perspectivism, as it assumes objectivity constituted as such,
i.e., without relations to other things, eyes, or minds.8 The logical
consequence of discarding the notion of an „object as such‟ is paving the
way for a perspectival-phenomenal world of relationships. As we shall
see, Nietzsche‟s epistemological perspectivism becomes Phenomenalism
and indeed Relativism.
1.3. The Development in the Understanding of the „Thing‟ in GD
The famous aphorism from Götzendämmerung (GD), “Wie die „wahre
Welt‟ endlich zur Fabel Wurde,” may serve us as a quick summary of the
development of the understanding of the „thing-in-itself‟ as Nietzsche
would see it. After two pre-Kantian positions and one Kantian position,
Nietzsche introduces in his three final positions the abolishment of the
„thing.‟
In his positions from (4) over (5) to (6), the deconstruction of the
Kantian „thing‟ is carried out in still more uncompromising language, to
the extent that we end up with a „thing‟ that is hardly recognizable as
Kantian any longer. If position (4) states that the “true world” is
unreachable and unknowable, position (5) infers that it is useless and can
be discarded; the recognition that a „true‟ world is unreachable and need
not concern us is entailing the realization that a „true world‟ is useless
baggage we can get rid of. After this realization, Nietzsche suggests (6),
the somewhat puzzling conclusion that the notion of an apparent world is
useless too. This conclusion immediately appears as counter-intuitive
given that we without a „true‟ world are inclined to believe that we are left
with an „apparent.‟
8
Several passages from the late work substantiates this interpretation, for
example in NF 1885-86, KSA 12, 2[85], KSA 12, 2[149], KSA 12, 2[154],
KSA 12, 9[40], KSA 12, 10[202])
6
2. Eliminating the True-Apparent Distinction
When Nietzsche abandons the true-apparent distinction, a world emerges
disrobed of all logical, teleological, and/or theological rationalizations.
In the chaotic world of becoming no grandiose narratives or moral
fictions survive. Not even the binary „true-apparent‟ survive, because an
always emerging world is no longer an appearance of something else; the
„apparent‟ is not a reference to the „true.‟ There is no depth to the world,
but „only‟ a phenomenal surface of relationships and relationships
between relationships, ad infinitum. Only what we do with that surfaceworld is a „fiction,‟ the world itself is no fiction; it „does not lie.‟
2.1. Beyond the Classical Binary: Appearances without Things
Position (6) seems out of nowhere to declare the „apparent‟ world
abolished as well as the „true.‟ Is Nietzsche‟s world now a „fiction‟ or an
„idea‟; is he a „fictionalist‟ and an „idealist‟; is he suggesting the
abandonment of both empirical and transcendent world?
I will answer in the negative and suggest that he in (6) is discussing the
concept of the real rather than the real. If we abandon the concept of the
„true,‟ we immediately annihilate the classical hierarchical opposition
between „true‟ and „apparent‟ according to which „true‟ is appreciated and
„apparent‟ depreciated. If there is no „true world‟ as concept, the
background on which appearances emerge as appearances disappears and
the philosophical dichotomy true versus apparent collapses. From a
structural-linguistic point of view, it is the law of binary opposition that
nothing can reside in one term. According to binary logic, the opposition
A versus B is translated into the opposition A versus non-A, where A and
non-A are co-dependent in their complementariness. The two positions are
linked, and if we erase one, we erase the link as such; A is powerless to
designate anything without the help of non-A, and vice versa. Therefore,
when we retract one term in the opposition, both terms lose value,
because they are asserted only through their reciprocal difference in their
link. This is the hard rule for the binary opposition or what Nietzsche
calls the antithesis, and in several notes it is explicitly as „antithesis‟ he
understands the opposition „truth-appearance.‟9
If his position (6) applies on the level of conceptual logic, it entails no
judgment about the ontological existence of an appearing world. Thus, on
9
See e.g., NF, 1886-87, KSA 12, 6[23], NF, 1886-87, KSA, 12, 6[23], NF, 1887,
KSA12, 9[91], or letter to Carl von Gersdorff, late August, 18669
7
the one hand, we have an appearing world that will continue to appear as
it has always been appearing, on the other, we have a rejection of
„appearances‟ as linked to „truth,‟ i.e., understood as outward
representations of or references to a „true‟ world. „Appearances‟ have in
other words lost their sign-function, they no longer refer to a truer double.
E. Mach is expressing the same idea when in Science of Mechanics he
says, “Sensations are not signs of things. [ . . . ] The world is not
composed of „things‟ as its elements, but of colors, tones, pressures,
spaces, times, in short what we ordinarily call individual sensations.”10
Therefore, Nietzsche can in GD still go on maintaining that “Die
“scheinbare” Welt ist die einzige”.11 With an analogy, we may suggest
that he envisions the world like the surface of a piece of paper, but
without a backside (as a coin without flipside, a recto without verso). The
idea is paradoxical and impossible to conceptualize in classical geometry,
but it at least serves to illustrate that Nietzsche presupposes a flat
metaphysical universe, in which it is absurd to entertain notions of a
hypothetical extra-real or supernatural world, because his new „superapparent‟ world implies a world of impenetrable surfaces only.
Metaphysically speaking, we live in (or on) this two-dimensional flatland
blending seamlessly into this flatland ourselves (since our selves are „flat‟
as well).12
2.2. Senses do not Lie . . .
It must follow that if the apparent world is the only „world,‟ it cannot
be a „falsification.‟ When the „thing-in-itself‟ has been abandoned, there
is nothing left to falsify. The surface is what is and can only present itself
as such. Therefore Nietzsche can with logical consistency declare that
senses “do not lie at all [sie lügen überhaupt nicht]”; only what “we make
of them is a lie,” namely of “unity, of thinghood, of substance, of
10
11
12
Mach, Ernst: Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of its
Development. (Translation T. J. McCormack. Chicago/London, Open Court,
1919); p. 483.
Nietzsche: GD, Die Vernunft in der Philosophie, II 2.
In his letter to von Gersdorff, he with agreement summarizes Lange‟s positions:
“[Lange‟s] conclusions are summed up in the following three propositions: 1)
The world of the senses is the product of our organization. 2) Our visible
(physical) organs are, like all other parts of the phenomenal world, only images
of an unknown object. 3) Our real organization is therefore as much unknown
to us as real external things are. We continually have before us nothing but the
product of both.” Nietzsche: Letter to Carl von Gersdorff, late August, 1866;
quoted from T. Brobjer: Nietzsche‟s Philosophical Context, op. cit., p. 33.
8
permanence.” (GD II, “Die Vernunft in der Philosophie”). R. Avenarius
had expressed a similar idea in his “Prolegomena”: “The senses do not
deceive, but the judgment does.”13
Since we do not and cannot receive something differently from how
we receive it, nor have any influence on what and how we receive what
we receive, we can no longer talk about simple sense-data as lying. Since
furthermore, sense-data are our primary encounter with the world, we
cannot conclude that they are about something that is not a lie, because
that would falsely imply that we could have an encounter with this other
something. Consequently, if Nietzsche like the early positivists is
reducing everything to appearances, he has abandoned the logical
possibility for falsifying a ground.
