HARDER, BETTER, FASTER,
STRONGER: EPISTEMIC STANDARDS
AND MORAL BELIEFS
Nicole DULAR
ABSTRACT: Much work in moral epistemology is devoted to explaining apparent
asymmetries between moral and non-moral epistemology. These asymmetries include
testimony, expertise, and disagreement. Surprisingly, these asymmetries have been
addressed in isolation from each other, and the explanations offered have been piecemeal,
rather than holistic. In this paper, I provide the only unified account on offer of these
asymmetries. According to this unified account, moral beliefs typically have a higher
epistemic standard than non-moral beliefs. This means, roughly, that it is typically more
difficult for agents to receive the relevant positive epistemic credit (e.g. knowledge) for
moral beliefs than for non-moral beliefs. After presenting this account, I consider two
alternative unified accounts. According to the first alternative, moral matters are more
cognitively demanding; according to the second, moral beliefs have more defeaters. I
argue that neither of these alternative accounts succeed, and that my higher standards
account is the best unified explanation.
KEYWORDS: epistemic standards, moral testimony, moral expertise,
moral disagreement
Introduction
A quick survey of recent literature in moral epistemology will tell you that many
think that moral beliefs are epistemically special. More particularly, one will find
many papers dedicated to discussing noteworthy asymmetries between certain
areas in our moral and non-moral epistemology, like testimony, expertise, and
disagreement. These differences are often viewed as obstacles or hurdles moral
beliefs face on their way to moral knowledge that non-moral beliefs don’t face. For
example, while non-moral knowledge is thought to be easily achieved via
testimony, moral testimony is thought to be epistemically problematic, morally
problematic, or both.1 In the same vein, while non-moral expertise is obvious,
Roger Crisp, “Moral Testimony Pessimism: A Defense,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
Supplementary Volume 88, 1 (2014): 129-143; Nicole Dular, "Moral Testimony under
Oppression," Journal of Social Philosophy 48, 2 (2017): 212-236; Allison Hills, “Moral Testimony
and Moral Epistemology,” Ethics 120, 1 (2009): 94-127; Robert Hopkins, “What is Wrong with
1
© LOGOS & EPISTEME, XI, 1 (2020): 29-51
Nicole Dular
moral expertise is highly controversial and doubtful at best, and moral
disagreement threatens skepticism in a way that non-moral disagreement fails to.
What explains these puzzles? Perhaps different things explain each: the
proper explanation of the puzzle concerning testimony will in turn differ from the
proper explanation for the puzzle concerning expertise which will differ from the
proper explanation of the puzzle concerning disagreement. In fact, those who have
sought to explain these puzzles in moral epistemology have done just that, seeking
to explain them individually rather than collectively.2 I am not interested here in
these piecemeal accounts. Rather, I am interested in the possibility of giving a
unified explanation of all of these puzzles. As I’ll argue, we can give such a unified
explanation. The unified explanation I articulate here is an elegant, simple
explanation that utilizes a familiar epistemic mechanism. Given that, all things
considered, a unified account ought to be preferred, and provided that this account
can adequately explain the puzzles and explain them better than alternative
unified accounts, we have reason to prefer the account I give.
Moral Testimony?,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74, 3 (2007): 611-634; Robert J.
Howell, “Google Morals, Virtue, and the Asymmetry of Deference,” Nous 48, 3 (2014): 389-415;
Sarah McGrath, “The Puzzle of Pure Moral Deference,” Philosophical Perspectives 23, 1 (2009):
321-344; Andreas L. Mogensen, “Moral Testimony Pessimism and the Uncertain Value of
Authenticity,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92, 1 (2015): 1-24; Philip Nickel,
“Moral Testimony and its Authority,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4, 3 (2001): 253-266.
2 For accounts which deal only in moral testimony, see Crisp, “Moral Testimony Pessimism,”
Hills, “Moral Testimony,” Hopkins, “What is Wrong,” Howell, “Google Morals,” McGrath, “Pure
Moral Deference,” Mogensen, “Moral Testimony Pessimism,” and Nickel, “Moral Testimony”; for
accounts which deal only in moral expertise, see Sarah McGrath, “Skepticism about Moral
Expertise as a Puzzle for Moral Realism,” Journal of Philosophy 108, 3 (2011): 111-137 and
Gilbert Ryle, “On Forgetting the Difference between Right and Wrong,” in Essays in Moral
Philosophy, ed. A. Melden (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1958), 147-159; for accounts
which deal only in moral disagreement, see William Tolhurst, “The Argument from Moral
Disagreement,” Ethics 97, 3 (1987): 610-621. Although no accounts exist which seek to explain
all three puzzles together, some accounts consider two of the puzzles in tandem, looking to the
bearing one puzzle may have on explaining the other (but not giving an account of what explains
them both): for example, Ben Cross, “Moral Philosophy, Moral Expertise, and the Argument
from Disagreement,” Bioethics 30, 3 (2016): 188-194 argues that the puzzle of moral
disagreement undermines the possibility of moral expertise; Julia Driver, “Autonomy and the
Asymmetry Problem for Moral Expertise,” Philosophical Studies 128, 3 (2006): 619-644 considers
the puzzle of our resistance to accepting the testimony of supposed moral experts, and Sarah
McGrath, “Moral Disagreement and Moral Expertise,” in Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 4 , ed.
Russ Shafer-Landau (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 87-108 looks to moral disagreement
within the context of there being no moral experts.
30
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
This paper will proceed as follows. First, I will look more closely at these
longstanding puzzles of testimony, expertise, and disagreement, and the existing
piecemeal explanations on offer. Then, I will provide my unified explanation, the
Higher Standards account, which holds that moral beliefs typically have a higher
epistemic standard than non-moral beliefs. After providing my unified account and
showing how it explains the puzzles, I consider two competing unified accounts
and argue that both are unacceptable. Finally, I consider and respond to two
objections to my own account.
1. The Oddity of Moral Epistemology
Here, I’ll explain briefly why each of the three puzzles noted above has been
thought to be especially puzzling. In the next section, I’ll explain how to deal with
these puzzles in a unified way.
One area of moral epistemology that has recently received a great deal of
attention is moral testimony, and for good reason: our judgments regarding moral
and non-moral testimony exhibit a striking asymmetry. While we think it’s
perfectly acceptable to form non-moral beliefs solely on the basis of others’ reports,
we balk at instances of forming moral beliefs solely on another person’s say-so.
Consider:
Eleanor has always enjoyed eating meat but has recently realized that it raises
some moral issues. Rather than thinking further about these, however, she talks
to a friend, who tells her that eating meat is wrong. Eleanor knows that her friend
is normally trustworthy and reliable, so she believes her and accepts that eating
meat is wrong.3
Danielle hears about an upcoming demonstration protesting Israel's war in Gaza.
