Theoretical Grounding in African Research
This book is a product of CODESRIA College of Mentors.
Theoretical Grounding in
African Research
CODESRIA College of Mentors
Handbook II
Edited by
Abdul Karim Bangura
Joseph Mensah
Anthony Bizos
Council for the Development of Social Science Research in Africa
DAKAR
© CODESRIA 2023
Council for the Development of Social Science Research in Africa
Avenue Cheikh Anta Diop, Angle Canal IV
BP 3304 Dakar, 18524, Senegal
Website: www.codesria.org
ISBN: 978-2-38234-096-7
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any
form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording or any
information storage or retrieval system without prior permission from CODESRIA.
Typesetting: Stefanie Krieg-Elliott
Cover Design: Genevieve Simpson
Distributed by CODESRIA
The book can be purchased directly at CODESRIA through this link:
https://bookshop.codesria.org
The Council for the Development of Social Science Research in Africa (CODESRIA) is
an independent organisation whose principal objectives are to facilitate research, promote
research-based publishing and create multiple forums for critical thinking and exchange
of views among African researchers. All these are aimed at reducing the fragmentation
of research in the continent through the creation of thematic research networks that cut
across linguistic and regional boundaries.
CODESRIA publishes Africa Development, the longest standing Africa based social
science journal; the African Sociological Review; Africa Review of Books and the Journal of
Higher Education in Africa. The Council also co-publishes Identity, Culture and Politics:
An Afro-Asian Dialogue; and the Afro-Arab Selections for Social Sciences. The results of
its research and other activities are also disseminated through its Working Paper Series,
Book Series, Policy Briefs and the CODESRIA Bulletin. All CODESRIA publications
are accessible online at www.codesria.org.
CODESRIA would like to express its gratitude to the Swedish International Development
Cooperation Agency (SIDA), the Carnegie Corporation of New York (CCNY), Andrew
W. Mellon Foundation, the Open Society Foundations (OSFs), Oumou Dilly Foundation,
Ford Foundation and the Government of Senegal for supporting its research, training and
publication programmes.
Contents
Dedication: Heed and Hail the Aiding Caller without Caning
(Poem in Honour of CODESRIA)
Olumuyiwa Adekunle Kehinde........................................................................................................................vii
Preface..........................................................................................................................................................................................................ix
Acknowledgements ........................................................................................................................................................................ xv
Notes on Editors and Contributors ...........................................................................................................................xvii
List of Doctoral Scholars ....................................................................................................................................................... xix
General Introduction
Abdul Karim Bangura, Joseph Mensah and Anthony Bizos.................................................. 1
I
BRIEF DISCUSSIONS OF THE THEORIES
1. African-centred
Doctoral Scholars............................................................................................................................................................ 11
2. Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
Doctoral Scholars............................................................................................................................................................ 53
3. Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
Doctoral Scholars............................................................................................................................................................ 77
4. Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
Doctoral Scholars.........................................................................................................................................................109
5. Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
Doctoral Scholars.........................................................................................................................................................139
6. Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
Doctoral Scholars.........................................................................................................................................................155
7. Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
Doctoral Scholars.........................................................................................................................................................187
8. Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
Doctoral Scholars.........................................................................................................................................................225
vi
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
II
APPLICATIONS OF A SAMPLE OF THEORIES
9. Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
Abdul Karim Bangura ..........................................................................................................................................245
10. Dialectics: Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
Joseph Mensah ................................................................................................................................................................265
11. Theorising Norms: Constructivism and its Application to the Study
of Africa’s International Relations
Anthony Bizos.................................................................................................................................................................285
12. Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
Abdul Karim Bangura ..........................................................................................................................................317
Apendices ............................................................................................................................................................................................341
Appendix A: List of CODESRIA Staff and Facilitators .....................................................341
Appendix B: Table of Contents (General Introduction, List of Sections
and Chapters, with page numbers) ..........................................................................................................343
Dedication
Heed and Hail the Aiding Caller Without Caning
(Poem in Honour of CODESRIA)
Olumuyiwa Adekunle Kehinde
Clarion calls coded in colours,
Like a rainbow the strata created.
And before you go-giggle, is blue the warmest colour?
When others in rainbow have not reigned?
Being coached like gazelles to run and outrun others
In the race out of the race, and from a distinct race
But out of haste and hate.
Rare mentors, real mentorship
Fashioned-not lately-but passionately delivering
To make we-cubs roar like ogidan* across the cedars and oaks.
Souls alloyed, spirits paired, hearts glued,
Head-to-head not just a rule or fluke
But a formulaic of excellence-ing
So as a team, we are lovely raised and trained to reign.
From stories to theories, and now a memory,
Indelibly marbled and stamped on these mending minds.
Oh CODESRIA, here we hail thee!!!
And as we hail, we sail to research-gates and to the rest of the cosmos.
Of what are we made? The African Elephant of Erudition,
With majestic matches and lumbering from savannahs to rainforests.
viii
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Clarion calls obeyed, creative power instilled and installed,
Hail Africa – Hail CODESRIA –
Creatively Organising Diligent Erudition and Spreading Reformation in Africa!!!
Hail CODESRIA – Hail Africa!!!
You are “Great oaks from little acorns grow”.
We are Africa, We are the World.
*
A Yoruba name for lion to show its majesty and physical power
Preface
This handbook is a continuation of Conducting Research and Mentoring Students
in Africa: CODESRIA College of Mentors Handbook (2019). In the hardcopy
textbook version of that handbook, Abdul Karim Bangura, Joy A. Obando,
Ishmael I. Munene and Chris Shisanya noted their awareness of research
methodology and mentoring needs in Africa, and addressed those needs. But
they were also cognisant of the need for theoretical grounding.
The authors added that Divine Fuh, who was not present at the CODESRIA
College of Mentors (CCoM) Institute in Nairobi, Kenya, made a similar
observation at the first CODESRIA Meaning-Making Research Institute (MRI)
convened in Harare, Zimbabwe from April 18 to 24, 2018.
This meant that there was a need for another volume that would cover the
principal African-centred and Western theories. Bangura and his colleagues also
noted that limited time and other resources could not permit them and the
Doctoral Scholars to take up this task when they wrote the first volume. It was
their hope that this second CCoM Institute (2019) would take up the challenge.
Undoubtedly, there are some students – and others – who see theorisation as
an abstract, idealist, or academic, if not esoteric, exercise undertaken merely for
the purpose of writing theses, dissertations, journal articles, etc. or for making
arguments, with little or no social relevance outside of an academic context.
To help address this misconception, it is important to make the imperative of
theory as explicit as possible here, rather than simply assume that it is self-evident.
Theories and theorisation help us to draw connections among different concepts
or phenomena and thus help guide our thoughts and organise our ideas about
reality. With the inherent, hidden and, sometimes, obvious interconnections
brought to light, we are able to generate new insights and ask novel questions
about phenomena in the real world. Not only does theorisation help us to make
sense of empirical data, it also assists us to tease out the subtle and not-so-subtle
relationships among variables.
Put differently, theories with their attendant theorisation help us to see the
proverbial forest and not just the individual trees, isolated from one another.
Many observers insist that facts speak for themselves. However, it is our belief
x
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
that facts never speak: it is only with theories and theorisation that we are able to
interpret facts or data meaningfully. Facts are analogous to bricks lying around
randomly in a brickyard; they become meaningful only after we systematically
bring them together with the aid of theorisation. Clearly then, thought
cannot proceed very far without some underlying theories, just as one cannot
write a good dissertation, thesis, or journal article without a conceptual or
theoretical framework.
Students are also unduly influenced by those in government circles who
propound that theory is removed from the ‘real’ day-to-day public policy problems
that need to be confronted and addressed. There are academics who accentuate
this thinking by arguing that theory-based teaching is not consistent with policyrelevance. This short-sightedness perpetuates the erroneous assumption that
theory and practice are separate spheres of activity, and that scholasticism which
is devoid of ‘real’ world data is fraught with peril. Nothing could be farther from
the truth. Since facts do not speak for themselves, it is theorising which helps us
to decide which facts are important and which are not, and theory prompts us
to explain how the same fact can be interpreted differently. Even policy-makers
who are dismissive of theory are implicitly or explicitly relying on their own ideas
and assumptions about how the world works in order to decide what to do. Thus,
both scholars and policy-makers are always engaged in theoretical speculation,
since it is difficult to make good policy if one’s basic organising assumptions are
flawed, just as it is hard to develop good theories without knowing a lot about
the real world.
Even though this handbook deals with theories in general, the selection was
based on the criterion of having social relevance and applicability to the African
context. There are a few theories that have not been used to study Africa, but
being the currencies of their disciplines, they have the potential to be used at
some point. To ignore them would be foolhardy. We nonetheless give primacy
to African-centered and African-related theories in the handbook. We make no
claim, however, to exhaustiveness regarding the theories covered, or to homogeneity
in the use of these theories for African people, or among African scholars. While
Africans have some cultural values and ethno-racial attributes that bind them
together as people, there is no denying that Africa, like any other continent,
is imbued with substantial cultural and linguistic diversity. With its Africancentredness, the handbook is a decidedly subaltern voice aimed at subverting
the ersatz objectivity and value-neutrality in the Eurocentric orthodoxy in
theorisation. It seeks to alleviate the systemic suppression of African voices in the
production of knowledge in the global academy.
We must also add that this is a handbook dealing with about 150 theories
from across the disciplines for easy reference. It is not a book on theories in one
discipline where each theory is augmented by a case study or several case studies.
Preface
xi
The reader who is interested in application will be well-served by looking at the
four chapters in which the studied theories are applied to relevant case studies. In
addition, a relationship between all the theories covered has not been established
by making references across disciplines and chapters in the book because theories
are used for different purposes in different disciplines, for the obvious reason
that their foci of analyses are different. Furthermore, our handbook is not about
challenging or refuting theories, no matter their origin. It is about their existence.
It is up to the user to do so if and when necessary, just as we did in our four
application chapters.
Moreover, this handbook is not an ‘academographic toolkit’ towards
epistemic ‘decolonisation’. It does not offer a voice about the importance of
critically situating knowledge production, by putting different epistemological
perspectives into dialogue and by self-critiquing the colonial library in which we
operate (as African universities are still a colonial project). This is not the goal of a
handbook. There are special journals and books for that. Finally, we do not open
the Pandora’s Box of ‘post-colonial’, ‘decolonisation’ and ‘deneocolonisation’
designations, as that is not the intent of the handbook.
The handbook is divided into the General Introduction chapter and two
major sections. The first section comprises descriptions of the almost 150 theories
covered and presented within various subject titles in alphabetical order. The
second section is composed of a sample of chapters that show how a theory can be
used to explore Africa in general or a particular African phenomenon. It must also
be noted here that we could not name 50 authors in a chapter. We had the same
dilemma for the first volume and decided that the designation Doctoral Scholars
was better because all of them contributed to all of the chapters. Even though
they were divided into eight groups, the entries ran into different disciplines.
Also, the scholars reached out across groups for assistance from those who knew
their assigned disciplines better, and during the oral presentations benefited from
one another.
It behooves us to end this Preface with the brief history of the CCoM as
presented by Ibrahim Oanda. In 2016, CODESRIA sought to reorganise and
transform the Small Grants Programme for Thesis Writing that the organisation
had used as a vehicle to support graduate students in African universities for
about three decades. The small grants programme had been introduced in 1988
and provided fieldwork grants to masters and doctoral students registered in
African universities. The grants programme contributed to ameliorating the needs
of graduate students by supporting the fieldwork phase of their graduate work,
as institutions faced resource scarcities. For a high number of graduate students
in African universities in the late 1980s and most of the 1990s, a CODESRIA
grant for thesis writing was all they would access to support their work. The
requests for support from graduate students to CODERSIA continued to rise.
xii
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
By 2014, proposals submitted from graduate students from across the continent
were tending towards 1,000, competing for about 50 available grants. Even a
proposal by the organisation to reduce the amount of grants and support more
students would not lead to adequate grants compared against the number of
applicants and would potentially lead to another problem, that of lack of quality.
Also, the expansion of higher education institutions on the continent had
led to another staff crisis, undergraduate student enrolments had increased, and
barely enough academics were available in most institutions to give sufficient
and quality supervising and advising to doctoral students. An internal analysis
of the doctoral theses submitted to CODESRIA from students who had
benefited from the small grants from 2010 to 2014 showed serious gaps in
quality across all the core parts of a doctoral thesis. While the broad objective of
the small grants was to support students for fieldwork and improve quality, the
quality of the theses suggested that a different approach was required if doctoral
students were to be mentored in a culture of academic quality and with a focus
on future scholarship.
In 2015, with a grant from the Carnegie Corporation of New York (CCNY),
CODESRIA 2015, established the College of Senior Academic Mentors as part
of the African Academic Diaspora to African Universities Programme. Those
who serve as mentors in the College are senior academics from the Diaspora
(both outside and within Africa) who volunteer their time to be linked to
doctoral students in African universities for purposes of mentoring and
advising the students throughout their doctoral programmes. The mentors read
and comment on the students’ proposals and thesis/dissertation chapters; assist
the students with relevant reading materials; and link the students to other
means of support within their (the mentors’) network for purposes of workshop
and conference participation and co-publication. The doctoral students are
paired with established scholars both in Africa and around the world working
in the same areas of research and who have accepted membership of the
College. The mentors provide the students with the critical methodological
and epistemological guidance that they require for their doctoral studies and
further academic development. The purpose of this mentor-mentee relationship
is to raise the quality of academic material being generated by young African
scholars. The College currently has 26 senior academic mentors linked to 91
doctoral students in African universities.
The students admitted to the College have to apply and be nominated by their
schools/deans and involve their primary supervisors. A mentorship relationship,
though virtual, involves three people: (1) the student, (2) the primary supervisor
and (3) the mentor. The mentors have to copy any advice to students to the
primary supervisors, and also to CODESRIA for purposes of monitoring the
relationships. The primary supervisors likewise are requested to do the same.
Preface
xiii
We see this approach as beneficial in four respects:
1. It gives the students the academic support needed to complete their doctoral
programmes in ways that would not have been possible without the support. A
number of doctoral students in African universities lack quality and timely advice
which would push them to complete their studies in time. Studies in a number
of institutions have documented the lack of comprehensive written advice to
students as a limiting factor in timely and quality completion of programmes.
2. The approach permits sharing of knowledge and insights between the mentors
and primary supervisors in ways that contributes to enriching supervisory capacity
in African institutions.
3. The mentor-mentee relationship has the potential for establishing long-term
relationships beyond the doctoral degree in ways that ultimately contribute to
re-establishing cultures of academic excellence in African universities.
4. By supporting the timely completion of doctoral programmes, the intervention
contributes to increasing the qualified staff pool in a number of African universities,
in the social sciences and humanities.
The first cohort of 49 doctoral students was linked to mentors in the College in
2016. About 90 per cent of this initial cohort has completed their doctoral studies,
besides other achievements such as publication and conference attendance. The
institute held in Nairobi from October 21 to November 1, 2019 was for the
second cohort of 42 students who had been selected to the College that year. They
are linked to the mentors for two years. CODESRIA undertakes an evaluation of
the programme twice in a year to get feedback from the mentors and the students
on how the relationships are proceeding and what needs adjusting.
Abdul Karim Bangura,
Joseph Mensah
Anthony Bizos
Acknowledgements
We, and hopefully many readers, owe gratitude to:
The Carnegie Endowment, for funding the Council for the Development of
Social Science Research in Africa (CODESRIA) College of Mentors.
CODESRIA administrators and support staff, for successfully designing and
launching the programme.
Administrators and staff at the Kenya School of Monetary Studies, for successfully
hosting the 2019 CODESRIA College of Mentors Institute.
Leonide Azah Awah and Dominique Tania Sambou-Tchicaya, for their exemplary
administrative assistance before, during, and after the Institute.
Renee Moodie, for her thorough editing work.
Dr Robin Blake, for his research assistance on Chapter 6.
The two referees, for their suggestive evaluations; asking difficult questions leads
to better answers.
Family members, colleagues and friends, for their prayers and support.
Notes on Editors
Abdul Karim Bangura is a Senior Mentor of the CODESRIA College of
Mentors based in Dakar, Senegal for doctoral candidates in Africa; a ResearcherIn-Residence of Abrahamic Connections and Islamic Peace Studies at the
Center for Global Peace at American University and the director of The African
Institution, both in Washington DC; a Visiting Graduate Professor of Regional
Integration at the University of Cabo Verde in Praia, Cabo Verde; an External
Reader of Research Methodology and Municipal Government at the Plekhanov
Russian University in Moscow; and the International Director and Adviser of the
Centro Cultural Guanin in Santo Domingo Este, Dominican Republic. He holds
five PhDs in Political Science, Development Economics, Linguistics, Computer
Science, and Mathematics. Bangura is the innovator of Ubuntugogy Educational
Theory, Consciencist Communication Theory, Ujamaa Communication Theory,
Theorem of Accelerated Language Deaths, African Peace Paradigms, Rekh
Methodology, Utchā and Uhem Methodology, Behsâu-Pehsa Methodology,
Er/Set/Sthenå/S-tut/Tut Methodology, Ujamaa Methodology, Consciencist
Methodology, and Hrārā/S-tut/Qeṭ Methodology. He is the author of more than
100 books and more than 700 scholarly articles. He is also the winner of more
than 50 prestigious scholarly and community service awards. He is fluent in
about a dozen African and six European languages, and is studying to increase his
proficiency in Arabic, Hebrew, and Hieroglyphics. Bangura was among the group
of first four scholars to address the United Nations General Assembly. He is also a
member of many scholarly organisations, has served as President and then United
Nations Ambassador of the Association of Third World Studies, and is a Special
Envoy of the African Union Peace and Security Council and the Editor-in-Chief
of the Journal of Living Together dealing with peace and conflict resolution.
Anthony Bizos is a Lecturer in the Department of Political Sciences at the
University of Pretoria in South Africa and the coordinator of the department’s MA
degree programme in Diplomatic Studies. His areas of specialisation are Theories
of International Relations, Foreign Policy Analysis and Research Methodology.
He teaches modules on these and related topics at both an undergraduate and
postgraduate level. His research interests include norm emergence, evolution
xviii
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
and contestation in international relations; the responsibility to protect and
associated norms of human protection; decolonising the curriculum and
indigenous knowledge systems, as well as African agency in international affairs.
He has in the past taught Research Methodology at the Diplomatic Academy of
the South African Department of International Relations and Cooperation, as
well as programmes on Negotiation and Conflict Management at the Ministry of
Foreign Affairs in the Democratic Republic of Congo. He is currently a member
of the teaching faculty at the African Leadership Centre (ALC) in Nairobi, Kenya,
where he conducts seminars on Research Methodology with PhD students from
the University of Nairobi and King’s College, London. In 2014, he was a research
fellow at the Centre for the Study of International Relations, Sciences-Po, in
Paris, France, and he is currently a teaching fellow at the Panteion University
of Political Sciences in Athens, Greece. He is a committed Pan-Africanist and
considers it a distinct honour that he was invited to serve as a resource person at
the CODESRIA College of Mentors Institute in 2019.
Joseph Mensah is a product of the University of Ghana and is now a Full Professor
of Geography at York University in Toronto, Canada. He completed his MA and
PhD at the Wilfrid Laurier University and the University of Alberta, respectively,
and taught at the Simon Fraser University and the University of British Columbia
before joining York in 2002. He was the Head of the Department of Geography at
York from 2016 to 2019. Professor Mensah’s specialties are in Social and Cultural
Geography, Research Methodology, and Quantitative Techniques. His current
research interests are in critical development theory, globalisation and health,
and transnational migration. Professor Mensah has received several competitive
grants from the likes of the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of
Canada (SSHRC), the Gates Foundation, the Global Development Network,
International Labor Organization, and the Commonwealth Secretariat. He has
written several journal articles, book chapters, encyclopedia entries, and books.
He is the author of the well-received Black Canadians: History, Experiences, Social
Conditions (Fernwood Publishing, 2002/2010). His latest book (co-authored) is
Boomerang Ethics: How Racism Affects Us All (Fernwood, 2017). Professor Mensah
has been an instructor for the Carnegie Corporation-sponsored Pan-African
Doctoral Academy (PADA) at the University of Ghana since 2015. He was one
of the winners of the Council for the Development of Social Science Research in
Africa’s (CODESRIA) Inaugural Diaspora Visiting Professor Fellowships in 2016
and a co-Applicant and Research Advisor to the Borderless Higher Education
for Refugees project (BHER) that offers on-line degree courses to refugees in the
Dadaab Refugee Camp in Kenya.
List of Doctoral Scholars
N° Name
Institutional Affiliation
1.
Abati, Omomayowa Olawale
Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile Ife,
Nigeria
2.
Adeleke, Victoria Ajibola
University of KwaZulu-Natal, South
Africa
3.
Ahmed, Beyan Yuya
Haramaya University, Ethiopia
4.
Aworefa, Tolulope Samuel
Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile Ife,
Nigeria
5.
Balogun, Cecy Edijala
University of Ibadan and the Nigerian
Institute of Social and Economic
Research, Ibadan, Nigeria
6.
Bamidele, Seun
Ekiti State University, Nigeria
7.
Bekele, Helina Befekadu
Makerere University, Uganda
8.
Chollom, Kachollom Monday
University of KwaZulu-Natal, South
Africa
9.
Dalalo, Tefera Tesfaye
Mekelle University, Ethiopia
10.
Dogbey, Nancy
Nelson Mandela Metropolitan
University, South Africa
11.
Erima, Juliet Awinja
Moi University, Kenya & University of
Kwazulu-Natal, South Africa
12.
Eshalomi, Henrietta
University of Ibadan, Nigeria
13.
Gule, Zanele Muntu
University of eSwatini, Luyengo,
eSwatini
14.
Gweru, Benjamin
Stellenbosch University, South Africa
15.
Hammond, Adubea Pearl
University of Cape Coast, Ghana
16.
Idowu, Harrison Adewale
Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile Ife,
Nigeria
17.
Kamanzi, Stella-Maris
Makerere University, Uganda
18.
Kehinde, Olumuyiwa Adekunle
University of Zululand, South Africa
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
xx
19.
Kanyingi, Benson Waiganjo
Karatina University, Kenya
20.
Mayoyo, Nancy
Kenyatta University, Kenya
21.
Metu, Somtochukwu Janefrances
University of Nigeria, Nsukka,
Nigeria
22.
Moli, Jacques Bertrand Mengue
International Relations Institute of
Cameroon, Yaoundé, Cameroon
23.
Mugocha, Everisto
University of the Witwatersrand, South
Africa
24.
Namukasa, Jacqueline
Makerere University, Uganda
25.
Nweke, Precious Ifunanya
University of KwaZulu-Natal, South
Africa
26.
Odeyemi, Samuel Oladunjoye
University of KwaZulu-Natal, South
Africa
27.
Ogbonna, Maimuna Immaculata
University of Ibadan, Nigeria
28.
Ojukwu, Njideka Charlotte
University of KwaZulu-Natal, South
Africa
29.
Olick, Lilian
University of Nairobi, Kenya
30.
Oluwawehinmi, Ayokunle
Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile Ife,
Nigeria
31.
Omotuyi, Modesola Vic
Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile Ife,
Nigeria
32.
Omowumi, Moromoke Salau
Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile Ife,
Nigeria
33.
Onuoha, Nwawuloke Beatrice
University of Fort Hare, South Africa
34.
Oyekanmi, Omosefe
University of Ibadan, Nigeria
35.
Oyekola, Isaac Akintoyese
Landmark University, Omu-Aran,
Nigeria
36.
Owusu, Emmanuel Asare
University of Ghana, Legon, Ghana
37.
Oyinloye, Bosede Odunola
Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile Ife,
Nigeria
38.
Udo, Fidelis Joseph
University of KwaZulu-Natal, South
Africa
39.
Usman, Abdullahi Kofar Naisa
Bayero University, Kano, Nigeria
General Introduction
Abdul Karim Bangura, Joseph Mensah and Anthony Bizos
The focus of this handbook is to introduce scholars to African-centred and
Western theories that can be employed to ground research on Africa or on an
African phenomenon. This endeavour, however, requires an immediate word of
caution. It would appear that some scholars regularly conflate ‘grounding’ one’s
research in a theoretical framework with Grounded Theory. This requires a bit
more elucidation here since the two are fundamentally different.
Grounded Theory was introduced in 1967 with the publication of the book
titled The Discovery of Grounded Theory by Barney Glaser and Anselm Strauss. As a
product of Columbia University, Glaser had been trained in quantitative methods;
whereas Strauss, as a graduate of the Chicago School of Sociology, understood
social reality qualitatively, as the outcome of interactions among people in their
given contexts. Both scholars, however, ultimately came to agree that ‘pure’ reality
is what social science should endeavour to capture. As a result, they went against
the mainstream of sociological research at the time and suggested that one should
not start with existing ‘grand’ or middle- range theories so as to empirically test
reality, but that one should rather be preoccupied with discovering theories.
Grounded Theory is therefore not a theory. Rather it is a methodology which
consists of techniques and guidelines for data collection and analysis to produce
theory grounded in data. As such, Grounded Theory is an inductive approach to
research which seeks to ‘build theories’ which are grounded in data and which
might also explain observed phenomena. According to Charmaz, who has applied
the method to investigate real-life situations and offers cutting-edge examples
and tips, the distinguishing characteristics of grounded theory are the following
(Charmaz 2006:5):
(a) ‘The researcher begins with data collection and analysis as opposed to starting
with an existing theory.’
(b) ‘Codes, concepts and categories to sort the data come from the data and not from
hypotheses.’
2
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
(c) ‘Analysis proceeds in stages with constant comparisons between data and ideas.’
(d) ‘Theory is developed in stages.’
(e) ‘Memoranda in the field are used to elaborate on codes.’
(f ) ‘Sampling is for theory construction not representativeness.’
(g) ‘The literature review comes later, after the independent analysis.’
Indeed, this handbook is not concerned with Grounded Theory or the
question of how to ‘build theory.’ Rather it is concerned with the use of ‘topdown theory’ – understood as the use of theory that has been formulated
prior to empirical research either by other theorists or by the researchers
themselves. The focus of this handbook responds to the reality that many
studies in the social sciences are conducted without, or with scant reference
to, theory. Consequently, much of the existing scholarship in the disciplines
tends to be atheoretical and overtly descriptive in nature. It can be said that
descriptive studies do result in some interesting findings, but this handbook’s
proposition is that these studies do not necessarily serve to move knowledge
forward. There are several explanations as to why researchers conduct studies
that are not based on theory. Shoemaker, Tankard and Lasorsa (2011)
highlight some of the possible reasons as follows:
(a) ‘Expediency – it is difficult to formulate hypotheses which will contribute to our
theoretical understanding; so, it is easier to conduct descriptive research.’
(b) ‘Inadequate training – a thorough training in social science disciplines requires
time and resources.’
(c) ‘Lack of clear definition or identification of theoretical problems in a particular
discipline.’
(d) ‘Lack of precedent – some areas of research have few examples of good theories or
many social science theories are not well developed.’
(e) ‘A field’s lack of a clearly defined and agreed upon paradigm – in the Kuhnsian sense
(i.e. Thomas Kuhn 1962), a field moves forward when a community of scholars
identify theoretical puzzles that need to be solved. However, it is often the case
that many disciplines lack an agreement on what these puzzles are.’
One might also add that determining what constitutes a ‘good’ theory or deciding
which theory to ‘choose’ contributes to the aversion to grounding research in
theory. In this respect, one might ask whether this is a question of deciding
whether one theory is better than another, or whether the existence of a plurality
of theories makes it difficult for researchers to make a choice. So as not to fall
into the relativism trap, it is prudent to recognise that theoretical options and
preferences converge around researcher interpretations and practices when they
evaluate the choice of theory and, simultaneously, these choices are bound by
elements of subjectivity and disciplinary positioning.
Bangura, Mensah and Bizos: General Introduction
3
Those scholars with a positivistic leaning, for example, are primarily interested
in empirical and explanatory theories which are generally understood as a set
of interconnected abstract statements consisting of assumptions, definitions
and empirically testable hypotheses which purport to describe and explain the
occurrence of a given phenomenon or a set of phenomena (Sanders 2002).
According to David Sanders, the following are three main ways by which
positivists might evaluate explanatory theories before deciding on which one to
select (Sanders 2002:47):
(a) ‘A ‘good’ theory must be internally consistent: it must not make statements such
that both the presence and the absence of a given set of antecedent conditions are
deemed to ‘cause’ the occurrence of the phenomenon that is purportedly being
explained.’
(b) ‘A “good” theory relating to a specific class of phenomena should, as far as possible,
be consistent with other theories that seek to explain related phenomena.’
(c) ‘Critically, genuinely explanatory theories must be capable of generating empirical
predictions that can be tested against observation.’
On the other hand, those with a more interpretivist or anti-foundationalist
leaning might challenge the positivistic assumption that explanation needs to be
a causal account of the occurrence of some phenomenon or set of phenomena,
or that explanation needs to provide a set of antecedent necessary and sufficient
conditions to account for this occurrence. Interpretivists might rather suggest
that claims to knowledge are always provisional and contested, and that there
is always a fusion among all types of theorising. Interpretivists might find that
whereas it is difficult to generalise about the role of theory, at the very least,
the use of a pre-formulated theoretical or conceptual scheme is indispensable
when attempting to classify, characterise and understand the social world. For
interpretivists, therefore, a major benefit of theory should be that it provides
guidance for research. Starting with a theory mitigates against data-gathering
and observation becoming a ‘wild-goose chase’ and prompts the researcher to
interrogate the value of a research project and how this project might relate to
other projects.
Since, as stated earlier, the focus of this handbook is on the principal Africancentred and Western theories that can be employed to ground research on Africa
or an African phenomenon, in the rest of this chapter we first discuss what a
theory is, the general types of theory, the levels of theory, and why theories are
important in systematic inquiry.
Next, we describe how a theoretical framework can be constructed. We must
mention here that some of what is in this chapter also appears in Conducting
Research and Mentoring Students in Africa: CODESRIA College of Mentors
Handbook (2019). It is replicated here in the spirit of the proverbial ‘there is no
need to reinvent the wheel’.
4
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Theory: What It Is, General Types, Levels, and Import
If a researcher is to consult 100 sources that have discussed theory, s/he will
encounter at least 50 different definitions of the notion. For example, the
Merriam-Webster Dictionary alone provides the following six definitions:
1. a plausible or scientifically acceptable general principle or body of principles
offered to explain phenomena: e.g., the wave theory of light
2. a. a belief, policy, or procedure proposed or followed as the basis of action: e.g.,
her method is based on the theory that all children want to learn
b. an ideal or hypothetical set of facts, principles, or circumstances often used
in the phrase ‘in theory, we have always advocated freedom for all’
3. a. a hypothesis assumed for the sake of argument or investigation
b. an unproved assumption: conjecture
c. a body of theorems presenting a concise systematic view of a subject: e.g.,
theory of equations
4. the general or abstract principles of a body of fact, a science, or an art music theory
5. abstract thought: speculation
6. the analysis of a set of facts in their relation to one another (Merriam-Webster
Dictionary 2020:1).
Next, after discerning that the term theory tends to be conflated with other
scientific concepts such as conceptual framework, description, model, prediction,
and typology, and also that there is no universal agreement among writers about
the meaning of theory, Graham C. Kinloch offers the following definition: ‘a
theory is [an] attempt to explain or account for a particular phenomenon in terms
of some other phenomenon which is viewed as explanatory. It is this explanatory
function which distinguishes a theory from related but nonexplanatory concepts’
(Kinloch 1977:10).
According to Ian Robertson, a theory helps a researcher to organise a series of
concepts in a meaningful manner by explicating the nexus among them. Thus,
as he puts it, a valid theory can be used to accurately prognosticate that similar
connections will take place in the future. He adds that while it is often said that
‘facts speak for themselves’, they actually do not. This is because, as he observes,
facts lack meaning until they are endowed with meaning, and that meaning is
furnished by theory (Robertson 1987:17).
Relatedly, we find Friedrich Nietzsche, for instance, noting quite provocatively
in The Will to Power that there are no facts, only interpretations. Invariably, any
interpretation is grounded in one theory or another, be it implicit or explicit.
To the extent that research entails considerable interpretation (e.g., of concepts,
methods, data, findings, conclusion, etc.), one can hardly conduct any meaningful
Bangura, Mensah and Bizos: General Introduction
5
research without a theoretical grounding of a sort. Indeed, in research, theory (or
theorisation) is always present – one cannot do without it, any more than one can
write a language without adhering to the rules of grammar.
In addition, Jeanne H. Ballantine and Keith A. Roberts denote theory as a
statement about how and why facts are connected to one another. They point
out that a theory exists at each level of analysis in the social universe. Due to this
verity, they add, a theory a researcher employs to investigate the social universe
hinges upon the components of the social universe to be examined, which range
from the individual within a small group to societies within the world system
(Ballantine & Roberts 2007:34).
Realising that the meanings that underlie the many definitions of theory
share certain similarities, Abdul Karim Bangura provides the following scientific
definition of theory as ‘a generalised logical statement that shows the relationship
between two or more hypotheses – i.e. generalised logical statements that show the
relationships between two or more variables – i.e. elements, features, or factors
that are liable to vary or change’ (Bangura 2019:22, 29).
Thereafter, Bangura describes two general types of theories. One type
is deductive theory, which begins with the general and ends with the specific.
The other type is inductive theory, which goes in the opposite direction: i.e. it
commences with the specific and ends with the general. Bangura then provides
the diagrammatic representation that follows to describe the building processes
of these two types of theories (Bangura 2019:29):
Bangura then repeats the denotation of a hypothesis mentioned earlier: i.e. ‘a
generalised logical statement that shows the relationship between two or more
variables’. A variable, as he also defined it previously, is ‘an element, feature, or
factor that is liable to vary or change, and it also shows the commonality among
concepts’. A concept, he says, is ‘a definition of words which can be an abstract idea
or a general notion’. And a word, he states, ‘is the smallest element of linguistic
meaning’ (Bangura 2019:22, 29).
Deductive Theory
↑
Hypotheses
↑
Variables
↑
Concepts
↑
Words
Inductive Theory
↓
Hypotheses
↓
Variables
↓
Concepts
↓
Words
6
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
We ought to mention here that there are other contrastive categories under
which various types of theories can be subsumed. Among the main ones are the
following seven.
The first is the informal-formal, whereby the former is unstructured and
reminiscent of assumptions pertaining to daily life and the latter is structured
by assumptions that underlie the scientific method – i.e. a method of procedure
that has characterised natural science since the seventeenth century, consisting
in systematic observation, measurement, and experiment, and the formulation,
testing, and modification of hypotheses.
The second is the descriptive-explanatory: while the former lacks an underlying
explicative paradigm, the latter has this feature.
The third is the ideological-scientific; while the former concerns ideas and
manner of thinking, the latter is based on the scientific method. The difference
between these two types of theories hinges upon a matter of degree rather
than form, as they both contain elements entailed in each and no theory is
completely objective.
The fourth is the intuitive-objective, whereby the former argues that knowledge
is subjective and based on what one feels, while the latter argues that knowledge
is external and not influenced by personal feelings or opinions in considering and
representing facts.
The fifth is the microscopic-macroscopic; while the former’s level of analysis is
the specific and individual, the latter’s level of analysis is the general and societal.
The sixth is the structural-functional, where the former focuses on the
compositions of phenomena, while latter pays attention to how the phenomena
develop gradually and metamorphose.
The seventh and final is the naturalistic-social, where the former employs
biological and real-life variables to examine a phenomenon while the latter
employs communal variables to investigate a phenomenon (for more on these,
see, for example, Kinloch 1977:16–17).
Then, citing the work of Chava Frankfort-Nachmias, David Nachmias and
Jack DeWaard (2014), Bangura discusses four levels of theory.
Level one is made up of ad hoc classificatory systems whereby ‘arbitrary categories
are constructed in order to organise and summarise empirical observations’.
Level two is comprised of taxonomies whereby ‘systems of categories are
constructed to fit general observations in such a way that relationships among the
categories can be described’.
Level three entails conceptual frameworks whereby ‘descriptive categories are
systematically placed in a broad structure of explicit propositions, statements
of relationships between two or more empirical properties, to be accepted
or rejected’.
Bangura, Mensah and Bizos: General Introduction
7
And level four is composed of theoretical systems that ‘combine taxonomies and
conceptual frameworks by relating descriptions, explanations, and predictions in
a systematic manner’ (Frankfort-Nachmias et al. 2014:37–39; Bangura 2019:29).
In terms of the importance of theory in systematic investigation, many aspects
have been identified by various scholars. For the sake of brevity, only a few of these
features are presented here. The interested reader can consult, for instance, the works
by Graham C. Kinloch (1977), Jon M. Shepard (1981), Ian Robertson (1987),
and Jeanne H. Ballantine and Keith A. Roberts (2007) for additional attributes.
To begin with, researchers have used their knowledge of theory to delineate
the major organising features in post-industrial society. Theoretical knowledge
has been employed to develop innovations (e.g., computers have led to more
advanced defence systems) and to formulate government policies (e.g., computers
are used to simulate economic forecasts using different theories to see their
probable impacts if they were to be actually applied to the real economic system).
Educational research and intellectual institutions are continuously enriched as
theoretical knowledge continues to be treated as important (Shepard 1981:91).
Next, a researcher can employ a theory to make the facts of social life
comprehensible to us. S/he can do so by simply placing what appear to be
meaningless events in a general framework that allows them to determine
causality, to explain phenomena, and to make predictions (Robertson 1987:17).
Also, a theory can inspire a researcher to engage in an investigation whose
findings could render the theory either valid or invalid. This will allow them
to modify the theory or to provide the rationale for novel theories. As the
process repeats itself endlessly, the result is the accumulation of new knowledge
(Robertson 1987:29). In essence, theories change and are themselves a reflection
of the historical and cultural contexts of their enunciation.
Constructing a Theoretical Framework
Bangura culls from the work of the University of Southern California Libraries
System (USCLS) to denote a theoretical framework as ‘the configuration that
can accommodate or undergird a theory’ (Bangura 2019:28). He then proceeds
to state the following six steps which a researcher can employ to generate an
effective theoretical framework as delineated by the USCLS (parenthetical notes
are Bangura’s; see Bangura 2019:28):
1. ‘Examine your thesis title [hypotheses] and research problem. The research problem
anchors your entire study and forms the basis from which you construct your
theoretical framework.’ (USCLS 2017:1; Bangura 2019:28).
2. ‘Brainstorm about what you consider to be the key variables in your research. Answer
the question, “What factors contribute to the presumed effect[s]?” (USCLS
2017:1; Bangura 2019:28).
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
8
3. ‘Review related literature to find how scholars have addressed your research
problem. Identify the assumptions from which the author(s) addressed the
problem.’ (USCLS 2017:1; Bangura 2019:28).
4. ‘List the constructs and variables that might be relevant to your study. Group these
variables into independent and dependent [also, antecedent, intervening, and
mediating] categories.’ (USCLS 2017:1; Bangura 2019:28).
5. ‘Review key social science [and other sciences] theories that are introduced to you
in [the literature] and choose the theory [theories] that can best explain the
relationships between [among] the key variables in your study.’ (USCLS 2017:1;
Bangura 2019:28).
6. ‘Discuss the assumptions or propositions of this theory [these theories] and point out
its [their] relevance to your research.’ (USCLS 2017:1; Bangura 2019:28).
Bangura points out that the USCLS text concludes by stating that a theoretical
framework helps a researcher to restrict the extent of the pertinent data of their
study by paying attention to the particular variables and defining the particular
perspective or framework s/he will employ to analyse and interpret the data
to be collected. Moreover, according to Bangura, the USCLS notes that the
theoretical framework also assists the researcher to comprehend the concepts and
variables in relation to existing definitions and to develop new knowledge by
substantiating or questioning existing theoretical propositions (USCLS 2017:1;
Bangura 2019:28). There is no need to belabour the process here as the referenced
sources can be consulted for more details.
Some readers may argue that what is presented here is restrictive when thinking
about how to conceive and build a theoretical framework and is thus highly
positivistic and that it lacks a critical perspective on the framework. Readers may
also ask how this applies or relates to African-centred theories; and whether one
is supposed to go through the same ‘Western’ steps of formulation.
Such a postulation presupposes that African theoretical formulation need not
be systematic. But even Afrenaissance Theory, among many others discussed in
the next chapter, would debunk this proposition. Besides, the fact that positivism
has been found to have existed in Ancient Kemetian/Egyptian philosophical and
theological systems that date back to 4000 BC is hardly a matter of dispute (a
detailed discussion of this is beyond the scope of this chapter).
References
Ballantine, Jeanne H., and Roberts, Keith A., 2007, Our Social World, Thousand Oaks,
CA: Pine Forge Press.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2019, ‘Revisiting the Basics’, in A.K. Bangura; J.A. Obando;
I.I. Munene and C. Shisanya, eds., Conducting Research and Mentoring Students
in Africa: CODESRIA College of Mentors Handbook, Dakar, Senegal: CODESRIA
Publications.
Bangura, Mensah and Bizos: General Introduction
9
Bangura, Abdul Karim, Obando, Joy A., Munene, Ishmael I., and Shisanya, Chris, eds.,
2019, Conducting Research and Mentoring Students in Africa: CODESRIA College of
Mentors Handbook, Dakar, Senegal: CODESRIA Publications.
Charmaz, Kathy, 2006, Constructing Grounded Theory: A Practical Guide through
Qualitative Analysis, London, UK: Sage Publications.
Frankfort-Nachmias, Chava; David Nachmias and DeWaard, Jack, 2014, Research
Methods in the Social Sciences, 7th edition, New York, NY: Worth Publishers/Palgrave
Macmillan.
Glaser, Barney G., and Strauss, A., 1967, The Discovery of Grounded Theory: Strategies for
Qualitative Research, Chicago, IL: Aldine de Gruyter.
Kinloch, Graham C., 1977, Sociological Theory: Its Development and Major Paradigms,
New York, NY: McGraw-Hill Book Company.
Kuhn, Thomas, 1962, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago, IL: The University
of Chicago Press.
Merriam-Webster Dictionary, 2020, ‘Theory’. (https://www.merriam-webster.com/
dictionary/theory), 29 August 2021.
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 1967, The Will to Power, translated by Walter Kaufmann and R. J.
Hollingdale, New York, NY: Random House.
Robertson, Ian, 1987, Sociology, New York, NY: Worth Publishers, Inc.
Sanders, David, 2002, ‘Behaviouralism’, in D. Marsh and G. Stoker, eds., Theory and
Methods in Political Science, New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Shepard, Jon M., 1981, Sociology, St. Paul, MN: West Publishing Company.
Shoemaker, Pamela J., Tankard, James William, and Lasorsa, Dominic L., 2004, How to
Build Social Science Theories, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
University of Southern California Libraries System (USCLS), April 21, 2017,
‘Theoretical Framework’, Research Guides. (http://libguides.usc.edu/writingguide/
theoreticalframework), 25 August 2021.
I
BRIEF DISCUSSIONS OF
THE THEORIES
1
African-centred
Doctoral Scholars
In this chapter, we provide brief descriptions of 29 African-centred theories. At
the core of these theories is the continent of Africa, with its culture as the major
unit of analysis. The level of analysis for most of these theories is global as their
foci are on the African continent and the Diaspora. There are scholars who would
insist that some of these theories are actually ideologies, or the beliefs or thoughts
of people in a community. Theories on the other hand are experimented concepts.
The difference between the two concepts is overstated, as ideologies themselves
are also experimented notions. A good example of this is Ujamaa as discussed
later in the chapter.
Afrenaissance
Afrenaissance as a concept based on the combination of the words ‘African’ and
‘Renaissance’. It postulates that African people and nations will overcome current
challenges confronting the continent and achieve cultural, scientific and economic
renewal. Cheikh Anta Diop was the first to articulate the theory in a series of
essays which commenced in 1946 and were collated in a book titled Towards
the African Renaissance: Essays in Culture and Development, 1946 – 1960. South
Africa’s second democratically-elected president, Thabo Mbeki, later popularised
the concept during his tenure as president and continued to do so as part of his
post-presidential campaigns.
More broadly, Afrenaissance speaks of the philosophical and political agenda
which aims to eliminate the violence, racism, corruption and poverty that have
plagued the continent of Africa. The political movements emanating from the
idea are aimed at replacing these plagues with an equitable and just order. Mbeki
proposed educational encouragement and urged African intellectuals to embrace
their heritage and take full control of their lives (Mbeki 1996). According to
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
14
Noel Moukala, Afrenaissance cannot be attained without unity among African
people. In his opinion, Africans must overcome their differences with respect
to unity before they can sit down to talk about an African renaissance (cited by
Mbeki 1998).
According to Mwalimu Ali Al’Amin Mazrui, who coined the term
Afrenaissance (Mazrui 1977), the theory describes the living evidence of Africa’s
self-renewal, and is living testimony that the human spirit is reasserting itself
among African people (Bangura 2019a). According to Abdul Karim Bangura, the
theory, on the basis of Mwalimu Mazrui’s idea, can be deployed to build a new
Africa based on seven imperatives – i.e.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
history,
language,
talent,
dignity,
self-reliance,
humane self-rule, and
creative accommodation of globalization’ (Bangura 2019a:32).
The application of the theory can be seen in the indigenous rebirth of the belief
in African gods in Ile-Ife in Nigeria. The reawakening of the forgotten gods
was brought to light by the newly installed king. This caused much debate in
the community with some arguing that the reawakening of these Africa gods
was an example of ‘backward’ thinking which would limit the progress of the
town. Other individuals thought that the reawakening of these gods was a step in
promoting African culture, which is what this theory suggests (for more details,
see Bangura 2019a).
The strength of this theory can be said to be the promotion of tradition and
the reawakening of dormant languages and cultures. The theory also encourages
the unity of Africans so as to promote culture and traditions that are dead or
forgotten, and to revive languages like Numidian (Algeria); Kwadi (Angola); and
Duli, Gey, Nagumi and Yeni (Cameroon).
African Essential Dignity
The theory of human dignity is more popularly known to African scholars as
the African Essential Dignity theory and it describes Africans’ quality of being
worthy of honour and respect. Bangura (2019a) argues that African manners and
styles, and a sense of pride and self-respect, are virtues with high and honourable
standing in global civilisation.
In a study on the relationships that exist between dignity and race, Mwalimu
Mazrui (1977) identified five key policy areas where tangible actions – vital to the
promotion of the essential dignity of Africans – are required in order to eradicate
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
15
racism, prejudice and ethnic hostilities. Top of the list is the restructuring of
the socioeconomic system in African nations, along with the effort to prevent
class differences and race distinctions from coinciding. The second area of policy
relates to the application of legal solutions to existing damaging racial problems
in Africa. Increasing and disseminating useful information is the third policy
area proposed. According to Mwalimu Mazrui, this policy could promote mutual
comprehension between groups. The fourth policy area includes engagement in
actions that can force the hand of a racist regime in the direction of greater liberty.
These actions could range from simple protests or expressions of disapproval
by influential spokespeople to demonstrations in foreign countries or military
interventions or economic sanctions. The final proposed policy area deals with
the mobilisation of the victims in a direct and continued confrontation with the
system oppressing them.
African Humanism
The theory of African Humanism helps to shape the study of Africa. African
Humanism examines norms and values that are in daily use in African communities
and examines the history of Africa and its diverse ways of life. The theory played
a major role during the transition period from the colonial era to democratic
statehood. In new democratic states, there was a need to use the ideologies that
fall under African Humanism to address social challenges.
The theory of African Humanism has been used in African communal settings
as a tool to assist communities in addressing their conflicts. Good examples are
Gacaca as applied in Rwanda and Mato Oput applied in Uganda. The theory is
rooted in other African ideologies such as Ubuntu and indigenous knowledge.
Kwame Nkrumah, the first Ghanaian president, adopted Humanism as his
philosophy, which ran parallel to President Julius Kambarage Nyerere’s ‘African
Socialism’ in Tanzania.
Kanduza (2011) reminds us that history is a study of human agency and
progress. The struggles for social justice and democratic value change over time.
Steve Biko and Kenneth Kaunda’s studies of African heritage were written during
different historical periods, but the context and meaning remain the same.
Kanduza (2011) notes that Biko and Kaunda believed in examining African
heritage in order to understand the sources of strength needed for the vision
underlying their struggles.
In essence, African Humanism pays attention to changes in social and political
settings. For example, when a study focuses on the social challenges that are faced
by the elderly in Africa, this theory can assist in explaining some of the changes
that have taken place in the chosen study area, given that the study tracks changes
that have occurred over time.
16
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
African Humanism pays attention to human self-development and to
communal development, and to the need for people to work together in building
their community. Ekanem (2012) tells us that Julius Nyerere’s understanding of
African Humanism is that people cannot be deprived of food and human dignity
if their wealth is held communally. When wealth is held personally it cannot be
shared. On the contrary, the wealth of the community could be the determining
factor in the wealth of individuals.
African Humanism is comprised of many types, which include Islamic
Humanism (relating to the faith of Muslims or Islam), Modern African Humanism
(relating to the present), and Secular Humanism (relating to attitudes, activities
or other things that have no religious or spiritual basis).
African Humanism provides for harmonious interaction among legal, political
and social activities. African Humanism can be practically applied in many spheres
of life, especially in the African context where there are many challenges. The
theory plays an important role in promoting indigenous knowledge in societies
where individuals need more freedom and more opportunities while at the same
time valuing their beliefs and ethics.
African Nationalism
African Nationalism implies the establishment of new African nations with a
view to achieving political and economic transformation for the benefit of the
citizens of those nations. The theory propounds a state of togetherness and
patriotism among the governed, who work toward national interests and toward
one another (Olasupo, Oladeji & Ijeoma 2017). African Nationalism also seeks
to liberate a nation from the clutches of colonial rule. It addresses the right
of a people to choose how they participate in political, social, cultural and
economic development.
Proponents of African Nationalism include Nkrumah Kwame, Léopold
Sédar Senghor, Jomo Kenyatta and others. Nkrumah’s African Nationalism
captures the right of people to determine the paths of their destinies and freedom
without being subject to discrimination because of the colour of their skin or the
level of their social development (Mjiba 2016). Senghor’s version hinges on the
uniqueness of the historical and cultural heritage of Black people within the
context of the culture that expresses their values (Vaillant 1976).
The concept of nationalism in Africa is not new. Olasupo, Oladeji and Ijeoma
(2017) argue that African Nationalism predates the colonial era as Africans had
always operated their own political and administrative institutions. The Ashanti
people’s resistance to European colonialism and the battles of the Zulus of South
Africa point to the pre-colonial nationalistic tendencies of Africans and portray a
sense of national identity.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
17
African Nationalism has contributed to the unity of Africa and has helped to
create a sense of belonging in the areas of shared identity and shared political,
cultural and social orientation. The Organisation of African Unity (now the
African Union) was set up to ensure the political, economic and social integration
of Africa. Integration has helped to strengthen economic development on the
continent through bilateral trade in goods and services, as well as joint resistance
to internal and external interference.
The drive for nationalism in Africa has not been without challenges. The
proliferation of centrifugal forces (different religions and languages, unstable
governments, internal conflicts, and geographic features) at different periods
has undermined nationalism in Africa. The unity and cohesion envisaged by the
proponents of the ideology have suffered setbacks as a result of ethnic divisions
and divisive formations. Mwalimu Mazrui (1982) argues that racial consciousness
promotes African Nationalism as opposed to ethnic consciousness, which is the
bane of nationalism. He notes that African Nationalism, which thrived on the
solidarity in shared Blackness, has been hampered by acute ethnic cleavages
that permeate different parts of the continent. In extreme cases, such ethnic
disturbances have led to secessionist groups. Resource sharing and control also
raise questions that have implications for the survival of many African nations. The
heterogeneous makeup of many African communities, especially localities where
resources are located, is a challenge to the unifying prospect of African Nationalism.
Africana Womanism
The theory of Africana Womanism was developed by Clenora Hudson-Weems in
the late 1980s. It is an ideology that addresses issues that affect African women
and women of African descent. The ideology is based on the uniqueness of the
woman in relation to her political, social and economic environment. Africana
Womanism considers the particularities of the woman’s world: her needs, desires,
challenges and experiences in a complex environment (Goldfine 2015).
Hudson-Weems conceptualises the Africana woman as a ‘self-namer’ and ‘selfdefiner’. This implies that the woman is who she sees herself to be and that she
should see herself on a high pedestal, rather than accepting the identity given to
her by the society. She is the one who defines how society perceives and names
her. The Africana woman is conceptualised differently from the feminist who
believes she is defined by man and is perceived as less than the man and, therefore
has engaged in competition with her male counterpart in terms of her roles in
society. The Africana woman conceptualised by Hudson-Weems is family-centred
and believes that she is not in competition with her male counterpart; rather,
she believes that the continuity of the African people is hinged on positive malefemale relationships. The ideology proposes that the Diaspora Africana connects
with Africa through a shared cultural identity that is defined by the authenticity
of their activities rather than by a dominant culture (Gilliam 2013).
18
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Womanism was first proposed by Alice Walker to highlight cultural affinity
among Black women in the Diaspora (Gilliam 2013). Hudson-Weems, however,
proposed the concept of Africana Womanism as the ‘woman’s establishment of
her cultural identity’. She emphasised the mutual involvement of Black men and
women in the emancipation of the African community and the relevance of the
African tradition to the welfare of Africans globally (Hudson-Weems 1993).
Hudson-Weems’s theory of Africana Womanism has been applied in
establishing a space for Africana women to express their views in all spheres of
life, including social, political and intellectual spaces. It has also found expression
in gender and women studies (Goldfine 2013). A good number of Africana
women in Africa have significantly impacted their spheres of influence and
have continued to actively lend voices in advocacy on issues affecting Africana
women. In Uganda, women’s representation in legislative governance is one of
the highest in the world. Also, women have been known to hold presidential and
governorship positions in places like Liberia and Nigeria, respectively. Indeed, in
both countries, women have asserted their rights by seeking the support of and
working with men that are sympathetic to their causes.
Through the influence of the paradigm, Africana women understand their
realm of possibilities in the realities of the world and actively participate in the
global struggle to address common issues challenging Africana women in the
Diaspora. Africana Womanism promotes self-naming as key to the emancipation
of the dignity of women and helps them to reflect on life’s experiences, beliefs,
and practices based on the authenticity of their activities rather than as defined
by another culture. The Africana woman has come to understand that she can
genuinely connect to family, career and community without necessarily losing her
identity. She is able to come to terms with the fact that she is equipped physically
and emotionally to pursue her ambitions while upholding family status and, at
the same time, maintaining healthy relationships with men.