That seems to be why M. Clark famously has concluded that Nietzsche
in late writings abandons his so-called „falsification-thesis.‟14 Clark sees
that Nietzsche rejects the „thing-in-itself,‟ and asks quite pertinently,
“What is left to be falsified?” The straightforward answer would seem to
be „nothing,‟ insofar as we construe Nietzsche to imply that there is no
„true‟ world left to be falsified. However, Clark‟s concludes that there is
no falsification of „the true world,‟ as she assumes that everything remains
non-falsified – in an argument often defended in her Nietzsche
commentaries. Clark defends consequently a Nietzsche, who in „late
work‟ concludes that a true world of objects as self-presently available is
carried over into human perception. Clark and like-minded assume a
camera-theory of knowledge where the image of the object duplicates the
object, as they tacitly assume that the human eye sees the world neutrally
and flawlessly (like the lens of a camera).
13
14
Avenarius is here quoted from H. Kleinpeter, op. cit., p. 69, as the perceptive
Kleinpeter continues the passage: “similar views have been stated by Nietzsche
and Mach.” Ibid.
See M. Clark, ibid., p. 120. M. Clark‟s argument that Nietzsche eventually
abandons his so-called „falsification-thesis‟ (the idea that truth and knowledge
are „illusions‟ falsifying the world), has been met with objections from several
quarters in Nietzsche-commentary, e.g., L. Anderson: “Overcoming Charity:
The Case of Clark‟s Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy.” (Nietzsche-Studien,
vol. 25, 1996), and N. Hussain: “Nietzsche‟s Positivism” (European Journal of
Philosophy 12:3, Blackwell, 2004). I find especially Hussein‟s response
compelling as he develops Nietzsche‟s position in juxtaposition to Mach‟s. This
strategy helps him to see Nietzsche as both “rejecting the thing-in-itself,
accepting a falsification thesis and defending empiricism.” Hussain:
“Nietzsche‟s Positivism,” op. cit., p. 357. In response to Hussain, Clark and
Dudrick dismiss the correspondences between Nietzsche and Machean
positivism, in Clark & Dudrick: “Nietzsche‟s Post-Positivism”; The European
Journal of Philosophy, Blackwell, 2004.
9
The element of truth in Clark‟s reading is of course that Nietzsche does
indeed establish that senses „do not lie,‟ although he in the same passage
continues to explain that what we make of them explicitly do: was wir aus
ihrem Zeugniss m a c h e n , das legt erst die Lüge hinein (we notice that
„machen‟ is emphasized). So, sense-receptions may not lie, but our
processing of them lie, falsify, or interpret. “Die „Vernunft‟ ist die
Ursache, dass wir das Zeugniss der Sinne fälschen (ibid.).” This so-called
„Vernunft‟ is perceptive, and must be pre-linguistic since it is the
spontaneous abbreviation and simplification of a chaotic sense-data
world. It is accountable for an elementary cognitive-perceptive ordering
of the universe, which we would share with all higher animals.15
Nietzsche is here expressing a view identical to views of Avenarius and
Mach, presented even in similar vocabulary, since Mach too talks about
the distinct, independent, and self-identical object as a „fiction.‟
If in Nietzsche, senses or impressions do not „lie‟ (but perceptions do)
it is because there is nothing left to lie about; it is the „that about which‟
that disappears, i.e., the supposed thing-hood or objectivity outside us.
This has the consequence that the world of „objects‟ is annihilated as
origin of knowledge – not restored. In Analytic-Rationalist epistemology,
the world of objects is the origin of knowledge (therefore is true by
definition); in the new empiricism of Nietzsche, Avenarius, and Mach, the
world of objects is the end-product of a perceptive and conceptual
processing (asserting something to be true).
2.3. Nietzsche‟s Positions in the Context of his Peers
We notice that Nietzsche positions (3), (4), (5), and (6) in GD resemble
positions discussed by a number of predecessors and contemporaries such
as Kant, Schopenhauer, Drossbach, Comte, Helmholtz, Du BoisReymond, Teichmüller, Lange, Spir, Avenarius, and Mach.
The Kantian position (3), with its often-criticized „thing-in-itself,‟
finds a variation during 19th century thinking, for example when
Schopenhauer and later Drossbach reinterpret the „thing-in-itself‟ into a
„force-in-itself.‟ Already in his early essay, On the Fourfold Root,16
Schopenhauer suggests as „ground‟ for all becoming, matter and force. To
15
16
We recall that Schopenhauer anticipated Nietzsche when already in the
Fourfold he talked about the “intellectual character of perception.” He already
then distinguished between „raw sense data‟ and „perceptive reason.‟ Cf.
Schopenhauer: Fourfold, loc. cit. p. 58.
Schopenhauer: On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. See
also Schopenhauer: On the Will in Nature. (London: George Bell, 1889).
10
Schopenhauer, we experience change because cause-effect relations
repeat themselves in a never-ending succession of causes changing into
effects, as these effects become causes for new effects, etc., which
indicates that our world is in a constant state of becoming. However,
Schopenhauer believes there must be a foundation for his „world of
becoming,‟ and argues that „change‟ must presuppose two affairs that
precondition change, but themselves do not change, matter and force.
Still, as an indeterminable „something,‟ both matter and force are an
„enigmatic x,‟ and as such in the position of the „thing-in-itself.‟ This idea
of a force preconditioning cause-effect relations is by Drossbach
developed into a radical force-metaphysics in work, which Nietzsche had
read.17 Drossbach‟s point of departure is the usual critique of the „thingin-itself,‟ which he like several neo-Kantians is criticizing as knowable
objectivity. If according to this critique we do not perceive bodies and
matter, it becomes an open question what we then perceive18 In resolving
this pertinent question, Drossbach regresses to an extreme forcemetaphysics, which is far removed from the empiricist, sensualist,
phenomenalist, and positivist agendas of several of his contemporaries,
including Nietzsche. To Drossbach, we only perceive what „acts‟ on us
and since neither things (which are passive) nor appearances (which are
effects of something that acts, therefore also passive) „act‟ on us, we are
left with the alleged effect „forces‟ have on us (his examples indicate that
he takes for granted that he may apply the sense of „pressure‟ in tactile
perception to all kinds of perception). He can therefore conclude that only
forces are epistemologically „real,‟ that only forces are „really
perceived.‟19
It is well-known that Nietzsche on several occasions dismisses this
idea of „acting forces‟ (whether this dismissal is his critical response to
Schopenhauer or Drossbach). To Nietzsche, a „force‟ acting on an
appearance re-applies his often criticized doer-deed metaphysics, the
notion of the „doer‟ conditioning and determining the „deed.‟ Drossbach‟s
„force‟ becomes such an undifferentiated, unconditioned, and unknown
„doer.‟ It can only constitute a metaphysical principle contrary to that
17
18
19
I am here referring to two works by Drossbach, Über die Objecte der Sinlichen
Wahrnehmung. Halle, C. E. M. Pfeffer, 1865, and Über die scheinbaren und
die wirklichen Ursachen des Geschehens in der Welt. Halle: C. E. M. Pfeffer,
1884.