Although she knows the causes of the war and knows that civilians are dying
from IDF bombing, Danielle is unsure whether the war is just. She doesn’t try to
think through the matter for herself. Instead, she asks a reliable and trustworthy
friend, who says the war is immoral. Danielle accepts her friend's claim and joins
the protest. Asked by a journalist why she is demonstrating, Danielle says she
knows the war is wrong because her friend told her so.4
Here, many object to Eleanor’s and Danielle’s reliance on their friends in forming
their moral beliefs: there is something prima facie wrong about Eleanor and
Danielle forming their moral beliefs solely on the basis of their friends’ say-so.
Importantly, these judgments don’t seem to be confined to the specific moral
subject matter (e.g. eating meat) or sporadic; as Sarah McGrath notes, “the attitude
3
4
Hills, “Moral Testimony,” 91.
Mogensen, “Moral Testimony Pessimism,” 1.
31
Nicole Dular
that pure moral deference is more problematic than non-moral deference is
widespread, even if not universal, in our culture.”5
Moral testimony isn’t the only area in moral epistemology that presents
unique epistemic challenges; consider expertise. While it’s obviously true that
there are experts on all kinds of non-moral subjects, moral experts are thought to
be at best few and far between, and at worst entirely non-existent.6 Moreover,
while it’s usually clear what’s required for non-moral expertise, there’s confusion
and disagreement over what is even required for moral expertise. To put it most
pessimistically: if, contrary to appearances, there even are any moral experts, we
will be seriously hard pressed to find them.7
And, if moral testimony and expertise weren’t enough, moral disagreement
poses its own unique challenges. Unlike disagreement in non-moral domains,
moral disagreement is thought to be especially intractable, as it persists even when
both parties appear to share the same (non-moral) evidence. Because of its
intractability and persistence, the mere fact of moral disagreement appears to lead
directly to moral skepticism. For example, Tolhurst argues that it makes our moral
beliefs never justified,8 while McGrath and Vavova both argue that disagreement
leads to skepticism about a certain subset of our moral beliefs.9 Note that no such
route to non-moral skepticism (about the existence of global warming, say) is
generally thought to be available. Worse, moral disagreement seems to be more
widespread than non-moral disagreement.
This way in which moral disagreement appears to lead to moral skepticism
will be my focus here regarding the epistemic asymmetry of moral and non-moral
disagreement. Even so, there two closely related questions regarding moral
disagreement that I’m not interested in pursuing here. I’ll mention them only to
set them aside for the remainder of the paper. First, the question of (a) why moral
disagreement is so widespread and intractable, and, second, the question of (b)
whether we should be “steadfast” and retain our moral beliefs when faced with
such disagreement. I set these related issues aside and focus on the question of how
moral disagreement can lead to moral skepticism for present purposes because
unlike the issue of skepticism, (a) and (b) do not directly concern notable epistemic
McGrath, “Skepticism about Moral Expertise,” 323.
McGrath, “Skepticism about Moral Expertise,” 323; McGrath, “Moral Disagreement;” Ryle, “On
Forgetting.”
7 Michael Cholbi, “Moral Expertise and the Credentials Problem,” Ethical Theory and Moral
Practice 10, 4 (2007): 323-334.
8 Tolhurst, “Moral Disagreement.”
9 McGrath, “Moral Disagreement;” Katia Vavova, “Moral Disagreement and Moral Skepticism,”
Philosophical Perspectives 28, 1 (2014): 302-333.
5
6
32
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
asymmetries in moral epistemology. I take (a) to be a metaphysical metaethical
question, as the widespread and persistent nature of moral disagreement typically
requires metaphysical explanations, such as that either moral relativism or
expressivism is true.10 Although (b) is an epistemic question, I take it to be a
question about the correct response to peer disagreement in general, not a question
about moral epistemology in particular. In other words, it’s unlikely that the
correct response to peer disagreement about morality differs the correct response
to peer disagreement about non-moral matters. In any case, I won’t pursue either
of these questions here.
Now, while moral epistemologists have offered explanations of these three
asymmetries between moral and non-moral epistemology, what is striking is that
all extant approaches have been piecemeal in nature: such accounts aim to explain
only why moral testimony is especially problematic, or why moral expertise is
especially difficult, or why moral disagreement is especially bad news for moral
knowledge. For example, proposals to explain moral testimony appeal to problems
it creates for moral agency,11 or moral understanding (the true “aim” of moral
beliefs),12 or that we can’t identify reliable testifiers.13 Likewise, explanations of the
puzzle of moral expertise have pointed to difficulties in identifying experts14 or to
the widespread presence of disagreement as undermining the possibility of moral
experts.15 Lastly, accounts of moral disagreement have claimed that the explanation
of why moral disagreement leads to skepticism is that we should all be
conciliationists about disagreement in general.16 But when each of the issues of
moral testimony, moral expertise, and moral disagreement are taken together as a
whole, the phenomenon to be explained changes its shape and becomes quite
striking: it seems that there’s not one special problem with moral testimony, one
special problem with moral expertise, and one special problem with moral
For examples of these types of arguments, see: Gilbert Harman, “Moral Relativism,” in Moral
Relativism and Moral Objectivity, ed. Gilbert Harman and Judith Jarvis Thomson (Cambridge,
MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1996), 1-64; Jesse Prinz, The Emotional Construction of Morals (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2007); David Wong, Natural Moralities: A Defense of Pluralistic
Relativism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006).
10
Crisp, “Moral Testimony Pessimism;” Hills, “Moral Testimony;” Hopkins, “What is Wrong;”
Howell, “Google Morals;” Mogensen, “Moral Testimony Pessimism;” Nickel, “Moral Testimony.”
12 Hills, “Moral Testimony.”
13 McGrath, “Pure Moral Deference.”
14 Cholbi, “Moral Expertise;” Driver, “Moral Expertise.”
15 Cross, “Moral Philosophy.”
16 Vavova, “Moral Disagreement.”
11
33
Nicole Dular
disagreement. Instead, it seems there’s some special problem with moral
epistemology as a whole.
Of course, some think that our judgments concerning the asymmetry of
moral testimony, expertise, and disagreement with their non-moral counterparts
are illusory, preferring instead to offer debunking explanations of these
judgements.17 My purpose in this paper is not to take issue with the asymmetry
judgments themselves. Rather, I’ll simply assume things are as they appear to be.