Africanism
As a theory, Africanism encompasses all aspects of African history and culture and
provides an outline for the future development of Africa. It includes all people
of African descent, regardless of nationality. It aims to emancipate Africans from
European cultures and traditions, and looks to the mental liberation of Africans
from the lifestyles of Europeans and Western culture, along with self-discovery in
all situations. Africanism is a systematic ideology that attempts to study African
heritage from pre-historic times, believing that civilisation is rooted in Africa.
It seeks to build a sense of unity among Africans and to aid the socioeconomic
integration of the continent. Africanism is meant to reshape what has been
taught and to upgrade knowledge about Africa, as well as to re-orientate Africans’
worldview about Africa as a continent of people united in a culture of love,
understanding, respect and communalism for the common good of all.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
19
Achieving the goals of Africanism requires reorientation through African
education on culture and history, as well as values that define Africans. Africanism
can serve as an academic discipline to nurture African studies as an entity.
Community involvement is also a key component of Africanism. Africans live
communal lives, where injury to one is injury to all, the safety of one is the safety
of all, the prosperity of one is the prosperity of all, and the suffering of one is
the suffering of all. This is a mindset in which a unifying African social bonding
helps to build communal relationships. Africanism also seeks to remove ethnic or
religious labels in order to establish an inclusive Africa where all are free to relate
to one another, irrespective of ethnicity or religion.
A number of Africans contributed to the theory of Africanism; they include
Ahmed Sékou Touré, Julius Kambarage Nyerere (Bjerk 2017; Smith 1973) and
Kwame Nkrumah. For example, Nkrumah’s idea of Africanism portrays Africa as
independent and absolutely free from imperialism, organised on a continental scale,
founded on the concept of one united Africa. He argues that Africans are capable
of managing their own affairs and strongly believes that the free development
in all is the condition for the free development of all (Botwe-Asamoah 2005).
Africanism contributes to the regional integration of African countries as
it helps to address the political, economic, social and cultural concerns of the
continent through the African Union (AU). In the academic space, Africanism
has enhanced the knowledge of Africa through scholarly studies of African culture,
traditions and heritage. The African Studies Association of Africa (ASAA), for
instance, is an agency that promotes Africanism in the academic space. The
dignity of Africans is restored through Africanism as the de-neocolonisation
(which transcends decolonisation) of the continent results in a sense of ownership
and control of African heritage. Cultural and social values of African origin find
expression through Africanism as an ideology. It is also worth mentioning that
Africanism is a specialist knowledge area in Western social sciences.
A critique of Africanism is that the achievement of unity on the African
continent is threatened by the diversity of cultural and ethnic sentiments. Lack
of effective leadership has also affected the search for unity on the continent.
Another critique of Africanism is the fact that it is an ideology that is pursued
under the philosophy of equality without taking into consideration the varied
capacities of the participating states.
Afrocentricity
In a bid to address the anomalies of the Eurocentric worldview of Africa, Mwalimu
Molefi Kete Asante espoused the theory of Afrocentricity as a counter-ideology.
He argues that Eurocentricity has succeeded in making Africa lose consciousness
of Black heritage, leaving it without an understanding of the richness of African
culture, which could aid the social and economic development of the African
20
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
(Asante 1990). He conceptualises Afrocentricity as a manner of thought and
action that puts the interest of Africa at its centre. He raises questions about the
natural responses that would occur in relationships, kinship patterns, preferences
for skin colour, types of religion and historical heritage in the absence of the
colonial experience (Asante 2001).
Reed, Lawson and Gibbs (1997) argue that Afrocentricity gives Africans a
sense of the reality of their origins and define it as a transformation of attitudes,
beliefs, values and behaviours. In the view of Stikkers (2008), Afrocentricity
projects Africans as the centre of any analysis of African origin in terms of action
and behaviours. In order words, it implies that whatever one seeks to know
about Africans should be understood from the African perspective and defined
in the context of Africa. Yoshitaka Miike (2008) identifies six dimensions of
Afrocentricity:
1. Africans as subjects and agents who should see themselves as agents in the
historical process;
2. the interests of Africans and Africa at the centre of knowledge reconstruction
about the African world;
3. centrality of African values and ideals;
4. groundedness in African historical experiences;
5. African contextual representation of data; and
6. Critique of the dislocation of Africans.
Pioneers like Marcus Garvey, Cheikh Anta Diop and W.E.B. Du Bois made
contributions to Afrocentricity ideology. Cheik Anta Diop views Afrocentricity
as ‘the doctrine to recover the past and systematically overturn Western cultural
assumptions of Africa’ (Asante 2001:1). In order to connect to Africa as a centre
of origin, the Black person has to gain a self-defined dignity. Mwalimu Asante
conceptualises Afrocentricity as a ‘philosophical perspective associated with the
discovery, location, and actualisation of African agency within the context of
history and culture’ (Asante 2001:1). These pioneers of Afrocentricity seek to
liberate Africans from the very strong clutches of the West and situate Africa as
the centre of humanity (Asante 2001). Afrocentricity is used widely in the areas
of communication, history, sociology, social work, psychology and education,
language development, economics, and intercultural communication.
Afrocentricity has its strength in giving Africans in the Diaspora a perspective
on African history and cultural heritage as the bases of African knowledge that
will help to correct the Eurocentric perspective on Africa. It also helps Africans
to overcome the social malaise associated with marginalisation as it restores their
sense of humanity and dignity by seeing themselves as subjects rather than objects
of humanity. Afrocentricity allows Africans to be conscious of their identity and
aspirations as they strive to defy racial stigma, giving a sense of self-motivation
for success.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
21
In addition, as Early, Moses, Wilson and Lefkowiz (1994) point out,
Afrocentricity, as an interdisciplinary theory, serves to bind the various elements
of African and African-American studies into a unified discipline with ideological
and intellectual goals, political purposes and a set of commonly understood
methods and theories.
Miike (2008) highlights some misconceptions of Afrocentricity held by critics
of the ideology as follows: the ideology pays more attention to African-ness than
African diversity; it ignores the dynamics of Africa; it contradicts the tenets of
Eurocentricity; and it is still confined by Eurocentricity. He says that those who
harbour these misconceptions are either ill-informed or have not bothered to read
most of the works in the field.
Afropolitanism
Afropolitanism is a theoretical linkage between African heritage and cosmopolitan
identity through the combination of the words ‘African’ and ‘Cosmopolitanism’.
Cosmopolitanism advances the idea of a world citizen, in the sense of a mental
bridge between ‘I’ and ‘humanity’, while Afropolitanism advances the idea of
an African of the world in the form of a mental bridge among ‘I’, ‘humanity’,
and ‘Africa’. This idea was popularised in 2005 by Taiye Selasi in an essay titled
Bye Bye, Babar. Although the concept had featured in earlier discussions as a
description of a pluralism of African cultures in one geographical space, Selasi
referred to a generation of the African Diaspora seeking identity. She made the
distinction between an ‘African of the world’ and a ‘citizen of the world’ in the bid
to provide an understanding of the individual positioning of an average emigrant
African in the worldview.
Afropolitanism is a theory of African Diaspora identity based on the experiences
of ordinary citizens. It provides a lens for members of the African Diaspora to
identify themselves as African without the labels of ‘mixed race’ and ‘half-caste’.
This way, geographic and racial differences are minimised. Although similar
to Pan-Africanist ideology, given its reaction to the Afropessimism with which
African identity has continued to grapple, it rejects its victimhood undertone.
Instead, it defines African identity away from a backward-looking, past-digging
and reactionary perspective to a forward-looking, continent-wide and multiracial
perspective. Other proponents of the theory like Achille Mbembe (2001, 2007)
have argued that to overturn the Afropessimism of African discourses, there is
a need to identify sites within the continent which depict African excellence in
areas like fashion, the visual arts and music.
The theory helps Africans in the Diaspora to ‘recognise their face in that of a
foreigner’, as Mbembe (2007:28) puts it. For example, individuals who have never
visited their fatherland, nor speak their mother tongue, can nevertheless associate
themselves with Africa; this theory provides a closure in their search for identity.
22
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
At the same time, it provides a radical turn in the history of Black emancipatory
discourse. While earlier discourses on Pan-Africanism and Afrocentrism had been
criticised as being racial in their solidarities, Afropolitanism imagines a future
where the difference between African-ness and non-African-ness is immaterial.
While the theory advances a closure for an African Diaspora identity search,
it is not without shortcomings. First, its fusion of African and Cosmopolitanism
implies that being an African is not cosmopolitan enough; the addition of
Cosmopolitanism is needed for acceptance and validation. Second, identifying
Afropolitanism with a chic and rosy lifestyle restricts its scope and opens it
to accusations of class and elitist bias. It reserves ‘modernity exclusively for a
population who is wealthy enough to travel around the world’ (Santana 2015).
Asanteism
Unlike Afrocentricity, for which Mwalimu Molefi Kete Asante provided the most
cited definition and which has been developed by many other scholars, Asanteism
is about his work on the theory and other African-centred aspects. Asanteism
is a theory advanced to describe the philosophical contributions of Mwalimu
Asante. He campaigned for a reconnection to ancient African consciousness
with the view to overthrowing parochial, provincial and narrow visions of the
world. Mwalimu Asante asserted the need for a paradigmatic shift from limiting
perspectives on African knowledge towards an African truth that has been hitherto
neglected. Asanteism holds that Eurocentric worldviews are not effective lenses
for observing African realities, and aims to break the intellectual and cultural
Eurocentric particularism that universalises knowledge and ways of knowing. The
theory advances the belief that reconnecting with these African truths is the only
way through which African people can regain sanity across the Diaspora.
Asanteism offers an epistemological, cosmological, ontological, ethical and
aesthetic organisation of the world in a way that it is not compliant with European
conceptualisations and hegemonic worldviews. It canonises the proverbial sayings
of ancient African sages as a worldview in the same sense that a Socrates-based
worldview is regarded as an accepted way of knowing. Asanteism employed
Kemetic civilisation, similar to Afrocentricity, to rewrite the history of African
civilisation as a way of demystifying both the European falsification of African
history and the knowledge systems which legitimised racial superiority and
colonial enterprise. The theory intends to provide a clear, coherent, and persuasive
argument for the reconceptualisation of the way Africans view themselves and the
way others view Africans.
Abdul Karim Bangura in his 2019 publication titled Branches of Asanteism
canonises the structural depth into 13 epistemological and methodological
branches as follows:
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
23
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
Mwalimu Mazrui’s Afrenaissance,
Nantambu’s Pan-African Nationalism Approach,
Collins’ Afrocentric Feminist Epistemology,
Hudson-Weems Africana Womanism Theory,
Mazama’s Afrocentric Spirituality,
Bangura’s Ubuntugogy,
Bangura’s African Mathematization,
Bangura’s African-centred Computational Techniques,
Schiele’s Afrocentric Organizational Theory,
Schiele’s Afrocentric Social Work Practice Paradigm and Social Welfare
Philosophy and Policy,
11. Pellebon’s Asante-Based Afrocentricity Scale,
12. Miike’s Asiacentricity, and
13. Kondo’s Black Consciousness Epistemology’ (Bangura 2019a).
Bangura argues that what unites these branches is the way that they put forward a
systematic, chronological, linguistic, and cultural approach toward liberating the
minds of African people while also freeing truths from the hegemonic clutches
of European dominance. Using analytic historiography, Asanteism displaces
negative and revisionist Eurocentric anti-African history.
Ben Bellaism
Ben Bellaism is a theoretical postulate adapted from the foreign policy positions
of Ahmed Ben Bella, a former Algerian revolutionary leader. Having fought for
France in World War II, he returned to Algeria and rose to fight against France in
a revolutionary struggle for Algeria’s independence. He later become Algeria’s first
elected president. Addressing the United Nations General Assembly at the time
of Algeria’s admission into the organisation in 1962, he averred that ‘liquidation
of colonialism in both its classic and disguised form will be the credo of our
political and diplomatic line of actions’ (Ottaway & Ottaway 1970:145). This
won him the admiration of many as a die-hard nationalist and de-colonialist.
Driven by the ideological principles of African Socialism, Ben Bella
propagandised Algeria’s socialism as the model for other African countries to
follow. He believed that this was the only way African and Asian nations could
come together to resist and overthrow imperialist powers. Consequently, he
sought the unity and cooperation of North Africa, the Arab world and Africa. By
Algerian Socialism, he meant the postcolonial movement away from economic
and political exploitation to economic sufficiency and political dignity (Ottaway
& Ottaway 1970).
24
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Black Feminism
The theory of Black Feminism advances the notion that Black women are positioned
within structures of power relations in fundamentally different ways from their
white counterparts. As such, the experience of a Black woman cannot be fully
comprehended by simply evaluating her being a woman and being Black; rather,
the experience must be evaluated separately because these identities complicate
and reinforce one another. That is to say that Black women experience a radically
different oppression than both Black men in racial hegemonic characteristics and
white women in manifestations of gendered segregation.
The theory started as a reaction by enslaved Black woman to the oppressive
power structures of white supremacy and patriarchy during the slave era.
During this time, racial discrimination was at its peak and Black women were
doubly vulnerable to the two hegemonic powers of the predominantly racial and
patriarchal society – (1) being female and (2) being Black. During the postslavery era, the idea expanded to include advocacy for Black women’s suffrage
and a number of Black organisations were birthed. Among these were the
National Association of Colored Women (NACP), the National Association for
the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP), and the National Association
of Wage Earners (NAWE). Among the leading proponents of the theory are
Sojourner Truth, Ida B. Wells, Zora Neale Hurston, Anna Julia Cooper, Angela
Davis, Kimberlé Crenshaw, Mary Church Terrell, and Frances Ellen Watkins
Harper. By the 1960s, the advocacies of Black Feminism included the fight
for abortion, sexual orientations, proportion of representation in politics and a
critique of the portrayal of Black women in television, movies, magazine covers,
etc. (Blay & Gray 2015).
With the advent of social media, Black Feminism has gained more traction.
The methods of ‘call out’ and ‘shaming’ of sexual and racial offenders on the
internet are increasingly revolutionising the way Black Feminism is advancing
its position in this digital era. This has given the theory more power and visible
force than it has had in its several decades of existence. In this regard, celebrities
like Beyonce and Chimamanda Ngozi Adichie have also lent their voices and
influence (Blay & Gray 2015).
While Black Feminism has been praised for making giant strides in the
pursuit of equality for Black women, it has been criticised for its exclusionary
tendencies. In a bid to fight for the social and political justice of Black women,
it often excludes other groups and concerns which are not part of the dominant
categories of race, class, gender and sexual orientations. Other critics of Black
Feminism argue that this division along the lines of gender and race impinges on
the overall agenda of women’s right advocacy. In recent times, Black Feminism
has been taunted with the dichotomous label of ‘White Feminism’ in a bid to
point to the exclusive undertones of the theory (Blay & Gray 2015).
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
25
Cabralism
The theory of Cabralism is based on the influence of Amilcar Cabral on
decolonisation and revolution in the African continent. Cabral was born in
Guinea-Bissau in 1924 but was raised in Cape Verde during a time of colonial
injustice: the famine in the 1940s. He studied in Lisbon and was known as an
agricultural engineer as well as a poet and writer (Van Veen 2016). According to
Rabaka, Cabral was known as ‘an innovative and complex organic intellectualactivist’ and a ‘trans-disciplinary critical social theorist’ (2014:14).
The driving force behind Cabralism Theory was liberation of Africa from
colonialism. The theory emphasises rising above ethnic divisions to use unity
among citizens to get justice and freedom. Cabral understood the differences
between ethnic groups, but he aimed to bring all of them together to fight for
freedom in the struggle for decolonisation in Guinea Bissau. This oneness among
ethnic groups is referred to as ‘unified revolutionary nationalism’ by Rabaka
(2014). This strategy was believed by Cabral to be the first step to decolonisation,
even if there were disputes later about the geographical bourndaries of territories
(Rabaka 2014).
Cabral’s first phase aimed to defeat colonialism, and also encompassed
Humanism, a school of thought that believes that disputes can be solved
through reasoning rather than religion. Cabral believed that Black people need
to change the negative way in which they were portrayed by the colonialists,
bringing about a new human and a new Africa. Importantly, Cabralism is also
about a rebirth of Africa or a struggle to newness. Cabralism also called upon
Africans to oppose the oppression of other groups. To be unlike Europeans
like the British, Cabral urged Africans to dismiss the act of imperialism after
decolonisation (Rabaka 2014).
Cabral believed that national revolution should focus on the liberation of
citizens from oppressors, and should also entail a fight for material benefits,
improved living standards, and a good and bright future for children. Cabralism
Theory focuses on total liberation of the oppressed in terms of freedom, improved
environment conditions, and a better life (Rabaka 2014).
The strength of this theory lies in the way Cabral preached about unity
against ethnic divisions. Through the strength of unity, Cabral argued, walls are
broken and freedom and independence can be achieved. Moving together with
one voice and one aim is the key to progress, freedom and, most importantly,
national revolution. The weakness of Cabralism Theory is that the unity of
some groups in the cause of freedom could spring from a selfish perspective, or
the strength of unity could be used to cause problems for other citizens in the
same country.
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
26
Consciencism or Nkrumahism
Consciencism or Nkrumahism was developed by African philosopher Kwame
Nkrumah, prime minister of Ghana from 1952 to 1960 and first postindependence President of Ghana from 1960 to 1966. The theory envisioned
the development of a Union of African States, free from foreign rule, in
principle and reality. Nkrumah sought to build new Africa which could
manage its own affairs and operate within the context of its social and political
realities. Nkrumah drew out the three segments that made up African society:
1. western/Christianity,
2. Islamic, and
3. traditional beliefs.
These, he said, were always in conflict with one another. He did not recommend
that these beliefs were to be regretted, but he stated that ‘practice without
thought is blind; thought without practice is empty’ (Nkrumah 1964:78).
This implies that the principles of both Christianity and Islam must be
practiced purposefully and thoughtfully in a traditional African society context.
The philosophical ideology of Nkrumahism is that for social revolution to
be effective, it must have an intellectual undertone which works towards the
development and redemption of African society. For an African society to be
redeemed, according to Nkrumah, it must aim to be an egalitarian human society
where everyone is seen as one and the same, and its resources are used to satisfy
everyone. Ikuenobe defines egalitarian as ‘a principle (which) says that everyone
must be given equal treatment and accorded equal value, dignity and respect’
(2013:1). The concept of egalitarianism, in the context of Consciencism, rejects
the idea of materialism, which holds material possessions and comfort as more
important than spiritual beliefs. Ikuenobe argues that the political terrain in
Africa must contain traditional African ideas along with Islamic and Christian
ideas arising from colonisation. He adds that the successful practice of this idea
can only be done through Socialism (Ikuenobe 2013).
Flowing from his belief in an egalitarian society, Nkrumah embraced Socialism
rather than Capitalism. He argued that the fundamental basis of all humanist or
socialist concepts, as identified by Immanuel Kant’s Moral Order, is that a person
should be treated as an end in himself or herself, and not a means to an end.
Nkrumah believed that capitalist society is a structure with ruling and working
classes. This structure does not confer equal rights as the working class will be
exploited by the ruling class (Ikuenobe 2013). This will lead to two competing
and antagonistic groups:
1. the oppressors and
2. the oppressed.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
27
These two groups cannot live together in peace because there will be a struggle
for power. Nkrumah also stated that for peace and development to occur in a
society, there must be development of the individual which can only be achieved
through Socialism. Nkrumah argued that Capitalism does not conform to the
moral principles of an African society of equality (Ikuenobe 2013).
The theory of Consciencism can be employed to analyse the Indigenous People
of Biafra (IPOB) movement in Nigeria whereby the Igbo, who feel neglected or
marginalised by other ethnic groups in power, advocate for their own country.
Their situation has caused unrest. In 2019, the agitation was taken abroad – to
be specific, Germany – where some IPOB members attacked a Nigerian National
Assembly leader visiting that country. The emergence of militants in the Niger
Delta can also fit into this theory. The people in the region feel cheated and have
come together to fight for their right to accountability and environmental care.
The strength of Consciencism can be found in the argument that religion
should not be practiced with a blind mind but with an open mind to foster
the unity of a society. Nkrumah did not place one religion over another, but
instead advocated for the combination of different religious ideas to undergird
the politics of a society without losing African traditional values. The weakness
of this philosophy is that Nkrumah did not take into consideration that human
needs are insatiable. It is not possible to have an egalitarian society in Africa
because the rich will want to become richer and make the poor poorer.
Diopism
Diopism deals with the influence of Egyptian civilisation on the culture of
African people. Cheikh Anta Diop’s pioneering work asserts that Egyptians are
Africans and have a strong place in African history and culture. Diop was born
in Diourbel in Senegal in 1923. In this area, there are many Muslim scholars
and historians. His environment stimulated a passion for this work and he took
an interest in African history, the humanities and social sciences. He became an
anthropologist, historian, linguist, and a nuclear physicist. Diop also became a
nationalist and a voice for African federalism (Bangura 2018).
In his book titled The African Origin of Civilization: Myth or Reality (1974),
Diop maintains that ‘Western historians’ claim that Egyptians were white people
is false. Diop also questions the location of Egypt on the ancient map. He asserts
that what is Egypt today was once one of Ethiopia’s colonies brought into Egypt
by the deity Osiris (Diop 1974). Diop references the writing of Herodotus, a
Greek historian, who said that Egyptians were dark-skinned people with woolly
hair. Herodotus said Egyptians have the same kind of skin as Ethiopians. Diop
concluded that Ancient Kemetians/Egyptians were neither Asian nor European
but were Africans who migrated from ancient Ethiopia to ancient Egypt
(Diop 1974).
28
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Diop argues that Western civilisation was influenced by ancient Egyptian
culture, which was originally from Ethiopia. He asserts strongly that ancient
Egyptians who migrated from ancient Ethiopia were acknowledged as Black
people who brought civilisation to the rest of Africa.
Falolaism
Falolaism is a theoretical postulate that ‘focus[es] more on the life histories,
the times, the political and economic contexts of the intellectual production of
the prominent Yoruba intelligentsia outside of the Western academy’ (Bangura
2019b:2). Falolaism is supported by African-centred Gnoseology, defined by
Bangura as the ‘scientific or philosophical study of knowledge strengthened
by the positive-intuitive thinking that is driven by the African’s spiritual mind’
(2019b:8). Falolaism is heavily focused on African thinking and aims to give a
positive picture of the great minds and schools of thought of African scholars.
Toyin Falola, after whom the theory is named, was born in 1953 in Ibadan,
Nigeria. He is a historian and Professor of African Studies and the Humanities
at the University of Texas in Austin. Falola’s work has continued to promoting
the thinking and culture of Africans, especially the Yoruba culture in Nigeria. He
obtained his first degree and PhD in History from Obafemi Awolowo University
in Ile-Ife, Nigeria. He is a thinker who seeks to merge the ideas of Yoruba gurus
who do not have Western education with the work of academic historians to
provide a rich history of the Yoruba (Bangura 2019b).
The theory of Falolaism argues that for Africa to develop universal knowledge
there is a need for scholars to acknowledge the intellectual contributions of great
Yoruba thinkers and scholars who do not have Western educations. Falola notes
that their ideas and thoughts are marginalised and treated as only a source rather
than as knowledge production. In his article ‘Alternative History’, as quoted by
Bangura (2019b), Falola stresses the fact that for solid knowledge production to
occur, there is a need to encourage the production of local histories to add value
to historical consciousness. This would promote knowledge that is specific to the
Yoruba and aid understanding of the production of such knowledge.
Falolaism seeks to describe materialism in a a different dimension from the
Western interpretation of the concept. He draws ideas from African-centred
scientific methodologies such as Utchā and Uhem Methodology (the former was
an approach used by Ancient Kemetians/Egyptians to rectify facts and the latter
was used by them to narrate, recount, repeat, or tell a story or dream); Diopian
Intercultural Relation Methodology; Africancentric Methodology; Complex
Methodology; and Consciencist Methodology, among others (for more on these
methodologies, see Bangura et al. 2019).
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
29
A strength of Falolaism is the way Falola acknowledges the thoughts and
writings of Yoruba scholars who do not have Western education as a source
of knowledge production about the history of the Yoruba. Falolaism draws its
strength from the fact that the theory emphasises the reawakening of African
historical consciousness.
Gaddafism
The theory of Gaddafism, also known as ‘The Third International Theory’,
contains tenets of Islamic Socialism, Arab Nationalism, African Nationalism,
and partly the principle of direct democracy. It was proposed as an alternative
to capitalism and communism for African countries. It builds a form of
Socialism based on religion, morality and patriotism. As noted by Damaji
(1972), the major strands of the theory are postulated in Gaddafi’s ‘magnum
opus’, The Green Book published in three volumes from 1976 to 1979. The
theory propagates that governance must be based on social justice, high levels
of production, the elimination of all forms of exploitation and the equitable
distribution of national resources. It also advocates people power to solve the
democratic dilemma as well as the social injustices underpinning economic
problems (Damaji 1972).
Muammar Gaddafi (1942–2011) pioneered the theory based on his worldview,
which was shaped by his environment, which included his Islamic faith, Bedouin
(village) upbringing, and his anti-colonial stance, among others. According to
him (as cited in Ozoigbo 2016), the purpose of a socialist society is the happiness
of a person, which can only be realised through material and spiritual freedom.
Attainment of such freedom depends on the extent of a person’s ownership of his
needs, an ownership that is personal and sacredly guaranteed in Islam. He also
rejected liberal democracy based on party politics, electing representatives and
plebiscites. Instead, he advocated for direct democracy which allows direct people
participation in a General People’s Congress named Jamahiyyah. True democracy,
according to him, exists only through direct participation of the people and not
through the activities of their representatives.
He also condemned Communism and Capitalism, arguing that they are two
sides of the same coin, as the latter denotes monopoly of the powerful and the
former denotes monopoly of the state, both of which are antithetical to natural
justice. Although Arab Nationalism was at the core of his ideology (El-Khawas
1984), Gaddafi also aspired for the superiority of Black people. He wrote: ‘The
world civilizations are now giving way to the re-emergence of black people after
centuries of subjugations’ (Gaddafi 1972:1). In addition, Gaddafi proffers the
idea of women’s liberation, minorities’ rights and the welfare state, among others
(Gaddafi 1972).
30
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Gaddafism has a wide range of applications to African issues like African unity,
democratic development, gender equity, social policies, and economic growth.
For Garcia and Echeverria (2018), the theory could be used to explain many
issues around African economic systems, especially a shift from a Western type
of sociology to a home-grown one which accords private property to individuals
but on a limited scale.
While the theory explains how nationalism and religion could be used to
move Africa forward and provide solutions to many of Africa’s political, economic
and social problems, it, overemphasises Arab supremacy and contradicts African
Unionism. Also, the Green Book contains more aphorisms than completely
integrated philosophical statement. This is not necessarily bad, for even Nietzsche
wrote mainly in aphorisms.
Garveyism
Marcus Garvey (1887–1940), who was the founder of the Universal Negro
Improvement Association (UNIA) and leader of the Back-to-Africa Movement,
was the pioneer of Garveyism as a theoretical proposition (Dagnini 2008). Garvey
believed that Black people will never achieve true freedom while under the rule of
whites. He therefore advocated for a return of Blacks to their African homeland
as the only place they could attain the economic and political independence
that would lead to true emancipation. Garvey viewed education as the means to
liberate his people. He saw it as the medium by which a people are prepared for
the creation of their own particular civilisation and the advancement and glory of
their own race (Dagnini 2008).
The main goal of UNIA, as expressed by Blaisdell (2004), was to institute
a separate-but-equal collegiate educational system for Blacks. Garvey also
advocated for the purity of the Black race just as whites believed in a pure white
race (Edgar 1976). Garvey also asserted that Black communities should strive for
self-determination rather than integration. He said ‘nationhood’ was the strongest
security of any people and Blacks must strive to attain the goal of an ‘African
Republic’ on African soil. Above all, he preached African fundamentalism: ‘We
must canonise our own saints, create our martyrs, and elevate to positions of fame
and honour, black men and women who have made their own contribution to
our social history’ (Blaisdell 2004:1). In the case of governance, he argued that
‘government is not infallible. It is only an executive control, a centralised authority
for the purpose of expressing the will of the people. Without the people, there can
be no government’ (Blaisdell 2004:3).
Garvey he supported the struggle of Africans in their fight against imperialist
and colonial domination in the 1920s and 1930s. The essence of Garveyism is Black
unity, Black consciousness, and Black liberation, as well as a desire to unify and uplift
African nations and the African Diaspora as a universal community (Dagnini 2008).
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
31
The theory of Garveyism has applications to the study of colonialism, neocolonialism, racism, nationalism, Pan-Africanism, and African unity, among
other topics. The strands of Pan-Africanism ingrained in Garveyism served as
inspiration to famous Black nationalists like Kwame Nkrumah, Léopold Sédar
Senghor and Patrice Lumumba, to mention but a few. Nevertheless, it has been
argued that Garvey’s push for African redemption and the establishment of
an African State as a sovereign political entity in world affairs is still a dream
without fulfilment. Garvey’s ideological stance on African pride is criticised for
its near-extremist positions with its idolising of African sages seen as close to
the idolisation of Western leaders such as Napoleon and Hitler (Dagnini 2008).
The segregationist undertone of Black purity as advocated by Garvey led other
contemporary Pan-Africanists like W.E.B. Du Bois to engage in an ideological
conflict with him.
Gnoseology
The idea of Gnoseology embraces positive thinking in the mindsets of Africans
over time. It involves a range of notions that represent the virtues of self-pride,
independence, freedom, liberation, strength and peace promotion, as well as
being a wellspring for knowledge production (Bangura 2018:215). It has a highspirited belief in the ability of Africans to console themselves for the suffering
caused by the operations of the white man from the time of slavery, colonialism
and neo-colonialism to the present-day global domination of the West.
The theory of Gnoseology was birthed by late Guinean President Ahmed
Sékou Touré, who referred to it as the positive intuitive thinking that is driven by
Africans’ spiritual minds (cited in Bangura 2018). In his essay titled ‘A Dialectical
Approach to Culture’, Bangura states that Sekou Touré argues that Africans are
right-thinking individuals, both in the continent and in the Diaspora. They
demonstrate ingenuity and a positive mindset when dealing with things, no
matter how unpalatable. This was manifested in their thinking as colonised and
enslaved people throughout history. The pain of slavery and Western domination
did not corrupt this positive mindset as can be seen in the singing of inspiring
choruses to comfort themselves through the excruciating pains of slavery and
colonisation (Bangura 2018 ).
The application of the theory is present in almost all African symbols, art and
culture and is integrated in all aspects of African national identities. One can find
derivatives of the theory (bravery, self-pride, independence, freedom, liberation,
strength, peace and positive thinking) conspicuously incorporated in the national
anthems of African countries. For example, the third line of the first stanza of the
Cameroonian anthem depicts bravery: ‘Their tears and blood and sweat thy soil did
water’. The second line of Ethiopian anthem indicates pride as follows: ‘National
pride is seen, shining from one side to another’. In the anthem of Ghana, there
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
32
is clear expression of determination for freedom: ‘And blazes the trail of freedom
far and wide’. In other words, the theory lays down a philosophical foundation
of group solidarity, which was central to the survival of African communities and
triggered their liberation struggle in the 1950s and 1960s.
The theory has been praised for its cardinal tenets of bravery and tolerance
which encourage the spirit of teamwork and group solidarity. This underlies
the African struggle against hunger, deprivation, poverty and oppression.
However, it has been criticised for being based on unrecorded practices and
insufficient information.
Kagisano
Kagisano is a Botswanan philosophy which literally translates as ‘making peace’.
Botswana has not engaged in civil or international war, either pre- or postindependence, and is guided by this principle of peace and social harmony in
ensuring individual development that will ultimately lead to a better society
(Seekings 2016). While individual development is stated as the principal aim of
Kagisano, it also reinforces the aims of nation building and national unity. These
goals are based on the four principles of:
1.
2.
3.
4.
democracy,
development,
self-reliance and
unity, culminating in a national philosophy of Kagisano, embracing the
concepts of social justice and harmony, interdependence and mutual assistance
(Seekings 2016).
Seretse Khama (1921–1980), who ruled Botswana from 1966 to 1980, pioneered
Kagisano as an ideology of equality, meaning that the benefits of economic growth
must be shared widely, with everyone receiving a fair share (Khama 1972, cited in
Ozoigbo 2016). He also taught people the essence of the four major social virtues
of (1) unity, (2) peace, (3) harmony, and (4) a sense of community. For the actual
realisation of these virtues, Khama was of the view that certain intrinsic concepts
had to be in place: democracy, self-reliance, and development. If people could
actually embrace these, then a better and fruitful life would be achieved (Seekings
2016). The ideology of Kagisano is that of hard work, both physical and mental,
for the general good. With regards to development, Khama posited that besides
the demands of the economy, government must consider access to basic education
as a fundamental human right, and the education system must develop moral and
social values, cultural identity and self-esteem, good citizenship and a desirable
work ethic (Seekings 2016).
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
33
Kagisano could be used to examine the democratisation of education in
Africa. Jotia (2006) applied the theory and explained how school governance
through participative democracy could be improved. Similarly, Connie Scanlon
(cited in Seekings 2016) employed the theory in her study titled ‘Educating for
Peace: Politics and Human Rights in Botswana’ which demonstrates the wide
range of applications of the theory in peace studies and human rights in Africa.
Equally, Seekings (2016) uses the theory to study the welfare policies of Botswana
in the sense that the theory is judged to be the normative foundation of a welfare
state of food aid, workfare for working-age adults, and modest cash transfers for
the elderly, orphaned children and other destitute people.
The theory has been applauded for providing a plausible basis for the ideological
and programmatic foundations of a conservative welfare state in Africa. Also, it
explains the dynamics of peacebuilding, democracy, and peaceful co-existence
which led to the rejection of racism, apartheid, and ethnic schisms in Botswana.
However, Khama was accused by critics of dressing up capitalism in the clothes
of socialist rhetoric. Seekings (2016) noticed a shift in government policies in
the 1970s to better accommodate the emerging elites’ thirst for accumulation in
cattle ranching, commerce and industry.
Mandelaism
According to Babjee (2013), Mandelaism (see Chapter 9) is a doctrine for conflict
resolution through perseverance, tolerance and peaceful negotiations unfettered
by past bitterness. Nelson Mandela, the first Black president of South Africa, is
the proponent of this ideology. For Babjee, Mandela’s legacy to the world was
the achievement of freedom for Blacks, Indians, coloureds and whites of South
Africa, uniting them into a single nation with equal rights protected by the
constitution. He showed his benevolence in the peaceful negotiations with the
white government by rising above his and the African National Congress’s years
of suffering.
Munusamy (2014) highlights how a United Nations resolution adopted in
2009 recognises Mandela’s values and dedication to the service of humanity
in the fields of conflict resolution, race relations, promotion and protection of
human rights, reconciliation, gender equality, and the rights of children and
other vulnerable groups, as well as the upliftment of poor and underdeveloped
communities. It acknowledges his contribution to the struggle for democracy
internationally and the promotion of a culture of peace throughout the world.
Mandelaism continues to be relevant in the contemporary world; Mandela Day
is widely celebrated and, more importantly, the Nelson Mandela Foundation
continues to work in South African society. In the United States, the Obama
Washington Fellowship was renamed the Mandela Washington Fellowship in
honour of Mandela.
34
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The people of South Africa are divided on the theory of Mandelaism. Some
Black people demand that their lands, which were taken by the whites, should
be given back to them. These people see no value in Mandelaism, which speaks
of peaceful negotiations unregulated by past bitterness. Mandelaism has failed
to equally unite whites and Blacks in South Africa because wealth is still in the
hands of the few. Smith (2014) illuminates how academics such as Xolela Mangcu
criticise Mandelaism by pointing out that the doctrine is preserved by political
parties, which are impermanent. Mangcu also suggests that legacies of leaders
such as Mandela need to be protected from misuse by succeeding generations.
Nasserism
Nasserism (Arabic: يرصانلا رايتلاat-Tayyār an-Nāṣerī) is a socialist system of ideas
and ideals predicated on the philosophy of Gamal Abdel Nasser, the leader of the
1952 Egyptian Revolution (Mohamed Anwar el-Sadat was second in command).
Nasser succeeded Mohamed Naguib as president of Egypt. When Nasser ascended
to power in 1956, he brought with him a vision of building a new Egypt and
Arab world. On the political front, he ushered in a centralised parliament and
changed the country into a republic (Mansfield 1973). Nasser remains an iconic
figure in Egypt and the rest of the Arab world (Ghanem 2016). Nasser’s aim was
to forge a united Arab nation led by Egypt. One of the distinguishing features of
Nasserism is its emphasis on social justice and the adoption of Arab Socialism.
During his reign, Nasser implemented land reform in Egypt, confiscating land
from feudalists and distributing it to landless peasants.
While opposed ideologically to Western Capitalism, Arab Socialism also
developed as a rejection of Communism, which was seen as incompatible with
Arab traditions and the religious underpinnings of Arab society. As a consequence,
Nasserists from the 1950s to the 1980s sought to prevent the rise of Communism
in the Arab World and advocated harsh penalties for individuals and organisations
identified as attempting to spread Communism within the region (Peter 1973).
It is important to note that Nasserism was not considered to be as consistent or
comprehensive as other ideologies such as Liberalism, Socialism, or Communism;
instead, it was seen as a system of ideas comprising all or some of the following:
anti-imperialism, Pan-Arabism (or Nationalism), and Arab Socialism.
Elie Podeh and Onn Winckler, drawing from the works of other scholars
who have written on the ideology, suggest five clusters within which the various
elucidations of Nasserism can be subsumed. The first cluster comprises writers who
characterise Nasserism as an ideological movement advocating “anti-imperialism,
Pan-Arabism (or nationalism), and Arab socialism’ (Podeh &Winckler 2004:1).
The second cluster is composed of writers who portray Nasserism as a reflection
of ‘Nasser’s charismatic personality, autocratic rule, direct connection with the
masses, and the use of rhetoric …’ (Podeh & Winckler 2004:2). The third
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
35
cluster includes authors who paint Nasserism as a ‘modernization movement and
Nasser as a modernizing leader’ (Podeh & Winckler 2004:2). The fourth cluster
is made up of authors who depict Nasserism as ‘a protest movement against
Western colonialism and imperialism, which appeared following a significant
period of crisis or disorientation’ (Podeh & Winckler 2004:3). The fifth and
final cluster constitutes observers who see Nasserism as similar to ‘populist …
movements, mainly found in Latin America during the first half of the twentieth
century’ (Podeh & Winckler 2004:4). Nasserism continues to be relevant in the
contemporary Arab world (Podeh & Winckler 2004). Nasserism had a significant
impact on left-wing movements in other parts of the developing world, especially
Africa south of the Sahara and Latin America. Nasser provided moral and material
support to liberation movements fighting colonialism and imperialism across
Africa. In fact, Nasser stated repeatedly in his speeches and writings that Egypt is
in Africa and that the country owes allegiance to the African struggle for freedom.
Nelson Mandela remarked that this support was crucial in helping to sustain
the morale of such movements, including the anti-apartheid one in South Africa.
Similar sentiments were expressed by Fidel Castro, the former Cuban President,
with regard to the Cuban Revolution and the country’s later adversities at the
hands of the United States government (Podeh & Winckler 2004).
According to Mansfield (1973), Nasser’s Arab Socialism has been criticised
by both the right and the left. Marxists claim that Nasserism has not achieved a
radical redistribution of wealth because there continues to be a huge gap between
the rich and the poor. Mansfield (1973) also maintains that Nasserism showcases
the unusual bureaucratic inefficiency of a huge state apparatus. More importantly,
Nasserism set unrealistic goals: for example, hastily planned and unrealistic
industrialisation, the flight of capital, and the loss of technical and commercial
skills of foreign minorities. The ideology is also criticised by Mansfield (1973) for
leading to the serious decline in Egypt’s financial credit abroad which led to the
loss of foreign aid and investment, especially during the 1960s. Other scholars
argue that the term Nasserism is a Western invention; as a result many Arab
intellectuals and politicians have been reluctant to adopt the term. The belief that
Nasserism is of Western origin caused unease among followers of Nasserism, as it
had been perceived to be an anti-imperialist and anti-Western ideology. The term
seems to overstate the personal role of Nasser and, thus, unjustifiably diminishes
other important aspects of the theory (Choueiri 2000).
Négritude
The word Négritude is fraught with connotations, some of which are negative.
The theory was founded by Martinican poet, playwright and politician Aimé
Fernand David Césaire and Senegalese president and scholar Léopold Sédar
Sengor. Négritude is a framework of critique and literary theory developed by
36
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Francophone intellectuals and writers of the African Diaspora in the 1930s.
Négritude is violently opposed to the European reason. It is deeply grounded in
the values of Black people but, at the same time, opens up to other civilisations.
Launched as a literary movement in the hothouse of 1930s Paris, Négritude
rejected the French colonial policy of cultural assimilation and espoused
a renewal of African culture as a vehicle for Black consciousness. According
to Echeruo (1993), the movement achieved post-war prominence with the
publication of Senghor’s Anthology of New Negro and Malagasy Poetry in 1948,
which featured extended excerpts from Césaire’s great autobiographical poem
Return to My Native Land as well as an influential introduction by Jean-Paul
Sartre (cited in Echeruo 1993).
During Césaire’s studies in France he discovered the Black community. He
saw Négritude as being Black and accepting that you are Black, and accepting this
was the means by which decolonisation of the mind would be achieved (Echeruo
1993). Négritude was about freeing Blacks in the Diaspora from isolation. It was
a cry against assimilation; because of this it holds interest today. Senghor’s theory
of Négritude lent itself to his political theory of African Socialism. In 1989, he
made an important policy statement in which he defined his political goal as the
creation of African Socialism. To him, the ideal society had to be both African
and socialist (Echeruo 1993).
One of the strengths of Négritude is that it has united Black people. The
theory inspired many movements across the African Diaspora including Black
is Beautiful in the United States. It is also an important ideology taken up by
various movements such as Hashtag Melanin on Instagram which emphasises
the importance of Black skin. Criticising Négritude, Lundhal (2009) illuminates
how aphorisms such as Sartre’s celebrated phrase found in Black Orpheus that
‘Négritude is a form of anti-racist racism’ have sparked debate. The overemphasis
on Blackness is said not to define a new kind of perception that would free
Black people and Black art from Caucasian conceptualisations. There is now a
lack of consensus about the movement. Scholars such as Thompson (2002) say
the concept is of no service to African culture. To him, the concept has been
overtaken by history and it is nonsensical to keep clinging on to it.
Pan-Africanism
Pan-Africanism as a theory does not lend itself to simple or precise definition.
Rather, it is a convenient assembly of related ideas. The ideas jostle and contradict
themselves. Scholars have provided multiple definitions for Pan-Africanism.
Senegalese writer and editor Alioume Diop believes that it is more or less
synonymous with the concept of Négritude.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
37
Its major constituent concepts are:
•
•
•
•
Africa as the homeland of Africans and persons of African ancestry;
solidarity among men and women of African blood;
belief in a distinct African blood;
Africans for Africans in church and state; and
•
the hope for a united and glorious future for Africa.
Pan-Africanism can be seen as a collective effort by African peoples worldwide to
promote unity and solidarity among people of African origin and to liberate them
from various forms of European oppression (Enoh 2013). It is important to note
that although the most visible aspect of Pan-Africanism is manifested politically,
it is a multi-faceted approach that also includes economic, cultural and religious
aspects in the struggle for the unification, rehabilitation and regeneration of
peoples of African descent around the world.
Pan-Africanism as an intellectual idea and a political project had been
advocated long before the Pan-African movement of the twentieth century. It was
born in the African Diaspora of North America and the Caribbean, where people
of African descent found emotional and intellectual satisfaction in identifying
with the African continent as a whole. Being for the most part uncertain of their
real areas of origin, descendants of enslaved Africans embraced the idea of the
continent in its fullness as ‘Mother Africa’ (Nzongola-Ntalaja 2014).
Pan-Africanism was born at the beginning of the twentieth century as a protest
against the supposed ‘otherness’ of Black people: i.e. the universal inferiority of
their status. Minkah (2011) points out that at its core, Pan-Africanism is a belief
that African people, both on the continent and in the Diaspora, share not merely
a common history, but a common destiny. For Ackah (1999), Pan Africanism is
a movement by Africans for Africans in response to European ideas of superiority
and acts of imperialism.
To Padmore (1956), Pan-Africanism offers an ideological alternative to
Communism on the one side and ethnic cleavages on the other. The strength
of Pan-Africanism is that it is all-encompassing – it rejects both white racialism
and Black chauvinism. It stands for racial co-existence on the basis of absolute
equality and respect for human personality. Pan-Africanism looks above the
narrow confines of class, race, ethnicity, and religion. In other words, it wants
equal opportunity for all, which is its greatest strength. It is universalistic in that
its vision stretches beyond the limited frontiers of the nation-state. All people,
regardless of ethnic group, race, colour or creed, are equal and free in a PanAfrican society, based on the belief that unity is vital to economic, social and
political progress. The theory aims to unify and uplift people of African descent.
38
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The concept is said to have been coined by Pan-Africanist Henry Sylvester
Williams, although today it is more known to have been popularised by PanAfricanist and African-American W.E.B. Du Bois (1868–1963) who made it
possible for African political thinkers during his time and Africans in the Diaspora
(and other Blacks) to begin a political revolution that sought to free Africans or
Blacks from slavery and colonisation, and also to unify Black people (Ola 1979).
In Africa, as noted earlier, the theory was promoted by Nyerere, Nkurumah and
Touré. In contemporary times, it has been supported by Muammar Gaddafi and
Robert Mugabe.
Pan-Africanism as an idea of African self-affirmation and a political movement
for African emancipation from colonialism and imperialism played a critical role
in the decolonisation of the African continent, and it continues to inspire the
dream of African political and economic integration. Contemporary efforts in
this regard have been entrusted to the African Union with technical support
from the African Development Bank. These Pan-African institutions have made
some progress in galvanising support for a meaningful Pan-African agenda for the
twenty-first century, although they cannot succeed in carrying out the tasks of
African integration and development without the political will and the necessary
financial contributions of African states (Nzongola-Ntajala 2014). It is therefore
imperative that these states be ruled by men and women with unequivocal
identification as Pan-Africanists and unbending support for the Pan-African
ideals and values to which scholar-activists such as W.E.B. Du Bois devoted a
lifetime of struggle (Nzongola-Ntalaja 2014).
In Ghana, Pan-Africanism has given birth to the W.E.B. Du Bois Centre for
Pan-African Culture (CPAC) and the Association for the Study of the World-Wide
African Diaspora (ASWAD). In South Africa, the Economic Freedom Fighters as
a political party follows the ideology of Pan-Africanism and during their election
campaign in 2019, their leader, Julius Malema, called for the unification of Africa.
A large apostolic sect in Zimbabwe founded by Paul Mwazha follows the ideology
of Pan-Africanism – one of its slogans is ‘Africa yedu’ (loosely translated as ‘Our
Africa’). Undeniably, Pan-Africanism paved the way for political and economic
independence on the continent, at least in the context of allowing African leaders
to realise the potentials existing within their respective countries (Ake 1965).
Critics of the ideology of Pan-Africanism have pointed out how Du Bois’ PanAfricanism as a mechanism to remind Black Americans of their African identities
and heritage (which can also be likened to the Négritude movement) differs from
Africans’ conception of Pan-Africanism (Adeleke 1998). On this point, there is
a clear emphasis on the significance of race in the Pan-Africanism dialogue that
does not entirely exist today. Because Du Bois is recognised as the founding father
of modern Pan-Africanism, some scholars scrutinise the concept as not being
authentically an African idea.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
39
One of the shortcomings in earlier studies on Pan-Africanism is the lack of
focus on the development aspect of the concept as scholars tend to bend toward the
political liberation and integration phases of Pan-Africanism. To Potekhin (1964),
Pan-Africanism started as a political movement with its own ideological basis at
the end of the nineteenth century and has since followed a very complicated,
contradictory course. Pan-Africanism in the context of unifying Africa has shifted
from a political approach to an economic policy. Adeyemo (2018) opines that
establishing a United States of Africa is a mythical idea in contemporary Africa,
no matter how popular the idea might be. To him, the idea is over-ambitious;
Pan-Africanism does not outline how Africa can become united.
Pan-Blackism
The theory of Pan-Blackism has been used in different ways and so has been
variously defined. While the theory is sometimes erroneously characterised
as simply referring to being a Black person or having black skin, others state
that it is a movement geared toward promoting Black people in every sphere of
human endeavour across the globe. Pan-Blackism aims for an awakening to the
re-identification and unification of Africans at home and in the Diaspora. It is a
call for a conscious movement towards the freedom of the African continent from
every form of foreign domination.
In the definition of Ajidahun (2019), Pan-Blackism is a tool used to redefine
and reaffirm the primacy and identity of Black people in Africa and the rest of the
world. In other words, the author views Pan-Blackism as an African awakening,
a revitalising ideology that pushes for the total freedom and emancipation of
Black people, including the rejection of all forms of colonialism, neo-colonialism
and ethnic strife among Black people all over the world. Critically analysed, PanBlackism is a post-colonial ideology which criticises the underdevelopment of
the African continent stemming from the deliberate attempt to keep African
countries in perpetual bondage by the former colonialists. As Ajidahun points
out, the Pan-Blackism ideal underlies revered Nigerian writer Femi Osofisan’s call
for unity and solidarity among all Blacks all over the world to uplift all Africans
(Ajidahun 2019).
One major criticism of Pan-Blackism is its conceptualisation. Its weak
theoretical underpinning makes it challenging to develop it into a better and more
encompassing concept. It is unlike Pan-Africanism, which is the movement that
began among the leading African figures for the purpose of attaining political,
economic as well as psychological power through strengthening the bonds of
solidarity between all Africans at home and abroad (Falola & Essien 2013). Also, while
Pan-Africanism transcends skin colour, Pan-Blackism is decidedly only for Blacks.
40
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Sankarism
Sankarism, also called Sankaraism, is a political ideology which supports social
equality and egalitarianism, often in opposition to social hierarchy. Thomas
Sankara is one of the most famous political figures in contemporary African history.
He served as a President of Burkina Faso (formerly known as Upper Volta) from
1983 to 1987 when he was assassinated in a military coup led by Blaise Compaore,
his successor. Sankara attempted to bring about what he called the ‘democratic
and popular revolution’, a radical transformation of society (Ouedraogo 2018).
Sankara’s pragmatic and ambitious agenda for his country and Africa
propelled him into the spotlight of Cold War international politics and discourse.
Ideologically, Sankara sought to reclaim the African identity of his nation and
opposed neo-colonialism. Even though Sankara was a major figure in postindependence Africa and a strong voice of the Non-aligned Movement during the
Cold War, only a few scholars have documented his legacy (Ouedraogo 2018).
After his death, Sankara is still celebrated and often remembered with deep
sorrow among people who are familiar with his Pan-Africanist and anti-imperialist
ideology, as many Sankarist leaders have attachments to either Sankara’s political
ideologies or to the organisations he created. For example, one of the first groups
to support the ideology of Sankarism was the Sankarist movement of Paris which
was formed a few weeks after his death (Hughes 1992). The Journal of Pan African
Studies in 2016 made a call for papers to evaluate how scholars and activists in
and beyond Africa have employed Sankara’s political ideology and praxis since
his assassination (Ouedraogo 2018). Many political parties and organisations
within Burkina Faso, such as the Burkinabe Party for Refoundation, the National
Patriots’ Party, The Citizens’ Boom and the Union of Sankarists’ Party (Hughes
1992), among others, have continued to identify with Sankara’s ideology. In the
wake of the Burkinabe 2014 popular revolution, which ousted Sankara’s successor,
many scholars have started to look back into Sankara’s ideological legacy and
what it could mean today. The ousting of Blaise Compaore has offered multiple
opportunities for people to talk openly about Sankara and to freely display his
images in public (Kingsley 2014).
Despite his short rule, Sankara’s political ideology helped to shape the
economy of Burkina Faso through the establishment of a self-accepting people
and a self-reliant economy. His ideology also served as a drive to achieve African
Nationalism in his country and other parts of Africa. For instance, the 2014
elections in South Africa featured the invoking of the name of Thomas Sankara
by the Economic Freedom Fighters (EFF) party (Kobo 2014).
A major shortcoming of Sankaraism is that to date, it is still a philosophical
idea that lacks strong empirical underpinning. The death of its proponent did not
allow the theory to be highly demonstrated in undiluted form.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
41
Ubuntuism
Ubuntuism, which emerged from early usage in literary and philosophical
writings, is a theoretical postulate that originated from southern Africa that
literarily means ‘humanity’. It emphasises collectivity and the connectivity of
humankind and not individualism. Ubuntu has been succinctly defined in the
phrase ‘I am because we are’; however, it is more often used in a philosophical
way to explain the belief in universality. Various words have been used to
describe aspects of Ubuntu: sympathy, benevolence, harmony, compassion,
interdependence, generosity, etc. Although the concept of Ubuntu has its origin
in the Zimbabwean political context, its prominence in the wider world is based
on three major developments: (1) its adoption as a post-colonial term in the 1980s
when used to signify the return of African dignity after the dehumanisation of
people by the British; (2) its use in the sense of brotherhood and distinctiveness
from colonially given classifications; and (3) a shift from African liberalism and
brotherhood to Christian values, identifying God as the creator. This gave room
for the mixing of African culture and biblical teachings (Metz 2011).
From the theological point of view, Ubuntuism, which preaches love,
togetherness and forgiveness, could be related to Nelson Mandela’s political
construct – Mandelaism as discussed earlier. Mandela preached forgiveness and
love, not only to the citizens of South Africa, but to the entire world. Prior to
Mandela’s reign as a leader in South Africa, the spirit of brotherliness could be
seen as the basis upon which Africa based its struggle to gain independence
in all its states, including the fight against apartheid which culminated in the
independence of South Africa.
The Ubuntuism approach could play a pivotal role in determining the success
of any African organisation. By promoting collectivism and communalism,
African culture can still come together to fight neo-colonialism, poverty and
other challenges confronting it. With the overhauling of African culture by the
Western world, however, only time will tell whether African leaders can come
together to form a union.
In Ubuntuism, the community is more important than an individual, which
negates the West’s advocacy of rugged individualism (capitalism). The philosophy
promotes positive behaviour through conscientiousness and love. Synergies
and competitive advantages arise. Ubuntuism promotes teamwork, giving
organisations and political systems competitive advantages, including effective
human relationships, language and communication, decision-making, time
management, productivity and leadership. There is respect for community in
general. There is good corporate governance founded upon the values of business
ethics (Metz 2011).
42
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Some of the core values of Ubuntuism Theory are weak. For example, openness
to new ideas and respect for authorities has often been cited as one of the major
precursors to the advent of colonial imperialism in Africa. The philosophy may
result in a herd mentality in a particular group and lead to possible exclusion of
other groups. An example is the xenophobic attacks that have been witnessed
several times in South Africa. According to Metz (2011), Ubuntuism has failed to
recognise the value of individual freedom. It also promotes an indigenous, smallscale culture as against that of industrialised society.