Drossbach: Über die Objecte, op. cit., 6-7.
Drossbach: Über die Objecte, op. cit., 11
11
unique experience and observation of world in the radical empiricism that
was more attractive to Nietzsche.20 A force in itself we cannot perceive.21
Nietzsche‟s position (4), that we cannot and will never know the
physical world as a thing-in-itself, but only as an apparent world for-us,
repeats the „ignorabimus-argument‟ in Du Bois-Reymond, who had
concluded that not only are we ignorant (ignoramus) about matter and
force, but we must also accept that we can never hope to understand, that
we will stay forever ignorant about them (ignorabimus).22 Given our
ignorance, we are condemned to stay within the realm of the knowable,
i.e., the appearing. A. Comte too had admonished us to, “give up the
search after the origin and hidden causes.”23 And Nietzsche important
source of influence, F. Lange, repeating the same insight, gives the advice
that we as consequence should give up all search for the inaccessible
„thing‟ (corresponding to Nietzsche‟s position (5)): “Who says that we are
to occupy ourselves at all with the inconceivable „things-in-themselves‟? [
. . . ] Do not the [natural sciences] accomplish what they accomplish,
quite independently of the ideas as to the ultimate grounds of all nature? 24
Several scientists of the nineteenth century, such as H. C. Ørsted and
M. Faraday, adopt this economical principle of knowledge in their
research into electromagnetism, as they realize they no longer need a
speculative explanation of nature. The power or force of magnetism is
accepted as an unknown, a thing-in-itself, and therefore utterly irrelevant.
To ruminate over the nature of forces „inside‟ the magnet is a sterile
enterprise, worthy only of „philosophers.‟25
Discussing the view, Lange‟s “corrected Kantianism” becomes, in his
own succinct expression, “a materialism of the phenomenon”26 – neither
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
M. Riccardi is of an opposite opinion: “Despite several fundamental
differences, both [Nietzsche and Drossbach] defend the view that reality is
ultimately constituted by force or power centres.” Riccardi, M.: “Nietzsche‟s
Sensualism” in European Journal of Philosophy (Blackwell, 2011), p. 233.
Avenarius repeats the same idea: “Not even the most precise observation of
moving things makes us perceive the force.” Avenarius, R.: Philosophie als
Denken der Welt Gemäss dem Princip des kleinsten Kraftmasses. Leipzig,
Fues‟s Verlag, 1876; p. 45.
Du Bois-Reymond, E.: Über die Grenzen des Naturerkennens. 1872. Hamburg,
Tredition Classics, Reprint; p. 43.
Comte, A.: op. cit. p. 2
Lange, Fr. A.: History of Materialism, 2nd Book, 1st section, p. 200.
Cf. Lange, History of Materialism, 2nd Book, 2nd Section, p. 163.
Cf. G. Stack: “With this conception of a materiale Idealismus Lange, before the
phenomenologists, and independent of them, was seeking a mediation between
materialism and idealism, a “third way.” [ . . . ] I believe that [Nietzsche]
absorbs and reflects the materio-idealism or idealo-materialism that Lange
12
„metaphysical realism‟ nor „idealism,‟ but a theoretical creed
foreshadowing Nietzsche‟s position (6) and his notion of a phenomenal
Relations Welt, reminiscent of the explicit phenomenalism of Avenarius
and Mach.
3. Perspectivism, Phenomenalism, Relativism
Perspectivism is phenomenalism. The insight emerges as a logical
consequence of the criticism of the „thing-in-itself‟ insofar as a „no‟ to the
„thing-in-itself‟ is a „no‟ to a depth-dimension for Truth and a „yes‟ to
horizontal surfaces of relationships. „Perspectivism‟ implies that (1)
knowledge emerges from a selection of relations, determined (2)
according to survival and advancement interests of a particular
biological species. Since „relationships‟ replace „substances,‟
perspectivism is relativism.
3.1. Nietzsche in the Phenomenalist tradition
H. Kleinpeter, O. Ewald, P. Frank, R. von Mises, and other Machean
philosophers of science saw Nietzsche as a member of their group of
phenomenalist, positivist, and pragmatic thinkers.27 Especially Kleinpeter
was explicitly regarding Nietzsche as a representative for the new
phenomenalist-positivist movement with its strong adherence to
evolutionary biology:
First of all, Nietzsche‟s theory of knowledge [Erkenntnislehre] is thoroughly
biological. Everywhere do we feel the formative influence of Darwin, even in the
details. Strongest revealed in Nietzsche is however the opposition to the Absolute;
he is perhaps the most radical representative for relativism in the theory of
knowledge [er ist vielleicht der radikalste Vertreter des Relativismus in der
Erkenntnistheorie]. [ . . . ] Pragmatism is entirely part of Nietzsche. The truth of
the categories, logic, he views in their use for advancing our insight and our
actions, in the last analysis to advance the organism. 28
27
28
sketches.” Stack, G. J.: Lange and Nietzsche. Berlin, New York (Walter de
Gruyter), 1983, p. 97.
Recently, this relation between Nietzsche and phenomenalists like Mach and
Kleinpeter has been noticed also by P. Gori: “Nietzsche as Phenomenalist?” in
Heit, et al: Nietzsches Wissenschaftsphilosophie, Berling/New York, Walter de
Gruyter, 2011; & Gori: “The Usefulness of Substances. Knowledge, Science
and Metaphysics in Nietzsche and Mach.” In Nietzsche-Studien 38, Berlin/New
York, Walter de Gruyter, 2009.
Kleinpeter, Hans: Letter to Ernst Mach, 22.12.1911; in Nietzsche Studien bd. 40
(Berlin/New York, de Gruyter, 2012; ed. Pietro Gori); p. 295.
13
Nietzsche‟s contribution to the theory of knowledge is not limited to this
reformulation of the Kantian teaching. He would also be the creator of a new
positive theory of knowledge based on biology. Darwin would be the great guiding
star for his life and work. [ . . . ] Nietzsche is no longer a mere precursor for
phenomenalism, but is himself effectively its most important representative.29
With his [Nietzsche‟s] penetrating truth-critical spirit, he realized the impracticality
of the current ideal of knowledge; truth is un-knowable: o n l y t h r o u g h t h e
glasses of our concepts is it possible for us to see
t r u t h . Appearance is a necessity; it arises as a result of the nature of our
knowledge. In this sense, all knowledge is relative; an absolute unconditional truth
is not only unreachable but also unthinkable and logically impossible. Nietzsche
destroys Kant‟s a priori and transforms his teaching into relativism. 30
P. Frank too sees Nietzsche‟s thinking as echoing Mach‟s, and regards
them even as representatives of the enlightenment project:
Nietzsche is the other great enlightenment philosopher of the end of the nineteenth
century. The harmony of his epistemological views with those of Mach, who had
gone through an entirely different course of instruction and possessed an entirely
different temperament and entirely different ethical ideals, seems to me to be
evidence for the fact that such view must have penetrated to the enlightened minds
of that time. [ . . . ] I am strengthened by the striking agreement of his [Mach]
views with [ . . . ] Friedrich Nietzsche. [ . . . ] The more one delves into the
posthumous works of Nietzsche, the more clearly one observes the agreement,
particularly in the basic ideas related to the theory of knowledge. 31
Phenomenalist, positivist, and/or pragmatic philosophers of science
like Kleinpeter, Frank, and von Mises are especially impressed by
Nietzsche‟s criticism of the Kantian „thing-in-itself‟ and his emphasis on
a relational sensation-world replacing the old-fashioned „schoolphilosophical‟ belief in a world of substances. In this, they see obvious
parallels to Mach‟s epistemology. In addition, they frequently notice the
shared evolutionary-biological understanding of knowledge in both
Nietzsche and Mach.