Supposing that there are these puzzling differences, we are faced with two options:
either go piecemeal, and explain each puzzle independently, or go wholesale, and
offer a unified account that explains them all together. Again, what’s notable is
that all approaches to these puzzling asymmetries between moral and non-moral
beliefs (including the debunking ones) have taken the first option, offering
disunified, piecemeal explanations.18 What hasn’t been attempted, though, is
taking the second option and going wholesale in our explanation. My aim in this
paper is to do just that, taking the second, unexplored option, and providing a
unified account.
In the next section, I will lay out my unified account. Importantly, my
account has advantages over the piecemeal accounts currently on offer. Beyond the
fact that, all things considered, unified explanations ought to be preferred to
disunified ones, my account avoids positing any exceptional features of moral
beliefs that some other piecemeal accounts have relied on, like the idea that moral
beliefs have a distinct “aim” that non-moral beliefs don’t. Rather, my account relies
on a familiar epistemic mechanism that is commonplace and widely discussed:
epistemic standards and how they shift. According to my account, moral beliefs
typically have a higher epistemic standard than non-moral beliefs. This means,
Driver, “Moral Expertise;” Jason Decker and Daniel Groll, “Moral Testimony: One of These
Things is Just Like the Other,” Analytic Philosophy 54, 4 (2014): 54-74; Jason Decker and Daniel
Groll, “The (In)significance of Moral Disagreement for Moral Knowledge,” in Oxford Studies in
Metaethics, Volume 8, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), 140167; Karen Jones “Second-hand Moral Knowledge,” Journal of Philosophy 96, 2 (1999): 55-78;
Karen Jones and Francois Schroeter, “Moral Expertise,”Analyse and Kritik 34, 2 (2012): 217-230;
Andrew Reisner and Joseph Van Weelden, “Moral Reasons for Moral Beliefs: A Puzzle for Moral
Testimony Pessimism,” Logos and Episteme 4 (2015): 429-448; Peter Singer, “Moral Experts,”
Analysis 32, 4 (1972): 115-117; Paulina Sliwa, “In Defense of Moral Testimony,” Philosophical
Studies 158, 2 (2012): 175-195.
18 To be clear: while some have considered two of these puzzles together (e.g., Kieran Setiya,
Knowing Right from Wrong (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), addresses both
disagreement and testimony, and Cross, “Moral Philosophy” considers how the presence of
disagreement bears on expertise), there exists no account that explains all three in a wholly
unified manner.
17
34
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
roughly, that the standard agents must meet in order to receive the relevant
positive epistemic credit (e.g., knowledge or justification) is typically more
stringent for moral beliefs than the corresponding standard is for non-moral
beliefs. To be clear, I won’t be arguing for a universal claim: that every single
moral belief will have a higher epistemic standard compared to any other nonmoral belief. Such a universal claim is too strong to be plausible. Rather, my claim
will be that this is typically the case, and as such it is a characteristic and
noteworthy feature of moral epistemology as such. Importantly, one need not
endorse such a universal claim to adequately explain the asymmetries between
particular areas of moral and non-moral epistemology, since, as we’ve seen, these
concern general issues with particular aspects of moral epistemology. For example,
the testimony-involving asymmetry is not that for every single possible instance of
non-moral testimony, any possible instance of moral testimony will be more
problematic than any possible instance of non-moral testimony. That would be
quite implausible; rather, it is that moral testimony in general is (more)
problematic.19 In order to assess this account, we should first turn to the concept of
an epistemic standard.
2. The Higher Standards Account
2.1. Epistemic Standards
In very basic terms, we can think of an epistemic standard as marking how good of
an epistemic position an agent needs to be in to count as knowing or as having a
justified belief. The idea of an epistemic standard captures the intuitive thought
that in order to determine whether an agent’s belief is justified or counts as
knowledge, we need to know not just how much evidence theyhave, but how
much theyneed.
This concept of an epistemic standard allows us to capture the thought that
in some areas of inquiry, or in some contexts, what’s required for knowledge or
justification can change: it’s not that knowledge of every kind of fact requires the
19 The same can be said for the other aspects of moral epistemology that have received
widespread attention, namely expertise, and the effect disagreement has in undermining
knowledge or leading to skepticism. Expertise by definition concerns a general ability, or
knowledge of a range of facts about a particular topic, not perfect ability or knowledge of every
single fact about a particular topic. Likewise, the phenomenon regarding moral disagreement
concerns how it in general leads to skepticism, not how every single instance of moral
disagreement undermines the status of knowledge for every single moral belief every single
person has. I further explain how my account of there typically being a higher epistemic
standard for moral beliefs explains puzzling asymmetries in moral epistemology in section 2.2.
35
Nicole Dular
same strength of evidence. This is just to say that sometimes at least, the epistemic
standards shift.20
This shiftiness of epistemic standards has been utilized by contextualists in
epistemology to explain otherwise surprising patterns in our knowledge
attributions. For it seems that, while we may want to deny large-scale skepticism
wherein agents always know little to nothing at all, we may also want to allow for
small-scale skepticism, wherein agents fail to know particular propositions in
particularly demanding circumstances. For example, while it seems perfectly
innocuous to say that I know that I have hands when I am walking to class, once I
find myself embedded in a classroom discussion about skepticism it seems correct
to deny that I know I have hands. Contextualists explain these shifty judgments by
appealing to epistemic standards: from the walk to the classroom to the discussion
of skepticism within the classroom the epistemic standard has shifted (more
specifically it has gotten more strict).21 In this case, while my perception of having
hands was good enough to make my belief that I have hands knowledge outside of
the classroom, this evidence is no longer sufficient to make my belief knowledge
once inside the classroom’s skeptical walls with its stricter epistemic standard.
That is the intuitive idea. But we can get a bit more specific. We can say that
an epistemic standard specifies a range of possibilities that an agent may ignore or
fail to rule out while still counting as knowing or having a justified belief.22 These
possibilities specify ways the world could be in which not-p is true (when one’s
belief is p). Importantly, this means that for any given belief, there is more than
one epistemic possibility: we don’t divide up the epistemic possible worlds simply
into two worlds, p and not-p, where one of these is the actual world. Rather,
epistemic possibilities are individuated by ways in which your belief could be false.
I use an evidentialist model of standards here for the sake of simplicity. Nothing in my
argument hangs on this assumption.
21 Stuart Cohen, “Knowledge and Context,” Journal of Philosophy 83, 10 (1986): 574-583.
22 Strictly speaking, this is actually where contextualists and fallibilists—who also appeal to
epistemic standards—part ways in their understanding of what a standard specifies. Fallibilists
will say that an agent does not need to rule out every possibility, while contextualists will say
that they do; the difference is how each is quantifying over ‘every.’ For the fallibilist, ‘every’
really does pick out every single possibility, while for the contextualist ‘every’ picks out a certain
subset of every single possibility, for example every salient possibility. This is perhaps why some
contextualists hold that contextualism is an infallibilist position (see David Lewis, “Elusive
Knowledge,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 4 (1996): 549–567.), while others hold it to
be fallibilist in nature (see Mark Heller, “The Proper Role for Contextualism in Anti-Luck
Epistemology,” Nous 33, 13 (1999): 115-129.). In the end, though, each camp seems to agree on
this general statement: out of all the total possibilities, in order to know an agent must be able to
rule out only all of those possibilities in a subset of these total possibilities.
