Knowing What It Is Like
Yuri Cath
La Trobe University
This manuscript has been published by Cambridge University Press (2024). This version (which is prior to copy
editing) is free to view and download for personal use only. Not for re-distribution, re-sale or use in derivative
works. © Yuri Cath 2024. For non-personal use including citations, please consult the published version here:
https://www.cambridge.org/core/elements/knowing-what-it-islike/9243527F6BCB30B7AA963526A0FDADE3?utm_campaign=shareaholic&utm_medium=email_this&utm
_source=email
Cambridge University Press
Abstract: What kind of knowledge does one have when one knows what it is like to,
say, fall in love, eat vegemite, be a parent, or ride a bike? This Element addresses this
question by exploring the tension between two plausible theses about this form of
knowledge: (i) that to possess it one must have had the corresponding experience, and
(ii) that to possess it one must know an answer to the ‘what it is like’ question. I show
how the tension between these two theses helps to explain existing debates about this
form of knowledge, as well as puzzling conflicts in our attitudes towards the possibility
of sharing this knowledge through testimony, or other sources like literature, theories,
and simulations. And I offer a view of ‘what it is like’ knowledge which can resolve
both the tension between (i) and (ii), and these puzzles around testimony.
2
Contents
1. Introduction
2. Anti-Intellectualism
3. Qualified Intellectualism
4. Downstream Intellectualism
5. Testimony and Partial WIL-knowledge
6. Pitfalls and Possibilities
7. Conclusions
3
1. Introduction
For any type of experience—be it momentous, amusing, traumatic, entertaining, or just
trivial—we can identify a corresponding form of knowledge about what it is like to have that
experience. So, not only can we experience grieving, falling in love, eating durian, seeing
something red, being a parent, smelling a skunk, sitting in an anechoic chamber, or riding a
bike, but we can also know what it is like to grieve, fall in love, eat durian, see something red,
be a parent, smell a skunk, sit in an anechoic chamber, or ride a bike. What is involved in
possessing this ‘what it is like’ knowledge? How is such knowledge gained, retained, and
shared? And how does it relate to other forms of knowledge?
These are the central questions this Element will address, and these are all epistemological
questions, as they concern the nature and character of a certain form of knowledge. However,
when such questions are discussed, it is normally within the context of debates in the
philosophy of mind, not epistemology. This is because claims about ‘what it is like’-knowledge
(‘WIL-knowledge’ or ‘knowing-WIL’ for short) have played a central role in debates about the
nature of phenomenal consciousness, especially in connection to Jackson’s (1982) knowledge
argument against physicalist theories of consciousness. And outside of the philosophy of mind
claims about the nature of WIL-knowledge have also played notable roles in other areas
including transformative experiences (Paul 2014, 2015a), the philosophy of religion
(Zagzebski 2008), and moral philosophy (Grace-Chappell 2017).
Many important ideas and theories about WIL-knowledge have been advanced in these areas,
especially in relation to the knowledge argument, and some of these ideas and theories will be
significant characters in the discussion to come. But my approach to thinking about WILknowledge will be somewhat different than the usual approach taken in discussing this topic.
This is because I want to think about WIL-knowledge, first, as a topic of intrinsic interest within
4
epistemology, rather than approaching it as primarily a topic of applied interest in relation to
other areas of philosophy. A lot can be learned about WIL-knowledge by thinking about how
it relates to these applied issues, but, equally, I think a lot can be learned by selectively
bracketing those issues and considering WIL-knowledge more on its terms, and in relation to
connected issues not only in the philosophy of mind but also in epistemology.
To clarify this difference in approach, recall Jackson’s famous thought-experiment of the
super-scientist Mary who knows all possible physical truths, including all the physicals truths
about what goes on in a human brain when have visual experiences. However, despite having
excellent vision herself, Mary has never had any experiences of seeing something red, as she
has been kept her whole life in a room where she can only have black-and-white visual
experiences. One day Mary is released from her room and she sees something red for the first
time and, thereby, comes to know what it is like to see something red. Jackson’s knowledge
argument then goes (roughly) like this: pre-release Mary knew all the physical truths, but there
was at least one truth (namely, what it is like to see something red) that pre-release Mary was
ignorant of before leaving her room, therefore, physicalism (understood as the view that all
truths are physical truths) is false.
Probably the most noticeable way in which my approach will differ from most existing
discussions of WIL-knowledge is that my ultimate aim is not to offer a response to Jackson’s
knowledge argument, or an analysis of what happens to Mary when she leaves her black-andwhite room. The views about WIL-knowledge that I will go on to discuss and advance will
have implications for how one evaluates that argument, and I will sometimes comment on those
implications when relevant, but these views are not developed with such implications in mind.
From the perspective of a philosopher of mind interested in debates about the nature of
phenomenal consciousness, such possible implications would understandably be their main
5
concern, given the huge role that the Mary thought experiment has played in such debates. But
from the perspective of an epistemologist, who wants to understand the nature of a given form
of knowledge, it would be odd, and perhaps even methodologically suspect, to let these possible
implications play a major role in guiding one’s theorizing about that form of knowledge. And
while our intuition that Mary would gain new WIL-knowledge when she leaves her room is
one interesting ‘data point’ that one might want one’s theory of WIL-knowledge to
accommodate, it is not more than that and there are other more humdrum and less contentious
thought-experiments which provide similar lessons for our theories about WIL-knowledge.
Relatedly, when Jackson’s Mary is mentioned in the discussion to come, in most cases she
could be replaced with Paul’s (2014: 9) less tendentious character of ‘ordinary Mary’ who is
not omniscient with respect to all the physical facts, but just has more normal levels of
knowledge about the human brain and colour perception, etc. So, while Mary will be a notable
character in the discussion to come—this is unavoidable given how central she is to many
existing discussions of WIL-knowledge that we will need to engage with—she will not be our
main protagonist.
Instead, our main protagonist will be the relationship between two theses about WILknowledge (or, more precisely, schemas for generating putative necessary conditions for
possessing specific instances of this knowledge):
The Experience Condition: One knows what it is like to Φ only if one has had an
experience of Φ-ing oneself.
The Answer Condition: One knows what it is like to Φ only if one knows an answer to
the question ‘What is it like to Φ?’.
These theses are both related to central themes in existing discussions of WIL-knowledge. The
experience condition is simply a way of generalizing a kind of powerful intuition that you
6
cannot know what it is like to do or be something until you have done or been that thing oneself.
This is the intuition that supports the standard assumption that Mary cannot know what it is
like to see something red until that fateful day that she sees something red herself, and this
intuition is prominent in most of the other applied discussions of WIL-knowledge (e.g., it plays
a crucial role in characterising Paul’s notion of a transformative experience). But it is also an
intuition found in everyday and non-philosophical contexts, including numerous pop songs,
like Smokey Robinson’s “You Don't Know What It’s Like” where he sings “‘Til you fall until
it happens to you. Oh, no, no, no, you don't know what it’s like”.1
The answer condition is supported by plausible ideas that were identified as far back as Ginet
(1975), although it took a long time for these ideas to be more widely accepted in the literature
on the knowledge argument, due to the work of Lycan (1996: 92–94) and others. These ideas
can be stated both in the formal mode as claims about the structure and semantics of knowingWIL ascriptions and by parallel claims, in the material mode, about the conditions in which
someone knows what it is like to Φ. In short, knowing-WIL appears to be a form of so-called
knowing-wh, and the sentences ascribing knowing-WIL appear to be knowing-wh ascriptions.
The term ‘knowing-wh’ refers to any form of knowledge ascribed by sentences where the
compliment of ‘knows’ is an interrogative clause denoting an embedded question and headed
by a question word like ‘why’, ‘when’, ‘where’, ‘what’, ‘whom’, or ‘how’ (as most of these
question words start with ‘wh’ we get the slightly awkward phrase ‘knowing-wh’). And the
standard question-answer semantics for knowing-wh ascriptions is, roughly, that they are true
just in case the subject knows a relevant answer to the given embedded question. In which case,
as knowing-WIL is a form of knowing-wh, we should expect that knowing-WIL is also
analysable in terms of knowing an answer to an embedded question.
1
See Kind (2021) and Stoljar (2016) for similar examples.
7
While strong prima facie cases can be made for both the experience and answer conditions
there is also a prima facie tension between these theses, as they seem to push us towards
inconsistent views of WIL-knowledge. To be clear, there is not an inconsistency between these
theses, and we will see later that some theorists have offered views of WIL-knowledge that
entail both theses. However, there is still an apparent tension between endorsing both theses
because accepting each thesis seems to push us towards accepting one of two different, and
mutually inconsistent, views of WIL-knowledge.
On the one hand, the answer condition clearly pushes us towards an ‘intellectualist’ view on
which knowing-WIL is a kind of propositional knowledge or ‘knowing-that’, that is, the
knowledge you have when you know that something is the case. This is because knowing an
answer to a question is naturally analysed as a matter of knowing that p, for some proposition
p which is an answer to that question. In which case, it is hard to accept the answer condition
without granting that WIL-knowledge can be at least partly analysed in terms of propositional
knowledge. And once one accepts the answer condition one might naturally take a further step
and claim that WIL-knowledge can be fully analysed in terms of propositional knowledge, such
that knowing a propositional answer to the relevant embedded question is not just a necessary
but a sufficient condition for possessing WIL-knowledge. In other words, once one accepts the
answer condition it might seem natural to also endorse the following biconditional: one knows
what it is like to Φ if and only if one knows an answer to the question ‘What is it like to Φ?’.
In which case, WIL-knowledge would be a straightforward instance of propositional
knowledge.
On the other hand, however, the experience condition might seem to push us towards an ‘antiintellectualist’ view on which knowing-WIL is some form of non-propositional knowledge.
For if WIL-knowledge was propositional knowledge about experiences why would possessing
that knowledge entail one’s having had an instance of the very thing that is the intentional
8
object of one’s knowledge? (I know that houses are overly priced but, sadly, possessing this
knowledge does not entail that I have ever had an overpriced house.) This entailment would
make sense if knowing what it is like to Φ was a matter of knowing a proposition that entails
that one has had an experience of Φ-ing at some point. For, given the factivity of knowledgethat, it would thereby follow that one has had an experience of Φ-ing. But, as we will see later
in Section 3.1, intellectualist analyses of WIL-knowledge do not appeal to such propositional
contents. The contents they appeal to might entail conditionals like if the subject of the
knowing-WIL ascription were to have an experience of Φ-ing then it would feel a certain way
for them, but they do not entail that the subject has had such an experience. So, why would the
experience condition be true if knowing-WIL is just a matter of knowing such a proposition?
More generally, one might worry that in being subject to the experience condition the properties
of WIL-knowledge will diverge in significant ways from those of knowledge-that. So, for
example, consider testimony. Knowing-that, and many forms of knowing-wh other than
knowing-WIL, can usually be shared via testimony (Poston 2016), at least in suitably
favourable circumstances. But is WIL-knowledge transmissible through testimony? If the
experience condition is true, it seems not, as while testimony might transmit knowledge it
cannot transmit experiences. If you have just returned from a visit to the pyramids no amount
of reliable testimony from you about what it was like will magically provide me with that
experience.
My aim in this Element is to show how we can illuminate the nature of WIL-knowledge by
exploring and, ultimately, resolving this tension between the experience and answer conditions.
For, as we will see, the apparent tension between these theses is at the heart of various key
issues concerning WIL-knowledge, including whether it can be analysed in terms of other
forms of knowledge and the possible sources of this knowledge. In Sections 2 and 3, I will
consider two broadly different ways that one might respond to the apparent tension between
9
these theses that each appeal to two importantly different views of WIL-knowledge found in
the literature. The first family of views, discussed in Section 2, are those which take WILknowledge to be some kind of non-propositional knowledge. Specifically, we will consider the
ability hypothesis and the acquaintance hypothesis which respectively identify WILknowledge with non-propositional knowing-how and acquaintance knowledge. The second
family of views, discussed in Section 3, are what I will call qualified intellectualist views as
these views hold that knowing-WIL is a kind of knowing-that, but a distinctive species of
knowing-that which is subject to some further condition beyond just knowing an answer to the
embedded WIL-question.
Our discussion in Section 2 will show that the ability hypothesis and the acquaintance
hypothesis can, at best, only provide us with an analysis of the epistemic states denoted by one
of two different disambiguations of knowing-WIL sentences, and they cannot resolve the
tension between the experience and answer conditions. Our discussion in Section 3 will show
how qualified intellectualism can give us an account of the epistemic states denoted by the
other disambiguation, and in Section 4 I will develop my own preferred form of qualified
intellectualism—what I call downstream intellectualism—which can resolve this tension, and
in a non-ad hoc way appealing to general patterns in how we think about and ascribe knowingwh. In Section 5 these ideas are refined again to show how WIL-knowledge can come in
degrees, which will help us to resolve certain puzzling conflicts in our attitudes and practices
concerning WIL-knowledge and testimony which relate to the tension between the experience
and answer conditions. One of the ideas to come out of that discussion will be that we can gain
certain forms of partial WIL-knowledge about experiences we have not had ourselves,
including the experiences of other people whose lives may be very different from one’s own
life. In Section 6 I will close by considering certain objections, both epistemological and
ethical, that might be made to that idea.
10
2. Anti-Intellectualism
One way to react to the apparent tension between the experience and answer conditions would
be to simply reject the answer condition by appealing to a view on which WIL-knowledge is
some form of non-propositional knowledge, whilst maintaining that the experience condition
is true and appealing to certain characteristics of this non-propositional knowledge to explain
why it is true.
But what kind of knowledge could WIL-knowledge be if not a kind of knowledge-that? In
textbooks one often finds the claim that as well as (i) knowing-that (or ‘propositional
knowledge’), there is also (ii) knowing-how, and (iii) acquaintance knowledge. Knowing-how
is sometimes called ‘ability knowledge’ because following Ryle (1949) it is often assumed that
to know how to Φ is to possess an ability or disposition to Φ. The term ‘acquaintance
knowledge’ is sometimes used interchangeably with ‘objectual knowledge’ because the
supposed examples of acquaintance knowledge are all cases where what one knows is a thing
or object of some kind. But, for clarity, I will use these terms differently. I will use ‘objectual
knowledge’ to refer to any form of knowledge where what one knows is an object of some kind
(e.g., ‘Mary knows Tokyo’, ‘Mary knows Fred’, or ‘Mary knows the experience of seeing
something red’) with no further assumptions made about the nature of this knowledge, e.g.,
whether it can or cannot be analysed in terms of knowing-that. And I will reserve the term
‘acquaintance knowledge’ to refer to those supposed forms of objectual knowledge which also
meet at least some of the substantive conditions associated with Russel’s (1911) famous
account of knowledge by acquaintance; including the negative claim that acquaintance
knowledge is not a form of knowing-that, and the positive claim that it involves some kind of
direct awareness of the known object (for discussion see Duncan 2021).
11
The standard story in the textbooks is that Ryle taught us that knowing-how is not reducible to
knowing-that, and Russell taught us the same with respect to acquaintance knowledge, and
there is clearly an implicit assumption that knowing-that could not be reducible to either
knowing-how or acquaintance knowledge. So, if this standard picture is right, these are three
mutually irreducible forms of knowledge. This tripartite picture can be challenged in lots of
ways, and even if it is correct there are difficult questions about how to best interpret and
develop it (e.g., what, if anything, unifies these three things such that we can consider them as
all being different species of one overarching category of ‘knowledge’?). But, for the moment,
let us put such questions to the side, and assume that this standard picture is correct. Can we
plausibly identify WIL-knowledge with either knowing-how or acquaintance knowledge?
2.1 The Ability and Acquaintance Hypotheses
Both identifications have been tried in the knowledge argument literature, with the hope being
that one could thereby block the argument’s crucial assumption that if Mary gains new WILknowledge then she must thereby come to know a new fact. Perhaps most famously, there is
Lewis (1998) and Nemirow’s (1990) respective versions of the ability hypothesis according to
which knowing what it is like to Φ is identified with knowing-how. So, for example, Lewis
holds that knowing what it is like to Φ is a matter of knowing how to imagine, remember, and
recognise experiences of Φ -ing. Nemirow has the same kind of view, but he only appeals to
the ability to imagine: “Knowing what an experience is like is the same as knowing how to
imagine having the experience” (1990: 495).
Furthermore, Lewis and Nemirow implicitly endorse a Rylean view of knowing-how on which
knowing how to Φ is identified with the ability to Φ, and it is also assumed that this means that
knowing-how is not identical to, and does not, in any other way, involve the possession of any
12
states of knowing-that. Putting these points together, and using Lewis’ set of abilities, we can
usefully represent the ability hypothesis as being composed of three claims where the final
claim follows from the first two claims:
i)
To know what it is like to Φ is to know how to imagine, remember, and recognise,
experiences of Φ-ing.
ii)
To know how to imagine, remember, and recognise, experiences of Φ-ing is to have
abilities to imagine, remember, and recognise, experiences of Φ-ing, abilities which
do not involve the possession of any form of knowing-that.
iii)
Knowing what it is like to Φ does not involve the possession of any form of
knowing-that [from (i) and (ii)]
If this view is correct then we should reject the answer condition because WIL-knowledge is
not a matter of knowing propositions at all and, hence, it cannot require knowing a proposition
that answers a question. With regards to the experience condition, Lewis would reject this
thesis as stated, as he thought that it was at least metaphysically possible to have the abilities
to imagine and recognise experiences of Φ-ing without ever having Φ-ed oneself. But Lewis
did think that, normally, one would need to have had an experience of Φ-ing in order to have
the abilities to imagine, remember, and recognise experiences of Φ-ing, and Lewis could appeal
to this idea in explaining the intuitive appeal of the experience condition, and he could even
claim that it explains why a modified version of the experience restricted to ‘normal
circumstances’ is true (we will explore Lewis’ views more fully in Section 4.2).
In line with the tripartite picture of knowledge, the other strategy if one wants to reject the
answer condition and deny that knowing-WIL is any kind of knowing-that is to identify it with
13
some form of direct acquaintance knowledge, and then to claim, in addition, that possessing
acquaintance knowledge is not a matter of possessing any form of knowledge-that. More
precisely, this view will endorse some version of the following three claims paralleling (i)-(iii)
above:
(iv)
To know what it is like to Φ is to possess a form of acquaintance knowledge.
