SITING HAZARDOUS FACILITIES: LESSONS FROM LNG
Howard Kunreuther and John W. Lathrop
International Institute for Applied Systems Analysis, Laxenburg, Austria
RR-82-36
November 1982
Reprinted from Risk Analysis , volume 1(4) (1981)
INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS
Laxenburg, Austria
Research Reports, which record research conducted at IIASA, are independently reviewed before
publication. However, the views and opinions they express are not necessarily those of the Institute or
the National Member Organizations that support it.
Reprinted with permission from Risk Analysis 1(4):289-302, 1981.
Copyright© 1981 Society for Risk Analysis.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by
any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage or
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the copyright holder.
iii
FOREWORD
The International Institute for Applied Systems Analysis has undertaken a study of
the use of risk analysis in siting liquefied energy gas facilities in four countries: the Federal
Republic of Germany, the Netherlands, the United Kingdom, and the United States. The
work on which the present paper is based was part of this larger study.
The authors of this paper have devised a descriptive framework for the issues raised
by siting large-scale technological facilities, and have illustrated its concepts by applying
them to an LNG siting process in California. They also suggest ways of using analytical
methods to improve both the interaction process among the interested parties and the
outcome of the siting debate.
Their ideas are in the spirit of the research that IIASA is presently carrying out on
the role of analysts in the policymaking process. Thus, this paper not only contributes to
the Institute's work on the problems of risk but also has somewhat broader implications.
ALECM.LEE
Chairman
Management and Technology Area
Risk Analysis, Vol. I, No. 4, 1981
Siting Hazardous Facilities: Lessons from LNG
Howard Kunreuther 1 and John W. Lathrop1
Received February 9, 1981 - Revised November 30, 1981
This paper develops a descriptive framework for siting large scale technological facilities such
as liquefied natural gas (LNG) terminals, and suggests ways of using analyses to improve the
process. A key feature of these problems is that they involve relatively new technologies where
there has not been a long history with which to construct a statistical data base. Hence the
interested parties will each have different estimates of the probabilities and losses associated
with events that affect the environment or safety of the population. The decision-making
process can be characterized as a sequence of decisions, subject to change over time, which
are influenced b)' exogenous factors and new legislation. Each of the separate decisions
involves an input phase and an interaction phase. The input phase specifies the relevant
alternatives and attributes associated with a particular decision. The interaction phase focuses
on the nature of the conflicts between the different parties in evaluating the alternatives.
Conflicts are often difficult to resolve because each stakeholder in the process has his own
objectives, a limited information base shaped by these objectives and scarce computational
resources. We illustrate the above descriptive framework through a case study of the LNG
siting process in California. The paper then explores possible ways of improving the input
and interaction phases through more structured analyses. Specific attention is given to the
role of decision analysis, the analytic hierarchy process, examining assumptions, and the use
of interactive computer models for scenario generation. The paper concludes by suggesting
future research needs on jesigning policy instruments for helping to reconcile conflicts
between the vying interest parties. Promising areas for more problem-focused research include
the role of insurance and compensation schemes.
KEY WORDS: Siting; decision processes; conflict; use of analysis; low probability events.
reached in the United States. On the basis of this
descriptive model, suggestions are made for improving the process. The paper thus is designed to integrate descriptive aspects with prescriptive recommendations.
Section 2 details the elements of a descriptive
framework for siting large-scale facilities. A key feature of the process is the interaction of interested
parties, each of whom have specific goals and objectives, a limited information base shaped by these
objectives, and scarce computational resources.
Section 3 illustrates the framework with empirical evidence from the LNG siting decision process in
1. INTRODUCTION
Society has become increasingly concerned with
the appropriate procedures for evaluating projects
which promise to yield long-run benefits, but also
create potentially catastrophic consequences. Recent
examples of such problems are the siting of energy
facilities such as nuclear power plants or liquefied
natural gas (LNG) terminals.
This paper has two principal purposes. Utilizing
recent theoretical and empirical contributions to the
literature on choice under uncertainty, it proposes a
descriptive framework as to how such decisions are
289
0272-4332181 / 1200-0289$03.00/1 © 1981 Society for Risk Analysis
290
California which has been studied extensively [see
Ahern,<1> Deutsch,(2) Linnerooth,(3) and Lathrop<4l].
Section 4 indicates how we might improve the current
decision procedures, recognizing that the political
decision-making process is based on a number of
institutional and legal constraints which may be difficult to change. The concluding section suggests
future research needs with respect to developing
policies for reconciling differences between interested
parties in the siting debate.
2. A DESCRIPTIVE FRAMEWORK OF
SOCIETAL DECISION-MAKING PROCESS
2.1 Relevant Concepts
In contrast to most textbook analyses of decision
making under uncertainty, where there is a
well-specified set of probabilities of certain events
occurring and potential gains or losses from them,
the problems discussed in this paper involve more
fundamental uncertainties. For one thing, there has
not been a long history with which to build a statistical data base. The technologies are relatively new and
in many cases past experience provides us with limited
guidance as to the chances of severe accidents occurring. In a similar vein one has to speculate as to
what the losses might be should a particular
catastrophic event occur in a given location. These
two elements of uncertainty represent a challenge for
both risk analysis and decision-making.
On the analysis side there is a need to systematically estimate probabilities and consequences from
both past data and judgmental studies. There is an
extensive literature from controlled laboratory experiments over the past decade which have uncovered a
set of biases and heuristics that individuals utilize in
dealing with low-probability events [Fischhoff, Slovic,
Lichtenstein,C5l Tversky and KahnemanC 6l]. Other
studies have suggested that the context in which a
problem is framed plays a key role in how people
make their decisions [Tversky and Kahneman, (7)
Hershey, Kunreuther, and SchoemakerC 8l]. These
findings, partly due to computational limitations on
the part of individuals, present a challenge to the
analyst who would like to improve the decision-making process.
Kunreuther and Lathrop
An attempt in this direction has been taken by
Fairley( 9l who provides a detailed set of guidelines
for estimating " small" accident probabilities based
on a consideration of catastrophic risk analyses for
LNG marine transportation. His motivation for suggesting systematic analyses is that there is a great
danger that many sources of an accident will otherwise be omitted. In addition, there are numerous
opportunities for bias with respect to judgmental
estimates of accident probabilities when there is not a
long history of past events. Similar reasoning would
apply to the analysis of losses from a given accident,
such as a major breach of an LNG tank.