20
36
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
For example, there are many possible worlds in which your belief that you have
hands is false: you could be hallucinating, you could be dreaming, etc. But only
some of the ways the world could be—only some of these possible worlds—are
relevant to the epistemic status of your beliefs in the actual world. This is because
of some relation they bear to you, and that you bear to them: they are salient, or
relevant, etc. Provided you are able to rule out that set of worlds where your belief
would be false, your beliefs enjoys the relevant positive epistemic status (e.g.
knowledge, justification). Overall, the rigor of an epistemic standard can be
specified in one of two ways: sometimes, a more rigorous standard specifies more
possibilities that one must be able to rule out, while other times it specifies
possibilities that are simply harder to rule out. My account allows for both of these
interpretations of rigor.
Like rigor, the notion of “ruling out” possibilities can be understood in a
number of ways. On a probabilistic model, this could mean either that some
possibilities are made more improbable, or that more possibilities are made
improbable. My claim is just that for moral beliefs, the epistemic standard shifts,
becoming more rigorous and thus requiring more in at least one of these two ways.
Importantly, this view of standards is also compatible with both internalist and
externalist theories of justification and knowledge. For example, if one were a
reliabilist, the upwards shift in the rigor of the standard would require one to have
more safety or sensitivity. If one were an evidentialist, one would be required to
possess stronger evidence that rules out more possibilities. What’s important for
my claim is that what it takes to have an epistemic state (justification, knowledge)
depends on the rigor of the standard, and that morality makes this rigor increase.
Additionally, my account is neutral between competing accounts of how
standards are fixed.23 For example, some hold that this range is flexible, picking out
different worlds in different contexts, while others hold that the same range of
worlds is picked out in all contexts.24 Articulating the causes of the shiftiness of
epistemic standards in general, and the shiftiness of standards for moral beliefs in
particular, is a large project unto itself. Happily, it’s mostly outside the scope of the
current paper. This is because there are two independent questions: whether moral
beliefs typically have a higher standard and what exactly fixes standards. These
questions are obviously related, since one’s answer to the latter might determine
23 To be clear: my account of what an epistemic standard is neutral along these lines; however,
invariantism regarding epistemic standards (that is, standards for any and all kinds of beliefs) is
incompatible with my argument for the higher standard for moral beliefs.
24 The former being contextualists and subject sensitive invariantists, and the latter being
invariantists.
37
Nicole Dular
one’s answer to the former. But answers to the two can come apart in the sense
that many can agree that moral beliefs have a higher standard while completely
disagreeing about what fixes the standard. For example, many can agree that
skeptical scenarios have a higher epistemic standard than non-skeptical ones while
disagreeing over what functions to make the standard stricter in skeptical scenarios
(e.g. whether contextualism or subject sensitive invariantism is the best account).
However, to preserve the credibility of my claim that moral beliefs typically have a
higher standard it is important that there at least be someinitially plausible models
available, so I will briefly address this issue here.
One possible model of how standards are fixed is the well-known stakesmodel, wherein an epistemic standard is determined in part by the practical stakes,
or the costs of one’s belief turning out to be false.25 Such a standards-fixing model is
taken up elsewhere, where it is said that there are certain practical stakes are
unique to moral beliefs (for example, the costs of being the target of certain
reactive attitudes) such that when we account for these stakes, such a model does a
good job of tracking how most moral beliefs have a higher epistemic standard and
how the ones that intuitively don’t, don’t.26 Although articulating further details of
this model would take us too far afield here, I hope this gives the intuitive, initially
plausible flavor of the model. Of course, if this particular model does not sound
appealing, one needn’t reject my claim that moral beliefs typically have a higher
standard: again, these are distinct claims, and so we can agree that moral beliefs
typically have a higher standard while disagreeing over the correct account of
what fixes those standards. The claim that moral beliefs have a higher epistemic
standard does not depend on the success of my—or any—particular standardsfixing model. For example, we could instead adopt a kind of Relevant Alternatives
Contextualist view, where the possibilities that one must be able to rule out are
those that are presupposed or otherwise entered into the conversational score,
coupled with a view that moral beliefs presuppose more or more difficult to rule
out possibilities.27 Again, although I lack the space here to adequately address
which particular standards-fixing models are the best accounts of the typical
higher standard for moral beliefs, such plausible models are available. Given the
Jeremy Fantl and Matt McGrath, Knowledge in an Uncertain World (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2009); Robin McKenna, “Interests Contextualism,” Philosophia 39, 4 (2011):
741-750; Jason Stanley, Knowledge and Practical Interests (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2005).
26 Nicole Dular, “Moral Stakes, Higher Standards,” (unpublished manuscript).
27 Michael Blome-Tillman, “Knowledge and Presuppositions,” Mind 118, 470 (2009): 241–294.
25
38
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
availability of such models and their initial plausibility, the credibility of the claim
I make here that moral beliefs have such a higher standard should remain intact.
2.2. A Unifying Explanation
With this conception of epistemic standards and the idea that the epistemic
standard is typically stricter for moral than for non-moral beliefs in hand, we can
approach our original problem. I’ll now briefly explain how my Higher Standards
account resolves the three puzzling featured in moral epistemology with which we
began.
First, consider moral testimony and the default judgment that it is an
illegitimate way to gain moral knowledge. According to my account, in order to
have moral knowledge the requirement that an agent rule out possible worlds is
relatively stringent: an agent either needs to rule out a significant number of
possible worlds or to rule out a set of worlds that is harder to rule out. The reason
why agents are unable to gain moral knowledge from testimony is because merely
forming one’s belief on the basis of another’s report does not provide one with the
ability to rule out all of the possibilities that one would need to in order to have
(moral) knowledge. Although testimony may equip one with true moral beliefs, it
does not equip one with the ability to rule out the demanding set of possible
worlds that one needs to in order to have moral knowledge.28
One may wonder how far my Higher Standards account goes in explaining not just
asymmetries in judgments about cases of pure moral and non-moral deference (where speakers
do not inform hearers of any of the reasons for the truth of their belief) but also in explaining
asymmetries in judgments about cases of impure moral and non-moral deference (where hearers
come to adopt not only the speaker’s belief, but also their reasons in support of the truth of their
belief). The worry is that since my account explains the asymmetry in terms of being in a
position to rule out possibilities, in cases of impure moral deference the hearer would be able to
rule out all of the same possibilities as the speaker, since they possess the same reasons for the
belief; but, the asymmetry remains even in these cases, as we still judge that the hearer lacks
justification or knowledge while the speaker does not. However, my Higher Standards view is
amenable to preserving this asymmetry of impure testimony: it can do so by adopting a more
robust interpretation of what “ruling out” requires. For example, on some contextualist views,
ruling out would require more than just possessing evidence that makes certain propositions
improbable to a certain degree. Rather, it requires that one is able to engage with others in a
certain way, for example by appeasing any objections they may have about the truth of your
belief. For this more robust understanding of “ruling out”, see David Annis, “A Contextualist
Theory of Epistemic Justification,” American Philosophical Quarterly 15, 3 (1978): 213-219, and
Carl Wellman, Challenge and Response: Justification in Ethics (Southern Illinois University
Press, 1971) on the Challenge-Response Model.