(v)
Possessing this form of acquaintance knowledge is a matter of standing in a certain
direct awareness relation to one’s own experiences of Φ-ing, a relation which does
not involve the possession of any form of knowing-that.
iv)
Knowing what it is like to Φ does not involve the possession of any form of
knowing-that [from (i) and (ii)]
In the knowledge argument literature, Conee (1994) offered an acquaintance hypothesis like
this, where he endorses each of (iv)-(vi) above. Conee holds, broadly following the tripartite
picture and Russell (1911), that acquaintance knowledge requires neither information nor
abilities and, hence, is “irreducible to factual knowledge or knowing how” (1994: 136). On
Conee’s view, knowing what it is like to, say, see something red is a matter of being directly
acquainted with an experience of seeing something red (which he treats as equivalent to
becoming directly acquainted with the property of phenomenal redness). And being directly
acquainted with an experience is, for Conee, simply a matter of having the experience and
noticing it. If correct, this view of Conee’s entails both that the experience condition is true
(because one cannot know an experience in the way Conee describes without having an
experience of that type) and that the answer condition is false (because this acquaintance
knowledge is non-propositional knowledge).
14
2.2 Propositional Objections and the Ambiguity Reply
The ability hypothesis has been subjected to intense scrutiny, with numerous objections being
made to it, including: arguments that Lewis’ abilities are not sufficient (Conee 1994) or not
necessary for the possession of WIL-knowledge (Conee 1994, Tye 2000), objections that
contest its assumption that knowing-how is not a kind of knowing-that (Stanley and Williamson
2001), objections that contest the assumption that knowing-how can be identified with abilities
(Alter 2001), and objections that contest the assumption that Lewis’ abilities would not involve
the possession of propositional knowledge (Coleman 2009).
Most importantly, for our purposes, there are also objections based on direct arguments that
knowing-WIL is a form of knowing-that (e.g., Ginet 1975, Lycan 1996). These arguments
appeal to the same kinds of considerations which support the answer condition, namely, that
knowing-WIL ascriptions are a form of knowing-wh ascription, and that knowing-wh
ascriptions are naturally analysed in terms of propositional knowledge where one knows a
proposition that answers the embedded wh-question. And if any one of these arguments is
sound, then we must also reject the acquaintance hypothesis (which has not been subjected to
the same levels of intense scrutiny as the ability hypothesis), given that both hypotheses share
the anti-intellectualist commitment that knowing-WIL is not any kind of propositional
knowledge (claims iii/vi in Section 2.1).
In response, anti-intellectualists about WIL-knowledge could try to argue that there is no good
sense at all in which we can say that WIL-knowledge is a kind of knowing-that. But I think the
prospects for that kind of reply are dim, given the strength of the reasons supporting the answer
condition. Another, and more promising, strategy would be to concede that these arguments
provide us with good reasons to think that the epistemic states denoted by one disambiguation
15
of knowing-WIL sentences are a kind of knowing-that, but then claim that there is another
disambiguation which denotes a non-propositional form of knowledge.
This kind of reply can appeal to the plausible linguistic claim, following Stoljar (2015, 2016),
that knowing-WIL ascriptions like ‘John knows what it is like to have a toothache’ are
ambiguous between: (i) an interrogative reading on which the sentence tells us that John knows
that p for some proposition p that answers the embedded question ‘what is it like to have a
toothache’, and (ii) a free relative reading on which the sentence tells us that John knows the
thing or property denoted by the referring expression ‘what it is like to have a toothache’. As
Stoljar (2016: 1182–1183) points out, the interrogative reading is used when we say things like
“I wonder what it is like to have a toothache” as what you are wondering is what true
proposition or fact answers a question. And the free relative reading is used when we say things
like “John hates what it is like to have a toothache” because what John hates is something like
the way it feels to have a toothache, not a proposition that answers a question.
The free-relative interpretation obviously fits very naturally with the acquaintance hypothesis,
because Conee can claim that on the free relative interpretation of “John knows what it is like
to have a toothache” what the sentence says is that John knows a certain experience or
phenomenal quality, rather than any proposition that answers a question about that experience.
Conee could then qualify his acquaintance hypothesis and claim that it is a view just about the
kind of knowledge ascribed by the free relative interpretation of knowing-WIL ascriptions. In
which case, Conee could plausibly maintain that the standard arguments for thinking that
knowing-WIL is a form of knowing-that only apply to the interrogative reading of knowingWIL ascriptions, and so they don’t conflict with this ambiguity version of his acquaintance
hypothesis.
16
Conee’s reply to the knowledge argument would then be reformulated along similar lines. In
Conee’s original reply he agrees with Jackson that, before her release, Mary does not know
what it is like to see something red, and after her release she gains this knowledge. But in
learning what it is like to see something red Conee claims that Mary does not thereby come to
know any new fact because WIL-knowledge is non-propositional acquaintance knowledge.
Now if Conee were to accept that there is both a free-relative and an interrogative reading of
knowing-WIL ascriptions his modified view would be that Mary has interrogative WILknowledge before leaving her room, but only after she leaves her room does she gain this
acquaintance WIL-knowledge. And this reformulation fits well with claims Conee makes about
pre-release Mary being able to know certain demonstrative facts concerning phenomenal
redness, as some of these facts will plausibly be answers to the question ‘what is it like to see
something red?’. Conee (1990: 142) writes:
There are closely related facts, such as the fact concerning phenomenal
redness that red things look that way. But we have no reason to doubt that
Mary knew all such facts before knowing how red things look. Mary already
had the capacity to form thoughts using this demonstrative sort of reference
to phenomenal qualities. She was able to demonstrate them with
comprehension, at least via others’ experiences of them, e.g. as 'that look'
while indicating another person's attentive experience of phenomenal
redness.
In embracing the ambiguity thesis in this way, this reformulation of Conee’s acquaintance
hypothesis could sidestep any arguments for thinking that knowing-WIL is a kind of knowingthat, by claiming that they only show us that the interrogative WIL-knowledge Mary had prior
to leaving her room is a kind of knowing-that.
17
More importantly, for our purposes, this ambiguity version of the acquaintance hypothesis
could also be used to motivate an interesting response to the prima facie tension between the
answer and experience conditions. Now instead of denying the answer condition outright the
proponent of this version of the acquaintance hypothesis could maintain that: (i) the answer
condition is true, but only when we interpret it using the interrogative readings of knowingWIL ascriptions, whereas it is false when we interpret it using the free relative reading; and (ii)
the experience condition is true, but only when we interpret it using the free relative reading of
knowing-WIL ascriptions, whereas it is false when we interpret it using the interrogative
reading. And this position would have the attractive virtue of allowing that there is something
right about each condition, whilst also dissolving the prima facie tension between them.
Furthermore, and surprisingly, these benefits of the ambiguity thesis may even be available to
proponents of the ability hypothesis. For Stoljar (2015) has argued that Lewis’ version of the
ability hypothesis is best interpreted as an account of the epistemic states denoted by the freerelative interpretation of knowing-WIL ascriptions. The initial idea then would be that we could
still endorse claims (i)-(iii) that we used early in characterising the ability hypothesis, but on
this free-relative interpretation they will be equivalent to the following claims:
i)
To know the experience of Φ-ing is to know how to imagine, remember, and
recognise, experiences of Φ-ing.
ii)
To know how to imagine, remember, and recognise, experiences of Φ-ing is to have
abilities to imagine, remember, and recognise, experiences of Φ-ing, abilities which
do not involve the possession of any form of knowing-that.
iii)
Knowing the experience of Φ-ing does not involve the possession of any form of
knowing-that [from (i) and (ii)]
18
Although, as Stoljar discusses, given the arguments for thinking that knowing-how is a kind of
knowing-that (Stanley and Williamson 2001), and the close parallels between those arguments
and the direct arguments for thinking that knowing-WIL is a kind of knowing-that, a proponent
of this ambiguity version of the ability hypothesis may well choose to remove any claims about
knowing-how from their view, and just identify this objectual knowledge directly with abilities.
In which case, we would be left with the following theses:
i)
To know the experience of Φ-ing is to have abilities to imagine, remember, and
recognise, experiences of Φ-ing, abilities which do not involve the possession of
any form of knowing-that.
ii)
Knowing the experience of Φ-ing does not involve the possession of any form of
knowing-that [from (i)]
This interpretation of Lewis’ ability hypothesis, combined with the ambiguity thesis about
knowing-WIL ascriptions, can have the same payoffs as the proposed reformulation of Conee’s
view identified above. That is, Lewis can now simply sidestep the arguments for thinking that
WIL-knowledge is a form of knowing-that, as well as the related arguments for thinking that
knowing-how is a kind of knowing-that, and he can dissolve the tension between the answer
and experience conditions by claiming that each condition is true on one disambiguation of ‘S
knows what it is like to Φ’ ascriptions, but not the same disambiguation.
2.3 Objectual WIL-knowledge
My focus in Sections 3 to 5 will be on interrogative WIL-knowledge alone, partly because I
take this to be the more dominant interpretation of knowing-WIL ascriptions and partly
because, as I will argue in Section 2.4 below, the tension between the answer and experience
19
conditions remains for interrogative WIL-knowledge even once we distinguish it from
objectual WIL-knowledge. But, before moving on to this focus on interrogative WILknowledge, it will be useful to briefly consider the nature of objectual WIL-knowledge. Does
either the acquaintance hypothesis or the ability hypothesis provide us with a plausible theory
of these epistemic states ascribed by the free-relative interpretation of knowing-WIL
sentences?
Interestingly, there is a view on which we can see both the acquaintance hypothesis and the
ability hypothesis as providing us with part of the picture when it comes to analysing objectual
WIL-knowledge. This idea relates to arguments made by Conee and others that Lewis’ abilities
are not necessary for the possession of WIL-knowledge. So, Conee (1994: 139) appeals to a
variant of Jackson’s thought experiment where the added wrinkle is that Mary “has no visual
imagination” and is thereby “unable to visualize anything”. Now, consider this Mary when she
sees something red for the first time. Conee claims that it is evident that at that moment she
looks at the red tomato this Mary knows what it is like to see something red but “A fortiori, she
is not able to imagine, remember, and recognize the experience, as Lewis’ Ability Hypothesis
requires” (1994: 139). Furthermore, Conee suggests that the moral of his version of the Mary
case is that Mary could lack all three of Lewis’ abilities whilst still knowing what it is like to
see something red. For Conee thinks that what this Mary case shows is that “that knowing what
an experience is like requires nothing more than noticing the experience as it is undergone”
and, hence, requires “no ability to do anything other than to notice an experience” (1994: 139).
In response, Nemirow (2006: 35) suggests that in “stripping [Mary] of all ability to imagine
colour, Conee may have inadvertently denied her the knowledge at issue” on the grounds that
when attributing knowledge of what it is like to see a red tomato “to ordinary people who are
staring at a red tomato, we assume that they can activate a panoply of imaginative abilities”. It
is true that we make this assumption, as Conee acknowledges, as normally anyone who is
20
knowing the experience of seeing a red tomato as they have that experience would also have
the abilities Nemirow has in mind. But Conee’s thought, I take it, is that this connection looks
to be only a contingent connection, in which case we cannot identify knowing an experience
with those abilities. And Nemirow’s response doesn’t seem to do much more than just point to
the assumption that normally WIL-knowledge will be accompanied by such abilities, and so it
is not clear that he has addressed Conee’s objection.
At the heart of this dispute is, of course, Conee’s assumption that there is this distinctive way
of knowing an experience as one is having that very experience, which simply consists in
having the experience and noticing it. And if Conee’s argument against the ability hypothesis
is on the right track then it seems that we cannot analyse that knowledge in terms of the
possession of abilities to imagine, remember, and recognise experiences of that type. However,
as Conee himself discusses (1994: 139), his view is consistent with the idea that such abilities
could be involved in knowing an experience after the experience has ended. In which case, we
could see the acquaintance hypothesis as providing us with the correct account of the distinctive
objectual WIL-knowledge one can possess as one is having an experience, and the ability
hypothesis as providing us with the correct account of the objectual WIL-knowledge one can
possess after the experience has ended.
Of course, a proponent of the ability hypothesis would surely reject this split view of the
conditions needed to possess objectual WIL-knowledge. They might argue, for example, that
Conee is simply confusing properties of our experiences themselves—that they are a kind of
event and so cannot be identified with abilities as those are a kind of standing state as opposed
to an event—with properties of our knowledge of those experiences as they occur. So, a
proponent of the ability hypothesis might well grant to Conee the, in principle, possibility of
cases where someone has an experience without possessing any of Lewis’ abilities, but they
will maintain that in such a scenario one would not know what it is like to have that experience;
21
and then they could try to argue that any inclination we have to think otherwise is a confusion
stemming from the fact that normally the experience would always be accompanied by this
knowledge.
More could be said on these topics. But for my purposes we need not investigate these issues
further here, given that I want to focus on interrogative WIL-knowledge. In the remaining
discussion, I will simply take it as a working assumption that objectual WIL-knowledge cannot
be reductively analysed as a species of propositional knowledge, and that its correct analysis
will be one that analyses it at least partly in terms of either acquaintance and/or ability
knowledge.
2.4 Limitations of the Ambiguity Reply
The acquaintance and ability hypotheses might be plausible when we restrict them to the
objectual interpretation of knowing-WIL sentences, and as just discussed there may even be a
sense in which both accounts can provide us with partially correct analyses of objectual WILknowledge. Furthermore, as we saw in Section 2.2, the ambiguity versions of these hypotheses
have some initially attractive features insofar as they enable one to sidestep arguments for the
conclusion that knowing-WIL is a kind of knowing-that, and one can appeal to the ambiguity
thesis to defuse the apparent tension between the experience and answer conditions. However,
on closer inspection, I think that, for related reasons, the ambiguity versions of these hypotheses
cannot provide us with either a good reply to the knowledge argument, or a good way of
dissolving the tension between the experience and answer conditions.
The problem with respect to the knowledge argument is that it is not plausible that Mary would
only gain objectual WIL-knowledge, and not any propositional WIL-knowledge. When Mary
sees something red for the first time Conee acknowledges that she will make “an exciting
22
discovery. ‘Aha!’, she might well exclaim” (1994: 139), but Conee holds, of course, that this
discovery will consist solely in her becoming acquainted with the property of phenomenal
redness. However, as well as exclaiming ‘Aha!’ Mary might also say to herself “I always
wondered what it is like to see something red, and now I know!”. But the use of ‘wondered’
here forces the interrogative reading of ‘what it is like’ (Stoljar 2016) because wondering is a
relation to a question. What Mary wonders is what the answer might be to the question ‘what
is it like to see something red?’ indicating that when Mary becomes acquainted with
phenomenal redness for the first time, she not only comes to know that property itself, but she
also comes to know a new fact about that property (that this is what it is like to see something
red) which answers the question that was the object of her wondering prior to leaving her room.
As noted in Section 2.2, Conee seems to think that any such demonstrative knowledge-that is
knowledge Mary could already have possessed before leaving her room, on the grounds that
she could demonstratively refer to phenomenal redness in other ways (e.g., by demonstrating
the attentive experiences of another person). But, as Tye (2011: 306) discusses in relation to
similar cases, the state of demonstrative knowledge that pre-release Mary has when she knows
that that [demonstrating the occurrent experience of another person] is what it is like to see
something red is, intuitively, different from the state of demonstrative knowledge that postrelease Mary has when she knows that that [demonstrating her own occurrent experience] is
what it is like to see something red. How exactly to account for this difference is, of course, a
difficult matter (e.g., whether to account for it in terms of different demonstrative concepts of
some kind, or the same concept but still a different type of knowledge-that), and we will touch
on these issues in Section 3.2. But we shouldn’t let that difficulty obscure the point that,
intuitively, these are two very different states of knowledge.
Related issues undermine the ambiguity strategy for defusing the tension between the
experience and answer conditions. The problem with this strategy is that it is not plausible that
23
the intuitive case for the experience condition only applies to the objectual knowledge ascribed
by the free-relative interpretation of knowing-WIL ascriptions, and not the propositional form
of knowledge ascribed by the interrogative interpretation. For the natural explanation of why
Mary does not possess the relevant demonstrative knowledge-that prior to leaving her room is
that she has not yet had an experience of seeing something red, which suggests that
interrogative WIL-knowledge is subject to an experience condition. And, yet, knowing what it
is like to see something red (in the interrogative sense) is a matter of knowing that p for some
proposition p that answers the question ‘what is it like to see something red?’. So, the prima
facie tension between the experience and answer conditions remains for the form of knowledge
ascribed by the interrogative interpretation of knowing-WIL ascriptions.
3. Qualified Intellectualism
Turning to the epistemic states denoted by the interrogative interpretation of knowing-WIL
sentences it seems undeniable (once we acknowledge that there is such an interpretation) that
we should endorse the intellectualist view that these are states of knowing-that, where the
known proposition answers the relevant embedded WIL-question. But if we embrace the
answer condition like this, what are we to do about this remaining tension with the experience
condition?
One approach would be to argue that we should reject the experience condition outright for the
interrogative interpretation of knowing-WIL sentences, thereby endorsing the mirror image to
what proponents of non-propositional views of WIL-knowledge might try to say in response to
the apparent tension between these two theses. In due course we will consider reasons for
weakening and qualifying the experience condition in different ways but even then, we will
still be able to acknowledge that there are important truths in the vicinity of this idea that
24
interrogative WIL-knowledge is subject to an experience condition. And that is important,
because as we have just seen, the intuitions expressed by the experience condition arise for
interrogative WIL-knowledge and not just objectual WIL-knowledge. (Please note that from
here on any unqualified uses of ‘WIL-knowledge’ and ‘knowing-WIL’, should be taken as
referring to interrogative WIL-knowledge.)
Fortunately, rejecting the experience condition outright is not the only response that an
intellectualist can make to this tension between the experience and answer conditions. Another
strategy is to claim that knowing what it is like to Φ is not merely a matter of knowing some
proposition which answers the embedded WIL-question, but also satisfying some further
condition which explains why the experience condition is true, or at least why this principle is
intuitively appealing. So, on this kind of view WIL-knowledge is a species of knowing-that but
a distinctive species of it which involves the satisfaction of this further condition. This strategy
relies on the fact that the answer condition only tells us that knowing an answer to the
embedded WIL-question is a necessary condition for possessing WIL-knowledge, not that it is
both a necessary and a sufficient condition.