On the decision-making side , the lack of a detailed data base implies that different interested parties will have different estimates of the probabilities
and the losses that guide their own judgments. We
will look at the process in terms of a scenario involving a number of different decisions, which taken
together resolve a particular problem. Some of the
decisions may be solved in parallel by different parties; others may be dealt with sequentially.
The decentralized and sequential nature of the
process are key concepts which guide the descriptive
framework. March< 10l characterizes this process as
one of limited rationality, whereby individuals and
groups simplify a large problem into smaller pieces
because of the difficulties they have in considering all .
alternatives and all information. Support for these
concepts at the level of governmental, firm, and
consumer decision-making comes from several
quarters. Lindblom< 11 l and Braybrooke and
Lindblom,<12l emphasize the incrementalism in decisions made by bureaucracies where there is a tendency for government agencies to " muddle through"
by making small changes from the status quo rather
than attempting to structure and solve a larger problem. Cyert and March,<13 > in their classic study of the
behavorial theory of the firm, demonstrate empirically that organizations decentralize decisions and
attend to different goals and objectives at different
times. Bettmann< 14l integrates findings from a number
of studies on consumer choice which suggest that
individuals simplify the decision-making process by
decomposing the problem, utilizing limited search
and behaving sequentially with appropriate feedback
loops.
Another important concept, which also relates to
the uncertainty of information on probabilities and
losses, is the importance of exogenous events in in-
Siting Hazardous Facilities
fluencing the decision process. Random events, such
as disasters, play a critical role in triggering specific
actions to "prevent" future crises. The small data
base for judging the frequency of low probability
events, coupled with systematic biases of individuals
in dealing with concepts of chance and uncertainty,
increase the importance of a sali.ent event in the
decision-making process. Tversky and Kahneman< 15l
describe this phenomenon under the heading of availability, whereby one judges the frequency of an event
by the ease with which one can retrieve it from
memory. The importance of past experience in influencing insurance purchase decisions against low
probability events [Kunreuther et ai.< 16)) reflects this
characteristic of human behavior.
March and Olsen< 17l suggest that random events
and their timing play a critical role in many organizational decisions because of the ambiguity of many
situations and the limited attention that can be given
to any particular problem by the interested parties
unless it is perceived as being critical. They provide
empirical evidence to support their theory using empirical studies of organizations in Denmark, Norway,
and the United States.
In a similar spirit Holling< 18l summarizes empirical evidence on how unexpected events played a role
in the institutional response to environmental problems. Studies in five different areas of social or
economic importance reveal that specific events (e.g.,
the destruction of forests by an outbreak of the
spruce budworm) frequently generate surprise and
trigger specific policies designed to cope with the
resulting negative outcomes.
With respect to legislative decision making,
Walker< 19l notes the importance of graphically and
easily understood evidence of trouble as an importance factor in setting the discretionary agenda of the
U.S. Congress or a government agency. He also suggests that the political appeal of dealing with a speci{ic
problem is increased if it has an impact on large
numbers of people. To support these points, Walker
presents empirical evidence on the passage of safety
legislation in the U.S. Numerous examples of this
process are also provided by Lawless< 20J through a
series of case histories of problems involving the
impact of technology on society. He points out that
frequently:
New information of an "alarming" nature is announced and
is given rapid and widespread visibility by means of modem
mass communications media. Almost overnight the case can
291
become a subject of discussion and concern to much of the
populace, and generate strong pressures to evaluate and
remedy the problem as rapidly as possible. (p. 16)
In the case of decisions such as the siting of
facilities, random events such as an LNG fire or oil
spill may be sufficiently graphic and affect enough
poeple to generate surprise and cause a reversal of
earlier decisions, inject other alternatives into the
process and change the relative strength of parties
interested in the decision outcome. The mass media
may play a critical role in focusing on these specific
events and in many cases exaggerating their importance.
2.2 Model Formulation
The concepts discussed above have motivated
the following descriptive framework of the facility
siting process. A scenario consists of a sequence of
decisions {D 1, ... , Dn}, which have to be made by
different interested parties. In focusing on any particular problem, it is necessary to specify what the n
different decisions are that comprise a particular
scenario. For example, Lathrop< 4 l and Linnerootb< 3l
have constructed a detailed flow diagram of the different decision points with respect to the siting of the
LNG terminal in California. Here the process begins
with the Western LNG Terminal Company filing an
application with the Federal Power Commission
(FPC) for terminal facilities. It continues through a
set of interactions between federal, state, and local
governmental agencies, special interest groups, and
the Western LNG Terminal Company. In the case of
nuclear power plant licensing decisions, Jackson and
Kunreuther< 21 J have constructed a scenario which
emphasizes the decentralized nature of decisions by
separate divisions of the Nuclear Regulatory Commission. The performance of a plant under a series of
predetermined accident scenarios is a basis for the
final decision as to whether or not to approve a
power plant.
These two examples suggest that, although one
can look at a particular decision in isolation, it will
be integrated with other actions by being depen<lent
on earlier decisions (e.g., the case of LNG siting) or
by being integrated at a later stage with other decisions which are made independently of it (e.g., the
licensing of nuclear power plants).
Kunreuther and Lathrop
292
Previous Decisions
D 1, ... ... ,Dj - l
EXOGENOUS
FACTORS
INPUT
PHASE
l
.----..&..,
'-.:~
Evaluation of
Attributes and
Alternatives
by Each
Interested Party
INTERACTION
PHASE
Nature of Conflicts
Between Parties
t =t +1
Final Action on Di ? 1-~
NO
YES
Is this the Last
Decision?
NO
j =j + 1
YES
END
Fig. I. Descriptive model of choice for decision D1.
Consider a particular decision, D1 , (e.g., whether
or not an LNG terminal is acceptable with regard to
population risk), which is part of an overall scenario.