Ujamaa
Ujamaa Theory emanated from President Julius Kambarage Nyerere of Tanzania
in 1967 when he advanced the view that there is a need for Africa to develop,
which can mainly be achieved through African Socialism. Just like the concept
of Ubuntu, Ujamaa is used to depict familyhood, brotherhood, sisterhood, or
socialism. These formed the basis of social and economic development policies
of Tanzania after its independence in 1961. The Kiswahili concept Ujamaa, in
its political form, asserts that an individual can only exist and be recognised as
one through the people or community. Nyerere believed in a classless society
where there should be respect for human rights and all talents and resources
should be pooled to achieve a common good. From this political perspective,
Nyerere developed several models which formed his national development
plans among which were the establishment of a one-party system to strengthen
the cohesion of the newly obtained independence, the abolition of social class
discrimination through the promotion of socioeconomic and political equality,
the implementation of compulsory but free education, and so on. Nyerere’s
ideology and political administration attracted international attention as a result
of his respect for the community and its effect on economic development (Legum
& Mmari 1998).
Ujamaa promoted consensus democracy, based on its promotion of a classless
society and respect for the rights of all citizens. Many African countries still
operate consensus democratic systems of government as a result of its flexibility
and respect for citizens’ rights, as opposed to autocratic rule.
The proponents of Ujamaa tried to end dependence on rich foreign countries.
This movement served as a push for many of Africa’s formerly colonised countries
to develop economic self-reliance through societal collectivity in the production
of goods and services and the eradication of the class society established by whites.
Tanzania tried to achieve self-reliance through the mobilisation of its resources.
One cannot ignore the concept of Ujamaa as it helped to define the new freedom
and independence of Tanzanian society, and also in the whole of Africa and the
rest of the Third World (Legum & Mmari 1998).
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
43
To this day, the spirit of Ujamaa is still used by the citizens of many African
countries to fight erring political leaders and to communicate their needs to their
governments. Ujamaa promoted unity, cooperation, and oneness between leaders
and citizens. This led to some of the socioeconomic achievements of Nyerere
during his administration among which are the reduction in infant mortality
(from 138/1,000 live births in 1965 to 110 in 1985), the increase in life
expectancy at birth (37 in 1960 to 52 in 1984), and the rise in the adult literacy
levels from 17 per cent in 1960 to 63 per cent in 1975 (Legum & Mmari 1998).
Ujamaa fostered cultural, ethnic and racial unity among its people. Although
many African economies are still controlled by the West, Ujamaa has served as a
philosophical model for other African countries to develop internally as well as
gain political freedom the Westerners (Legum & Mmari 1998).
Although the goal of Ujamaa to promote societal collectivism for the greater
good led to the formation of a one-party political system, it is arguably preferable
to the autocracy of corrupt leaders who served in the years after Nyerere. These
political figures created oppression in society by the rich, creating a class-based
society. Ujamaa preached against capitalism, but, unknown to Nyerere, capitalism
finds its way into all societies. Nyerere was ignorant of the continued inequality
between rural and urban farmers during his administration; this situation affected
productivity negatively. In addition, the promotion of self-reliance and collective
mobilisation of resources without the introduction of foreign mechanised
equipment and assistance cannot sustain an economy. Ujamaa’s villagisation
failed. Tanzania became one of Africa’s poorest countries with heavy dependence
on international aid. Other disadvantages of Ujamaa include underdeveloped
industrial and banking sectors and poor transportation networks (Legum &
Mmari 1998).
The absence of a complete overhaul of the political framework and ideologies
of the colonial figures is also one of the factors responsible for the failure of
Ujamaa. Nyerere, though he was an anti-colonialist, did not totally ignore the
political ideologies of the British in Tanzania. Instead, he adopted some of their
views and, as such, established capitalism, class distinctiveness, and the practice
of British culture in society (Legum & Mmari 1998).
Womanism
Womanism is a social theory based on the history and everyday experiences
of women of colour, especially Black women. United States writer and social
activist Alice Walker founded Womanism based on the African-American
experience of the troubled period of slavery and the long struggle for civil
rights. As we learn from Alice Walker’s book titled In Search of our Mother’s
Garden: Womanist Prose (1983), the term Womanism was coined in her short
44
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
story titled Coming Apart in 1979. As her literary scope continues to expand,
she sees the need to have a movement different from feminism, which will offer
Black women an opportunity to formulate their course of action. Womanism
holds tenaciously the position that both femininity and culture are of utmost
importance to the existence of women. One’s femininity cannot be examined
outside of the culture in which it exists. Proponents of the theory go further to
advocate that the culture of a woman should not be a yardstick to measure her
femininity; rather, it is the window through which femininity thrives. It then
follows that a woman’s blackness is not a component of her feminism; rather,
her blackness is the window by which she understands her femininity.
Womanism emerged as a result of the racism suffered by Black women in
the feminist movement. They believe that the experiences of Black women
cannot be equated to those of white women who have treated Blackness with
contempt throughout history. Womanism is not an extension of feminism; it is
a theoretical framework that exists independent of Feminist Theory. Womanism
presents itself as being stronger and more original than feminism. Womanists’
intention is to ‘decenter white feminists and challenge the normality of their
perspective’ (Bryson 2003:228). Many writers in Africa such as Buchi Emecheta,
Mariama Ba and Miriam Tlali identify with Womanism rather than feminism
as a paradigm in the analyses of their works about women. Womanism is a
functional paradigm not just for Black women in North America and Africa
but also for women in Latin America due to issues of common interest they
share (see Nnaemeka 2010). Womanism challenges all structures of power that
pose a problem for the development and growth of the human circle. Thus,
according to Nnaemeka (2010), the impact of Womanism has gone far beyond
the United States, and many women scholars and literary critics have embraced
it as an analytical tool.
Womanism is a broader category that includes feminism as a subtype. It
is a theory for the survival of the Black race and it takes into cognisance the
experiences of Black women, Black culture, Black myths, spiritual life and orality
(Walker 1983). Walker’s most quoted phrase, ‘womanist is to the feminist as
purple is to the lavender’ means that feminism is an element under the conceptual
umbrella of Womanism.
One of the weaknesses of the theory of Womanism is its failure to critically
examine homosexuality in Black people. There is a minimal amount of literature
that associates Womanism to lesbian, gay, bisexual, transgender, and queer
(LGBTQ) concerns. Womanism has also been criticised for its inclusion policy
which led Walker to incorporate coloured or white women, and even men who
are women-friendly, under the auspices of Womanism.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
45
Zuluism
The theory of Zuluism encompasses a discourse that examines the role of Black
Nationalism. The production of the image of the Zulu as fierce and war-like
began with the first Anglo-Zulu encounter in the nineteenth century. In 1879,
the Anglo-Zulu War set the pace for image-making which was developed further
in the late nineteenth century. In 1982, Samuel Martin completed a work on
British portrayals of the Zulu. His work critiqued the origins of images of the
Zulu. He based his research on Edward Said’s Orientalism, which depicts how
Western images of the Orient fashioned by generations of scholars paint Orientals
as lazy, deceitful and irrational.
The African continent offers fertile ground for self-fulfilling imaginings,
providing a thematic space in which writers can discharge their fantasies. Africa
was and is a symbolic hunting field leading to a magic world of trials and noble
achievements (MacKenzie 1992). These fantasies – on which Zuluism is based –
arose out of notions of heroic masculinity, the development of militarism in the
late nineteenth century and the need for entertainment (MacKenzie 1992). The
Zulu people believe that it is not victory that establishes a soldier’s greatness but
the qualities he shows in confronting defeat. Only in this way can the soldier’s
heroic virtue be made manifest (MacKenzie 1992).
The word Zulu means ‘Sky’ and history records that Zulu was the name of the
ancestor who founded the Zulu royal kingdom in about 1670. They originally
came from the Nguni people who inhabited Central and Eastern Africa and
migrated to South Africa in the ‘Bantu Migration’ which took place centuries
earlier. They are the largest ethnic group in South Africa today and are known for
their strong fighting spirit. The history of South Africa would not be complete
without them being mentioned (MacKenzie 1992).
The founder of the Zulu kingdom, Shaka Zulu, is celebrated and remembered
in the month of September of every year. The celebration is held in KwaDukuza
where Shaka’s tombstone is located. It is marked by poets singing the praises of all
the Zulu kings from Shaka to the current king (MacKenzie 1992).
A majority of the Zulu-speaking people live in KwaZulu-Natal Province
in South Africa. They speak isiZulu. They strongly believe in ancestral spirits
known as amadlozi, the spirits of the dead. Zulu ancestors are believed to live
in a spirit ancestral home called Unkulunkulu (the ‘greatest of the great’). They
are the intermediaries between the living and the spirit world, and they work
hand-in-hand with God. The presence of ancestral spirits undergirds Zulu beliefs
(MacKenzie 1992).
The Zulu are known for their belief in and practice of Ubuntu, which denotes
‘humanness’ and it is also a part of the daily life of the Zulu people. This belief is
enshrined in many proverbs relating to good and bad behaviour among human beings.
46
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
One may argue that Zuluism does not carry much weight in contemporary
South Africa, considering that Zuluism is about Ubuntuism which implies
humanness. One may argue that Zuluism does not carry much weight in
contemporary South Africa. One tenet of Zuluism is Ubuntuism, and it hard
to square this with the intra-racial attacks that take place in the country. These
attacks do not resemble the Pan-Africanism which advocates for the unification
of Black people.
References
Ackah, William, 1999, Pan Africanism: Exploring the Contradictions: Politics and Identity
and Development in the Africa and the African Diaspora, London, UK: Ashgate
Publishing Company.
Adeleke, Tunde, 1998, ‘Black Americans and Africa: A Critique of the Pan-African and
Identity Paradigms’, The International Journal of African Historical Studies, Vol. 31,
No. 3, pp. 505–536.
Adeyemo, A., 2018, ‘The Spirit is Willing, But the Flesh is Weak: Contemporary Pan–
Africanism and the Challenges to a United States of Africa’, Master’s thesis, 1157.
(https://repository.usfca.edu/thes/1157). 8 September 2021.
Adichie, Chimamanda Ngozi, 2015, We Should All Be Feminists, New York, NY: Penguin
Random House.
Ajidahun, A. Clement, 2019, ‘Blackism and Pan-Africanism in Post-Colonial African
Literature: A Reading of Femi Osofisan’s Plays’, International Journal of African
Literary and Comparative Studies, Vol. 9, No. 2, pp. 1–15. (https://journals.co.za/
doi/10.25159/2663-6565/5179). 8 September 2021.
Ake, Claude, 1965, ‘Pan-Africanism and African Governments’, The Review of Politics,
Vol. 27, No. 4, pp. 532–542.
Asante, Molefi Kete, 2001, The Afrocentric Idea, Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
Babjee, A. Mustaffa, 2013, ‘“Mandelaism” – A Doctrine for Conflict Resolution’, The Star
Online. (https://www.thestar.com.my/opinion/letters/2013/12/24/mandelaism-adoctrine-for-conflict-resolution). 8 September 2021.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2018, ‘A Diopian Analysis of the Symbolism of the Council
for the Development of Social Science Research in Africa’, Africology: The Journal
of Pan-African Studies, Vol. 11, No. 4, pp. 205–224. (http://www.jpanafrican.org/
docs/vol11no4/11.4-15-Bangura-final.pdf ). 5 September 2021.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2019a, The Branches of Asanteism, Lanham, MD: Lexington
Books.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2019b, Falolaism: The Epistemologies and Methodologies of Africana
Knowledge, Durham, NC: Carolina Academic Press.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, Obando, Joy A., Munene, Ishmael I. and Shisanya, Chris, eds.,
2019, Conducting Research and Mentoring Students in Africa: CODESRIA College of
Mentors Handbook, Dakar, Senegal: CODESRIA Publications.
Bjerk, Paul, 2017, Julius Nyerere, Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
47
Blaisdell, Bob, ed., 2004, Selected Writings and Speeches of Marcus Garvey, New York, NY:
Dover Publications.
Blay, Zeba and Gray, Emma, August 10, 2015, ‘Why We Need To Talk About White
Feminism’, The Huffington Post. (http://www.huffingtonpost.com/entry/why-weneed-to-talk-about-white-feminism_55c8ca5ce4b0f73b20ba020a). 2 September
2021.
Botwe-Asamoah, Kwame, 2005, Kwame Nkrumah’s Politico-Cultural Thought and Policies:
An African-Centred Paradigm for the Second Phase of the African Revolution, Hove,
East Sussex, UK: Psychology Press.
Bryson, Valerie, 2003, Feminist Political Theory, New York, NY: Macmillan.
Césaire, Aimé, 2004, Discours sur le colonialisme (followed by Discours sur la Négritude),
Paris, France: Présence Africaine.
Choueiri, Youssef M., 2000, Arab Nationalism: A History, Nation and State in the Arab
World, Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell Publishing Company.
Collins, Patricia, H., 1996, ‘What’s In a Name? Womanism, Black Feminism, and
Beyond’, The Black Scholar, Vol. 26, pp. 9–17. (https://doi.org/10.1080/00064246.
1996.11430765). 8 September 2021.
Dagnini, Jeremie Kroubo, 2008, ‘Marcus Garvey: A Controversial Figure in the History
of Pan-Africanism’, The Journal of Pan-African Studies, Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 198–208.
Damaji, U.G., 1972, Leadership Ideology in Africa, New York, NY: Praeger Publishers.
Diop, Cheikh Anta, 1974, The African Origin of Civilization: Myth or Reality, New York,
NY: Lawrence Hill Books.
Diop, Cheikh Anta, 2000, Towards the African Renaissance: Essays in Culture and
Development, 1946–1960, Trenton, NJ: Red Sea Press.
Early G., et al., 1994, ‘Symposium: Historical Roots of Afrocentrism’, Academic Questions,
Vol. 7, No. 2, pp. 44–54.
Echeruo, Michael J.C., 1993, ‘Négritude and History: Senghor’s Argument with
Frobenius’, Research In African Literatures, Vol. 24, No. 4, pp. 1–13.
Edgar, Robert, 1976, ‘Garveyism in Africa: Dr Wellington and the African Movement in
the Transkei Ufahamu’, A Journal of African Studies, Vol. 6, No. 3, pp. 31–57.
Ekanem F. E., 2012, ‘On the Ontology of African Philosophy’, Pakistan Journal of Social
Sciences, Vol. 9, No. 6, pp. 306–310.
El-Khawas, Mohammad A., 1984, ‘The New Society in Gaddafi’s Libya: Can it Endure?’,
Africa Today, Vol. 31, No. 3, pp. 17–44.
Enoh, Richard A.A., 2013, ‘The Global Implications of Pan Africanism and the
Establishment of “New Communities” in Africa: The Case of Victoria in Southwest
Cameroon’ in T. Falola and K. Essien, eds., Pan-Africanism, and the Politics of African
Citizenship and Identity, London. UK: Routledge.
Falola. Toyin and Essien, Kwame, eds., 2013, Pan-Africanism and the Politics of African
Citizenship and Identity, London. UK: Routledge.
Forsyth, Paul, 1992, ‘The Past in the Service of the Present: The Political Use of History
by Chief A.N.M.G. Buthelezi 1951–1991’, South African Historical Journal, Vol.
26, pp. 74–92.
48
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Gaddafi, Muammar, 1972, Libyan Arab Republic: First September Revolution and
Contemporary World, Tripoli, Libya: Government Printer.
Garcia, S.E. and Echeverria, M.P.D, ‘Muammar Gaddafi’s Legacy: A Domestic and
Intellectual Approach’, Journal of Pan-African Studies, Vol. 11, No. 3, pp. 4–25.
Ghanem, Hafez, 2016, ‘Egypt’s Difficult Transition: Options for the International
Community’, Milken Institute Review, Vol. 1, pp. 1–47.
Gilliam, Waddell Doris, 2013, ‘I Have to Know Who I Am: An Africana Womanist
Analysis of Afro-Brazilian Identity in the Literature of Miriam Alves, Esmeralda
Ribeiro and Conceição Evaristo’, Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations, The
Graduate School, Florida State University Libraries. (https://diginole.lib.fsu.edu/
islandora/object/fsu:183926/datastream/PDF/view). 2 September 2021.
Goldfine, Rebecca, 2015, ‘Clenora Hudson-Weems: Africana Womanism: A Global
Paradigm for Women of African Descent’. (https://www.bowdoin.edu/talks/
recordings/2015/clenora-hudson-weems.html). 2 September 2021.
Hudson-Weems, Clenora, 1993, in Goldfine Rebecca, 2015, ‘Clenora HudsonWeems: Africana Womanism: A Global Paradigm for Women of African Descent.
(https://www.bowdoin.edu/talks/recordings/2015/clenora-hudson-weems.html).
2 September 2021.
Hughes, Arnold, 1992, Marxism’s Retreat from Africa, London, UK: Psychology Press.
Ikuenobe, Polycarp, 2013, ‘Consciencism: Kwame Nkrumah’. (http://homepage.westmont.
edu/hoeckley/readings/symposium/pdf/201_300/207.pdf). 26 October 2019.
Jotia, Agreement Lathi, 2006, ‘The Quest for Deep Democratic Participation: Schools as
Democratic Spaces in the Post-Colonial Botswana’, a PhD dissertation presented to
Faculty of College of Education of Ohio University. (http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/
view?acc_num=ohiou1147360469). 6 September 2021.
Kanduza, Ackson M., 2011, ‘Steve Biko and Kenneth Kaunda: Sampling Youth in
History’, New Contree, Vol. 62, pp. 71–90.
Kobo, Kingsley, 2014, ‘Burkina Faso: Ghost of Africa’s Che Guevara’. (https://www.
aljazeera.com/features/2014/10/31/burkina-faso-ghost-of-africas-che-guevara).
8 September 2021.
Legum, Colin and Mmari, G R.V., eds., 1998, Mwalimu: The Influence of Nyerere,
Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press.
Lundhal, Mikela, 2009, Négritude: An Anti-racist Racism, Newcastle upon Tyne, UK:
Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
MacKenzie, John, M., 1992, Popular Imperialism and the Military: 1850–1950,
Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press.
Mansfield, Peter, 1973, ‘Nasser and Nasserism’, International Journal, Vol. 28, No. 4,
pp. 670–688.
Manyonganise, Molly, 2015, ‘Oppressive and Liberative: A Zimbabwean Woman’s
Reflections on Ubuntu’, Verbum et Ecclesia, Vol. 36, No. 2. (https://doi.org/10.4102/
ve.v36i2.1438). 8 September 2021.
Maparyan, Layli, 2012, The Womanist Idea, New York, New York: Taylor and Francis.
Martin, S.J.R., 1982, ‘British Images of the Zulu c.1820–1879’, PhD thesis, University
of Cambridge. (https://doi.org/10.17863/CAM.19842). 8 September 2021.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
49
Mazrui, Ali Al’Amin, 1977, Africa’s International Relations: The Diplomacy of Dependency
& Change, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Mazrui, Ali Al’Amin., 1982, ‘Africa Between Nationalism and Nationhood. A Political
Survey’, Journal of Black Studies, Vol. 13, No. 1, pp. 23–44.
Mbeki, Thabo, 1996, ‘Statement on behalf of the African National Congress, on the
occasion of the adoption by the Constitutional Assembly of The Republic of South
Africa Constitutional Bill 1996’. (https://www.gov.za/about-government/tmmbeki-adoption-rsa-constitution-bill). 9 September 2021.
Mbeki, Thabo, 1998, ‘The African Renaissance Statement’. (http://www.dirco.gov.za/
docs/speeches/1998/mbek0813.htm). 9 September 2021.
Mbembe, Achille, 2001, On the Postcolony, Berkeley, CA and London, UK: University of
California Press.
Mbembe, Achille, 2007, ‘Afropolitanism’, in N. Simon and L. Durán, eds., Africa Remix:
Contemporary Art of a Continent, Johannesburg, South Africa: Johannesburg Art Gallery.
Mboti, Nyasha, 2015, ‘May the Real Ubuntu Please Stand Up?’, Journal of Media Ethics,
Vol. 30, No. 2, pp. 125–147. (https://doi.org/10.1080/23736992.2015.1020380).
9 September 2021.
Metz, Thaddeus, 2011, ‘Ubuntu as a Moral Theory and Human Rights in South Africa’,
African Human Rights Law Journal, Vol. 11, pp. 532–559.
Miike, Yoshitaka, 2008, ‘Advancing Centricity for Non-Western Scholarship: Lessons
from Molefi Kete Asante’s Legacy of Afrocentricity’, in A. Mazama, ed., Essays in
Honor of an Intellectual Warrior, Molefi Kete Asante, Paris, France: Menaibuc.
Minkah, Makalani, 2011, Pan-Africanism, New York NY: The New York Public Library,
Africana Age.
Mjiba, Frehiwot, 2016, ‘Kwame Nkrumah’s Social-Political Thought and Pan-African
Movement’. (https://www.researchgate.net/publication/305461927_Kwame_Nkru
mah’s _Social-Political_Thought_and_Pan-African_Movement). 1 September 2021.
Munusamy, Ranjeni, 2014, ‘The 20 Years from Mandela to Zuma’, Daily Maverick.
(https://www.dailymaverick.co.za/article/2014-03-12-sas-20-year-review-frommandela-to-zuma/). 8 September 2021.
Nkrumah, Kwame, 1964, Consciencism: Philosophy and Ideology for Decolonization and
Development with Particular Reference to the African Revolution, London, UK:
Heinemann.
Nnaemeka, Obioma, 2010, ‘Womanism’. (https://science.jrank.org/pages/8159/
Womanism.html). 8 September 2021.
Nzongola-Ntalaja, Georges, 2014, ‘Pan-Africanism since Decolonization: From the
Organisation of African Unity (OAU) to the African Union (AU)’, African Journal
of Democracy and Governance, Vol. 1, No. 4, pp. 31–47.
Ola, Opeyemi, 1979, ‘Pan-Africanism: An Ideology of Development’, Présence Africaine,
Vol. 112, pp. 66–95.
Olasupo, Olusola; Oladeji, Isaac Olayide and Ijeoma, E.O.C., 2017, ‘Nationalism and
Nationalist Agitation in Africa: the Nigerian Trajectory’, The Review of the Black
Political Economy’. (https://ideas.repec.org/a/spr/blkpoe/v44y2017i3d10.1007_
s12114-017-9257-x.html). 1 September 2021.
50
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Ouedraogo, Lassane, 2018, ‘Mediated Sankarism: Reinventing a Historical Figure to
Reimagine the Future’, African Studies Quarterly, Vol. 18, No. 1, pp. 19–30.
Ozoigbo, Bonaventure Ikechukwu, 2016, ‘African Theories of Development and the
Reality of Underdevelopment’, International Journal of Development and Economic
Sustainability, Vol. 4, No. 4, pp.12–19. (http://www.eajournals.org/wp-content/
uploads/African-Theories-of-Development-and-the-Reality-of-Underdevelopment.
pdf ). 5 September 2021.
Padmore, George, 1956, Pan-Africanism or communism? the coming struggle for Africa,
London, UK: D. Dobson.
Phillips, Layli, 2006, ‘Introduction: Womanism On Its Own’, in L. Phillips, ed., The
Womanist Reader, New York, NY and Abingdon, UK: Routledge.
Ottaway, D. and Ottaway, M., 1970, Algeria: the politics of a socialist revolution, Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press.
Podeh, Elie and Winckler, Onn, 2004, Rethinking Nasserism: Revolution and Historical
Memory in Modern Egypt, Gainesville, FL: University Press of Florida.
Potekhin, Ivan, 1964, ‘Pan-Africanism and the Struggle of the Two Ideologies’,
Communist, pp. 36–48. (https://disa.ukzn.ac.za/sites/default/files/pdf_files/
Acn1964.0001.9976.000.019.Oct1964.7.pdf ). 8 September 2021.
Pratt, Cranford, 1999, ‘Julius Nyerere: Reflections on the Legacy of His Socialism’,
Canadian Journal of African Studies, Vol. 33, No. 1, pp. 137–52. (https://doi.
org/10.2307/486390). 9 September 2021.
Rabaka, Reiland, 2014, Concepts of Cabralism: Amilcar Cabral and Africana Critical
Theory, New York, NY: Lexington Books.
Reed, W.; Lawson, E.J. and Gibbs, T., 1997, ‘Afrocentrism in the 21st Century’, The
Western Journal of Black Studies, Vol. 21, No. 3, pp. 73–79.
Santana, S. Bosch, 2015, ‘Exorcizing the Future: Afropolitanism’s Spectral Origins’,
Journal of African Cultural Studies, Vol. 128, No. 1, pp. 120–126.
Seekings, Jeremy, 2016, ‘“A Lean Cow Cannot Climb out of the Mud, but a Good
Cattleman Does not Leave it to Perish”: The Origins of Conservative Welfare Doctrine
in Botswana under Seretse Khama, 1966–1980’, CSSR Working Paper, 387.
Selasi, T., 2005, Bye-Bye, Babar. (https://thelip.robertsharp.co.uk/?p=76). 2 September
2021.
Shivji, Issa G., 2003, ‘The Rise, the Fall, and The Insurrection of Nationalism in
Africa’, Paper From Keynote Address to the CODESRIA East African Regional
Conference held in Addis Ababa, Ethiopia, October 29–31, 2003. (https://www.
semanticscholar.org/paper/The-rise%2C-the-fall%2C-and-the-insurrection-of-inShivji/de596b34a5d4edc8f36838d745e5f186711c63f3). 9 September 2021.
Smith, D, 2014, South Africa: One Year after Nelson Mandela’s Death. (https://www.
theguardian.com/world/2014/dec/06/south-africa-one-year-after-nelson-mandeladeath). 8 September 2021.
Smith, William Edgett, 1973, Nyerere of Tanzania, London, UK: Victor Gollanz.
Stikkers, K.W., 2008, ‘An Outline of Methodological Afrocentrism, with Particular
Application to the Thought of W.E.B. Du Bois’, Journal of Speculative Philosophy,
Vol. 22, No. 1, pp. 40–49.
Doctoral Scholars: African- centred
51
Thompsell, Angela, 2019, ‘Get the Definition of Ubuntu, A Nguni Word with Several
Meanings’. (https://www.thoughtco.com/the-meaning-of-ubuntu-43307).
9 September 2021.
Thompson, Peter S., 2002, Négritude and Changing Africa: An Update in Research in
African Literatures, Concord, MA: Wayside Publishing.
Tutu, Desmond, 1999, No Future Without Forgiveness, New York, NY: Doubleday Books.
Tutu, Desmond, 2013, ‘Who We Are: Human Uniqueness and the African
Spirit of Ubuntu’, Templeton Prize, YouTube. (https://www.youtube.com/
watch?v=0wZtfqZ271w&feature=share). 9 September 2021
Vaillant, Janet, 1976, ‘Perspectives on Leopold Senghor and the Changing Face of
Negritude’, African Studies Association Review of Books, Vol. 2, pp. 154–162. (https://
www.jstor.org/stable/532364). 1 September 2021.
Van Veen, Tobias, 2016, ‘Concepts of Cabralism: A Review.’ Decolonization: Indigeneity,
Education & Society, Vol. 5, No. 1, pp. 79–89. (https://jps.library.utoronto.ca/index.
php/des/article/view/26535). 3 September 2021.
Walker, Alice, 1983, In Search of our Mother’s Garden: Womanist Prose, New York, NY:
Harcourt Brace.
Winchell, Donna Haisty, 1992, Alice Walker, New York, NY: Twayne Publishers.
2
Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
Doctoral Scholars
This chapter covers three theories on architecture, three on art, three on
community, and seven on culture. The first set of theories deals with the complex
or carefully designed structure of an entity or a phenomenon. The second set
concerns the expression or application of human creative skill and imagination,
typically in a visual form such as painting or sculpture, producing works to be
appreciated primarily for their beauty or emotional power. The third set is about
a group of people living in the same place or having a particular characteristic
in common. And the fourth set has to do with what shapes a people’s total way
of life: i.e. the customs, arts, social institutions, and other manifestations of the
intellectual achievements of a particular people.
Architecture
Abstraction Theory
In the field of architecture, Abstraction Theory refers to a conceptual process by
which general rules and concepts are derived from the usage and classification of
specific instances, which could be real or concrete signifiers. It is also a concept
that acts as a common noun for all subordinate concepts and connects any related
concepts as a group, field, or category. It can be done by sifting the information
content of a concept or any observable phenomenon and picking those aspects
that are applicable to a particular value. According to Milton, Abstraction in
architecture is ‘a process by which something innate is revealed whether willed
or not. Abstraction is suggestive, oblique and symbolic. It is a dream, selfexpression and hopefully even true insight. The abstracted element in intuition
that specifically links to an idea and to notion of actual design that takes on
reality as it is developed into building design’ (2017:265).
54
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
This excerpt implies that Abstraction is a powerful tool meant to support
architectural design and creative thinking. It is believed to be as old as human
language. It involves the assimilation of an idea into one general theory about
something. Abstraction was discussed in Francis Bacon’s book Noyum Organum
(1920) in which he encouraged modern thinkers to collect specific facts before
making any generalisations.
A person’s relationship with architecture has always been via nature, starting
with early humans and evolving throughout history. According to Pashmeena,
Abstraction Theory leads us to view the ‘art, beauty and architecture’ of nature
(Pashmeena 2017:118). He goes on to say that the sole target of Abstraction ‘is
to simplify nature, to extract primary logic for design expression’ (Pashmeena
2017:118). Through Abstraction, the intricate power of natural occurrences
can be stripped down, simplified, studied and shifted into possible dynamic
designs. The artist first distinguishes the appearance of things and by intuition
recognises a design pattern that will fit their purpose. Abstraction has two basic
design directions: the first leads to an abstracted design element for a twodimensional design and the second extends the Abstraction process to a higher
level for architecture and three-dimensional designs (Pashmeena 2017). These
two possibilities begin from nature, but each departs from nature ‘just as the body
dies, but the spirit lives on’ (Pashmeena 2017:118). In the design process, the
more repetition, the further one gets from nature. At the end of the day, what is
left of nature is its essence. The power of Abstraction proceeds from the spirit of
nature to the creativity of the human mind and finally to an art form.
Abstraction is motivated by indicative ideas that task our minds, leading to
the inspiration that precipitates abstract notions. These inspirations give organic
design its psychological and inventive power. This inventive power of imagination
can be either positive or negative and it is one of the most potent forces in the
world, producing myths, religions, arts, architecture, peace, cold wars, hot wars,
and oil wars (Pashmeena 2017:119). The significance of abstraction lies in its
capacity to arouse creative thought, to inspire flexible reason, and to involve the
mind, leading to creative power. A creative mind enables the designer to achieve
continual perception, thereby leading to original construction.
Induction was promoted by Pashmeena as an Abstraction tool. It distorts the
deductive thinking methodology that has dominated the intellectual world since
the ancient philosophers. It can also be seen as a process which maps multiple
different pieces of constituent data to a single piece of abstract datum based
on similarities in the constituent data. In summation, according to Pashmeena
(2017), the beauty of abstracting nature for the purpose of architecture and life
is a timeless idea, with no final process. This means that there is an always an
opening in Abstraction for architecture and other creative designs.
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
55
Concretion Theory
According to Norvig (1983) and Wilensky (1983), Concretion Theory is an
approach in which a more specific interpretation of an utterance is made than can
be sustained on a strictly logical manner. The two authors point out that French
architect and author Eugène Viollet-le-Duc proposed the theory of Concretion
based on his view that the art of building construction should create spaces arising
from the structural materials used.
A Concretion Theory may differ from traditional theories in that a concretion
inference may be incorrect. For instance, ‘to use a pencil’ means to write with
a pencil, whereas ‘to use a dictionary’ means to look up a word. To use a pencil
may mean writing; but in a particular context, it might mean opening the door
with a pencil. In the absence of compelling evidence to the contrary, the natural
interpretation is writing.
A concretion mechanism attempts to find clues in a set of general concepts
to generate concepts that are more specific. Writing, for example, is a specific
type of activity in which the tool being used may be a pencil. The use of such
a principle allows a straightforward approach to manipulating hierarchical
knowledge structures. The original interpretation of an utterance may include
concepts too general for an utterance to be understood in computational
analysis. Concretion Theory has the mandate of making the right interpretation
of a concept by choosing one of its available models. It is important to know
how to understand a specific concept before applying Concretion principles.
Different categories are necessary based on various situations. For instance, it
is okay in some cases to leave the meaning of ‘eating’ as ‘eating some food’.
Perhaps, in a context involving picnics, a more specific interpretation may be
achieved. (Norvig 1983; Wilensky 1983).
It is also imperative that the mechanism be able to recognise from a wide variety
of clues that there is sufficient evidence to ‘concrete’, to resolve an ambiguity. A
constant process of demonstrating the rules by which a Concretion may be made
would be welcome. Some means must be provided to correct wrong inferences
and contradictory facts when found (Norvig 1983; Wilensky 1983).
Phenomenology Theory
Phenomenology Theory is an approach initiated by Edmund Husserl (1859–
1938) and later developed by Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), which seeks to
study lived human experiences and the way things are perceived and appear to
the consciousness. Around the turn of the twentieth century, Husserl established
his Phenomenology as a philosophy to challenge Cartesian philosophy which
was objective, empirical, and positivist (Barnacle in Barnacle 2001). From a
philosophical perspective, Husserl saw Phenomenology as a way of reaching
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
56
true meaning by penetrating deeper and deeper into reality. His theory was later
followed up by Heidegger, who developed his own strand of the philosophy named
Existential Phenomenology (Spinelli 2005) or Hermeneutic Phenomenology
(Smith et al. 2009).
There are two main approaches to Phenomenology:
1. descriptive and
2. interpretive.
Descriptive Phenomenology was developed by Husserl and Interpretive
Phenomenology by Heidegger (Connelly 2010). Husserl’s approach is also
known as Transcendental Phenomenology and preceded Heidegger’s Interpretive
Phenomenology historically (Spinelli 2005). Interpretive Phenomenology is also
known as Hermeneutic Phenomenology (Laverty 2003; Langdridge 2007) and as
Existential Phenomenology (Spinelli 2005). The general focus of the descriptive
phenomenological approach is to examine the essence or structure of experiences
in the way they occur to our consciousness.
Phenomenological Theory can be applied in every public and professional
practice, including nursing science, education, psychology, social work, etc.
In architecture, phenomenology involves the study of how light and shadow,
material and space are controlled to provide an indelible experience by affecting
the human senses. The theory advances the amalgamation of sensory perception
as a raison d’être for a built form.
Phenomenology evolved into a relatively mature qualitative research
methodology during the last decades of the twentieth century largely due to a
seismic shift from mainly deductive quantitative research to inductive qualitative
research. Such interest has also contributed to the proliferation of the approach
with little consensus on what constitutes the methodology (Spinelli 2005).
Husserl’s Phenomenology has been criticised by many scholars for being too
philosophical, conceptual, and difficult to decipher. The notion that the ultimate
human experience can be examined by setting aside preconceived knowledge
has been dismissed as simplistic and unattainable. Pure experience advocated by
Husserl is elusive and inaccessible because experience is usually witnessed after
the event has already happened.
Art
Abstraction Theory
Abstraction Theory in the art discipline is used to explain the use of visual or
pictorial language of form, shape, colour and line to define a phenomenon. It
could also mean creating a composition through social language, which may
exist independently of a visual object in the world (Arnheim 1969). Up to
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
57
the mid-nineteenth century, Western art had been underpinned by an attempt
to reproduce reality, even if that was by means of inference. By the end of
nineteenth century, however, many artists saw the need to develop a new kind
of reality through art, which would encompass the changes and processes
of transformation in different fields, including technology, science, and
philosophy. Simply put, abstract art does not represent an accurate depiction
of a visual reality but rather uses shapes, colours, forms and gestural marks to
achieve its effect and purpose. A work of abstract art can be classified as ‘nonfigurative’, ‘non-representational’, and ‘geometric abstraction’. This tells us that
abstract art is a rather vague umbrella term for any painting or sculpture that
does not depict recognisable objects or scenes.
Russian painter Wassily Kandinsky (1886–1944) is considered the father
of Abstraction Theory in art and was among the first artists to delve into pure
abstract art. His paintings in the early 1900s are considered to be among the first
completely abstract compositions in modern art history. Although the sources
from which artists drew their constructions of visible reality differed, their work
reflected the social and intellectual preoccupations in all areas of Western culture
at that time (Gooding 2000). Abstraction indicates a departure from reality, but
in art, Abstraction Theory describes how signs, lines, marks, and even inscriptions
on rocks, walls, stones, sculpture works, textiles are used to define reality. For
instance, one can enjoy the beauty of Chinese calligraphy without being able to
read it (Leys 2013).
The works of painters like Van Gogh, Cezanne, Paul Gauguin and Georges
Seurat developed what is known as ‘modern art’. These artists used multicoloured, expressive landscapes and figure paintings to portray visual reality.
In Africa, several artists in abstract art have emerged among whom are Ernest
Mancoba of South Africa; Cheri Samba of the Democratic Republic of Congo;
El Anatsui, Nnenna Okore and Peju Alatise of Nigeria; and Aboudia Abdoulaye
Diarrassouba of Côte d’Ivoire. Abstract art has also been used to express situations
in Africa such as wars, colonial rule and emotions or has been used as a means of
hearing the voice of marginalised populations.
As mentioned earlier, one of the major purposes of abstract art is its use of
visual language, shape, form, colour and line to create a composition which
may exist with a degree of independence from visual references in the world.
Abstract arts aids creativity and is used to express feelings and thoughts.
Nonetheless, Abstraction Theory in the field of art is somewhat complex to
understand and use to define reality. In actuality it is separated from reality.
Also, due to its abstract presentation, many interpretations could be given to
explain a reality or an event.
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
58
Divine Principle Theory
The Divine Principle Theory, also referred to as the Divine Command Theory, is
the fundamental theology of Sun Myung Moon (1920–2012), developed in 1935.
Moon insisted that the words he spoke did not come from theological research or
from books. Rather, he spoke of fundamental principles that he learned through
experience, as he overcame all manner of difficulties and communed directly with
God and the spirit world. He said that God is invisible. Ever since the creation of
the world, his invisible nature (eternal power and deity) has been clearly perceived
in the things that have been made.
In this theory, religion is often considered the most widely used system to
make ethical decisions and to conduct moral reasoning (Pollock 2007): it serves
a purpose in society. This resonates very well with the Durkheimian notion of
religion (i.e. a unified system of beliefs and practices relative to sacred things –
see Chapter 7). To rely upon the Divine Principle Theory, a person must believe
that there is a rational God providing direction towards an ethical outcome. It
is from God’s commands that actions are determined to be right or wrong and,
because of this, Divine Principle Theory provides an objective assessment of what
is ethical or moral.
As it relates to art, Divine Theory focuses on the fact that even though we
find artworks representing God, prophets and other figures in Christian houses
of worship and sometimes in synagogues, the Holy Torah, the Holy Bible, and
the Holy Qur’an forbid such images in houses of worship. Islam still eschews the
practice. The Divine Theory of art is about the fundamental righteousness of the
nexus between art and religion vis-a-vis the reciprocity between image-making
and meaning-making.
There is ambiguity in the way in which some scriptures are interpreted (Pollock
2007). According to Pollock, there are four assumptions of Divine Command
Theory:
1. there is a God,
2. God commands and forbids certain acts,
3. an action is right if God commands it, and
4. people ascertain what God commands or forbids.
What essentially makes religion such a powerful ethical system is that there is
a potentially eternal punishment in the afterlife (Pollock 2007). This notion of
eventual punishment reinforces in its followers the necessity to make ethical
decisions based on the commands of their God. It helps followers decipher the
truth in different situations and helps in preventing bad behaviour in a society.
The theory also helps in administering justice in the judicial systems of African
countries and elsewhere.
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
59
The theory is applied in most religious organisations whose belief is in one God.
While Divine Principle Theory is widely used in research across the world, there are
differences: the application of the theory may differ from religion to religion, and
it may differ even within each religion (Pollock 2007). In many African societies,
divorce, bisexualism, homesexuality and prostitution are prohibited while they
are acceptable in other places. The theory is not uniformly applied in all places.
Science has no evidence of the existence of God. Divine Principle Theory loses
its authority among a large portion of people who base their lives on science and
empiricism. Those who believe in God can interpret the commandments in their own
way, thereby establishing different interpretations to the solutions sought for ethical
dilemmas; consequently, there can be confusion about what exactly is God’s will.
General Theory of Patterns or Meta-Morphology Theory
This theory, which is based on a synthesis and continuation of the works of
Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Gregory Bateson, and Christopher Alexander, is
popular in some parts of the computer science community through the Software
Patterns movement. The theory introduces the concept of ‘process patterns’.
Contributions to the theory seek to establish some preliminaries for an arttheoretical foundation for the design of large edifices of process patterns – in
other words, an Art Theory of Event-Scape Architecture (Goppold 2000).
Bateson (1972) defines ‘Meta-Patterns’ as patterns of patterns. In technical
terms, this indicates the familiar computer science concept of recursion for the
pattern processing mechanism of the nervous system. Meta-Morphology is the
systematics of patterns that connect, or the Systematics of Meta-Patterns. Our
familiar world of objects, phenomena and qualia is, by current neurological
knowledge, based on the electrical activation and connectivity patterns of
our nervous system. Inside our brains, the neuronal ‘enchanted loom’ weaves
a complicated spatiotemporal meta-pattern structure from which derives
our familiar world impressions. In abstract terms, the neuronal apparatus
can be described as a Meta-Pattern Machine. The ‘Art Theory of Event-Scape
Architecture’ is also expected to bring practical results, since computer software
systems are large edifices of process patterns (Goppold 2000).
Pattern theories have a long history due to the protean character of patterns;
they are a most general, most abstract concept. They re-appear in many sciences.
There exists as yet no coherent way of organising and cross-referencing this
thoroughly trans-disciplinary topic. At the level of research, the earliest attempts
at constructing a General Pattern Theory date back to the ancient Pythagorean
thought system. It is overgrown with folklore, magic, and mythology; and
attempts at finding a unifying conceptual base for mathematics, music, and
astronomy can be classed as one of the earliest recorded attempts at a general
theory of patterns (Bateson 1972; Bamford 1994).
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
60
The concepts of General Neuronal Networks and Meta Pattern Machines
served as an abstract formulation of that substrate which underlies the foundation
of any higher-order symbolisation. The connection with ancient mythology
serves to recall an earlier cultural phase of humanity when symbolisation had
not yet reached its present form of standardisation (and ossification) that was
mainly an effect of alphabetisation. Computing led to a new appreciation of
the claim that ancient mythology contains not just old and discarded folklore,
but rather that it contains a sophisticated kind of computational time machine
device. More powerful practical graphic representation of process patterns would
greatly enhance the control of the ever-increasing complexity of software systems
(Goppold 2000).
The theory of computing machinery or pattern is difficult to understand or
represent. This is because it is difficult to separate (temporally) when one pattern
begins and when it ends. Then there is also the problem of storing the pattern.
Meta machine pattern is contrasted against the familiar computer science model
of the Turing Machine which uses an external storage tape and a clearly-defined
character set, which is not recognised in pattern templates (Goppold 2000).
Community
Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft
According to the New World Encyclopedia,
Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft are German words that mean ‘community’ and
‘society’ in English, respectively. Introduced in Classical Social Theory, they
are used to discuss the different kinds of social ties that exist in small, rural,
traditional societies versus large-scale, modern, industrial ones. Early German
sociologist Ferdinand Tönnies introduced the concepts in his 1887 book titled
Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft. Gemeinschaft comprises personal social ties and
in-person interactions that are defined by traditional social rules and result in
an overall cooperative social organisation. The values and beliefs common to
Gemeinschaft are organised around appreciation for personal ties and, because of
this, social interactions are personal in nature. Tönnies believed that these kinds of
interactions and social ties were driven by emotions and sentiments (Wesenwille)
by a sense of moral obligation to others and were common to rural, peasant,
small-scale and homogenous societies (New World Encyclopedia 2019:1).
Gesellschaft, on the other hand, is composed of impersonal and indirect social
ties and interactions that are not necessarily carried out face-to-face; they can
be carried out via telephone, in written form, through a chain of commands,
etc. The ties and interactions that characterise a Gesellschaft are guided by
formal values and beliefs that are directed by rationality and efficiency, as well
as by economic, political and self-interests. Gesellschaft, frequently translated as
‘society,’ refers to associations in which self-interest is the primary justification
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
61
for membership. This kind of social organisation is common to large-scale,
modern, industrial, and cosmopolitan societies that are structured around large
organisations of government and private enterprise, both of which often take
the form of bureaucracies. Organisations and the social order are organised by a
complex division of labour, roles and tasks.
Although the concepts are useful tools for seeing and understanding how
society works, they are rarely if ever observed exactly as they are defined, nor are
they mutually exclusive. ‘Instead, when you look at the social world around you,
you are likely to see both forms of social order present. You may find that you are
part of communities in which social ties and social interaction are guided by a
sense of traditional and moral responsibility’ (New World Encyclopedia 2019:1).
Brink (2001) observes that the ideas behind Tönnies’ theory are on one side of
a theoretical division. Brink notes the following weakness in the theory: common
ways of life do not necessarily imply common beliefs; small numbers of people
do not necessarily imply common ways of life; and continuous relations do not
necessarily imply emotional bonds. Furthermore, social relations characterised
by ‘natural will’ do not necessarily lead to all the outcomes Tönnies associated
with Gemeinschaft. The ‘natural will’ of a commune or collective, for example,
typically leads to considerably more social control (Kanter 1972) than the ‘natural
will’ of an ‘imaginary community’ where physical co-presence is missing and
the object of commitment is typically a vague and abstract symbol (Anderson
1983). Finally, Tönnies’ highly connotative approach invited confusion about the
defining coordinates of community (Brink 2001).
One advantage of Gemeinschaft over Gessellschaft is that its values are founded
upon Communism and Socialism. That is, the wealth, means of production and
resources are shared by the community. On the other hand, Gessellschaft, which
can be equated to Capitalism, promotes self-interest and self-reproduction.
Independent vs Dependent Communities Theory
The Independent vs Dependent Community Theory encompasses opposing
perspectives. The notion of Dependent Community was pioneered by plant
ecologist Frederic Clements (1874–1945). Although Clements was a biologist,
his theories also apply to human communities. The concept of Independent
Community was later propounded by Henry Gleason as a response to various
flaws observed in Clements’ theory.
The idea behind Clements’ Dependent Communities Theory is that a
community can survive by the teamwork of its members. In other words, a
community will continue to exist by depending on its members. The philosophy
behind the Independent Communities Theory is that communities do not
function in unions (associations); instead, a community is determined by the
individuals (Relyea & Ricklefs 2014).
62
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
According to Clements, dependent communities act as super organisms.
Based on this perspective, members of the community are like the organs of
an individual. Just as an organism survives by the teamwork of all the organs, a
community survives by the teamwork of its members. In other words, communities
exist with the co-dependency of each organism on others of its own species. For
example, people in a society grow and help one another in the development of
the economy. An instance is the coming together of people in different African
societies to attain independence and operate freely without external interference,
as well as for the overall economic development of the countries. Despite their
different political affiliations, the Zanu-PF and Movement for Democratic
Change (MDC) came together to remove President Robert Mugabe from power
in Zimbabwe in November of 2017.
Contrastingly, Independent Theory emphasises the importance of individual
existence, despite the fact that the people live in the same community. In other
words, people cannot be grouped into units. Instead, the community exists as a
continuum impacted by all individual members. One major advantage of this
theory is that it brings together different ideas; however, it can be dysfunctional,
since it does not call for unity and collective action (which Pan-Africanism
advocates). For example, in the last presidential election held in Nigeria in
February of 2019, there were more than 200 political parties contesting for the
same post. Another example is Zimbabwe’s harmonised elections held in July of
2018 which were contested by 23 political parties. One more example that shows
how dysfunctional the Independent strand can be comes from Zimbabwe in the
2000s when Mugabe postulated the following: ‘Keep your England and I will
keep my Zimbabwe’. This affected Zimbabwe because no country in this era of
globalisation can live on its own without relating to other countries.
Naturalistic Hierarchy Theory
This theory emerged from the General Systems Theory. Naturalistic Hierarchy
Theory was developed with perspectives from the disciplines of management
sciences, economics, psychology, biology, and mathematics. The theory is
an alternative and complement to other approaches to complexity, based on
the premise that ‘complexity frequently takes the form of hierarchy’ (Simon
1962:468). The originator of the theory was Herbert A. Simon (1916–2001).
The idea of the theory is that real- and artificial-world complex systems are
often hierarchically organised. In other words, they tend to be structured in
layers of levels (Simon 1962:52, 56). This fundamental property is called near
decomposability. As noted by Wu (2013), Naturalistic Hierarchy Theory is a
general approach that aims to simplify the description of and improve the clarity
of complexity by taking advantage of near decomposability.
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
63
Other influential contributors to the theory are Koestler (1967), Whyte et al.
(1969), and Pattee (1973). The theory was extended and expanded by many other
scholars such as Allen and Starr (1982), Eldredge (1985), O’Neill et al. (1986), Allen
and Hoekstra (1992), and Ahl and Allen (1996). Janak (2014) explored the emotional
dimensions of teachers’ work by using the theory. The study sought to understand
the emotional experiences of high school teachers in the type of work they do.
The theory also provides a unifying conceptual framework and an approach for
testing the implications of spatiotemporal aggregation of demographic data (Ahl
& Allen 1996). The theory can be helpful in dealing with the costs and benefits of
simplifying or partitioning complex ecological systems across space and time (Wu
2013). The theory also provides a set of tools for population ecologists to identify
a set of nested spatiotemporal scales to facilitate the understanding of population
dynamics, make observations and develop models of population dynamics at
a focal scale, and extrapolate or simplify demographic complexity across scales
using a hierarchy of nested models (Wu 2013).
A fundamental weakness of Naturalistic Hierarchy Theory is that it is not a
formal theory: i.e. it lacks clearly-defined terms, well-developed methodologies,
and clear forecasts. Another limitation of the theory noted by Eldredge (1985) is
that it fails to recognise the unique status of intentionality. The theory depends
on a related (‘objective’ or ‘mind-independent’) world of its own.
Culture
Cognitive Theory
Cognitive Theory proposes that people’s behaviours are reflections of their
thoughts. In other words, the theory postulates that people become what they
think. Interestingly, the theory also posits that people’s external behaviours
can be changed or controlled by changing their thought patterns, especially if
individuals become conscious of them. This is applicable when one recognises
destructive behaviours which, according to the cognitive theorists, are a result of
distorted patterns of thought.
Cognitive Theory has its origin in the thoughts of Jean Piaget (1896–1980)
who proposed that intelligence is not fixed, but is something that can be learnt.
Piaget believed that people are born with intelligence or cognition, upon which
all subsequent knowledge and learning are based. Cognitive development, then,
is a result of one’s interaction with one’s environment. Put differently, one’s
socialisation, which is a result of environmental factors, shapes one’s pattern of
thinking (see Bandura 2002).
The idea that we learn from the society in which we live gives rise to
Cognitive Theory, which adopts an agentic perspective to human development:
i.e. development is through adaptation and change. Agency, then, refers to one’s
ability to take conscious action capable of changing one’s life (Bandura 2002).
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
64
Cognitive Theory recognises three types of agency:
1. the individual,
2. the proxy, and
3. the collective.
Individuals can make conscious decisions to achieve what they desire. Proxy
agency implies that people can influence others to act on their behalf to achieve
their desired outcome. Collective agency means that individuals can come
together to influence their collective action to attain a common good, which is a
result of individuals’ collective efforts (Bandura 2002).
The theory postulates that although determinants of the different modes
of agency vary across cultures, all three modes are necessary to achieve desired
outcomes, irrespective of the cultural context. Thus, the theory believes that
variations in individuals’ psychosocial orientations exist; and, the fact that
intelligence is not fixed results in intracultural and intercultural differences and
the diverse and dynamic nature of society (Bandura 2002).
If people can achieve growth through adjusting their thoughts, that implies that
beliefs in personal or collective efficacy lead to proper functioning of individuals
or society. Collective efficacy is a result of the shared positive beliefs of individuals
to achieve required outcomes through collective action. As Cognitive Theory
posits, the thinking that one needs the efforts of others to succeed motivates
individuals to embrace collective action. As suggested by Albert Bandura (2002),
perceived collective efficacy enhances group functioning, just as perceived
personal efficacy enhances individual functioning. Cultural analysis then must
consider the existence of individual differences and the necessity of collective
action in its analysis.
Cognitive Theory is applicable to the concept of Ubuntu which, as mentioned
earlier, is the African belief in the necessity of collective action. As the maxim
goes, ‘I am because you are’, which means that even though we exist individually,
our individual existence and success depend on the collective existence and efforts
of others. The idea of Ubuntu has spurred people to embrace collective action.
It leads to social cohesion, especially in societies with diverse cultures. The idea
of Ubuntu is strongly emphasised in southern Africa, where it has great social
implications, especially in culturally and racially diverse countries such as South
Africa. In such countries, an emphasis on the philosophy of Ubuntu cannot be
underestimated in its potential to shape people’s beliefs and actions, thereby
promoting social cohesion. The ideas of Umunna bu ike (‘brotherhood is strength’
of the Igbo in West Africa) and Ọmọlúàbí (‘person of integrity’ of the Yoruba
in West Africa), which both suggest social solidarity and emphasise unity and
respecting the rights of others, are applicable too.
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
65
Cultural Relativity Theory
The theory of Cultural Relativity seeks to explain every event in the world from
a point of subjectivity. For the relativist, there is no objective reality but, rather,
truth or reality is dependent on the perception or worldview of the individual.
Cultural Relativity Theory implies that no individual culture is superior to
another; no cultural belief, practice or value is better than another. The goodness
of any moral value, knowledge, or meaning is relative to the particular framework
of an individual subject, culture, era, etc. Cultural Relativity Theory postulates a
position that neutralises people from criticising any ethical standard of any society.
Postmodernists therefore regard Cultural Relativity Theory as a postmodern way
of thinking simply because of its disdain of the superiority of one culture or moral
standard over another (Howson 2009).
Cultural Relativity Theory can be traced to Immanuel Kant’s idea of
cognitive relativism in Critique of Pure Reason (1788). Kant argued that people’s
experiences of the world are mediated through the ideas and knowledge they
hold about the world (Howson 2009). As a result, it becomes difficult to have
a universal experience, since no one’s experience is the same as another’s. This
idea of cognitive relativity refers to the intellectual viewpoint that there is no
absolute standard of judging what is real or true. Franz Boaz (1887) asserts that
unlike the natural sciences, the social sciences cannot point out objective reality,
but only customs and beliefs that differ from one society to another. Building
on the work of Ludwig Wittgenstein on attempting to distinguish categories
available to the social sciences to differentiate what is real and what is not, Peter
Winch (cited by Howson 2009), argues that the social sciences should avoid
using the methods of the natural sciences. Rather, they should rather seek to
identify ideas distinctive from Western cultures and strive to understand or
interpret how members of those cultures use those ideas. According to Winch,
adds Howson, some cultural concepts are inexpressible among the languages
of various other cultures. Hence, the idea of rationality seems not to apply
to cultural comparison (cited in Howson 2009). One of the applications of
Cultural Relativism is that proposed by Edward Said, who argues against the
ideas that inspired Western colonialism (Howson 2009).