I think this kind of qualified intellectualism provides us with the best view of interrogative
WIL-knowledge. But there are notable issues that this broad kind of view needs to address.
One obvious set of issues concerns just what exact form of qualified intellectualism we should
endorse, including what kinds of propositions are thought to answer embedded WIL-questions,
and what further condition exactly will be added to the analysis of WIL-knowledge. Another
important, but I think overlooked, issue is how to address the following concern one could have
with qualified intellectualism: Why isn’t adding some kind of further condition to our analysis
of WIL-knowledge not just an ad hoc solution to the problem of analysing this form of
knowledge and addressing the tension between the experience and the answer conditions? In
this section I will consider how the qualified intellectualist position might be developed so that
25
it addresses the first set of issues, and then in the next section I will offer my on preferred form
of qualified intellectualism that can also address the ad hoc concern.
3.1 The Contents of WIL-Knowledge
What kinds of propositions does one know when one knows what it is like to Φ? A number of
views have been suggested but, for reasons of space, I will focus on just explaining some of
the key details of what I take to be the most plausible and well-developed theory, namely,
Stoljar’s (2016) affective theory of ‘what it is like’ expressions (including but not limited to
knowing-WIL sentences). To help introduce and motivate this view it will be useful to consider
how some other forms of knowing-wh are standardly analysed. For example, if we take
knowing-where, knowing-why, and knowing-how ascriptions it is often suggested that these
ascriptions respectively quantify over locations, reasons, and ways of performing actions. So,
consider the following sentences:
1a) Hannah knows where Bill is.
1b) Hannah knows why Bill left the party.
1c) Hannah knows how to ride a bike.
1d) Hannah knows what it is like to ride a bike.
A standard application of the question-answer semantics for knowing-wh2 would give the
something like the following truth conditions for sentence (1a)-(1d):
For simplicity I am just focusing here on the more dominant ‘mention-some’ reading of these sentences (where
one merely needs to know one answer to the embedded question), rather than the ‘mention all’ reading (where
one needs to know all its answers).
2
26
1a*) ‘Hannah knows where Bill is’ is true in a context c if and only if, in c, there is
some location l such that Hannah knows that Bill is at l.
1b*) ‘Hannah knows why Bill left the party’ is true in a context c if and only if, in c,
there is some reason r such that Hannah knows that r is the reason Bill left the party.
1c*) ‘Hannah knows how to ride a bike’ is true in a context c if and only if, in c, there
is some way w such that Hannah knows that w is a way for her to ride a bike.
Stoljar (2016: 1169-1170) thinks there are close connections between knowing-WIL
ascriptions like (1d) and other knowing-wh ascriptions like (1a)-(1c), and especially knowinghow ascriptions like (1c), as indicated by the fact that ‘what is it like’ questions can be very
close in meaning to ‘how’ questions. And, in line with those connections, Stoljar suggests that
knowing-how and knowing-WIL ascriptions both quantify over ways, with knowing-how
ascriptions quantifying over ways of performing actions, and knowing-WIL ascriptions
quantifying over ways of being affected by events. More specifically, Stoljar’s theory gives us
the following truth conditions for a sentence like (1e) above:
1d*) ‘Hannah knows what it is like to ride a bike’ is true in a context c if and only if, in
c, there is some way w such that Hannah knows that y’s bike riding affects x in way w.
There are two key elements in Stoljar’s theory: (i) the idea that WIL-sentences express affective
relations between subjects and events, and (ii) the claim that there are two subject positions—
one for an agent of the event, and one for an experiencer of the event—in the logical form of
the embedded question.
Affective relations are relations of an individual being affected in some way by the occurrence
of an event, where the relevant sense of ‘affect’ is a “modest” one on which “it means
something like ‘influence’ or ‘bring about a change or condition in’” (Stoljar 2016: 1173). This
modest notion of an affective relation helps Stoljar to explain the fact that we typically use
27
WIL-sentences to talk about experiences, whilst still managing to accommodate certain nonexperiential uses of WIL-sentences. Consider the following sentences:
(2a) What has it been like for the UK to leave the EU?
(2b) Mary knows what it has been like for the UK to leave the EU.
In many contexts, (2a) would be used to ask a question just about how the UK has been
economically or politically affected by the event of leaving the EU, as opposed to, say, how
the average UK citizen, or the UK as a collective, has been experientially affected by that event.
In which case, in such contexts, if we were to assert (2b) we would only be attributing
knowledge to Mary of some fact about how the UK has been economically or politically
affected by its leaving of the EU.
Still, while WIL-sentences can be used to talk about non-experiential ways of being affected
by an event, Stoljar maintains that the stereotypical use of such sentences is to talk about
experiential ways of being affected by events, where this is a matter of an individual feeling a
certain way in virtue of that event. On Stoljar’s theory then in a stereotypical context c a
sentence of the form “There is something it is like to ride a bike” will be true if and only if
there is, in c, some experiential way that y’s event/act of riding a bike affects x.
This example can also be used to illustrate Stoljar’s claim that the logical form of a WILexpression contains two argument positions: the standard one generated by the covert pronoun
in the infinitival ‘to ride a bike’ which identifies the agent of the event, and the further argument
position Stoljar posits for the finite clause ‘what it is like to ride a bike’ which identifies the
experiencer of the event. In most contexts these will naturally be interpreted as being one and
the same subject. So, if you ask me “Do you know what it is like to ride a bike?” and I respond
by saying “No” (as I have, in fact, never ridden a bike) I will usually be interpreted as either
communicating that I don’t know how my riding a bike would make me feel, or perhaps that I
28
don’t know how one’s riding a bike makes one feel, but not that I don’t know how, say, my
riding a bike would make Bob feel, or how Bob’s riding a bike would make me feel. However,
in certain contexts, the actor and experiencer positions can come apart. So, you might be
interested, for example, in knowing what it is like to me for my son to ride a bike (say, shortly
after he has first learnt to do so), and I might tell you that “it’s nerve wracking!” or “it’s
humbling” (thinking of my inability to do the same).
3.2 The Extra Condition
Stoljar’s affective theory has the significant virtue of being able to give an account of WILsentences which explains their intimate connections with how we think and talk about
experiences, whilst also being able to accommodate a range of different uses of these
expressions including non-experiential uses and uses where the experiencer of the event and
the subject of the event come apart.
However, a key limitation of the affective theory, which is also a limitation of all the main
competitors to this theory, is that such views purport to offer necessary and sufficient
conditions for possessing WIL-knowledge (or the truth of knowing-WIL ascriptions) but they
only seem to provide us with at best a necessary and not sufficient condition. The problem is
that there are many contexts where someone knows the right kind of answer to an embedded
‘what it is like to Φ’ question but, intuitively, does not know what it is like to Φ.
So, for example, Tye (2011) imagines pre-release Mary having access to a cerebroscope which
allows her to see an image Tye of the precise brain state that a person is in as they are having
an experience of seeing something red, and which “according to some physicalists, just is what
it is like to see something red” (2011: 305). If we assume, for the sake of argument, that the
relevant form of physicalism is correct, then Tye thinks pre-release Mary could know that that
29
[demonstrating the brain state displayed on the cerebroscope] is the way it feels to see
something red (I’m adjusting Tye’s example slightly here to fit with Stoljar’s semantics), and
she would thereby know a proposition that answers the question ‘what is it like to see something
red?’ but, intuitively, she still does not yet know what it is like to see something red, given that
she has not yet had the experience of seeing something red.
There are also more humdrum cases with this structure. Imagine Hannah, who has never ridden
a bike or even tried to ride a bike. Nonetheless, echoing Conee’s ideas discussed in Section 2.2,
Hannah might still know that it feels that way to ride a bike, where the demonstrative denotes
the way it feels to ride a bike for some person riding a bike past Hannah, or the way it feels to
ride a bike as described in a book that Hannah has read, etc. But, given that Hannah has never
experienced riding a bike herself, one might think, in line with the experience condition, that
she still does know what it is like to ride a bike.
To better understand how an intellectualist about knowing-WIL might try to solve this problem
it will be useful to compare it to the closely parallel, and better known, insufficiency problems
that arise for intellectualist views of knowing-how. So, in their well-known defence of
intellectualism about knowing-how (or, more specifically, knowing-how-to) Stanley and
Williamson (2001) initially give (1c*) as the truth conditions for (1c), that is, they hold that
knowing, for some way w, that w is a way one can ride a bike is both a necessary and sufficient
condition for knowing how to ride a bike. However, as Stanley and Williamson discuss, the
Hannah example looks to be an insufficiency counterexample to their analysis of the truthconditions for ‘S knows how to Φ’ sentences. For, looking at the person riding a bike near her,
Hannah can know that that way is a way for her to ride a bike. However, intuitively, Hannah
does not know how to ride a bike, given that she has never even tried to ride a bike and, hence,
lacks the ability.
30
To address this problem Stanley and Williamson suggest that we need to add a ‘practical mode
of presentation’ condition to either the semantic truth conditions for ‘S knows how to Φ’
sentences themselves, or to the pragmatic conditions for making felicitous assertions of such
sentences (in which case, it would be true but infelicitous, at least in certain contexts, to assert
that Hannah knows how to ride a bike).3 So, for example, if we added this condition to the truth
conditions of (1c), the idea is that they will now look like this:
(1d**) ‘Hannah knows how to ride a bike’ is true in a context c if and only if, for some
way w, Hannah knows, under a practical mode of presentation, that w is a way for her
to ride a bike.
Stanley and Williamson do not say a lot about what practical modes of presentation are, relying
instead on the claim that as we need some notion of modes of presentation more generally (e.g.,
to handle cases of de se knowledge) it is justifiable to posit their existence. However, crucially,
Stanley and Williamson do tell us that knowing, under a practical mode of presentation, that w
is way for oneself to ride a bike “will entail the possession of certain complex dispositions”
(2001: 429) which are surely dispositions connected in some way to the performance of
successful actions of riding a bike and are dispositions which Hannah lacks.
Stanley and Williamson also tell us that practical mode of presentations can be thought of either
as a constituent of a fine-grained ‘Fregean’ proposition, or as a special way of entertaining a
A reviewer asks how the ‘mention-all’ reading I put aside earlier (fn. 4) interacts with the insufficiency problem.
It is a good question because there will be some insufficiency cases where the explanation of why a subject lacks
some form of knowing-wh will be that the mention-all reading is at issue (e.g., I usually won’t count as knowing
who went to the meeting if all I know is that Stephanie was there). But that kind of move won’t help here. One
problem is that the ‘mention-all’ reading is implausible in most contexts where we ascribe knowing-how.
Furthermore, even if for every way to swim, say, one knew the relevant proposition of the form ‘w is a way to
swim’ the concern at issue here is that it seems possible to possess all that knowledge in a way that, intuitively,
does not suffice for knowing how to swim (e.g., by reading a book). What these points suggest is that the
insufficiency problem at issue here is to do with how we possess knowledge of an answer to an embedded question
(or perhaps knowing the right ‘fine-grained’ answer, see discussion above), rather than how many answers we
know.
3
31
coarse-grained ‘Russellian’ proposition in thought; where a coarse-grained proposition is just
an ordered sequence of objects and properties, whereas a ‘fine grained’ proposition also
contains something like Fregean senses. On the Fregean view, one could respond to the
insufficiency problem by claiming that knowing the right fine-grained answer to an embedded
‘how to Φ’ question will entail knowing how to Φ (Stanely 2011, Pavese 2015). On the
Russelian view, however, one grants that mere knowledge of any propositional answer to an
embedded ‘how to Φ’ question does not entail knowing how to Φ, but knowing the right
proposition, in the right way, does (Stanely and Williamson 2001). What both views have in
common is that they try to address the insufficiency problem by identifying knowing how to Φ
with a form of propositional knowledge (distinguished either by its content, or by the way in
which one entertains that content) which entails the possession of certain relevant dispositions
or abilities.
What might a similar reply to the insufficiency problem look like for the intellectualist about
WIL-knowledge? Following the structure of Stanley and Williamson’s view, we might use the
notion of a ‘knowing in a phenomenal way’ condition and then offer the following
reformulation of Stoljar’s affective theory:
‘S knows what it is like to Φ’ is true in a stereotypical context c if and only if, for some
way w, S knows, in a phenomenal way, that y’s Φ-ing feels a certain way w for x.
The phenomenal way of knowing condition here is stated as part of the semantic truth
conditions of knowing-WIL ascriptions. However, like Stanley and Williamson, I can be
neutral on whether this phenomenal way of knowing condition should be incorporated into the
semantics of knowing-WIL ascriptions as above or, alternatively, whether it should only find
a place in the pragmatics of such ascriptions, that is, as a condition on when it is
32
conversationally appropriate to make a knowing-WIL ascription. But, for simplicity, I will
often talk as if it is part of the truth conditions.
As with practical modes of presentation, this notion of a ‘phenomenal way of knowing’ should
be understood as a placeholder notion which can then be filled out in different ways. But,
roughly paralleling Stanley and Williamson’s claimed entailment from knowing under a
practical mode of presentation to possessing certain dispositions or abilities, one initial claim
one might make about this condition is that knowing, in a phenomenal way, that w is a way it
feels to Φ entails one’s having had an experience of Φ-ing oneself. Alternatively, one could
parallel the practical mode of presentation even more closely, and appeal to an entailment from
knowing, in a phenomenal way, that w is a way it feels to Φ to having Lewis’ abilities to
imagine, remember, and recognise experiences of Φ-ing. I will develop that latter idea in
Section 4.2 but for now I will focus on the former idea, as that is the one most often developed
in the literature (e.g., Tye 2011).
So, the suggestion for now will be that the insufficiency cases for WIL-knowledge can be
avoided because while Hannah can know that that way is a way it feels to ride a bike (or, more
precisely, “a way it feels to Hannah for her to ride a bike”), she does not know this proposition
in a phenomenal way, as that would entail her having had an experience of Φ-ing, and she has
not had such an experience. And one can also appeal to this condition to reconcile the tension
between the answer and experience conditions. For knowing in a phenomenal way entails
experience in line with the experience condition, but knowing-WIL is still at least partly a
matter of knowing an answer to the embedded WIL-question in line with the answer condition.
However, beyond this bare entailment claim, what more can been said to fill out this notion of
a phenomenal way of knowing? Following Tye (2011), one broad family of views we can
identify here are views according to which knowing, in a phenomenal way, that w is a way it
33
feels to Φ is a matter of (i) knowing that w is a way it feels to Φ, and (ii) this knowledge must
be based on one’s own direct acquaintance with w through one’s own experience(s) of Φ-ing.
But what is the relevant notion of ‘being based on’ here? One way of interpreting it would be
appeal to special experience/acquaintance dependent concepts of the way it feels to Φ and
require that one’s knowledge of an answer to the ‘what is it like to Φ’ must involve such a
concept. So, for example, Tye (2011: 313) endorses a view like this when he writes:
To know what it is like to experience red, one needs to know that
experiencing red is (phenomenally) like this, where the demonstrative
concept at play in one’s knowledge was introduced into one’s mental
economy via an act of attending to the relevant phenomenal character in
one’s own visual experience.
On Tye’s view knowing what it is like to experience red is a kind of knowing-that, but one
which is based in acquaintance knowledge in the sense that this knowledge-that involves a
demonstrative concept that was formed via one’s direct acquaintance with the phenomenal
character of one’s own visual experience. And Tye and Sainsbury (2012), develop an
‘originalist’ theory of concepts, on which concepts are distinguished partly by their origins,
which allows them to further support this idea that the demonstrative concept Mary forms using
the cerebroscope is a different concept from the demonstrative concept she forms when she
sees something red for the first time.
More generally, many notions of ‘phenomenal concepts’ could be appealed to explain why
knowing, in a phenomenal way, that w is a way it feels to Φ entails one having Φ -ed at some
point. This is because phenomenal concepts are often assumed to be experience entailing. As
Sundström (2011: 271) says: “phenomenal concept theorists typically claim that phenomenal
34
concepts are experience-dependent in the sense that, in order to possess a phenomenal concept
of some conscious state S one needs to oneself have experienced S.”
There are also ways of developing the ‘basing’ idea without appealing to any notion of special
concepts. Grzankowski and Tye (2019), for example, suggest that the relevant sense of ‘basing’
involved in possessing WIL-knowledge is the epistemic basing relation. Applying this idea to
post-release Mary, Grzankowski and Tye claim that her knowing what it is like to see
something red is not only a matter of her knowing the right proposition (as they think that prerelease Mary already knew all the same fine-grained propositions) but also “Mary’s reason for
believing that this is an experience of red…is the fact that she is acquainted with red through
her experience of it” (2019: 86).
4. Downstream Intellectualism
There are many ways then to develop the notion of a phenomenal way of knowing. But why
isn’t adding any such condition to our analysis of WIL-knowledge not just an ad hoc solution
to the tension between the answer and experience conditions and the related insufficiency
challenges faced by intellectualist accounts of WIL-knowledge? As noted in Section 1,
knowledge-that more generally is not subject to any similar kind of experience condition, so
why would this species of knowledge-that be (or at least appear to be) subject to such a
condition? What I want to do in this section is, first, introduce some broader ideas concerning
our concept of knowledge and knowledge ascribing practices, which I will then appeal to in
developing an intellectualist view WIL-knowledge that can reconcile the tension between the
answer and experience conditions whilst also addressing these ad hoc concerns.
35
4.1 Clients and Downstream Knowledge
Craig (1990) famously advocated for a new approach to epistemological inquiry. Craig
suggests that we start by identifying plausible hypotheses about the function of our concept of
knowledge, and then seek to provide analyses of the concept of knowledge that would explain
how that concept could serve that function (as opposed to what Craig takes to be standard
method which is trying to provide an analysis of our concept of knowledge that fits with our
intuitions about its extension and intension). Given the limits of what we can learn about our
environment just using our own faculties of perception and reason, Craig thought that as
inquirers we have a basic human interest in accessing the information that other people have
gained via their perceptual and reasoning faculties, which generates an interest in identifying
people who are reliable sources of information. And Craig’s hypothesis is that the central
function of our concept of knowledge is to serve our interests as inquirers in identifying reliable
informants.