Figure l depicts the relevant aspects of the process. 2
At any time period, t, there are a set of exogenous
factors which limit the set of alternatives for consideration. For example, a disaster may trigger specific
legislation which provides restrictions on where a
hazardous facility can be located. For each set of
alternatives there are interested parties who enter the
area. One set of alternatives then can determine the
2
A more structured model for the siting process has since been
developed at IIASA and is discussed in Kunreuther, Lathrop and
Linnerooth (38).
attributes (e.g., number of lives lost from an LNG
fire) which are considered important by at least one
of these parties. In Fig. 1 we refer to the relationship
between these three components as the input phase of
the process. Thus if one changes the composition of
parties as well as the alternatives, one will also change
the relative importance of attributes. For example, if
special interest groups are concerned with a particular site, then the safety factor may be treated as much
more relevant than if these parties do not have an
input into the final decision. Similarly if certain
attributes are specifically introduced into the picture
by one of the interested parties, then this may cause
other groups to play a more active role in the process.
For example, if the federal government suggests the
293
Siting Hazardous Facilities
critical importance of safety factors as part of the
siting decision, then concerned citizens may unite to
prevent their community from being chosen as a site.
Each interested party is likely to have a different
set of attributes that they consider to be important to
the particular problem. Furthermore, there is no
guarantee that two interested parties who focus on
the same attribute will measure it in the same manner.
For example, public interest groups concerned with
the safety of potential sites may have a different
estimate of the number of lives lost from a severe
accident than the gas companies or the consortium
proposing the project. Over time the nature and
importance of these attributes may also change due
to exogenous factors and a new set of alternatives.
When it comes to the interaction phase, stakeholders are likely to evaluate different alternatives by
looking for satisfactory options rather than trying to
find an optimal solution [Cyert and MarcH 13 Jj. For
each decision D1 there may be some level of a particular attribute that is deemed satisfactory, but that level
may differ between interested parties. For example,
public interest groups may specify an acceptable level
of risk to be lower than the gas company proposing
the project. As a result these two interested parties
may have differing views on the acceptability of
alternative sites even if they agree on the chances of
an accident. When such conflicts occur, they may
cause long delays in reaching a final decision because
of the difficulties in resolving conflicts based on value
differences. Eventually they may be resolved through
some form of consensus by the interested parties, by
court rulings or by governmental bodies with specific
legislative powers to settle the controversy. For some
problems no resolution may take place and the status
quo is maintained.
Looking at the interaction phase depicted in Fig.
1, a central component is the nature of the conflicts
between parties. If no final action is taken on a
particular decision during period t because of a failure
to resolve certain conflicts, this is treated schematically as postponing action until the next period. In
period t + 1, a set of exogenous events may occur that
substantially change the situation. The breach of a
storage tank or the discovery of an earthquake fault
may reveal certain features of facilities or sites
which may make them unacceptable. These exogenous events may change the relative importance of
different interested parties and attributes. In addition, the events and the public's reaction to them may
trigger new legislation which deem certain previously
satisfactory alternatives unacceptable and force a
reevaluation of earlier decisions { D 1, ••• , D1 _ 1}.
To summarize, there is a set of decisions which
have to be made over time as part of a scenario for a
particular problem. There are laws and regulations
which guide the acceptability of specific alternatives
and there are different interested parties involved in
the process. Because of the uncertainty regarding the
probability and potential impacts of catastrophic
events, interested parties with different goals and
objectives and with limited computational capacities
may have different estimates of the risks associated
with specific actions (e.g., the siting of an LNG
terminal at a particular location). Furthermore, random events can have a major impact on the decisionmaking process by triggering new legislation which
may change the set of alternatives, relevant stakeholders and attributes for consideration. Conflicts
between these parties can lead to lengthy delays.
3. THE LNG SITING DECISION IN
CALIFORNIA
The above descriptive framework outlined in
Fig. 1 will be illustrated here by analyzing the decision process associated with siting an LNG terminal
in California. This description will reveal implications of the structure of such a process concerning
societal decision making for low probability events.
We will first describe the nature of the problem,
delineate the relevant interested parties and attributes
perceived to be important, comment on the implications of this structure, and then discuss the role of
exogenous events on the decision process.
3.1 Nature of the Problem
Liquefied natural gas (LNG) is a medium for
transporting energy that has the potential, albeit with
very low probability, of creating severe losses. To
transport natural gas over long ocean distances it has
to be converted to liquid form at about -160°C and
1/ 600 the volume. It is then shipped in specially
constructed tankers and received at a terminal where
it undergoes regasification and is then distributed.
The entire system (i.e., the liquefication facility, the
LNG tanker, and the receiving terminal and regasification facility) can cost more than $1 billion to
construct [Office of Technology Assessment< 22l]. The
294
siting problem of interest consists of two principal
decisions : whether the proposed LNG project is in
the best interest of society in terms of its impact
on the future U.S. energy mix (D 1) , and if so, whether
the proposed site is appropriate in terms of meeting
specific safety, environmental and economic criteria
(D2 ). Note that the alternatives for D 1 are whether or
not to have an LNG project, while those for D 2 relate
to proposed terminals at specific sites.
3.2. Interested Parties and Relevant Attributes
There is a set of interested parties associated
with each of the above two decisions. Some of these
parties are specified by law (e.g., government agencies), others play a role because of specific concerns
with the hazard (e.g., public interest groups), and
others because of their economic interest in the project (e.g., gas companies). In the case of D 1, there are
three principal stakeholders, each of whom considers
different attributes as important. The gas company or
the consortium proposing the project considers such
attributes as gas price and capital base as they affect
its financial position, degree of control over the
source, and supply security.
The second party is the Department of Energy
(DOE), which must ascertain whether the project is in
the national interest. 3 Two agencies within the DOE
are involved: the Federal Energy Regulatory Commission (FERC), which rules on site and project suitability, and the Economic Regulatory Administration
(ERA), which evaluates economic aspects of the project and its effects on national energy supply security.
Among the princ~
attributes that these two agencies are supposed to consider are the security of
supply, the proposed LNG price in relation to the
price of alternative supplies, impact of the price
schedule on conservation of energy, and whether the
proposed site meets safety and environmental requirements as stated in any national guidelines.
[DOE/ ERA< 23 >]. The third principal party involved
in D 1 is the California Public Utilities Commission
(CPUC), which has responsibility at the state level
for issues similar to those considered by DOE at the
federal level.