Cultural Relativity Theory is applicable to the study of gender and its relations
to climate change adaptation. There is a tendency for practitioners to adopt a
dichotomous view of gender: men versus women. This view seems to categorise
all women of different classes, racial groups, ages, etc. as belonging to the same
category. But climate change affects people differently based on their access to
resources and positions in a society. So, an understanding that not all women have
equal access to resources or are in similar privileged positions in a society helps
in determining how an intervention should seek to understand the specific need
of the specific group of women for whom the intervention is to be implemented.
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
66
For instance, interventions done for a group of women in an urban area need to
be different from the interventions done for women in a rural area. These two
groups of people may experience similar climate disaster, but their vulnerability
to it is not the same, and their need for adaptation can also not be the same.
Despite belonging to the same gender group, their socioeconomic and locational
situations are different, which makes their experiences different.
Cultural Relativity Theory has the capacity to stimulate peaceful coexistence
in countries with diverse cultures. It acts as a deterrent to subjugation of one
group or culture over another, especially in countries with diverse cultures such
as South Africa and Nigeria. Nonetheless, the theory fails to recognise that while
some cultures promote good moral values, there are some cultural practices
that are clearly detrimental to human rights – female genital mutilation/female
circumcision/female genital cutting.
Cultural Selection Theory
Cultural Selection Theory holds that certain cultures (which include cultural
elements such as ideologies, norms, symbols, rituals, morals, and traditions) have
the tendency to replicate themselves from one stage or one generation to another
and can undergo change. Second, the theory posits that some cultures have the
tendency to withstand pressures and even spread at the expense of others which
then disappear. Cultures that have the capacity to stand the test of time can
even absorb other cultures into themselves. These attributes of Cultural Selection
Theory are analogous to Darwin’s theory of natural selection (Fog 1999).
In addition, the theory of Cultural Selection implies that some cultures
possessing certain features or traits that are resilient or good or attractive have the
tendency to spread and reproduce, or evolve more than others that may not have
those desired qualities. It is also possible that these beneficial cultural features
could evolve. Fog (1999) says that it is possible that not all cultures that have
the capacity to evolve are beneficial to everyone. He believes humans have the
tendency to rationalise unconscious motives or justify their bad behaviours so
that they appear as planned and intended, even if they were not. What then
influences the evolution of culture could be the unconscious motives of the
participants of the culture, the unintended consequences of rational choices, the
unintended consequences of the sum of the actions of the individual members of
the culture, and other such factors (Fog 1999).
Cultural Selection Theory can also be attributed to the views of the British
Economist Walter Bagot, who expressed his view of why an organisation survives
as follows:
‘But when once polities were begun, there is no difficulty in explaining why they
lasted. Whatever may be said against the principle of “natural selection” in other
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
67
departments, there is no doubt of its predominance in early human history. The
strongest killed out the weakest, as they could’ (Bagot, as quoted by Fog 1999:12).
The anthropologist Edward Taylor said: ‘History within its proper field, and
ethnography over a wider range, combine to show that the institutions which can
best hold their own in the world gradually supersede the less fit ones, and that this
incessant conflict determines the general resultant course of culture’ (quoted by
Fog 1999:12). Taylor also said that ‘the more homely and useful the art, and the
less difficult the conditions for its exercise, the less likely it is to disappear from
the world, unless when superseded by some better device’ (Fog 1999:13).
Cultural Selection Theory can be applied in several ways in society today. For
instance, the dominance of the English language in the international business
arena portrays the power that the language has over other languages. Despite the
fact that other languages like French are widely spoken, English keeps spreading
its global dominance as the medium of instruction.
Cultural Selection Theory’s strength lies in its ability to explain social inequality
and why some cultures disappear at some point, especially when such cultures are
absorbed by other cultures. One weakness of the theory is that, as Winsmatt
(quoted by Crozier) says, there seem to be no ‘standard memetic models’ for
analyzing cultural change that will make its comparison to Natural Selection
Theory’s gametes, genomes, and genes valid (Crozier 2008: 464).
Ecological Theory
Ecological Theory was propounded by Urie Bronfenbrenner (1979). According
to him, in order to comprehend human development, it is important to consider
the entire ecological system in which growth occurs. The ecological system
encompasses an evolving body of theory and research concerned with the
processes and conditions that govern the lifelong course of human development
in the actual environments in which human beings live (Bronfenbrenner 1979).
The theory has three main assumptions:
1. the individual is an active player and applies substantial force on his or her
own environment,
2. the environment can force an individual to adapt to its restrictions and
conditions, and
3. the environment is perceived to comprise of dissimilar size entities that are
positioned one inside another (Bronfenbrenner 1979).
The theory explains the environment as a system that is composed of five socially
organised subsystems that help to support and guide human growth. The five
subsystems are:
1. microsystem,
2. mesosystem,
3. exosystem,
4. macrosystem, and
5. chronosystem.
68
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The microsystem refers to the relationship between a developing person and the
immediate environment. The theory explains that a microsystem is a pattern of
activities, social roles, and interpersonal relations experienced by the developing
individual in a given face-to-face setting. The mesosystem consists of the linkages
and processes taking place between two or among more settings containing the
developing person. An example is the relationship between home and school,
neighbourhood, peer-group, or workplace (Bronfenbrenner 1979). The exosystem
consists of the connections and developments taking place between two or more
settings, at least one of which does not comprise the developing person, but in
which events occur that indirectly influence the development of the individual
(Bronfenbrenner 1979). The macrosystem includes the principal pattern of
micro, meso, and exosystem characteristic of a given culture or subculture, with
particular reference to the belief systems, bodies of knowledge, material resources,
customs, lifestyles, opportunities, structures, hazards, and life course options that
are embedded in each of these broader systems (Bronfenbrenner 1979). The
chronosystem encompasses modifications over time in the characteristics and the
environment in which the individual lives. Examples include changes over the
life course in family structure, socioeconomic status, employment and place of
residence (Bronfenbrenner 1979).
One notable asset of the Ecological Theory is that it helps a researcher to
understand how different actors and factors in the environment influence a
person’s experiences. It highlights the unique experiences of an individual that
shape that person’s development. It acknowledges agency and pays attention to
details, rather than wholesale generalisations that do not work for many. Research
on criminal justice systems in Africa could benefit from the theory. Ecological
Theory can be useful in chronicling the social ecology of a person and identifying
defective subsystems that must be corrected in order to address crime and proper
rehabilitation interventions for criminals. Nonetheless, an observable flaw is that
the theory seems too complex to apply because an extensive scope is required to
build an accurate developmental account of a person. Since the theory does not
provide specific mechanisms for doing this, it would be practically challenging to
decide what aspects of a person’s life experience should be considered or ignored
to make a useful assessment.
High and Low Context Theory
High and Low Context Theory describes the broad cultural differences among
cultures and societies. The theory classifies cultures and societies into two broad
categories: High Context Culture and Low Context Culture. The classification
is mainly based on the perceived distinctive manner in which every culture
communicates. The theory postulates that one’s manner of communication, in
a broader perspective, is mainly determined by one’s cultural context, which at
most times remains largely embedded in a person’s day-to-day life (Ryan 2011).
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
69
The theory was first described by Edward Hall (1914–2009) in 1976. When
he was with the United States Army during World War II, Hall observed
that there were significant differences in the way members of the Army
communicated. He observed that people from a particular culture tended to
have similar communication patterns with the members of their group which,
in turn, were quite different from those by members of other cultures who
also tended to have similar manners of passing messages across. Differences
in communication patterns tended to cause some differences among members
of a group. Hall then carried out research to explain the reason for the
difficulties caused by intercultural communication and concluded that the
differences among members of a group were a result of how each member
perceived reality, which was responsible for miscommunication of the most
fundamental kind. Hall then classified cultures, on a country level, into two
broad categories:
1. High Context Cultures and
2. Low Context Cultures.
Each has its own distinctive way of communication. Countries such as the
United States, Switzerland, Germany, and Sweden fall under Low Context
Culture; while African and Middle Eastern states fall under the High Context
Culture (Ryan 2011).
Individuals from a High Context Culture are collectivistic, pass messages
across implicitly, value relationships over material achievements, have loyalty
and attachment to cultural bonds, are non-confrontational and reserved, take
responsibility for their actions and failures and are able to easily multitask, etc. On the
other hand, individuals from a Low Context Culture are individualistic in nature,
pass messages across explicitly, value achievements and authority over interpersonal
bonds, are not very culturally attached, are confrontational, are assertive, blame
others for their failures, value careful and strategic planning and scheduling,
and finish one task before embarking on another. One thing to note about the
High Context-Low Context classification is that it is not totally a dichotomous
categorisation; rather, the differences exist in a continuum (Ryan 2011).
One advantage of the High Context and Low Context Theory is its ability
to offer a succinct analysis of the reasons behind the differences that exist
among people from different cultural and language backgrounds. The theory
is also able to offer an explanatory model that can be applied in the analysis of
conflict among groups of different language backgrounds. According to Ryan
‘many other cross-cultural misunderstandings are unrecognised ... Intercultural
communication theories are a good starting point to frame how these kinds of
cross-cultural conflicts arise and how to highlight the underlying norms that
exist as cultural background knowledge or schema’ (2011:231). However, the
theory seems to put human beings in a box in that it fails to recognise their
70
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
dynamic nature as changing beings. In addition, the theory seems to account
only for the differences in worldviews that exist among groups of individuals
from similar language backgrounds and not among the individuals in a
group themselves.
Linguistic Relativity Theory
Linguistic Relativity Theory links language to culture. The main postulate of the
theory is that the language that individuals speak determines their perception of
the world. In other words, one’s reality is shaped by one’s language. The theory can
be presented syllogistically. First, it assumes that languages can differ distinctively
in their semantics and syntactic constructions (Wolf & Holmes 2011). Second, it
holds that the semantics of a language can significantly shape the way its speakers
view the world and, in extreme cases, completely shapes their thoughts. This is
referred to as linguistic determinism (Wolf & Holmes 2011). Third and finally,
the theory posits that because one’s thought pattern is shaped by one’s language,
speakers of different languages must think or view the world differently (Wolf &
Holmes 2011).
The early pioneers of linguistic relativism include Plato and Immanuel
Kant. According to Plato, ‘the soul, when thinking, appears to me to be just
talking’ (quoted by Wolf & Holmes 2011:2). For Kant, ‘thinking is speaking to
ourselves’ (quoted by Wolf & Holmes 2011:2). Max Muller asserts that ‘language
is identical with thought’ (quoted by Wolf & Holmes 2011:2). The German
philosophers Johann Gottfried Herder and Friedrich Wilhelm Christian Karl
Ferdinand von Humboldt added their perspectives to the theory. Humboldt, for
instance, looked at the role of language in forming ideas. He believed that if
language has the capacity to form ideas, it must also have the capacity to shape
people’s attitudes. Hence, people with different languages must possess distinctive
worldviews. Later, the version of linguistic relativism as postulated by the early
philosophers was employed to associate thinking to expressions, both verbal and
non-verbal. A later version of linguistic relativism links language to culture. And,
a much later variant by Edward Sapir claimed that the culture of a people finds
some reflection in the language they use (Elmes 2013:12).
Although Sapir did not doubt the existence of an objective world independent
of language, he did believe that the real world is inevitably unconsciously
influenced by the language patterns of a group. Benjamin Lee-Whorf extended
Sapir’s view to a more radical extent by stating that the relationship between
language and culture is a deterministic one. From the combination of the two
scholars’ ideas, we have the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis (see Chapter 5), which claims
that we see and hear and otherwise experience very largely as we do because the
language habits of our community predispose certain choices of interpretation
(Hussein 2012:2).
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
71
Linguistic Relativity Theory is therefore a call for a deeper reflection on
how different writers writing about the same phenomenon tend to write from
different perspectives. The theory also shows how different countries express a
certain phenomenon with so much obvious linguistic difference. For example, a
closer look at the national anthems of most African countries demonstrates the
linguistic tokens that cut across many of them: words like ‘God’, ‘blessed’, ‘peace’,
‘together’, and other similar words express a seemingly passive, submissive, and
theocentric approach to reality. On the other hand, an analysis of the words in
national anthems of many Western countries such as France and the United States
reveals a revolutionary, aggressive and authoritative undertone. The terms used in
these anthems show their countries’ readiness to exert influence and protect their
territories, by whatever means possible, from any influence. The differences in
the use of language in this way could arise from the differences in their historical
experiences, which tend to shape the way people act, react, or view the world.
A major strength of Linguistic Relativity Theory is its ability to account for the
reasons individuals from the same language background are more prone to agree
with the opinions of others from the same language background. It also helps to
explain why people from the same language background tend to come together on
occasions or at events that have individuals from diverse language backgrounds.
Nonetheless, the theory fails to account for the existence of differing worldviews
of individuals from the same language background.
Social Learning Theory
Social Learning Theory was proposed by Albert Bandura in 1977 and is often
described as the ‘bridge’ between Traditional Learning Theory (i.e. behaviourism)
and the cognitive approach. This is because Social Learning Theory focuses on
how mental (cognitive) factors are involved in learning. The theory emphasises
the importance of observing and modelling the behaviours, attitudes, and
emotional reactions of others. According to Bandura (1977), learning would be
exceedingly laborious, not to mention hazardous, if people had to rely solely on
the effects of their own actions to inform them what to do. Because of this, most
human behaviour is learned observationally through modelling (Bandura 1997).
This means that people observe others about how an idea is formed or how new
behaviours are performed, which serves as code for later personal action. Social
Learning Theory assumes therefore that personality is learned. It is premised on
a stimulus-response orientation of behaviourism and extends it by changing its
focus to the aspect of learning being influenced by social interaction. Earlier
renderings of Social Learning Theory focused on society’s attempts to teach
children to behave like adults in the society. Bandura, having introduced the
important role of modelling in learning, believed that behaviour can be acquired
by simply watching a model (Bandura 1986).
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
72
Consequently, according to Bandura, Social Learning Theory has a link
with Constructivism since it holds the view that people are active agents in
their environments. Some important constructs of social learning include
the following:
1. ‘vicarious reinforcement: the punishment or reinforcement of the model’s
behaviour has the same effect on observers’;
2. ‘abstract modelling: abstracting a general rule from observing specific
behaviours’; and
3. ‘reciprocal determinism: the entire learning context includes biological and
psychological characteristics of the person; the person’s behaviour, and the
environment’ (Bandura 1986:12).
These three components influence each other and are highly interdependent.
The principle of observational learning asserts that the highest level of
observational learning is achieved by first organising and rehearsing the modelled
behaviour symbolically and then enacting it overtly. The coding of modelled
behaviour into words, labels or images leads to better retention than simply
observing it (Bandura 1973). Furthermore, the principle holds that individuals
are more likely to adopt a modelled behaviour if it results in outcomes they value.
Similarly, individuals are more likely to adopt a modelled behaviour if the model
is similar to the observer, has an admired status, and the behaviour has functional
value (Bandura 1973).
Indeed, Social Learning Theory is applicable in working with people from all
backgrounds, especially children with intellectual disabilities. For example, in
special schools, social learning can be applied to inculcate social and behavioural
skills. In the same manner, it can be applied to modify behaviours such as anger,
disrespect, and bad social interaction skills. One of the primary strengths of this
theory is its flexibility in explaining differences in a child’s behaviour or learning.
The theory provides a more complete explanation of human learning than the
behaviourist approach by recognising the role of meditational processes. Many of
Bandura’s ideas were developed by observing children’s behaviours in laboratory
settings. A major weakness of the theory is the lack of emphasis on biological
processes in mediating and constraining behaviour.
References
Ahl, Valerie and Allen, Timothy F.H., 1996, Hierarchy Theory: A Vision, Vocabulary, and
Epistemology, New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Alexander, Christopher, 1979, The Timeless Way of Building, New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Allen, Timothy F.H. and Starr, Thomas B, 1982, Hierarchy: Perspectives for Ecological
Complexity, Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Allen, Timothy F.H. and Hoekstra, Thomas W., 1992, Toward a Unified Ecology, New
York, NY: Columbia: University Press.
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
73
Anderson, Benedict, 1983, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origins and Spread of
Nationalism, London, UK: New Left Books.
Arnheim, Rudolf, 1969, Visual Thinking, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Bacon, Francis, 1920, Noyum Organum, Foligno, Italy: Sumptibus Joannis Ravesteiny,
Amsteledami.
Bamford, Christopher, 1994, Homage to Pythagoras, Northumberland, UK: Lindisfarne
Press.
Barnacle, Robyn, 2001, ‘Phenomenology and Wonder’, in R. Barnacle, ed., Phenomenology,
Melbourne, Australia: Royal Melbourne Institute of Technology University Press.
Bandura, Albert, 1973, Aggression: A Social Learning Analysis, Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bandura, Albert, 1977, Social Learning Theory, New York, NY: General Learning Press.
Bandura, Albert, 1986, Social Foundations of Thought and Action, Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bandura, Albert, 1997, Self-efficacy: The Exercise of Control, New York, NY: W.H. Freeman.
Bandura, Albert, 2002, ‘Social Cognitive Theory in Cultural Context’, Applied Psychology
and International Review, Vol. 51, No. 2, pp. 260–290.
Bateson, Gregory, 1972, Steps to Ecology of Mind, Toronto, Canada: Chandler Publishing
Company.
Boaz, Franz, 1887, ‘The Principle of Ethnological Classification’, in G.W. Stocking,
Jr., ed., 1997, The Reader, The Shaping of American Anthropology, Chicago, IL:
The Chicago University Press.
Brink, Steven, 2001, ‘Gemeinschaft Revisited: A Critique and Reconstruction of the
Community Concept’, Sociological Theory, Vol. 19, pp. 1–23.
Bronfenbrenner, Urie, 1979, ‘Ecological Models of Human Development’, International
Encyclopedia of Education, 2nd edition, Oxford, UK: Elsevier.
Connelly, L.M., 2010, ‘What is Phenomenology?’, MEDSURG Nursing, Vol. 19, No. 2,
pp. 127–128.
Crozier, G.K.D., 2008, ‘Reconsidering Cultural Selection’, The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, Vol. 59, No. 3, pp. 455–479.
Danver, Steven, L., 2015, Native Peoples of the World: An Encyclopedia of Groups, Cultures
and Contemporary Issues, Vols. 1–3, London, UK: Routledge.
Eldredge, Niles, 1985, Unfinished Synthesis: Biological Hierarchies and Modern Evolutionary
Thought, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Elmes, David, 2013, ‘The Relationship between Language and Culture’, National Institute
of Fitness and Sports in Kanoya Exchange and Language Education Centre. (http://
www.lib.nifs-k.ac.jp/nii/46-11.pdf ). 16 September 2021.
Fog, Agner, 1999, Cultural Selection, Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany: Springer.
Gooding, M., 2000, Abstract Art, London, UK: Tate Publishing.
Goppold, Andreas, 2000, ‘Time, Anticipation, and Pattern Processors’, International
Journal of Computing Anticipatory Systems, CHAOS ASBL, Liège, Vol. 7,
pp. 99–120.
Heidegger, M., 2002, The Essence of Truth, translated from the German by T. Sadler, New
York, NY: Continuum.
74
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Howson, Alexandra, 2009, ‘Cultural Relativism’, Academic Starters. (https://
www.ebscohost.com/uploads/imported/thisTopic-dbTopic-1247.pdf ).
16 September 2021.
Hussein, Basel, 2012, ‘The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis Today’, Theory and Practice in
Language Studies, Vol. 2, No. 3. pp. 642–646.
Husserl, Edmund, 1931, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, translated by
D. Carr, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Husserl, Edmund, 1975, The Paris Lectures, translated P. Koesterbaum, The Hague, The
Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
Janak, Raksha, 2014, ‘An Exploration of the Emotional Dimensions of Teachers’
Work’. (https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/An-exploration-of-the-emotionaldimensions-of-work.-Janak/d008b8b9771fc29bcdf92f8f2fad18bb46844ae9).
16 September 2021.
Jansen, Jonathan D. and Christie, Pam, eds., 1999, Changing Curriculum: Studies on
Outcomes-Based Education in South Africa, Kenwyn, South Africa: Juta.
Kanter, Rosabeth M., 1972, Commitment and Community, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Koestler, Arthur M., 1967, The Ghost in the Machine, New York, NY: Random House.
Langdridge, Darren, 2007, Phenomenological Psychology: Theory, Research and Method,
Harlow, UK: Pearson Education Limited.
Laverty, Susann M., 2003, ‘Hermeneutic Phenomenology and Phenomenology:
A Comparison of Historical and Methodological Considerations’, International
Journal of Qualitative Methods, Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 21–35.
Leys, Simon, 2013, The Hall of Uselessness: Collected Essays, New York, NY: New York
Review Books.
MacLeod, Robert, 1947, ‘The Phenomenological Approach to Social Psychology’,
Psychological Review, Vol. 54, pp. 193–210.
Milton, Stricker, 2017, Design through Abstraction: The Wright Source to Art and
Architecture, Scotts Valley, CA: CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform.
New World Encyclopedia, 2019, ‘Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft’. (https://
www.newworldencyclopedia.org/entry/Gemeinschaft_and_Gesellschaft).
15 September 2021.
Norvig, Peter, 1983, ‘Frame Activated Inferences in a Story Understanding Programme’,
Proceedings of the English International Joint Conferences on Artificial Intelligence.
(https://norvig.com/ijcai83.html). 15 September 2021.
O’Neill, Robert V.; Deangelis, Donald Lee; Waide, J. B. and Allen, Timothy F.H., 1986,
A Hierarchical Concept of Ecosystems, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Pashmeena, Vikramjit G., 2017, ‘Use of Abstraction in Architectural Design Process’,
International Journal of Engineering Research and Technology, Vol. 10, No. 1,
pp. 118 –122.
Pattee, E.E., ed., 1973, Hierarchy Theory: The Challenge of Complex Systems, New York,
NY: George Braziller.
Pollock, Joycelyn, 2007, Ethical Dilemmas and Decisions in Criminal Justice, Belmont,
CA: Wadsworth Cengage Learning.
Doctoral Scholars: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture
75
Relyea, Rick and Ricklefs, Robert, 2014, Ecology: The Economy of Nature, 7th edition, New
York, NY: W.H. Freeman.
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1998, ‘Phenomenological Movement:
4.
Existential
Phenomenology’.
(https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/
overview/phenomenological-movement/v-1/sections/existential-phenomenology).
16 September 2021.
Ryan, Stephen, 2011, ‘Highlighting the Merits and Demerits of High and Low Context
Oriented Communication Cultures in Business: Fukushima Nuclear Accident and
Japan’s Communication with the International Community’, Proceedings of the
International Conference on Humanities, Society and Culture, Vol. 20, pp. 231–235.
Simon, Herbert A., 1962, ‘The Architecture of Complexity’, Proceedings of the American
Philosophical Society, Vol. 106, pp. 467–482.
Smith, Jonathan A.; Flowers, Paul and Larkin, Michael, 2009, Interpretative
Phenomenological Analysis: Theory, Method and Research, London, UK:
Sage Publications.
Spinelli, Ernesto, 2005, The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological
Psychology, London, UK: Sage Publications.
Tönnies, Ferdinand, 1957, Community and Society: Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft,
translated and edited by Charles P. Loomis, Lansing, MI: Michigan State
University Press.
Whyte, Lancelot Law; Wilson, Albert G. and Wilson, D., eds, 1969, Hierarchical
Structures, New York, NY: American Elsevier Publishing Company.
Wilensky, Robert, 1983, Planning and Understanding: A Computational Approach to
Human Reasoning, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Wolf, Phillip and Holmes, Kevin J., 2011, ‘Linguistic Relativity’, Wiley Interdisciplinary
Reviews: Cognitive Science, Vol. 2, pp. 253–265.
Wu, Jianguo, 2013, ‘Hierarchy Theory: An Overview’, in R. Rozzi, J. Callicott, J., S.T.A
Pickett, Clare Palmer and J.J. Armesto, Linking Ecology and Ethics for a Changing
World: Values, Philosophy, and Action, Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany: Springer.
Zaczek, Iain, 2013, The Illustrated Story of Art, London, UK: Dorling Kindersley
Publishing.
3
Decision-making, Economics,
and Education – Learning/Teaching
Doctoral Scholars
This chapter entails brief elucidations of three decision-making theories, five
economic theories, and eleven education (learning/teaching) theories. The
theories on decision-making concern the action or process of choosing among
alternative options, especially important ones. Those on economics deal with
the production, consumption, and transfer of wealth. And those on education –
learning/teaching – discuss the acquisition and instruction of knowledge or skills
through experience, study, or by being taught.
Decision-Making
Incrementalism/Muddling-Through Theory
Incrementalism or Muddling-Through Theory is a decision-making approach
which suggests that policy decisions should be made in a progressive manner.
Admitting that changes cannot be wholesale, Incrementalism posits that policy
decisions must be developed and implemented to respond gradually to needs.
It is also termed Muddling-Through Theory because it assumes less control
over the external environment in decision-making (Bailey & O’Connor
1975). According to Incrementalism, there should be a step-by-step, pieceby-piece implementation of decisions. Since change cannot be a one-time
instant occurrence, Incrementalism requires that decisions on a particular issue
should made in bits. This suggests that policies meant to address a particular
phenomenon of concern must be broken down into units and addressed one
after the other (Bailey & O’Connor 1975).
78
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
One principle on which Incrementalism operates is that there are many
competing interests and competing needs in a context of scarce societal or
institutional resources (Friedman 1975). These competing interests and needs
culminate into competing policy formulations that confront insufficient
resources for implementation. Against this backdrop, policies must be formulated
and implemented in smaller and manageable units. This suggests that a policy
consideration should not be fully addressed immediately. Instead, resources should
be allocated to address parts of it in a gradual but steady manner. Furthermore,
parts of many competing policy needs should be given partial consideration
across a period until the entire policy needs are fully addressed (Friedman 1975).
A major proponent of Incremental Theory is Charles E. Lindblom (1917–
2018). In the 1950s, Lindblom’s theory was a response to the growing needs
of the time to explain policy-making decisions. Lindblom (1959) opined that
in order to make a rational decision that maximises value, there should be
significant consideration of past decisions. For Lindblom, rational decisionmaking aimed at fully solving a problem is unattainable and idealistic
(Friedman 1975). Consequently, policy makers must focus on ameliorating
the presenting problems. Incremental Theory pushes for policies that focus on
the management of problems. Based on Lindblom’s theories, variations such as
logical incrementalism and disjointed incrementalism have emerged to provide
various perspectives for progressive decision-making (Friedman 1975).
Having been tested across a number of policy fronts such as social justice and
law, Incrementalism has been found to have its strengths and weaknesses. The
incremental model gains its advantage in its critique of Rational Choice Theory.
Since it is an impossible reality for actors to have all the needed information
required to make a rational choice, relying on the Rational Choice Theory in
decision-making can lead to faulty policy decisions. The incremental model
provides a safer option, with decision-making focussing on selecting alternatives
that are similar or marginally different from previous policies or decisions. It
also ensures fairness in the distribution of resources, thereby maintaining
peace and satisfaction among people even when they have competing interests
(Friedman 1975).
Incremental Theory is largely irrelevant in emergency or time-bound
situations. For example, in the case of maternal deaths or outbreaks of Ebola,
approaching a policy from an incremental orientation will make no valuable
impact on the situation at hand. Another critique of Incrementalism comes from
a legal perspective, where the theory is examined in the light of entrenchment,
which happens when documents like constitutions or charters entrench certain
policies and prevent change (Gilbert 2017). It is argued that when entrenchment
deepens, change that is gradual and non-holistic cannot attain the purpose of
helping end a bad situation (Gilbert 2017). Once a law is entrenched, relying
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
79
on gradual policy processes such as repeal to bring about a change is almost
impossible. The incremental approach to policy changes is weak in such instances.
The technicality of legal matters in a complex human institution reveals that
addressing legislative matters using incremental models can be detrimental
(Gilbert 2017) because gradual amendments to faulty laws impede the need to
completely repeal or replace them.
Mixed-Scanning Theory
Mixed-Scanning Theory combines useful aspects of rational decisions and
incremental thinking in decision-making and policy consideration. The theory
refers to the search, the gathering, and the evaluation of all information for
decision-making (Etzioni 1986). Mixed-Scanning Theory combines principles
of economics and the progressive idea of making choices and meeting needs.
Goldberg (1975) says this approach combines higher order and lower order
decision-making processes. The theory proposes that decisions must be made
incrementally, paying attention to fundamental rational decisions. In any major
policy issues, Mixed-Scanning holds that the rational examination and assessment
of all possible options in the cost and benefits of a situation should be fairly done
while distributing resources among identifiable interests (Etzioni 1986).
The theory touts itself as a third approach to Rational Choice Theory (see
the next section) and Incrementalism. It is considered as a realistic approach to
decision-making. It does not run away from the two extreme theories. Rather, it
blends elements of both theories in policy decisions. The viability of the MixedScanning Theory is in fact embedded in its methodology. Etzioni asserts that ‘the
decision on how the investment of assets and time are to be allocated among the
levels of scanning is, in fact, part of the strategy’ (1967:389). Although the theory
takes into consideration the allocation of resources and time, it also pays attention
to other factors such as the total amount of time, availability of resources and
other interests.
Amitai Etzioni, born in 1929, is one of the scholars who have contributed
significantly to the Mixed-Scanning Theory. Etzioni supports moral social and
political societies and communitarian ideas. He established the Communitarian
Network for this reason. As someone who believes in having a careful balance
between individual rights and social responsibilities, autonomy and order, his
ideals in the Mixed-Scanning Theory offer a striking balance between personal
satisfaction and collective welfare; rationality and Incrementalism.
The theory seeks to ensure that in any decision-making quest, the best
elements of rational choice thinking and Incrementalism are to be employed in
order to arrive at a final conclusion. Mixed-Scanning Theory acquires its strength
from its eclectic nature (Etzioni 1967).
80
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The complexity of some issues on the African continent cannot be handled
using a single approach. In instances where one is presented with making policy
decisions on both cultural and emergency economic situations, such as to invest
in strengthening a community culture or in refurbishing a public toilet, the best
approach would be the Mixed-Scanning Theory which can pay attention to both
culture and economics.
Nonetheless, the combination of the principles of two conflicting theories
makes decision-making under Mixed-Scanning complex. A policy decision is not
a mere intellectual exercise; it is a complex practical venture that requires the
simplification of an already complex issue to make it implementable. Indeed,
relying on the Mixed-Scanning approach could make decision-making unrealistic
and complicated. For example, how can a decision maker know how to practically
scan through the economic benefits and costs of all issues, select some of them,
and finally allocate resources to address them at the same time?
Rational Choice Theory
Rational Choice Theory (also referred to as Rational Action Theory or simply
Choice Theory) is premised on the assumption that a phenomenon must be
explained by taking into consideration its possible outcomes (Boudon 2003). Its
orientation towards examining consequences of actions prior to decision-making
makes the Rational Choice Theory one of the best decision-making theories. The
theory assumes that an actor chooses an alternative that they believe brings about
a social outcome that optimises their preference under subjectively conceived
constraints (Sato 2013). The theory maps outcomes to numerical values for the
purpose of computation before making a policy decision based on the highest
outcome or expected outcome based on cost effectiveness, average benefit, or
benefit ratio (Sato 2013).
Utilitarianism, developed by Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and John Stuart
Mill (1806–1873), served as the foundation for the development of the Rational
Choice Theory. These philosophers, having coined the term ‘rational decision’,
then developed ideas that helped build the theory. Their main idea was that
policy decisions should be rational and must be aimed that attaining maximum
utility. Rational Choice Theory can be crucial in guiding policy decisions in
societies where very scarce resources are expected to yield maximum utility
(Sato 2013). For example, a decision to construct factories in every district in
Ghana under the government’s ‘one district one factory’ flagship programme
versus constructing a national cathedral can be arrived at by examining all the
cost components, and the short- and long-term benefits of both projects. A
good policy decision can be arrived at after comparing the outcomes using the
principles of Rational Choice Theory.
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
81
Rational Choice Theory lived up to expectations by providing incontrovertible
explanations of happenings of the end of the Cold War and the disappearance
of the Soviet Union (Mortazavi 2004). As a powerful theory, it provides an
approach for assessing all real or perceived benefits and consequences of a
phenomenon before proceeding with implementation. When confronted
with competing interests, the theory helps policy-makers to decide which of
the options should benefit from the use of scarce resources in a way that will
bring the ultimate benefit. For example, the theory can be used to guide the
government of Kenya to decide whether to invest KSH 100 million in the
purchase of motor bicycles for the transport system or purchase buses or taxis,
all of which are aimed at consolidating public transportation in the capital.
The theory will provide policy makers with independent tools to make rational
decisions usually using statistical methods.
Rational Choice Theory finds it difficult to provide rational justifications
in every situation. Some sociologists have argued that the theory has failed
significantly in explaining decisions that are founded on values and nontrivial
and nonconsequential beliefs (e.g. Boudon 2003). Beliefs and values do not lend
themselves rationally to material costs and benefits. Hence, it would be unwise
to use Rational Choice Theory as a model to arrive at a decision on issues that
compete purely based on values and beliefs that are non-material in nature.
Acknowledging that social stabilisation is broader than political stabilisation
(Mortazavi 2004), harmony or social equilibrium is attained when attention is also
given to cultural value systems rather than just the economic decisions suggested
by Rational Choice Theory. A critique of the theory is that it is reductionist and
skewed to the subset of economic consideration, hence missing very important
parameters of social stability.
Economics
Anarchist Theory
Anarchist Theory is geared toward investigating the state of disorder originating
from the absence or non-recognition of authority and controlling systems. Such
characteristics are associated with the absolute freedom of individuals. Harmony
in such a society is then obtained not by submission to law or by compliance to
authority but by free treaties on production and consumption established among
the various groups, regions and professions. The underlying principle is that the
state is a capitalist institution based on force. Since the state sides with capitalists,
it is an unnecessary evil.
Anarchist Theory hold that the state should be completely eradicated and
replaced by voluntary institutions. These voluntary institutions would then
perform their respective functions with cooperation (Woodcock 2010). This means
82
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
that there would be social control over land and the factors of production. The
elimination of the state would also mean the abolition of all political limitations.
Anarchists also oppose religion and private property. They contend that there is
no fear of anarchy even after the abolition of the state as they believe that the
motive for all crimes is the unfair division of property. Crime will be eliminated
as cooperation and education spread to everyone. Such claims are underpinned
by a belief in the principles of equality, liberty and fraternity (Dolgoff 1974).
Anarchist Theory can be broken down into two variants: anarchists like
Tolstoy were in favour of nonviolent means to achieve their aims, while anarchists
like Kropotkin were ready to adopt violent means for the achievement of
their aims (Dolgoff 1974). These can be divided into more branches: Political
Anarchism, Religious Anarchism, Theoretical Anarchism, Applied Anarchism,
Anarchism in Political Philosophy, Anarchism in the History of Political
Philosophy, Contingent, Consequentialist, Posterior Anarchism, Individualism,
Libertarianism, Socialist Anarchism, Nonviolence, Violence, Disobedience,
Revolution, Utopian Communities, and Non-Revolutionary Anarchism, among
others (Dolgoff 1974).
Dolgoff (1974) says French socialist Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809–1865)
was one of the first philosophers to propound this theory and the first to call
himself an anarchist. His book What is Property? contained the well-known
saying: ‘Property is theft’. He criticised the state because it is synonymous with
private property. Proudhon believed that governments of many and by many
were a very strong form of oppression. He argued that the highest perfection of
society is found in the union of order and anarchy. American naturalist Henry
David Thoreau (1817–1862) postulated that the individual is wise. Therefore, it
is right to leave him to be free (Dolgoff 1974).
A major limitation of Anarchist Theory is that although it assumes that
government is evil and should be eradicated, many modern governments are
welfare institutions providing public goods and redistributing wealth to address
high inequality levels. The claim by anarchists that in a stateless and classless
society there would be an end to crime and all the functions would be performed
on the basis of mutual co-operation has been observed not be true in modern
economies. Some anarchists are in favour of adopting violent action in order to
achieve their aims, which could lead to civil wars and death.
Capitalist Theory
Capitalist Theory defines an economy generally dominated by two economic
agents, namely the capitalists (bourgeoisie class) and the proletariat (working
class). The bourgeoisie or the upper classes are the ones who gain wealth from
the proletariat, the lower classes of society. Adam Smith is regarded as the father
of Capitalism which he demonstrated in his 1776 work titled An Inquiry into
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
83
the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Capitalism is often thought of
as an economic system in which private actors own and control the factors of
production. Adam Smith emphasised the nature of Capitalism as hinging on the
importance of specialisation, division of labour, and the gains and prominence of
trade (Baumol et al. 2007).
Capitalists get richer while the workers do all the hard work and get poorer.
Capitalists also get more power to promote their self-interests. Capitalism creates
a working-class group of people who soon get angry at the way they are treated,
and will eventually demand changes. The essential feature of Capitalism is the
desire to make maximum profit, which is achieved by paying lesser wages and
charging relatively high prices for their produce. Capital assets such as plants,
mines, and railways are privately owned and controlled by the capitalists. All
the capital gains on these assets accrue to private owners. Labour is procured via
wages which are relatively low (Baumol et al. 2007).
In Capitalist Theory, there are six major pillars of functionality that explain
how an economy operates. They are
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
private property,
self-interest,
competition,
market mechanism,
freedom, and
6. the limited role of government.
Private property allows people to own tangible assets, both movable and
immovable. Self-interest is what drives the wedges among different economic
agents. People act in pursuit of their own good, without regard to sociopolitical
issues. Self-interest creates competition among the economic markets. Barriers
to entry into economic markets are established through economies of scale,
efficiency and price wars. The notion of a strong market mechanism is of great
significance. Such a mechanism determines prices in a decentralised manner
through market interactions between buyers and sellers (Baumol et al. 2007).
Economic agents allocate resources and naturally seek the highest reward for
goods and services. Another important pillar of captitalism is the freedom
to choose with respect to consumption, production, and investment. This
leads dissatisfied customers to buy different products and investors to pursue
more lucrative ventures, while workers will leave their jobs for better-paying
ones. Lastly, there should be limited government role; the main purpose for
the government is to protect the rights of private citizens and maintain an
orderly environment that facilitates the proper functioning of markets (Rajan
& Zingales 2003).
84
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Critics of capitalism point to its slow speed in correcting economic challenges
like recessions. In his 1936 work titled General Theory of Employment, Interest, and
Money, John Maynard Keynes argued that capitalism struggles to recover from
slowdowns in investment because a capitalist economy can remain indefinitely
in equilibrium with high unemployment and no growth. This is because the
government has a limited role in driving the real economic variables. Externalities
and imperfect market competition are among the economic ills of a capitalist
economy. Keynesian economics challenged the notion that laissez-faire capitalist
economies could operate well on their own without state intervention to promote
aggregate demand and fight high unemployment and deflation of the sort seen
during the 1930s. During a recession, there is a consensus on the need for cutting
taxes and increasing government spending in order to restore the economy to its
potential. According to Rajan and Zingales, society must ‘save capitalism from
the capitalists’ (2003:1): i.e. take appropriate steps to protect the free market
from powerful private interests that seek to impede its efficient functioning
Communist Theory
Communist Theory is a philosophical approach to studying society or government
based on the ideas of Karl Marx (1818–1883). The theory is grounded on the idea
of a classless and egalitarian society. There is common ownership of all resources,
no private property and equality. Such characteristics were first observed in
Greece and in the Mazdak movement in Persia (now known as Iran), both during
the fifth century. Thomas More is one of the first contributors to the theory
of Communism in his work named Utopia in 1516. More portrayed a society
based on mutual ownership of property, whose rulers administered it through
the application of reason. Marx and Friedrich Engels (1820–1895) contributed
significantly to the theory (Engels & Marx 1969). These two German philosophers
both hated the conditions that the Industrial Revolution had brought to workers.
Their essays were published in a book titled Communist Manifesto, also known as
the ‘Marxist Bible’, which was issued in 1848 (Sedov 1980).
The evolution of government and economic theories starts with primitive
communism and moves to feudalism, capitalism, socialism and finally to Marxist
communism. Primitive Communism describes how humans first lived together
in small groups. In these groups, everything was shared including food, jobs, and
belongings. There was no private ownership of assets like land. This was followed by
feudalism, then capitalism and socialism and finally Marxist Communism. Under
Marxist Communism, everyone works together to develop and benefit one another.
War is a thing of the past as different groups come together to contribute to the
development of their communities. Sharing and working together removes capitalist
structures as everything is now provided by the people and money loses its function.
All economic and productive activities are channelled to benefiting each member of
the society, thereby allowing all to live their lives to the full (Sedov 1980).
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
85
The main criticism of Communism is against its practicability and application
in the modern world. Despite the existence of philanthropists, the ideology of selfinterest can never be ignored. Marxism is criticised as historical determinism that
suppresses liberal democratic rights. It is criticised for its economic reductionism
– basing almost all explanations on the influence of economics or the economic
base of society (Sedov 1980).
Public Choice Theory
Public Choice Theory (see Chapter 12) defines the use of economic tools to deal
with traditional and political science problems. It includes the study of political
behaviour. The theory studies self-interested agents like politicians, voters and
bureaucrats and their interactions. The key tools used in making public choice
include standard constrained utility maximisation, game theory, and decision
theory, among others (Mueller 1976). The Journal of Economic Literature’s
classification regards public choice as a sub-area of microeconomics under the
analysis of collective decision making, economic models of political processes,
rent-seeking, elections, legislatures, and voting behaviour. The theory has roots
in positivist analysis, but is often used for normative purposes as it identifies a
problem and suggests improvements to existing systems. Public Choice Theory is
related to Social Choice Theory which is a mathematical approach to aggregation
of individual interests and welfares of a population (Buchanan 1990).
The ancestor of modern Public Choice Theory is Swedish economist Knut
Wicksell (1851–1926). In his 1896 work, he treated governments as political
exchanges connecting taxes and expenditures. Public Choice Theory therefore
models the government as comprised of officers who, besides pursuing the public
interest, might act to benefit themselves – for example, in the budget-maximising
model of bureaucracy, possibly at the cost of efficiency. The government seeks to
maximise social welfare functions subject to economic constraints. The founder
of modern Public Choice Theory is Scottish economist Duncan Black (1908–
1991), who is sometimes called ‘the founding father of public choice’. Duncan’s
works culminated in the Committees and Elections Theory and Voting Theory
(Mueller 2008).
The processes of Public Choice Theory and state decision-making start
with how a constitution is drafted and enacted. The collective which chooses
the constitutional rules process will require a collaborative and a critical process
starting with nationwide consultation, creating respective committees and all the
processes which lead to the acceptance and implementation of the constitution.
The other branch of the theory includes the study of bureaucracy (Niskanen 1971).
The model depicts the top bureaucrats as being chosen by the chief executive and
legislature, usually the presidency or parliament. The characteristic image of a
bureaucrat is a person on a fixed salary who is concerned with pleasing those who
86
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
appointed him or her (Mueller 1976). This includes civil servants whose benefits
are protected by the bureaucratic system. The system is skewed towards the selfinterests of bureaucrats, causing democratic irrationality as the system works to
protect itself. According to Buchanan and Tullock (1999), calculus models are
used in Public Choice Theory but that does not mean that all individuals act in
accordance with the behavioural assumption made, or that any one individual
acts this way at all times (Buchanan 1986). Thus, the theory cannot explain the
undetermined results of collective action.
Socialist Theory
Socialist Theory emerged from Capitalist Theory. Under the Socialist Revolution,
all capitalists, including all the rulers, are eliminated. The low-income group
previously called the workers under the capitalists now takes control of the
country in making key decisions about what to produce, how to produce, and
how the produced goods will be distributed (Yunker 1992). The question of the
ownership of the factors of production differs in different socialist theories. It
can be based on public ownership by a state machine, direct ownership by the
users of the productive property through workers’ cooperatives, or universally
owned by all of society with administration and governing delegated to those
who operate and use the factors of production. The main pillar of this system
is that nothing is made for profit; the system must increase the supply of public
goods which include education, health, transportation, etc. The objective is for
people to benefit from economic activities (Nove 1991).
In the socialist economy, production of goods and services is done directly and
solely for utilitarian reasons. Given that the natural and technical resources of the
world are held in common and controlled democratically, the sole objective of
production will be to meet human needs (Campbell 2002). Such an economic
structure thus eliminates market-induced needs which are meant to ensure
sufficient demand for products to be sold at a profit. For the socialist economy
to achieve the above, a well-planned and highly coordinated production system
which does not suffer from business cycles characteristic of capitalism is needed. In
some socialist economic systems, planning only covers the factors of production
and not the allocation of goods and services produced for consumption, which
would be distributed through a market system (Campbell 2002).
Socialist Theory uses self-management and self-governance techniques. Here,
equal power is the order of the day in the workplace to maximise occupational
independence (Sewell 2012). A socialist form of organisation eliminates
controlling hierarchies so that only a hierarchy based on technical knowledge
in the workplace remains. Early writers include Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, a
popular political economist during the nineteenth century, and a number of
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
87
anti-capitalists like Henri de Saint Simon, Thomas Spence, and Enrico Barone.
The classical economist David Ricardo also influenced the early socialist writers
(Busky 2000).
Socialist Theory is criticised for its reliance on a centrally planned economy.
Advocates of Libertarian Socialism and Market Socialism point to the limitations
of a centrally planned economy and are in favour of decentralisation and
devolution in which different regions are given the right to plan and manage their
economic activities. Such moves would increase efficiency and quicken decisionmaking. Socialist Theory eliminates the free market and its price signals, which
are considered necessary for rational economic calculation. This could also cause
a lack of incentive, leading to a slower rate of technological progress and sluggish
rate of growth of gross domestic product (GDP). János Kornai (1992) argues that
the abolition of private ownership of the factors of production would be likely
to cause inferior economic conditions for the general populace than those that
would be found in market economies. He argues that depriving the market of
price signals is highly likely to complicate calculations of the rational concepts to
be used in allocating resources (Kornai 1992).
Education – Learning/Teaching
Andragogy
Andragogy as a concept was coined from two Greek words, ‘andr’ (man) and ‘agogos’
(leading), and literarily means ‘man-leading’. Andragogy, also known as Adult
Learning Theory, simply refers to the art and science of adult learning. In 1833,
German educator and editor Alexander Kapp used the concept to describe Plato’s
educational theory but this was disputed until 1926 when American educator
Eduard C. Lindeman wrote extensively on the concept (Van Enckevort 1971).
In 1968, the concept finally came into the limelight when American educator
Malcom Shepherd Knowles (1913–1997) proposed Adult Learning Theory and
called any form of adult education or learning Andragogy. Before then, the whole
idea of teaching and learning was unidirectional (encapsulated in a well-used
concept of Pedagogy), where ‘teacher’ passes knowledge to ‘students’ without due
consideration for the possibility of ‘students’ teaching ‘teacher’. Knowles was of
the opinion that adults’ ways of learning differ markedly from those of children.
His thoughts on Andragogy sought to emphasise the uniqueness and strength of
adult learners (Van Enckevort 1971).
Knowles’ theory of Andragogy rests on key assumptions which include:
1.
2.
3.
4.
the need for adults to know why learning is important;
adults’ ability to decide what to learn;
the importance of experience in the learning process;
the positive relationship between a readiness to learn and the relevance of the
learning content to evolving social responsibilities;
88
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
5. adults’ expectation of life-centred content; and
6. adults’ internal motivation towards learning (Knowles 1980; Krajnc 1989;
Knowles, Holton & Swanson 1998; Noor, Harun & Aris 2012).
More elaborately, people mature over time and this gives them more control
over their ‘self-concept’ which permits them to actively take part in the learning
process. Next, individuals accumulate vast ‘experience’ as they mature, and this
serves as a useful resource for learning. Also, individuals’ ‘readiness to learn’
increases as they mature and see the responsibilities that are attached to their
social roles. Also, ‘orientation to learning’ changes from subject-centredness
to problem-centredness as individuals mature because knowledge application
happens immediately and not later (as Pedagogy claims). In addition, emphasis is
placed on internal ‘motivation to learn’ (such as a self-driven goal) as individuals
mature, unlike external motivation (such as reward and punishment) in child
learning (Knowles 1980).
Based on these assumptions, Knowles’ theory of Andragogy rests on four
principles applicable to adult learning. First, involvement of adults in the
planning, process, and evaluation of their learning is important since they are ‘selfdirected’. E-learning, for instance, is an example where learners are self-directed
and under less supervision: these have proven successful in developing countries
(Barteit et al. 2019; Hubalovsky, Hubalovska & Musilek, 2019; Al-Fraihat, Joy &
Sinclair 2020). Second, the basis of learning activities should focus on ‘addition to
knowledge’, considering adults’ life experience. This is a deviation from Pedagogy
whereby a child’s previous knowledge is not often recognised or seen as relevant.
Effective learning requires that learning is directed towards building on prior
knowledge as reflected in many pre-colonial African (Egizii 2015; Chen & Hong
2016). Third, it is expedient for the content of the learning to be relevant to adults’
personal lives and works. With the emergence of unprecedented social problems
affecting all facets of people’s lives, knowledge must be directed towards solving
immediate problems and learning/teaching must aim at achieving the same.
Fourth, adult learning centres on problem-solving and not content memorisation
(Kearsley 2010). The focus of learning must be redirected and the use of small
group discussions (or a small number of students in a class) that will allow all
participants significant contribution should be emphasised.
Andragogy fails to recognise different kinds of adults in different places and
times and with different preferences; as a result, the theory cannot be adequately
applied to all adults: third-agers and fourth-agers, young, middle-aged and older
adults, healthy and unhealthy, working and retired adults, among many other
classifications. In other words, differences in learning are associated with individual
psychosocial and political economic characteristics such as context, power and
culture, and not according to age or one’s stage of life (Hanson 1996; Noor, Harun
& Aris 2012). Furthermore, it has been questioned whether the continuous use
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
89
of the word ‘adults’ in Andragogy suggests that the theory only applies to adults
and not children. In reality and in its true sense, Andragogy applies to both adults
and children as Andragogy-Pedagogy represents a continuum process requiring a
student-directed and/or teacher-directed approach depending on many factors,
including context (Merriam, Caffarella & Baumgartner 2006). Empirically, some
of the assumptions of Andragogy such as self-directed e-learning especially among
adults have not been proven (Blondy 2007), and preference for an AndragogyPedagogy model is not one-sided; instead, it is located along the AndragogyPedagogy continuum (Delahaye, Limerick & Hearn 1994; Noor, Harun & Aris
2012). Perhaps, the most radical of these criticisms was the one provided by Kidd
(1973) who stated that the principle of learning is a lifelong experience and that
building Adult Learning Theory or Andragogy is pointless.
Conflict Theory
This theory postulates that society is made up of different groups and interests
that compete for both power and resources. So rather than these groups working
together for a social good, they compete for power and scarce resources and this
division has led to two broad classes of people: the haves and the have-nots. The
‘haves’, usually called the bourgeoisie, are the owners of the means of production
such as farms, businesses, and so on; the have-nots, usually called the proletariat,
are the workers who earn wages and are of benefit to the owners of the means of
production (Cole 2008).
The origins of Conflict Theory can be traced back to the classic works of
Karl Marx who believed that the school as an institution is not striving for social
equilibrium at all, but that it reinforces and perpetuates social inequalities that
arise from class, race, gender and ethnicity. To conflict theorists, the school
preserves the status quo and pushes people of lower status into obedience,
protecting the power of those who rule society. The purpose of education is to
maintain social inequality. Nearly every aspect of school functioning (academic
achievement, level of aspiration, extracurricular activities, or drop-out rate, for
example) is influenced by social class. Functionalists claim that schools sort pupils
based upon merit, but conflict theorists argue that schools sort pupils along
distinct class and ethnic lines. In other words, schools train those of the working
class to accept their position as lower-class members of the society and those of
the upper class to maintain their position (Ballantine & Hammack 2012).
Conflict theorists hold that the way one receives formal education is determined
by social class which can dictate the ability to access and fund education. Power
groups have access to resources and life chances which the unprivileged have not,
a situation leading to social class reproduction. These theorists also argue that the
curriculum reflects a dominant culture, not shared values. School knowledge is
based on what is valued by the ruling class (Ballantine & Hammack 2012).
90
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
For example, when Zambia got its independence in 1964, the slogan ‘One
Zambia One Nation’ was used. This slogan, instead of uniting the people
of Zambia, was used to silence those people who would try to challenge the
president’s decisions and way of ruling. The president’s power and that of other
ruling-class people in Zambian society were maintained during that period.
Consequently, inequality among people in society was widened.
One of the major strengths of the theory is that it can be employed to explain
social change and how it is brought about by minority groups within the school
set-up to effect change. Proponents of the theory urge the minorities to wake
up from their slumber and revolt to receive the same education and equal
opportunities, bringing about social change. This mode of ‘unmasking’ is one
of the attractive elements of Conflict Theory. This also emphasises individual
creativity, recognising that in any situation in which a person finds themselves,
adaptations can be made to change the situation.
Conflict Theory is limited to certain environments. For example, the theory
only affirms the negative and conflicted state of society and discounts all acts of
kindness as having an ulterior motive or personal agenda. The theory suggests
that the division between social classes is usually a power struggle in which one
group seeks domination and control over the weaker group, neglecting that this
power struggle may also exist within the weaker group.
Ergonagy
The term Ergonagy originated from the Greek words ergon, which means in
English ‘work’, and agogos, which denotes ‘lead’. Generally, Ergonagy Theory
refers to ‘the art and science of helping people learn how to work’ (Bangura
2017:1). This concept is associated with education and training that promotes
one’s occupational, vocational and professional skills (Bangura 2017). In other
words, the theory supports a continual combination of academic and vocational
education or skills for improved working opportunities throughout an individual’s
life whether in one or several careers.
According to Tanaka and Evers (1999), Ergonagy Theory rests on three
basic key principles. The first and foremost is its integration of Pedagogy and
Andragogy as a strategy for applied ideal learning. This principle emphasises a
combination of those two models in order to enhance high-quality vocational
learning (Tanaka & Evers 1999). The second principle is Ergonagy’s promotion
of life-long education devoted to knowledge and skills associated with work.