However, in an illuminating discussion, Hawley (2011) explored how our concept of
knowledge—especially in relation to knowledge-how—can also be viewed as serving our
interests as clients where, unlike the inquirer, the client seeks people with knowledge not
because they want their information for themselves but because they want someone who can
reliably perform certain actions connected to that information. On this perspective then the
function of our concept of knowledge is to serve our basic human interests in identifying
reliable performers, rather than reliable informants. So, as Hawley points out, when I seek
someone who knows how to fix a leak it is often because I simply want someone who can
reliably perform controlled and intentional actions of fixing leaks, not because I want to know
how to fix a leak myself. For I might have this knowledge already but just not want to do the
work myself, or I may simply have no interest in acquiring this knowledge.
36
Craig’s talk of the function of a concept might seem elusive, and his own function hypothesis
is supported by a controversial state of nature argument. But, without taking any position on
Craig’s approach to epistemology, I think Craig and Hawley’s very different observations
about the interests served by our knowledge ascribing practices point us towards two
importantly different ways of thinking about what knowledge is, and the conditions that a
subject must meet to possess knowledge. Specifically, in other work (Cath 2023), I suggested
that the distinction between the inquirer and the client points us towards a distinction between
what I call upstream knowledge versus downstream knowledge.
To help explain this distinction, it is useful to make the orthodox (but by no means universal)
assumption that knowledge is a species of true belief, such that any state of knowledge is a
state of true belief but one which has certain further properties which ‘upgrade’ it into a state
of knowledge. Typically, when epistemologists try to analyse knowledge the further properties,
or conditions, that they reach for are ‘upstream’ properties, in the sense that they are properties
to do with the etiology of the true belief state. As Hookway (2006: 105) says the ‘‘features that
have been taken to be characteristic of knowledge have been backward-looking”. So, for
example, that the true belief was the output of a reliable belief forming process, or that it was
not based on an inference from a justified but false premise, or that it was based on good
evidence, and so on. However, when we turn to knowing how to Φ it is more natural to look to
‘downstream’ conditions connected to whether the true belief state is a state that is a reliable
guide to possible future actions of Φ-ing, which relates to the interests of the client.
If we focus in on a true belief that w is a way for oneself to Φ (the kind of content that features
in intellectualist analyses) the idea is that a subject S has upstream knowledge that w is a way
for S to Φ just in case they have a true belief that w is a way for S to Φ, and this state of true
belief has whatever upstream properties feature in one’s preferred analysis of knowledge. On
the other hand, a subject S has downstream knowledge that w is a way for S to Φ just in case
37
they have a true belief that w is a way for S to Φ, and this true belief state has further
downstream action-guiding properties such that S’s being in this true belief state will entail and
explain S’s having a reliable ability to intentionally Φ in normal circumstances. And one can
then plug in any existing account of how a true belief state could entail that one has such an
ability, including views which appeal to different notions of practical modes of presentation
(Pavese 2015, Stanley 2011), and accounts which appeal to practical ways of being in a
propositional attitude state (Waights Hickman 2019, Cath 2020).
The hypothesis then is that ‘S knows how to Φ’ ascriptions are often, and stereotypically, used
to attribute states of downstream knowledge to people. Note that this hypothesis is intentionally
neutral on the semantic value of ‘knows’ in ‘S knows how to Φ’ ascriptions. It could be, for
example, that in stereotypical contexts the semantic value is downstream knowledge and in
other contexts it is upstream knowledge. But it could equally be that it is always one or the
other epistemic state, and that when ‘S knows how to Φ’ ascriptions are used to attribute the
other state this is achieved via pragmatics rather than the semantic meaning of the sentence. I
will not take a stance on these options here. But if this use hypothesis is true then I think there
is a good informal sense in which we can say that knowing-how is a form of downstream
knowledge (the more precise claim being that one of the epistemic states that we use knowinghow ascriptions to identify is a form of downstream knowledge).
More importantly, intuitions about various hypothetical cases that feature heavily in debates
about the nature of knowing-how can be usefully illuminated using this hypothesis. These
include the insufficiency cases we discussed in Section 3.2, but also redundancy cases which
arguably show that knowing-that (as normally conceived) is not necessary for knowing-how.
This is because in these redundancy scenarios knowing-how is intuitively present despite a
standard condition on knowing-that not being met, like one’s true belief not being a
38
‘Gettierized’ true belief (Cath 2011, Poston 2009), or one’s true belief being a doxastically
justified true belief (Cath 2011, Carter and Navarro 2017).
With regards to the insufficiency cases, part of the explanation of why someone like Hannah
intuitively fails to know how to ride a bike relies on the point that her true belief that that way
[demonstrating the way that someone else riding a bike] is a way for her to ride a bike at best
only constitutes downstream, and not upstream, knowledge, given that her possession of this
true belief does not entail her having an ability to ride a bike intentionally in normal
circumstances. And then, given the hypothesis that knowing-how ascriptions are
paradigmatically used to attribute downstream knowledge, we can explain our intuition that
Hannah lacks knowledge-how in terms of a kind of default expectation that someone who
knows how to ride a bike will possess the relevant downstream knowledge and, consequently,
will be able to ride a bike in normal circumstances.
With regards to the redundancy cases, these are explained by the fact that the relevant kinds of
etiological properties that are absent in these cases—being a non-accidentally true belief or
being a doxastically justified belief—are irrelevant to whether it is a state that can reliably
guide actions of Φ-ing.
As just described, this upstream/downstream distinction only applies to the kind of
propositional true beliefs involved in knowing how to Φ. But there are good reasons to think
that the distinction will apply to propositional knowledge much more broadly. As Hawley
(2011: 288–9) discusses, there are redundancy cases for other forms of knowing-wh where,
intuitively, someone possesses knowing-wh even though their relevant true belief is a
Gettierised true belief. And, in these cases, one could offer a parallel explanation to that for
knowing-how of why this intuition is correct using the hypothesis that the relevant epistemic
state is a form of downstream knowledge.
39
There are also insufficiency cases for other forms of knowing-wh. Consider James who has a
true belief that the City Basement bookshop is on Flinders Street, but he has no ability to locate
that bookshop when in the Melbourne CBD as this proposition is essentially all he knows about
the location of the bookshop, and he is otherwise totally unfamiliar with the CBD area, etc.
Finding yourself lost with James it would be natural to say “you don’t know where the
bookshop is” or to criticise James if he had previously claimed to know where the bookshop
is, etc. And, again, the assumption that knowing-wh ascriptions are often used to identify
people who possess downstream true beliefs can explain our intuitions about these
insufficiency cases, as James’ true belief is not one that will enable him to reliably perform
successful actions of locating the bookshop. In which case, while James’ true belief might
constitute upstream knowledge (if it has the relevant upstream properties) it is, by definition,
not a state of downstream knowledge.
4.2 Knowing-WIL as Downstream Knowledge
But what about knowing-WIL? Can the client’s perspective and the idea of downstream
knowledge illuminate the insufficiency cases we find for WIL-knowledge, and the related
tensions between the answer and experience conditions? Here one might think that there is a
big disanalogy between the factors that generate the insufficiency cases for other forms of
knowing-wh and the factors that generate the insufficiency cases for knowing-WIL.
After all, the reason mere knowing-that seems to be insufficient for knowing how to Φ is that
knowing-how entails some kind of ability condition. But the reason mere knowing-that seems
to be insufficient for knowing what it is like to Φ is meant to be that this knowledge entails the
possession of an experience, not an ability. However, I think this disanalogy is superficial
because we can provide a deeper explanation of why mere knowing-that is insufficient for
40
knowing-WIL in terms of the client’s perspective and the hypothesis that knowing-WIL
ascriptions are used to track a form of downstream knowledge.
To see how Hawley’s perspective of the client can relate to WIL-knowledge recall Lewis’
abilities to imagine, recognise, and remember experiences of Φ-ing. Now imagine a head chef
who wants to choose one of her staff to replace her while she takes a holiday. In selecting
someone for this role one of the things this chef will be interested in is identifying a person
who possesses various forms of WIL-knowledge and the related abilities to imagine, recognise,
and remember the way various experiences feel. So, for example, they will want someone who
recognises what it is like to taste a dish which has too much salt, too little, or just the right
amount. And the head chef will want someone who can imagine what it would be like if you
added more umami flavouring to a dish, can recognise when their version of a dish tastes like
the one made by the head chef, and can remember what the head chef’s version of that dish
tasted like, etc. In seeking someone with these forms of WIL-knowledge and their associated
abilities, the head chef is not in the situation of Craig’s inquirer or apprentice (1990: 156) who
is trying to acquire knowledge or skills for themselves, as they already possess these forms of
knowledge and skills. Rather, the head chef is in the client’s situation, as they are seeking
someone who has certain forms of knowledge that will support that person in reliably
performing associated actions for the client.
A qualified intellectualist needs to reject either Lewis’ identification of knowing-WIL with the
abilities to imagine, remember, and recognise, or his assumption that these abilities do not
involve the possession of any propositional knowledge. But either way a qualified
intellectualist can allow that knowing what it is like to Φ is closely connected to, and even
entails, the possession of such abilities. Furthermore, they can endorse the following hypothesis
about our uses of knowing-WIL ascriptions paralleling the one about knowing-how given in
the previous section: ‘S knows what it like to Φ’ ascriptions are often, and stereotypically, used
41
to attribute relevant states of downstream knowledge. So, the idea is that when we make a ‘S
knows what it like to Φ’ ascription we are usually interested in identifying someone who not
only has a true belief about the way it feels to Φ, but who possesses that true belief in such a
way that they thereby possess certain relevant abilities, which following Lewis we can take to
be abilities of imagining, recognising, and remembering experiences of Φ-ing.
This idea can help us to explain: (i) why WIL-knowledge is subject to insufficiency cases where
someone knows a proposition that addresses the relevant embedded WIL-question but,
intuitively, does not know what it is like to Φ; (ii) why, in normal circumstances, WILknowledge is subject to a qualified experience condition; and (iii) why adding this version of
a phenomenal way of knowing condition to our intellectualist analysis is not just an ad hoc
response to these insufficiency cases and the tension between the answer and experience
conditions.
The explanation of (i) is that mere knowledge-that concerning the way it feels to Φ need not
suffice for one to have any relevant abilities to imagine, recognise, and remember experiences
of Φ-ing. We will look at these abilities more carefully in Section 4.3 below, which will help
us to unpack this idea in more detail. But for now, the basic idea should be clear. Suppose Mary
has never been to space but is reading an astronaut’s autobiography which includes a rich
description of the way it feels to walk on the moon. Reading this description Mary might think
to herself “so that [the feeling described in the book] is the way it feels to walk on the moon”
and this thought could easily constitute knowledge (assuming that the description in the book
is accurate, etc.). But Mary’s new knowledge-that will not suffice for her to have reliable
abilities to imagine and recognise the way it feels to walk on the moon, especially not when
compared to someone who has had that experience. In which case, given the assumption that
knowing-WIL ascription paradigmatically ascribe downstream knowledge, we will in many
42
contexts intuit that Mary’s new knowledge-that does not suffice for her to know what it is like
to walk on the moon.
The explanation of (ii) relates to Lewis’ claim that while experience is not the only possible
teacher when it comes to gaining WIL-knowledge and the abilities he identified that knowledge
with, it is the best teacher with respect to that knowledge and those abilities. That is, having an
experience of Φ-ing is usually the best, and often the only practicable, way to gain abilities to
imagine, recognise, and remember experiences of Φ-ing (these claims will be qualified
somewhat in Section 5, but not in a way that conflicts with the key ideas here). In which case
if knowing-WIL ascriptions are paradigmatically used to attribute a form of downstream
knowledge that entails the possession of such abilities then it makes sense that, in most
contexts, we will assume that having had such an experience is a requirement of someone’s
knowing what it is like to Φ.
The explanation of (iii) can start with the observation that if one thinks of WIL-knowledge as
a form of downstream knowledge then some relevant phenomenal way of knowing condition
will be an essential part of one’s intellectualist analysis, given that mere upstream knowledgethat will not suffice for one to possess Lewis’ abilities. Furthermore, the idea of downstream
knowledge is motivated by a much larger set of considerations concerning not only the truth
conditions of knowing-WIL ascriptions, but also knowing-wh ascriptions in general, and even
some uses of knowing-that ascriptions. And it is also motivated by Hawley’s related work on
the client’s interests in tracking reliable performers. From this perspective then the fact that
mere knowing-that often appears to be insufficient for possessing different forms of knowingwh, including but not limited to WIL-knowledge, can be given a unified explanation in terms
of how we use knowledge ascriptions to identify reliable performers.
43
What about redundancy cases? If the downstream-use hypothesis is correct then we might
expect there to also be redundancy cases for knowing-WIL, that is, cases where intuitively
someone possesses WIL-knowledge despite their relevant true belief failing to meet some
orthodox condition on knowing-that, like the anti-luck or justification condition. The possible
existence of such cases is almost never discussed in the literature—the one exception I know
being Currie (2020: 89)—but I do think there are such cases, and their existence provides
further support for the downstream-use hypothesis.
Imagine Jackson’s Mary again before she has left her room.4 One day pre-release Mary is told,
by a usually reliable source, that she will be given brief access to a previously locked cupboard
within her room, which contains thousands of closed white envelopes each of which contains
a red coloured sheet of paper. Unbeknownst to Mary, this information is wrong and all but one
of the envelopes has a green sheet of paper in it. Luckily, Mary happens to grab the one
envelope with a red sheet of paper in it, and then the cupboard is locked again. Looking now
at the red paper Mary comes to truly believe that this is the way it feels to see something red.
Doesn’t that true belief constitute a genuine state of knowledge for Mary, namely, knowledge
of what it is like to see something red? At least when the client’s perspective is salient (e.g., a
context where someone is concerned with whether Mary could now fetch them the red tube in
an unlabelled box of paints), I suspect we will find the intuition that she does possess this
knowledge, even though her true belief is ‘gettierized’ and hence she does not meet the standard
anti-luck condition on knowledge.
Some support for this position comes from the fact that Currie (2020) reaches similar
conclusions and gives his own example of a case where he thinks WIL-knowledge is present
in a Gettier-style situation. Furthermore, I think support for this idea that WIL-knowledge is
4
This case is adapted from one in Cath (2023).
44
consistent with Gettier-style luck can also be found in Lewis’ claim that experience is the best,
but not the only possible, teacher when it comes to WIL-knowledge.
When Lewis made this claim what he had in mind were cases where someone gains abilities to
imagine, recognise, and remember experiences of Φ-ing without ever having Φ-ed themselves.
The specific scenarios that Lewis imagined were metaphysically possible cases where, by
advanced neuroscience or magic (one could also appeal to cases involving incredible
coincidences like swampman), a person is put into the same underlying types of physical states
that someone comes to be in when they come to know what it is like smell a skunk on the basis
of having smelled a skunk themselves. Lewis assumes that in such a scenario this person would
know what it is like to smell a skunk, despite never having smelled a skunk themselves.
Lewis’ position here makes sense when we think of his abilities, or at least his abilities to
imagine and recognise, as these abilities are plausibly downstream states themselves. That is,
any etiological properties of how a person came to acquire a putative ability to imagine or
recognise what it is like to Φ are irrelevant to whether or not they actually possess that ability.
All that is relevant is, looking downstream, whether they would successfully imagine what it
is like to Φ-ing, or recognise an experience of Φ-ing, in certain relevant circumstances.
The case of the ability to remember experiences of Φ-ing is different though. Like any ability
it is a downstream state in the sense that possessing it is roughly a matter of whether someone
would successfully perform a certain kind of action in the right circumstances. However, for a
mental action to be an action of remembering an experiencing of Φ-ing one must satisfy the
upstream condition of having had such an experience at some point in the past. So, in the
neuroscience and magic situations that Lewis imagines the subject would only have an ability
to have apparent memories of smelling a skunk.5 But given that Lewis thinks that such a
5
One might object that even a newly materialised swampman has the ability to remember experiences they have
not had yet. After all, while I have never travelled to India, surely, I have the ability to remember what it is like
45
subject would still know what it is like to smell a skunk, it seems he was at least inclined not
to take the ability to have genuine memories of the experience of Φ-ing to be a necessary
condition for knowing what it is like to Φ. Also, later in his discussion Lewis (1998: 98) notes
the possibility that over time one might lose one’s ability to remember one’s past experiences
of eating vegemite whilst still retaining one’s ability to imagine experiences of eating vegemite.
And while Lewis does not explicitly state that in such a circumstance one would still know
what it is like to taste vegemite, in context it reads (to me at least) that he is assuming that
would be the case. Anyway, regardless of how we should interpret Lewis, I think the above
considerations suggest that the ability to remember experiences of Φ-ing may not be a strictly
necessary condition for knowing what it is like to Φ although usually we would expect someone
who knows what it is like to Φ to have this ability (for this reason I will often talk of the memory
condition as if it is on an equal footing to the imagination and recognition conditions).
4.3 Objectual Abilities
To further clarify and fill out this proposal that WIL-knowledge is a form of downstream
knowledge, I want to say more now about how I think we should interpret these abilities to
imagine, remember, and recognise. One simple point about how to interpret the ability to
imagine condition is that it involves an ability to imagine the experience of Φ-ing itself—or,
equivalently, imagine the way it feels to Φ itself—rather than just a mere ability to, say, imagine
that the experience of Φ-ing is like such-and-such. So, if you eat Dutch liquorice for the first
to travel in India, I have just never had the opportunity to exercise it. But this worry merely reveals the care we
need to take in making ability ascriptions, given that they are always evaluated relative to contextually relevant
sets of circumstances which are often left unstated. So, I have the ability to remember what it is like to travel in
India in circumstances where I have travelled in India. For if I were to travel in India I could form and later recall
memories of how it felt. But I do not have the ability to remember travelling in India in my currently normal
circumstances. For those circumstances are ones in which I have never travelled to India, so I have no memories
to recall of India and how it feels to travel there. And it is this kind of ability that matters to Lewis (as otherwise
he would have to say that Mary has the ability to remember experiences of seeing something red before leaving
her room).
46
time afterwards it is true that you will be able to imagine that the experience of eating Dutch
liquorice is comparable to experiences of eating other very salty things. But that is an ability
you would’ve had before ever eating Dutch liquorice, and it is not the kind of ability at issue
here. Rather, the relevant ability that you gain is an ability to imagine the way it feels to eat
Dutch liquorice itself, you can in some sense make that taste experience present to one’s mind
again.