In addition to these three parties, other agencies
set safety standards for all proposed LNG projects.
3
Prior to 1977 this responsibility resided with the Federal Power
Commission (FPC).
Kunreuther and Lathrop
The Office of Pipeline Safety Regulations (OPSR), is
responsible for the landward side of the LNG terminal, while the Coast Guard has jurisdiction over the
marine side of the terminal, including ship movements and the portion of the LNG system that
connects the tanker to the storage system.
The site-specific decision, D 2 , involves some of
the same parties as D 1, as well as additional groups.
The set of relevant attributes are likely to differ from
the ones related to the first decision. For example, the
gas company now focuses on site-specific costs,
accessibility of tankers, and where appropriate landuse and environmental factors [OTA< 22>]. The FERC
examines site suitability with particular attention to
environmental impacts and safety.
Before 1977 the city and county governments
had responsibility for evaluating local impacts of a
project, while at the state level the California Coastal
Commission (CCC) ruled on the impact of a particular site on the environment with special sensitivity to
preservation of coastal natural resources. These
agencies were required to hold public hearings in
which all the parties had a chance to be represented,
including special interest groups and local citizens
groups concerned with safety and environmental impacts. The California LNG Terminal Siting Act of
1977 essentially removed local authority and centralized the state approval authority in the CPUC,
changing the CCC role to determining a ranking of
alternative sites.
3.3. Implications of the Decision Process Structure
The current LNG siting process illustrates two
key features of multiparty societal decision processes.
First, the decision is disaggregated in such a way that
each agency focuses on a subset of all the attributes
in comparing different sites. For example the CCC,
which has a responsibility to preserve the environment, is now given authority to rank the proposed
sites in California. The CPUC, which focuses on
questions of supply reliability, has final authority on
approval of the proposed site. This decision can be
made more or less independently of the CCC rankings. No single agency is now given a mandate to
make trade-offs between environmental and energy
supply concerns in considering the proposed site.
The second feature of multiparty decision
processes illustrated in the California case is the
importance of the structure of that process. Where
295
Siting Hazardous Facilities
there are conflicts of interest between different parties, the most effective power normally lies with the
agency in the position to make the final decision. In
the case of California, a key question considered in
drafting the LNG Terminal Siting Act of 1977 was
whether a conservation-minded group, such as the
CCC, or an agency concerned with energy needs such
as the CPUC, would have final siting authority. Once
the CPUC was chosen, the final decision regarding a
site was constrained in different ways than if the
CCC had been given this authority. The dynamics
and the structure of the process had a critical bearing
on the final decision.
But there are broader implications of the multiparty character of societal decision processes for
low-probability events. Conflicts among parties are to
be expected, since each stakeholder implicitly assigns
different importance weights to the relevant attributes. Yet when one is concerned with low-probability events associated with a new technology (e.g.,
determining the chances and consequences of a severe
accident of an LNG terminal), the analyses
marshalled by the conflicting parties are not based on
statistical analysis and tested assumptions. Instead,
the analyses must rely on subjective probabilities and
choices of assumption sets from a wide range of
defensible scenarios [Lathrop and Linnerootli 24l]. The
net result is that analysis does not play as important
a role in such cases as it might if actuarial data were
available on which to estimate probabilities and losses.
Arguments concerning low-probability events
often involve the concept of acceptable risk. While
the definition of acceptable risk assumes many guises
[Lathrop<25 l], a procedure like the following is often
employed: a detailed risk analysis of a proposed site
specifies the chances of death per year ( p) from
LNG-related accidents to an individual at risk. If pis
below some threshold level, p*, then the project is
considered safe; if p > p* then it is not. For example,
the FERC estimated the values of p for three proposed California LNG terminal sites as ranging from
2 X 10- 7 to 8 X 10- 1 . It pointed out that such risks
are comparable to the risks from natural events such
as lightning, tornadoes, and hurricanes, and concluded: "The staff believes that this level constitutes
an acceptable risk to the public" [FERC<26l]. 4 Yet of
4
Keeney, et al. (39) utilize a particular p* in support of the
acceptability of an LNG terminal in Matagorda Bay, Texas,
They cite a rough criterion for risk acceptability of p = 10 - 1
suggested by Starr (40), and compare it to their estimated p for
the Matagorda Bay terminal of 2· 10- 9 .
course this form of argument does not in itself resolve
safety debates, as the different parties can argue over
what values of both p and p* are appropriate for the
case at hand.
3.4. Role of Exogenous Events
Another implication of the decision process associated with facility siting is that exogenous events
can play an important role in triggering new coalitions and frequently new legislation. Each interested
party focuses on limited information and uses the
data in different ways. Due to the difficulty of resolving stakeholder conflicts, a particular event can cause
a reversal or reinvestigation of a particular decision if
the case has not been finalized . Consider the following four examples associated with LNG siting in the
United States:
1. In 1973 an LNG tank in Staten Island, New
York, exploded and the roof collapsed burying 40
workers. There was no LNG in the tank but it had
seeped through the insulation and caused a huge fire.
A result of this explosion was the increased concern
with the dangers of LNG by Staten Island residents.
The neighborhood organization called BLAST, which
was formed a year before the accident, attracted
considerable attention and interest because of the
media coverage of the tank explosion. In the context
of our descriptive model of choice, a new interested
party played a key role because of a random event.
What may have been a foregone deicison regarding
the location of an LNG tank in Staten Island became
problematical [Davis< 27l].