The third principle is the theory’s assumption of the considerate co-existence of
humankind and nature. It seeks to reduce consumption and environmental wear
by promoting education and training that include the importance of work that
protects the environment (Tanaka & Evers 1999).
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
91
This theoretical approach is imperative for Africa’s education system to fill
the void created by preceding models. If well-planned in the context of solving
practical societal problems, it can help to reduce unemployment as well as help in
the development of African economies. Many African countries are encouraged
to adopt and implement the tenets of this theory especially in secondary schools.
Among the theory’s strengths is the ability to subsume strategies of Pedagogy
and Andragogy to benefit both the individual and society (Tanaka & Evers 1999).
During childhood and adolescence, learning is based on societal needs; and, during
adulthood, teaching is based on one’s individual interests and technological and
job skills. The theory impacts an individual’s subsequent careers and retirement
activities due to the fact that learning is expected to produce multiple outcomes
like securing a future life, leisure and work. Ergonagy rejuvenates and encourages
African traditional education systems which, despite not having curricula content
in the disciplines of arts, science, economics, among others, can weld children’s
daily routines and livelihoods of their families and lives into a single curriculum
to prepare them to function efficiently in their communities.
Ergonagy is limited by the fact that it compiles individualities (traits) which
stakeholders perceive as popular but lacks empirical scrutiny of the outcomes and
challenges that they represent. Some studies have indicated that with the exception
of Botswana, Namibia and South Africa, a majority of African countries remain
weak in integrating life-long learning in the pedagogical and organisational
delivery systems. This, according to Walters (2006), has been attributed to the
impracticality of providing life-long learning materials.
The theory needs to factor in the aspect of financial constraints as a hindrance
to individual work progress. High rates of unemployment and poor living
standards in the global South have affected the implementation of this theory
in Africa.
Functional Theory
Functional Theory focusses on the way something works for a society and so
looks at the role of education in a society. Functional Theory is based on the
works of Auguste Comte, Herbert Spencer, Emile Durkheim, Talcott Parsons
and Robert Merton. These theorists viewed education as one of the important
social institutions in a society, believing that the educational system and society
are intertwined (Theodorson 1969).
The theory views education as having two important types of functions:
1. the manifest or primary functions and
2. the latent or secondary functions.
The manifest functions are those that are intended and visible and include transfer
of knowledge and skills to children, socialisation, social placement, and cultural
92
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
innovation. The latent functions are those that are unintended and hidden and
include, among many others, childcare, the establishment of peer relationships, the
transmission of core values, social control, individualism, fostering self- esteem,
and replacement of the family (Merton 1968). Functionalists also emphasise the
interconnectedness of society by focusing on how each part of a society influences
and is influenced by other parts, meaning that any change in education reflects a
change in society and vice versa (Theodorson 1969).
The main strength of Functionalist Theory is that it posits that humans
are predictable; therefore, one can tell over time how an education system will
influence people. Also, humans are driven by values which aim to maintain social
equilibrium; in the education setup, moral values such as integrity, honesty and
punctuality are part of the hidden curriculum and contribute to society. The
school transmits culture, promotes social and political integration and maintains
social control.
The main weakness of the theory is the way it overemphasises social stability
brought about by the education system and ignores other aspects of education
that perpetuate social inequalities. The theory also ignores how the school can
contribute to struggles over scarce resources.
Heutagogy
Heutagogy is an education theory that entails the study of self-determined
learning within an educational environment (Hase & Kenyon 2013). This theory
promotes a learner-centred instructional strategy that emphasises the development
of autonomy, capacity, and capability. It looks at the learner as having the ability
to set the learning objectives, resources, and means of learning and learning
outcomes. In other words, it allows for the recognition of the critical importance
of the learner in all aspects of the learning process (Hase & Kenyon 2013).
Chris Kenyon and Stewart Hase pioneered the theory in 2000 as a holistic
form of learning and teaching that emphasises vocational, occupational and
professional purposes with four basic assumptions. The first is learners’ agency
(learner-centredness) which highlights a self-defined path not designated by the
instructor. It encourages giving learners complete responsibility to manage their
own learning in addition to assessing their own success. The second is capability
– the focus on developing capable learners who are prepared for the demands of
complex and changing environments. The third is the principle of self-reflection
and metacognition (double-looping), where a learner engages in self-reflection of
the new knowledge they have learnt and the different ways through which the
knowledge has been acquired. The fourth and final is the tenet of non-linear
teaching and learning that empowers the learner to determine their own learning
pathways (Hase & Kenyon 2013).
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
93
Heutagogy can be relevant in many developing countries where computer
technology is gaining ground and social media outlets such as Twitter, WhatsApp,
and Facebook are increasingly serving the young generation. It can offer support
for learner-determined learning, and personalisation of learning by using
connectivity networks that can bridge the gap between academics and other
professionals. Heutagogy facilitates a new role for learners as active participants
rather than passive recipients. The University of South Africa (UNISA), for
instance, serves over 300,000 urban and rural students across Africa in First and
Third World settings (Louw 2014).
The theory is ideal for the distance and online learning environments that
many African universities are now encouraging their students to adopt. Through
this method, students can enrol for online Master’s and PhD programs on the
continent and around the world. In countries like Uganda where the Ministry of
Education and Sports is continuously embracing and encouraging e-learning, the
theory can be helpful.
Among Heutagogy’s strengths is the fact that it envisages a natural progression
from earlier educational methodologies to allow an ideal approach to learning
in the twenty-first century. This is because the theory provides a foundation for
developing learning ecologies which can be maximised by digital media. Together
with other available resources, learners can explore many community problems
in order to become problem-solvers and experts in their different communities.
Bangura (2005) recognises the theory as a potential route to the finding of the
African voice as well as promoting its autonomy to suit the African context.
Heutagogy emphasises self-discovery which can develop confidence in a
learner’s perceptions to enable them to interrogate their interpretation of reality
within the framework of competence. It is therefore an ideal approach for the
current global market’s demand for creative and competent employees within
different organisations.
The limitations of the theory are manifest in its non-applicability at certain
levels and in the area of assessment. For instance, in primary schools, it may be
difficult for the learners to know how and what is required of them to gain certain
skills. Also, the tenet of learning agency emphasises learners in determining their
path which may turn problematic because teachers and learners are both learners.
This makes it difficult to ascertain who the learner really is and whether learning
has taken place.
Interactionist Theory
Interactionist Theory states that meanings are derived from interactions among
individuals. Consequently, the theory focuses on the interactions during the
schooling process and the outcomes of those interactions. The theory was
influenced by the works of early sociologists and philosophers such as George
94
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Simmel, Charles Cooley, George Herbert Mead and Erving Goffman. These
scholars emphasised that human behaviour is influenced by definitions and
meanings that are developed and maintained through symbolic interactions
among people. In other words, a person’s identity or sense of self is shaped by
social interaction (Ballantine & Hammack 2012).
According to Manis and Meltzer (1978), people develop a sense of selfconcept by observing how others interact with and label them. As a result, the
interaction between teachers and students can give rise to expectations on both
sides. For example, if a teacher expects a certain behaviour from a student, this
expectation can lead to that very behaviour – i.e., a ‘teacher expectancy effect’.
Students pick up on their teachers’ expectations of them and perform accordingly:
i.e. a ‘self-fulfilling prophecy’. Students may pick up some subtle cues from the
teacher about how well they should be performing. Thus, teacher’s expectations
of students can affect the learning process as students tend to behave in relation
to what the teacher expects (Manis & Meltzer 1978).
In African schools such as those in Zimbabwe and eSwatini, the Interactionist
Theory is relevant to classroom teachers and pupils. Some teachers use praises
such as ‘excellent’ and ‘good work’ and rewards in the classroom. Some call their
pupils ‘bright’, ‘brilliant’ and other names, and these affect the pupils positively
in terms of academic achievement. Or teachers might label some pupils as bullies.
These pupils eventually behave in accordance with the label, and bullies usually
perform badly in their academic subjects. Alvidrez and Weinstein (1999) in their
study on the subject conclude that teacher expectations explain some of the
reasons some learners are successful and happy at school and others are not. As
stated by Covington (1992), teacher expectations do often play a role in students’
classroom achievements.
The major strength of this theory is that it helps us to understand what
happens in schools themselves and how it is relevant for larger society: e.g.,
how children’s playground activities reinforce gender-role socialisation. Girls
tend to play cooperative games, while boys play more competitive sports. It also
underscores the relationships between symbols and a person’s behaviour (BooherJennings 2008).
A major weakness of this theory is that symbols may be interpreted differently
or wrongly by different groups of people. So, at school, pupils can interpret their
teachers wrongly. In addition, Interactionist Theory does not focus heavily on
relationships between a formal education system and the economy. While the
theory can be used to document how teachers’ expectations and attitudes of
requirements from students affect their opportunities in life and education, it
fails to define the exact process of how teachers form these expectations or how
students may communicate subtle messages to teachers about intelligence, skill,
and so forth (Blumer 1969).
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
95
Organisational Theory
According to Kritsonis (2016), Organisational Theory is used to describe how
schools and school systems are organised and managed. The major founders of
and contributors to the theory are Frederick Tylor, Henri Fayol, Luther Gulick,
and Max Weber. Organisational Theory is categorised into
1.
2.
3.
4.
the bureaucratic,
the scientific management,
the human relations, and
the open systems approach (Kritsonis 2016).
Bureaucratic Organisational Theory focuses on the structure and administrative
processes of an educational organisation. It envisages
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
a hierarchical arrangement with separation of authority,
task specialisation among employees (division of labour),
hiring of professional personnel based on technical knowledge,
separation of personal and organisational property, and
implicit rules and regulations that govern official decisions and actions.
The intent of this theory is to maximise rational decision-making and facilitate
increased efficiency within the organisation. This organisational theory has drawn
four criticisms:
1.
2.
3.
4.
hierarchical authority can perpetuate rigidity and adherence to rules,
the impersonal focus can result in low morale and alienation,
division of labour can stifle initiative, and
informal relationships and individual needs are ignored (Goffman 1974).
Scientific Management Organisational Theory pays attention to increasing
efficiency and maximising human productivity by identifying the ‘best’ way to
do a job. Scientific analysis and time-and-motion studies were used to identify
and help eliminate muscular and physiological activities that lead to worker
fatigue. In an effort to optimise work performance, pay was linked to output.
This theory has been criticised because it embodies a mechanistic view of workers
as extensions of machines (Goffman 1974).
The major lens of the Human Relations Organisational Theory is on the
social and affective needs of employees and emphasises the importance of
feelings, attitudes, and the social climate of organisations. Although the basic
organisational structure may resemble a bureaucratic model, informal interactions
that exist outside bureaucratic norms or formal dimensions of an organisation are
identified. Employees whose social and psychological needs have been fulfilled
are motivated to work more productively (Goffman 1974).
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
96
Systems Organisational Theory can be viewed from three different perspectives:
1. biological (living organisms),
2. mechanical (automobiles), and
3. social (organisations).
Within each of these perspectives, there are two basic system types:
1. closed and
2. open.
Closed systems, like the bureaucratic and human relations models, have
impenetrable boundaries and derive few inputs from the environment. Although
thought to be self-sufficient, these systems can experience entropy, a movement to
disorder, lack of resource transformation, and eventually death. In contrast, open
systems have permeable boundaries exchanging resources with the environment.
The open systems approach views organisations as open systems that interact with
the environments in which they exist. The relationship of organisational parts
and the link between the organisation and its larger environment are stressed. The
input-throughput-output model is used in this approach. Organisations maintain
themselves by processing inputs from their environments and converting them
into outputs (Goffman 1974). One criticism of the systems approach is that
it fails to adequately account for changes that result from interactions among
people (Goffman 1974).
Pedagogy
This education theory is specifically formulated to study teaching/learning
practices involving children. Its pivotal tenets highlight the underlying processes
that teaching, learning and assessment follow. Pedagogy emphasises the study
of methods in education. The theory addresses the fundamental issues that are
peculiar to a unidirectional teaching method whereby instructions are handed
over by the teacher to the students without objection or contribution (Freire
1970). According to Knowles (1984) and Bangura (2004), Pedagogy is suggestive
of imposition and compelling attendance. This attribute contrasts with that of the
Andragogy model which is more interactive and encourages learners’ participation
as against the inherent feature of dependence found in Pedagogy.
In Pedagogy, the entire process, methods, and even the type of study materials,
are decided by the teacher because of the dependent nature of the learners (Tam
2010; Noor, Harun & Aris 2012). The instructional materials are expected to
complement verbal and qualitative teaching. In this learning technique, the
teacher defines the expected standard of intellectual response from the learners
without paying attention to individual peculiarities and talents, leaving the
learners at the receiving end.
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
97
The applicability of the Pedagogy Theory within the context of doctoral
supervision in Africa is apposite. As Ellsworth (1999) argues, the Pedagogy model
of teaching has elements of domination and victimisation, and this is the main
reason some doctoral supervision processes drag on for longer than necessary.
Supervisors try to impose decisions on the supervisee. At the very extreme, this
practice often leads to drop-out cases among students.
One of the drawbacks of Pedagogy is that in a place where teachers do not
receive enough training or where they do not have the skills to deal with students’
learning deficiencies (for instance autistic pupils or other kinds of challenges),
it becomes difficult for teachers to pass on knowledge. That is why the modern
approach is called ‘intellect-led’. This means that teaching is inspired by the
abilities of the learners to identify and clearly state their own learning paths.
This is also why artificial intelligence is coming to the fore in education, as it
is no longer teacher-centric. It is not just about reading a text and passing it
down as understood by the teacher, but about how it tallies within the situational
complexities of the learner. This is done taking into consideration the intellect,
psychological, psychoanalysis, and cultural factors affecting the individual learner
so that the teacher no longer has a messianic approach but now has a participatory
one. With the modern Pedagogy approach, everybody is taught based on his/her
peculiarities, especially his/her intellectual prowess and disposition (Ellsworth
1999). Kullman (2019) suggests that pedagogic materials should be close to the
lived experiences of the learner because the configurations and experiences of
learners vary and that should be a critical variable for consideration.
In childhood education learning, classroom punishment is a mechanism that
is seen to ensure orderliness in Pedagogy (Tam 2010). But this could swing to
either side of the pendulum. Some pupils might become apprehensive or timid
while others might improve on their academic ability as desired and expected by
the teachers.
Although Pedagogy nurtures and grooms the learner, it also represses the
intellectual ability of the learner. Pedagogy has become outdated because teaching
and training are now more interactive. The Montessori Model, for instance,
provides early educational support and one-on-one coaching for the child
(Kinshuk 2002).
Social Closure Theory
As its name suggests, Social Closure Theory is an approach used to explain the type
of social structure in which less advantaged (socio-economically, educationally,
etc.) people are excluded from certain societal goods and privileges. While these
boundaries are to the advantage of some individuals, others are at a disadvantage.
The theory describes how social exclusion (Coetzee et al. 2019) creates some level
of marginalisation and discrimination of those with little or no access to certain
98
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
opportunities. The ‘privileged’ use this opportunity not only to exclude others
but also to monopolise resources, thereby demonstrating selfishness. Rooted in
Max Weber’s ideas postulated posthumously by Gerth and Mills (1946), Social
Choice Theory promotes a framework that explains the different types of social
marginalisation and exclusions prevalent in societies. This theory establishes that
people may be alienated from a social group because they lack the capacity for
inclusion, thereby giving monopolistic advantage to a few fortunate individuals,
an outcome Schirmer and Michailakis (2015) call ‘functional differentiation’.
Social Closure Theory posits that some members of society are excluded using
criteria such as socioeconomic status, education, and knowledge, race, ethnicity
and place of residence. The common practice of funding elementary and middle
schools on the basis of local or municipal taxes is a clear case of social closure
(per exclusion). With this practice, we have a situation where the low-income
areas of cities, often populated by ethno-racial minorities, have less resources
due to their lower tax base. Meanwhile, with the insistence that pupils attend
school in their neighbourhoods, low-income children encounter social closure in
their effort to access better schools outside of their poor neighbourhoods. This
empowers the more privileged in society over the less privileged (Foucault 1978).
Frank Parkin (1979) argues that in societies that are capitalist-oriented, social
exclusion implies lack of capacity-building in certain individuals. This could be
in the areas of academic and professional advantage and property ownership, etc.
Parkin therefore suggests education would increase economic worth and respect
that would translate into social inclusion.
According to Larkin (1983), the critical elements of exclusion basically take
two forms:
1. formal or official, such as those that are products of the state; and
2. informal or unofficial, such as those that are products of family and relationships
and manifested in different social contexts such as ethnicity, language, racism,
gender, politics and governance, education and learning, marriage and family,
profession, etc.
Social Closure Theory cannot be divorced from social class/status structures where
interactions are balanced among people of relatable social status or imbalanced
as in the case of a superior-inferior dichotomy. Murphy (1988) argues that
even within interactions in a group of equal status, there exists a hierarchy that
produces a group of people with similar interests which is oblivious of other
members of the group. Put differently, social closure has layers and opportunities,
and these are assessed based on disclosed or undisclosed criteria .
A major drawback of Social Closure Theory is that attention is not paid to the
ameliorating mechanisms deployed to salvage the ruins of exclusion: for example,
the efforts of social service providers like electricity and water suppliers and waste
management bodies. Such service providers’ scope is limited to cushioning of
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
99
the effect of exclusion and may not include the excluded into social groups.
Nevertheless, these gestures may increase the chances of inclusion into existing
socially closed groups. The position of Parkin (1979) shifts the pendulum of
blame to the excluded rather than addressing a critical cause of ‘social construct’
that has been perceived and accepted as the norm. On the flip side, he underscores
contemporary realities that have economic underpinnings with little or no
emphasis on other aspects such as social factors (Parkin 1979).
Social Closure Theory best describes a plethora of social issues across Africa.
Having educational or professional qualifications is not a guarantee of social
inclusion because there are many higher degree holders who still experience
exclusion especially in the search for economic empowerment. In that context,
an educational criterion which Parkin (1979) emphasises as a requirement for
economic empowerment that promises social belonging is questionable. In the
same vein, the theory resonates with women marginalised from education especially
in pre-colonial Africa and who suffer its residual consequences: exclusion from
political participation, leaving the continent and its people economically weak.
Tirbyi
Tirbyi is an Arabic term which refers to a form of education which contrasts with
Western education in terms of cultural orientation. It derives from the Islamic
philosophy and way of life, tawhid. The term Tirbyi is associated with Bangura
(2004), who argues that despite having different foundations, Western education
and Islamic education – which Tirbyi epitomises – have something in common:
i.e. they both prioritise knowledge. Tirbyi seeks to impart knowledge relying
solely on the standards set by religious institutions. Bangura (2004) explains
Tirbyi as operating to conform to an eternal force by championing the cause of
unity. Tirbyi encourages the pursuit of knowledge and postulates that only Allah
can give it (Qur’an 17:36; 20:114).
According to Bangura (2004), Tirbyi has three basic tenets:
1. religiosity,
2. consensus, and
3. dialogue.
Religiosity has to do with the belief that knowledge essentially comes from Allah
and He alone has the monopoly on knowledge. To obtain knowledge, one must
inevitably rely on God. For Tirbyi, knowledge is built on religious practices and
beliefs. The consensus tenet of Tirbyi is demonstrated in its pursuit of widespread
agreement (consensus) and reconciliation among peoples of the world. Islamic
traditional societies and culture, including their educational systems, are built
on this tenet of Tirbyi. The consensus tenet of Tirbyi promotes and protects the
opinions and positions of minority groups in societies, while also appreciating
100
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
individual and group differences. This ensures societal and group unity (Bangura
2004). The dialogue aspect of Tirbyi emphasises flexibility, consideration for
others, and unity in diversity. This implies that humans must be accommodating
of others in all things, including in teaching, knowing the differences in skills,
assimilation rate, and languages, and so on. Humans must be able to see and
consider other humans in their actions and decisions; they must be ready to let
go of certain ‘self-interests’ for the good of others. Humans must ‘dialogue’ their
differences with their fellows and be able to shift ground whenever the need arises.
The dialogue tenet of Tirbyi has been identified as a major factor responsible for
the growth of Islam all over the world (Said & Bangura 2004).
Though its basic tenets, Tirbyi encourages unity in diversity, recognises
the place and importance of knowledge in societies, and emphasises the need
for human selflessness. All these characteristics are important to aid learning
and teaching, and societal growth and development. Tirbyi is important in
explaining, for instance, the activities of some radical Islamic groups. For
example, the activities of the Islamic Movement of Nigeria (IMN), the Boko
Haram in Nigeria, and the Islamic Movements in West Africa could be traced
to some of the arguments of Tirbyi. These groups, just as Tirbyi posits, believe
that knowledge can only be obtained through Islamic ways and that only
Allah gives knowledge. The groups condemn Western education in its entirety
and propagate the replacement of Western education with Islamic education
(Tirbyi) which is rooted in the Holy Qur’an.
Tirbyi, however, falls short in not providing sufficient explanation for some
Islamic extremism which exists even within the knowledge obtained from the
Holy Qur’an. It fails to account for why people kill others while justifying their
actions by the knowledge they obtain from Allah. The quest to impose such
knowledge obtained from Allah on heterogeneous and religiously diverse societies
across the world has resulted in religious crises and acts of Islamic extremism.
While Tirbyi paints the picture that this sort of knowledge promotes peace, unity
and selflessness, some radical groups have betrayed this and Tirbyi has not been
able to account for this deviance.
Ubuntugogy
Ubuntugogy is an African education paradigm embedded in the Ubuntu existential
philosophy which emphasises community and cultural and social values, rather
than individualism (Ganyi & Owan 2016). The father of Ubuntugogy, Abdul
Karim Bangura, defines it as ‘the art and science of teaching and learning
undergirded by humanity towards others’ (Bangura 2017:3). He advocates for
knowledge systems that are integral to the traditional African environment.
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
101
Characterising it as an African-centred education paradigm, Bangura coined
the term ‘Ubuntugogy’ from ‘Ubuntu’ in 2005 to demystify the reasons underlying
the failure of Western-orientated educational theories to provide solutions to
Africa’s education problems – seen for example in issues like low literacy rates.
He urges African people and scholars to enhance their creativity by using ideas
and methodologies that are compatible in the larger historical, economic, cultural
and political African context (Bangura 2017). Bangura’s Ubuntugogy is based on
three major tenets of Ubuntu.
First, Ubuntu rests upon religiosity, believing that Africans are indisputably
religious. Ubuntu holds that ‘a person is a person through other persons’ and so ‘a
person does not only exist as an independent entity but also as part of the entire
humanity’. The entirety of a person can be expressed through the concept of
‘familyhood’ that metamorphoses into a true African society. To many Africans,
dying is the ultimate home-coming and our ancestors are part of the extended
family. In African tradition, the ‘dead are not dead’, which makes Africans believe
and respect them as both sides care for and depend on each other. Ubuntu calls for
deep respect and regard for religious beliefs and practices that Western education
systems, with their epistemological approaches which detach Africans from their
religion, failed to uproot. Ubuntugogy challenges policy makers and education
practitioners in Africa to develop value-centred curricula applicable to the needs
of their communities and to ensure that science and technology be generalised in
ways that are relevant to address the problems of rural communities where most
Africans live (Bangura 2017).
Second, Ubuntu’s principle of consensus-building provides the capacity for
the pursuit of consensus and reconciliation. Although there may be hierarchy
in the African tradition, all members in a group are given a chance to speak and
deliberate before cohesion and consensus can be attained. Bangura emphasises
slogans like ‘we are one’ or ‘unity is strength’ vis-à-vis Ubuntugogy. If applied in
African education systems, the gap between African elites and the communities
from which they come can be narrowed to ensure that education is available to all
Africans and knowledge is drawn from communities (Bangura 2017).
Third and finally, Ubuntu sees dialogue as a means of inspiring us to expose
ourselves to others in order to encounter humanness to inform and enrich our
own. Bangura (2017) emphasises the genuine otherness of our fellow humans in
order to appreciate the diversity in languages, histories, values and customs, all
of which make up society. Ubuntugogy is an ideal vehicle for the increased input
of African knowledge into the body of global human knowledge and for linkages
between sources of African knowledge and centres of learning on the continent
and in the Diaspora. The theory breaks the vicious cycle of the domination of
Western-oriented approaches in knowledge production.
102
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Ubuntugogy’s diverse approaches can be applied in the area of conflicts,
especially the intra- (with multi-layered issues of ethnicity, boundaries, resources
and inequality) and inter-state conflicts that have touched all aspects of African
life. The comradeship and sense of moral responsibility that this philosophical
assumption emphasises can eliminate individual interests among African political
leaders, major international actors and African Union member states. This unity
can, through conflict-resolution mechanisms, foster social progress in the areas of
peace, security, and development.
Drawing on Ubuntugogy, political leaders and education ministries in Africa
can examine why significant amounts of human and financial investments in
the education sector have failed to translate into quality education and better
service delivery. This can help them develop value-centred curricula and make
policy reforms applicable to the needs of their communities and citizens. The
moral literacy emphasised in Ubuntugogy can inform practitioners, stakeholders
and students in the education sectors of the different countries with a spirit of
Pan-Africanism whereby education should promote peaceful coexistence and be
available for the good of all Africans. Ubuntugogy provides the possibility of
reawakening all sectors, researchers and politicians to the importance of African
indigenous knowledge systems and practices that can address the realities of the
day on the continent.
Ubuntugogy calls for a relational ethical framework in the production and
dissemination of human knowledge on the global market. The theory is limited
by the fact that its applicability and success depends on the implementation
commitments of the concerned communities. In South Africa, for example,
Ubuntu is practiced as a widespread way of life but issues like xenophobic attacks
are still manifest in society. As the theory develops, insights on how school systems
in African countries can respond to social changes caused by globalisation and
migration (and suggested mechanisms of protection from their interference,
infiltration, and negative inferences) would be welcome.
References
Al-Fraihat, Dimah; Joy, Mike, and Sinclair, Jane, 2020, ‘Evaluating E-learning Systems
Success: An Empirical Study’, Computers in Human Behavior, Vol. 102, pp. 67–86.
Alvidrez, J., and Weinstein, R.S., 1999, ‘Early teacher perceptions and later student
academic achievement’, Journal of Educational Psychology, Vol. 91, No. 4,
pp. 731–746. (https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-0663.91.4.731). 2 October 2021.
Bailey, John, J. and O’Connor, Robert, J., 1975, ‘Operationalizing Incrementalism:
Measuring the Muddles’, Public Administration Review, Vol. 35, No. 1, pp. 60–66.
Ballantine, Jeanne H., and Hammack, Floyd M., 2012, The Sociology of Education: A
Systematic Analysis, 7th edition, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2004, ‘Tirbyi in the Muslim World, with a Focus on Saudi
Arabia’, ERIC Institute of Education Sciences, United States Department of
Education. (https://eric.ed.gov/?q=bangura&id=ED490341). 21 September 2021.
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
103
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2005, ‘Ubuntugogy: An African Educational Paradigm that
Transcends Pedagogy, Antragogy, Ergonagy and Heutagogy’, Journal of Third World
Studies, Vol. 22, No. 2, pp. 13–53.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2017, ‘African-Centered Internet Literacy: An Ubuntugogy
Metadata Approach’, Africology: The Journal of Pan-African Studies, Vol. 10, No. 10,
pp. 88–108.
Barteit, S.; Guzek, D.; Jahn, A.; Bärnighausen, T.; Jorge, M.M. and Neuhann F.,
2020, ‘Evaluation of e-learning for medical education in low- and middle-income
countries: A systematic review’, Computers & Education, Vol. 145, p. 103726.
Baumol, William J.; Litan, Robert E. and Schramm, Carl J., 2007, Good Capitalism,
Bad Capitalism, and the Economics of Growth and Prosperity, New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Blondy, Laurie C., 2007, ‘Evaluation and Application of Andragogical Assumptions to
the Adult Online Learning Environment’, Journal of Interactive Online Learning,
Vol. 6, No. 2, pp. 116–130.
Blumer, Herbert, 1969, Symbolic Interactionism: Perspective and Method, Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Booher-Jennings, J., 2008, ‘Learning to Label: Socialisation, Gender, and the Hidden
Curriculum of High-stakes Testing’, British Journal of Sociology of Education,
Vol. 29, pp. 149–160.
Boudon, Raymond, 2003, ‘Beyond Rational Choice Theory’, Annual Review of Sociology,
Vol. 29, pp. 1–29.
Buchanan, James M., 1986, ‘The Constitution of Economic Policy’, Nobel Prize Lecture,
republished in 1987, American Economic Review, Vol. 77, No. 3, pp. 243–250.
Buchanan, James M., 1990, ‘The Domain of Constitutional Economics’, Constitutional
Political Economy, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 1–18.
Buchanan, J.M., and Tullock, G., 1999 [1962], The Calculus of Consent: Logical
Foundations of Constitutional Democracy, Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund. Inc.
Busky, Donald F., 2000, Democratic Socialism: A Global Survey, Westport, CT: Praeger
Publishers.
Campbell, Al, 2002, ‘Democratic Planned Socialism: Feasible Economic Procedures’
Science & Society, Vol. 66, No. 1, pp. 29–42. (DOI:10.1521/siso.66.1.29.21009).
18 September 2021.
Chen, Bodong and Hong, Huang-ao, 2016, ‘Schools as Knowledge-Building
Organizations: Thirty Years of Design Research’, Educational Psychologist, Vol. 51,
No. 2, pp. 266–288. (https://doi.org/10.1080/00461520.2016.1175306).
20 September 2021.
Coetzee, Stephen A.; Leith, Karin and Schmulian, Astrid, 2019, ‘Accounting students
access to social media related resources and the risk of tacit social exclusion’,
Accounting Education, Vol, 28, No 5, pp. 465–483. (https://doi.org/10.1080/09639
284.2019.1641116). 2 October 2021.
Cole, Mike, 2008, Marxism and Educational Theory: Origins and Issues, New York,
NY: Routledge.
Covington, M.V., 1992, Making the grade: A self-worth perspective on motivation and
school reform, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
104
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Delahaye, Brian, L.; Limerick, David C., and Hearn, Greg, 1994, ‘The Relationship
between Andragogical and Pedagogical Orientations and the Implications for Adult
Learning’, Adult Education Quarterly, Vol. 44, No. 4, pp. 187–200.
Dolgoff, Sam, 1974, The Anarchist Collectives: Workers’ Self-Management in the Spanish
Revolution, Quebec, Canada: Black Rose Books.
Egizii, Rita, 2015, ‘Self-directed Learning, Andragogy and the Role of Alumni as Members
of Professional Learning Communities in the Post-secondary Environment’,
Procedia-Social and Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 174, pp. 1740–1749.
Ellsworth, Elizabeth, 1999, ‘Why Doesn’t this Feel Empowering? Working through the
Repressive Myths of Critical Pedagogy’, in Bernice A. Pescosolido, ed., The Social
Worlds of Higher Education: Handbook for Teaching in a New Century, Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University Press.
Engels, Friedrich and Marx, Karl, 1969, Principles of Communism, Vol. 1, Moscow,
Russia: Progress Publishers.
Etzioni, Amitai, 1967, ‘Mixed-scanning: A Third Approach to Decision Making’, Public
Administration Review, Vol. 27, No. 5, pp. 365–392.
Etzioni, Amitai, 1986, ‘Mixed Scanning Revisited’, Public Administration Review,
Vol. 46, No. 1, pp. 8–14.
Foucault, Michel, 1978, ‘The Eye of Power’, SEMIOTEXTE, Vol. 3, No. 2, pp. 6–19.
Freire, Paulo, 1970, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, New York, NY: Continuum.
Friedman, Lewis, 1975, ‘The Concept of Incrementalism’, Public Administration Review,
Vol. 35, No. 3, pp. 311–312.
Ganyi, Francis Mowang and Owan, Jayne Ise, 2016, ‘Impact of Transculturalism and
Globalisation on the Concepts of Oral Literature and “Ubuntugogy” as Educational
Paradigms for African Liberation and Development in the 21st Century’, English
Language, Literature and Culture, Vol. 1, No. 3, pp. 30–39.
Gilbert, Michael, D., 2017, ‘Entrenchment, Incrementalism and Constitutional
Collapse’, Virginia Law Review, Vol. 103, No. 4, pp. 631–671.
Goffman, Erving, 1974, Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Goldberg, Marc A., 1975, ‘On the Inefficiency of Being Efficient’, Environment and
Planning A: Economy and Space, Vol. 7, No, 8, pp. 921–939.
Hanson, Ann, 1996, ‘The Search for a Separate Theory of Adult Learning: Does Anyone
Really Need Andragogy?’, in R. Edwards; A. Hanson and P. Raggatt, eds., Boundaries
of Adult Learning, New York, NY: Routledge.
Hase, Stewart and Kenyon, Chris, 2000, ‘From Andragogy to Heutagogy’, in ultiBASE
In-Site, Melbourne, Australia: RMIT.
Hase, Stewart and Kenyon, Chris, 2013, Self-determined Learning: Heutagogy in Action,
London, UK: Bloomsbury Academic.
Hubalovsky, Stepan, Hubalovska, Marie and Musilek, Michael, 2019, ‘Assessment of
the Influence of Adaptive E-learning on Learning Effectiveness of Primary School
Pupils’, Computers in Human Behavior, Vol. 92, pp. 691–705.
Kearsley, G., 2010, ‘Online teaching: State of the art’, Contemporary Educational
Technology, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 87–89.
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
105
Keynes, J.M, 1936 [1997], General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money, Buffalo,
NY: Prometheus Books.
Kidd, J.R., 1973, How adults learn, New York: Association Press.
Kinshuk, 2002, ‘Does intelligent tutoring have future!’, Proceedings, International
Conference on Computers in Education, Vol. 2, pp 1524–1525. (https://www.
semanticscholar.org/paper/Does-intelligent-tutoring-have-future!-Kinshuk/
f811a5f337cd92cf7d58a526aaa4c14a6607a940). 21 September 2021.
Knowles, Malcom Shepherd, 1980, The Modern Practice of Adult Education: From
Pedagogy to Andragogy (revised and updated), Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Cambridge
Adult Education.
Knowles, Malcom Shepherd, 1984, Andragogy in Action: Applying Modern Principles of
Adult Learning, San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Knowles, Malcolm S.; Holton III, Elwood F., and Swanson, Richard A., 1998, The
Adult Learner: The Definitive Classic in Adult Education and Resource Development,
Butterworth, UK: Heinemann.
Kornai, János, 1992, The Socialist System: The Political Economy of Communism, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Krajnc, Ana, 1989, ‘Andragogy’, in C. Titmus, ed., Lifelong Education for Adults: An
International Handbook, Oxford, UK: Pergamon Press.
Kritsonis, William Allan, 2016, ‘Organizational Theory in Education’. (https://www.
slideshare.net/guestcc1ebaf/theories-and-organizations). 21 September 2021.
Kullman, John, 2019, ‘The Critical Turn in Language and Intercultural Communication
Pedagogy: Theory, Research and Practice’, Language and Intercultural Communication,
Vol. 19, No. 1, pp. 10–112.
Larkin, Gerald, 1983, Occupational Monopoly and Modern Medicine, London, UK: Taylor
& Francis.
Lindblom, Charles E., 1959, ‘The Science of Muddling Through’, Public Administration
Review, Vol. 19, No. 2, pp. 79–88.
Louw, Willa, 2014, ‘Designing Learning Experiences to Prepare Lifelong Learners for
the Complexities of the Workplace’, in M. Coetzee, ed., Psycho-social Career Metacapacities, Zurich, Switzerland: Sprinter International Publishing.
Manis, Jerome G. and Meltzer, Bernard N., 1978, Symbolic Interaction: A Reader in Social
Psychology, 3rd edition, Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon.
Merriam, Sharan B.; Caffarella, Rosemary S. and Baumgartner, Lisa M., 2006, Learning
in Adulthood: A Comprehensive Guide, New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.
Merton, Robert, 1968, Social Theory and Social Structure, New York, NY: The Free Press.
More, Thomas, 1516 [1999], Utopia, New York, NY: Saint Martin’s Press.
Mortazavi, Saeed, 2004, ‘Rational Choice Theory: A Cultural Reconsideration’, Humboldt
Journal of Social Relations, Vol. 28, No. 1, pp. 135–153.
Mueller, Dennis C., 1976, ‘Public Choice: A Survey’, Journal of Economic Literature, Vol.
14, No. 2, pp. 395–433.
Mueller, Dennis C., 2008, ‘Economic Approach to Constitutions’, The New Palgrave
Dictionary of Economics, 2nd edition., New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
106
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Murphy, Raymond, 1988, Social Closure: The Theory of Monopolization and Exclusion,
London, UK: Oxford University Press.
Niskanen, William A., 1971, Bureaucracy and Representative Government, New York, NY:
Aldine-Atherton.
Noor, Norah Md.; Harun, Jamalludin and Aris, Baharuddin, 2012, ‘Andragogy and
Pedagogy Learning Model Preference among Undergraduate Students’, ProcediaSocial and Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 56, pp. 673–678.
Nove, Alec, 1991, The Economics of Feasible Socialism Revisited, London, UK: Routledge.
Parkin, Frank, 1979, Marxism and Class Theory: A Bourgeois Critique, New York. NY:
Columbia University Press.
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, 2018 [1840], What is Property?, CreateSpace Independent
Publishing Platform.
Rajan, Raghuram, and Zingales, Luigi, 2003, Saving Capitalism from the Capitalists:
Unleashing the Power of Financial Markets to Create Wealth and Spread Opportunity,
New York, NY: Crown Publishing Group.
Said, Abdul Aziz and Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2004, The World of Islam: Country-byCountry Profiles, Boston, MA: Pearson Publishing Prentice-Hall.
Sato, Yoshimichi, 2013, ‘Rational Choice Theory’, Sociopedia.isa. (https://www.
researchgate.net/publication/323953966_Rational_choice_theory). 17 September
2021.
Schirmer, Werner and Michailakis, Dimitris, 2015, ‘The Help System and its Reflection
Theory: A Sociological Observation of Social Work’, Nordic Social Work Research,
Vol. 5, No. 1, pp. 71–84.
Sedov, Lev, 1980, The Red Book on the Moscow Trial: Documents. New York, NY: New
Park Publications.
Sewell, Rob, 2012, ‘Origin of the Family: In Defence of Engels and Morgan’, Socialist
Appeal. (https://www.socialist.net/origin-of-the-family-in-defence-of-engels-andmorgan.htm). 18 September 2021.
Smith, Adam, 1776 [1976], An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations
Vol 1, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.
Tam, Po-chi, 2010, ‘The Implications of Carnival Theory for Interpreting Drama
Pedagogy’, Research in Drama Education: The Journal of Applied Theatre and
Performance, Vol. 15, No. 2, pp. 175–192.
Tanaka, Kazutoshi and Evers, Michael B., 1999, ‘Ergonagy: Its Relation to Pedagogy
and Andragogy’, paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Comparative
and International Education Society (43rd, Toronto, Ontario, Canada,
April 14–18, 1999).
The Holy Qur’an, n.d., Medina, Saudi Arabia: King Fahd Complex for the Printing of the
Holy Qur’an.
Theodorson, George A., 1969, A Modern Dictionary of Sociology, New York, NY: Ty
Crowell Co.
Tullock, Gordon, 1987, ‘Public Choice’, The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, New
York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Doctoral Scholars: Decision-making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching
107
Van Enckevort, G., 1971, ‘Andragogy: A new science’, Aontas, Vol.1, No. 1, pp. 37–52.
Walters, Shirley, 2006, ‘Adult learning within lifelong learning: a different lens, a different
light’, Journal of Education, Vol. 39, pp. 7–26.
Weber, Max, 1946, From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, translated and edited by H.H.
Gerth and C.W. Mills, New York, NY: Routledge.
Wicksell, Knut, 1896, A New Principle of Just Taxation, New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan
Woodcock, George, 2010, Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements,
Peterborough, Canada: Broadview Press.
Yunker, James, 1992, Socialism Revised and Modernized: The Case for Pragmatic Market
Socialism, Westport, CT: Praeger Publishers.
4
Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
Doctoral Scholars
Concise explications of two family, twelve geography and three health and
medicine theories are presented in this chapter. The first group of theories
postulates notions about a group consisting of parents and children living
together in a household. The second group posits ideas regarding physical
features of the earth and its atmosphere, and of human activity as it affects and
is affected by these, including the distribution of populations and resources,
land use, and industries. The third group broaches conceptions relating to the
state of being free from illness or injury and the science or practice of the
diagnosis, treatment, and prevention of diseases.
Family
Biological Theory
Theories on family have been dominated by behavioural scientists for centuries
without recourse to the role of biological factors. Biological Theory seeks to
explain the influence of genetic factors on the behaviour of family members.
It argues that genetic factors can only support (and not replace) the role that
the environment plays on the behaviour of family members. According Ehrman
and Parsons (1981), Charles Darwin was the first to introduce Biological Theory
in the field of genetics and evolution research in 1859. Although psychologist
William James (1842–1910) recognised the role of physiological processes in his
study, these processes were neither empirically established, nor was their nature
known until very recently when biological determinants of family processes and
behaviour became an acceptable explanation in academic discourse (Booth,
Carver & Granger 2000). This has generated what is now commonly known as
the nature-nurture debate.
110
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The introduction of genetics into family studies rests on two major pillars. The
first is to recognise those factors that actually influence psychosocial behaviour
without attributing those factors to either genetics or the environment by chance.
The second is to advance a better model for the explanation of psychosocial
behaviour. In other words, attempts to understand the biopsychosocial
determinants of family behaviour prompted studies that examined the
interrelationships between and among biological, psychological and social
processes of family life (Cairns, Gariépy & Hood 1990; Pereira & Smith 2006;
Frazier 2020; Odimegwu et al. 2020).
According to Biological Theory, DNA defines individual uniqueness and is
inherited by one’s children (Seringhaus & Gerstein 2008). This genetic factor
influences the synthesis of proteins that combine to make the systems involved in
behaviour. Genes mediate both short-term (such as response to hunger and sex)
and long-term (such as reproduction and growth) processes through hormones,
chemical messengers that balance and control bodily functions (Booth, Carver &
Granger 2000). Hormones like testosterone, dehydroepiandrosterone (DHEA),
oxytocin, estradiol and cortisol have been established to influence individual and
family behaviour (D’Onofrio & Lahey 2010). In other words, genetic factors
have been confirmed to have an influence on behaviour right from childhood
through to adolescence and adulthood.
Empirical studies by Udry, Morris and Kovenock (1995) and Walther et al.
(2019) confirmed that hormones (such as estradiol and others that are related
to reproduction) influence women’s depression and decision to have children,
initiation of and interest in sexual activity, and likeliness to conceive. Also,
mothers’ strong feelings of attachment to their children and calm feelings while
breastfeeding their infants have been established to be caused by estradiol, which
triggers the production of oxytocin – a particular hormone that influences various
cognitive, affiliative, maternal and reproductive behaviour (Altemus at al. 1995;
Kim et al. 2014). Moreover, later child development, parent-child relations,
mate selection, and marital relationship quality and stability are all influenced
by some biological factors (Freese, Li & Wade 2003; Kendler & Baker 2006;
Diamond 2009). Today, there is growing research on the biological determinants
of family life.
A significant limitation of Biological Theory is its failure to recognise the
influence of culture on the expression of genes. Although the sequence of DNA
cannot be altered, it can be turned on or off by environmental or cultural factors
(Rutter, Moffitt & Caspi 2006). Biological Theory considers only one side of a coin
by focusing on ‘nature’ without paying attention to ‘nurture’ or the role of cultural
factors such as norms, values and socioeconomic status on human and family
behaviour (Rutter, Moffitt & Caspi 2006; Troost & Filsinger 2009; D’Onofrio
& Lahey 2010). In addition, an ethical issue has been raised against biological
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
111
theorists who follow their subjects (or individuals or groups) under controlled
experiments in order to establish their claims. Today, researchers on family studies
agree that behaviours are influenced by both biological factors (Germenis et al.
2019) and cultural factors (Rutter, Moffitt & Caspi 2006; Freese 2008).
Cultural Theory
Cultural studies on family began in England in the 1950s and 1960s by workingclass men such as Richard Hoggart and Raymond Williams with the purpose
of teaching society appropriate behaviours through music and books. These
men expected the power relations in society to be changed by the introduction
of mass communication. The expected removal of power relations, however,
demanded more effort than just mass communication (Hsu 2017).
Cultural Theory emerged as one of the sub-branches of the fields of
anthropology, semiotics, political economy, sociology and communication. The
theory aims to explain the power of culture in every aspect of life. Culture is
defined as a society’s unique thoughts, views and knowledge. It examines the
techniques through which societies understand their social, economic and political
environments. Cultural Theory focuses on issues like nationality, ethnicity, social
class and gender. The purpose of Cultural Theory is broad, and its practitioners
have borrowed many concepts from different fields of study and established
relationships among diverse approaches, methods and academic models. The
theory argues that individuals are the result of society’s thoughts, philosophies,
principles and knowledge. It also suggests that the culture of any society can
be used as a means to boost development as long as solidarity is maintained,
and individualism avoided. In addition, advocates of Cultural Theory agree that
culture can facilitate a society’s progress and improve life for its citizens. In order
to benefit from culture, its nature and possible productivity must be analysed
intensively (Serrat 2008).
Cultural Theory seeks to understand how culture can be used in the
development agenda. The theory seeks to investigate coexisting issues in cultural
practices and power relations; analyse the relationships between culture, social
and political settings; and tries to study culture as an underlying factor of
development or other issues (Serrat 2008).
Cultural Theory is important because it gives due consideration to general
as well as specific aspects of social issues; values and value systems; and the
interactions among variables such as countries, human beings, and the natural
environment. It also tasks development workers with incorporating conceptual
insights and the practical aspects of culture in their ment endeavours (Verhelst &
Tyndale 2002). Nevertheless, there is a challenge with implementing the theory
as it is not possible to apply one generic approach to every society.
112
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Cultural Theory is useful for development workers in culturally rich African.
For example, in Ethiopia, almost all ethnic groups have their own cultural means of
dealing with socioeconomic and political problems. Even before the introduction
of collaboration through sustainable development goals, they addressed their
problems in a communal way. Before development workers impose that which
they think is important for the society, it is necessary to start from the society’s
indigenous strategies and coping mechanisms and then merge them with modern
strategies (Verhelst & Tyndale 2002; Serrat 2008).
Geography
Agricultural Land Use Theory
According to Norton (1992) Agricultural Land Use Theory was first introduced in
1826 by Johann Heinrich von Thünen (1783–1850) and translated into English
in 1966. Reflecting the transport realities of the time the theory was developed,
the model was based on the assumption that the food and fuel demands of a
city were supplied by farmers from surrounding areas with traditional means of
transportation (for example wagons). The arrangement of the areas around the
city is in four rings. First are the dairy and intensive farming activities, where
perishable products (i.e. fruits, milk, and related products) have to get to town
quickly. Second are timber and firewood as sources of energy and for construction.
Third is crop production to serve the city with bread and other food. Fourth is
cattle raising which is placed further away, on the assumption that cattle can get
to the city without transportation.
The model was developed in the era when modern transport and infrastructures
were non-existent, but it is still important as a way of establishing the relationship
between land value and transportation cost. The structure of the model helps to
analyse the resources-based relation between the city and its surrounding areas.
Von Thünen’s model helps to analyse land usability for farming activities in
relation to distance from cities and towns. The accessibility of a central market
determines transportation costs and therefore the amount of profit one farmer
can make in selling agricultural products. Easy access to the market allows
farmers to hire more workers for longer periods. In addition, farmlands that are
closer to cities are usually smaller in size owing to the high cost of land per square
kilometre in such locations.
Agricultural Land Use Theory is not fully applicable to modern-day agriculture
which uses technology and is based on different resources. For example, the
sources of power and construction materials have been replaced by electricity
and metal rods, cement blocks and bricks. The assumption of the location of
timber production no longer applies. Widespread commercial farming and nonagricultural industries have replaced fruit and milk production. The movement
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
113
of fruit and milk production to locations further away from cities is due to the
introduction of modern toll roads, refrigerated trucks and the cultivation of fruit
varieties that take longer to perish. Nonetheless, the theory is important because
it can serve as a springboard for decisions on major variables like the price of a
product, the mobilisation of labour, and the size of land available for agriculture.
Von Thünen’s theory is important in Africa because many African states are
still developing. The model can inform urban planning in terms of establishing
cities with proper consideration of agricultural food supply and power sources.
In the case of rural economies, the theory can be employed to help boost the
livelihoods of farmers in the surrounding areas by raising awareness of what to
produce depending on the nature of the agricultural products and their distance
from towns and cities.
Agricultural Models and Theories
Agricultural models are particularly used to explain the relationship between
macroeconomic variables and agricultural decisions. The models posit that
agricultural activity and individual decisions within society are impacted by the
social, natural and political dynamics of a country in particular or the world in
general. This affects the production, consumption and labour supply decisions
of rural households, as well as the consumption patterns of urban households.
Agricultural economics as a field has developed models and theories to analyse
the relationship between macroeconomic variables and agricultural decisions.
An example is the Agricultural Household Model. According to Singh,
Squire and Strauss (2019), the Agricultural Household Model helps a researcher
to analyse urban and rural household decision-making on production,
consumption and labour. The model is used to examine agricultural policy from
three angles. The first angle is the implications of agricultural policy for the
welfare of households in terms of income and nutrition. This examines how an
agricultural policy provides food at affordable prices to urban populations while
also establishing access to balanced nutrition to the rural inhabitants with the
incomes they generate from their agricultural activities. The second angle analyses
the ‘spillover effect’ of agricultural policy on other sectors’ activities. Since the
major aim of an agricultural programme is to increase the incomes of agricultural,
a household that does not have land will not be a part of the programme. The
model can help researchers to analyse the profitability of agricultural households
and their spending on non-agricultural goods. The third and last angle of the
model is to give feedback to governments so that they can make knowledge-based
decisions on macroeconomic variables like agricultural input pricing and tax and
foreign exchange. Generally, the model is used to analyse the spillover effects of
agricultural policy on other policies, on individuals’ spending decisions, and on
economic activity at large (Singh, Squire & Strauss 2019).
114
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The Agricultural Household Model uses producer, consumer and labour
supply decision-making models. The analysis shows that the decision-making
of households varies depending on prevailing macroeconomic variables and
household levels of production. For instance, subsistence households make
decisions on production, consumption and labour supply concurrently, whereas
an increase in the level of their production would make their decision-making
more complex. There is the need to consider macroeconomic variables like
demand and labour price to secure profitability. Trade also affects the decisions
of households on production, consumption and labour supply as it provides an
opportunity to sell their products and get income to buy other agricultural and
non-agricultural goods and services. The reduction of the price of agricultural
products in turn reduces the incomes of agricultural households but at the same
time, it benefits them as consumers of agricultural goods. The reciprocal effect
of price also plays out clearly on the profit margins of agricultural households
and their consumption patterns. Government decisions on tax and foreign
exchange also affect the decisions of households as consumers and producers. It is
necessary to analyse agricultural policy in order to discover the key issues affecting
household welfare and the spillover effect of non-agricultural activities (Singh,
Squire & Strauss 2019).
The Agricultural Household Model is important because it helps to fine-tune
government decisions about macroeconomic and fiscal policies to improve life
for rural and urban dwellers alike. This model is crucial for African states. Even
though farming activities in most parts of the continent are still at subsistence
level, agriculture is still the backbone of the continent and most agricultural
production comes from subsistence farmers. To transform agricultural activities
and increase the return from agriculture, the focus must be on households, and the
government must be conscious about decisions it makes. For example, in Ethiopia,
85 per cent of the population earns its livelihood from agriculture, and this is
usually from households (UNDP 2016). Government’s decisions must be based
on household conditions. Since the population of Ethiopia is large and resources
are few, paying attention to the spillover effect of agriculture is very important.
A challenge of the Agricultural Household Model is that it needs continuous
analysis and tracking of the effects of the different factors on the decisions of
households with respect to production, consumption, and labour supply.
Culture Theory
Culture Theory in geographic thought deals with concepts such as knowledge,
beliefs, morals, art, laws, customs and other capabilities and habits acquired by
humans as members of a society, as they interact with the physical environment
(Stoddard, Wishart & Blouet 1986). From an anthropological perspective, culture
is defined as an integrated system dedicated to transmitting the acquisition of
values, beliefs and rules of conduct that delimit the range of acceptable behaviour
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
115
in a society (Oswell 2010). According David Oswell (2010:1) ‘culture was
deployed as a means to understand national and subnational social and symbolic
systems. The economic organization has to do with how people produce,
distribute and consume cultural values.’ It therefore appears that Culture Theory
is an analytical approach that intends to understand the modern world via various
cultures (Oswell 2010).
In the early 1950s, cultural theorists such as the French anthropologist Claude
Levi-Strauss took advantage of the growing interest in the study of culture to
provide an structuralist foundation of culture. The works of these authors were
reinforced in the 1960s and 1970s by French theorists led by Michel Foucault,
Gilles Deleuze, Jean-Francois Lyotard and Jacques Derrida, in what culminated
in the post-structuralist and post-modernist traditions in the academy. In the late
1980s, cultural theorists turned their focus to nature and the environment, and
recently to global information and cultural markets (Oswell 2010).
Culture Theory has been applied to understand African societies in the context
of modern capitalism. A good example is a work of anthropologist Jean Comaroff
examining a South African community in his book titled Body of Power, Spirit of
Resistance: The Culture and History of a South African People. In this book, he paints
a picture of a society where the big South African cities consume the resources
and the populations at the periphery reproduce their capitalistic patterns (cited
by Switzer 1986).
In recent years, globalisation, global information, cultural markets and
cultural hybrids have become leading issues in cultural geography, with cultural
geographers such as Don Mitchell (2000), taking the lead in this scholarship.
This development has seen the use of Culture Theory to investigate related
phenomena such as cultural wars, cultural diffusion, and the cultural studies of
ethno-racial issues, especially in modern cities. A tendency towards generalisation
has been seen as a weakness in the approach. Another criticism of the theory is
the fact that it is not a unitary theory and is not dictated by a normative style or
narrative structure that might be seen as philosophical (Oswell 2010).
Geographic Location Theory
It behooves us to begin this section by pointing out that there is significant overlap
between Geography Location Theory and Industrial Location Theory (see below).
However, each theory has certain unique features and they developed separately.
It makes sense to present them separately, the repetition notwithstanding.
The meaning of the term ‘geography’ is not limited to physical places; it
includes existence (i.e. of people, cultures, settlements, animals, plants, landforms
etc.). Geographic location deals with where existence lies, what brought it there
or why it is there, and how the existence has historically changed (Friedman
2005). Geographic Location Theory therefore seeks to explain the forces (or the
116
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
extremely complex actions, interactions and interconnections among economic,
state, religious and powerful individual actors) that shape or determine the
location of existence, including the interaction of different geographic activities
and how that has shaped the characteristics of the world as a geographical
location. Specifically, Geographic Location Theory seeks to understand where
things or existences are found and why they are not found in other places, the
reason for their presence in those places, the influence of their interactions with
other things in the same or another geographic location, and why they develop
and change in certain ways (Dicken 2007).