28
39
Nicole Dular
Next, consider the apparent lack of moral expertise. According to my
account, the standard for moral expertise is stricter than the standard for expertise
in other, non-moral domains. This means that the kind of epistemic credentials
one would need to have in order to count as an expert are greater for moral
expertise. For example, one would need to be able to rule out a comparatively large
amount of possibilities for a comparatively large amount of moral beliefs to count
as an expert. The reason why moral experts are either scarce or entirely nonexistent is because few or perhaps none of us have the ability to do this.
Lastly, my model can explain how disagreement may, after all, lead to
skepticism. One way it could do this is by functioning to make relevant new
possibilities. For example, it may function to make relevant possibilities like
making a mistake in reasoning, or succumbing to a bias. The more widespread a
case of disagreement over some moral proposition m, the more possibilities must be
ruled out in order to qualify as having knowledge that m. Provided that I cannot
rule these out, I fail to secure knowledge. Since standards are understood in terms
of possibilities that must be ruled out, moral disagreement leads to skepticism by
making more possibilities relevant, and thus by making the epistemic standard
more stringent.
Now that we’re clear on how my Higher Standards account explains these
problematic asymmetries, we should look to see how alternative unified accounts
would explain the asymmetries. Again, since in this paper I am seeking an
explanation of the apparent oddity of moral epistemology that would vindicate our
commonsense judgments about moral testimony, moral expertise, and moral
disagreement, I will not be considering debunking explanations of that oddity. As
alternative explanations, the accounts to consider are those that posit a mechanism
other than the one I appeal to, namely epistemic standards. In the next section, I
will consider such rival accounts.
3. Alternative Explanations
3.1. Morality is Hard
One explanation that moral epistemology in general is more problematic than nonmoral epistemology is that moral matters are just so exceedingly difficult to figure
out. It’s just so much more difficult, the thought goes, to determine moral matters
such as whether abortion or eating meat is morally permissible than whether the
bus runs on Saturdays. It’s a very difficult task to do the work that is necessary to
adequately settle moral questions: one must consider arguments for and against,
checking for falsities, fallacies, counterexamples, and more. Both the kind of
40
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
reasoning and time required to consider such questions is large and looming.
Morality is hard.
Of course, I agree that morality is hard: this is something that my Higher
Standards account explains. In order for this view to be a real competitor, it can’t
simply amount to the view that moral matters are difficult, since the Higher
Standards account may admit this, and then just explain this fact in terms of a more
rigorous epistemic standard for morality. Instead, this account must explain what
makes moral matters epistemically difficult. Moreover, it must do so by appeal to a
mechanism other than the one I’ve identified in order to be a genuine rival.
There are two mechanisms that this rival account might point to. One way
of thinking about the “morality is hard” view is that settling moral questions
requires a large amount of time; alternatively, one may think that the kind of
reasoning required to settle moral questions is exceedingly demanding. Using E to
stand for the evidence base that’s required to have a justified belief, the view might
be either (a) that it is harder to obtain E, i.e. one generally needs to spend more
time working in order to obtain E, or (b) that it is harder to draw the correct
conclusion on the basis of E, i.e. that the kind of reasoning required to work
through one’s evidence in order to arrive at a justified belief is of a high level or is
quite complex (e.g. it involves the use of difficult mathematical formulas), or both
(a) and (b).
Let’s take option (a) first. Given this mechanism, one would say that the
reason why moral knowledge or justification is harder to obtain is that one needs
more time working through or thinking about moral issues in order to successfully
arrive at knowledge. More specifically, many agents considering moral questions
just haven’t obtained E yet (or, more minimally, that they’ve been able to obtain
less of E than the amount of E they’re typically able to obtain within the same time
for the E that corresponds to various non-moral beliefs).29 Taking option (b)
instead, one would say that the reason why moral knowledge or justification is
harder to obtain is that moral issues require one to engage in more demanding or
complex forms of reasoning in order to successfully arrive at knowledge. More
specifically, many agents considering moral questions just haven’t successfully used
the kind of higher level reasoning required to adequately draw conclusions on the
basis of E. Lastly, if one held both (a) and (b), one would say that the reason why
moral knowledge or justification is harder to obtain is that moral issues both
require greater time and more complex reasoning in order to successfully arrive at
a justified belief or knowledge.
29 For example, one could think that one needs normative evidence to justify a normative belief,
and it is generally harder to acquire normative evidence (than descriptive evidence).
41
Nicole Dular
In general, this unified account could explain the initial asymmetries in the
following way. If moral beliefs are hard with respect to (a) and (b), and moral
expertise requires one to have a high amount of evidence and evaluate it extremely
well when reaching certain moral beliefs, then moral expertise would be hard to
come by. Likewise, given (a) and (b) reliable testifiers would be hard to come by.
And, lastly, if it is difficult to assess moral claims in the ways (a) and (b) outline,
moral disagreement can lead to skepticism by causing one to lose the evidence one
may have had or undermining one’s ability to work through the now-competing
evidence one has.
Are either of these mechanisms a good explanation of the epistemic
difficulty of morality? I think that they are not. Remember here that in order for
this rival explanation to explain why moral beliefs have certain epistemic puzzles
that non-moral beliefs don’t, the mechanisms it points to need to be distinctive of
moral beliefs. This is because the explanation we are seeking is one that explains
how there are certain systematic differences between moral and non-moral
epistemology. The reason why this rival account fails is simply because the
mechanisms it picks out are not distinctive. To see why, consider the following
pair of moral and non-moral beliefs:
(NM2): Daria is a college freshman taking an applied ethics course and after one
month in the course has just been told that many animals were killed last year for
their meat, as well as the fact that many animals (e.g. mice, rabbits, and moles) are
killed each year in producing and maintaining crops for food that all vegetarians
depend on. Daria considers the question of whether being vegetarian kills more
animals than being a meat-eater does. After consulting a few reliable yet neutral
sources (e.g. peer-reviewed scientific journals, not PETA) on each side of the
debate and crunching the numbers, Daria forms the belief that being vegetarian
kills more animals than being a meat-eater.