2. The worst LNG accident occurred in 1944
when the storage tank operated by the East Ohio Gas
Company in Cleveland ruptured, spilling LNG on
adjacent streets and sewers. The liquid evaporated,
the gas ignited and exploded, resulting in 128 deaths,
300 injuries, and approximately $7 million in property damage. An investigation of this accident indicated that the tank failed because it was constructed
of 3.5% nickel steel, which becomes brittle when it
comes in contact with the extreme cold of LNG. All
plants are now built with 9% nickel steel, aluminum,
or concrete and the storage tanks are surrounded by
dikes capable of containing the contents of the tank
if a rupture occurs. This example illustrates the impact of a particular incident on the passage of new
regulations.<27l
296
3. In December of 1976, the Los Angeles City
Council voted to allow work to begin on an LNG
terminal in San Pedro Bay. The following day an
explosion ripped the oil tanker Sansinena in Los
Angeles harbor leaving 9 dead and 50 injured. A
week later the City Council commissioned a study as
to the relative safety of the proposed site. They later
approved the terminal. This explosion, although it
had nothing to do with liquefied natural gas, alerted
many Californians to the potential dangers of
LNG.< 27l
4. Until the publication of several worst case
scenarios in 1976 on the possible consequences of a
$300 million terminal in Oxnard in California, there
was general agreement by almost all stakeholders that
Oxnard would be an acceptable site for an LNG
terminal. At the time event the Sierra Club was in
favor of this location. (They changed their feelings
about Oxnard in 1977.) One worst case scenario
indicated that a spill of 125,000 m3 of LNG from all
five tanks on a tanker would cause a vapor cloud
which would affect up to 70,000 people. Any resident
could look on a map to determine whether the cloud
covered his own house [Ahern< 28 l]. No estimate of a
probability was attached to this scenario. The graphic
depiction of these consequences generated a public
reaction by groups of local citizens. The California
legislature was influenced by this public reaction.
One legislative staff member stressed that it was not
possible to allow a site that would lead to a large
number of deaths in a catastrophe. 5 As a result, new
siting regulations were passed stating that no more
than an average of 10 people per square mile could
be within one mile of the terminal and no more than
60 within four miles of the terminal. The President's
National Energy Plan incorporated similar population guidelines which effectively ruled out any high
density areas as candidates for an LNG terminal.
This example illustrates how the context in which
information is presented (e.g., a worst case scenario)
may provoke strong reactions by interested parties
and eventually lead to legislative changes.
Kunreuther and Lathrop
and interaction phases of the facility siting process.
In this section we will explore possible ways of improving each of these phases of the decision process
through more structured approaches. How successful
these techniques are likely to be will vary with each
specific problem and depends crucially on the resulting dynamics between the interested parties.
4.1. The Input Phase
The above descriptive framework has revealed
the set of difficult problems associated with the input
Keeney< 29l has shown how decision analysis can
help structure the siting decision but has focused
primarily on the perspective of a single decision-maker
rather than on more than one interested party with
conflicting objectives and different information bases.
Yet many of the general concepts proposed by Keeney are relevant for facilitating the input phase of our
descriptive framework. It is particularly important to
specify the set of decisions {D 1,. •• , Dn} that have to
be made, how they relate to each other, and the
relative importance each party gives to specific attributes. 6
Figure 2 is a representation of the interrelationship between parties, attributes, and alternatives for
one· decision, D2 . The figure is made up of three
two-dimensional matrices. The upper left matrix relates alternatives, sites A, B, C, or no site, with
attributes: supply interruption risk, risk to life and
limb, land-use environmental degradation, and financial cost, respectively. The cell entries range from
- - , a very unfavorable outcome, to + +, a very
favorable outcome.
This matrix, as it is drawn, implies that either
there is a supra decision-maker who has characterized
each site with respect to its ranking with regard to
different attributes or there is consensus among the
different interested parties on these rankings. In reality, there may be differences between how the relevant actors perceive each of the proposed sites. Thus,
industry might view the cost to society of having no
site as being very unfavorable (as actually shown in
Fig. 2). Local interest groups might have a different
view on the subject. In this case, each of these interested parties would construct their own alternativeattribute matrices. The shaded matrix on the lower
left relates attributes to parties: government regulator
(e.g., the CPUC or FERC), government coastal zone
planner (e.g., the CCC), industry (e.g., the gas com-
5
6
4. IMPROVING TIIE FACILITY SITING
PROCESS: PRESCRIPTIVE ANALYSIS
This comment was made to John Lathrop in an interview in
Sacramento, California, in July 1980, regarding the siting process
of an LNG terminal.
See Keeney and Raiffa (41) for a more detailed discussion of
techniques for assessing the value tradeoffs of a decision maker
among several attributes.
297
Siting Hazardous Facilities
o~
§"'-0
Risk: Risk : Land
Supply Life Use Cost
2
+
Site A
Site B
+
+
+
Site C
++
+
++
No Site
«:-q,<$
++
3
4
++
~
~'-:I
....~
,._;;;.
·,e
,<::-'/$
cf'
2
3
2
2
3
2
3
3
4
4
q,'"~
4
~
l..
v<F
Party
Ranking
4
Regulator
Planner
Industry
Societal
Local
Relative Weights
Fig. 2. Relationship between parties, attributes, and alternatives.
pany), societal interest group (e.g., the Sierra Club),
and local interest group (e.g., neighboring
landowners), respectively. The cell entries range from
no shading, indicating little or no relative concern
with the particular attribute by the party, to dark
shading, indicating a great deal of concern. The right
matrix could have been generated from more quantitative versions of the two left matrices. The cell
entries reflect the relative rankings of each of the
alternative sites by each of the interested parties.
The value of developing a structured approach
to the problem, such as the matrix developed in Fig.
2 is that it points out differences between the parties.
The diagram involves important simplifi_cations in
that it does not consider possible uncertainties as to
which outcomes will result if different alternatives are
chosen. It also does not consider the types of decision
procedures which each of the parties are likely to
utilize in determining the relative rankings between
alternatives. These issues are more appropriately discussed in the interaction phase, to which we now
turn.
4.2. Interaction Phase
Suppose that at the end of the input phase, we
were able to arrive at a set of matrices, such as the
one depicted in Fig. 2, where each of the five different interested parties had their own ranking between
sites. One way to resolve differences would be to
assign specific weights to each of the parties and
choose the alternative which received the highest
weighted score. This rather arbitrary way of resolving
conflicts implies that there is some supra decisionmaker who has the authority to assign these weights.
In reality, this is rarely the case. Instead, there is a
process of bargaining, negotiation, and long-term delays induced by this conflict as illustrated by the
California siting process. Several approaches have
been proposed for reducing these conflicts which may
be useful here.