This clarification relates to the fact that Lewis (1998: fn. 12) regards the ability to imagine,
remember, and recognise an experience E as being just the same thing as an ability to imagine,
remember, and recognise what it is like to have experience E. Note that when described in the
latter way the same ambiguity that we found in knowing-WIL ascriptions will arise for these
ability conditions given the use of ambiguous ‘what it is like’ phrase. That is, if we take the
ability to imagine what it is like to Φ condition, for example, and where w is the way it feels to
Φ, we can interpret this ability as either: (i) an ability to imagine that w is the way it feels to
Φ, or (ii) an ability to imagine w itself.6 And the suggestion just made is that the objectual
interpretation (ii) is the relevant one when interpreting the ability to imagine condition.
What is involved in making an experience of Φ-ing present to one’s mind through one’s
imagining of that experience? Roughly following Paul (2015b: 476)—who suggests that when
we have a new experience, we gain abilities to “imagine, recognize, and cognitively model
possible future experiences of this kind”—I take it that the relevant idea is one of cognitive
modelling or simulating an experience in one’s imagination. So, when one imagines, say, the
experience of eating Dutch liquorice that mental event of imagining is an imagining of that
target experience in part because it itself possesses some of the same phenomenal properties as
that target experience.
6
For discussion see D’Ambrosio and Stoljar (2021).
47
The ability to remember the experience of eating Dutch liquorice will then be analysed in the
same way but when one simulates that experience in one’s imagination, that imagining must
relate one in some appropriate way to one’s own past experiences of eating Dutch liquorice.
The recognition ability should also be interpreted as an ability to recognise an experience itself,
rather than just recognise that p, for some proposition p concerning the way it feels to Φ. So, if
one knows what it is like to have a panic attack, having had panic attacks before, then if one
has that experience again one may well recognise the experience itself—that is, one will
recognise the feeling involved in having a panic attack—rather than merely recognising that,
say, the experience one is having is an experience of having a panic attack; as even if one had
never had a panic attack before one might recognise that one is having a panic attack on the
basis of one’s prior knowledge of the typical causes and symptoms involved in a panic attack.
When it comes to possessing objectual WIL-knowledge it might suffice to possess these
abilities to objectually imagine, remember, and recognise the relevant experience. But as
interrogative WIL-knowledge is a form of propositional knowledge one will also need an
ability or disposition to make relevant propositional judgments when one exercises these
objectual abilities. So, possessing interrogative knowledge of what it is like eat Dutch liquorice
is not only a matter of having an ability to bring that experience to mind, but being able to form
an occurrent judgement that this is the way it feels to eat Dutch liquorice when one imagines,
remembers, or recognises that experience.
The full view here then is that interrogative WIL-knowledge is a form of downstream
knowledge defined in terms of abilities to objectually imagine, remember, and recognise
experiences, and an ability to make relevant propositional judgments when exercising those
abilities. And the relevant forms of objectual imagining and remembering will be objectual and
simulative in the way defined above, that is, the imagining shares some phenomenal properties
48
with the target experience, and it is an imagining of that experience at least partly in virtue of
simulating it.
There are two further qualifications we need to make about this notion of objectually and
simulatively imagining an experience. One obvious qualification is that ‘bringing an
experience to mind’ again in one’s imagination is not the same thing as actually having that
experience again. This point can be accommodated nicely within the framework of mental
simulation because, in general, simulations almost always differ in significant ways from what
they simulate. Think of, say, the differences in scale between a physical model of an America’s
Cup yacht used for testing in a wind tunnel versus the actual yacht it is a simulation of, or the
deep ontological differences between the actual yacht and a computer simulation of it.
Similarly, when it comes to simulating an experience in one’s imagination, we should expect
the relevant event of imagining to differ in notable ways from the target experience that it is a
simulation of. And candidate differences might be that the imagining is typically less vivid and
intense, and it may lack many of the phenomenal properties possessed by the target experience
and/or possess other phenomenal properties (e.g., connected to the characteristic
phenomenology of imagining) not possessed by the target experience, etc. Nonetheless, as the
simulative imagining will share some actual phenomenal properties with the relevant target
experience—rather than, say, sharing mere structural properties—there is still a good sense in
which we can say that one is bringing the experience to mind when one imagines it in this way.
And a notable consequence of these points is that someone’s ability to simulatively imagine an
experience can be evaluated as more or less accurate, depending on how closely the
phenomenal properties of the imaginings one has when one exercises that ability match those
of the target experience itself (this idea will be important in Section 5.4).
The other qualification is that when an experience is sufficiently complex then one may only
be able to imagine different parts of that complex experience at any one time. Consider the
49
difference between simple sensory experiences—like, say, the experience of smelling basil,
seeing something green, or hearing a D flat note played on a piano—versus experiences that
have very complex structures involving lots of different events over time and different sensory
modalities and emotional and cognitive phenomenology—like, say, the experience of
exploring Tokyo as a tourist, or being a parent, or grieving the loss of a loved one.
The way it feels to have one of these simple experiences is, arguably, something that can be
fully present to one’s mind at one time, so when you have an experience of smelling basil the
phenomenal properties which constitute that experience are fully present to one’s mind. But
this is not the case with the more complex experiences. For such experiences don’t feel just
one specific way, as these experiences are composed of lots of different sub-experiences which
have different phenomenal properties, which are not instantiated together at any one time. So,
when we talk about the way these complex experiences feel we will normally be talking about
a range of different sub-experiences that can be involved in that complex experience, and their
constituent phenomenal properties, or perhaps one of the sub-experiences which is especially
salient when people think about the relevant type of experience—like, say, the distinctive
feelings of love, concern, and responsibility, that are paradigmatically
involved in the
experience of being a parent (Paul 2015b: 485).
Now think about what is involved in objectually imagining or remembering one of the simple
versus one of the complex experiences. When one simulatively imagines or remembers an
experience of, say, tasting something lemony you don’t literally have such an experience. But
with simple experiences like that there is still a good sense in which you are imagining the full
way it feels to have that experience, it is just that your mental act of imagining manages to have
that full experience as its direct intentional object despite only being a partial simulation of it.
However, when you imagine or remember a more complex experience, like say the experience
of exploring Tokyo, you imagine that complex experience more indirectly in the sense that you
50
succeed in imagining it by imagining different sub-experiences involved in that complex
experience and partially simulating their respective phenomenal properties. So, if you have
explored Tokyo and then you try to reimagine that experience you might first remember the
way it feels to walk around the Shibuya scramble, and then you might move to reimagining the
way it feels to wander down the quieter back street streets, and so on. And as you do this your
cognitive modelling of the complex experience will likely draw upon, and perhaps be partially
constituted by, propositional imaginings and semantic memories, as well as simulative
imaginings and memories.
4.4 Phenomenal Concepts and Downstream Intellectualism
Unlike other forms of qualified intellectualism, the view of downstream intellectualism
developed above made no appeal to any notion of special concepts. It is worth clarifying then
that downstream intellectualism is consistent with the idea that WIL-knowledge involves the
possession of phenomenal concepts. It is true that accounts of phenomenal concepts on which
they are experience entailing do not fit naturally with downstream intellectualism given that
entailing that one has had an experience of Φ-ing is kind of upstream condition (at least for
standing states of WIL-knowledge possessed after the relevant experience has ended). But there
are other accounts of phenomenal concepts which fit more naturally with downstream
intellectualism because they characterise phenomenal concepts in terms of upstream
recognitional abilities. And the view of the phenomenal concepts recently offered by Lee
(2023) fits nicely with downstream intellectualism because it is a view on which a phenomenal
concept of an experience is a mental representation of it that is: (i) defined in terms of its
psychological role in enabling not only abilities to recognise such experiences and think about
what they are like, but also to imagine these experiences, and (ii) possessing such a concept
does not entail having had such an experience oneself.
51
A proponent of downstream intellectualism might appeal then to Lee’s account of phenomenal
concepts as part of an explanation of how states of WIL-knowledge can entail the possession
of abilities to imagine and recognise, with the idea being that one has to not only know a
proposition that answers the embedded WIL-question but in possessing that knowledge one
has to possess a phenomenal concept. But a downstream intellectualist may also choose not to
build an account of phenomenal concepts into their view, and there might be advantages to
doing that.
Again, there are useful comparisons with issues in the knowing-how literature. As discussed in
Section 3.2, one way of developing a qualified intellectualism for knowing-how is to appeal to
some disposition-entailing notion of a practical mode of presentation. Those moves are quite
closely analogous then to Lee’s (2023) notion of phenomenal concepts as a special abilityenabling concept of the way it feels to have the relevant experience. But in the knowing-how
literature not all qualified intellectualists appeal to practical modes of presentation. Rather,
some appeal to practical ways of being in a propositional attitude state (Waights Hickman 2019,
Cath 2020), rather than practical constituent concepts of the propositional content of that state,
or practical ways of entertaining that content in thought. Cath (2020), for example, offers a
view on which being in the relevant propositional attitude state is itself a matter of possessing
certain practical dispositions, and one might offer a similar view in explaining how the true
belief states involved in possessing WIL-knowledge entail abilities to imagine and recognise.
Relatedly, these versions of qualified intellectualism for knowing-how and WIL-knowledge,
which eschew practical/phenomenal concepts or modes of presentation, could be motivated by
similar concerns including the desire to sidestep arguments that such special concepts or modes
52
of presentation simply do not exist7 or that these notions ultimately do not help to address the
problems they are introduced to address.8
These choices are related to much larger choices between different accounts of the contents
and nature of propositional attitude states, and their relation to the sets of dispositions or
abilities they are most closely associated with. For example, we might think of these
dispositions or abilities as something that is distinct from and explained by relevant
representational and/or functional properties of the propositional attitude state. Or,
alternatively, we think might of the propositional attitude state as something partly constituted
by those dispositions or abilities, as on dispositional theories of the attitudes like Schwitzgebel
(2013). I will not wade into these deeper waters here, for it will suffice to note that downstream
intellectualism could be developed in different ways depending on one’s positions on these
larger issues.
5. Testimony and Partial WIL-Knowledge
In What It Is Like to Go to War the Vietnam War Veteran Karl Marlantes aims “to explain what
it was like for me to go to war” (2011: 255). And Marlantes makes it clear in his introduction
that part of the audience that he wants to share his WIL-knowledge with includes people who
have never been to war themselves, especially young people considering whether to enlist, and
politicians deciding whether to send young people to war. From the perspective of the answer
condition alone, Marlantes’ aspirations make perfect sense. For Marlantes knows what it is like
to go to war, which means that he knows true propositions that answer the question ‘what is it
7
See e.g., Ball (2009).
8
See e.g., Glick (2015).
53
like to go war’ and he wants to share those answers with other people through his words. And
Marlantes’ ambition to communicate his WIL-knowledge is no aberration, as a bit of googling
(try searching for ‘what is it like’ or ‘how does it feel’) quickly reveals lots of apparent attempts
to do the same in books, youtube videos, blogs, articles, etc.
More generally, knowing-that and knowing-wh (Poston 2016) can often be shared via
testimony, at least in suitably favourable circumstances (e.g., where the hearer has good reasons
to trust the speaker, and is not aware of any defeaters for those reasons). So, if Sarah knows
that the play starts at 8pm, and Sarah tells Sam this then, if she didn’t already know this fact,
Sam can easily come to know that the play starts at 8pm on the basis of Sarah’s testimony.
And based on this same testimony Sam can also come to know when the play starts, given the
plausible assumption that knowing when the play starts is just a matter of knowing a relevant
propositional answer to the question ‘when does the play start?’. Similarly, if Sarah knows who
is playing the lead role in the play, and she tells Sam this, then Sam can come to also know
who is playing the lead role on the basis of Sarah’s testimony, etc. In which case, if we follow
the answer condition and think of WIL-knowledge as a form of knowing-wh that can be
analysed in terms of knowing-that—like knowing where, when, who etc.—then it seems we
should expect that WIL-knowledge can also be shared via testimony. And similar points can
be made for other forms of acquiring knowledge of propositions that answer a WIL-question
without having the relevant experience oneself, including consulting sources like films or
novels, or theories about the subjective character of such experiences, and so on.
But from the perspective of the experience condition, Marlantes’ aspirations seem futile. For if
WIL-knowledge requires experience then it cannot be transmitted or acquired from mere
testimony. And the strong intuitions that support the experience condition often find expression
in claims that WIL-knowledge cannot be communicated or gained through testimony or other
sources that do not involve having the relevant experience. So, Paul (2014: 13) expresses this
54
outlook when she writes that what we learn from the case of Mary is that “stories, testimony,
and theories aren’t enough to teach you what it is like to have truly new types of experiences—
you learn what it is like by actually having an experience of that type.”
The tension between the experience and answer conditions then seems to be reflected in a
tension in our attitudes and practices concerning the relationship between WIL-knowledge and
testimony. Now in Section 4, I argued that we can reconcile the apparent tension between the
experience and answer conditions by viewing WIL-knowledge as a form of downstream
knowledge. And one can appeal to that same framework again here to explain why WILknowledge cannot be easily acquired through testimony in a way that is consistent with the
answer condition. The idea will be that WIL-knowledge cannot be easily acquired from mere
testimony because it is a form of downstream knowledge that involves the possession of Lewis’
abilities, and obviously such abilities cannot be easily acquired through mere testimony. If you
tell me what it is like to eat durian, I might acquire some knowledge of truths about the way it
feels to eat durian, but I will not thereby acquire an ability to imagine the experience of eating
durian. And, more generally, any view on which WIL-knowledge is not only a matter of
knowing the right kind of proposition, but knowing it in a phenomenal way, can likely appeal
to that phenomenal way of knowing condition to explain why WIL-knowledge cannot be
shared through testimony.
But now our apparent practices of trying to share and acquire WIL-knowledge through
testimony present a challenge to such views, for if WIL-knowledge is partly a matter of
possessing abilities that cannot be acquired through testimony, why do we sometimes act as if
such knowledge can be acquired through testimony? I think this challenge reveals that the
framework offered in Section 4 requires further qualifications and supplementations if it is to
accommodate the full range of our attitudes and practices concerning how we think about and
ascribe WIL-knowledge. In particular, what we need to bring in and develop is the idea that
55
WIL-knowledge can come in different degrees and grades—that there can be partial WILknowledge—and then we need to examine how this idea can help us to resolve these tensions
in our attitudes and practices concerning the possibility of acquiring WIL-knowledge through
testimony and other means that do not require one to have had the experience in question.
5.1 Degrees of Knowing-Wh
It is easy to think of WIL-knowledge as a binary, all or nothing, matter. Either you have had
the experience, in which case you will know what it is like, or you haven’t, in which case you
won’t. Obviously, this outlook relates to the intuitions that support the experience condition,
and even if one agrees with Lewis that it is metaphysically possible to know what it is like to
Φ without having had an experience of Φ-ing, one might still think there is always a sharp
divide between those who have such knowledge, and those who do not.
But our discussion already contains materials which suggest that this binary view is too
simplistic, and that we should expect there to be good sense in which we can distinguish
different degrees and grades of WIL-knowledge. So, for example, one way of motivating the
degree view for WIL-knowledge is by noting that Lewis’ abilities look like abilities that one
can possess to different degrees. In which case, if possessing WIL-knowledge is partly a matter
of possessing such abilities one might expect that WIL-knowledge will in turn come in degrees.
We’ll look at this idea more carefully in Section 5.4.
A different, but complimentary, way to motivate the degreed view is to appeal to the answer
condition and the fact that other forms of knowing-wh typically come in different degrees. This
point relates to the linguistic fact that knowing-wh ascriptions are usually gradeable (Pavese
2017). This means such ascriptions can be modified by degree and adverbial modifiers like
‘largely’, ‘in part’, ‘well’, ‘very well’, and ‘better than’. So, for example, we might say
56
‘Marama knows in part why the Roman Empire fell’ if Marama knows some, but not all, of the
reasons why the Roman Empire fell. Or we might say ‘Marama knows how the Roman Empire
collapsed better than Ari’ if Marama knows more facts than Ari does about the way in which
the Roman Empire collapsed. And as Pavese (2017) demonstrates in detail we can explain how
knowing-wh comes in degrees in a way that is consistent with the assumption that knowingwh can be analysed in terms of knowing-that, even if we assume (as is common) that knowingthat itself does not come in degrees. For the idea is not that knowing that p comes in different
degrees, but that knowing-wh comes in different degrees because there can be more than one
propositional answer to an embedded wh-question, so we can comparatively evaluate the
different answers one might know to such a question with respect to how informative these
answers are.
Given that knowing-WIL ascriptions are ascriptions of knowing-wh we should expect then to
find that similar gradable constructions can be made for knowing-WIL. And that is the case.
So, I might say ‘Stephanie knows what it is like to live in Australia better than I do’ because,
while both of us live in Australia, she has lived here all her life, and has seen much more of the
country than I have, while I only moved to Australia as an adult. Or we might say ‘Unlike Ari,
Marama only knows in part what it is like to live with cancer’ if, say, Ari has been living
through cancer treatments for a long time, whereas Marama has just received her diagnosis.
These considerations suggest then that we should expect WIL-knowledge to come in different
degrees (e.g., being more/less complete or precise) and grades (e.g., being evaluated as
better/worse than someone’s else’s WIL-knowledge).
57
5.2 Gold, Silver, and Bronze WIL-knowledge
In earlier work (Cath 2019) I unpacked one way that WIL-knowledge can come in different
degrees by drawing a tripartite distinction between what I called gold, silver, and bronze
knowledge of propositions of the form ‘w is a way it feels to Φ’. Applied to the example of
going to war, I characterised these three forms of knowledge like so:
Gold WIL-Knowledge. There is some way such that Mary knows that this way is a way
that it feels to go to war, and Mary knows this proposition in a phenomenal way, in the
sense that her concept of that way originated in acts of directly attending to the phenomenal
properties of her own experiences of going to war.
Silver WIL-Knowledge. There is some way such that Mary knows that this way is a way
that it feels to go to war, and Mary knows this proposition in a phenomenal way, in the
sense that her concept of that way originated in acts of directly attending to the phenomenal
properties of her own experiences distinct from, but relevantly similar to, the experience of
going to war (which she has not had).
Bronze WIL-knowledge. There is some way such that Mary knows that this way is a way
that it feels to go to war, and Mary knows this proposition in some non-phenomenal way.