29
30
31
Kleinpeter, H.: Der Phenomenalismus: Eine Naturwissenschaftlichen
Weltanschauung. Leipzig, Verlag von J. A. Barth, 1913; p. 27 [my emphasis].
Kleinpeter, H.: Der Phenomenalismus: Eine Naturwissenschaftlichen
Weltanschauung. Leipzig, Verlag von J. A. Barth, 1913, p. 27.
Frank, P.: Between Physics and Philosophy. Cambridge, Harvard University
Press, 1941; p. 51. Frank has several positive references to Nietzsche also in his
The Law of Causality and its Limits (Vienna: Springer Verlag, 1932). R. von
Mises refers to Nietzsche on several occasions in his Positivism: A Study in
Human Understanding (Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1951), and Mach‟s
biographer J. Blackmore comments on this association as well in his: Ernst
Mach: His Work, Life, and Influence. (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1972), p. 123.
14
In the context of current commentary, these are rather surprising and
unconventional assessments. The emphasis on the connection between
Nietzsche and Central European Phenomenalism and Positivism virtually
disappeared in later 20th century receptions and has only recently
resurfaced thanks to a small group of intellectual historians.32
3.2. Teichmüller on the Brink of Introducing Perspectivism
In his Die wirkliche und die scheinbare Welt,33 Teichmüller introduces
a dichotomy between „perspectival perception‟ of an apparent
[scheinbare] world and a non-perspectival real [wirkliche] world – a
discussion, which must have engaged Nietzsche into developing his own
notion on „perspectivism‟ in the later work.34
Teichmüller offers an analysis of perspectivism that reminiscences
Nietzsche and Mach‟s. The precondition is an „apparent‟ world without
32
33
34
We have mentioned N. Hussain, P. Gori, and M. Riccardi. However, T. Brobjer
has been particular thorough in documenting Nietzsche‟s relationship to these
early phenomenalist, positivist, and pragmatic schools of thought at the turn of
the century: “Nietzsche read texts by Ernst Mach in a public reading room in
Zürich in 1884. [ . . . ] Later, probably in 1886 or 1887, Nietzsche bought and
read one of Mach‟s most important works, Beiträge zur Analyse der
Empfindungen. [ . . . ] We know that he read it, for two pages contain
annotations. Brobjer, Nietzsche‟s Philosophical Context, op. cit., p. 94. Brobjer
also notices that the connection between Nietzsche and Positivism has been
neglected: “Nietzsche‟s relation to critical positivism (empirio-criticism) has
received no attention at all by historians of philosophy in spite of the fact that
he had read books by the two founders of critical positivism, Richard Avenarius
and Ernst Mach (although he never mentions or discusses any of them
explicitly). [ . . . ] There has been almost no awareness and discussion of
Nietzsche‟s reading of three of the most significant contemporary philosophers
of science: Emil Du Bois-Reymond (1818–96), Richard Avenarius (1843–96),
and Ernst Mach (1838–1916).” Brobjer, ibid., pp. 17-18 & 91-92. Brobjer
correctly points out that seeing Nietzsche in relation to these early positivists
“can help us to understand his often paradoxical statements regarding
positivism, empiricism, truth, and science.” Brobjer, ibid., 17-18. Also R. Small
and G. Moore have contributed to illuminate various aspect of this inheritance.
Finally, we may recall that already Danto saw a connection between Nietzsche
and the positivist/pragmatic movements; cf. Danto: Nietzsche as Philosopher,
op. cit., p. 65.
Teichmüller, G.: Die wirkliche und die scheinbare Welt: neue Grundlegung der
Metaphysik. Breslau, Verlag von W. Keobner, 1882.
We know from Brobjer that Nietzsche re-read Teichmüller‟s work in the mideighties: “During the autumn of 1885, [Nietzsche] reread Teichmüller‟s Die
wirkliche und die scheinbare Welt [ . . . ] for a second time [ . . . ] very
attentively, writing down arguments and quotations, with page references.”
Brobjer: Nietzsche‟s Philosophical Context, op. cit., p. 97.
15
unity, stability, and permanence, fluctuating in time and space. Contrary
to Nietzsche, however, Teichmüller sets about to think a principle beyond
that fluctuating unstable surface, a principle that can bring unity and
permanence to our appearing perceptions. His theoretical point of
departure is the phenomenal perspectivism, but his theoretical purpose is
to restore unity in the perspectival world. This he does, not by reasserting
a thing-in-itself as objectivity, but by deducing a unifying „I see‟ in or
behind all perspectival seeing. We look at the appearing surface as in a
mirror, seeing ourselves in the mirror as appearing surface as well, but we
“completely forget” the “real I” seeing that appearing surface. Therefore
Teichmüller concludes: “We see then that it is our I [Ich], our substantial
being [sein], our best-known, most certain and in-alienable being, whose
image we see reflected in the mirroring of objects. Therefore, there is [es
giebt] no other source for the concept of substance than the I.”35
Much of the conceptual material in the passage is adopted by
Nietzsche (e.g., the concept of substance deriving from the „I‟), but given
different value. Most importantly, Nietzsche has no desire to establish a
seeing self that is self-identical, simple, unifying, and substantial, but sees
rather the self as another aspect of the fragmented perspectival world.
Mach concurs, even did an effort to illustrate the idea in a sketch where
we see the torso, waist, legs of the artist lying on a couch, but – since he is
drawing himself – not his face. Consequently, in Mach as in Nietzsche,
the „I see‟ is always and necessarily missing and shall never „appear‟ to us
except when we fortuitously add a mirror; i.e., add the appearance of
ourselves revealing the „I see‟ as appearance.