Generally, the distribution of geographic locations has been influenced by
people’s search for opportunities and advantages. Countries or geographies with
higher opportunities and advantages often achieve greater standards of living
for their people. A country’s opportunities and advantages can be determined
by various factors such as natural (e.g., land, water, forest, and so on) and
human (e.g., available unskilled workers and educated professionals) resources.
Individuals can increase their opportunities and advantages by increasing their
education or migrating to a geographic location with improved employment
prospects. Spatial drift occurs when people, wealth and culture migrate from one
geographic location to another. National, continental and global geographical
distributions often follow a pattern where people and wealth are moved from
places without opportunities (the ‘have-not’ geography or countries) to places
with opportunities and advantages (the ‘have’ geography or countries). This
migration pattern, which characterises rural-urban or periphery-core shifts, allows
people to search for better opportunities or advantages elsewhere (Dicken 2007).
Various theories have been developed over the years to explain the
geographical distribution of locations. Thompson’s Demographic Transition
Model and economist Rostow’s Stages of Economic Growth are arguably the
most relevant. While American demographer Warren Thompson’s revised model
explains population growth according to five stages of demographic change
from rural traditional societies to urban modern societies, American economist
Walt Whitman Rostow’s model describes five stages of economic growth from
traditional societies to the age of high mass consumption (Rostow 1959; Kirk
1996). The combination of the two ‘five stage’ models provides a broader and
better understanding of the determinants of geographic locations.
The first stage describes traditional rural societies with agriculture as the main
preoccupation and with no dependence on other geographic location (Robinson
1964; Dai 2016). The families in these societies are larger as a result of high
birth and death rates and have low income levels and few opportunities and
advantages. With a very low human development index (HDI), geographies at
this stage of development attract no other geographic locations but are attracted
to others for better opportunities and advantages (Rostow 1959).
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
117
As population grows due to large family size, improved modern medicine and
nutrition and lower death rates, rural stage two geographies begin to urbanise
and trade their economic activities with other geographic locations (Robinson
1964). At this stage, youths from rural areas often move to urban centres in
search of employment opportunities, and industries consider cheap labour in
these regions as a major determinant of their locations. Although income level
remains low at this stage, countries often have a rapidly expanding population
pyramid (Kirk 1996).
Stage three represents the rural-urban drift phase and defines regions as
developed on the basis of industrial activities, increased service sectors and
increasing income levels (Rostow 1959). These geographies attract multinational
corporations because there is a cheap averagely skilled labour supply. As many
more people migrate to urban areas in search of opportunities, urban populations
grow and core cities experience a high number of self-developed slums. Although
family size at this stage begins to drop, there is still an expanding population
pyramid (Kirk 1996).
Regions in the fourth stage of development constitute urbanised, industrialised
and globalised societies with very strong economic networks (Isard & Liossatos
1972; Sheppard 1979; Kirk 1996). More women in these regions enter the workforce
and smaller numbers of children are born, causing small family sizes. Income levels
and HDI continue to rise with a stationary population pyramid (Kirk 1996).
Stage five represents consumer societies with increasing levels of income
and decreasing family sizes (Rostow 1959). Geographic regions at this stage
of development experience dramatic economic development but negative
population growth which eventually leads to reduced numbers of young people
in the workforce (Kirk 1996; Dai 2016). These regions (such as Britain and
the United States) serve as centres of attraction for people in other geographic
locations (such as Nigeria and Kenya) in search of opportunities and advantages.
This stage has a contracting population pyramid (Kirk 1996).
Geographic Location Theory has been employed to explain how people
and resources are distributed differentially across different regions based on the
availability of opportunities and advantages. The impacts of other demographic
variables such as migration are, however, not considered in the demographic
transition model, nor does the model predict how long a country will be in each
stage. Regions need not necessarily pass through all the stages, as demonstrated
by the Eastern-Asian region.
Industry and Economic Development Theories
Industrial and Economic Development Theories are approaches which provide
explanations and a better understanding of global industrial and economic
development. There is a plethora of such theories in the geographic study of
118
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
development. Nafziger (2012) identifies the classical models as Marx’s Historical
Materialism, Rostow’s Stages of Economic Growth, Vicious Circle Theory, the
Theory of Balance versus Unbalance Development, and the Coordinate Failure
Theory. Others include the Lewis-Fei-Ranis Model, Baran’s Neo-Marxism,
Dependency Theory, Neo-Classicism, Solow’s Neo-Classical, and the New
Development Theory. The Schumpeterian Theory of Economic Development
and Rostow’s Stages of Development are discussed in the paragraphs that follow
as well-known examples in the geography of development.
Joseph Schumpeter (1934) propounded a theory of industrial and economic
development which was in sharp contrast with the classical school of thought
which had exclusively linked economic development with capital accumulation.
Schumpeter refused to align with the notion that economic development results
exclusively from the accumulation of capital. For him, the entrepreneur who
innovates (entrepreneur-innovator) and is creative is the major driver of a nation’s
industrial and economic development. Schumpeter refers to such an entrepreneur
as a ‘hero developer’. The theory argues that innovation and creativity are the
driving forces of economic development. As such, any entrepreneur who is
an innovator and a creative thinker contributes immensely to the economic
development of a country. Schumpeter believed that the economic development
pattern would become unbalanced over time because when inventions are newly
introduced, the profits of the entrepreneur increase; over time, however, when the
‘competition copies the invention’, then profits begin to decline (Pietak 2014:50).
Schumpeter referred to this process as the ‘nature of the jump’ (Schumpeter
1934:65). The theory links industrial and economic development to private
property, competitive markets, and efficient financial markets. Schumpeter warns
that this theory of economic development is only fully feasible among democratic
states (Schumpeter 1934).
Schumpeter’s Industrial and Economic Development Theory is demonstrated
in the Chinese economy and the economies of the Asian Tigers. These countries’
economies were comparable to those of African states only a few decades ago,
but they are now far ahead of Africa, owing mostly to technological innovations.
These countries serve as examples of Schumpeter’s entrepreneur-innovator model
as the driver of industrial and economic development.
A major strength of the theory is that it stresses the need for humans to be
innovative and creative, thereby promoting individual development and intellect.
The theory comes up short in exclusively limiting industrial and economic
development to innovative entrepreneurs without looking at other economic,
political and social indices which affect industrial and economic development.
While the theory assumes that the model will only favour democracies, the
examples of China and the Asian Tigers deviate from this assumption and the
theory is not able to provide explanations for this deviation.
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
119
Rostow’s five stages of economic growth hold that countries’ economic growth
must necessarily undergo five different stages before attaining full economic
development. The stages of economic growth for Rostow include the traditional
society, precondition for take-off, take-off, drive to maturity, and age of high mass
consumption (Nafziger 2012; Rostow 1960:4–16). In 1971, Rostow added yet
another stage, which he termed the quality stage where there is an expectation
for there to be continuous improvement in the quality of goods and services.
For Rostow, economic development is dependent on capital accumulation,
a sharp contrast to the Schumpeterian school of thought. Rostow argued that
poor countries have not been able to experience economic development because
they have failed to achieve the third stage (take-off), which he believed is only
achievable via capital accumulation.
Rostow’s theory is well demonstrated in the history of economic development
of some countries’ economies in the world today. Europe (Britain, Italy, Spain, etc.)
and America have passed through the various stages of Rostow’s economic growth
in history. The theory’s strength is in its ability to treat economic development
as a gradual process, and only achievable over time. The theory falls short by
exclusively explaining economic development on the basis of capital accumulation
without consideration of other social, political and economic factors affecting the
economies of states. This also explains why not all countries that have attained
economic growth have necessarily gone through Rostow’s stages of growth. The
spontaneous but steady growth of the economies of the Asian Tigers, for instance,
demonstrates that some of Rostow’s stages can be skipped by countries on their
way to development.
Industrial Location Theory
Generally, Location Theory is an integral term that lends to the understanding
of economic geography, industrial organisation, spatial economics, geographic
information systems, rural-urban development and regional science, and so
on. Industrial Location Theory is an economic theory that seeks to examine
the determinants of industrial location in a particular geography. Specifically,
it aims at unravelling the rationale behind the location of industries especially
as it concerns what influences a firm or industry’s location and how and why
industries are located in one place and not another (Weber 1929). Building on
the work of Johann Heinrich von Thünen (1783–1850), scholars such as Alfred
Weber (1868–1958), Walter Christaller (1893–1969) and August Lösch (1906–
1945) sought to offer universal explanations for industrial locations without
being limited by any disciplinary orientation or prejudice.
To fill the theoretical gap noted in the works of classical economics, Weber
(1929) proposed a ‘Pure Theory’ that explains those factors that pull an industry
toward different geographical locations. In his definition, locational factors are
120
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
forces that determine industrial location decisions, especially as they pertain to
cost reduction and profit maximisation. The theory posits that two broad factors
affect location of industries: regional factors, which are the primary causes of
industrial distribution, and the agglomerative factors, which are secondary causes
of industrial distribution and redistribution (Weber 1929).
Industrial Locational Theory differentiates between special factors (those
peculiar to an industry like nature of product) and general factors (those that affect
all industries like costs of transportation, labour, buildings, and materials, etc.).
Of particular interest to the theory are the general regional factors influencing
cost of production which, in turn, determines industrial locational decisions
(Abumere 1978; Nickel & Puerto 2006). These include transportation and labour
costs. As a vitally important determinant of industrial location, transportation
costs are influenced by cargo weight and distance of raw materials. Raw materials
can first be categorised into ubiquitous raw materials (which can be found in
virtually all places, e.g. water) and specific/fixed raw materials (which are only
available in some places e.g. gold). While pure raw materials do not lose weight
during production processes, gross raw material is that which has more weight
than the finished product. This understanding in a given geographic market and
using a particular raw material engenders three possibilities for industrial location
(Predöhl 1928; Weber 1929). First, industries are located near markets when
ubiquitous raw materials are involved as this will remove or reduce transportation
costs. Second, industrial location is neither based on market nor raw material
when pure raw materials are under consideration. Here, decision on industrial
location is determined by other factors like labour costs. Third and finally,
industries that deal with gross raw materials are located near markets (Predöhl
1928; Weber 1929).
Besides general regional factors, Industrial Location Theory also considers
local factors such as the influence of agglomeration and deglomeration. In other
words, industries are located where there is a cluster or agglomeration of other
industries in order to gain economic advantage. When the costs of locating
industries in an industrial area outweigh the perceived benefits, there tends to
be deglomeration: i.e. the dispersion of industries from a given location (Predöhl
1928; Weber 1929). This accounts for the relocation of many multinational
organisations from Nigeria to Ghana. Industrial Location Theory therefore
affirms that costs/profits are greatly influenced by transportation costs, labour
costs, and the agglomeration factor.
Evidently, not all industries, especially in developing countries in Africa
south of the Sahara follow the principle of least transport cost. Some Dangote
Cement industries across Africa are located close to sources of raw materials
in mostly remote locations. Labour cost is another factor: some industries are
located near cheap labour, despite the huge transportation costs involved. Labour
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
121
costs are influenced by factors such as differing levels of efficiency of labour
and of organisation, population distribution, etc. (Kuchhal 1981; Nnamdi &
Owusu 2014).
Despite its values, strengths and significance, and being one of the very
few theories with universal application, Industrial Location Theory has some
limitations. First, the theory has unrealistic assumptions such as two-factor
determinants of transportation cost –
1. weight and
2. distance.
Other factors like type of transportation, topography, quality of goods and political
economy are equally important (Ogbuagu 1985). Second, in a rapidly changing
and globalised world, the idea of a fixed market or consumption point can no
longer hold. Consumers’ locations might have changed before raw materials
reach the destination. Third, Industrial Location Theory cannot be considered
a deductive theory as acclaimed by a majority of its proponents because the
theory ‘selects’ transport and labour costs as the only general factors without
explaining, for instance, why capital and management costs cannot be considered
(Predöhl 1928). Fourth, the theory’s focus on transportation costs overlooks the
possibility of increased freight charges over the same distance, varied rates for raw
materials, and finished goods (Dennison 1939). Nevertheless, this theory has laid
the foundation for understanding some determinants of disparity in industrial
locations across different geographies.
Land Use and Resources Models
It is worth noting here that the Von Thünen agricultural model described earlier
is also considered a Land Use Model. These types of models are characterised
as prototypes that aid a researcher to better understand the allocation and use
within societies of land and other resources.
Stated differently, the models can be used to explain how and why land
and other resources are put to use the way they are. The land share or the
Econometric Land Use Model is the commonest of such prototypes (Chakir
& Lungarska 2015). The model is associated with Lichtenberg (1989), Stavins
and Jaffe (1990), Wu and Segerson (1995), Plantinga (1996) and Miller and
Plantinga (1999).
The Land Share or Econometric Land Use Model posits that landowners
will put their land and resources to use only for those causes that will maximise
profit and yield returns. The theory argues that the land and other resource owner
attaches profit or returns to his land and resources. Chakir and Lungarska (2015)
identify at least five sources uses a land and other resources owner could deploy
in order to maximise profit. They include:
122
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
1.
2.
3.
4.
agriculture,
forest,
pastures,
urban, and
5. other uses.
To determine the use to which land and other resources will be deployed, the
landowner identifies the use that yields the greatest value in terms of profits
(Stavins & Jaffe 1990; Plantinga 1996).
Land Use and Resources Models are demonstrated in every capitalist economy
in the world today, as lands and other resources are solely and intentionally
directed toward causes that will yield profit. From the United States (the pioneer
state of capitalism) to other capitalist countries across Europe and Africa, land and
other resources are deployed by both private and public institutions, including
individuals, for profit maximisation. One strength of the Land Use and Resource
Models hinges on their ability to explain how individuals and societies prioritise
the use and deployment of land and other resources. The models also aid the
understanding of why individual landowners use their resources and land the way
they do. In addition, the theory can be used to emphasise the role and place of
the individual landowner in the larger societal use of land use and other resources
which, in turn, contributes to societal development. The models create a better
understanding of how the deployment of individual land and other resources
conditions a state’s resource use and consequent development.
The theory’s shortcoming hinges on the fact that it is a long-term model; it
is not able to demonstrate or explain the transitions between resources, land use
and cost at the time those transitions occur. Also, the theory fails to state how a
landowner is able to predict the profit accruable from putting a particular land
or other resource into a given use. In addition, while the theory emphasises that
landowners will put their land and other resources into use that will maximise
profit, it does not explain how a landowner knows which use which will yield the
most benefit before proceeding. The models see profit as the exclusive motivator
for putting land and other resources into use without accounting for other factors,
such as their use for personal purposes.
Geopolitical Theory
Geopolitical Theory is employed to explain the link between a people, a state,
and a territory. It is concerned with the study of particular circumstances on
political processes and the way in which those political processes are influenced by
particular contexts. Geopolitical Theory describes the world as a political theatre
made of lines and poles (Rosière 2001). The lines here refer to the boundaries or
territorial limitations, and the poles refer to the concentration of power in certain
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
123
regions, which regulate the functions of other regions. The territories or theatres
can be at the level of states and regions, or they can be transnational. Although the
boundaries which define political geography are mainly physical, there are also
other boundaries which can be religious, linguistic, or cultural (Rosière 2001).
One of the pioneers of Geopolitical Theory was German geographer Freidrich
Ratzel, who published a book in 1897 titled Politish Geographie, where he claimed
that states are like human beings who need space and resources to feed themselves
(James & Martin 1981). British scholar and geographer Sir Halford Mackinder
extended the theory to include the idea of ‘heartland’ in 1904 in an article titled
‘The Geographical Pivot of History’. As used by Mackinder and later geographers,
the notion of ‘heartland’ or a ‘core region’ connotes the centre of hegemonic
power for countries like Britain, the United States, and other advanced Western
countries, which are distinguishable from the “hinterland’ or “a peripheral region”
in the global South (McCann 1987). But, as some analysts such as James and
Martin (1981) have observed, Mackinder at his time could not anticipate the
extent of technological innovations that would occur in the years ahead to break
the stranglehold of the ‘heartland’.
In the African context, an example of the application of Geopolitical Theory
can be seen in the regular conflict between Rwanda and the Democratic Republic
of Congo (DRC). There was an attempt by Rwanda to capture some territories in
the Eastern region of the DRC in order to secure development. Kigali politicians
believe that the DRC is wasting the resources needed to sustain development,
especially in the regions of South and North Kivu. These regions are near the
Rwandan border and are rich in minerals, resulting in regular conflicts between
the two countries.
One of the strengths of Geopolitical Theory resides in the fact that it helps to
understand how powerful nations act, an example being the struggle between the
United States and China to secure their access to petroleum. The theory examines
how the two countries enhance their economies by controlling strategic resources.
Population and Migration Models
Several models have been propounded over time to explain population and
migration, including ways to project population growth. Zlotnik (1998),
Kupiszewski (2002) and Bijak (2006) have categorised these models into
Sociological (intervening opportunities, push-pull factors, migrant networks,
transnational social spaces, cumulative causation, Institutional Theory, and
World Systems Theory); and Economic (Macro: classical, neo-classical,
Keynesian, dual labour, cumulative causation, institutional and word
systems model; Micro: neo-classical, value-expectancy, and new economics
of migration) models. Others include Geographical (gravity theory, entropy,
Catastrophe Theory, and bifurcations and mobility transition models) and
124
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Unifying (Migration Systems Theory, multidisciplinary approach, and mobility
transition models) models. The geographical models of gravity and mobility
transition models which address more explicitly issues relating to population
and migration will be the focus here.
The Gravity Model of Population and Migration is associated with Stewart
(1941), Zipf (1946) and Isard (1960). The model takes its cues from the law
of gravity as articulated by Isaac Newton. It posits that the population size of
countries and regions can best be explained by the volume of migration between
such countries and regions. The basic tenet of the model is that migration between
countries/regions A and B is proportional to the product of population size in
both countries/regions (Bijak 2006). This implies that migration influences the
population size of both the countries and regions of origin and destination of
migrants. The Gravity Model of Population and Migration explains the population
sizes of countries/regions by looking at the volume of migration (emigration and
immigration) taking place in such countries and regions (Bijak 2006).
In Africa, the gravity model plays out significantly in the rural-urban drift
where populations of rural areas have been significantly decimated, while there
is a population explosion in most cities and towns. Lagos State of Nigeria is a
prominent example of an area where the population size is significantly influenced
by migration activities. In another example, the influx of migrants to Canada has
caused a drastic increase in the country’s population. The model’s strength is
its potential to be used for population projections. It also aids in the tracking
of the source of immigration and the destination of out-migration. The model,
however, comes up short in that it is mostly suitable for explaining internal
migration; it cannot quantify the processes that drive population and it lacks
systematic effects (Poot et al. 2016). The model also seems to link population size
exclusively migration.
The Mobility Transition Model of Population and Migration as propounded
by Zelinsky (1971) posits that regularities in migration have been definite and
patterned over time, and that this has contributed to the modernisation processes
of societies. According to this model, urban-urban, international and ruralurban migrations have characterised human history. It argues that demographic
transition (migration) has contributed to population explosion in major cities
and towns (Skeldon 2013). Rural-urban migration is likely to peak and then
decline, followed by increases in urban-urban and intra-urban migration. At
an advanced stage of migration, the model predicts a decline in international
migration. Zelinsky (1971) argues that with advances in the means of movement,
people transit more than they migrate permanently to places. Zelinsky calls
this transition ‘circulation’, and he posits that it will eventually result in drastic
reductions in migration. The potentials of technological advancement in reducing
migration are also put forward by the Mobility Transition Model.
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
125
Zelinsky argues that as people can communicate over long distances owing
to the advancement in technology, migration would decline. The population
explosions in most African cities like Lagos, Ibadan, etc. find expression in the
model. It also explains how the urban-urban or intra-migration experience is
predominant among South Africans rather than out-migration. The model
is significant in explaining the high population concentrations in major cities
and towns across the globe. It is limited in that it has not been able to provide
explanations for the continued high rate of out-migration in Africa despite
technological advancements and developments in communication technology.
Rather, improvements in technology, communication and the means of movement
(transportation) seem to have caused an increase in migration, especially in Africa.
Migration activities in search of greener pastures, especially among Africans, are
also not accounted for in this model. Lastly, the model was built on a developed
United States country experience (Skeldon 2013), making its general application
to developing countries difficult.
Process Theory
This theory explains the processes involved in geographical change and
development. Generally, Process Theory explains how agencies, systems, structures
and entities change and develop. Everything and everyone everywhere experience
change and development, making this a multidisciplinary theory, drawing from
fields such as education, psychology, sociology, geology and geography. For
instance, there have been changes in the ways learning occurs, medical technology
is changing everywhere, and people move from one place to another. There are
many processes driving these dynamics.
The literature in the field of geography is laden with theories that describe
change processes in organisations and, by extension, in different geographic
locations. Van de Ven and Poole (1995) have summarised these theories into the
following four categories:
1.
2.
3.
4.
dialectical,
evolutionary,
lifecycle, and
teleological.
These categorisations are used to explain geographical differentials in terms of
change and development. This requires the understanding of complex processes
which involve all natural components, their interaction and interconnection. This
helps us to determine the peculiarities or uniqueness of separate territorial units
or spaces, the character of their internal development, and the unique nature of
external forms of the earth’s surface.
126
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Dialectic Process Theory is rooted in Hegelian philosophy which posits inevitable
competing forces for power and domination among geographical entities. These
contradictions are internal when different interest groups within a geographical
unit compete for priority, or external when one geographical entity pursues
goals that contradict the goals of another geographical area. This theory explains
stability, change and development in terms of power tussles among opposing
geographical entities (Harvey 1981; Van de Ven & Poole 1995). For example,
the relative power of African societies during the colonial era (anti-thesis) led to
their ability to challenge colonial rule (thesis), and this resulted in independence
(synthesis). Over time, the resultant synthesis develops into a new thesis, thereby
demonstrating the continuity of the dialectical process. It is possible for opposing
geographic units to mobilise sufficient resources to overthrow and replace the
status quo as happened in many ancient societies. It is also possible for powerful
geographic entities to sustain adequate power to prevent the mobilisation of
opposing groups as the relationship between the global North and South reflects.
In terms of geographical change, maintenance of the status quo characterises
stability while replacement of the status quo either by antithesis or synthesis
signifies change.
Evolutionary Process Theory examines the cumulative changes in culture,
social structures and institutions of a given geography. Evolution means change
from a simple homogenous to a complex heterogeneous stage. Using Biological
Evolutional Theory, geographical dynamics are explained in terms of variations
(establishment of new forms of geographies), selection (choosing between
alternatives as a result of limited geographical resources), and retention (forces
that preserve certain geographical forms) (Darwin 1859; Van de Ven & Poole
1995). Evolutionary Process Theory is used to explain change as a recurrent and
accumulative progression of variation, selection and retention of geographical
entities. Being rooted in Charles Darwin’s 1859 The Origin of Species, this theory
emphasises a gradual and continuous process of evolution. Darwin wrote: ‘as
natural selection acts solely by accumulating slight, successive, favourable
variations, it can produce no great or sudden modifications; it can act only by
short and slow steps’ (1859:3). But how are traits inherited, and at what rate
does change occur? While some scholars argue that traits are inherited through
intergenerational processes (e.g. Hannan & Freeman 1977, 1989; McKelvey
1982), others claim that traits are acquired within a generation through
socialisation and acculturation (e.g. Burgelman 1991; Boyd & Richerson 1993;
Kuczynski & Navara 2006). Variations in traits account for differences in societal
and geographical evolution (from hunting and gathering to artificial intelligence,
and from rural areas to mega-cities).
Lifecycle Process Theory posits that change is a continuous process and every
stage of development is simply a preparation for future changes. Every entity
has within itself the capacity to regulate and propel change as determined by the
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
127
entity’s experience, rationality, and structure (Audretsch et al. 2008). An idea,
value, norm, or logic that defines a geographic location or a traditional society
progressively becomes more realised and mature through developmental processes.
External processes or a diffusion of ideas can influence how a geographic location
changes; but such external factors are often regulated by the immanent logic,
norms and values of an entity’s system (Van de Ven & Poole 1995).
Teleological Process Theory is used to analyse geographical changes by deliberate
social construction and reconstruction among members within a geographical
entity. In this type of process theory, change proceeds toward a goal, an
envisioned end state that has been constructed. Change or development is as a
result of repetitive sequences of goal formulation, implementation, assessment
and alteration based on geographic experience and intentions (Driver 1988; Van
de Ven & Poole 1995). A geographic unit that adapts faster or that establishes a
better relationship with other geographic entities changes more than others. The
Industrial Revolution that started in Britain due to its internal innovations and
then spread to other parts of the world, is a good example of this teleological
process. Although Teleology Process Theory emphasises the rationality of a
geographic unit as the driver for change, the theory also identifies certain
limitations. For example, geographical environment and resources constrain
what can be achieved. These constraints eventually serve as an opportunity for a
geographic entity to achieve its purpose through the process of working together
to overcome obstacles (Gibson 1988).
Urban Structure Theory
There is no better time to revisit Urban Structure Theory than the present,
characterised as it is by rapid urbanisation and development in different shades
and hues across the continents of the world. First propounded by sociologist
Ernest Burgess in 1924, the theory describes the rippling nature of cities’ growth.
For Burgess, a city’s expansion is represented in concentric rings in ways that
produce fragments of spatiality and settlement patterns, like the ripple effect
produced when a stone is thrown into water. These fragments move from the
innermost to the outermost part of the ring, from the central business district
to transitional districts, to the middle-class zones, with a last ring known as the
commuters’ area or suburb. In 1939, economist Homer Hoyt critiqued Burgess’s
position of fragmenting the city in rings. Hoyt argued that a city’s development
can only be be achieved by sectors. For him, different areas of the city are distinct
and have their strengths and weaknesses, making particular activities attractive in
those areas.
Geographers Chauncy Harris and Edward Ullman (1945) proposed what
they called the multiple-nuclei model of the city. According to them, this model
accentuates the attraction of activities to a city because it contains more than one
128
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
centre; clusters of activities are produced. In other words, and as theorised by
Hoover and Giarratani (1984), the siting of an institution or parastatal would
result in the emergence of other, related activities.
With the rapid proliferation of tangible and intangible phenomena (physical
structures, ideas, cultures, patterns, practices, etc.), the discourse of urban studies
and urbanisation is not only pertinent but has continued to occupy centre stage
in academic discourse.
Lynch (1981) espoused the evolutionary development and survival of a city.
Crucial to his position are elements such as the ecological and spatial patterns
of humans, communication networks, economic strength, multiple synergies of
interactions and social constructs that inform the continued metamorphosis of
an urban space.
Urban Structure Theory has relevance to the African context, especially when
economic, social and political parameters are considered. If we consider big cities
like Cairo, Lagos, Johannesburg, Nairobi and Accra., the indices for urban structure
are not only prominent but thriving. The spatial settlement patterns accentuate
inequalities that divide the rich from the poor. A further narrowing of the context
with specific emphasis on, say Lagos, gives more credence to the theory as the
city shows typical urban structures and constructions in housing, infrastructural,
economic, social and political configurations. These variables cannot be discussed
in isolation without linkages to globalisation, multiculturalism and government,
and the city’s policies, especially because housing policy determines the structures
that exist in the society.
The theory is not without limitations. For starters, the theory has only an
overarching focus on the developmental process that informs the prevalent urban
structures often found in developing countries. Also, it shows the oppositional
standing between countries of the global North and global South and not
what unites them. The theory highlights the processes that shape cities and its
proponents emphasise fragmented elements inherent in the theory’s discourse.
But from society to society, the dynamics are different in ways that defy the
idea of unitary formations (Banai & Rapino 2009). The structure cannot be
divorced holistically from the urban construct and the peculiar perceptions of
the people. Today, Urban Structure Theory is caught in the matrix of developed/
underdeveloped or high/low disparity that has continued to reinforce the rich/
poor dichotomy.
Urbanisation Models
Urbanisation Models are theoretical constructs that emerged with the rise of
industrialisation to help a city manage its use of space better. There are many
strands to this theory, although there are many convergences in ways of thinking
about a city. Four significant models are mentioned when talking of urbanisation
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
129
theory (Norton 1992). First is the Concentric Zone Model, also called the
Chicago Model, which was introduced at the beginning of the twentieth century
by Burgess. The model postulates that the business centre located around the
intersection of communication channels gives birth to cities. People come to do
business in the centre and rich people move out of the business centre to enjoy a
comfortable life.
Second is the Sector Model which was developed by Hoyt (1939). The model
claims that industries establish themselves along railway lines, well-connected
roads and canals to access the commodities needed for their businesses. In these
zones, businesses can easily acquire the goods necessary for their activities and
export the products of their industries to the zone of consumption.
Third is the Polycentric Model. This was developed by Harris and Ullman the
late 1940s. The model proposes that train stations, metro stations, airports and
ports produce many activities in a city and, therefore, each can become the centre
of a town.
Fourth and last is the New Urbanism Model. This was developed in the United
States in 1980. The model has as instigators a group of American architects whose
aim was the promotion of ecological and sustainable cities.
Health and Medicine
Germ Theory
The Germ Theory of health and medicine can be considered as the successor to
the Humoral Theory (see below). The germ theory contends that microorganisms
are the genesis of disease. These organisms are so small that they can only be seen
via a microscope. According to Germ Theory, infections are directly linked to the
entry of these microorganisms into the human body (Stewart 1968).
The pioneers of Germ Theory are Louis Pasteur, John Lister and Robert
Koch. They developed the idea that the changes in human cells and tissues that
affect human organs are because of microorganisms known as germs (Lagay
2002). As pointed out by Lagay (2002), Pasteur’s formulations examined airborne organisms; Lister oversaw the adoption of anti-septic surgical procedures ,
whereas Koch is credited with the discovery of the causes of tuberculosis as well
as cholera.
In an African context, Germ Theory is applicable in the use of traditional
medicine. Most African communities have community-based healers who use
special herbs to treat various infections. While these communities may not have
fully embraced Western medicine arising from Germ Theory research, they have
recognised that there are non-spiritual causes of diseases or infections and have
embraced some non-traditional African medicines to combat health problems.
130
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Germ Theory is considered the basis of modern medicine. By linking diseases
to infectious microorganisms, subsequent research focused on controlling them
and led to the development of antibiotics and other medications to combat
the diseases (Lagay 2002). With time, there has been a realisation that germs/
infections from microorganisms affect each person differently and, thus, it is
essential to focus on the medication administered to enhance efficiency.
Germ Theory simply links infection to a host of germs/microorganisms. The
theory, however, overlooks other aspects that can influence infection such as
behavioural, genetic and socioeconomic factors (Stewart 1968). The theory is also
challenged in some regions by religious beliefs; some religions do not believe in
the use of medicine to treat infections as they contend that illnesses are spiritual
and, thus, only spiritual intervention can result in healing.
Hippocratic Theory
The Hippocratic Theory of health and medicine concentrates on the causes of
diseases. Its dominance as a medical opinion reaches back 2,000 years. Hippocrates
of Kos (460–377 BC) believed that the body consists of four fluids or humours:
1.
2.
3.
4.
black bile,
yellow bile,
phlegm, and
blood.
He also believed that four elemental conditions controlled the body:
1.
2.
3.
4.
cold,
hot,
dry, and
moist (Wright 1920).
Hippocrates postulated that diseases emerge because of an imbalance of humours
in the body. A state of health exists when the humours are in balance. The balance
of wet, dry, cold and hot preserved health while the dominance of any one of
these elements produced disease (Wright 1920).
Hippocrates is regarded as the father of modern medicine. He introduced
the term ‘epidemic’ that is still used in contemporary epidemiological practices
(Wright 1920). This theory emanated from observations of clinical signs and then
drawing a rational conclusion. Hippocrates discounted the belief of the time that
supernatural forces caused diseases. A physician had to diagnose the imbalance
of humours and facilitate a healing process through bleeding (bloodletting) or
surgery (Wilson 2006). To achieve the state of balance, a physician is supposed to
first examine the patient, observe symptoms carefully, draw a conclusion, make
a diagnosis, and then treat the patient. It is through Hippocratic Theory that
medical science established the basics of clinical medicine that are now universally
applicable (Wright 1920).
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
131
Bloodletting is widely practised in Africa; also, many African societies perform
purging: for example, mothers suck nostrils of toddlers to remove the mucus in
order to get rid of blockages. Induced vomiting is also practised in Africa, where
concoctions are mixed to remove ingested poison or to settle a stomach upset.
Hippocratic Theory taught people that sickness had a natural cause – a rational
and scientific view rather than superstitious (Wilson 2006). But one could not
pinpoint what made one humour dominate the others. Hippocrates associated
imbalance with improper diet and bodily injury. The theory did not inform the
Hippocratic physician of the cause of the disease or illness; they often knew only
the effects. The theory failed to show the correct amount of fluid one was to draw
from various organs to reach the state of balance (Carrick 2001).
Humoral Theory
The Humoral Theory attempts to demystify the human body by defining the
cardinal fluids in it. The fluids, as stated in the previous section, include blood,
yellow bile, black bile, and phlegm. According to the theory, there are four
humours with each linked to a different body organ and season. According to
proponents of this theory, black bile is related with spleen and autumn, yellow
bile with the liver and summer, phlegm with the brain and winter, and blood is
linked to the heart and spring (Sebers 2016). The theory further contends that
every human being is defined by two contrasting qualities:
1. hot vs dry and
2. moist vs cold.
The maintenance of equilibrium for these fluids is distinct in each individual and
defines the person’s health. Any deviation from this would lead to illness (Sebers 2016).
The genesis of this theory is traceable to the pre-Greek period; nevertheless,
Hippocrates of Kos later reworked it into the Hippocratic Humoral Theory. The
overriding factor that characterised the beliefs of the pioneers of this theory was
the departure from the belief that diseases were caused by supernatural forces.
According to this theory, diseases result from an imbalance of the fluids in the
body. The treatment is thus possible by reversing these imbalances (Bos 2009).
Galen, 600 years after Hippocrates, did some additional work on the Humoral
Theory. He espoused that a combination of humours could impact human
moods, emotions and behaviours.
One of the practices associated with the Humoral Theory is bloodletting
(plethora). This involves making an incision into an artery, allowing blood to
flow out. According to humoralist theorists, this practice would remove illness
from the body and the fluid balances of the body would be restored, leading
to a subsequent recovery (Thomas 2014). This practice started in Egypt before
spreading to Greece, Europe and other regions. Some North African countries
still practice bloodletting to treat infections such as pneumonia (Thomas 2014).
132
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The major strength of the Humoral Theory is that it discarded the notion that
diseases are attributable to supernatural causes. Based on the belief that illnesses
resulted from an imbalance of the four humours and the subsequent efforts to
restore this balance in the human being, a foundation for modern medicine was
laid down (Kushner 2012). Humoral Theory provided a platform to understand
the human body from a medical perspective as opposed to the religious viewpoint,
as was commonly practiced.
A major limitation of this theory is the numerous deaths that resulted from
the bloodletting exercise. Although there were other forms of regaining the fluid
balance in the body such as induced vomiting or improved hygiene, bloodletting
was the most common exercise and, in some cases, it proved fatal (Thomas 2014).
References
Abumere, Sylvester I., 1978, ‘Multinationals, Location Theory and Regional
Development: Case Study of Bendel State of Nigeria’, Regional Studies, Vol. 12,
No. 6, pp. 651–664.
Altemus, M.; Deuster, P.A.; Galliven, E.; Carter, C.S. and Gold, P.W., 1995, ‘Suppression
of hypothalmic-pituitary-adrenal axis responses to stress in lactating women’, The
Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism, Vol. 80, No. 10, pp. 2954–9.
Audretsch, David; Falck, Oliver; Feldman, Maryann and Heblich, Stephan, 2008, ‘The
Lifecycle of Regions’, CEPR Discussion Papers, No. 6757.
Banai, Reza and Rapino, Melanie A., 2009, ‘Urban Theory since “A Theory of Good City
Form” (1981) – A Progress Review’, Journal of Urbanism: International Research on
Placemaking and Urban Sustainability, Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 259–276.
Bijak, Jakub, 2006, ‘Forecasting International Migration: Selected Theories, Models, and
Methods’, CEFMR Working Paper, No. 4/2006. (http://www.cefmr.pan.pl/docs/
cefmr_wp_2006-04.pdf ). 26 September 2021.
Booth, Alan; Carver, Karen and Granger, Douglas A., 2000, ‘Biosocial Perspectives on
the Family’, Journal of Marriage and Family, Vol. 62, No. 4, pp. 1018–1034.
Bos, Jacques, 2009, ‘The Rise and Decline of Character: Humoral Psychology in Ancient
and Early Modern Medical Theory’, History of the Human Sciences, Vol. 22, No. 3,
pp. 29–50.
Boyd, Robert and Richerson, Peter J., 1993, ‘Rationality, Imitation, and Tradition’,
in R.H. Day and P. Chen, eds., Nonlinear Dynamics and Evolutionary Economics,
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Brenner, Neil; Madden, David J. and Wachsmuth, David, 2011, ‘Assemblage Urbanism
and the Challenges of Critical Urban Theory’, City, Vol. 15, No. 2, pp. 225–240.
Burgelman, Robert A., 1991, ‘Intraorganizational Ecology of Strategy Making and
Organizational Adaptation: Theory and Field Research’, Organization Science,
Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 239–262.
Burgess, Ernest W., 1924, ‘The Growth of the City: An Introduction to a Research
Project’, Publications of the American Sociological Society, Vol. 18, pp. 85–97.
Cairns, Robert, B.; Gariépy, Jean-Louis and Hood, Kathryn E., 1990, ‘Development,
Microevolution, and Social Behavior’, Psychological Review, Vol. 97, No. 1, pp. 49–65.
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
133
Carrick, Paul, 2001, Medical Ethics in the Ancient World, Washington, DC: Georgetown
University Press.
Chakir, Raja and Lungarska, Anna, 2015, ‘Agricultural Land Rents in Use Models: A
Spatial Econometric Analysis’, Paper Prepared for Presentation at the 150th EAAE
Seminar, Scotland’s Rural College, Edinburgh, Scotland, October 22–23, 2015.
Dai, Wenqian, 2016, ‘Demographic Transition’, Encyclopedia of Family Studies, 2016,
pp.
1–6.
(https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781119085621.
wbefs411). 24 September 2021.
Darwin, Charles, 1859, The Origin of Species; and, the Descent of Man, Giant, NY: Modern
Library.
Dennison, Stanley Raymond, 1939, The Location of Industry and the Depressed Areas,
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Diamond, Adele, 2009, ‘The Interplay of Biology and the Environment Broadly Defined’,
Developmental Psychology, Vol. 45, pp. 1–9.
Dicken, Peter, 2007, Global Shift: Mapping the Changing Contours of the World Economy,
5th edition, London, UK: Sage Publications.
D’Onofrio, Brian M. and Lahey, Benjamin B., 2010, ‘Biosocial Influences on the Family:
A Decade Review’, Journal of Marriage and Family, Vol. 72, No. 3, pp. 762–782.
Driver, Felix, 1988, ‘The Historicity of Human Geography’, Progress in Human Geography,
Vol. 12, No. 4, pp. 497–506.
Ehrman, Lee and Parsons, Peter A., 1981, Behavior Genetics and Evolution, New York,
NY: McGraw-Hill.
Frazier, Leslie D., 2020, ‘The Past, Present, and Future of the Biopsychosocial Model: A
Review of “The Biopsychosocial Model of Health and Disease: New Philosophical
and Scientific Developments” by Derek Bolton and Grant Gillett’, New Ideas in
Psychology, Vol. 57, No. 100755, pp. 1–4.
Freese, Jeremy, 2008, ‘Genetics and the Social Science Explanation of Individual
Outcomes’, American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 114 Suppl., pp. S1–S35.
Freese, Jeremy, Li; Jui-Chung Allen and Wade, Lisa D., 2003, ‘The Potential Relevances of
Biology to Social Inquiry’, Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 29, No. 1, pp. 233–256.
Friedman, Thomas L., 2005, The World is Flat: The Globalized World in the Twenty-First
Century, London, UK: Penguin.
Germenis, A.E.; Margaglione, M.; Pesquero, J.B.; Farkas, H.; Cichon, S.; Csuka, D.; Lera,
A.L.; Rijavec, M.; Jolles, S.; Szilagyi, A.; Trascasa, M.L.; Veronez, C.L.; Drouet, C.;
Zamanakou, M. and Hereditary Angioedema International Working Group, 2020,
‘International Consensus on the Use of Genetics in the Management of Hereditary
Angioedema’, The Journal of Allergy and Clinical Immunology: In Practice, Vol. 8,
No. 3, pp. 901–911. (doi.org/10.1016/J.JAIP.2019.10.004). 24 September 2021.
Hannan, Michael T. and Freeman, John 1977, ‘The Population Ecology of Organizations’,
American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 82, No. 5, pp. 929–964.
Hannan, Michael T. and Freeman, John, 1989, Organizational Ecology, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Harris, Chauncy D. and Ullman, Edward L., 1945, ‘The Nature of Cities’, Annals of the
American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 242, pp. 7–17.
134
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Harvey, David, 1981, ‘The Spatial Fix – Hegel, Von Thunen and Marx’, Antipode,
Vol. 13, No. 3, pp. 1–12.
Hoover, Edgar Malone and Giarratani, Frank, 1984, An Introduction to Regional
Economics, New York, NY: Alfred Knopf.
Hoyt, Homer, 1939, The Structure and Growth of Residential Neighborhoods in American
Cities, Washington, DC: Federal Housing Administration.
Hsu, Hua, 2017, ‘Stuart Hall and the Rise of Cultural Studies’, The New Yorker. (https://
www.newyorker.com/books/page-turner/stuart-hall-and-the-rise-of-culturalstudies). 24 September 2021.
Isard, Walter, 1960, Methods of Regional Analysis: An Introduction to Regional Science, New
York, NY: John Wiley.
Isard, Walter and Liossatos, Panagis, 1972, ‘On Location Analysis for Urban and Regional
Growth Situations’, The Annals of Regional Science, Vol. 6, No. 1, pp. 1–27.
James, Preston E. and Martin, Geoffrey J., 1981, All Possible Worlds: A History of
Geographical Ideas, New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Kendler, Kenneth S. and Baker, Jessica H., 2006, ‘Genetic Influences on Measures of
the Environment: A Systematic Review’, Psychological Medicine, Vol. 37, No. 5,
pp. 615–626.
Kim, S.; Fonagy, P.; Koos, O.; Dorsett, K. and Strathearn, L. ‘Maternal oxytocin response
predicts mother-to-infant gaze’, Brain Research, Vol. 1580, pp. 133–142.
Kirk, Dudley, 1996, ‘Demographic Transition Theory’, Population Studies, Vol. 50,
No. 3, pp. 361–387.
Kuchhal, Suresh Chandra, 1981, Industrial Economy of India, Allahabad, India: Chaitanya
Publishing House.
Kuczynski, Leon and Navara, Geoffrey S., 2006, Sources of Innovation and Change in
Socialization, Internalization and Acculturation: Handbook of Moral Development,
London, UK: Taylor and Francis Group.
Kupiszewski, Marek, 2002, The Role of International Migration in the Modelling
of Population Dynamics, Warsaw, Poland: Institute of Geography and Spatial
Organization, Polish Academy of Sciences.
Kushner, Irving, 2012, ‘The 4 Humors and Erythrocyte Sedimentation: The Most
Influential Observation in Medical History’, The American Journal of the Medical
Sciences, Vol. 346, No. 2, pp. 154–157.
Lagay, Faith, 2002, ‘The Legacy of Humoral Medicine’, Virtual Mentor, Vol. 4, No. 7, p. ii.
(https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/article/legacy-humoral-medicine/2002-07).
26 September 2021.
Larkin, Gerald, 1983, Occupational Monopoly and Modern Medicine, London, UK: Taylor
& Francis.
Lichtenberg, Erik, 1989, ‘Land Quality, Irrigation Development and Cropping Patterns
in the Northern High Plains’, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, Vol. 71,
pp. 187–194.
Lynch, Kevin, 1981, A Theory of Good City Form, Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts
Institute of Technology Press.
McCann, Larry, ed. 1987. Heartland and Hinterland: Canadian Regions in Evolution.
Toronto: Prentice-Hall.
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
135
McKelvey, Bill, 1982, Organizational Systematics – Taxonomy, Evolution, Classification,
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Miller, Douglas J. and Plantinga, Andrew J., 1999, ‘Modelling Land Use Decisions
with Aggregate Data’, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, Vol. 81, No. 1,
pp. 180–194.
Mitchell, Don, 2000, Cultural Geography, Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers.
Nafziger, E. Wayne, 2012, Economic Development, 5th edition, Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Norton, William, 1992, Human Geography. Toronto, Canada: Oxford University Press.
Nickel, Stefan and Puerto, Justo, 2006, Location Theory: A Unified Approach, Berlin,
Germany: Springer Science & Business Media.
Nnamdi, Oguji and Owusu, Richard, 2014, ‘Africa as a Source Location: Literature
Review and Implications’, International Journal of Emerging Markets, Vol. 9, No. 3,
pp. 424–438.
Odimegwu, Clifford O.; De Wet, Nicole; Adedini, Sunday A.; Nzimande, Nompumelelo;
Appunni, Sathiyasusuman and Dube, Tanyaradzwa, 2020, ‘Family Demography in
Sub-Saharan Africa: A Systematic Review of Family Research’, African Populations
Studies, Vol. 31, No. 1, pp. 9–56.
Ogbuagu, Chibuzo, 1985, ‘The Politics of Industrial Location in Nigeria’, Africa
Development/Afrique et Développement, Vol. 10, No. 4, pp. 97–122.
Oswell, David, 2010, ‘Cultural Theory: Genealogies, Orientations and Territories’, in D.
Oswell, ed., Cultural Theory, Volume I: Legacies and Innovations, Los Angeles, CA:
Sage Publication.
Pereira, M. Graça and Smith, Thomas Edward, 2006, ‘Evolution of the Biopsychosocial
Model in the Practice of Family Therapy’ International Journal of Clinical and Health
Psychology, Vol. 6, No. 2, pp. 455–467.
Pietak, Lukasz, 2014, ‘Review of Theories and Models of Economic Development’,
Comparative Economic Research, Vol. 17, No. 1, pp. 45–60.
Plantinga, Andrew J., 1996, ‘The Effect of Agricultural Policies on Land Use and
Environmental Quality’, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, Vol. 78,
No. 4, pp. 1082–1091.
Poot, Jacques; Alimi, Omoniyi; Cameron, Michael P. and Maré, David C., 2016, ‘The
gravity model of migration: the successful comeback of an ageing superstar in
regional science’, INVESTIGACIONES REGIONALES – Journal of REGIONAL
RESEARCH, Asociación Española de Ciencia Regional, Vol. 36, pp. 63–86.
Predöhl, Andreas, 1928, ‘The Theory of Location in its Relation to General Economics’,
Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 36, No. 3, pp. 371–390.
Robinson, Warren, C., 1964, ‘The Development of Modern Population Theory’, The
American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Vol. 23, No. 4, pp. 375–392.
Rosière, Stephane, 2001, ‘Proposition pour une distinction opératoire entre la géographie,
la géographie politique et la géopolitique’, L’information Géographique, Vol. 65,
No. 1, pp. 33–42.
Rostow, Walt Whitman, 1959, ‘The Stages of Economic Growth’, The Economic History
Review, Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 1–16.
136
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Rostow, Walt Whitman, 1960, The Stages of Economic Development: A Non-Communist
Manifesto, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Rostow, Walt Whitman, 1971, Politics and Stages of Development, Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Rutter, Michael; Moffitt, Terrie E. and Caspi, Avshalom, 2006, ‘Gene-environment
Interplay and Psychopathology: Multiple Varieties but Real Effects’, Journal of Child
Psychology and Psychiatry, Vol. 47, No. 3–4, pp. 226–261.
Schumpeter, Joseph Alois, 1934, The Theory of Economic Development, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Sebers, Riley, 2016, ‘What’s Your Temperament: The Humoral Theory’s Influence on
Medicine in Ancient Greece’, Young Historians Conference, Vol. 12. (https://pdxscholar.
library.pdx.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1095&context=younghistorians).
26 September 2021.
Seringhaus, Michael and Gerstein, Mark, 2008, ‘Genomics Confounds Gene
Classification’, American Scientist, Vol. 96, No. 6, pp. 466–472.
Serrat, Oliver, 2008, Culture Theory, Asian Development Bank. (https://ecommons.
cornell.edu/handle/1813/87360). 24 September 2021.
Sheppard, Eric, S., 1979, ‘Spatial Interaction and Geographic Theory’, in G. Olsson and
S. Gale, eds., Philosophy in Geography, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.
Singh, Inderjit, Squire, Lyn and Strauss, John, 2019, ‘A Survey of Agricultural Household
Models: Recent Findings and Policy’, The World Bank Economic Review, Vol. 1,
No. 1, pp. 149–179.
Skeldon, Ronald, 2013, ‘Global Migration: Demographic Aspects and its Relevance
for Development’, Technical Paper, No. 2013/6, New York, NY: United Nations
Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Population Division.
Stavins, Robert N. and Jaffe, Adam B., 1990, ‘Unintended Impacts of Public Investments
on Private Decisions: The Depletion of Forested Wetlands’, American Economic
Review, Vol. 80, No. 3, pp. 337–352.
Stewart, G.T., 1968, ‘The Limitations of the Germ Theory’, The Lancet, Vol. 291,
No. 7551, pp. 1077–1081.
Stewart, John Quincy, 1941, ‘An Inverse Distance Variation for Certain Social Influence’,
Science, Vol. 93, No. 2404, pp. 89–90.
Stoddard, R.H.; Wishart, D.J. and Blouet, B.W., 1986, Human Geography: People, Place,
and Cultures, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Switzer, Les, 1986, ‘Cultural Studies and African Culture’, Cahiers d’Etudes Africaines,
Vol. 101–102, pp. 257–263.
Thomas, D.P., 2014, ‘The Demise of Bloodletting’, The Journal of the Royal College of
Physicians of Edinburgh, Vol. 44, No. 1, pp. 72–77.
Troost, Kay Michael and Filsinger, Erik, 2009, ‘Emerging Biosocial Perspectives on the
Family’, in Pauline Boss; William J. Doherty; Ralph LaRossa; Walter R. Schumm
and Suzanne K. Steinmetz, eds., Sourcebook of Family Theories and Methods:
A Contextual Approach, Boston, MA: Springer.
Udry, J. Richard; Morris, Naomi M. and Kovenock, Judith, 1995, ‘Androgen Effects
on Women’s Gendered Behavior’, Journal of Biosocial Science, Vol. 27, No. 3,
pp. 359–368.
Doctoral Scholars: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine
137
United Nations Development Programme (UNDP), 2016, Agricultural Growth and
Transformation, New York, NY: UNDP Publications.
Van de Ven, Andrew, H. and Poole, Marshall Scott, 1995, ‘Explaining Development
and Change in Organizations’, The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 20, No. 3,
pp. 510–540.
Verhelst, Thierry and Tyndale, Wendy, 2002, ‘Cultures, Spirituality and Development’,
in D. Eade, ed., Development and Culture, Oxford, UK: Oxfam.
Walther, A.; Tsao, C.; Pande, R.; Kirschbaum, C.; Field, E. and Berkman, L., 2019,
‘Do dehydroepiandrosterone, progesterone, and testosterone influence women’s
depression and anxiety levels? Evidence from hair-based hormonal measures of 2105
rural Indian women’, Psychoneuroendocrinology. Vol. 109, pp. 104382.
Weber, Alfred, 1929, Theory of the Location of Industries, Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
Weber, Max, 1946, From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, translated and edited by H.H.
Gerth and C.W. Mills, New York, NY: Routledge.
Wright, Jonathan, 1920, ‘The Origin of Hippocratic Theory in Some of the Science of the
Nature Philosophers’, The Scientific Monthly, Vol. 11, No. 2, pp. 127–140.
Wu, JunJie and Segerson, Kathleen, 1995, ‘The Impact of Policies and Land Characteristics
on Potential Groundwater Pollution in Wisconsin’, American Journal of Agricultural
Economics, Vol. 77, pp. 1033–1047.
Wilson, Nigel, 2006, ed., Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece, New York, NY: Routledge.
Zelinsky, Wilbur, 1971, ‘The Hypothesis of the Mobility Transition’, Geographical Review,
Vol. 61, No. 2, pp. 219–249.
Zipf, George Kingsley, 1946, ‘The P1P2/D Hypothesis: On the Intercity Movement of
Persons’, American Sociological Review, Vol. 11, No. 6, pp. 677–686.
Zlotnik, Hania, 1998, ‘The Theories of International Migration’, Paper for the Conference
on International Migration: Challenges for European Populations, Bari, Italy,
June 25–27, 1998.
5
Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
Doctoral Scholars
Summaries of nine language and linguistics and four law and order theories are
provided in this chapter. The theories on language and linguistics explore methods
of human communication, either spoken or written, consisting of the use of
words in a structured and conventional way, and the scientific study of these
features. Those on law and order examine the system of rules which a particular
country or community recognises as regulating the actions of its members and
which it may enforce by the imposition of penalties, and a state in which the
laws and rules regulating the public behaviour of members of a community are
observed and authority is obeyed.
Language and Linguistics
Deficit Hypothesis
The Deficit Hypothesis, also known as the Deprivation Hypothesis, is the
theoretical view that some children are handicapped linguistically because they
belong to a societal collective with a deficient body of languages (Broughton et
al. 1978). Bernstein (1973) defines the theory as a set of propositions which try
to explain failure in education by tracing its roots to the learner’s community
and family. Therefore, deficit theorists hold that socially stratified educational
attainment is a result of differences between languages spoken by working class
or lower class and by middle-class families (Jones 2013). Deficit Hypothesis
distinguishes between the languages of learners from the middle class and the
lower class. According to Halliday (1978), Bernstein’s Deficit Hypothesis is
about societal persistence and change. It is a theory of the processes and nature of
cultural transmission and the important role of language therein.
The concept of ‘elaborated and restricted language codes’ was proposed by
Basil Bernstein in 1971 (for details, see Bernstein 1973). Bernstein was from
140
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
an education background and attempted to explain the reason behind the
underperformance of lower-class students in languages compared to learners from
the middle class. According to Bernstein, lower-class language was deficient in
comparison to middle-class language. His theory directly correlates language and
learners’ social backgrounds and proposes that a learner’s social class determines
his or her competence and proficiency in language use. This implies that an
individual’s social class determines the extent of his or her level of proficiency in
the language used in the society. Bernstein’s 1973 theory was later tagged Deficit
Hypothesis by his critics (Ajayi 2015).