4.3. The Analy!ic Hierarchy Process
Saaty<3> has developed an approach for reconciling differences between parties. His analytic hierarchy
process (AHP) is a systematic procedure for representing the elements of a problem through a
hierarchical structure. By decomposing the problem
into its smaller consitutent parts one only has to
make simple pairwise comparison judgments to develop priorities in each hierarchy.
To illustrate how a hierarchy might be constructed for the LNG siting problem, consider the
illustrative example presented in Fig. 2. We have
represented the problem of choosing an appropriate
site in terms of a four-level hierarchy, as depicted in
Fig. 3. The first level is the single overall objective:
which LNG site (if any) to select? The second level
specifies the set of five interested parties and then
lists the attributes which are considered to be important to each of these groups (Level 3). The lowest
level consists of the set of alternatives available at a
given point in time.
Priorities are established within each level of the
hierarchy by assessing the relative importance of one
298
Kunreuther and Lathrop
Level 1:
Focus
Level 2:
Interested
Parties .
Which LNG Site (if Any) to Select
Regulator
Planner
Societal
Local
Risk :
Life
Risk :
Life
Land Use
Land Use
Risk:
Risk:
Supply
Risk:
Life
Industry
Supply
Risk:
Life
Level 3 :
Attributes
Land Use
Cost
Level 4:
Alternatives
ElBBB
Fig. 3. Hierarchical structure for siting LNG facility.
element over the other in a pairwise comparison with
respect to the criterion in the next higher level. For
example, the importance of each of the interested
parties with respect to the others (Level 2) will be
determined in reference to the question of siting a
facility (Level 1). A measurement theory is used to
determine the priorities of the hierarchy based on the
judgmental data provided by the decision-maker(s).
The potential success of the AHP for problems
such as the siting of LNG facilities depends on the
ability of the analyst to bring the relevant parties
together, to elicit value judgments, and to reconcile
differences between the different stakeholders with
respect to assigning priority weights in pairwise comparisons. The LNG siting process in California reveals that each of the parties had their own objectives
as well.as their own, possibly hidden, agenda. Some
of the stakeholders may be reluctant to articulate
their value structure for fear that they will lose some
of their negotiating power as well as being publicly
responsible for their positions. Ward Edwards< 31 > encountered this latter problem in his study of evaluating school desegregation plans for Los Angeles. He
noted that the interested parties in a societal decision
problem are unlikely to reveal their value structure
because this information then becomes public and
groups would be accountable for numerical judgments. Whether the Saaty approach can overcome
this problem with respect to such emotionally charged
issues as LNG siting is still an open question. Even if
each party is willing to provide relevant pairwise
comparisons it is not clear how one utilizes this
approach when there are significant differences between the weights each of them assigns.
4.4. Examining Assumptions
One way to understand and possibly reconcile
differences between parties is to have each of them
299
Siting Hazardous Facilities
state the assumptions which they are utilizing in
arriving at their conclusions. For example, industry
would have to provide a rationale as to why it ranked
site C as most desirable and the "no site" alternative
as least desirable. Representatives of societal and
local interest groups would have to defend their
assumptions regarding their choices, which in this
case were in the reverse order. Mitroff, Emshoff and
KilmamP 2> have proposed this type of dialectical
approach to planning, as a way for each of the
interested parties to better appreciate the other's
position and perhaps arrive at some compromise.
Majone< 33 l also subscribes to such a process for decisions like that of facility siting, where the knowledge
base is so poorly understood that this type of open
discussion is likely to improve everyone's understanding of the problem.
Since there is limited statistical evidence which
one can utilize for defending one's position it may be
possible to undertake some type of sensitivity analysis to examine the consequences of changing specific
assumptions. For example, suppose one is uncertain
as to the magnitude of the methane cloud dispersion
should there be a tank rupture of an LNG storage
tank. By acknowledging this type of uncertainty and
examining the consequences of locating plants in
each of the three proposed locations, one can determine how important differences will be in terms of
favoring one site over another. Even if this type of
analysis does not reconcile differences, it will at least
indicate to all the concerned parties on what basis
one alternative is preferred over another.
4.5. Utilizing Interactive Computer Modeling
If it is impossible to bring the different interested parties together, then other techniques may
have to be used. One of the most promising approaches is the use of interactive computer modHs
for scenario generation. Each interested party would
be able to construct his/ her own scenario as to
potential consequences of adopting one strategy over
another, and determine the consequences of changes
in assumptions of different parameters. The computer terminal plays the role of a giant calculator by
processing new data and displaying the resulting
outputs. Having already constructed different
matrices, such as the one that comprises Fig. 2, each
stakeholder would be in a position to articulate the
potential consequences of say, locating an LNG
terminal at several proposed sites or deciding not to
construct a project. At this point, it would be possible
to develop not only "worst case scenarios," but also
less extreme situations, including the possibility that
no accident occurs. 7
There undoubtedly will be differences between
the way interested parties view the situation, but the
advantage of interactive-computer models is that these
differences can then be examined in some detail to
stimulate discussion between the interested parties.
For example, scenarios could be generated which
would permit one to analyze very uncertain data
(such as probability and loss information) to determine their impact on relative rankings of sites.
For example, suppose one estimated the annual
probability of a severe accident to be between P 1 to
P2 with losses ranging from L 1 to L 2 • One could
then develop scenarios which examine the relative
merits of different alternatives as one changed these
estimates. If specific sites were preferred over a wide
range of values for probabilities and losses then this
would simplify the choice process. If the rankings
changed as P; and L1 were varied, then this would
suggest that these estimates be refined if possible.
5. SUGGESTIONS FOR FUTURE RESEARCH
The resolution of conflicts between interested
parties may be extremely difficult even if one uses the
more structured approaches proposed above. In fact,
our descriptive framework suggests that interested
parties may not want to get together to solve a
particular problem unless they are forced to by existing legislation. Reconciliation of stakeholder conflicts
is a time-consuming and threatening process since it
involves detailed analysis on the part of each of the
groups and acceptance of responsibility for one's
actions. From a political standpoint, this may not
always be the wisest thing to do. Hence, the above
prescriptive suggestions can only be viewed as a
starting point for developing a dialog between the
parties. We need more research on designing policy
instruments for reconciling differences between the
vying groups.