3.3. The Relations-Welt
In aphorism 354 from FW, Nietzsche addresses several issues such as
language, communication, consciousness, and thinking. He concludes the
aphorism by explicitly labeling his epistemological position,
“phenomenalism and perspectivism”:
At bottom, all our actions are incomparably and utterly personal, unique, and
boundlessly individual, there is no doubt; but as soon as we translate them into
consciousness, they no longer seem to be. – This is the true phenomenalism and
perspectivism,
as I understand it [ Diess ist der eigentliche
Phänomenalismus und P e r s p e k t i v i s m u s , wie ich ihn verstehe]: The nature
of a n i m a l c o n s c i o u s n e s s entails that the world of which we can become
conscious is merely a surface- and sign-world [Oberflächen- und Zeichenwelt], a
generalized and degraded world where everything that becomes conscious becomes
shallow, thin, relatively stupid, general, a sign, a herd-mark; everything becoming
35
Teichmüller, op. cit., p. 347
16
conscious involves a vast and thorough corruption, falsification, superficialization,
and generalization. [ . . . ] We simply have no organ for k n o w i n g , for „truth‟:
we „know‟ (or believe or imagine we do) exactly as much as is u s e f u l to the
human herd, to the species. (FW 354, KSA 3, p. 593)
We notice that „perspectivism‟ and „phenomenalism‟ are used
synonymously as concepts for the one and same position, supporting my
argument that perspectivism is phenomenalism. We notice as well that
Nietzsche‟s „perspective‟ is species-specific, implying that it is as Homo
Sapiens we construct the world according to our perspective in contrast to
all the possible perspectives of other species and the impossible
perspective of an omniscient all-seeing nobody. This species-specific
perspectival world is explicitly understood as a relationship-world, seen
differently from species to species.
The world, apart from our condition of living in it, the world that we have not
reduced to our being, our logic, and psychological prejudices does n o t exist as a
world „in-itself‟ it is essentially a world of relationships [Relations-Welt]: it has,
under certain conditions, a d i f f e r e n t l o o k [Gesicht] from each and every
point [Punkt]; its being [Sein] is essentially different in every point; it presses upon
every point, every point resists it. [ . . . ] Our particular case is interesting enough:
we have produced a conception in order to be able to live in a world, in order to
perceive just enough to e n d u r e i t . (NF 1888, KSA 13, 14[93]).
Repeating for emphasis: The world does not exist as a world „in-itself‟
it is essentially a world of relationships [Relations-Welt]. Thus, the objectworld is transformed into a world of relationships, where a „point‟ is here
the abstract idea of a location from where something has a relation to
something else. There is thus no absolute location – i.e., no absolute „eye‟
seeing and no absolute „cause‟ effecting. We cannot imagine a point
except as an intersection in the net. Take away the „net,‟ and we will in
vain try to locate the „point.‟ As little as Mach‟s elements exist alone,
Nietzsche‟s „points‟ do.
This Nietzschean Relations-welt is objectively relative; it is not
subjectively relativized or becoming relative because we as individuals
walk around and look at pre-given objects from different angles, or voice
our different opinions on different objects or issues.36 As such,
Nietzschean/Machean Relativism is not a disguised Subjectivism. It is
rather the other way around: instead of the world being objective in-itself
36
It is objective as is Einstein‟s theory of relativity (inspired from Mach). Like in
Einstein movement and velocity of bodies is relative because there is no
absolute rest that the velocity of moving bodies can be measured against. Still,
the theory of relativity does not abandon the relative universe to subjective
interpretation.
17
with us relativizing this in-itself, the world is in-itself relative, while we
objectify this relative world out of biological-cognitive necessity and
thanks to our abstracting intelligence. We create unity out of the
fragmentary, and this is our species-specific „falsification‟ of (our socalled „lie‟ about) the world, which is understood originally as presenting
itself as sensation (e.g.: “Die Sensationen sind die letzte Realität.” (NF
1888, KSA 13, 11[332]; see also KSA 13, 14[93]). There is no the world,
there is only our world, given to us from our biological species-specific
perspective (cf.: we are “adapted to a perspectival way of seeing [ . . . ] as
creatures of our species must in order to preserve their existence.” (NF
1886, KSA 12, 6[23])).37
4. The Status of the Object in Perspectival Epistemology
The Object does not disappear in Perspectival Epistemology, but is
explained as constructed from a string of Physical, Physiological, and
Psychological impressions woven together to form what is called „object.‟
An empirical world of relations of elements is after-reconstructed as a
world of objects, but under „precise analysis,‟ there is no radical
distinction between the three domains, the physical, the physiological,
and the psychological (formalized in Mach as strings of letters).
According to this „string-theory‟ of elements, the distinction between
object and subject collapses and we can no longer precisely determine
what is objective and what subjective. Consequently, we can also not
clearly determine essential objectivity.
4.1. Elements are Qualities
In the notion „element,‟ Mach is introducing a neutral entity that may
apply equally to the three traditional centers of knowledge, the physical,
the physiological, and the psychological.
In his notion of elements, Mach was undoubtedly informed by one of
his important sources of influence, G. Th. Fechner.38 Fechner had in a
number of experiments demonstrated that „raw‟ stimuli had to be
37
38
This Darwinism in Nietzsche‟s thinking has been discussed by a number of
commentators; so Stegmaier, W.: “Darwin, Darwinismus, Nietzsche. Zum
Problem der Evolution,” in Nietzsche Studien 16. Berlin, New York (Walter de
Gruyter), 1987; and Richardson, J.: Nietzsche‟s New Darwinism. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2004.
See Fechner, G. Th.: Elements of Psychophysics. New York/Chicago (Holt,
Rinehart and Winston), 1966. Translated by H. Adler.
18
increased in intensity before they were noticed. He concluded that “it can
be shown that every stimulus [ . . . ] must already have reached a certain
finite magnitude before it can be noticed at all – that is, before our
consciousness is aroused by a sensation.”39 This implied that there was a
“threshold” below which the subject did not sense and register stimuli, but
remained unconscious about them. When stimuli became conscious, it
happened in qualitative jumps from a zero-sensation response to a
sensation-response. At a seemingly arbitrary point, the mind was affected
and it started to become aware.
Accordingly, we may see a Machean element as a sensation of which
the mind has become aware. In a qualitative jump, an anonymous sensedata has become a conscious sensational element. An element cannot be a
sensation of which we are not aware. Nietzsche concurs in this
understanding, when he writes,
Qualities are our insurmountable barriers. [ . . . ] All our feelings of value (i.e., all
our feelings) adhere to qualities, that is, to the perspectival „truths‟ that are ours
and nothing more than ours, that simply cannot be „known.‟ [ . . . ] Qualities are
our real human idiosyncrasy: wanting our human interpretations and values to be
universal [ . . . ] is one of the hereditary insanities of human pride, which still has
its safest seat in religion. (NF, KSA 12, 1886-87, 6[14]).
In the passage, qualities are our “real human idiosyncrasy,” imposed
on the world by us as one of our “hereditary insanities of human pride.”
That „idiosyncrasy‟ is perspectivism in the most rudimentary Nietzschean
sense. The qualitative world is our world, a world invested with feelings
and values. As humans, we cannot sense quantities, but only qualities,
which are the limits or “barriers” within which we „construct‟ our world
(this position reaches back to the discussion of „forces,‟ which we also
cannot sense). Within these barriers, we formalize, schematize, and
quantify our experiences as an after-reconstruction or secondary
elaboration.