Gold WIL-knowledge is the kind of knowledge of experience connected to the intuitions which
support the experience condition. Adapting ideas from Tye (2011), I suggested that to possess
gold WIL-knowledge one must have a concept of the way it feels to Φ which originated in acts
of attending to one’s own experiences of Φ-ing. So, Mary has gold WIL-knowledge just in case
she not only knows a relevant proposition of the form ‘w is a way it feels to go to war’ but her
knowledge involves a concept of the way it feels to go to war which was formed in response
to her own experiences of going to war. This is a kind of ‘upstream’ way of developing a
phenomenal mode of knowing condition which will entail the experience condition. In Section
5.4, I will consider how to think of this gold, silver, bronze, framework in a way that it more
58
clearly fits with the downstream version of intellectualism I offered in Section 4. But before
doing that, it will be useful to just set up the gold, silver, bronze distinctions on their own terms,
and then show (Section 5.3) how they can help to solve the puzzles around testimony.
At the other end of the spectrum from gold WIL-knowledge is bronze WIL-knowledge.
Consider someone who has never been to war but who wants to learn something about what it
is like to have that experience. What can do they do? Well, they might read Marlantes’ book,
and then they could go further and consult literature, art, or movies, or they might read the
books of Nancy Sherman (e.g., Sherman 2010), a philosopher who has not been to war herself,
but who is a prominent expert on the subjective experiences involved in going to war and
returning to civilian life, and has interviewed hundreds of veterans about their experiences.
Merely gaining this second-hand knowledge will typically not put one in a position to satisfy
the kind of phenomenal ways of knowing conditions that qualified intellectualists add to their
theories to accommodate the intuitions that support the experience condition. But consulting
sources like testimony, stories, and theories can provide one with knowledge of propositions
of the form ‘w is a way it feels to go to war’ that answer the embedded WIL-question ‘what is
it like to go to war?’. And, in that sense, it can be considered a form of WIL-knowledge.
Importantly, however, even if one has not been to war there are still ways in which one’s
knowledge of truths of the form ‘w is a way it feels to go to war’ could satisfy a kind of
phenomenal way of knowing condition. These are the cases I called silver WIL-knowledge.
So, in contrast to mere bronze WIL-knowledge, one might not only consult the books of
Marlantes and Sherman, or Remarque’s famous novel All Quiet on the Western Front, but one
might also have had relevantly similar experiences that one could now relate to the target
experience of going to war based on what one has learned from such sources. If Mary had been
an ambulance officer, for example, she might have had relevantly similar experiences of
dealing with people in a state of shock, seeing traumatic injuries and witnessing their effects
59
on people and feeling one’s own emotional reactions to those situations, etc. When reading
about what it is like to go to war, Mary might note certain similarities between her own
experiences and certain experiences involved in going to war, and that could help her to not
only know, of some way w, that w is a way it feels to go to war, but she could also possess that
knowledge in a phenomenal way. For Mary could possess that knowledge in a way which
draws upon her abilities to simulatively imagine and remember the way it feels to have these
relevantly similar experiences.
So, Mary, might use her own experiences as “samples”—in the sense discussed by Walton
(2015)—judging the way it feels to go to war must feel, in part, like this, where the
demonstrative either picks out certain phenomenal properties of her relevantly similar
experiences as an ambulance officer as she is having those experiences (this is the kind of case
Walton discusses) or, more likely, her experiences of simulatively imagining or remembering
such experiences (Cath 2019, 2022). Or the demonstrative might just pick out features of
Mary’s attempt to imagine the target experience of going to war directly (rather than imagining
the similar experiences and then judging that they are like the target experience), but where
that attempt draws on her abilities to imagine and remember these distinct but relevantly similar
experiences. Kind (2020) introduces the useful concept of imaginative scaffolding for this kind
of process whereby one imagines a target experience one has not had by way of making
additions, subtractions, and modifications to one’s imaginings of experiences that one has had.
So, Mary might try to imagine the way it feels to be in a combat situation directly but achieve
a more accurate and informative imagining of that experience than someone who had never
had any relevantly similar experiences. The role of sources like testimony, stories, and theories,
in supporting this kind of silver WIL-knowledge is that it can serve as a guide to one’s attempts
at imagining the target experience, and at drawing the right connections between one’s past
experiences and the target experience.
60
Importantly, there may be principled limits to what kinds of experiences we can gain silver
WIL-knowledge of. As Kind (2020) and Werner (2023) discuss it might be that some
experiences, like simple sensory experiences, are “undifferentiated wholes” (Kind 2020: 153)
or “atomic experiences” (Werner 2023: 177) which lack any phenomenal structure or
complexity. And if that is the case then there may be no relevant shared properties between this
simple experience and other experiences, which someone who had only had the later
experiences could use as a basis for imagining the simple experience. As Kind notes, whether
there are any atomic experiences like this is not clear, and prima facie candidates may turn out
to have more complex structures on closer inspection. But if there are atomic experiences this
might help to explain why, barring the kinds of remote possibilities that Lewis discussed
(involving magic or future neuroscience), it seems to be a plausible hypothesis about human
psychology that some kinds of very simple experiences (like seeing something red) can’t be
simulatively imagined without having had an experience of that kind oneself. In which case, it
may be that a restricted version of the experience condition is true where it is restricted both to
normal circumstances, to rule out the remote possibilities that Lewis discussed, and to atomic
experiences, to rule out cases where one succeeds in obtaining partial WIL-knowledge via
one’s distinct but relevantly similar experiences.
Returning to bronze WIL-knowledge, it is worth clarifying that in saying that bronze WILknowledge is non-phenomenal the idea is not that any associated occurrent judgments would
lack any phenomenal properties, rather the idea is just that one’s knowledge does not draw
upon one’s acquaintance with the phenomenal properties of one’s own experiences in either of
the respective ways described for gold and silver WIL-knowledge. So, the notion of bronze
WIL-knowledge is consistent with possible views on which all knowledge might be said to be
phenomenal in a certain sense, like, say, a view on which knowing that p will always involve
61
a disposition to form a conscious judgment that p which has some kind of cognitive
phenomenology.
It is also worth noting that bronze WIL-knowledge itself can come in degrees (Cath 2019: 11).
So, consider two people each of whom has been studying the subjective experiences involved
in going to war, but neither of whom has been to war themselves and neither of them have had
any relevantly similar experiences which that they can draw on in conceptualising the
experiences involved in going to war. But one of these people has simply read and studied more
than the other, such that the first person has studied only the negatively valenced feelings
involved in going to war, whereas the second has studied those and the positively valenced
feelings (like feelings of elation that people can have during combat experiences). In this
situation it would make sense to say that the second person knows more about what it is like to
go to war than the first. The difference between these two subjects is a difference in the quantity
of information that they possess, that is, it is a difference in the number of answers they know
to the WIL-question, or the completeness of the answers that they know. On the other hand,
the differences between gold, silver, and bronze WIL-knowledge also concern the quality of
those answers or one’s epistemic access to those answers. And, as Pavese (2017) discusses,
knowing-wh ascriptions in general are gradeable in both quantitative and qualitative senses so
this, again, fits with more general patterns of how we ascribe knowing-wh.
5.3 Solving the Testimony Puzzles
The solution to the puzzles around testimony is implicit in the ideas just discussed but its exact
form needs to be spelled out carefully. The solution, as I will develop it here, appeals to just
two key ideas. The first idea is that in stereotypical contexts, a ‘S knows what it is like Φ’
ascription (on its interrogative interpretation) will be judged to be true just in case the subject
62
knows a relevant proposition, and they also possess this knowledge in a phenomenal way. This
idea is then used to explain the force, and partial correctness, of our intuitions about the inability
to acquire WIL-knowledge from testimony; with that explanation differing in some of its
details depending on whether we ultimately analyse the phenomenal way of knowing condition
in terms of a requirement that either directly entails that we have had certain experiences, or
that entails that we have certain abilities, as I advocated in Section 4.
If we go with the former idea, then we will explain the intuitions about WIL-knowledge not
being transmittable via testimony in terms of the stereotypical use claim and the inability of
testimony to transmit experiences. For on this approach the phenomenal way of knowing
condition entails that one has gold WIL-knowledge which, of course, requires one to have had
an experience of Φ-ing. On the other hand, if we go with the latter idea—which I take to be the
better one given the considerations discussed in Section 4 and also below in this section—then
we will explain the intuitions about WIL-knowledge not being transmittable via testimony in
terms of the stereotypical use claim and the difficulty of acquiring abilities through mere
testimony. For downstream knowledge requires one to have abilities to simulatively imagine
and recognise experiences of Φ-ing. But, as discussed before, this will often still mean that the
subject has had an experience of Φ-ing themselves—and thereby has gold WIL-knowledge on
that basis—because, following Lewis (1988: 77), the “best teacher” of those abilities is having
the experience oneself.
But while having an experience is the best teacher for gaining such abilities it is not the only
possible teacher, and those other possible teachers are not limited to just the kinds of remote
possibilities that Lewis discussed (being put into the relevant physical states through magic or
future neuroscience). For, and this is the second key idea, at least with respect to complex/nonatomic experiences, people can develop abilities to imagine and cognitively model experiences
they have not had themselves, by drawing on their imaginative abilities gained from having
63
distinct but relevantly similar experiences. And these imaginings of experiences they have not
had can then be incorporated into their knowledge of what that target experience is like, giving
one silver WIL-knowledge. And while testimony cannot transmit silver WIL-knowledge—
because it also involves abilities that cannot be transmitted by mere testimony—it can transmit
bronze WIL-knowledge and that knowledge can play a role in our acquiring silver-WIL
knowledge by informing us of these similarities and providing information that can guide our
attempts to better imagine experiences we have not had ourselves.
The reason then that there is an apparent tension in our practices and attitudes towards the
possibility of sharing WIL-knowledge with those who have not had the relevant experiences,
is that, on the one hand, when we make unqualified utterances of the form ‘S knows what it is
like to Φ’ we will usually communicate that someone has had an experience of Φ-ing (either
because the phenomenal way of knowing condition entails that they have had such an
experience or because it entails that they have certain abilities which usually indicate that
someone has had such an experience). But, on the other hand, many of our practices around
WIL-knowledge suggest that we are committed, at least implicitly, to the possibility of people
acquiring WIL-knowledge with respect to experiences they have not had themselves.
The idea that WIL-knowledge can come in different degrees and grades allows us to
acknowledge that there can be an epistemic payoff from people’s attempts to share and acquire
WIL-knowledge, whilst still acknowledging that there are forms of WIL-knowledge that are
very difficult, and in some cases practically impossible, for one to acquire without one having
had the relevant target experience oneself.
64
5.4 Degrees of Abilities
The gold, silver, and bronze distinctions are a useful way of thinking about how WILknowledge can come in different degrees and grades, as evidenced by how these distinctions
can be used to illuminate the puzzles around testimony, and how these distinctions have also
been fruitfully applied to other issues.9 But, with respect to partial WIL-knowledge, I do not
think these distinctions are exhaustive, and there are other ways to think of how WILknowledge can come in different degrees that might capture more detailed aspects of this
phenomena.
They are not exhaustive because, for example, we may want to distinguish a further grade of
WIL-knowledge, what we could call platinum knowledge of experience. This would be the
knowledge one has when, for some way w, one knows that w is a way it feels to Φ as one is
having an experience of Φ-ing. This may seem to a better grade of WIL-knowledge than gold,
given the fact that reimagining an experience is not the same thing as reliving it. So, think of
eating vegemite for the first time, and knowing as one has that experience, that this is the way
it feels to vegemite. One might think that the knowledge one has at that moment of what it is
like to eat vegemite is better than the knowledge one will have of it later, after the experience
has ended, because as one is having that experience the phenomenal properties that constitute
it will be more vividly and precisely present to one’s mind than they will be later on when one
merely recalls the experience in one’s imagination.
People who have had the same experiences can also differ later in the quality of their respective
abilities to imagine, remember, and recognise experiences of that type. So, suppose Marama
and Jane have both eaten vegemite, in which case, they should both have gold knowledge of
what it is like to eat vegemite, according to the definition in Cath (2019). But there could still
9
See e.g., Allen (2022), Fürst (2023), and Cawston and Wildman (2023).
65
be lots of different ways in which one of these two people might be said to know what it is like
to eat vegemite better than the other. Perhaps Jane has only eaten vegemite a couple of times,
and some years ago, and so while she can bring that experience back to mind in her imagination,
when she does so her imaginings of it are not very vivid or precise. Marama, on the other hand,
eats vegemite regularly which contributes to her having very good abilities to imagine and
remember what it is like to eat vegemite. And Marama might also have better recognition
abilities, so she might be able to recognise the difference between the experiences of eating
vegemite versus eating marmite (which has a similar taste), whereas Jane might only be able
to recognise the experience of eating vegemite in less demanding contexts (like when asked to
distinguish it from an experience of eating jam).
There could also be cases where someone with silver WIL-knowledge will be in a better
position to imagine the given target experience that they have not had themselves than someone
who has had the experience and so has gold WIL-knowledge. Take the ability to imagine what
it is like to look around a certain room and consider two people, one of whom has looked
around that room many times, and the other who has never been in that room but has seen a
photo of it. Normally, it would be natural and justifiable to assume that the first person will
have better abilities to imagine the experience of looking around the room, but this need not
always be the case. For example, if the first person has severe aphantasia, but the second person
has very good abilities to perform visual imagination tasks, then the second person may have
better abilities to imagine this experience.
One lesson suggested by these examples is that people can possess Lewis’ abilities to different
degrees. And, relatedly, while having an experience is often the only practical way of gaining
abilities to imagine and recognise experiences of that type, there is no determinate path from
having had an experience to possessing those abilities to any given degree. Another lesson is
that, given the connections between WIL-knowledge and Lewis’ abilities, we should expect
66
that there will also be close connections between how WIL-knowledge can come in different
grades and degrees and how these abilities can come in different degrees. Lee (2023) develops
a rich view of this broad kind in relation to his account of phenomenal concepts mentioned in
Section 4.4, and this idea also follows naturally from our earlier discussion of downstream
intellectualism and how the ability to imagine condition should be interpreted in terms of
simulatively imagining the target experience. For the extent to which an event of imagining
shares phenomenal properties with the target experience will clearly be a matter of degree.
To help illustrate some of these points, consider what a perfect imaginative simulation of an
experience would be. Like Nozick’s ‘experience machine’, with respect to its constituent
phenomenal properties it would be subjectively indistinguishable from the target experience it
simulates, with the only difference being its non-standard cause. So, if you intended, say, to
reimagine what it is like for you to sit in your favourite park on a summer’s day you would
have an experience which would be indistinguishable from, and have the exact same
phenomenal properties as, a normal experience of you sitting in that park on a summer’s day;
it is just that the cause of your experience would be your intention to imagine an experience of
that type rather than an event of sitting in the park.
Of course, for us normal human beings, imagining an experience is not reliving it. But now
think of one these hypothetical perfect imaginings and how it could be made to be more like a
normal imperfect imagining by selectively removing, distorting, or adding phenomenal
properties to it. That is a process that would clearly come in degrees, as one might just change
the phenomenal greenness of the grass to a lurid lime green, or one might do that and remove
the feeling or the sun on one’s skin, or one might make both those changes and then also
intensify the prickly feeling of the grass beneath one’s body, and so on. This indicates how real
people’s partial and imperfect imaginings of the experience of Φ-ing might be compared to
each other and considered better or worse, or more or less precise, and so on.
67
Furthermore, as Lee (2023: 191) shows the recognition ability can also come in different
degrees. Lee gives the example of Ms. Scarlet who, like Jackson’s Mary, is kept in a black and
white room but on day n she is allowed to enter another room for 5 minutes. In that room are
100 colour chips each of which is a different shade of red and is labelled with a term for the
kind of visual experience Ms. Scarlet will have when looking at it, where one of these colour
chips will induce scarlet experiences in Ms Scarlet and is labelled as such. At the end of day n,
after looking at all the colour chips, Ms Scarlet is given a test where she has to identify the
colour experiences induced by the colour chips again, but now the chips are not labelled. On
day n, after she has looked at the colour chips for just 5 minutes, Ms. Scarlet will do very poorly
on the test. But on each day after n Ms. Scarlet is allowed to see the same labelled colour chips
again for five minutes each time, and afterwards she is given the same test. As the days go by,
we would expect Ms. Scarlet to do better and better on the tests, as her abilities to recognise
scarlet gradually improve with time and training.
So, the abilities to imagine and recognise experiences can come in different degrees of
accuracy, depending on how many phenomenal properties are shared between one’s
imaginings of that experience and the target experience which they are imaginings of, or how
well one can recognise experiences of that type. Furthermore, there are clearly close
connections between, on the one hand, our assessments of WIL-knowledge as coming in
different grades and degrees and, on the other hand, the degrees to which one possesses these
abilities to imagine and recognise. For example, it is very plausible that Ms. Scarlet on day 100
knows what it is like to see something red better than she did on day 5, and that on day 5 she
only knows approximately what it is like to see something scarlet, whereas she might know
exactly what it is like on day 100.
In line with points made at the end of Section 4.4, how we ultimately explain these
correspondences will differ depending on larger issues concerning the content and nature of
68
propositional attitudes, and their relationship with the abilities they are closely associated with.
So, for example, one might hold a ‘Fregean’ view according to which each day Ms Scarlet
comes to stand in the knowledge relation to a new fine-grained proposition which provides a
more complete answer to the question ‘what is it like to see something scarlet?’, and this is
what explains the increasing accuracy of her abilities (cf. Pavese 2015 on practical senses and
degrees of knowing-how). Or we might follow Lee’s (2023) view on which Ms Scarlet’s
improving abilities are explained by her gaining new phenomenal concepts of scarlet
experiences (i.e., a new mental representation which constitutes part of her belief state, rather
than a new Fregean sense which is part of the believed proposition) each of which eliminates
more “phenomenal possibilities” (Lee 2023: 198) than the previous concepts. Or, if one held a
dispositional view of the propositional attitudes (like e.g., Schwitzgebel 2013), one might
maintain that it is the differences in the accuracy of Ms. Scarlet’s WIL-knowledge from one
day to the next that are explained by, and grounded in, the changes in her different abilities
from one day to the next, and not the other way around . I will not try to adjudicate here between
these kinds of options. But on any of these views we can acknowledge that our judgements
about WIL-knowledge coming in different degrees or grades will be intimately linked with our
judgments about the degree to which one possesses these abilities to imagine and recognise
experiences.