(M2): Daria is a college freshman taking an applied ethics course and after one
month in the course has learnt about arguments both for and against eating meat,
considering only arguments for its permissibility and impermissibility (not its
obligatoriness), and considering the same quantity (e.g. one each) and quality (e.g.
both valid, with plausible premises) of arguments for each side, from a credible
yet neutral source (e.g. the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Daria considers
the question of whether eating meat is morally permissible or morally
impermissible. Without consulting anyone else, and after carefully considering
the arguments, Daria forms the belief that eating meat is morally permissible.
In these cases, it’s clear that the non-moral belief is difficult with respect to
(a): Daria would need to spend a lot of time working collecting the relevant data
about the statistics of animal deaths in crop cultivation and meat farms. It’s also the
case that each belief is difficult with respect to (b): Daria would need to engage in
42
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
some high-level reasoning such as higher-level math to work through all of the
information on statistics he had gathered. And, as this account stipulates, the moral
belief is likewise difficult with respect to (a) and (b). Yet, it seems that the moral
belief still lacks the same kind of epistemic credit that the non-moral belief has (for
example, it appears to be less justified).30 Moreover, upon reflection is it simply not
true that morality is the only domain of inquiry that requires a great amount of
time or complex reasoning to arrive at knowledge or justified beliefs within that
domain: various complex scientific questions also require these. So, even though
this account is unified, it does not succeed in accounting for the asymmetries of
moral and non-moral epistemology.
However, defenders of this alternative account might object. They might
insist that the kind of reasoning required for moral beliefs is always going to be
more demanding or complex than that required for any other domain of inquiry, as
it’s of its own special kind, unlike any other type of reasoning used in any other
domain. For example, perhaps moral reasoning requires a special kind of sense or
faculty that other domains don’t, the operation of which is itself extremely
complex. But it’s terribly ad hoc to posit a special kind of reasoning just to save this
account. Moreover, this seems to just put a name to the problem, rather than
offering an explanation of it. We started by observing that moral knowledge is
hard to come by. It won’t do to end simply by observing that the kind of reasoning
that leads to moral knowledge is also itself hard to come by. We would still want to
know why this is.
We’ve just seen why this Morality is Hard explanation fails. In the next
section, I’ll explain why the other competing explanation won’t work either.
3.2. Morality’s Many Defeaters
Another unified explanation claims that the reason moral beliefs lack the kind of
epistemic credit non-moral beliefs enjoy is that moral beliefs typically come with
more defeaters than non-moral beliefs do. There are two ways of understanding
this defeaters account. On one way of understanding it, the accounts turns out not
30 At this point one may object that we would not have the judgment that the moral belief is less
justified here if the non-moral belief were to be some controversial scientific claim. First, notice
that the non-moral belief presented is controversial: Daria is confronting conflicting accounts of
the number of animals killed. Second, in order for the cases to be analogous, if the controversial
scientific claim considered is abstract and general, so must the moral claim, which would force us
to consider a new moral case as well (e.g., if we are to consider a controversial scientific theory
we would need to consider a controversial moral theory); here, both beliefs are comparative and
concrete in nature.
43
Nicole Dular
to be a genuine rival to my Higher Standards account. On another understanding,
although it is a genuine rival, it results in counterintuitive conclusions, and so
ought to be rejected. First, let me briefly explain the relevant notion of defeaters in
play.
Defeaters come in roughly two kinds: rebutting and undercutting
defeaters.31 On an evidentialist picture, rebutting defeaters are those that serve as a
reason to believe a proposition that’s incompatible with one’s conclusion from the
evidence (e.g. d is a defeater that warrants not-p (on the basis of E) when one was
originally warranted in concluding p on the basis of E), while undercutting
defeaters serve as reason to believe that E does not actually itself warrant p,
without providing reason to believe the negation of p. Given this characterization,
one way to understand defeaters is as a kind of higher-order evidence, that is,
evidence about the character of one’s (first-order) evidence.32 For example,
consider your belief that the apple is red that you formed on the basis of your
perception of the apple appearing red to you. Your belief would be accompanied
by the first type of (rebutting) defeater if you were told that you were given an
inverted color spectrum drug: in this case, the fact that you were given such a drug
means that you now have, on the basis of your perception, a reason to believe that
the apple is green, not red. It is evidence that your original first-order evidence—
your perception—actually does not warrant p (that the apple is red), but rather
warrants a proposition incompatible with p (that the apple is green). In this case
we can say that your total evidence consisting of E+d warrants not-p. Your belief
would be accompanied by the second type of (undercutting) defeater if you were
told that there’s a 50/50 chance that you were given an inverted color spectrum
drug: in this case, your original evidence for your belief that the apple is red (your
visual perception) would be insufficient evidence for your original belief, such that
you ought to abstain from believing what color the apple is. In this case we can say
that your total evidence consisting of E+d fails to warrant p.
Now, for the opponent who wants to claim that the grounds of the
asymmetries in moral epistemology is that moral beliefs typically have more
defeaters than non-moral beliefs, they must not only point to defeaters that
accompany moral beliefs, but also point to ones that are specific to moral beliefs
such that non-moral beliefs either don’t also typically have them or don’t typically
John Pollock, Contemporary Theories of Knowledge (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield,
1986).
32 David Christensen, “Higher-Order Evidence,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81,
1 (2010): 185-215; Maria Lasonen-Aarnio, “Higher-Order Evidence and the Limits of Defeat,”
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88, 2 (2014): 314-345.
31
44
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
have them to the same degree. Otherwise such defeaters would not account for the
difference in epistemic credit between moral and non-moral beliefs. Given this
constraint, there are a few considerations one might cite. One might point to the
fact that there is a lot of disagreement surrounding moral claims, much more than
what typically surrounds non-moral claims. Likewise, one might argue that there
are more counter-arguments to consider with respect to moral claims than nonmoral claims. With each of these options, one could claim that one’s (first-order)
evidence E doesn’t yield a justified moral belief or knowledge because any of these
considerations would serve as a kind of defeater for E, either in the sense that it
makes E insufficient to warrant the belief that p, or that it makes E warrant the
belief that not-p: either way, one’s total evidence consisting of E+d fails to make
one epistemically justified in believing p or knowledge that p. For example,
consider a case where I originally believe that eating meat is morally permissible,
but then come across another rational person (perhaps even with all the same nonmoral evidence that I have) who disagrees with me and who instead believes that
eating meat is morally impermissible. One could claim that that’s a reason to think
that my original evidence E is not sufficient to justify me in believing that eating
meat is morally permissible, such that I should abstain from believing it. In this
case, the fact of this disagreement undercuts my (first-order) evidence E to believe
that eating meat is morally permissible; thus, my total evidence consisting of E+d
would fail to make my belief that eating meat is morally permissible epistemically
justified. In this way, even if an agent had roughly the same amount of first-order
evidence for both her moral and non-moral beliefs, her moral belief would be less
justified because there would be more defeaters present, and so more reasons that
make it the case that E is not sufficient to warrant her moral belief. The total
evidence the agents typically have for moral and non-moral beliefs is not the same.