„Knowledge‟
is
this
ordering,
schematization,
conceptualization, organization, and interpretation of the world. It only
manifests a „truth‟ that is our own, thus a perspectival rather than
universal truth. Nietzsche seems to find this point self-evident, when he
continues the passage by insisting, “Need I add, conversely, that
quantities „in themselves‟ do not occur in experience, that our world of
experience is only a qualitative world.” (NF, 1886-87, KSA 12, 6[14]).
39
Fechner, op. cit., p. 199.
19
4.2. On the Constitution of Objectivity
Qualities are the nether limit in Nietzsche, while elements are the
nether limit in Mach. Mach tries to organize these elements, although they
have in principle the same epistemological weight. He suggests three sets
of elements as corresponding to the physical, physiological, and
psychological, and formalizes these three sets respectively: (1) A B C . . .
(complexes consisting of outside, physical, spatio-temporal, objects), (2)
K L M . . . (complexes of bodily sensations, and related objects), and „3‟ α
. . . (complexes of imagination, memory-images, etc.).40
If we accept this new notational system, we can say that our perception
of an object (or of something we spontaneously construct as an object) is
the coming-together of a string of elements, say A C L M
. . . , in such
a way that the string (A C L M
. . . ) is the object.
In this anti-Aristotelian epistemology, an „object‟ is an appearances
constructed as a string of elements. We will represent to ourselves the
object as a body. However, under “precise analysis,” there is no
determinable body in the Nietzsche-Machean Relations-Welt. Under
precise analysis, we are presented with certain elements standing in
relations to each other and to the perceiving subject. Only the relations
remain permanent, while the properties are in constant flux and change. In
Nietzsche‟s vocabulary, it is as such we live in a world of constant
becoming. This view does not argue idealistically that the appearing
object is our idea, our fantasy, or our hallucination. It rather argues that
the object is not determinable. I can walk around a disk, view it from
different angles, in different light, feel its texture, or in frustration, like
honorable Dr. Johnson, give it a good kick to prove its existence, but I
remain lost in these and multiple other sensations. They all prove me right
that there is a disk-object, but I remain unable to articulate this object as
the promised body that can be subtracted from its aspects or properties
that I perceive/receive in a perspectival world.
Let us exemplify the thinking. A pain-sensation impresses itself from
the „outside‟ while being interpreted from the „inside‟ as „pain,‟ and as
„this pain‟ (recognized in memory). In Mach‟s formulaic language we
may now explain „pain‟ as follows: something, say a needle, (element40
Mach: On the Analysis of Sensations, op. cit., p. 9. I will not here go into a
detailed description of Mach‟s formulaic language. Discussions may found in
in Mises, R. von: Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding op. cit.; in
Sommer, M.: Husserl und der Frühe Positivismus. Frankfurt a/M, Vittoria
Klostermann, 1985; and recently, in P. Gori: The Usefulness of Substances, loc.
cit., p. 120.
20
group A B C . . . ) touches the skin (element-group K L M . . . ) and is felt
as pain (element-group K L M . . .), but as this characterized, recognized,
and remembered pain (element-group α
. . .), which is partly
recognized by perceiving that which touches the skin (element-group A B
C . . . ), remembering one‟s fear of needles (elements group α
. . .),
hereby augmenting the pain-sensation (element-group K L M . . .). Where
exactly (“under precise analysis”) is the cause of pain located in these
element-groups? The outside helps defining „pain‟ as much as the inside.
„Pain‟ is A, K, and α; remove one, and there is no pain!
It is not clearly determinable whether „pain‟ belongs to the outside, the
inside, or that in-between we call the skin. If we extrapolate on the
example and apply it to visual perception, I ask the same question and get
the same answer: does an impression belong to the outside, as object; to
the inside as recognized/remembered image in our visual cortex, or to that
in-between we call the retina? For sure, I can repeat the argument:
„perception‟ is A, K, and α; remove one, and there is no perception.
In Mach as in Nietzsche the psyche is rather than a camera a filter
where the filtration screens material and removes superfluities that are
unnecessary or irrelevant to the psychical apparatus. Both of the writers
have a biological-evolutionary explanation of this filtration and
abbreviation process: the „subject‟ must reduce its perceptions to what it
needs and maybe wants to see. It removes impressions unnecessary for
the immediate interest in the strength, growth, or perseverance of its own
organism.
4.3. The Perspectival World of Claude Monet
It is helpful for our understanding of the phenomenal epistemology of
Nietzsche and Mach to contemplate the painting of Claude Monet,
especially his „series‟ of motives painted at different seasons or different
times of day, under different light conditions, or from slightly different
angles. His haystacks, his water lilies, or his Cathedrals of Rouen are
excellent illustrations of a Nietzschean-Machean phenomenalism. His
series of a few dozen paintings of the Cathedral of Rouen, seen at
different times of the day and in different light, shows us a destabilized
cathedral broken up into „sensation-elements.‟ Here we are presented to a
world that is clearly neither a Cartesian substance nor a Berkelean idea,
but a complex of sensations, which antedates our mental construction of
the physical-material cathedral as object. In Claude Monet‟s world, there
is no „thing-in-itself‟ and no „true‟ substance or body, but a world broken
up in a flicker of impressions. It is characteristic in impressionist painting
21
that the outline of the object is replaced with brush-stokes of color. The
clearly delineated „solid‟ object disappears and is replaced with strokes
and points. This technique may occur to us as the painter‟s best analogy
on how we cognitively „construct‟ an object.
If Monet had painted only one cathedral, he would already have made
his point; by painting a series of 28, he demonstrated with great ingenuity
how the „permanent object‟ is broken up in an infinite series of flickers of
impressions of the same. This insistence on repeating the same also shows
us that repetition of the same is never repetition of the self-same, but
rather an eternal repetition of variations of the same. Monet‟s serial
paintings give us, with Nietzsche‟s phrase, a “new infinite,” cf. FW 374,
KSA 3. The surface is inexhaustible.
5. Economy, Simplification, and Biology
The condition of the possibility of the formation of knowledge is the
ability to abbreviate and simplify a multitude of experiences into a
minimal sign-world. The principles of least force (in Avenarius), thoughteconomy (in Mach) and simplification (in Nietzsche) are addressing this
cognitive economy characteristic of the human species.
When Kleinpeter in his letter to Mach summarizes the similarities
between Mach and Nietzsche, he is somewhat at a loss to find in
Nietzsche a parallel to Mach‟s principle of Denkökonomie: “The principle
of thought-economy [Der Princip der Denkökonomie] I have only
occasionally found in Nietzsche.”41 As perceptive as he is, it seems odd
that Kleinpeter overlooks this parallel, since Nietzsche‟s discussions of
cognitive-linguistic processes as simplifying, abbreviating, and
facilitating is the obvious introduction of an economy, and specifically
(insofar as we talk about concepts) a thought-economy.
This is an important issue deserving much more consideration than I
am able to give it here, and which I will continue elsewhere. Here I only
demonstrate Denkökonomie by offering the briefest of outlines, which
again suggests the fundamental correspondences between Nietzsche,
Avenarius, and Mach.
If Nietzsche on numerous occasions describe our perceptive-cognitive
apparatus as an “Abstraktions- und Simplifikations-apparat” (NF, KSA
41
Kleinpeter, H.: Letter to Mach, op. cit., p. 296.