One of the critical questions that needs to be
addressed is how to design mechanisms for control7
This approach differs from decision analysis by focusing on
individual scenarios rather than a probability distribution over
outcomes. For a more detailed discussion of interactive computer models in a policy context see Kunreuther et al. (42).
300
ling uncertain and unknown consequences of a particular decision. For example, in the case of the siting
of an LNG facility we have limited statistical evidence to estimate probabilities and losses associated
with a catastrophic accident and there is no experimental laboratory except the real world from which
to obtain such data. Holling< 18l points out that there
are two extreme reactions to this concern with an
unknown and uncertain future: regulation and prediction. We have seen these two forces at work with
respect to LNG siting in the form of new restrictions
as to the location of a terminal regarding population
density (regulation) and new design features of a
terminal to prevent an accident (prediction). Interestingly enough, these changes in siting procedures were
triggered by exogenous events and crises and were
designed to reduce the chances that an undesirable
event would occur in the future. Holling< 18l noted
similar reactions to a variety of environmental problems which he and his colleagues at the Institute of
Resource Ecology (University of British Columbia)
examined through case studies.
Another area for future research is the design of
policies to compensate parties at risk from the siting
of a new facility. In the case of LNG there are many
potential causes of an accident (e.g., ships, tanks,
etc.), so it may be difficult to attribute fault to any
one party. Furthermore, the ships, the liquefied natural gas, and the terminals are owned by different
subsidiaries and companies. The local, national, and
international jurisdictions make legal problems even
more difficult.< 27l
One possible direction for future study is the
role of insurance as a way of protecting potential
victims against potential property losses and physical
injury. A General Accounting Office report of July
l 978<34l concluded that injured parties could not be
fully compensated for a serious accident under present liability arrangements. What type of insura!lce
arrangements are feasible between private firms and
the industrial partners who are involved in the shipping, storage, and transmission of LNG? What role is
appropriate for government to play with respect to
offering protection? The Price Anderson Act as it
applies to nuclear safety may provide some guidance
in the design of some system of liability which involves joint private industry-federal government
financial responsibility.
With respect to the more immediate consequences of siting a new facility, O'Hare<35l has proposed a particular type of compensation scheme
Kunreuther and Lathrop
whereby each community proposed as a potential site
determines a minimum level of per capita compensation so that it is willing to make a legal commitment
to have the project in their backyard if the compensation is paid. The applicant would utilize this compensation as part of his calculations as to the relevant
costs associated with locating the facilities in community A, B, or C. The final decision would then be
made by the applicant taking into account the amount
of compensation it would have to pay residents in
each of these three localities.
This type of system would only be applied to
potential sites that had satisfied specific governmental criteria related to safety and environmental risk.
O'Hare recognizes that there will still be some individuals in a given community who will be compensated more than they need to be and others who
will not be rewarded enough. He also recognizes that
for such a system to be implemented there must be
good information on the relevant costs, including an
environmental impact statement, and that the system
has to be designed to overcome the incentive to
overbid.
Whether or not some type of compensation
scheme is a useful policy prescription depends on the
specifics of the situation. In this connection, it would
be interesting to ask what type of payments would
have been required to appease the citizens of Oxnard
so that an LNG terminal could have been located
there. What would the Sierra Club require in payments so that they would support a site which might
have adverse environmental effects? These questions
can only be answered in a real world problem context. They do reflect an increasing concern of
economists and lawyers in dealing with windfalls or
wipeouts from specific actions which involve the public sector. Hagman and Misczynski<36l in their comprehensive study of the subject believe that windfalls
should be partially recaptured to help compensate for
wipeouts. They propose a number of alternative
mechanisms for ameliorating this problem ranging
from special assessments to development permits.
These types of policy instruments could also be investigated in the context of specific siting problems.
The final outcome is likely to represent some
type of balance between the political constraints and
economic criteria. As Wildavsky<37l has pointed out:
The criterion of choice in politics and markets is not being
right or correct as in solving a puzzle, but agreement based
on interaction among partially opposed interests. (p. 133)
Siting Hazardous Facilities
The framework presented in this paper does not
provide answers to the dilemma between economics
and politics but it does help the analyst gain a better
understanding of the causes of these conflicts. How
one actually improves the process is a challenge for
future problem-focused research.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
The research reported in this paper is supported
by the Bundesministerium filr Forschung und Technologie, F.R.G., contract no. 321/7591 / RGB 8001.
While support for this work is gratefully acknowledged, the views expressed are the authors' and not
necessarily shared by the sponsor. This paper is part
of a larger project a group of us at IIASA are
undertaking with respect to siting decisions of LNG
facilities.
We would like to acknowledge very helpful discussions with our IIASA colleagues; Hermann Atz,
Joanne Linnerooth, Giandomenico Majone, Michie!
Schwarz, Craig Sinclair, Michael Thompson, and
James Vaupel. Randolph Deutsch, Jorg Finsinger,
Ralph Keeney, Paul Kleindorfer, and Detlof von
Winterfeldt provided helpful comments on an earlier
draft of this paper. A more detailed discussion of the
problems associated with siting LNG facilities in
European countries and the United States appears in
H. Kunreuther, J. Linnerooth, and R. Starnes Liquefied Energy Gas Facility Siting, Proceedings of an
IIASA Task Force Meeting, 23-26 September 1980,
(IIASA, Laxenburg, Austria, in press).
REFERENCES
I. W. Ahem, "The Role of Technical Analyses in California
Energy Facility Siting" in H. Kunreuther, J. Linnerooth, and
R. Starnes, eds. Liquefied Energy Gas Facility Siting Proceedings of an l!ASA Task Force Meeting, 23-26 September 1980
(in press).
2. R. Deutsch,' "Siting an L.N.G. Facility in California: The
Regulatory Framework and the Factors Involved in the Decision Making Process" in H. Kunreuther, J. Linnerooth, and R.
Starnes, eds., Liquefied Energy Gas Facility Siting Proceedings
of an l!ASA Task Force Meeting, 23-26 September 1980, (in
press).
3. J. Linnerooth, "A Short History of the California LNG Terminal," IIASA WP-80-155, Laxenburg, Austria (October 1980).
4. J. W. Lathrop, "Decision Making in LNG Terminal Siting:
The California Case" in H. Kunreuther, J. Linnerooth, and R.