At this point we need to consider precisely how defeaters function to make
one’s evidence insufficient to warrant one’s belief that p. On one understanding,
defeaters (or, more specifically, the fact of disagreement in the moral case) function
by raising a specific possibility that my belief is false. For example, maybe eating
meat is morally impermissible after all, given that (so many) reasonable others
think so; perhaps I made a mistake in my reasoning, or succumbed to bias. On this
understanding, while defeaters undermine my (first-order) evidence E for my
belief that p such that my total evidence of E+d is no longer sufficient to justify p,
they do this by introducing additional ways in which my belief could be false, that
is, possibilities. On this account, defeaters just introduce or make relevant certain
kinds of possibilities, ones that are not ruled out by one’s evidence (given that, if it
could be ruled out, it wouldn’t render E insufficient to justify p).
45
Nicole Dular
For example, consider our previous example involving the belief that the
apple is red, where one’s evidence consists of the perception of the apple appearing
red, and the defeater that’s present is the fact that there’s a 50/50 chance one was
given an inverted color-spectrum drug. On the proposed understanding of what
defeaters are, the fact that there’s a 50/50 chance that one was given an inverted
color-spectrum drug introduces a new possibility that the apple is not red (more
specifically, that it’s green). However, since one’s evidence—namely, one’s
perception—is not able to rule out this possibility, one’s belief fails to be justified
or count as knowledge.
At this point, talk of possibilities should sound familiar to the attentive
reader. This is because epistemic standards were originally understood as
specifying possibilities that must be ruled out in order for a subject’s belief to count
as justified or knowledge. Remember again that this is just to say that the more
rigorous the standard, the greater the set of possibilities. So, if defeaters are just
relevant possibilities—specifically, ones that one’s evidence is unable to render
sufficiently improbable—then one who holds that there are generally more
defeaters for moral beliefs than non-moral beliefs is committed to the view that
moral beliefs generally have higher epistemic standards.
To further understand how this 'More Defeaters' view is not a rival view to
my favored 'Higher Standards' view, consider the following model.
On this model, let the box indicate the set of all epistemic possibilities. Let the ‘P’
circle indicate the possible worlds in which p is true, and the ‘E’ circle indicate the
46
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
worlds that are compatible with one’s evidence; all of the space outside of these
circles consists of not-p worlds. Using our case, we can understand the ‘t1’ line as
indicating the epistemic standard at the time before the defeater was introduced
(before you were told that there’s a 50/50 chance you were given an inverted color
spectrum drug), while the ‘t2’ line indicates the epistemic standard at the time after
the defeater was introduced. The epistemic standard at t1 indicates all of the
possible worlds one needs to rule out at t1 in order to count as having a justified
belief that p (namely all of those worlds above the ‘standard at t1’ line), while the
epistemic standard at t2 indicates all of the possible worlds one needs to rule out at
t2 in order to count as having a justified belief that p (all of the worlds above the
‘standard at t2’ line). The standard at t1 is pretty low: it indicates, roughly, that one
can fail to rule out all of the not-p worlds that fall below it while still having a
justified belief that p. However, at t2 the standard increases, becoming more
stringent, thus indicating, roughly, that one can fail to rule out only those not-p
worlds that fall below it while still having a justified belief that p. Importantly,
though, while at t1 (pre-defeater) there are no not-p worlds that are compatible
with your evidence (that is, there are no worlds that are inside the E circle but
outside the P circle), at t2 (post defeater) there are; this means that while your
belief meets the epistemic standard at t1, it fails to meet it at t2, such that while
you have a justified belief or know that p at t1, you have an unjustified belief or
fail to know that p at t2.
It should be clear, then, that this particular interpretation of the More
Defeaters view is not a rival account to my Higher Standards account. Rather than
denying that moral beliefs enjoy higher epistemic standards than non-moral
beliefs, this More Defeaters view is just articulating a specific way in which the
standard is higher, or how it is that the standard is higher for moral beliefs (or,
more specifically, what makes a possibility one an agent must be able to rule out).
But, again, they are not disagreeing about the fact that the epistemic standard is
higher for moral beliefs.
However, there remains an interpretation of the More Defeaters view that is
a genuine competing alternative to my Higher Standards view. On this alternative
understanding, defeaters (or, more specifically, the fact of disagreement in the
moral case) function to make one’s evidence insufficient to warrant one’s belief
that p by directly affecting one’s evidence. It is not that the standard becomes more
rigorous, but just that one falls farther from it given the reduced strength of one’s
evidence. On this account, the epistemic standards for moral and non-moral beliefs
could be exactly the same and remain fixed, but yet moral beliefs are more
47
Nicole Dular
epistemically problematic because one’s evidence is typically comparatively worse
in the moral domain.
Importantly, for this view to capture cases of comparative lack of
justification and not just knowledge for moral beliefs, it would have to be the case
that the relevant defeaters are recognized or possessed by the agent. This is because
although some hold that the simple existence of defeaters—in this case, the simple
existence of moral disagreement—is enough to undermine knowledge, it is widely
held that in order to affect justification, the agent herself must be confronted with
the defeater or made aware of it.33
The problem with this account is that while it seems correct to say that
justification is undermined by defeaters only when agents are cognizant of them
for non-moral cases, in the moral case lack of awareness of the defeater leads to
counterintuitive results. For example, this understanding of the More Defeaters
view would implausibly conclude that in cases where agents just aren’t aware of
such disagreement concerning a moral issue (for example, because they live in very
isolated homogeneous communities, or never bothered to ask anyone else their
opinion on the matter), their moral beliefs would not suffer a loss of justification.
Likewise, if all that is required to be a moral expert is to have a sufficiently high
volume of justified moral beliefs, then one could become a moral expert quite
easily. But this is very counterintuitive. So, while this understanding of defeaters
can explain some cases, it cannot explain all the puzzles that would need to be
explained.
In the end, then, the More Defeaters view either is not a genuine rival to my
Higher Standards view, or is rife with counterexamples, and so ought to be
rejected.