In the African context, the Deficit Hypothesis can be applied in several ways.
Social class is perceived as a form of culture whereby individuals’ behaviours,
manners and etiquette are dictated by the societal classes in which they
belong. This can be seen in the health sector, where access to health facilities is
dependent upon the social class of individuals, resulting in the glaring disparities
in healthcare in most countries. It has been noted that lower-class individuals
are more vulnerable to physical diseases and psychological hardships than their
middle-class counterparts because the former have limited access to health
services. People from the lower classes have a higher risk of long-term and shortterm health conditions in comparison to their middle-class counterparts (Ajayi
2015). African countries are also increasingly focusing on the provision of better
and affordable healthcare to citizens, irrespective of social class.
The Deficit Hypothesis triggered discussions about the connections between
the school, family and social backgrounds of learners, resulting in ongoing debates
in the education sector advocating for joint efforts to ensure leaners’ success.
The Deficit Theory has been criticised for being in favour of, and biased
towards, the middle class (Labov 1972). There is a feeling that the theory
misrepresents lower-class children’s verbal capabilities (Labov 1968). Bernstein’s
theory assumes that learners who have poor language skills will inevitably be poor
performers, irrespective of other internal variables (Muvindi & Zuvalinyenga
2013). Bernstein’s work is not in support of, and even opposes, an explanation
of the failure of students as a result of deprivation or cultural deficits (Atkinson
1995). Karabel and Halsey (1977) are in support of this view and they construe
Bernstein’s work as directing the attention of the reader away from school
processes that influence the failure or success of learners who come to school
from different linguistic backgrounds and social classes.
Guthrie’s Association Theory
In linguistics, Guthrie’s Association Theory, also referred to as Contiguity
Theory, is used to compare the historical developments and the pros and cons of
uncertain linguistic evidence in language learning. The focus of users of the theory
in linguistic inquiry has been to identify the consequences of the connection
Doctoral Scholars: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
141
between a specific stimulus and response for learning a language, especially in a
classroom setting. According to the theory, a multiplicity of stimuli accompanied
by movement will, when repeated, result in learning.
Edwin Ray Guthrie (1886–1955), the initiator of the theory and after
whom it is named, advocated that the process of learning occurs as a result of
the interaction between a specific stimulus and response. Guthrie contends that
stimuli and responses will result in specific sensory-motor patterns. The learning
process results in movements, not behaviours. Guthrie argues that the simple
association within a given period of an external stimulus and a behavioural
response is enough for human beings or animals to connect the two mental
activities (Guthrie & Horton 1946).
The general test of the theory was first done on cats to observe them trying
to get out of a puzzle box fitted with glass panels. The box took photographs of
the cats as they attempted to move out of the box. Images of the cats’ movements
resulting in the same sequence of events were captured, leading to the conclusion
that improvement can only occur when unnecessary movements are discarded or
excluded from sequential activities (Guthrie & Horton 1946).
In the context of Africa, Guthrie’s theory could be applicable in the process
of bringing about change within societies, organisations, and individuals. The
continent has many countries run by dictatorships, some of which could be
changed, for instance, by citizens deciding to vote along non-ethnic lines. The
same is needed to deal with corruption and bad governance within organisations
and or with the negative behaviour of certain individuals. Guthrie’s theory is a
strong base for achieving cognitive-oriented learning where individuals can learn
from past mistakes and bring about the required changes.
Guthrie’s Association Theory can be criticised for extending the misconception
that the relationship between stimulus and movement must occur repeatedly for
a required action to occur. In reality, in some cases, one action is enough for
learning to take place.
Metalingual Theory
The Metalingual Theory refers to the use of a language to explain itself. In the
statement ‘God has three letters’, language is being used to explain itself. Tribus
(2017) defines metalinguistic function as one that is used to explain grammatical
or semantic constructs. According to Russian-American linguist and literary
theorist Roman Jakobson (1960), the metalingual role works whenever parties
in a conversation are triggered to confirm whether they are using the same code:
the people in the conversation are deriving meaning by using codes. Jakobson
(1960) uses the term ‘code’ to refer to signs that help language users to reference
their signifiers distinctively and consistently. While there is consistency among
the descriptions of the metalingual function offered by various scholars and
142
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
researchers (i.e. confirmation of code), linguists vary in their definitions of the
term ‘code’. Martin and Ringham (2006) describe the metalingual function as
communication that orients itself by confirming the code used. The authors
describe the code as the lexical meaning in a verbal text or number symbolism –
for instance, in a mathematical discourse.
Metalingual Theory is one of the subareas that deal with communicative
functions in the field of Linguistics. The theory was named and developed
by Jakobson (1960) as an extension of Bronisław Kasper Malinowski’s Phatic
Communion Theory (see below). Jakobson differentiates the metalinguistic
function from five other language functions:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
phatic,
referential,
poetic,
conative, and
emotive.
Angela Tribus (2017) defines the metalinguistic function as one where utterances
are not only characterised by codes but also used to explain grammatical or
semantic constructs, provide individuals with tools to monitor their own
learning, and to clarify misinterpretations. With differing meanings of ‘code’ as
a key concept of the theory, there would be obviously diverging interpretations,
usages, and applications.
A metalanguage is a necessary scientific tool used by logicians and linguists
in the Western world and in Africa. It comes into play in everyday language. For
instance, it is a key component of early language for children who are learning to
speak their mother or native tongues and for second language acquisition.
In Jakobson’s communicative function model, the metalingual role is defined
as one that deals with shared communication problems due to the variety of
the codes used. The metalingual function can be used to not only address code
problems but also to correct speech errors (the substitution of a chosen lexical
item by another one that the speaker feels is more appropriate in terms of his or
her intended meaning, etc.). In other words, the metalingual function should be
understood to include code-directed activity that may be either interactional or
speaker-oriented (Jakobson 1960).
Phatic Communion Theory
The phatic concept refers to verbal communication between the hearer and speaker
with the purpose of maintaining a social relationship. The communication does
not necessarily emphasise the conveyance of meaning and information content.
The concept of phatic communion was pioneered by British anthropologist
Bronislaw Malinowski in 1923. Malinowski (1923) described phatic communion
as aimless social intercourse: inquiries about health, comments on the weather,
Doctoral Scholars: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
143
greeting formulas, etc. The approach birthed by Malinowski (1923) became a
theoretical foundation for research on the functions of language and gave rise to
other phatic-related theories.
The Phatic Communion Theory describes a type of discourse that is different
from the conventional one where there must be a conveyance of information.
It describes a social function of language where it is used to establish or keep
an interactive contact between individuals through the flow and exchange of
purposeless and aimless words or ‘vocables’.
Jakobson (1960) defines Phatic Communion Theory in terms of the phatic
function of language, which emphasises the existence of contact between the
receiver (hearer) and sender (speaker) of a message. Tribus (2017) defines phatic
communion as a function of language that deals with the connection between
two speakers. Its key goal is to establish/create, extend, prove, confirm, or cease
the connection, and may comprise of phrases like ‘really?’ ‘Uh-huh’ ‘have a nice
day’ (what is generally referred to as small talk). Commonly, it is used to establish
social relationships (Tribus 2017). Jakobson (1960) extended and modified
Malinowski’s concept, describing it as a function of bonding and as a function
of language which is channel-oriented in that it contributes to the establishment
and maintenance of communicative contact.
Velghe (2014) demonstrates how impoverished communities of Westbank
Township near Cape Town in South Africa use phatic communication and a
sustained connected presence as critical strategies of social networking. In a
situation of impoverishment, aloneness, unemployment and tedium, the use of
phatic communicational expressions or ‘vocables’ such as a text message or a short
phone call forms one of the many coping tactics that the residents in Westbank
use to deal with the harsh conditions of poverty and insecurity.
Most writers and researchers consider phatic communion and phatic
communication as similar concepts; nevertheless, the terms are differentiated,
with the former describing the seeking of rapport or a social bond while the latter
achieves a social contact. Malinowski’s work involved a more exact description
of a field of communication that had not until then been clearly identified and
extended in the review of the functions of language. Nonetheless, as Laver (1975)
argues, the very act of description and identification provided by Malinowski
hindered further inquiry as a result of the traditional excessive focus of linguistics
on the review of form at the expense of a deeper insight into the communicative
functions and realisations of phatic communion.
Rhetic Theory
Rhetic Theory, also called Rhetic Act Theory, is characterised as a linguistic
phenomenon responsible for functions in language usage, such as designating
reference to texts or conversations; resolving the use of deictic words, expressions,
144
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
and utterances; and removing uncertainty from meaning in utterance-inscription
either lexically or grammatically. Odebode and Dabi (2015) define rhetic acts as
one of three subsets of locutionary acts. The other two subsets are:
1. phonetic acts and
2. phatic acts.
According to Thau (1972), rhetic acts use ‘vocables’ with a more or less welldefined perception of sense and reference or allusion. Within the locutionary
act, one can differentiate the phatic and rhetic concepts by marking the former
with oratio recta quotation marks (direct speech) and the latter with indirect
quotations. Thau (1972) says that a rhetic act occurs when individuals utter
‘phemes’ (i.e. words or sentences) with certain specific meanings that have the
most preferential philosophical senses of those words. In sum, Rhetic Theory
focuses on the specific or particular sense or reference.
Rhetic Theory was developed and pioneered by British philosopher of
language John Langshaw Austin (1911–1960) and described in the 1962 book
titled How to Do Things with Words compiled by his students. Many researchers
have defined the theory by differentiating it from illocutionary and locutionary
acts. Searle (1968) describes locutionary as voicing a sentence with a distinct
meaning, with connotation or meaning, which Austin (1962) characterises as
sense and reference, while an illocutionary act is defined as uttering a sentence
with a certain force. Whichever approach is used to describe the Rhetic Theory,
reference, sense, and connotation are key concepts.
The application of Rhetic Theory is limited because it is not well researched
and studied. Rhetic theory was applied by Moltmann (2016) in a study that
proposed a specific way of conceptualising the idea of a rhetic act. The study says
the rheric act is well-reflected in the semantics of natural language, specifically
in the semantics of verbs of saying and particular sorts of plural noun phrases
in English (and German). The author further established a novel semantics of
quotation by making crucial use of Austin’s differentiations among lower-level
linguistic acts, a semantics that promises a unified and compositional semantics
of quotation. Generally, a rhetic act or concept is used in the semantics of natural
language mainly to provide meaning and reference.
The distinction between Rhetic Theory and locutionary or illocutionary
acts is unclear. This situation has led to many differing distinctions, with
Odebode and Dabi (2015) classifying it as a locutionary act while Thau (1972)
has classified it as illocutionary act. Also, both Searle (1968) and Cohen (1964)
endeavour to demonstrate that, at least in some cases, the illocutionary force
of an utterance cannot be differentiated from the meaning of an utterance.
The two authors believe that the rhetic and illocutionary acts cannot be
differentiated. Searle (1968) rebuff Austin’s description of the rhetic act
and Cohen (1964) rejects Austin’s notion of the illocutionary act. Typically,
unclear distinctions lead to divergence in the interpretations of the concept.
Doctoral Scholars: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
145
Rhetorical Theory
Rhetorical Theory was developed by Aristotle (384–322 BC). The literature is
however not clear about the year in which the theory was developed (Burke 1969).
The term rhetoric refers to the method of bringing about action or the
formation of attitude in others (Burke 1969). Rhetoric is also defined as the ability
to see what is possibly persuasive in every given case (Rhetoric I–II, 1355b26f.).
Rhetorical practices constitute varying styles of persuasion or influence. Persuasion
refers to altering the attitudes of others or causing them to act in a manner that
they would otherwise not do on their own. Aristotle describes three types of
persuasion or appeal that speakers can use to influence their audience. These are:
1. logos – using sound and reasonable arguments to appeal to the audience’s
sense of logic;
2. ethos – drawing upon a speaker’s own character or credibility; and
3. pathos – the speaker appealing to the emotional investment of the audience
on a subject (Aristotle 1954).
In African countries, Rhetorical Theory can be used to provide insights into
the forces that influence and persuade people to work in cooperation within
organisations otherwise believed to be dysfunctional. Organisations have leaders
who are hardworking, intelligent and competent individuals. Nevertheless,
it is common to find that the organisations they lead are dysfunctional as
a result of inherent or external forces (Demkiw 2010). Rhetorical Theory
can be useful in understanding the causes of the dysfunctions of the modern
organisational environment.
The theory is also applicable during national campaigns where politicians
use persuasive language and calculated actions to persuade citizens to vote in
their favour.
The limitation for this theory lies in the diversity of methods used by
rhetoricians to examine rhetorical discourses to comprehend how they operate
to influence audiences (Demkiw 2010). The goal is to understand the rhetorical
processes that influence communication between people, to understand the
people being persuaded, and to gain insights into the nature of their persuasions.
Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis
As mentioned in Chapter 2, the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis states that there are
certain thoughts of humans expressed in language that cannot be understood by
another individual living in another cultural context (Kay & Kempton 1984).
The hypothesis claims that the mental state of a person is strongly determined by
his/her mother tongue. To be more precise, the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis posits
that the structure of a language itself affects the cognition procedures of its user
(Kay & Kempton 1984).
146
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis was developed by Edward Sapir in 1929 and
later advanced by his student Benjamin Whorf in the 1950s. The hypothesis has
been important for African scholars attempting to break free of the tentacles of
Western domination. For example, Mwalimu Ali Al’Amin Mazrui in an article
titled ‘Language and the Quest for Liberation of Africa: The Legacy of Frantz
Fanon’ (1993) maintains that an African language is a reservoir of culture which
contains the paths of human thought. He claims that language influences
the way we perceive reality, evaluate ourselves, and arrange our conduct. For
African liberation to be real and complete, Mwalimu Mazrui believes that there
is a need to make use of African languages. In his 1995 book titled Nations
Nègres et Culture, Cheikh Anta Diop states that African languages are useful for
Africans to better understand the world and manage themselves. He shows how
it is possible to use those languages, taking the example of Wolof, to deal with
sophisticated scientific notions like Einstein’s theory of relativity.
Despite the many criticisms against the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis by Noam
Chomski and other scholars, some believe that it has relevance. In fact, categorical
perceptions seem to be language dependent. Overall, the scientific community
has validated the statement that language can at certain moments influence the
thoughts of a person (Robertson, Davies & Davidoff 2000).
Tolman’s Sign-Gestalt Theory
Tolman’s Sign-Gestalt Theory is employed in the field of linguistics to examine
cognitivism in language learning. The use of the theory in the field has been
prevalent in the study of sign language, as the mental action or process of
acquiring knowledge and understanding through thought, experience, and the
senses is critical for the comprehension of a system of communication that uses
visual gestures and signs.
This theory describes attributes of behaviour; it expounds that goals drive
behaviour and that the environment plays a key role in shaping that behaviour.
Cognition also plays a key role in the prevailing behavioural state. This theory
posits that learning certain behaviours does not hinge upon a fixed pattern or
sequence; rather, learning changes based on variations in the situations at hand
(Tolman 1968). In addition, the theory defines learning as a process that can be
transferred to new situations leading to a redefinition of goals and, ultimately,
new results being obtained. Furthermore, according to this theory, repetitive
trials during learning lead to the development of cognitive mental maps that are
dependent on the end goal and environment (Agbonlahor & Oasgiede 2017).
These maps thus impact one’s behaviour and actions based on the environment
and the goal being targeted.
Edward Chace Tolman (1886–1959) developed the theory. According to
Ritchie (1964), Tolman was a scholar who conducted a series of experiments
Doctoral Scholars: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
147
to try to understand learning processes as well as behaviours. Tolman held that
experiments are needed to understand the concepts that encompass animal
behaviour. He thus carried out experiments using rats to clarify the concepts of
learning and rewards as well as the connection between stimulus and response
(Ritchie 1964).
The theory attempts to clarify the stimulus behaviour response based on the
environment. It states that different individual’s learning and response rates are
different based on the cognitive maps that they form during learning, which is a
useful insight for understanding the learning process (Tolman 1968). The use of
this theory can therefore aid in modifying the teaching approach to obtain the
desired behaviour as the ultimate goal.
Tolman’s Sign-Gestalt Theory can be applied during a teaching process in
an African context. Based on this theory, the teacher needs to understand the
cultural backgrounds of the learners as well as their expectations. This is because
the teacher has a specific approach to teaching, which would seem to benefit the
learners, whose expectations may or may not align with the teacher’s approach.
The teacher can try to understand the thoughts and actions of the learners and
try to come up with an inclusive teaching approach that would be beneficial to
the learners in attaining the desired learning outcomes (Agbonlahor & Oasgiede
2017). By applying this theory, the understanding of the concepts being taught
can be greatly enhanced.
The arguments against this theory are mainly based on the subjects used in the
experiments/trials carried out by Tolman. The major query appears to be whether
the behaviour as exhibited by rats can readily predict the way that humans would
respond if learning was initiated in a similar environment.
Variability Concept
The Variability Concept emerged from the perception that languages possess
multitudinous capabilities for reproducing a single linguistic expression. This
variation exists at all levels of the linguistic hierarchy. Linguistic variations are
evident in the pronunciation of words and syntax chosen (Labov 1972). The
concept of variation was coined by William Labov in 1968. Nonetheless, there is
scanty literature on the concept.
In Africa, most countries have a multiplicity of ethnic groups, with people
speaking different languages and dialects of those languages peculiar to a given
region. The variation concept comes into play when specific languages spoken
are influenced by external factors such as the speakers’ social classes or social
environments. For example, the youth in most countries have their own languages
which they use to communicate amongst themselves. For example, in Kenya, the
language of the youth is known as Sheng.
148
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Language variation can play a unifying role by creating a connecting bond
among the youth and the old in a nation. A criticism of language variation is that
it also results in exclusivity when members of a given subgroup communicate
only among themselves, making the rest of the community feel left out.
Law and Order
Marxist Theory
This theory proposes that laws and states emerge from social interactions within
economic and political structures that promote distinctions in classes. Simply
put, state and law arise from the ownership of properties by individuals. The
main proposition of the Marxist Theory of law and order is that society has
classes because of the existence of private property. Higher-class individuals
who own the means of production and who can exploit the lower class make
laws to protect their private property. Marxist theorists argue that societies in
the primitive era did not have states or laws. They recommend that achieving
perfect equality in the context of communism will translate into the extinction
of private property and, consequently, state and law. The contemporary version
of the theory postulates law to be the product of capitalistic economic, political
and social structures. Marxist approaches indicate that laws are political, coercive,
expressive of economic relations, ideological and often manifest the interest of the
dominant class (Hunt 2010). The dominant class in this context is often the class
with power, status and property.
The pioneers of this approach to the conceptualisation of law include Karl
Marx (1818–1883) and Friedrich Engels (1820–1895). The explanation of
subordination-domination relations in different epochs of history, as well as the
continued existence of such relations, was given by Marx who also proposed a
solution for its eradication. He argued that the attainment of an equality that
is perfect among individuals would translate into the eradication of law and
state, as there would be no private property. Engels added to this proposition by
considering the family and not just the state and property (Collins, cited in Hunt
1983), thereby incorporating issues such as gender rights.
In Nigeria, for instance, the dynamics of law formulation and political
leadership which are characterised more often than not by the dominance of
major ethnic groups to the detriment of minority ethnic groups manifest the
major themes of Marxist Theory. This is also manifested in the dominance of
the political leadership in the different contours of laws. For example, business
laws are favourable to the minority elite rather than the larger population, which
is often poor and marginalised. A new tax law in Nigeria that increases value
added tax (VAT) on all products, irrespective of the differences in the purchasing
power of its citizens, is an example. Similarly, the privatisation of the electricity
distribution company is indicative of a bias to the elite but oppression of the poor.
Doctoral Scholars: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
149
A major strength of the theory hinges upon the fact that in most societies, the
basis and/or foundation, the emergence, the sustenance and the promulgation of
most laws remain primarily products of economic, political and social dynamics
between high-class and low-class members of society.
A major limitation of the Marxist Theory on law and order is the reality that
some laws, such as traffic laws, may arguably not be related to economic and
political structures, the mainstay of Marxism. In addition, the failure of the equal
distribution of property as was (arguably) done in nation states such as the United
of Soviet Socialist Republics confirms its limitations (Beyene 2006).
Positivist Theory
In the traditional form of Positivist Theory, rules are said to become laws simply
by being commanded by the sovereign with possible sanctions for not obeying
them. This is irrespective of any other consideration like morality or legitimacy.
For this theory, three elements are pertinent:
1. sovereign,
2. command, and
3. sanction.
The sovereign is the command-giver, the command is the rule, and the punishment
for command violations is the sanction (Patton 1967). In its modern rendition,
the theory postulates that the validity of any law is dependent upon its source
and not on its merits (Patton 1967; Waluchow 1998; Gardner 2001), implying a
separation of ‘what is’ (i.e. realism) from ‘what ought to be’ (i.e. idealism).
Pioneers of this theory include Jeremy Bentham (1748–1842), John Austin
(1790–1859), and H.L.A. Hart (1907–1992) who based their postulates on the
foundations of empiricism and logical positivism. Command and separation are
major aspects of the theory. In the classical version of the theory, Bentham and
Austin viewed the sovereign as the ‘unobeying obeyed’ who enacts and enforces
a command with use of force or power whether or not it measures up to moral
standards. For his part, Hart introduced the concept of the authority of rules
as an attempt to debunk criticisms that ‘there is a difference between a valid
law and the orders of a gunman’ (as quoted by Beyene 2006:24). For Hart, the
general acceptability of a rule as the standard for conduct and the enactment of
rules in line with specific rule-creation procedure(s) gives authority to such rules
referred to as ‘primary’ and ‘secondary’ rules (‘rules of recognition’). These rules
give legal validity just to sovereign commands (Beyene 2006). In other words, a
law becomes a law not only because it is given as a command, but because it is in
line with the primary and secondary rules.
The proclamation by Shaka Zulu of two years of sexual abstinence for his
subjects as a grieving period illustrates commands given by sovereigns without
consideration for his subjects. Similarly, laws that either allow or restrict
150
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
abortion and homosexuality in the Western world and that seem to contradict
beliefs held in society are illustrations of laws based on the Positivist Theory.
Other relevant examples include apartheid laws in South Africa and the laws
enacted in Nazi Germany.
The ‘distinguishability’ of law from social norms inclusive of moral standards
and etiquette, as well as the acknowledgement of an overlap between the two, is
the strength of this theory. Positivists accept that laws can be ‘good or bad, wise or
foolish, just or unjust’ (Lyons 1977:417). The merit of the law is not as important
as its source in this context. The satisfaction of moral conditions is not necessary
to establish its validity.
The proposition that the command of a sovereign validates a law rather than
a rule being accepted by the people because it is reflective of natural justice is
a shortcoming of the theory. Similarly, law observance is not only secured by
sanctions; sometimes, positive rewards, habits, and respect for laws may secure
observance (Patton 1967). An individual can elect to obey a law not because of
its sanctions but because s/he feels fulfilled being obedient.
Social Contract Theory
This theory proposes that laws emerge as a result of an agreement among
members of a state. The agreement specifies rights and duties for the achievement
of common goals. Citizens agree to give up rights to the state in exchange for
the state ensuring the preservation of order, peace, fair access or the distribution
of resources of nature for the good of all (Ellis 2006; Laskar 2013; Jiboku &
Jiboku 2019). The key element here is ‘agreement’.
The initiators of the Social Contract Theory include Thomas Hobbes
(1588– 1679), John Locke (1632–1704), and Jean-Jacques Rousseau
(1712– 1778). Hobbes said that the natural need of humanity for safety and painavoidance led to the formation of agreements in which individuals gave up their
rights and freedom to a sovereign who had absolute power to give commands for
the good of all. He proposed an agreement constituting a mix of individualistic,
materialistic, utilitarian and absolutist principles (Laskar 2013). This perspective
is different from those of the other pioneers.
In Locke’s variation, citizens surrender only the rights of the preservation/
maintenance of order and enforcement of the natural laws to the state. Other
natural rights such as those to life and freedom of speech, among others, remain
with the citizens. The contract between government and its citizens becomes
invalid and not binding when the government fails to fulfil these rights surrendered
by the citizens. For Rousseau, sovereignty belongs to the majority of the people
whose general will determines the laws and it is within this context that laws are
representative (Laskar 2013). In essence, the people’s will validates a law.
Doctoral Scholars: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
151
Trade relations among West African countries as captured in the pact binding
the Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS) are an example of
an agreement among countries that is legally valid and binding on the partners of
the agreement, a reflection of the Social Contract Theory. Many laws establishing
businesses at individual, organisational, national and regional levels reflect
agreements based on this theory.
The theory is relevant now particularly in terms of the ‘social contractibility’
nature of laws; there is always an agreement of some sort for the emergence and
validity of laws (Laskar 2013). This agreement is ideally between the parties
affected by the law in question.
The placement of absolute power in the sovereign as proposed by Hobbes is
one of the major limitations of this theory. Other limitations include Rousseau’s
proposition of the interchangeability of government, state and law.
Utilitarian Theory
Utilitarian Theory as it pertains to law and order purports that the promulgation
of laws is aimed at the production of the greatest possible good for the majority
of individuals. It is considered a consequentialist theory because it seeks the most
positive consequence for the greatest number of individuals in any state. It also
emphasises an individualistic view of law built on the principle of utility. This
entails the prevention of evil and/or the procurement of good for the happiness of
the majority in a society. Enjoyment, pleasure-seeking, happiness or gratification
is proposed to be the primary obligation of the government to its citizens. In
simple terms, laws exist to ensure the furtherance of happiness of the majority of
the members of a state. Therefore, any action that contravenes the happiness of
the greatest number of the people of a society is unlawful (Welch 1989).
According to English philosopher Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), the major
proponent of this theory and who attempted a pain or harm calculus, the
validity of a law is depdendent on its usefulness in ensuring the prevention of
the most pain and production of maximum pleasure. Laws function to meet
the requirements of citizens’ equality, subsistence, abundance and security. John
Stuart Mill (1806–1873), another pioneer of this theory, emphasised hedonism
as pertinent in the formulation and functions of a law but differentiated the
quality of pleasure in terms of whether or not there were higher or lower pleasures
(Smart & Williams 1973). This categorisation of pleasures differentiates sensual
pleasure from other types of pleasure such as intellectual pleasure.
The Petroleum Act mandated by the Nigerian state that employs the resources
of the petroleum sector for the entire country rather than only for producing
states is indicative of the consequentialist attribute of utilitarianism. The good
of the majority of the people in the country as a whole rather than regionally is
the focus. Similarly, the prohibition of imports in many countries (for example
152
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
the staple food, rice, in Nigeria) also falls in line with the consequentialist feature
of this theory. The hedonist ethic is somewhat implicated in the ongoing debate
concerning sexual orientation and LGBTQ+ rights in many African countries,
including Ghana, Zimbabwe and Kenya, where there is an apparent clash
between individual happiness and a purported societal interest, at least from the
standpoint of those who oppose these rights.
A major strength of this theory lies in its relevance to the promulgation of
economic laws, particularly with regards to the importation and exportation of
products. The common good of the majority of the citizens overrides that of
the business individuals or organisations. Nevertheless, its shortcomings remain
its simplistic attempt to graft idealism and materialism and its failure to ensure
equilibrium between interests at the individual and community levels.
References
Agbonlahor, Elvis and Oasgiede, Isoken F., 2017, ‘Stimulus-Organism-Response (SOR)
Interaction Effects of the Sign Learning Theory in Achieving Motor Outcomes’,
Journal of Language, Technology and Entrepreneurship in Africa, Vol. 8, No. 1,
pp. 109–121.
Ajayi, Michael, 2015, ‘Bernstein’s Deficit Hypothesis and the Nigerian Context: A Survey
of the Performance of Students in the English Language in their Senior School
Certificate Examinations’, Journal of Linguistics and Language in Education, Vol. 9,
No. 1, pp. 60–78.
Aristotle, 1954, The rhetoric and the poetics of Aristotle, edited by Freidrich Solmsen and
translated by W. Rhys Roberts, Franklin Center, PA: The Franklin Library.
Atkinson, Paul, 1995, The Sociology of Basil Bernstein, Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing
Corporation.
Austin, John, 1962, How to Do Things with Words, Oxford, UK: Oxford Printing Press.
Bernstein, Basil, 1973, Class, Codes and Control: Applied Studies towards a Sociology of
Language, London, UK: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Beyene, Biset, 2006, Introductory Note on Law in General, pp. 5–10. (https://
www.abyssinialaw.com/online-resources/study-on-line/itemlist/category/964introduction-to-law-and-law-of-persons). 24 October 2019.
Broughton, Dr. G.; Broughton, G.; Brumfit, C. and Pincas, A., 1978, Teaching English as
a Foreign Language, London, UK: Routledge Educational Books.
Burke, Kenneth, 1969, A Rhetoric of Motives, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Bussotti, Luca, 2015, ‘Short Reflections on the History of African Communication’,
Historia y Comunicación Social, Vol. 20, No. 1, pp. 205–222.
Cohen, Jonathan, 1964, ‘Do Illocutionary Forces Exist?’ The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol.
14, No. 55, pp. 118–137.
Demkiw, Julian, 2010, ‘Taking Rhetoric to Work: A Dramatistic Analysis of Organizational
Leadership in The Office’, Master’s Thesis, Canada: Saskatchewan University.
Diop, Cheikh Anta, 1954, Nations Nègres et Culture, Paris, France: Présence Africaine.
Doctoral Scholars: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order
153
Ellis, Elisabeth, 2006, ‘Citizenship and Property Rights: A New Look at Social Contract
Theory’, The Journal of Social Politics, Vol. 68, No. 3, pp. 544–555.
Gardner, John, 2001, ‘Legal Positivism: 51/2 Myths’, The American Journal of Jurisprudence,
Vol. 46, No. 1, pp. 199–227.
Guthrie, Edwin, 1938, The Psychology of Human Conflict, New York, NY: Harper.
Guthrie, Edwin and Horton, George, 1946, Cats in a Puzzle Box, New York, NY:
Rinehart.
Halliday, Michael, 1978, Language as a Social Semiotic, London, UK: Edward Arnold
Publishers.
Hunt, A., 1983, ‘Marxist Legal Theory and Legal Positivism [Review of Marxism and
Law, by H. Collins]’, The Modern Law Review, Vol. 46, No. 2, pp. 236–243. (http://
www.jstor.org/stable/1095497). 29 September 2021.
Hunt, Alan, 2010, ‘Marxist Theory of Law’, in E. Patterson, ed., A Companion to
Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, London, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.
Jakobson, Roman, 1960, ‘Linguistics and Poetics’, in T. Sebeok, ed., Style in Language,
Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute Technology Press.
Jiboku, Joseph O. and Jiboku, Peace A., 2019, ‘Poverty and the Democratization Crisis
in Nigeria: A Failure of Social Contract’, Equiddad y Desaroll, Vol. 34, pp. 35–
56. (https://ciencia.lasalle.edu.co/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1320&context=eq).
30 September 2021.
Jones, Peter, 2013, ‘Bernstein’s “Codes” and the Linguistics of “Deficit”’, Language and
Education, Vol. 27, No. 2, pp. 161–179.
Karabel, J. and Halsey, A.H., 1977, Power and Ideology in Education, New York,
NY: Oxford University Press.
Kay, Peter and Kempton, William, 1984, ‘What is the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis?’,
American Anthropologist, Vol. 86, No. 1, pp. 65–79.
Labov, William, 1968, English Vernacular, Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.
Labov, William, 1972, Language in the Inner City, Philadelphia, PA: University of
Pennsylvania Press.
Laskar, Manzoor Elahi, 2013, ‘Summary of Social Contract Theory by Hobbes, Locke
and Rousseau’, Social Science Research Network. (doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2410525). 30
September 2021.
Laver, Jay, 1975, ‘Communicative Functions of Phatic Communion’, in A. Kendon, R.M.
Harris and M.R. Key, eds., Organization of Behaviour in Face-to-face Interaction, The
Hague, The Netherlands: Mouton Publishers.
Lyons, D., 1977, ‘Principles, Positivism, and Legal Theory’, [Review of Taking Rights Seriously
by R. Dworkin], The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 87, No. 2, pp. 415–435. (https://doi.
org/10.2307/795657). 11 November 2021.
Malinowski, B., 1923, ‘The Problem of Meaning in Primitive Languages,’ in C.K. Ogden
and I.A. Richards, eds., The Meaning of Meaning, London, UK: Kegan Paul, Trench,
Trubner & Company.
Martin, Bronwen and Ringham, Felizitas, 2006, Key Terms in Semiotics, London,
UK: Bloomsbury Publishers.
Mazrui, Ali Al’Amin, 1993, ‘Language and the Quest for Liberation in Africa: The Legacy
of Frantz Fanon’, Third World Quarterly Review, Vol. 14, No. 2, pp. 351–363.
154
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Moltmann, Friederike, 2016, ‘Levels of Linguistic Acts and the Semantics of Saying and
Quoting’, in S.L. Tsohatzidis, ed., Interpreting Austin: Critical Essays, Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Muvindi, Israel and Zuvalinyenga, Dorcas, 2013, ‘Educational Implications of the Deficit/
Deprivation Hypothesis in L2 Situations: A Case of Zimbabwe’, International
Journal of English and Literature, Vol. 4, No. 6, pp. 283–287.
Odebode, Idowu and Dabi, Oluwabukola, 2015, ‘Speech Acts in Billboard Messages of
the Redeemed Christian Church of God, Redemption Camp, Nigeria: A Pragmatic
Study’, English Linguistics Research, Vol. 2:17–23.
Patton, Alan, 1967, ‘Theories of Law, Natural Law, Legal Positivism, the Morality of
Law’, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 87, No. 2, pp. 415–435.
Ritchie, Benbow, 1964, Edward Chace Tolman, 1886–1959: A Biographical Memoir,
Washington, DC: National Academy of Sciences.
Robertson, David, Davies, Ian and Davidoff, John, 2000, ‘Color categories are not
universal: Replication and new evidence from a stone-age culture’, Journal of
Experimental Psychology, Vol. 129, No. 3, pp. 369–398.
Searle, John, 1968, ‘Austin on Locutionary and Illocutionary Acts’, The Philosophical
Review, Vol. 77, No. 4, pp. 405–424.
Smart, J.J.C. and Williams, B., 1973, Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Thau, S., 1972, ‘The Distinction between Rhetic and Illocutionary Acts’, Analysis,
Vol. 32, No. 6, pp. 177–183.
Tolman, Edward Chace, 1938, ‘The Determiners of Behavior at a Choice Point’,
Psychological Review, Vol. 45, No. 1, pp. 1–41.
Tribus, Angela C., 2017, ‘The Communicative Functions of Language: An Exploration
of Roman Jakobson’s Theory in TESOL’, SIT Digital Collections. (https://
digitalcollections.sit.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1725&context=ipp_
collection). 29 September 2021.
Velghe, Fie, 2018, ‘“Hallo hoe gaan dit, wat maak jy?”: Phatic communication, the
mobile phone and coping strategies in a South African context’, Multilingual
Margins: A Journal of Multilingualism from the Periphery, Vol. 2, No. 1. (https://doi.
org/10.14426/mm.v2i1.31). 29 September 2021.
Waluchow, Will, 1998, ‘The Many Faces of Legal Positivism’, The University of Toronto
Law Journal, Vol. 48, No. 3, pp. 387–449.
6
Literature, Mathematics, and Peace
and Conflict Resolution
Doctoral Scholars
In this chapter, we provide brief reviews of eight theories in the field of literature,
three in the field of mathematics, and eight in the field of peace and conflict
resolution. The first category of theories pertains to written works, especially
those considered of superior or lasting artistic merit. The second category
relates to notions dealing with abstract science of number, quantity, and space.
Mathematics may be studied in its own right (pure mathematics), or as it is applied
to other disciplines such as physics and engineering (applied mathematics). And
the third category is in reference to concepts regarding freedom from disturbance
and approaches two or more parties can use to reach a peaceful resolution to a
disagreement between or among them.
Literature
Cultural Studies Theory
Cultural Studies Theory is an outgrowth of a literary field that first emanated
from British Cultural Analysis, drawing tenets from The Long Revolution and
Culture and Society by Raymond Williams (Castle 2007). In the books, Williams
demonstrated that communication and media were changing citizens’ outlook on
life. Thus, Cultural Studies Theory is deeply rooted in the mechanics of popular
and contemporary cultures. Stuart Hall, in his lecture on Culturalism, argues that
culture is ‘experience lived, experience interpreted, experience defined’ (in Slack
& Grossberg 2016:33). Hall contends that even though many earlier academics
considered the study of popular culture to be an affront to their intellectuality,
Cultural Studies Theory ‘tells us things about the world that more traditional
studies of politics or economics alone could not’ (Hall 1981:2). As an approach
156
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
and an interdisciplinary stance, Cultural Studies Theory tends to fuse a number
of other approaches and theories like those found in gender studies, Marxism,
post-colonialism, feminist theory, history, and critical theory.
According to some observers of the Cultural Studies Theory, the crux of the
research by its practitioners examines the ideas that engender cultural practices and
how these practices are connected to the systems of power that emanate through
social phenomena and constructs like gender, sexual identity and orientation,
class divisions and structures, identity formations and queerness. Cultural Studies
Theory is therefore said to prompt examination of different classes of culture and
the varied margins of difference between categories of expression; however, for
Cultural Studies Theory critics, cultures are dynamic and are constantly changing
and merging with current trends and practices (for more on these aspects, see
Hall 1981).
Raymond Williams contends that works on Cultural Studies Theory
‘were revolutionary in that they sought to analyse culture through new ways
of conceiving the relationship between base and structure. Each of these
categories offers something of value to the critic, but none of them alone is
sufficient’ (Williams 1961:85). He also contends that the ‘theory of culture
must take into account elements from each and respond to the complexity and
significance of specific cultural organisations’ (Williams 1961:85). He defines
the theory ‘as the study of relationships between elements in a whole way of life’
(Williams 1961:85).
The theory allows for the fusion of different tenets from other theories in its
application, and therein lies its strength. Its limitation, however, is connected to
its strength because the diversity of its approach posits it as a theory that depends
on a number of other theories to support its postulates.
Ethnic Studies and Postcolonial Criticism
Ethnic Studies, which is also called Minority Studies, has a historical
relationship with Postcolonial Criticism (Singh & Schmidt 2000). This
relationship is based on Euro-American imperialism and colonisation
directed at some ethnic groups: Latino/Latina, African and African-American,
Filipino, Irish, the subaltern peoples of India, indigenous American, and
Chinese, among others. On the one hand, Ethnic Studies is located within
literature produced by groups that have either been marginalised or which
are in a subordinate position to a dominant culture. Postcolonial Criticism,
on the other hand, investigates the relationships between the colonisers and
the colonised in the period of post-colonisation. To put this more succinctly,
Postcolonial Criticism addresses the issues around politics and literature. It
examines politics, economics, issues of power, culture and wealth and what
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
157
underlies the ethnic imbalance which was informed by colonial incursion,
power and education relativism; and the demarcation of the colonised country
for administrative convenience, bringing people of different cultures together
to achieve their aims. Postcolonial criticism attributes the underdevelopment
of the colonised states to footprints and structures left by the colonial masters.
Although the two theories have points of intersection and are both activist
intellectual enterprises, Ethnic Studies and Postcolonial Criticism have
substantial differences in their history and ideas (Singh & Schmidt 2000).
Afro-Caribbean and African writers such as Aimé Fernand David Césaire
(1913–2008), Frantz Fanon (1925–1961), Chinua Achebe (1930–2013) and
others made significant early contributions to the theory. They explored the
traditions, sometimes repressed or subversive, of ethnic literary activity while
providing an evaluation of representations of ethnic identity as found within the
majority culture. Ethnic and Minority Literary Theory emphasises the relationship
between cultural identity and individual identity in historical circumstances of
obvious racial oppression.
Even though he was not the first writer to explore the historical condition of
post-colonialism, Palestinian literary theorist Edward Said’s book Orientalism
(1977) is generally regarded as having inaugurated the field of Postcolonial
Criticism in the West. Said argues that the term ‘the Orient’ was produced by
the ‘imaginative geography’ of Western scholarship and has been instrumental
in the colonisation and domination of non-Western societies. In the book,
Said characterises the concept of ‘Western Style’ as ‘dominating, restructuring,
and having authority over the Orient’ (Said 1979:2–12, 94). The work
of Gayatri C. Spivak (1988) focuses on the question of who speaks for the
colonial ‘Other’ and the relationship between the ownership of discourse and
representation and the development of postcolonial subjectivity. Like Feminist
and Ethnic Theory, Postcolonial Criticism also investigates the inclusion of the
marginalised literature of colonial people into the dominant canon and discourse
(Spivak 1988).
According to Said (1979), Postcolonial Criticism offers a fundamental critique
of the ideology of colonial domination and at the same time seeks to undo the
‘imaginative geography’ of Orientalist thought that produced conceptual as well as
economic divisions between the West and the East, ‘civilised’ and ‘uncivilised’, First
and Third Worlds. In this respect, the theory of Ethnic Studies and Postcolonial
Criticism is critical and adversarial in its basic aims. It therefore emphasises the
issues of identity and social justice orchestrated by ethnic imbalance from the
leftover structures of the colonial powers. Questions on the theory always revolve
around distribution of opportunities and privileges within a society.
158
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Formalism and New Criticism
Roman Jakobson (1896–1982) and Viktor Shklovsky (1893–1984) are popularly
known proponents of Formalism and New Criticism Theory (Curtis 1976). Their
study on formalism had a wider impact on later developments in structuralism
and theories of narrativity. The critical approach that interprets or evaluates the
inherent structures of a text and its analysis is known as Formalism (Hansen 2004).
These structures involve grammar, syntax, and literary devices such as tropes and
rhythms. The formalistic approach aims to reduce the significance of a text’s
historical, biographical and cultural context (Van Manen 2016).
Formalism and New Criticism Theory advocate for methodological and
systematic readings of texts. This premise led to the advancement of reading
strategies that isolate text objectively by looking at structure as well as authorial
techniques and use of language. The theory aims at classifying, categorising,
and cataloguing works by their formal attributes. Northrop Frye, John Crowe
Ransom and T.S. Eliot are among the contributors to the development of theory
(Drake et al. 2013).
The New Criticism component of the theory gained significant attention
in American academe in the 1930s and 1940s. This Anglo-American variety
of Formalism, developed as a new strategy for reading, viewed literature as
autonomous, an aesthetic object independent of past contexts, and treated as
a unified whole, echoing the unified sense-making of an artist. The primary
objective of New Criticism is to bring greater intellectual rigour to literary study,
emphasising metaphysical poets and a poetry type that is tailored to new critical
practice. The approach focused on delineating the formal structures of paradox,
irony, ambiguity, and metaphor, as well as to restraining itself to cautious
examination of a text (Castle 2009).
Formalism shared common assumptions that a work is autotelic: that is
complete in itself, that it is written for its own sake, and that it is unified by its
form (Ousby 1992). Table 6.1 illustrates the figurative usages and applications.
The strengths of Formalism and New Criticism Theory are rooted in the
following: it is a commonly understood approach that makes sense of literature;
it is appropriate for poetry analysis; and it enhances the development of reading
skills. Loesberg (2015) argues that a multiplicity of meanings exists in literary
language, diverting the reader from the familiar and making fresh the experiences
of daily life.
Castle (2007) argues that an inherent criticism of the theory lies in the
internal logic of aesthetic form. He denounces the theory for being insufficiently
historicised. Another defect of the theory is that it fails to pay attention to
biological matters and social issues by focusing only on content and form.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
159
Table 6.1: The Application of Formalism in Studies
Element
Usage
Application
Character
Creation and representation of
fictional persons and entries
Antagonist, antihero, dynamic,
flat, protagonist, round, static,
symbolic, analogy, irony,
sarcasm, satire, metaphor,
metonymy, personification,
simile, symbolism, intangible,
tangible, and synecdoche
Imagery
Specific details used to describe
character, situation, things, ideas
or events
Hearing, seeing, smelling,
tasting, touching, extrasensory
Plot
A series of events or happenings
that organise a text
Climax, complicated, conflict,
external, internal, denouement,
foreshadowing, implausible,
inciting event, plausible,
recognition, reversal, simple
Point of view
Perspective of the controlling
narrative voice
First person, limited
omniscience, objective,
omniscient, reliable, subjective,
third person, unreliable
Setting
Atmosphere, historical period,
physical setting, or mood of text
Place, time, ahistorical,
chronological, backward,
forward, circular, flashbacks,
historical, projections,
fragmented, atmosphere, mood
Theme
A major idea or message in the
text
Controlling ideas, separate issues
Source: Self-generated by the authors
Gender Studies and Queer Theory
Gender Studies Theory is an interdisciplinary approach that looks at how gender
shapes our identities, our social interactions and our world. It is employed to
examine identities and how these identities are categorised (Kieley et al. 2018).
According to Jagose and Genschel (1996), Queer Theory is commonly perceived
as the latest institutional transformation in the field of Lesbian and Gay Studies.
Combining the two theories, Piantato (2016) posits that Gender Studies and
Queer Theory comprise an interdisciplinary approach that examines the dominant
understanding of gender and the challenges surrounding the association that exists
amid gender identity, sexual orientation, and anatomical sex (see also Fineman
2009). Subversive approaches that challenge the hegemonic idea of gender and
sex highlight differences in the perspectives on identity inherent in Feminism
160
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
and Queer Theory (Piantato 2016). Abes and Kasch propound that Queer
Theory aims to ‘explain development toward complex ways of understanding
identity’ (2007:3).
Teresa de Lauretis is acknowledged as the coiner of the phrase ‘Queer Theory’
which she introduced during a conference at the University of California in 1990.
Other known queer theorists are David Halperin, José Esteban Muñoz, Eve
Kosofsky Sedgwick,and many others. Queer Theory ‘critically analyzes the meaning
of identity, focusing on intersections of identities and resisting oppressive social
constructions of sexual orientation and gender’ (Piantato 2016:1). It is through
the idea of fluidity that Queer Theory expresses a new understanding of gender
identity, by refusing the binarism between men and women (Piantato 2016).
Both Gender Studies and QueerTtheory explore issues of sexuality, power,
and marginalised populations (woman as other) in literature and culture (Purdue
Online Writing Lab, undated).
The application of Queer Theory in the African context is evident in the work
of Vasu Reddy (2005). The author formulates a critical method that demonstrates
the political construction of homosexuality in South Africa. The author reveals
that the appearance of the political queer character has its origins in the apartheid
state and the grounding of the identities is reinforced in the present postapartheid project. In addition, Reddy conceives homosexuality as a queer identity
that resists and subverts heteronormativity (Reddy 2005).
One of the strengths of Queer Theory is that it is perceived as a kind of inclusive
approach that ‘encompasses the whole marginalised identity, thus considered
as fluid and free-floating, incapable of fitting in a normative study, permitting
their legitimate recognition alternative to originality identity’ (Piantato 2016:17).
Queer Theory is considered to be strong because it embraces all forms of studies
that are labelled odd, weird, queer and gives them opportunities to be explored
and to pass through the inferno of criticism (Piantato 2016). In addition, Queer
Theory’s deconstruction of gender presents a wide range of implications that leave
the possibility of reviewing gender and sexuality in a new and more complex way.
Marxism and Critical Theory
The nexus between Marxism and Critical Theory hinges on the fact that the
latter (i.e. Critical Theory) seeks to expose any ideological system that buttresses
any aspect of economic subjugation. The theory’s objective is to add to the
efforts to eradicate such subjugation. In essence, the theory seeks to contribute
insights about socioeconomic life that are liberating: i.e. people come to perceive
the subjugation they are experiencing as subjugation and are thereby partly
emancipated from it. It is from this purview that the Marxist critique of capitalist
economic relations is akin to Critical Theory, as Marxism regards participants in
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
161
a capitalist society as uncritically accepting all aspects – including the oppressive
ones – of free exchange, laws of demand and supply, private property rights, etc. as
justifiable. In the same vein as Critical Theory, Marxism seeks to eliminate every
aspect of capitalist subjugation. The basic objectives of Marxism and Critical
Theory are to marshal actions geared towards ridding a society of despotism and
exploitation.
Ian Birchall argues that Marxism and Critical Theory are concerned with ‘the
analyses of the dynamics and contradictions of the capitalist system, and to show
how the working class has the historical potential to overthrow capitalism and
establish a classless, socialist society’ (Birchall 1977:9). Terry Eagleton says that
‘Marxist criticism is part of a larger body of theoretical analysis which aims to
understand ideologies, the ideas, the values and feelings by which men experience
the society at various times’ (Eagleton 1996:12).
Marxist criticism holds that literature can be viewed as ideological, and that it
can be analysed in terms of a Base/Superstructure model. Karl Marx argued that
the economic means of production in a society account for its base, which then
determines its superstructure. Human institutions and ideologies that produce art
and literary texts comprise the superstructure. ‘Marxist criticism thus emphasizes
class, socioeconomic status, and power relations among various segments of
society.’ (Eward-Mangione 2020).
For Marx ‘the history of a society is the history of dialectical transformations
in the relationship between labour and production’ (Castle 2007:108). There are
two classes dominant in a society as identified by Marx:
1. the capitalist and
2. the proletariat.
Important to Marx’s philosophy is his meeting with Friedrich Engels who
collaborated with Marx for the production of ‘the critique of capitalist society
based on a materialistic conception of history’ (Habib 2005:527). For Engels,
the aim was to formulate an ideology for socialism in order to seek the point of
intersection between natural science and dialectics and to explore the state of
the working class. Other notable proponents of Marxist and Critical Theory are
Gyorgy Lukacs (1885–1971 ) and Terry Eagleton (born 1943).
Critical Theory emanates from the Institute for Social Research (Institut fur
Sozialforschung) at the University of Frankfurt. Max Horkheimer (1895–1973),
director of the institute from 1930 to 1953, is recognised for his immense
contributions to the founding and upholding of the Frankfurt School tradition
of Critical Theory (Bolanos 2013). Other critical theorists like Theodor Adorno,
Herbert Marcuse and Eric Fromm were all affiliated with the Institute for
Social Research. The initial plan of these theorists was to critique and study a
society from the angle of Marxism. However, owing to their preoccupation with
162
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
‘superstructural’ phenomena like class formation, ideological hegemony and
problems of culture, they deviated from the mainstream ‘mechanistic’ approach
by rejecting economic forces and modes of production associated with classical
Marxism (Castle 2007:65). Drawing his conclusion from Horkheimer’s essay,
‘Tradition and Critical Theory’, Bolanos notes that Marxism and Critical Theory
concerns itself with ‘potentiality and liberation’ which create a path for humans
to transform themselves in society which appeals to an idea of liberation that may
not necessarily mean total freedom (Bolanos 2013).
The charm of Marxism and Critical Theory to African sensibilities (and
the rest of the world), lies in its foundation in political economy. The theory
concerns itself with social actualities but also sees a human as a political, social
and economic being. Marxism and Critical Theory propose that the realisation
of human potentialities is attainable through social structures. Chief among these
structuring efforts is the scrapping of all forms of tyranny which will bring about
the annihilation of injustice (Bolanos 2013). Whereas Marx’s concern was on the
exploitation of the proletariat in the production process, critical theorists were
mainly concerned with the explorations and deceits in the realm of consumption,
especially through the mass media and advertisement.
The strength of the theory hinges upon its almost perfect applicability and
suitability in the critical analyses of literary texts. It envisages a utopian state –
which is only possible in a fictitious universe. The theory’s limitation is therefore
embedded in its inapplicableness to the actual world.
New Historicism and Cultural Materialism
American scholar Louis Montrose, a major innovator and exponent of New
Historicism, defines it as a combination of ‘the textuality of history, the historicity
of texts’ (quoted by Peter 1995:1). This implies that literary texts, as cultural
products rooted in their time and place, should be studied and interpreted within
the context of the history of both the author and the critic (Parvini 2012). New
Historicism has its origin in America and was popularised in the 1980s by Stephen
Greenblatt. Other proponents were Michel Foucault and Clifford Geertz. The
term Cultural Materialism was coined by Raymond Williams and originated in
Britain. Jonathan Dollimore and Alan Sinfield made a huge contribution to this
theory through their work titled Political Shakespeare published in 1985.
The two theories are usually combined because of their similarity of focus on
the relationship between text and history. They both highlight how individuals
perceive themselves, their interactions with others, and how they exercise
power or are subjected to power. They also emphasise the close relationship
between literary texts and other texts. They do, however, differ in that while
New Historicism emphasises power and how the ‘self ’ is created through society,
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
163
Cultural Materialism pays more attention to ideology and leans towards Marxism
(Bertens 2008). The theoretical assumptions of the theories are:
1. every expressive act is entrenched in the cultural practices of a place;
2. culture is said to fundamentally contain characteristics of a text and,
consequently, can be studied just as texts are;
3. literary texts are intertwined with cultural texts through a connection with
other texts and rhetoric and can be analysed in similar way;
4. power always seeks to accommodate dissidence and this drive for containment
must be overcome if genuine subversion is to be achieved; and
5. an engagement with the ‘real’ lived experiences of people as documented by
anecdotes can lead to the reproduction of ‘counter histories’ (Parvini 2012).
The theory has been used in the analysis of Coming to Birth, an award-winning
work by Kenyan author Marjorie Macgoye (2000). The text demonstrates that
history does not homogeneously impact on both women and men. This is
reflected in the progressive social transformation of the female character Pauline
against the male character Martin’s regression. The novel depicts how social,
economic and political transformations are intertwined with the historical events
of the nation. In addition, the author is said to depict a conflict between the
main characters resulting in bitterness and lack of hope (Abungu 1997). This
scenario is comparable to the hopelessness experienced by Kenyans in the newly
independent country as a result of the failure of their new government, seen as a
new pattern of colonisation.
A strength shared by New Historicism and Cultural Materialism is that they
are grounded on post-structuralism and presented in an approachable way. The
empirical foundation upon which the interpretation is based is openly available
for scrutiny. The theory is not argumentative and relies on historical evidence. The
theory has contributed to literary criticism in its re-evaluation of the association
between the present and past. It also emphasises the influence of readers’ values
and attitudes in their interpretation of literature, their own culture, and the past
(Makaryk 1993).
A limitation of New Historicism and Cultural Materialism is that in using it
to study literary texts, critics highlight the history of the period in interpreting
dramatic facts, thereby disregarding the literary text’s own principles (Vickers
1993). It can be accused of bias as it can manipulate proof and circumstance
to fit a one-sided interpretation. Finally, the theory is anachronistic as it forces
contemporary political and cultural perspectives on (for instance) Renaissance
texts (Levin 2003; Parvini 2017). Finally, the theory is also limited in that could
exhibit political bias with its practitioners choosing texts that authenticate their
positions (Makaryk 1993).