Relatedly, it is also likely that the degree to which a subject needs to possess abilities to imagine
and recognise experiences of Φ-ing in order for the corresponding ascription of WILknowledge to be judged to be true will be a context sensitive matter. Recall the claim that, in
stereotypical contexts, for a knowing-WIL ascription to be judged to be true the subject will
need to know the right kind of proposition and in a phenomenal way, which will involve the
possession of abilities to imagine and recognise the relevant experiences. The suggestion now
then is that the degree to which one needs to be able to possess those abilities to count as
69
knowing that proposition in a phenomenal way is itself a matter that is likely to be context
sensitive. So, for example, when assessing an assertion that someone knows what it is like to
drink a good pinot noir, the recognitional abilities required for the assertion to be judged to be
true might be less exacting when the context of evaluation is a conversation amongst friends
who get together to taste different wines than when it is a conversation amongst sommeliers.
This general approach, on which we think of degrees of WIL-knowledge in terms of these
degreed abilities, fits more seamlessly with the view of downstream intellectualism I advocated
for in Section 4 because, unlike the concepts of gold and silver WIL-knowledge, there is no
upstream or ‘backwards’ looking experience condition (either for the same experience in the
case of gold WIL-knowledge or similar experiences for silver WIL-knowledge), built directly
into the account of degrees of WIL-knowledge itself. Rather we analyse WIL-knowledge, and
how it can come in degrees, in terms of a form of downstream knowledge that entails the
possession of certain abilities, and that knowledge can come in different degrees which either
explains, or is explained by, those abilities coming in different degrees.
That said, usually one can reasonably assume that someone who has had an experience of Φing will have better abilities to imagine experiences of that kind than someone who hasn’t, and
that someone who has had experiences which are importantly similar but distinct from the
target experience of Φ-ing will have better abilities to imagine such experiences than someone
who has had neither the target experience nor any relevantly similar experiences. Furthermore,
it does seem plausible that, apart from the remote metaphysical possibilities that Lewis
considers, there are certain very simple experiences which one wouldn’t be able to simulatively
imagine and recognise unless one has had an experience of that type in the past. In which case,
as discussed earlier, there will be, in principle, limits on what kinds of silver WIL-knowledge
we can achieve, and there will be a true version of the experience condition restricted to atomic
experiences and normal circumstances. Together these points indicate why the gold, silver,
70
bronze distinctions are a useful heuristic for thinking about how WIL-knowledge can come in
different degrees, even if there are other more detailed and accurate ways of thinking of how
WIL-knowledge can come in degrees. For in general one can safely assume that the gold, silver,
and bronze distinctions will roughly correspond with greater to lesser degrees of the abilities
to imagine, remember, and recognise experiences.
6. Pitfalls and Possibilities
Our experiences shape our identities, both individual and collective. Given the deep
connections between experience and identity, and between experience and WIL-knowledge,
any suggestion that people can have WIL-knowledge of experiences they have not had
themselves can quickly set off serious alarm bells, including both epistemological concerns
about whether we can achieve such knowledge, and related ethical concerns that there is
something morally wrong with attempting to gain such knowledge. A common response to
such concerns is to appeal (implicitly or explicitly) to the experience condition and deny the
possibility of people achieving any WIL-knowledge of experiences they have not had
themselves. But what I want to briefly explore now, in this closing section, is how we might
navigate these concerns in such a way that we can acknowledge the important insights they
raise, whilst still acknowledging the, in principle, possibility of people achieving partial WILknowledge of experiences they have not had.
6.1 Epistemic Arrogance and the Experience Condition
As Kind (2021) discusses, one common concern with the idea of people trying to obtain WILknowledge of the experiences of other people is that there is something arrogant about thinking
that one could gain such knowledge by merely doing things like consulting testimony or
71
reading a novel. There are also other related concerns including that such attempts can
constitute a form of epistemic trespassing, appropriation, or ‘experience tourism’, and that, as
such, these attempts can serve to trivialise the experiences they supposedly aim to illuminate
and, in some cases, even reinforce oppressive social structures they were meant to combat;
concerns like this have been raised by various authors including Ngo (2017a) and Ramirez
(2018, 2021) who raise them in relation to attempts to gain WIL-knowledge through the use of
supposed simulations of the given target experience.
There are strong connections, I think, between these kinds of concerns and the intuitive appeal
of the experience condition. For note that if this condition were true, without any qualifications,
then trying to obtain WIL-knowledge of experiences that one has not had oneself—through
activities of using one’s imagination, together with, say, consulting literature, testimony,
simulations, or theories about the relevant class of experiences—would be tantamount to trying
to have the relevant experience oneself through engaging in such activities. And if having such
an experience is part of what makes one a member of a given social group, then thinking that
one can obtain WIL-knowledge through such activities would almost be tantamount to thinking
that such activities could suffice to make one a member of that group.
But obviously it would be not only be arrogant and insensitive but absurd to think that engaging
in such activities could give you the relevant experiences or make you a member of the relevant
social group. If you have not been to war, no amount of reading Marlantes and Sherman’s
books, will give you the experience of going to war, or make you a veteran. And if you are a
white person, no amount of reading literature or phenomenological analyses of the experiences
of living with racism (e.g., Ngo’s own 2017b), or engaging with a supposed simulation of it
like the virtual reality simulation 1,000 Cut Journey (for discussion see Ramirez 2021), will
give you the experience of living with racism, or make you a person of colour.
72
The accounts of downstream intellectualism and degrees of WIL-knowledge developed in
Sections 4-5 allow us to agree that it would be absurd and arrogant to think that one could gain
an experience-entailing form of WIL-knowledge from merely engaging with sources like
testimony and simulations, and using one’s imagination, etc., whilst still acknowledging that
one could possibly gain limited forms of partial WIL-knowledge from such actions.10 For
having partial WIL-knowledge—in the form of silver or even just bronze WIL-knowledge—
with respect to a target experience of Φ-ing does not entail one’s having had an experience of
Φ-ing oneself.
However, as discussed earlier, in stereotypical contexts, an unqualified ‘S knows what it is like
to Φ’ ascription will communicate that one has an experience of Φ-ing in virtue of having an
experience or ability entailing form of WIL-knowledge. And this point helps to explain why
people so readily hear claims about someone acquiring WIL-knowledge as communicating that
they have had the corresponding experience, which in turns explain the deep resistance, and
even animosity, that people can have to any suggestions that someone could gain WILknowledge about experiences they have not had themselves. For, so interpreted, the suggestion
that someone can have WIL-knowledge of the experiences of other people from, say,
imagination and testimony, or a VR simulation, is a suggestion that they can have the very
same types of experiences themselves via such means, which is not only epistemically
implausible but also arrogant and offensive.
But we can block these inferences from claims that someone knows what it is like to Φ to the
conclusion that they must have had an experience of Φ-ing, by explicitly cancelling them, or
Kind (2021: 249) appeals to the notion of understanding experiential perspectives other than one’s own, on the
grounds that understanding, unlike knowledge, comes in degrees. But this move isn’t necessary given that, as
discussed in Section 5.1, most forms of knowing-wh come in degrees even if knowing-that does not. And, by
itself, just appealing to the notion of understanding won’t suffice to address the issues here because the same
intuitions that support the experience condition also arise for understanding what it is like to have experiences
(e.g., intuitively, Mary not only doesn’t know, but also doesn’t understand, what it is like to see something red).
In which case, one would still need to appeal here to something like the framework developed in Section 5.
10
73
by using qualified knowing-WIL ascriptions (adding modifies like ‘approximately’, ‘in part’
or ‘to some degree’, etc.), or by relying on features of the conversational context to do this
work. So, for example, it would be perfectly reasonable for me to say: “Neither of us have been
to war, but Nancy Sherman knows what it is like better than I do”. For in making such an
utterance I cancel any implication that either of us has been to war, and I communicate
something true, namely, that Nancy Sherman knows a great deal many more truths about the
way that the events involved in going to go to war can make a person feel. Relatedly, Lee
(2023: 195) points out that, for knowing-wh ascriptions in general an ascription of the form ‘S
knows approximately wh-Φ’ does not entail an unqualified ‘S knows wh-Φ’ ascription, and so
we should expect the same to be true for knowing-WIL ascriptions.
Importantly, the above points are consistent with endorsing concerns that attempts by people
to acquire WIL-knowledge of experiences they have not had can sometimes be morally
problematic, even if one grants that it is possible, in principle, for people to obtain partial WILknowledge through such attempts. And attempts to simulate the experiences of other people as
a way of gaining WIL-knowledge often elicit such concerns. So, for example, in 2017 an
Australian charity which runs a fundraising event called “CEO sleepout”—where CEOs sleep
outside for a night to raise money for the homeless—was widely criticised after footage came
out from the event of CEOs wearing virtual reality headsets running a simulation of being
homeless in an attempt “to get a glimpse of the realities faced by the people who experience
this everyday” (Zhou 2017).11
The images of wealthy CEOs trying to understand the experiences of homeless people by
donning a VR headset were criticised on twitter for being “tone deaf” and even “dystopian”
(Zhou 2017). Some of the implied criticisms were epistemic in nature with people rightly
11
Ramirez (2021: 99–100) discusses a similar case in the USA.
74
pointing to the vast differences between the experience a CEO would have in the virtual
simulation (where they know the experience is not real, that it will soon be over, and that they
can leave it at any time), and the real experiences of homelessness that the virtual experience
is attempting to simulate. We’ll return to these kinds of concerns in Section 6.3 below. But
many of the criticisms, like the “tone deaf” criticism, looked to be moral criticisms which could
still be made even if one granted that people can, in principle, gain partial WIL-knowledge by
using simulations like this. And there are lots of other moral criticisms that are often made
about attempts to use VR as a supposed “empathy machine”. For example, that one shouldn’t
need a VR simulation to know that we need to help the homeless or refugees, or that solitary
confinement is cruel and should be abolished, and so we should just be focused on taking
actions to address these problems, rather than trying to simulate these experiences. And there
are related concerns that such simulations might serve to ‘gamify’ and trivialise the experiences
they aim to simulate. Indeed, as Ngo (2017a) discusses, some attempts to simulate the
experience of racism explicitly present themselves as games and their users as players.
There are plausibly many ways then in which attempts by one subject to gain WIL-knowledge
of the experiences of other people can be morally problematic. But that important point doesn’t
reveal any, in principle, limitations to our epistemic capacities to gain partial WIL-knowledge
about the experiences of other people. And, even focusing just on the moral issues, it would be
a mistake to infer from these legitimate concerns about specific attempts to gain WILknowledge about other people, that any such attempt will always be morally problematic.
Indeed, it seems clear that sometimes people can have important moral obligations to attempt
to gain partial WIL-knowledge of the experiences of other people. Consider, say, a nondisabled partner of a person living with a disability that significantly impacts many areas of
their life. The non-disabled partner surely has an obligation to try and learn something about
what it is like for their partner to live with that disability in an ableist society. The non-disabled
75
partner may often fail in those attempts, and when they do succeed their WIL-knowledge will
be partial and limited, but they should try to gain this knowledge despite those difficulties and
limitations. The notion of partial WIL-knowledge allows us to make sense of how we can be
subject to these kinds of obligations in a way that: (i) does not commit us to the arrogant idea
that we could come to have the very same experiences and experiential knowledge as they do
merely by talking with them, or engaging with literature or simulations etc., but (ii) still
acknowledges that these are genuinely epistemic obligations to try to learn something about the
experiential perspective of the other person as opposed to just being, say, mere obligations to
listen with sympathy and concern when others talk about their experiences.
6.2 ‘No comparison’ Worries
However, is it really possible to achieve partial, but still non-trivial, WIL-knowledge of
experiences we have not had? The idea of silver WIL-knowledge rested on the assumption
that there can be similarities between one’s own experiences and a relevant target experience
that one has not had. But one might worry that often any such similarities will be so ‘thin’ that
one will not be able to use them to meaningfully improve one’s knowledge of the target
experience. It might be that one can achieve some very limited kinds of bronze and even silver
WIL-knowledge in such cases, but that knowledge will be uninformative and of little value.
This worry is most obvious when considering cases where the experience that a subject has not
had is one that involves a sensory modality that this subject either does not have access to at
all, or that they only have some very limited form of access to. Mary in her black-and-white
room is an example of this kind. For when Mary is in her room, she only has access to blackand-white visual experiences which obviously form a poor basis for building imaginative
models of coloured visual experiences. Similarly, Paul (2014: 106-7) discusses the case of
76
blind saxophonist who is given the opportunity to become sighted through surgery, and Paul
claims that the saxophonist “lacks the capacity to imaginatively represent the nature of this
lived experience” (2014: 107). In these kinds of examples there is a strong case to be made that
the “distance” (Cath 2022: 9) or “gulf” (Kind 2021: 237) between a subject’s own experiences
and the target experience which they have not had is too great for the former experiences to
form any kind of basis for the subject to build an informative model in their imagination of that
target experience.
There are good reasons then to think that in situations where has only very limited access to a
whole sensory modality, they will not be able to simulatively imagine experiences of that kind
and have informative silver WIL-knowledge concerning them on that basis. But most of the
cases where people try to acquire WIL-knowledge about other people’s experiences, or
possible experiences they could have themselves in the future, are not like this. Rather, they
are cases involving complex experiences—like going to war, or living in a new country, or
being a parent—with many experiential parts involving all kinds of sensory, affective, and
cognitive phenomenal properties, some of which the person may have been acquainted with
already in their own distinct but relevantly similar experiences. Is there any reason to think that
the distance between experiences in cases like this will as problematically large as the distance
between the experiences of two different sensory modalities?
6.3 Subjective Variations in Experience
One might think that when the background, and social location, of two subjects is very different
then the distance between their experiences will be so significant that neither subject could ever
have informative silver WIL-knowledge of the other’s experiences. Paul (2014: 7–8), for
example, expresses something like this assumption when she writes: “If you are a man who has
77
grown up and always lived in a rich Western country, you cannot know what it is like to be an
impoverished woman living in Ethiopia, and if she has never left her village she cannot know
what it is like to be you.”
One way to support this assumption, is to appeal to the further idea that differences in who we
are can led to differences in how we experience the same type of event or action. Ramirez
(2021), for example, appeals to this kind of idea in critiquing attempts to use VR simulations
to understand the experiences of other people, and more specifically he appeals to his own
‘intersectional theory’ of experience according to “which the content of an individual person’s
experience, at any given time, is going to be shaped not only by where they happen to be
looking, but also by the effects that their internalized concepts of race, gender, class,
nationality, etc., have on those experiences” (Ramirez 2021: 110). Appealing to this theory,
Ramirez’s idea is that there will usually be significant differences in the intersectional identities
of the intended users of a VR simulation of the experience of Φ-ing, versus the intersectional
identities of the group of people who are having the relevant target experiences of Φ-ing. In
which case, if the intended users of the VR simulation were to actually have an experience of
Φ-ing their resulting experiences would be very different from the experiences of the people
having the target experiences of Φ-ing, and that means the VR simulation could at best help
someone to know what it would be like for themselves to Φ not what it is like for that group of
people to Φ. As Ramirez (2018) states this idea: “For all its potential, VR can’t show us what
it’s like to be someone else. To echo Nagel, it can only reveal what it would be like for us to
have these experiences”.
Ramirez’s conclusion here relates to Stoljar’s claim, discussed in Section 3.1, that there are
different ways of disambiguating the two subject positions—one for an agent of the event, and
one for an experiencer of the event—in the logical form of an embedded WIL-question.
Consider (1):
78
(1) Marama knows what it is like to go caving.
The natural interpretation of (1) in many contexts would be one on which Marama is both the
experiencer and the agent. On Stoljar’s semantics this interpretation is represented like so:
(1.1) Marama knows what it is like to Marama for Marama to go caving.
But there could be contexts where we are interested in whether Marama knows what it is like
for Bill to go caving or, more precisely, what it is like for Bill to experience Bills’ action of
going caving. On Stoljar’s semantics this interpretation is represented like so:
(1.2) Marama knows what it is like to Bill for Bill to go caving.
Now, related to Ramirez’s discussion, we can easily imagine circumstances in which (1.1) is
true but (1.2) is false, due to differences between Marama and Bill. So, perhaps Marama has
been caving and so she knows what her going caving is like for herself, but Marama does not
suffer from claustrophobia whereas Bill does. In which case, the way that Bill feels when he
goes caving will be significantly different, and consequently Marama may fail to know what it
is like for Bill when he goes caving. For Marama may not be able to accurately imagine the
way that it feels to go caving whilst suffering from claustrophobia, and she may not even be
aware that Bill has claustrophobia which might lead her to falsely believe that the way it feels
for Bill when he goes caving is very similar to the way it feels for herself when she goes caving.
The psychological difference between Marama and Bill which leads to their different
experiences does not stem from differences in their intersectional identities. But the larger idea
is the same as Ramirez’s, namely, that differences in who we are—understood in a broad way
to include our background experiences and knowledge, psychological dispositions, and social
location, etc.—can led to differences in the way we experience the same event or action. So,
for example, as Ngo (2017a: 113–15) discusses, a white person engaging with a simulation of
being subjected to micro-level expressions of racism may come away with the mistaken
79
impression that such acts are not actually racist or that the events of being subjected to those
acts are not that bad, because if they were to encounter such events in their life those events
would not make them the feel the same way as a person of colour. This is because a person of
colour has knowledge and past experiences which allow them to interpret the racist significance
of such acts more accurately, and that in turn could result in those acts making them feel a very
different way from how a white person would feel if they were to somehow encounter those
acts in real life, or representations of such acts in a simulation.
I think these broadly related insights from Ngo and Ramirez are sound and important, as they
identify a source of significant errors—in the form of inaccurate imaginings of the target
experience and false beliefs about the way it feels to have that experience—that can happen
when people try to gain WIL-knowledge of the experiences of other people. But there is also
a danger, I think, of overestimating the wider significance of this fact that the content and
character of our experiences can be sensitive to differences in who we are.