4. Different but Equal?
Even if the first understanding of the More Defeaters view is not incompatible
with my favored Higher Standards view, we might still wonder why one should
favor my account. After all, if both accounts explain initial puzzles about moral
beliefs, and do so by appealing to epistemic possibilities, then why should we say
that what explains this difference is that moral beliefs have a higher epistemic
standard, rather than that they are accompanied by more defeaters?
33 Defeaters that undermine justification are commonly referred to as “mental state defeaters,” as
opposed to “propositional defeaters” which are not believed by the agent and only undermine
knowledge. On mental state and propositional defeaters see Michael Bergmann, Justification
without Awareness (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006) on mental state and propositional
defeaters.
48
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
For example, some may think that my Higher Standards view sacrifices
important intuitions regarding the relation between evidence and defeaters by
always viewing defeaters as relevant possibilities. On my view, the relationship
between evidence and defeaters involves the introduction of new possibilities. This
makes it seem as though while one’s epistemic position worsens, one’s evidence
doesn’t worsen at all—that is, one’s epistemic position worsens despite one’s
evidence not worsening at all. But this seems to sacrifice a very intuitive thought
that one’s evidence gets worse with the presence of defeaters. Instead of raising
epistemic standards, defeaters are typically conceptualized under the second
interpretation of the More Defeaters view, wherein they render one’s belief
insufficiently justified by just simply reducing the strength of what serves as one’s
justification, for example one’s evidence. Intuitively, we think that when one is
told that there’s a 50/50 chance that one was given an inverted color spectrum
drug, it’s not just that one’s belief now fails to be justified, but that one’s evidence
has gotten worse, and fails to be justified because one’s evidence has gotten worse.
On a probabilistic model of evidence, the thought is as follows: while initially one’s
evidence may have made p probable to degree .9, when a defeater is introduced
one’s evidence now makes p probable to degree .5. However, as noted, this
understanding of how one’s evidence has gotten worse when a defeater is present
is compatible with epistemic standards remaining at the same level. So, it might
seem as though my Higher Standards account cannot account for the
commonsensical thought that when defeaters get introduced one’s evidence
becomes worse.
While I agree that it would be problematic for my view if it was unable to
account for this commonsensical thought, I don’t believe that it faces this problem.
To see this, we should return to our model. On a standard probability model, a
defeater just functions to make E smaller (in other words, by making the not-p
space bigger), where a certain probability is specified for an epistemic standard,
and the probability that p is determined as follows (assuming for simplicity only
finitely many possible worlds):
Pr (p) = number of p-worlds in E / total number of worlds in E
There is, however, an alternative way to think of how defeaters affect
probability. On my model, it’s true that when a defeater is introduced, the degree
to which one’s evidence makes p probable decreases. Rather than utilizing the
above standard model of probability, though, my fallibilist view amends it as
follows:
Pr (p) = number of p-worlds in E above tn / total number of worlds in E above tn
49
Nicole Dular
While on this model of probability it’s true that one’s evidence is worse in the
sense of yielding a lower probability of p at t2 (post-defeater) than at t1 (predefeater), it has gotten worse precisely because the standard has gone up. So, this
alternative model can show how the probability of p given one’s evidence has
gotten worse when a defeater is present in a way that doesn’t make the raising of
epistemic standards irrelevant. Since my proposed way of understanding defeaters
in terms of possibilities can accommodate the sense in which one’s evidence has
gotten worse when a defeater is introduced, it ought not be abandoned
Another reason to favor my Higher Standards account is if it explains some
cases that this interpretation of the More Defeaters account doesn’t. Some of this
may turn on the precise theoretical explanation for the higher epistemic standard;
for example, if we endorse a kind of impurist view wherein the practical stakes of
holding a belief affects the degree of justification the belief has, then the More
Defeaters view would be an insufficient explanation of the degree of justification.
To see why this would be the case, take the classic bank cases as an example.34
Here, the proposition that the bank could’ve changed its hours isn’t properly
characterized as a defeater, since it’s not properly characterized as higher-order
evidence (that is, it’s not evidence that your first order evidence (that you were at
the bank last Saturday) does not warrant your belief (that the bank is open on
Saturdays)). Rather, something like the proposition that you were only dreaming
that you were at the bank last Saturday would be higher-order evidence. If we
should conceive of the way justification is determined for moral beliefs as
analogous to the bank cases (namely where the possibilities an agent must be able
to rule out in order to have a justified moral belief is partly determined by what’s
practically at stake in holding the belief), then this More Defeaters view will be
ruled out as the best explanation.
Moreover, it can also be said that in so far as defeaters introduce just one
type of possibilities, or hold that possibilities can be introduced in just one way, my
Higher Standards view will be able to explain more cases, and more diverse cases,
as possibilities are introduced in multiple ways (the presence of disagreement isn’t
the only way to introduce a possibility). These are all reasons to favor my Higher
Standards account over the first interpretation of the More Defeaters account, even
if the More Defeaters view is not a genuine rival to my favored Higher Standards
view.
34
Keith DeRose, “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” The Philosophical Review 104, 1 (1992): 1–52.
50
Harder, Better, Faster, Stronger: Epistemic Standards and Moral Beliefs
6. Conclusion
Moral testimony, moral expertise, and moral disagreement have all been thought
to be distinctively problematic—that is, problematic in ways non-moral testimony,
non-moral expertise, and non-moral disagreement are not. Previous explanations
of their problematic nature have been piecemeal in nature, seeking to explain why
each issue is problematic in isolation. In this paper, I’ve offered a unified
explanation of the problematic nature of these issues, the Higher Standards
account, thus departing from previous explanatory accounts of these phenomena.
According to this unified account, the relative epistemically problematic nature of
moral testimony, moral expertise, and moral disagreement is explained by the fact
that moral beliefs typically enjoy a higher epistemic standard than non-moral
beliefs. After first explaining my Higher Standards account, I considered two rival
unified accounts that would explain the problematic nature of moral testimony,
moral expertise, and moral disagreement, namely the Morality is Hard view and
the More Defeaters view. I argued that these accounts were either rife with
counterexamples, were ad hoc, or reduced to a variant of my view, concluding that
my Higher Standards account is the best unified explanation on offer.35
35 Acknowledgements: I am especially grateful to Hille Paakkunainen and Nathaniel Sharadin for
their many written comments on multiple drafts of this paper. I also thank Teresa Bruno-Nino,
Janice Dowell, Matthias Jenny, David Sobel, Preston Werner, and the Women’s Group of the
philosophy department at Syracuse University for helpful comments and conversations, as well
as audiences at the 2015 Rocky Mountain Ethics Congress and the 2016 Pacific Division Meeting
of the American Philosophical Association.
51