22
11, 26[61]),42 Avenarius introduces this simplification in his principle of
the kleinsten Kraftmasses and Mach in his principle of Denkökonomie.
Avenarius states that “the effort, to think a totality of objects according to
the greatest economy of force, i.e., under the general concept, and with
this make possible a concept for all individual things, is philosophy.” 43 In
Science of Mechanics, Mach explains the principle as follows: “[Given]
man‟s limited powers of memory, any stock of knowledge worthy of the
name is unattainable except by the greatest mental economy. Science
itself, therefore, may be regarded as consisting of the most complete
presentation possible of facts with the least possible expenditure of
thought.”44
List of Literature
Abel, G.: “Bewußtsein – Sprache – Natur. Nietzsches Philosophie des
Geistes,” in Nietzsche-Studien, Band 30. (Berlin/New York:
Walter de Gruyter, 2001)
Abel, G.: “Die Aktualität der Wissenschaftphilosophie Nietzsches” in
Heit, et al: Nietzsches Wissenschaftsphilosophie, loc. cit.
Abel, G.: “Wahrheit und Interpretation”, www.nietzschesource.org/gabel,
2003.
Abel, G.: Interpretationswelten: Gegenwartsphilosophie Jenseits von
Essentialismus and Relativismus. Frankfurt, Suhkamp Verlag,
1995.
Abel, G.: Nietzsche: Die Dynamik des Willen zur Macht und die Ewige
Wiederkehr. Berlin/New York (Walter de Gruyter), 1998.
Abel, G.: Zeichen der Wirklichkeit. Frankfurt, Suhrkamp Verlag, 2004.
Addis, L.: Nietzsche‟s Ontology. Munchen, Walter de Gruyter, 2013.
42
43
44
It is a theme often addressed by W. Stegmaier, Cf. Stegmaier, W.: “Nietzsche‟s
Doctrines, Nietzsche‟s Signs.” The Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Vol. 31, 2006,
p. 24; and Nietzsches „Genealogie der Moral.‟ Darmstadt (Wissenschaftlische
Buchgesellschaft), 1994, p. 134; and “Weltabkürzungskunst. Orientierung
durch Zeichen” (in Simon, Josef (ed.): Zeichen und Interpretation. Berlin,
Surhkamp Verlag, 1994) and Nietzsches Befreiung der Philosophie:
Kontextuelle Interpretation des V. Buchs der „Fröhlichen Wissenschaft.‟
Berlin/New York, De Gruyter, 2012.
Avenarius, R.: Philosophie als Denken der Welt Gemäss dem Princip des
kleinsten Kraftmasses. Leipzig, Fues‟s Verlag, 1876; p. 43
Mach: Science of Mechanics, op. cit., p. 490.
23
Anderson, R. L.: “Overcoming Charity: The Case of Clark‟s Nietzsche on
Truth and Philosophy.” In Nietzsche-Studien, vol. 25, 1996.
Anderson, R. L.: “Truth and Objectivity in Perspectivism.” In Synthese
115, 1-32, 1998. Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998.
Aristotle: Metaphysics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by R.
McKeon. New York (Random House), 1941.
Avenarius, R.: Philosophie als Denken der Welt gemäss dem Princip de
kleinsten Krafmasses. Leipzig, Fues‟s Verlag, 1876.
Babich, B. (ed.): Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science:
Nietzsche and the Sciences II, Kluwer Academic Publishers,
1999.
Blackmore, J.: Ernst Mach: His Work. Life, and Influence. (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1972
Bornedal, P.: “On the Institution of the Moral Subject: On the
Commander and the Commanded in Nietzsche‟s Discussion of
Law.” In Kriterion, Nietzsche and the Kantian Tradition. Brazil,
Minas Gerais, 2014.
Bornedal, P.: The Surface and the Abyss: Nietzsche‟s Philosophy of Mind
and Knowledge. Berlin/New York, Walter de Gruyter, 2010.
Breazeale, D. (ed.): Philosophy and Truth: Selections from Nietzsche‟s
Notebooks of the Early 1870‟s. Amherst (Humanity Books),
1999.
Brobjer, T.: “Nietzsche‟s Last View of Science.” In Heit et al: Nietzsches
Wissenschaftsphilosophie, loc. cit.
Brobjer, T.: “Nietzsche‟s Reading and Knowledge of Natural Science: An
Overview” in Moore/Brobjer: Nietzsche and Science, (loc. cit.).
Brobjer, T.: Nietzsche's Philosophical Context: An Intellectual Biography.
The University of Illinois Press, 2008
Clark, M. & Dudrick, D.: “Nietzsche‟s Post-Positivism” in The European
Journal of Philosophy, Blackwell, 2004.
Clark, M.: Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy. Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1991.
Cox, C.: Nietzsche: Naturalism and Interpretation. Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1999.
Danto, A. C.: Nietzsche as Philosopher. New York, Columbia University
Press, 2005.
Darwin, C.: The Origin of Species. New York: Signet Classics, 2003
Descartes, R.: Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical
Writings of Descartes, vol. II. Translated by J. Cottingham et al.
Cambridge: (Cambridge University Press), 1984.
24
Doyle, T.: Nietzsche on Epistemology and Metaphysics. Edinburgh
(Edinburgh University Press) 2009
Drossbach, M.: Über die Objecte der Sinlichen Wahrnehmung. Halle, C.
E. M. Pfeffer, 1865.
Drossbach, M.: Über die scheinbaren und die wirklichen Ursachen des
Geschehens in der Welt. Halle: C. E. M. Pfeffer, 1884.
Du Bois-Reymond, E.: “Über die Grenzen des Naturerkennens.” 1872; in:
Wollgast, S. (ed.): Vorträge über Philosophie und Gesellschaft.
Hamburg 1974.
Ewald, O.: Richard Avenarius als Begründer des Emiriokritizismus.
Berlin, Ernst Hofmann & Co., 1905.
Fechner, G. Th.: Elements of Psychophysics. New York/Chicago (Holt,
Rinehart and Winston), 1966.
Fischer, K.: A Commentary on Kant‟s Critick of the Pure Reason.
(London: Longmans, Green, & Co., 1866).
Frank, P.: Between Physics and Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1941).
Frank, P.: Das Kausalgesetz und Seine Grenzen (Vienna: Julius Springer,
1932).
Frank, P.: Modern Science and Its Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1950),
Gemes, K.: “Janaway of Perspectivism.” European Journal of Philosophy
17:1, pp. 101–112. London, Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2009.
Gori, P.: “Nietzsche as Phenomenalist?” in Heit, et al: Nietzsches
Wissenschaftsphilosophie, loc. cit.
Gori, P.: “The Usefulness of Substances. Knowledge, Science and
Metaphysics in Nietzsche and Mach” (In Nietzsche-Studien 38,
2009)
Hales, S. D. & Welshon, R.: Nietzsche‟s Perspectivism. Urbana and
Chicago (University of Illinois Press), 2000.