Starnes, eds., Liquefied Energy Gas Facility Siting Proceedings
of an IIASA Task Force Meeting, 23-26 September 1980 (in
press).
301
5. B. Fischhoff, P. Slovic, and S. Lichtenstein, "Lay Foibles and
Expert Fables in Judgments about Risk" in T. O'Riordan and
R. K. Turner, eds., Progress in Resource Management and
Environment Planning, Vol. 3 Wiley, (Chichester, in press) .
6. A. Tversky and D. Kahneman, "Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases," Science 185, 1124-31 (1974).
7. A. Tversky and D. Kahneman , "The Framing of Decisions
and the Psychology of Choice," Science 211 , 453-58 (1981).
8. J. Hershey, H. Kunreuther, and P. Schoemaker, "Sources of
Bias in Assessment Procedures for Utility Functions," Management Science (in press).
9. W. Fairley, "Evaluating the ' Small' Probability of a
Catastrophic Accident from the Marine Transport of Liquefied
Natural Gas," In Fairley and .Mosteller, eds., Statistics and
Public Policy Addison-Wesley, (Reading, Mass, 1977).
10. J. March, "Bounded Rationality, Ambiguity and the Engineering of Choice," Bell J ournal of Economics 9, 587-608 (Spring
1978).
11. C. Lindblom, "The Science of Muddling Through," Public
Administration Review 19, 79-88 (1959).
12. D . Braybrooke and C. Lindblom, A Strategy of Decision (The
Free Press, New York, 1963).
13. R. Cyert and J. March, A Behavorial Theory of the Firm ,
Prentice Hall, (Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1963).
14. J. Bettmann, An Information Processing Theory of Consumer
Choice , Addison Wesley, (Reading, Mass., 1979).
15. A. Tversky and D . Kahneman, "Availability: A Heuristic for
Judging Frequency and Probability," Cognitive Psychology, 5,
207-232 (1973).
16. H. Kunreuther, R. Ginsberg, L. Miller, P. Sagi, P. Slovic, B.
Borkan, and N. Katz, Disaster Insurance Protection : Public
Policy Lessons , New York, Wiley and Sons (1978).
17. J. March and J. Olsen, Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations,
Universtetsforlaget (Bergen, Norway, 1976).
18. C. S. Holling, " Resilience in the Unforgiving Society," Working Paper R-24, Vancouver Institute of Resource Ecology
(March 1981 ).
19. J. Walker, " Setting the Agenda in the U.S. Senate : A Theory
of Problem Selection," British Journal of Political Science, 7.
423-445 ( 1977).
20. J. Lawless, Technology and Social Shock, (Rutgers University
Press, New Brunswick, N.J., 1977).
21. J. Jackson and H. Kunreuther, "Low Probability Events and
Determining Acceptable Risk: The Case of Nuclear Regulation," IIASA PP-81-7, Laxenburg, Austria ( 1981 ).
22. Office of Technology Assessment (OTA), Transportation of
Liquefied Natural Gas, Washington, D.C., (1977).
23. DOE/ ERA, Opinion and Order on Importation of Liquefied
Natural Gas.
24. J. W. Lathrop and J. Linnerooth, "The Role of Risk Assessment in a Political Decision Process," in P. Humphreys and A.
Vari (eds), Analayzing and Aiding Decision Processes, Amsterdam, North Holland, (forthcoming).
25. J. W. Lathrop, "Measuring Social Risk and Determining its
Acceptability," in D. Fischer, ed., Two Blowouts in the North
Sea (Pergamon, Oxford, in press).
26. Federal Energy Regulatory Commission, " Western LNG Project, Final Environmental Impact Statement," FERC / EIS0002 F, Vol. III (1978).
27. L. N. Davis, Frozen Fire, (Friends of the Earth, 1979).
28. W. Ahem, "California Meets the LNG Terminal," Coastal
Zone Management Journal 7, 185-221 (1980).
29. R. Keeney, Siting Energy Facilities (Academic Press, New
York, 1980).
30. T. Saaty, The Analytic Hierarchy Process , (McGraw-Hill, New
York, 1980).
31. W. Edwards, "Reflections on and Criticisms of a Highly
Political Multi-attitude Utility Analysis," in L. Cobb and R.
302
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.
Thrall eds., Mathematica/ Frontiers of the Social and Policy
Sciences, (Westview Press, Boulder, 1981 pp. 157-189.)
I. Mitroff, J. Emshoff, and R. Kilmann, "Assumptional Analysis: A Methodology for Strategic Problem Solving," Management Science 6, 583-593 ( 1979).
N. Majone, "Process and Outcome in Regulatory Decisions,"
American Behavioral Scientist 22, 561-583 (1979).
General Accounting Office, "Liquified Energy Gases Safety,"
Report to the Congress, EMD-78-28 Volume I. Washington
D.C. ( 1978).
M. O'Hare, "Not On My Block You Don't: Facility Siting and
the Strategic Importance of Compensation," Public Policy, 25,
409-58 ( 1977).
D. Hagman and D. Misczynski, Windfalls for Wipeouts ,
(Chicago, American Society of Planning Officials, 1978).
Kunreuther and Lathrop
37. A. Wildavsky, "Rationality in Writing: Linear and
Curvilinear," Journal of Public Policy, 1, 125-40 (1981).
38. H. Kunreuther, J. Lathrop, and J. Linnerooth, "A Descriptive
Model of Choice for Siting Facilities: The Case of the California LNG Terminal," IIASA WP-82-18, Laxenburg, Austria.
39. R. Keeney, R. Kulkarni and K. Nair, "A Risk Analysis of an
LNG Terminal," Omega 7, 191-205 (1979).
40. C. Starr, "Social Benefit versus Technological Risk," Science
165, 1232-38 (1969).
41. R. Keeney and H. Raiffa, Decisions with Multiple Objectives,
(Wiley, New York, 1976).
42. H. Kunreuther, J. Lepore, L. Miller, J. Vinso, J. Wilson, B.
Borkan, B. Duffy, and N. Katz, An Interactive Modeling
(University of Colorado
System for Disaster Policy Ana~ysi
Press, Institute of Behavioral Science, 1978).