So, for example, Ramirez concludes, by way of appealing to his intersectional thesis, that we
should reject claims made by VR developers that their simulations “can give you these kinds
of experiences” (Ramirez 2021: 100) so that “you experience what it is like for someone else
to have these experiences, from their point of view” (Ramirez 2021: 108). This is a correct
conclusion to draw, I think, for given the fact that the way our experiences feel can be
influenced by differences in who we are, and other differences between simulation experiences
and their targets, like differences in duration (Bloom 2017), it would be extremely naïve to
hold that a VR simulation could actually give you an experience of the same type as the relevant
target experience. But as well as this reasonable conclusion should we also infer the further,
and much stronger, conclusion that such simulations could never help someone to gain any
partial knowledge of what it is like for the relevant group of people to have the relevant target
experience?
80
Ramirez seems to be committed to this kind of further conclusion because, for example, he
claims that "VR and AR simulations can’t give us access to the inner lives of other people”
(2021: 105) apart from very limited ‘base cases’ where there are no relevant psychological
differences between the person using the VR simulation and the people having the relevant
experience. Relatedly, Ramirez advocates thinking of VR simulations as only being able to
enhance sympathy and not empathy (2021: 121). And this suggests that Ramirez thinks of VR
simulations as having no epistemic value with respect to learning something about the
experiences of other people, given that when sympathy is distinguished from empathy the idea
is usually that the former is merely a matter of feeling concern for the other person rather than
feeling what they feel (affective empathy) or knowing how they feel (cognitive empathy).
But this inference from the claim that VR simulations cannot give you the experiences of other
people to the conclusion they cannot give you any knowledge of what those experiences are
like only makes sense if we accept the experience condition and think of all WIL-knowledge
in an experience entailing and binary way. For once we have the idea of WIL-knowledge
coming in degrees we can make sense of the, in principle, possibility of such simulations
helping one to gain partial WIL-knowledge concerning what the relevant target experiences
are like. For the fact that a simulation experience is not the same experience as the target
experience it is aiming to simulate is consistent with it still sharing phenomenal properties with
that target experience. In which case, if those resemblances are non-trivial then someone might
come to possess useful silver WIL-knowledge of the target experience based on their having
had the simulation experience.
This is not to say, of course, that any given attempt by someone to gain WIL-knowledge of
other people’s experiences using a VR simulation—or testimony, or literature, etc.—will result
in that person gaining partial WIL-knowledge. For as Bloom (2017), Ngo (2017a), and Ramirez
(2021) and others point out, such attempts can sometimes lead us to false beliefs about what
81
the relevant target experience is like, in which case those beliefs will not constitute knowledge
at all. The point is simply that we cannot infer from the assumed impossibility of using VR to
gain experience entailing forms of WIL-knowledge that it is also impossible to use VR to gain
partial and non-experience entailing forms of WIL-knowledge. And the same point applies to
any method of forming beliefs about what it is like to have an experience that does not involve
having the target experience oneself.
Relatedly, it would be a mistake to infer from the fact that there can be significant variations
in how the same event or action of Φ-ing can make different people feel, due to differences in
who they are, that there cannot be significant patterns and similarities in how different people
feel when they Φ. There is such a thing, after all, as “shared experiences” and it would be an
extremely sceptical position to maintain that people can only be said to have shared
experiences, and shared experiential knowledge, when they have the exact same experiences
due to their having the exact same intersectional identities and psychological dispositions etc.,
as that would effectively mean that people almost never have shared experiences and shared
experiential knowledge. Consider two friends who are both members of a student LGBTQIA+
group. They may differ in their gender identities and sexual orientations, and they might have
different class, cultural, and race experiences, and psychological dispositions, and so on. In
which case, following Ramirez’s intersectional theory of experience, any of those differences
could cause them to experience the same events in significantly different ways. But,
nonetheless, they might still find value and solidarity in certain significant similarities in their
distinct experiences of, say, navigating heteronormative cultures in the university, or coming
out to their families, even whilst acknowledging and learning from each other that there are
also important differences in their respective experiences. And in this qualified sense these two
82
people could be said to have “shared experiences” and shared WIL-knowledge with respect to
the overlaps in their distinct but partially similar experiences.12
The extent to which we can gain different forms of partial WIL-knowledge through activities
that do not involve having the relevant target experience—like consulting literature, testimony,
simulations, or theories—is an interesting and difficult question, and one that I think we should
approach on a careful case-by-case basis. Authors like Bloom, Ngo, and Ramirez show us that
there are significant epistemic pitfalls that we can fall into in trying to gain WIL-knowledge
through using simulations, and other authors, like Berninger (2023), have identified related
dangers with respect to testimony. The insights of these authors remind us that we should
approach any attempt to learn about experiences we have not had with a great deal of epistemic
humility and with due deference to the epistemic authority of those who have had experiences
of that type. But we should not let the intuitive plausibility of the experience condition trick us
into thinking that all such attempts are doomed to be epistemically fruitless just because they
can’t provide us with the actual experiences they aim to illuminate.
6.4 Combination Concerns
Another related worry one might have with the idea of partial WIL-knowledge is that even if
one has had an experience which shares certain experiential parts with the given target
experience, one still can’t know that the total experiential parts of the target experience won’t
combine in unexpected ways. Furthermore, such worries might seem compounded by the fact
that we still have such a poor theoretical understanding of how experiential parts combine into
12
See Allen (2022: 1127) for related discussion.
83
whole experiences, and the principles governing these mereological relations (see e.g., Lee
2014, Koksvik 2014).13
There are many interesting issues one could explore concerning the relation between partial
WIL-knowledge and the mereological properties of our experiences. But given the scope of
this discussion, I will limit myself here to explaining why I think that such explorations are
unlikely to support any deep scepticism about the, in principle, possibility of achieving forms
of partial WIL-knowledge.
Firstly, we shouldn’t infer from the mere fact that we have a poor theoretical understanding of
the principles governing how experiential parts compose larger experiences, that partial WILknowledge is impossible. For the general idea that a belief forming process can only lead us to
knowledge if we also have further explicit knowledge of how it works, and the principles it
relies upon, is an implausibly demanding condition that risks leading us into deep forms of
scepticism. And, more specifically, such a stance about partial WIL-knowledge would force us
to reject apparently clear cases of such knowledge. So, for example, I have never had the
experience of eating a kiwifruit whilst walking down Sydney Road. Nonetheless, I think I still
have good, albeit partial, knowledge of what it is like to have that experience, at least in normal
circumstances. For I have eaten kiwifruit in many other settings, and I have walked down
Sydney Road many times. So, given these experiences, I can form quite accurate imaginings
and beliefs concerning what it is like to have this target experience which I have not had.
In this example I make a ‘normal circumstances’ qualification. But what about less normal
circumstances? As Koksvik (2014: 115) points out, even the experiences of a routine walk can
be dramatically altered when they are had in combination with an intense mood:
13
Thanks to a reviewer and to Walter Pedriali who both pressed me to address these concerns.
84
Even going for a familiar walk can be a very different experience in a
buoyant mood. It is as if the good feeling bleeds into every other experience:
even mundane things look sparkly and full of promise at those times, utterly
different from their grey and hopeless appearance in negative moods.
However, as Koksvik also notes, most of us have experienced how intense moods can alter
familiar experiences. So, I think I can still have reasonable, albeit partial, knowledge of what
it is like to eat a kiwifruit whilst walking down Sydney Road in a mood of high elation, based
on my experiences of elated moods in other situations. And we shouldn’t overestimate the
degree to which our moods alter other experiences. There will usually still be significant
similarities between, for example, the visual phenomenology of the walk in a normal mood and
the same walk in a mood of intense elation. After all, while an elated mood might transform a
walk from being dull to being enchanting, it typically won’t result in one’s getting lost.
On the other hand, having never taken psychedelic drugs, I may not be in a position to have
any even partial knowledge of what it is like to eat a kiwifruit when walking down Sydney
Road as part of a larger psychedelic experience. Or if I can gain some such knowledge, it will
be thin and uninformative with respect to what makes psychedelic experiences so distinctive.
For I am not familiar with psychedelic experiences and how they combine with, and
dramatically alter, otherwise familiar experiences.
Perhaps we should view our attempts at understanding the experiences of other people in
different social locations as being a similar kind of case? The idea being that even if there are
some relevant similarities between the experiences of two people in different social locations,
the total parts of their respective experiences will combine in very different ways and to such
an extent that neither person can achieve any even partial WIL-knowledge of the other’s
experiences (or at least no non-trivial forms of such knowledge). There may be specific cases
85
where this is the right conclusion to reach. But it would be very implausible to generalise this
idea to all cases where people are in different social locations. For such a position would, again,
commit one to the implausible claim that in LGBTQIA+ student case that it is impossible for
either student to achieve any even partial WIL-knowledge with respect to the experiences of
their friend.
Furthermore, while testimony may do a poor job of conveying the phenomenal character of
experiences that are radically different from any of our previous experiences, it can at least
inform us that there are these significant differences. And, more generally, testimony can alert
us to all kinds of potential errors we might make in our assessments of a target experience
based on our familiarity with some, but not all, of its experiential parts; including mistaken
judgements about how those experiential parts combine with other experiential parts of the
target experience. And the fact that there are such means for detecting these errors is another
reason for cautious optimism about our abilities to sometimes achieve forms of partial WILknowledge. For this suggests that the serious errors we can make in trying to achieve partial
WIL-knowledge are best viewed not as insurmountable barriers, but challenges, which we can
manage and sometimes overcome.
Conclusions
There is a prima facie tension between the answer and experience conditions, as the answer
condition pushes us to think of WIL-knowledge as a form of propositional knowledge, whereas
the experience condition might seem to push towards thinking that WIL-knowledge is some
kind of non-propositional knowledge, like ability or acquaintance knowledge. However, in this
Element I argued that, ultimately, this tension can be resolved by thinking of interrogative
WIL-knowledge as a form of downstream knowledge which involves the possession of abilities
86
to imagine and recognise experiences. I also showed how WIL-knowledge on this view can
come in different degrees, and how that fact can illuminate the initially puzzling relationship
between WIL-knowledge and testimony. And, finally, I briefly explored some of the
possibilities and pitfalls involved in trying to acquire partial WIL-knowledge of experiences
one has not had oneself.
References
Allen, P. (2022). Experience, knowledge, and political representation. Politics & Gender,
18(4): 1112–1140.
Alter, T. (2001). Know-how, ability, and the ability hypothesis. Theoria, 67 (3):229–39.
Ball, D. (2009). There are no phenomenal concepts. Mind, 118 (472): 935–962.
Berninger, A. (2023). Experience and understanding in response to holocaust testimony. In T.
Petraschka and C. Werner, eds., Empathy’s Role in Understanding Persons, Literature, and
Art (pp. 84-102), New York: Routledge, pp. 84–102.
Bloom, P. (2017). It’s ridiculous to use virtual reality to empathize with refugees. The Atlantic.
https://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2017/02/virtual-reality-wont-make-youmore-empathetic/515511/
Carter, J.A. and J. Navarro. (2017). The defeasibility of knowledge-how. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 95: 662–85.
Cath, Y. (2011). Knowing how without knowing that. In J. Bengson and M. Moffett, eds.,
Knowing How: Essays on Knowledge, Mind, and Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp.
113–135.
87
Cath, Y. (2019). Knowing what it is like and testimony. Australasian Journal of Philosophy,
97(1), 105-120.
Cath, Y. (2020). Know how and skill: the puzzles of priority and equivalence. In Ellen Fridland
& Carlotta Pavese, eds., Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Skill and Expertise, New
York: Routledge, pp. 157–167.
Cath, Y. (2022). Transformative experiences and the equivocation objection. Inquiry, DOI:
10.1080/0020174X.2022.2107063
Cath, Y. (2023). Expanding the client’s perspective. Philosophical Quarterly, 73 (3): 701–721.
Cawston, A., and Wildman, N. (2023). Are you (relevantly) experienced? A moral argument
for video games. In L. D'Olimpio, P. Paris, and A. P. Thompson, eds., Educating Character
Through the Arts, London: Routledge, pp. 109–124
Coleman, S. (2009). Why the ability hypothesis is best forgotten. Journal of Consciousness
Studies, 16 (2-3): 74–97.
Conee, E. (1994). Phenomenal knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72 (2): 136–
150.
Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the State of Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Currie, G. (2020). Imagining and Knowing: The Shape of Fiction, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
D’Ambrosio, J. & Stoljar, D. (2021). Vendler’s puzzle about imagination. Synthese 199 (5-6):
2923–12944.
Duncan, M. (2021). Acquaintance. Philosophy Compass, 16(3), e12727: 1–19.
Farkas, K. (2019). Objectual knowledge. In T. Raleigh and Jonathan Knowles, eds.,
Acquaintance: New Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 260–276.
88
Fürst, M. (2023). Closing the conceptual gap in epistemic injustice. The Philosophical
Quarterly, 74 (1): 229–250
Ginet, C. (1975). Knowledge, Perception, and Memory, Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.
Glick, E. (2015). Practical Modes of Presentation. Noûs, 49 (3): 538–559.
Grzankowski, A. & Tye, M. (2019). What acquaintance teaches. In T. Raleigh & J. Knowles,
eds., Acquaintance: New Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 75–94.
Chappell, S. G. (2017). Knowing What to Do: Imagination, Virtue, and Platonism in Ethics,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hawley, K. (2011). Knowing how and epistemic injustice. In J. Bengson and M. Moffett, eds.,
Knowing How: Essays on Knowledge, Mind, and Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp.
283–299.
Hookway, C. (2006). Epistemology and inquiry: the primacy of practice. In S. Hetherington,
ed., Epistemology Futures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 127–36.
Kind, A. (2020). What imagination teaches. In J. Schwenkler and E. Lambert, eds., Becoming
Someone New: Essays on Transformative Experience, Choice, and Change, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 133–146.
Kind, A. (2021). Bridging the divide: imagining across experiential perspectives. In C. Badura
& A, Kind, eds., Epistemic Uses of Imagination, New York: Routledge, pp. 237–259.
Koksvik, O. (2014). Three Models of Phenomenal Unity. Journal of Consciousness Studies,
21 (7–8): 105–131.
Lee, A. Y. (2023). Knowing what it's like. Philosophical Perspectives, 37(1), 187–209.
89
Lee, G. (2014). Experiences and their Parts. In B, Hill, ed., Sensory Integration and the Unity
of Consciousness. MIT Press pp. 287–381.
Lewis, D. (1988). What experience teaches. Reprinted in P. Ludlow, Y. Nagasawa, and D.
Stoljar, eds., (2004). There's Something About Mary: Essays on Phenomenal Consciousness
and Frank Jackson's Knowledge Argument, Boston: MIT Press, pp. 77–103.
Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nemirow, L. (1990). Physicalism and the Cognitive Role of Acquaintance. In W. Lycan, ed.,
Mind and Cognition, Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, pp. 490–499.
Nemirow, L. (2006). So this is what it’s like: A defense of the ability hypothesis. In T.A. Alter
and S. Walter, eds., Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on
Consciousness and Physicalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 32–51.
Ngo, H. (2017a). Simulating the lived experience of racism and islamophobia: on ‘embodied
empathy’ and political tourism. Australian Feminist Law Journal, 43 (1): 107–123.
Ngo, H. (2017b). The Habits of Racism: A Phenomenology of Racism and Racialized
Embodiment, Maryland: Lexington Books.
Paul, L. A. (2014). Transformative Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Paul, L. A. (2015a). What you can't expect when you're expecting. Res Philosophica, 92 (2):
1–23.
Paul, L. A. (2015b). Transformative choice: discussion and replies. Res Philosophica, 92
(2): 473–545.
Pavese, C. (2015). Practical senses. Philosophers' Imprint, 15 (29): 1–25.
Pavese, C. (2017). Know-how and gradability. Philosophical Review, 126 (3): 345–383.
90
Poston, T. (2009). Know how to be gettiered? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79
(3): 743–747.
Poston, T. (2016). Know how to transmit knowledge? Noûs 50 (4): 865–878.
Ramirez, E. (2018, October). It’s dangerous to think virtual reality is an empathy machine.
Aeon. https://aeon.co/ideas/its-dangerous-to-think-virtual-reality-is-an-empathy-machine
Ramirez, E. J. (2021). The Ethics of Virtual and Augmented Reality: Building Worlds, New
York: Routledge.
Russell, B. (1911). Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, 11:108–128.
Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University Press.
Sainsbury, R. M. and Tye, M. (2012). Seven Puzzles of Thought and How to Solve Them: An
Originalist Theory of Concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.
Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). A Dispositional Approach to the Attitudes. In N. Nottelmann, ed.,
New Essays on Belief. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 75–99.
Sherman, N. (2010). The Untold War: Inside the Hearts and Minds and Souls of Our Soldiers.
New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Stanley, J. (2011). Know How. New York: Oxford University Press.
Stanley, J. and Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98: 411–44.
Stoljar, D. (2015). Lewis on materialism and experience. In B. Loewer and J. Schaffer, eds., A
Companion to David Lewis. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, pp. 519–532.
Stoljar, D. (2016). The semantics of ‘what it’s like’ and the nature of consciousness. Mind, 125
(500): 1161–1198.
91
Tye, M. (2000). Knowing what it is like: The ability hypothesis and the knowledge argument.
In Gerhard Preyer, eds., Reality and Humean Supervenience: Essays on the Philosophy of
David Lewis. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 223–238.
Tye, M. (2011). Knowing what it is like. In J. Bengson and M. Moffett, eds., Knowing How:
Essays on Knowledge, Mind, and Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 300–313.
Waights Hickman, N. (2019). Knowing in the “executive way”: knowing how, rules, methods,
principles and criteria. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 99 (2): 311–335.
Werner, C. (2023). “Tell me, how does it feel?”: Learning what it is like through literature. In
T. Petraschka and C. Werner, eds., Empathy’s Role in Understanding Persons, Literature, and
Art, New York: Routledge, pp. 174–196.
Zagzebski, L. (2008). Omnisubjectivity. In J. Kvanvig, ed., Oxford Studies in Philosophy of
Religion, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 231–248.
Zhou, N. (2017, June). CEO Sleepout criticised as ‘dystopian’ for homeless simulation with
VR headsets. The Guardian: Australia Edition. https://www.theguardian.com/australianews/2017/jun/23/ceo-sleepout-criticised-as-dystopian-for-homeless-simulation-with-vrheadsets
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to two anonymous reviewers for their insightful suggestions which improved this
Element. My thanks also to Stephen Hetherington for his encouragement, and to audiences at
the ANU for helpful feedback on an early draft of Sections 1–4, especially Andrew Y. Lee and
Daniel Stoljar.
92