Heit, H., Abel, G., & Brusotti, M. (eds.): Nietzsches
Wissenschaftsphilosophie: Hintergründe, Wirkungen und
Aktualität. (Berlin, New York, De Gruyter, 2011)
Helmholtz, H. von: Science and Culture: Popular and Philosophical
Lectures. Edited by D. Cahan. Chicago, The University of
Chicago Press, 1995.
Helmholtz, H. von: Scientific Subjects. London, Longmans, Green, & co.,
1893.
Hussain, N.: “Nietzsche‟s Positivism”. In European Journal of
Philosophy 12:3, 2004, pp. 326–368.
25
Hussain, N.: “Reading Nietzsche through Ernst Mach” in Moore, G, &
Brobjer T. (eds.): Nietzsche and Science. London (Ashgate),
2004
Kant, I.: Kritik der reinen Vernunft I, in WA 3.
Kant, I.: Kritik der reinen Vernunft II, in WA 4.
Kant, I.: Prolegomena zu einer jeden Künftigen Metaphysik, in WA 5.
Kant, I.: Werkausgabe 1-12. Ed.: W. Weischedel. Frankfurt am Main
(Suhrkamp Verlag), 1968.
Kleinpeter, H.: “Letters to Ernst Mach, 1912.” Nietzsche Studien 40
(Berlin/New York, de Gruyter, 2012; ed. Pietro Gori
Kleinpeter, H: Der Phenomenalismus: Eine Naturwissenshcaftliche
Weltanschauung. Leipzig, Verlag J. A. Barth, 1913.
Kofman, S.: Nietzsche and Metaphor. Translated by Duncan Large.
Stanford (Stanford University Press).
Lange, Fr. A.: Geschichte des Materialismus, bd. 2. Iserlohn (Verlag con
J. Daedeker), 1873.
Leiter, B.: “Perspectivism” in Nietzsche‟s Genealogy of Morals,” in
Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality (ed. R. Schacht. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1994)
Leiter, B.: Nietzsche on Morality (London, Routledge, 2002
Lightbody, B.: “Nietzsche, Perspectivism, Anti-realism: An Inconsistent
Triad”; in The European Legacy, Vol. 15/4, pp. 425-438, 2010.
Mach, E.: Knowledge and Error: Sketches on the Psychology of Enquiry.
Translation T. J. McCormack. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing
Company, 1976.
Mach, E.: Popular Scientific Lectures. Translation T. J. McCormack.
Chicago/London (Open Court) 1898.
Mach, E.: Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of its
Development. Translation T. J. McCormack. Chicago/London:
Open Court, 1919.
Mach, E.: The Analysis of Sensations and the Relations of the Physical to
the Psychical. Translation T. J. McCormack. New York: Dover
Publications, 1959.
Mayr, E.: One Long Argument: Charles Darwin and the Genesis of
Modern Evolutionary Thought. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1991.
Mises, R. von: Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding (Cambridge:
Harvard UP, 1951).
Moore, G, & Brobjer T. (eds.): Nietzsche and Science. London (Ashgate),
2004.
26
Moore, G.: Nietzsche, Biology and Metaphor (Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2002.
Müller-Lauter, W.: “On Judging in a World of Becoming” in Babich
(ed.): Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge and Critical Theory, loc.
cit.
Müller-Lauter, W.: Über Freiheit und Chaos: Nietzsche-Interpretationen
II. (Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1999).
Müller-Lauter, W.: Über Werden und Wille zur Macht: Nietzsche
Interpretationen I. Berlin/New York (Walter de Gruyter), 1999.
Nietzsche: [FW] Die fröhliche Wissenschaft, KSA 3.
Nietzsche: [GD] Götzendämmerung, KSA 6.
Nietzsche: [GM] Zur Genealogie der Moral, KSA 5.
Nietzsche: [JGB] Jenseits von Gut und Böse, KSA 5.
Nietzsche: [KSA] Sämtliche Werke Kritische Studienausgabe. G. Colli &
M. Montinari (eds.). Berlin/New York: W. de Gruyter, 1967-77.
Nietzsche: [MA] Menschliches, Allzumenschlisches, KSA 2
Nietzsche: [NF] Nachgelassende Fragmente, 1882-87, KSA 10-13.
Nietzsche: [WL] Über Wahrheit und Lüge in aussermoralischen Sinne,
KSA 1.
Nietzsche: [WM] Der Wille zur Macht. Stuttgart (Kröner Verlag), 1996.
Pippin, R.: Nietzsche, Psychology, and First Philosophy. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 2006.
Poeller, P.: Nietzsche and Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1995.
Riccardi, M.: “Nietzsche‟s Sensualism.” European Journal of Philosophy.
Oxford: Blackwell, 2011.
Richardson, J.: Nietzsche‟s New Darwinism. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2004.
Richardson, J.: Nietzsche‟s System. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1996.
Schacht, R.: “Nietzsche‟s Anti-Scientistic Naturalism” in Heit, et al:
Nietzsches Wissenschaftsphilosophie, loc. cit.
Schacht, R.: “Nietzsche‟s Naturalism” in The Journal of Nietzsche
Studies, vol. 43: no. 2, 2012.
Schacht, R.: Nietzsche. London/New York: Routledge, 1983.
Schopenhauer, A.: On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient
Reason. Translation E. F. J. Payne. La Salle (Open Court), 1974.
Schopenhauer, A.: The World as Will and Representation, vol. I & II.
Translated by E. F. J. Payne. New York (Dover Publications),
1969.
27
Simon, J. (ed.): Zeichen und Interpretation. Frankfurt am Main
(Suhrkamp Verlag), 1994.
Small, R.: Nietzsche in Context. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001.
Sommer, M.: Husserl und der Frühe Positivismus. Frankfurt a/M, Vittoria
Klostermann, 1985.
Spiekermann, K.: Naturwissenschaft als subjektlöse Macht? Nietzsches
Kritik physikalischer Grundkonzepte. Berlin/New York: de
Gruyter, 1992.
Stack, G. J.: Lange and Nietzsche. Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter,
1983.
Stack, G. J.: Nietzsche‟s Anthropic Circle: Man, Science, and Myth. New
York: University of Rochester Press, 2005.
Stegmaier, W.: “Darwin, Darwinismus, Nietzsche. Zum Problem der
Evolution,” in Nietzsche Studien 16. Berlin, New York (Walter
de Gruyter), 1987.
Stegmaier, W.: “Nietzsche‟s Doctrines, Nietzsche‟s Signs.” The Journal
of Nietzsche Studies, vol. 31, 2006.
Stegmaier, W.: “Weltabkürzungskunst. Orientierung durch Zeichen,” in J.
Simon (ed.): Zeichen und Interpretation (loc. cit.)
Stegmaier, W.: Nietzsches „Genealogie der Moral‟. Darmstadt
(Wissenschaftlische Buchgesellschaft), 1994.
Stegmaier, W.: Nietzsches Befreiung der Philosophie: Kontextuelle
Interpretation des V. Buchs der „Fröhlichen Wissenschaft.‟
Berlin/New York, De Gruyter, 2012.