164
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Structuralism and Poststructuralism
Althusser opines that Structuralism started as an intellectual paradigm in France
in the late 1950s (Elliot 1990). It developed across Europe over the rest of the
century as a result of an increase in human science research. Poststructuralism,
according to Beaumont and Baker (2011), also originated in France during the
time as a critique of Structuralism, arguing that all elements of human culture,
including literature, are understandable when seen as being a part of a system.
Structuralism is defined in the disciplines of sociology, anthropology and
linguistics as a methodology that implies that elements of human culture must
be understood by way of their relationship to a broader, overarching system or
structure. Poststructuralism is defined as ‘a movement that views the descriptive
premise of structuralism as contracted by reliance on borrowed concepts or
differential terms and categories and sees inquiry as inevitably shaped by discursive
and interpretive practices’ (Merriam-Webster 2021).
The main idea of Structuralism Theory is that human activity and its
products, even perception and thought itself, are constructed and not natural,
and in particular that everything has meaning because of the language system in
which we operate. Poststructuralism entails the study of underlying structures,
which are culturally conditioned and therefore subject to myriad biases and
misinterpretations (Foucault & Hurst 2017).
According to Foucault and Hurst, although German physiologist and
philosopher Wilhelm Wundt is often listed as the founder of Structuralism,
he did not coin the term. The theory was propounded by his student Edward
Bradford Titchener in the fields of anthropology and sociology. In the fields of
architecture and literature, the theory is associated with Swiss linguist Ferdinand
de Saussure. In anthropology, it is associated with Claude Levi-Strauss (Foucault
& Hurst 2017).
Applied to the African context, Sunday Anozie, an African literature critic,
feels that most Africans have ignored Structuralism as a theory because it is not
clearly defined and because it does not relate to political options and goals in
the African context. According to Anozie, most structural models and African
poetics are devoted to a critique of ‘traditional’ Structuralism as it is applied to
the African context (Eagleton 2014).
This theory’s concentration on structure is its strength. Studying the structure
of a work, for instance, gives room for the deconstruction of the work, leading to
greater understanding. Nonetheless, the theory does not go beyond the structure;
thus, it becomes reductionist by limiting the exploration and reading of a text to
its connection to other texts.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
165
Traditional Literary Criticism
Traditional Literary Criticism Theory is the approach that dominated the study
of literature until the 1930s and is still relevant today (Coyle et al. 2014). This
approach sees literary work as a reflection of its author’s life and times or the
life and times of the characters in the work. In other words, Traditional Literary
Criticism Theory sees literature as essentially biography or history. It explains
works of literature in relation to the history of the writer or the characters in
the work, or in terms of the moral philosophies that are embedded in a literary
work. The approach is much articulated in the writings of the nineteenth century
French historian and literary critic Hippolyte Adolphe Taine (Koller 1912).
The theory hinges on four pillars:
1. a focus on the purposes of the canonical writers;
2. the works of literature produced by geniuses – these works are associated with
great authors such as Shakespeare and Chaucer;
3. the works are self-explanatory and have organic unity; and
4. the works should be studied for intellectual reasons and not ideological
purposes (No author 2019).
Works such as Ayi Kwei Armah’s The Beautyful Ones Are Not Yet Born (1968) and
Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart (1958) are typical examples of the relevance
of the application of the theory in the African context as they treat their subject
matter as essentially biographies or histories.
There are several strengths of Traditional Literary Criticism Theory. To begin
with, the approach can be used to explain literary works that deal with politics
and power dynamics. Examples include John Milton’s ‘On His Blindness’, and
John Dryden’s satirical poem ‘Absalom and Achitophel’. The approach tells us
about the historical events that informed the writing of the literary work, the
geographical settings, as well as the politics prevailing at the time. The approach’s
foci on history and bibliography are helpful because knowledge of the past
gives readers a way to understand the language, ideas, and purposes of literature
more deeply and clearly. Such knowledge can make readers familiar with the
social trends and convictions that would have influenced a writer’s attitude and
tastes. Also, the approach explains the writer’s choice of words and expressions.
Furthermore, the approach identifies differences between contemporary writers
(No author 2019).
A weakness of Traditional Literary Criticism Theory is intentional fallacy: i.e.
the problem inherent in assuming that the meanings and values of a work may be
determined by the author’s intentions. Some critics of the theory believe that the
approach tends to reduce art to the levels of biography, meaning that the work has
no wider meaning. Other critics also argue that the approach tends to be deficient
in imagination as it is simply a common-sense interpretation of material.
166
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Mathematics
Ethnomathematical Theory
Ethnomathematical Theory can be defined as ‘the cultural anthropology of
mathematics and mathematics education’ (Gerdes 1997:332). The term ‘ethno’
is a combining form that means race, people or culture, while ‘mathematics’
points to ‘the techniques of doing and understanding activities like ciphering,
arithmetic, classifying, ordering, inferring and modelling’ (D’Ambrosio 1987:1).
Ethnomathematical Theory then focuses on mathematical practices outside
scholarly settings among particular groups of people sharing a culture such as
national-ethnic societies, work groups, young people of a certain age bracket or
professional classes (Powell & Frankenstein 1997). The theory was propounded
by D’Ambrosio in 1984. According to him, culture affects the ways people
acquire and put to use mathematical knowledge; thus, this approach deals with
the application of mathematical ideas and practices to problems encountered in
the past and present culture (D’Ambrosio 2013).
The basic tenet of the theory is that mathematical ideas are cultural
communication tools entrenched within cultural contexts. The ideas emphasised,
expressions and application differ from culture to culture (Ascher 2008). The
theory’s major goal when applied in the teaching of mathematics is to facilitate the
empowerment and transformation of learners. These learners are enabled to make
a connection between scholarly mathematics and other forms of mathematics;
thus, a connection is made between socio-cultural-ethnical aspects of culture and
mathematics. This paradigm enables educators to put into place practices that
take care of all learners, thereby giving them an opportunity to appreciate their
culture and other people’s cultures (Gay 2000).
The application of this theory is evident when used to understand how
different people from different cultures use and understand mathematics. The
theory explores how different people use mathematics in their daily workplace
activities. Research has been conducted to describe how bus conductors, for
instance, compute their mental mathematical calculations and to examine how
this insight can enhance the study of everyday mathematics (Naresh 2008). The
theory can also be applied to informal situations in teaching of mathematics to
specific groups like prisoners or even in schools. In school situations, the approach
empowers learners and widens the pedagogical understanding of both teachers
and learners (Naresh 2015).
One of the strengths of Ethnomathematical Theory is that when applied to
school situations, it promotes the equality of all students as they get to express
their cultures in the classroom. It also offers students opportunities to appreciate
the contributions of cultures in the establishment of a global society. This is made
possible through the ethics of diversity advanced by the theory (D’Ambrosio &
D’Ambrosio 2013:22).
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
167
A limitation of the theory is that it generally maintains the mainstream or
Eurocentric dominance in the field of mathematics while claiming to promote
equity since the subject is understood and used based on cultural perceptions
(Rowlands & Carson 2002). Hence, critics advocate for a homogenous curriculum
and pedagogy in teaching mathematics (Brandt & Chernoff 2015).
Relativity Theory
Relativity Theory, initiated by Albert Einstein in 1905, is a complex mathematical
postulate. Unlike Newton’s theory which assumes that the problems of Newtonian
Mechanics can be resolved with algebra alone, for Relativity Theory the degree
at which time moves and an object’s length with regards to speed of time change
noticeably with the speed with which the object approaches the speed of light
(Einstein 2011). This means that more computations and more variables
are needed to figure out an object’s motion. Einstein’s theory with its famous
equation E = mc2 (E = units of energy, m = units of mass, and c2 = the speed of
light squared, or multiplied by itself ) brings us the calculation that it takes light
from the sun eight minutes to reach Earth (Plus Magazine 2016).
In their application of the theory in an African context, James and his
colleagues did the following:
[They] calculated seismic velocities and rock densities from approximately 120
geothermobarometrically calibrated mantle xenoliths from the Archean Kaapvaal
craton and adjacent Proterozoic mobile belts. Velocity and density estimates are
based on the elastic and thermal moduli of constituent minerals under equilibrium
P–T conditions at the mantle source (James et al. 2004:1).
The researchers found that both xenoliths and generic petrologic models of the
upper mantle differ from commonly used standard earth models IASPEI (the
International Association of Seismology and Physics of the Earth’s Interior) and
PREM (Preliminary Reference Earth Model) (James et al. 2004:29). Relativity
Theory applies here because it is one of the two dynamic theories of plate tectonics
that are used to conduct research on the aforementioned earth models. The other
theory used in this area of research is quantum mechanics, which describes the
physical properties of nature at the scale of atoms and subatomic particles.
One of the strengths of Einstein’s theory hinges on the postulate that
mathematics cannot deal with contradictions; it requires an allegiance to axioms
or premises and postulates. The beauty of the theory lies in its simplicity, which
makes it one of the best-kept secrets in the sciences (Williams 2005). Nevertheless,
the theory is not without limitations. Williams (2005) points out that Relativity
Theory is intimidating, leading some observers to assume that they would need a
degree in advanced physics to understand it.
168
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Ideal-Proof Dialectic Theory
The Ideal-Proof Dialectical Theory in mathematics presents a more modulated
resolution of mathematical problems, giving proofs and discoveries that are
achieved by paying attention to the aspects of mathematical argumentation
which can be captured by informal, rather than formal, logic. Proofs are usually
presented as inductive-defined data structures like plan lists, boxed lists, or
trees, that are constructed according to the axioms and rules of inference of
logical system. Thus, as Jeremy Avigad maintains, the definition of the theory
‘is syntactic in nature, in contrast to a model theory, which is semantic in
nature’ (Avigad 2006:1).
Dialectic or dialectics (Greek word dialektike) is related to dialogue. Literature
indicates that the theory was one of the philosophies of Socrates and Plato in the
fourth and fifth centuries BC. According to Aristotle, the theory was propounded
by a pre-Socrates philosopher named Zeno of Elea (Popper 2004). Socrates’s main
objective was to improve upon the process of interlocutors by doing away with
unrecognised error and teaching the spirit of inquiry.
Dialectic Theory is different from a debate. There are three dialectic
components:
1. the thesis or the statement of an idea,
2. the reaction or the antithesis, and
3. the synthesis or the combination of the first two (i.e. thesis and antithesis) to
form a theory or system (Smith 2017).
The pioneer of Proof Theory was German mathematician David Hilbert
(1862–1943), who initiated the Hilbert Program as a proposed solution to the
foundational crisis of mathematics. Writers like Gottlob Frege, Giuseppe Peano,
Bertrand Russell and Richard Dedekind made contributions to the theory
(Smith 2017).
According to Munene (2011), the main idea behind the theory was to give
a finite proof for all the complex formal theories needed by mathematicians, so
that these theories could be grounded in terms of mathematics for an adequate
output. The theory can be used for mathematical arguments, showing that all
their purely universal assertions are finitely true.
Simon Blackburn (2004) writes that dialectic can be used to understand the
process of enlightenment. For example, one can find a path to enlightenment
through a mathematical algorithm – a process or set of rules to be followed in
calculations or other problem-solving operations. It is an expression of the beauty
in mathematics that it can yield such freedom and peace.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
169
Peace and Conflict Resolution
Negative Peace vs Positive Peace Paradigm
The renowned scholar and founding father of the field of peace studies, Johan
Galtung (1969), posits that the definition of peace depends on one’s understanding
of what violence is. In a 1964 study titled ‘An Editorial: Armed Conflicts 1946–
2010’ Galtung develops the two-sided description of peace:
1. positive peace – the situation of an absence of indirect or structural violence; and
2. negative peace which denotes an absence of visible or direct violence (see also
Boulding 1978; Grewal 2003).
Negative peace is the absence of violence, war and chaos, while positive peace is
emancipatory in nature, and implies the integration of human society (Galtung 1964).
Peace research involves the study of the conditions for moving closer to peace or at
least not drifting closer to violence (Galtung 1964). The concept ‘structural violence’
was placed in opposition to ‘human integration’ in Galtung’s 1964 study on peace.
These concepts are relevant in social and political philosophy today (Grewal 2003).
The major difference between negative peace and positive peace is stated by
Grewal as follows: ‘Negative peace is absence of violence, pessimistic, curative,
peace not always by peaceful means, while positive peace is structural integration,
optimistic, preventive, peace by peaceful means’ (2003:4). Grewal (2003) says
negative peace is common in a world dominated by a small number of superpowers
that possess coercive power with the readiness to use it.
The conceptualisation of conflict resolution as depending on an understanding
of violence, both direct and indirect, is the central point of Negative and Positive
Peace Theory. The founding assumption of peace research was to study the
conditions that attract peace while averting violence. Galtung conceptualised
negative peace as the absence of violence and positive peace as the integration of
human society and maintained that the two were interconnected and inseparable.
Negative peace can be seen in the military interventions of the superpowers using
their coercive power to end conflicts, war, or violence. For Galtung, this kind of
action occasionally leads to positive peace, although he did not endorse this form
of negative peace.
In his application of this theory to an African context, Makanda (2014) seeks
to understand the failings of the AU and ICC peace-building approach used
for resolving the 2007–2008 post-election violence in Kenya. He concludes that
the negative-positive peace approach advocated by Galtung offers a more robust
solution for dealing with post-conflict peace building.
The strength of the theory is in line with Galtung’s proposition that negative
peace may be essential for positive peace (Sandole 2010). Although the concept
of positive and negative peace has been expanded, the change has not altered
the basic paradigm in which negative peace is the absence of visible and direct
170
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
violence, while positive peace is emancipatory in nature (Grewal 2003). This idea
has remained the foundation of peace theory and a valuable concept for realistic
international relations theory.
Oliver Richmond (2015:3) says ‘hybridity’ characterises the contingent and
complex nature of the politics of peacemaking and the dynamics of power,
agency, and identity it involves. According to Staub (2005), in a post-conflict
society, addressing effective war resolution systems requires the participation of
all participants in the war (victims, committers, humanity, and decision makers),
thereby promoting the relevance of the negative and positive peace paradigm.
For a limitation of the theory, Sandole (2010) posits that irrespective of the
advantages of negative-positive peace, it fails in solving the fundamental causes
and conditions of conflicts. At the end of a war, various conflict resolution or
solution mechanisms arise which tend to solve issues from a political angle and
neglect the basic causes of conflicts, war, and violence (Sandole 2010).
Peace through Communication and Conflict Resolution Paradigm
The concept of ‘peace’ has its basis in both religion and culture. Embedded in
the concept of peace are values of security, harmony, justice, and human dignity
(Sponsel 2017). Peace is a continuous process of skilfully dealing with and, if
possible, preventing or transforming conflict. The concept of peace is always
used for an enduring solution in a conflict-ridden community. Abdul Karim
Bangura opines that ‘positive peace will eliminate the factors that spark violent
conflict. The process of establishing positive peace will require negotiations and
cooperation’ (Bangura 2012:215).
The presence of conflict in every human society has made peace – desired
by all – elusive. The Peace through Communication and Conflict Resolution
Paradigm provides a pragmatic approach to peace through the development and
refinement of skills for analysing conflicts and responding to them with effective
strategies of communication and negotiation. It emphasises the processes of
interaction among individuals and groups and the relationships that characterise
such interactions (Bangura 2012).
The Conflict Resolution feature of the paradigm addresses the causes of
conflicts and seeks to build a new and lasting relationship between and among
hostile groups. It seeks to devise a way to counteract the sensationalism and
divisiveness that lead to conflict by focusing on viable options of living and working
together. Examples of conflict resolution mechanisms are negotiation, mediation,
arbitration, third-party intervention, peace-making, peace enforcement,
and peace-building, among others. The Peace through Communication and
Conflict Resolution Paradigm seeks ways of ensuring the absence of violence
and the integration of human society by engaging the parties to a conflict in
communication with each other to settle their differences (Bangura 2012).
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
171
The paradigm advocates for a total departure from habitual conflict
management styles (competitive, collaborative, avoidance or submission) in order
to bring about a ‘win-win’ situation rather than ‘win-lose’ or’ lose-lose’. This is
done with the assistance of an external third party or moderator. Proponents
of the peace through communication and conflict resolution paradigm like
Mahatma Gandhi and Bangura advocate direct interaction with the ‘other’: i.e. if
you want peace, then you have to train for the processes of peace. Peace is tied to
developing skills for communication and coexistence.
This paradigm is linked to various distinctions between ‘negative peace’, which
is the absence of direct violence, and ‘positive peace’, which is the absence of
indirect or structural violence’ as noted by Galtung. Boutros Boutros-Ghali in his
An Agenda for Peace (1992) defines peacebuilding as the mechanisms put in place
to address the root causes of conflict in such a way that relapses are prevented.
According to Bangura (2006), the positive notion of communication
postulates that unless the peace deals with the underlying issues, the peace will
not last. Rather than empowering individuals in the conflict, African tradition
places emphasis on empowering communities. Unlike in the Western World
where written agreements close the resolution of a conflict, Africans use rituals
and other symbolic gestures such as handshakes, breaking of bread, or drinking
of a local brew from the same bowl.
An application of the Peace through Communication and Conflict Resolution
Paradigm on an African issue can be found in Bangura’s 2012 work in the
discussion of ‘The Wajir Peace Dialogue’. The inhabitants of Wajir, a district
in north-eastern Kenya bordering Somalia, are pastoralists. There is constant
competition over limited resources such as water, grass, and livestock in this
area. In 1993, this resulted in raiding, robbery and general lawlessness, loss
of life and properties. This problem prompted a group of women to form an
advocacy group to facilitate a dialogue among the parties in the conflict, with
the aim of a peaceful resolution. They convinced the elders of the importance of
ending the violent conflict. They held a community conference that involved all
stakeholders: elders, youth, women, religious leaders, and businesspeople. The
outcome of the conference was a peace declaration and a set of principles to
guide the community in its search for peace. They held an annual festival after
embarking on disarmament and gave an award to the most peaceful village (for
more details, see Bangura 2012).
The strengths of this paradigm lie in the fact that it promotes peaceful
coexistence. It is less expensive to manage than war and peacekeeping, and it calls
on people to reflect on and develop skills of communication and patience. The
limitation of the paradigm is captured by Fogarty (cited in Albert 2008) when he
states that values and justice in different societies are conceptualised differently,
thereby making the paradigm problematic: the assurance of basic human survival
differs from one society to the other.
172
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Peace through Law and World Order Paradigm
‘Peace’ is often defined as freedom from war or a state/period of no war or
when war has ended or being free from disturbances, while ‘order’ is frequently
defined as ‘the arrangement or disposition of people or things in relation to each
other according to a particular sequence, pattern, or method or an authoritative
command or instruction’ (Ranney 2012:3). One of the earliest proponents of
the Peace through Law and World Order Paradigm was British legal philosopher
Jeremy Bentham, who in his 1789 Plan for Universal and Perpetual Peace
proposed ‘a plan of general and permanent pacification for all Europe,’ with
troop reductions, especially in naval forces, and ‘a Common Court of Judicature’
(Ranney 2012:3).
The main notion of the paradigm is substituting the use of force with the
rule of law to resolve international conflict. The paradigm advocates societal
friendship and harmony in the absence of hostility and violence through the
rule of law. The idea is to conceptualise the process of peace through legal and
policy processes. The ideal of peace is very important in political and governance
practices. The cultivation of a peaceful disposition for oneself and others can
contribute to resolving of otherwise seemingly irreconcilable competing interests,
without the use of coercive power (Kelsen 2000).
An application of the theory to Africa issues is reflected in the work of
Mwalimu Toyin Falola and Raphael Chijioke Njoku (2011) who posit that
while armed conflicts in Africa have led to havoc, ironically, most conflicts in
society have been settled through negotiations and dialogue. They report that the
Western approach to conflict resolution using sophisticated weapons has failed
on the Africa continent over the years. This brings to mind the traditional ways
of settling disputes in Africa.
The strengths of the Peace through Law and World Order Paradigm
have resulted in the reduction and prevention of war, which has given rise
to democracy and political tranquillity in countries such as Senegal. It has
enhanced the building of strong state institutions and broadened a range of
agendas and sectors for development, security, governance and humanitarian
aid among others.
The weakness of the paradigm is that the international community is not
able to check the essence of the applicability of the law in developing countries.
This is a result of the international community still being largely dominated by
states with powerful governmental and non-governmental organisations (NGOs)
which strive to promote self-serving agendas rather than the interests of countries
they purport to assist.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
173
Peace through Nonviolence Paradigm
Holmes (1971) proffers the Peace through Nonviolence Paradigm from a
philosophical point of view. The theory assumes that nonviolence involves a
significant degree of power and is a forceful concept. It is not a passive form
of struggle, but a highly active struggle applying political, social and economic
pressure to overcome an opponent (Sharp 1973). Nonviolence has two strands:
1. pragmatic and
2. principled.
Principled nonviolence is a philosophy of life while pragmatic nonviolence is a
method used to achieve social or political change. Nonviolence includes pacifism,
strikes, civil disobedience, civil resistance and large-scale nonviolent campaigns
(Sharp 1973).
Pioneers of this theory include Mahatma Gandhi, Gene Sharp, and Martin
Luther King Jr. Truth and ahimsa (which, in the Hindu, Buddhist, and Jainist
tradition, means respect for all living things and avoidance of violence toward
others) are the two pillars of Gandhi’s moral structure. Gandhi coined the
concept satyagraha, which refers to holding on to truth in a firm way. Ahimsa
provides guidance for humans to discover complete truth (Gandhi 1961).
According to Gene Sharp, nonviolence consists of: ‘non-violent direct action,
non-resistance, peaceful resistance, active reconciliation, moral resistance, nonviolent revolution, selective non-violence, passive resistance, and satyagraha’
(Sharp 1959:46). For Martin Luther King Jr., nonviolence is a practical moral
principle. He illustrates his philosophical commitment to nonviolence by
outlining five notions. First, nonviolence is not for cowards. Second, it aims at
acceptance and the forging of friendship with an opponent without harming
him/her. Third, it is aimed at evil acts and not at the actor. Fourth, it is not
a fight against individuals but against oppressive structures. And fifth, it is
situated in self-suffering, which King considers a course of discovering oneself
and healing from bitterness (King 1958).
Nonviolence always involves a process of a person desisting from harm to
himself or herself and others. Positioned on an ethical, religious foundation
and on a collective philosophy of absence of violence, theorists believe that it
is not essential to harm people, animals or the environment so as to achieve
a goal. The paradigm focuses on the search for truth which seeks to deal
with the source of problems rather than the system of conflict (Naess 1965).
Nonviolence works perfectly and is morally acceptable in the fight for truth
and for peacebuilding in societies. Therefore, according to the Peace through
Nonviolence Paradigm, genuine power derives from will power and human
solidarity rather than violence.
174
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
A study by Batstone (2014) outlines how a nonviolent civilian resistance
strategy was successfully applied during the Arab Spring in Tunisia and Egypt
against repressive regimes. Oppressed masses stormed the streets in protests in
a fight against oppressive authoritarian regimes which had denied them their
freedom and human rights. The theory can be applied in the search for justice
and social reforms and societal equity, fighting internally oppressive governments,
and solving long standing conflicts and oppression.
A major strength of this approach is that it shields agents against the outrages
that combative conflict resolution movements constantly create. When successful,
the approach produces positive regime change as leaders who ascend to power
non-violently are likely to respect democracy and civil liberties. More people are
likely to participate in nonviolent campaigns than in violent ones as the moral,
physical and informational barriers to participation are much lower than for
violent insurgency (Chenoweth & Stephan 2011).
A weakness of the theory is that nonviolence does not always work to bring
about major socio-political change as such struggles can be crushed by regimes.
Only a small fraction of nonviolent campaigns remains consistent with strict
nonviolent discipline. Several resort to guerrilla tactics when nonviolence fails, as
in the cases of Palestine and Kosovo (Dudouet 2015) and it has proven difficult
to apply in societies that lack free media and freedom of association.
Peace through Personal and Community Transformation or Love Paradigm
This paradigm advocates for the imperative of consciousness, education, cultural
changes, and of spirituality in all genuine attempts to make peace a reality. The
paradigm postulates that through personal transformation, a person is empowered
and can positively impact his/her community. Human nature is viewed within
this paradigm as optimistic and good. The decision making is a movement from
within the self toward the outer world. Some of the virtues and values given
prominence within this paradigm are integrity, creativity, community, respect,
and cooperation. These are demonstrated by the behaviours of the masses and
by society as a whole. It is believed within this paradigm that ‘individual or
community conscience is strong enough to act as a sanction for any wrongdoing’
(Bangura 2012:217).
Essentially, transformation involves the cultivation of a peaceful consciousness
and character together with an affirmative belief system and skills through which
internal disarmament and personal integration may be expressed. Peaceful
behaviour is learned behaviour, and each individual is a potential as well as a
needed contributor to a culture of peace. Therefore, from the Peace through
Personal and Community Transformation or Love Paradigm, peace-making is
also an internal process in which the transformation of an individual becomes a
metaphor for and an instrument of broader change (Bangura 2012).
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
175
Mahatma Ghandi, Julius Nyerere and Abdul Karim Bangura are proponents
of this theory. Bangura, for instance, explains that within this paradigm through
inner personal transformation, one is empowered and can impact his/her
community (Bangura 2012).
The application of this theory on an African issue is described in Shaw’s 2000
work cited in Bangura’s 2012 work. The story goes as follows: Queen Nefertari
Merit-en-mut (the last name means ‘the lovely one’) was the Great Royal Wife of
Ramesses the Great. She is one of the best-known Egyptian queens. Her marriage
to Ramesses of lower Ancient Kemet/Egypt is one of the greatest royal love affairs
in history. The marriage brought to an end the hundred years of war between
upper and lower Kemet, leading to the unification of both into one great Kemet.
The monuments of love still exist today in the temples built by Ramesses for his
wife at Abu Simbel.
The paradigm places a premium on love and transformation as the best
mechanisms of resolving a conflict and uniting enemies. Some conflicts, however,
require that resolution be achieved through forceful means which the paradigm
cannot fulfil.
Peace through Power and Coercion Paradigm
The Peace through Power and Coercion Paradigm is rooted in the works of
Thucydides (c. 460–c. 400 BC) and later elaborated in the works of Thomas
Hobbes (1588–1679), Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli (1469–1527) and
others (Funk 2000). This paradigm highlights the dark side of the human
psyche, the desire for power and the competitive promotion of self-serving
interests. Peace is therefore only achievable through the coercive use of force
(Funk 2000). The Peace Research Institute Frankfurt (PRIF) defines coercion
as ‘the threat and/or the actual imposition of costs on an actor that is directed
towards eliminating this actor’s freedom of action with regard to a specific set
of actions’ (PRIF 2018:6).
One of the proponents of this paradigm, Nathan Funk (2000), posits that
for peace to exist, a nation must be ready for war. This is to be expected because
competition breeds violence. When this happens, peace is secured through the
forcible infliction of law and order. In the use of coercion, violence is unlawful
and is often a violation of rules and, therefore, possibly subject to reprimand by
some authority. Citing Jane Manbridge, the Peace Research Institute Frankfurt
argues that ‘in an increasingly interdependent world we need more coercion
in order to guarantee the provision of public goods such as peace, security and
wellbeing’ (PRIF 2018:9).
In the application of this approach, policies are formulated to pander to a
nation’s assumed national interest which Funk describes as the ‘the acquisition of
material power and military capability to compel and deter others’ (Funk 2000:2).
176
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
This paradigm can be seen in use in Malcolm X’s intervention in the Congo War,
of which Bangura says: ‘The United Nations dialogue on the Congo was one of
Malcolm X’s finest hours. The State Department credited him or rather blamed
him for a good part of the strong stand against American imperialism in the
Congo. Malcolm X unquestionably was threatening the United States’ role as
leader of the “free world”’ (Bangura 2016:75).
Bangura also notes that Malcolm X ‘took a stance against the nonviolent
way Martin Luther King Jr. handled the Civil Rights Movement. Malcolm X
preached violence to counterattack violence. Infuriated by the atrocities of Jim
Crow laws and Ku Klux Klan violence in the Southern states, Malcolm X saw
an increase of resistance to violence as the only answer to an augmentation of
rights’ (Bangura 2016:88). Bangura argues that Malcolm X believed that ‘peace,
freedom, and action were tied in undeniable ways. Furthermore, Malcom X used
his “true” Islam, discovered through brotherhood, to send messages of peaceful
action to all races and religions, all of which presently contribute to Malcolm X’s
legacy’ (Bangura 2016: 82)
The threats which are part of coercion may be in different forms: they may be
implicit, explicit, verbal, written, implied, in the form of actions to follow after a
warning, the cancellation of an agreement, a boycott, military action, and so on
(Rummel 1975). The strength of this paradigm lies in its call for the enforcement
of certain rules and regulations which some factions of the citizenry may find
problematic. Its weakness is in the coercive aspect, which bears some elements
of force.
Peace through Respect
The Peace through Respect Paradigm is as old as the existence of humankind.
As humans coexisted, and conflicting interests arose, the increasing need for a
better way of living together birthed ideas that could reduce the effects of conflict
in society. With the principle of collective security that formally established the
United Nations (www.un.org) in 1945 and the Human Rights Declaration of
1948 (United Nations 1948), these concepts became important in global and local
politics. The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization
(UNESCO) declaration of states in 1989 formally grounded the idea of peace
through respect, stating that peace is more than the end of armed conflict;
it is a mode of behaviour with deep-rooted commitment to the principles of
liberty, justice, equality and solidarity among all. This definition underpins the
paradigm. In essence, peace is examined through respect for persons (regardless
of race, sex, background, religion, or ideology), law, environment and traditions.
The common good is a sine qua non for a peaceful society. Peace through Respect
refers to a demand for rights and equal treatment to advance the dignity of a
person as a human being (Sen 2011).
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
177
Bearing in mind the far-reaching effect of violent conflicts on societies and
humankind, a peaceful world that is achieved through respect is critical. Both
international and state actors have been burdened with managing incessant
conflicts, especially because of the rise of global terrorism (Adetula 2014).
Specifically, for Africa, considering the volume of armed conflicts, which
hinge on the transcultural and multidimensional relationships acros the
continent, the African ideology on communalism, couched in sharing and
cooperation for the common good, gives credence to the Peace through Respect
Paradigm. In essence, the nature of civil wars and armed conflicts in Africa,
induced by ethnicity, religion, resource mobilisation and allocations, appears to
be a deviation from the principle of respect informing peace in the continent.
Consequently, since most conflicts in Africa are outgrowths of mistrust and
intolerance, the Peace through Respect Paradigm provides a fundamental basis
for understanding the dynamics between incessant conflicts and respect for
human dignity in Africa.
Although not all member states in the international system comply with
the rules guiding engagement, the paradigm shows its merits in numerous
international treaties and agreements binding signatories, such as the agreements
on trade and security. And, where there is a breach of an agreement, the use of
sanctions is explored when necessary. Importantly, these agreements are premised
on mutual respect for a peaceful international community, thereby averting the
possibility of a Third World War or nuclear war. Significantly, this systematic
pattern of peace and respect has resulted in more interconnectedness in the global
space, leading to more innovation and advancement for all.
Nevertheless, the idea of advancing peace through respect is not without its
limitations. In the proliferation of terrorist groups and separatist agitation, antigovernmental groups base their demands on specific group ideologies, whether in
conformity with the common good or not. The Peace through Respect Paradigm
which is based on the equality of all is problematic in this context. Under the law,
all citizens are equal. But resource control and allocation, and the ethnic rivalry
characterising Africa, allows marginalisation and disproportional representation
to sow the seeds for exclusion and inequality.
Peace through Ubuntu/Communalism Paradigm
The transformative effect of culture in determining human relations has
increasingly generated scholarly interest in recent times, making the Ubuntu
ideology a fundamental discourse in promoting peace and development in Africa.
In other words, a methodical frame showing the relationship between peace and
Ubuntu is imperative for understanding Africa’s particular characteristics in order
to advance a peaceful society.
178
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
As mentioned earlier in this book, the term Ubuntu originated from Nguni
aphorism Umuntu Ngumuntum Ngabantu, meaning that ‘a person is a person
because of or through others’ (Tutu 2004:25–26; Moloketi 2009:243). This
ideology of peace through Ubuntu hinges on the five stages of peacemaking
found among Ubuntu societies:
1.
2.
3.
4.
acknowledging guilt,
showing remorse,
repenting,
asking for and giving forgiveness, and
5. paying compensation or reparations (Murithi 2009).
These five stages signify the principles of reconciliation, reciprocity, inclusivity,
democracy, and humanism.
Asike (2016) affirms that Ubuntu is an African construct bearing both
positive and negative peacebuilding approaches in promoting tolerance, peaceful
coexistence, a culture of peace and, by extension, mutual development. Essentially,
it is a cultural global view of the dignity in humanity. Tutu (1999) succinctly puts
it that the Ubuntu ideology speaks to the very essence of being human; there is
interconnectedness in humanity that binds everyone together. The Peace through
Ubuntu or Communalism Paradigm is premised on the assumption that human
beings are only humans by virtue of their relationships with others in a society.
The levels of corruption and widespread disconnection among citizens and
their governments in most African states are not only appalling, they also have
hampered the quest for development on the continent. A survey on citizens’
views on corruption by Transparency International (2019) reveals that corruption
undermines chances for a stable and prosperous future, affecting the wellbeing
of individuals, families, and communities. Hence, as African citizens suffer the
consequences of corruption by the political elite, citizens’ apathy and unpatriotic
tendencies toward the state increase and become toxic. Unvaryingly, the political
class exacerbates security issues and the state of unrest. Violence then becomes
a weapon for marginalised citizens, especially with the median age of Africa’s
population being 19.5 years (UNDP 2017). For instance, in Northeast Nigeria,
the large conscription of youths into the Boko Haram group has been attributed
to the high unemployment and illiteracy levels in the region (United Kingdom
Border Agency 2013). The ripple effect of the negligence of the state in its
obligation to the people is evident in kidnappings, rapes, and suicide bombings,
all of which affect not only the poor but the rich and political class as well.
Against this backdrop, the Ubuntu spirit which asserts that what we do to others
eventually trickles down through the interwoven fabric of social, economic and
political relationships to influence the general public should be incorporated as a
way to bring peace in African governance.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
179
This ideology undermines ethnic fragmentation that breeds centrifugal forces
and rather focuses on humanity. It also promotes unity in diversity. This ideology
was used by Nelson Mandela and Desmond Tutu in restoring peace in South
Africa. Similarly, the principle promotes social and common good. Nonetheless,
the Ubuntu philosophy is not well known in parts of Africa beyond Southern
Africa; thus, its applicability in those other parts of the continent could be
problematic without serious efforts to educate other Africans about its tenets.
References
Abes, E.S. and Kasch, D., 2007, ‘Using Queer Theory to Explore Lesbian College
Students’ Multiple Dimensions of Identity’, Journal of College Student Development,
Vol. 48, No. 6, pp. 619–636.
Abungu, Maurice, 1997, ‘Character Transformation and Socio-Historical Awareness
in the Novels of Marjorie Oludhe Macgoye’, Master’s thesis, Kenyatta University,
Nairobi, Kenya.
Adetula, Victor Adebola, 2014, ‘African Conflicts, Development and Regional
Organisations in the Post-Cold War International System’, Annual Claude Ake
Memorial Lecture, Nordiska Afrikainstitutet, Uppsala, Sweden, January 30, 2014.
(https://searchworks.stanford.edu/view/11473060). 6 October 2021.
Albert, I.O., 2008, ‘Understanding Peace in Africa’, in D. J. Francis, ed., Peace and
Conflict in Africa, New York, NY: Zed Books Ltd.
Ascher, Marcia, 2008, ‘Ethnomathematics’, in H. Selin, ed., Encyclopaedia of the History
of Science, Technology, and Medicine in Non-Western Cultures, Dordrecht, The
Netherlands: Springer.
Asike, Jude Chinweuba, 2016, ‘The Philosophical Concept of “Ubuntu” as Dialogic
Ethic and the Transformation of Political Community in Africa’, OGIRISI: A New
Journal of African Studies, Vol. 12, pp. 1–16. (https://www.ajol.info/index.php/og/
article/view/140090). 6 October 2021.
Avigad, Jeremy, 2006, ‘Mathematical Method and Proof ’, Synthese, Vol. 153, No. 1,
pp. 105–159.
Avigad, Jeremy, 2008, ‘Understanding Proofs’, in P. Mancosu, ed., The Philosophy of
Mathematical Practice, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, ed., 2008, African Peace Paradigms, Dubuque, IA: Kendall/Hunt
Publishing Company.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2012, ‘Post-Election Conflict Resolution in Africa: Lessons
from African Peace Paradigms’, in A.G. Adebayo, ed., Managing Conflicts in Africa’s
Democratic Transitions, Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2016, ‘Malcolm X and United States Policies towards Africa:
A Qualitative Analysis of His Black Nationalism and Peace through Power and
Coercion Paradigms’, Africology: The Journal of Pan African Studies, Vol. 9, No. 4,
pp. 65–96. (http://www.jpanafrican.org/docs/vol9no4/JuneJuly-6-Bangura-MXfinal.pdf ). 6 October 2021.
Batstone, John, 2014, ‘The Use of Strategic Nonviolent Action in the Arab Spring’, Peace
Review, Vol. 26, No. 1, pp. 28–37.
180
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Beaumont, J., and Baker, C., eds., 2011, Postsecular Cities: Space, Theory and Practice,
(Continuum Resources in Religion and Political Culture), London, UK: Continuum.
(http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781472549198). 4 October 2021.
Bertens, Hans, 2008, Literary Theory: The Basics, London, UK: Routledge.
Birchall, Ian, 1977, ‘Marxism and Literature’, The Sociological Review, Vol. 25,
No. S1, pp. 92–108. (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1467-954X.1977.tb03233.x).
4 October 2021.
Blackburn, Simon, 2004, Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd edition, Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press.
Bolanos, Paolo, 2013, ‘What is Critical Theory? Max Horkheimer and the Makings of
the Frankfurt School Tradition’. (https://www.academia.edu/9844158/What_is_
Critical_Theory_Max_Horkheimer_and_the_Makings_of_the_Frankfurt_School_
Tradition). 13 November 2021.
Boulding, Kenneth, 1978, ‘Future Directions in Conflict and Peace Studies’, The Journal
of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 22, No. 2, pp. 342–354.
Boutros-Ghali, Boutros, 1992, An Agenda for Peace: Preventative Diplomacy, Peacemaking
and Peacekeeping, New York, NY: United Nations Publications.
Brandt, Alex and Chernoff, Egan J., 2015, ‘The Importance of Ethnomathematics in
the Math Class’, Ohio Journal of School Mathematics, No. 71, pp. 31–36. (https://
kb.osu.edu/handle/1811/78917). 5 October 2021.
Brannigan, John, 1998, New Historicism and Cultural Materialism, New York,
NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Castle, Gregory, 2007, The Blackwell Guide to Literary Theory, 1st edition, Singapore,
Malaysia: Blackwell Publishing.
Castle, Gregory, 2009, The Blackwell Guide to Literary Theory, 2nd edition, Singapore,
Malaysia: Blackwell Publishing.
Chenoweth, Erica, and Stephan, Maria J., 2011, Why Civil Resistance Works. The Strategic
Logic of Nonviolent Conflict, New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Coyle, M.; Garside, P.; Kelsall, M. and Peck, J., eds., 1991, Encyclopedia of Literature and
Criticism, Abingdon, UK: Routledge.
Curtis, James M., 1976, ‘Bergson and Russian Formalism’, Comparative Literature,
Vol. 28, No. 2, pp. 109–121.
D’Ambrosio, Ubiratan, 1987, Transdisciplinaridade [Transdisciplinarity], São Paulo,
Brazil: Palas Athena.
D’Ambrosio, Ubiratan, 2001, ‘What Is Ethnomathematics and How Can It Help
Children in School?’, Teaching Children Mathematics, Vol. 7, Issue 6, pp. 308–311.
D’Ambrosio, Ubiratan, and D’Ambrosio, Beatriz Silva, 2013, ‘The Role of
Ethnomathematics in Curricular Leadership in Mathematics Education’, Journal of
Mathematics Education at Teachers College, Vol. 4, No. 1, pp. 19–25.
Dollimore, Jonathan and Sinfield, Alan, eds., 1994, Political Shakespeare: Essays in
Cultural Materialism, New York, NY: Cornell University Press
Drake, Alfred J.; Armstrong, Rick and Steiner, Shep, eds., 2013, The New Criticism:
Formalist Literary Theory in America, London, UK: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
181
Dudouet, Véronique, 2015, Civil Resistance and Conflict Transformation: Transitions from
Armed to Non-violent Struggle, London, UK: Routledge.
Eagleton, Terry, 1996, Literary Theory: An Introduction, 2nd edition, Minneapolis MN:
The University of Minnesota Press.
Eagleton, Terry, 2014, Ideology, London, UK: Routledge.
Einstein, Albert, 2011, Relativity: The Special and the General Theory a Popular Equation,
3rd edition, London, UK: Project Gutenberg.
Elliot, Gregory, ed., 1990, Louis Althusser Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of the
Scientists & Other Essays, London and New York: Verso.
Eward-Mangione, Angela, 2020, ‘Marxist Criticism, Writing Commons. (https://
writingcommons.org/section/research/research-methods/textual-methods/literarycriticism/marxist-criticism/). 17 November 2021.
Falola, Toyin, and Njoku, Raphael Chijioke, 2011, War and Peace in Africa, Durham,
NC: Carolina Academic Press.
Fineman, Martha Albertson, 2009, ‘Evolving Images of Gender and Equality: A Feminist
Journey’, New England Law Review, Vol. 43, pp. 9–73.
Funk, Nathan, 2000, ‘Five Paradigms: Five Approaches to Peace’, Gandhi Marg,
Vol. 24, No. 3, pp. 298–306. (https://www.academia.edu/352904/_Peace_Paradigms_
Five_Approaches_to_Peace_). 6 October 2021.
Galtung, Johan, 1964, ‘An Editorial: Armed Conflicts 1946–2010’, Journal of Peace
Research, Vol. 48, No. 4, pp. 525–536.
Galtung, Johan, 1969, ‘Violence, Peace, and Peace Research’, Journal of Peace Research,
Vol. 6, No. 3, pp. 16–191.
Gay, Geneva, 2000, Culturally Responsive Teaching: Theory, Research, and Practice,
New York, NY: Teachers College Press.
Gerdes, Paulus, 1997, ‘Survey of Current Work on Ethnomathematics’, in A.B. Powell and
M. Frankenstein, eds., Ethnomathematics: Challenging Eurocentrism in Mathematics
Education, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Gandhi, Mohandas, 1961, My Philosophy of Life, compiled by Anand T. Hingorani,
Bombay.
Greenblatt, Stephen, 1980, Renaissance Self‐Fashioning: From More to Shakespeare,
Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Grewal, Baljit, 2003, ‘Johan Galtung: Positive and Negative Peace’, School of Social Science,
Auckland University of Technology, Vol. 30, pp. 23–26. (https://www.academia.
edu/744030/Johan_Galtung_Positive_and_Negative_Peace). 6 October 2021.
Habib, Rafey, 2005, Modern Literary Criticism and Theory: A History, Hoboken,
NJ: Blackwell Publishing.
Hall, Stuart, 1981, ‘Cultural Studies: Two Paradigms’, in T. Bennett, G. Martin, C. Mercer
and J. Woollacott, Culture, ideology and social process: A reader, London: Batsford
Academic and Educational in association with the Open University Press, 1981.
Hansen, J., 2004, ‘Formalism and its Malcontents: Benjamin and de Man on the Function
of Allegory’, New Literary History, Vol. 35, No. 4, pp. 663–683.
182
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Holmes, Robert L., 1971, ‘Violence and Nonviolence’, in J.A. Shaffer, ed., Violence:
Award-winning Essays in the Council for Philosophical Studies Competition, New York,
NY: David McKay Company, Inc.
Hurst, Andrea, 2017, ‘Post-structuralism’, Oxford Bibliographies. (https://www.
oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780190221911/obo9780190221911-0008.xml#). 7 October 2021.
Jagose, A. and Genschel, C., 1996, Queer Theory, Melbourne, Australia: Melbourne
University Press.
James, D.E.; Boyd, F.R.; Schutt, D.; Bell, D.R. and Carlson, R.W., 2004, ‘Xenolith
constraints on seismic velocities in the upper mantle beneath southern Africa’,
Geochemistry, Geophysics, Geosystems, Vol. 5, No. 1, pp. 1–32.
Kelsen, Hans, 2000, Peace through Law, Chapel Hill, NC: The University of North
Carolina Press.
Kieley, M.; Manze, M. and Palmedo, C., 2018, Personal Health: A population perspective,
Burlington, MA: Jones and Bartlett Learning.
King, Jr., Martin Luther, 1958, Stride Toward Freedom: The Montgomery Story, New York,
NY: Harper and Row.
Koller, Armin H., 1912, Johann Gottfried Herder and Hippolyte Taine: Their Theories of
Milieu, PMLA, Vol. 27, p. xxxix.
Levin, Richard, 2003, Looking for an Argument: Critical Encounters with the New
Approaches to the Criticism of Shakespeare and his Contemporaries, Madison, NJ:
Fairleigh Dickinson University Press.
Levinson, Marjorie, 2007, ‘What Is New Formalism?’, Publications of the Modern
Language Association of America, Vol. 122, No. 2, pp. 558–569.
Loesberg, Jonathan, 2015, ‘Wildean Interpretation and Formalist Reading’, Victorian
Studies, Vol. 58, No. 1, pp. 9–33.
Macgoye, Marjorie, 2000, Coming to Birth, New York, NY: The City University of New
York.
Makanda, Joseph, 2014, ‘The AU and ICC’s disagreement over the 2007/8 Kenya’s postelection violence: a challenge to post conflict reconstruction in Africa’, doctoral
dissertation, University of KwaZulu-Natal, South Africa. (https://researchspace.
ukzn.ac.za/handle/10413/12169). 6 October 2021.
Makaryk, Irena, R. 1993, ed., Encyclopedia of Contemporary Literary Theory: Approaches,
Scholars, Terms, Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press.
Merriam-Webster Dictionary, 2021, ‘Post-Structuralism’. (https://www.merriam-webster.
com/dictionary/post-structuralism). 8 November 2021.
Mikkola, Mari, 2008, ‘Feminist Perspectives on Sex and Gender’, Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-gender/). 2 October 2021.
Misra, R.P., 2008, Gandhian Economics and Contemporary Relevance, New Delhi, India:
Concept Publishing Company.
Moloketi, G.R., 2009, ‘Towards a Common Understanding of Corruption in Africa’,
Public Policy and Administration, Vol. 24, No. 3, pp. 331–338.
Munene, Mwaniki, 2011, ‘Language Management in Africa: The Dialectics of Theory
and Practice’, Southern African Linguistics and Applied Language Studies, Vol. 29,
No, 3, pp. 243–257.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
183
Murithi, Tim, 2009, ‘An African Perspective on Peace Education: Ubuntu Lessons in
Reconciliation’, International Review of Education, Vol. 55, pp. 221–233.
Naess, Arne, 1965, Gandhi and the Nuclear Age, Totowa, N.J: Bedminster Press.
Naresh, Nirmala, 2008, ‘Bus Conductors’ Use of Mental Computation in Everyday
Settings: Is It Their Ethnomathematics?’, Journal of Mathematics and Culture,
Vol. 3, pp. 308– 332.
Naresh, Nirmala, 2015, ‘The Role of a Critical Ethnomathematics Curriculum
in Transforming and Empowering Learners’, Revista Latinoamericana de
Etnomatemática, Vol. 8, No. 2, pp. 450–471.
No author, 2019, ‘Traditional Literary Study: The Assumptions’, (https://web.cn.edu/
kwheeler/documents/Traditional_Vs_Theory.pdf ). 28 October 2019.
Olssen, Mark, 2003, ‘Structuralism, Post-structuralism, Neo-liberalism: Assessing
Foucault’s Legacy’, Journal of Education Policy, Vol. 18, No. 2, pp. 189–202. (https://
issuu.com/gfbertini/docs/structuralism__post-structuralism__and_neo-liberal).
7 October 2021.
Ousby, Ian, 1992, The Cambridge Guide to Literature in English, Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Parvini, Neema, 2012, Shakespeare and Contemporary Theory: New Historicism and
Cultural Materialism, New York, NY: Bloomsbury Press.
Peace Research Institute Frankfurt (PRIF), 2018, Coercion and Peace, Frankfort, Germany:
Leibbniz-Institut Hessische Stiftung Friedens-und Konfliktforschung (HSFK).
Peter, Barry, 1995, Beginning Theory, Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press.
Piantato, G., 2016, ‘How Has Queer Theory Influenced the Ways We Think about
Gender?’, Working Paper of Public Health, Vol. 5, No. 1. (https://www.pagepress.
org/journals/index.php/wpph/article/view/6948). 2 October 2021.
Plus Magazine, 2016, ‘Maths in a Minute: Einstein’s General Theory of Relativity’,
University of Cambridge. (https://plus.maths.org/content/maths-minute-einsteinsgeneral-theory-relativity). 5 October 2021.
Popper, Karl R., 2004, What is Dialectic?, Klangenfurt, Germany: University of Klagenfurt
Karl Popper Library Press. (https://www.vordenker.de/ggphilosophy/popper_whatis-dialectic.pdf ). 6 October 2021.
Powell, Arthur B. and Frankenstein, Marilyn, 1997, ‘Ethnomathematics Praxis in
the Curriculum’, in A.B. Powell and M. Frankenstein, eds., Ethnomathematics:
Challenging Eurocentrism in Mathematics Education, New York, NY: State University
of New York Press.
Purdue Online Writing Lab, undated, ‘Gender Studies and Queer Theory (1970s-present)’.
(https://owl.purdue.edu/owl/subject_specific_writing/writing_in_literature/
literary_theory_and_schools_of_criticism/gender_studies_and_queer_theory.
html). 19 November 2021.
Ranney, James T., 2012, ‘World Peace through Law: Rethinking an Old Theory’, Cadmus
Journal, Vol. 5, No. 1. (https://www.cadmusjournal.org/article/issue-5/world-peacethrough-law-rethinking-old-theory). 6 October 2021.
Reddy, Vasu, 2005, ‘Moffies, Stabanis, and Lesbos: The political construction of queer
identity in southern Africa’, PhD dissertation, Department of Gender Studies,
School of Social Science, University of Kwazulu-Natal, South Africa. (https://
researchspace.ukzn.ac.za/handle/10413/2063). 2 October 2021.
184
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Richmond, Oliver, 2014, ‘The dilemmas of a hybrid peace: Negative or positive?’,
Cooperation and Conflict, Vol. 50, No. 1, pp. 50–68. (https://journals.sagepub.com/
doi/10.1177/0010836714537053). 6 October 2021.
Rowlands, Stuart, and Carson, Robert, 2002, ‘Where Would Formal, Academic
Mathematics Stand in a Curriculum Informed by Ethnomathematics? A Critical
Review of Ethnomathematics’, Educational Studies in Mathematics, Vol. 50, No. 1,
pp. 79–102. (doi:10.1023/A:1020532926983). 5 October 2021.
Rummel, Rudolph, 1975–1981, Understanding Conflict and War Volume 1 to 5, Beverly
Hills, CA: Sage Publications.
Said, Edward W., 1979, Orientalism, New York, NY: Vintage Books.
Sandole, Dennis J.D., 2010, Peacebuilding, War and Peace in the Modern World,
Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Sen, Amartya K., ed., 2011, ‘Why Do Respect and Understanding Matter?’ in Peace
and Democratic Society, Cambridge, UK: Open Book Publishers. (https://books.
openedition.org/obp/138?lang=en). 21 October 2021.
Sharp, Gene, 1959, ‘The Meanings of Nonviolence: A Typology’, Journal of Conflict
Resolution, Vol. 3, No. 1, pp. 41–66.
Sharp, Gene, 1973, Politics of Nonviolent Action, Boston, MA: Porter Sargent Publishers.
Singh, Amritjit and Schmidt, Peter, eds., 2000, Postcolonial Theory and the United States:
Race, Ethnicity, and Literature, Jackson, MS: University Press of Mississippi.
Slack, Jennifer Daryl and Grossberg, Lawrence, eds., 2016, Cultural Studies 1983: A
Theoretical History: Stuart Hall, Durham and London, UK: Duke University Press.
Smith, Robin, 2017, ‘Dialectic and Method in Aristotle’, in M. Sim, ed., From Puzzles to
Principles?: Essays on Aristotle’s Dialectic, Victoria, Canada: AbeBooks.
Spivak, Gayatri C., 1988, ‘Can the Subaltern Speak?’ in C. Nelson and L. Grossborg,
eds., Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture, Urbana, IL: University of Illinois
Press.
Sponsel, Leslie E., 2017, ‘The Anthropology of Peace and Nonviolence’, Diogenes, Vol.
61, No. 3–4, pp. 30–45.
Staub, Erwin, 2006, ‘Reconciliation after Genocide, Mass Killing, or Intractable Conflict:
Understanding the Roots of Violence, Psychological Recovery, and Steps toward a
General Theory’, Political Psychology, Vol. 27, No. 6, pp. 867– 894.
Stewart, Alasdair, 2008, ‘Althusser’s Structuralism and a Theory of Class’, Critique,
Vol. 36, No. 3, pp. 421–443.
Transparency International, 2019, Global Corruption Barometer Africa 2019: Citizens’
Views and Experiences of Corruption. (https://www.transparency.org/whatwedo/
publication/gcb_africa_2019). 6 October 2021.
Tutu, Desmond, 1999, No Future Without Forgiveness, New York, NY: Doubleday Books.
Tutu, Desmond, 2004, God Has a Dream: A Vision of Hope for Our Future, New York,
NY: Doubleday Books.
United Kingdom Border Agency, 2013, ‘Nigeria Country of Origin Information (COI)
Report COI Service, 2013’. (https://www.refworld.org/pdfid/51bf06554.pdf ).
6 October 2021.
Doctoral Scholars: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution
185
United Nations Development Programme, 2017, Africa’s Defining Challenge, New York,
NY: United Nations Publications. (https://www.africa.undp.org/content/rba/en/
home/blog/2017/8/7/africa_defining_challenge.html). 6 October 2021.
UNESCO, 1989, International Congress on Peace in the Minds of Men, 26 June–1 July
1992, Yamoussoukro, Côte d’Ivoire: final report. (https://unesdoc.unesco.org/
ark:/48223/pf0000092670). 8 November 2021.
United Nations, 1948, Universal Declaration of Human Rights. (https://www.un.org/en/
universal-declaration-human-rights/). 6 October 2021.
Van Manen, Max, 2016, Phenomenology of Practice: Meaning-giving Methods in
Phenomenological Research and Writing, London, UK: Routledge.
Vickers, Brian, 1993, ‘New Historicism: Disaffected Subjects’, in Appropriating
Shakespeare: contemporary critical quarrels, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Weinrib, Ernest, J., 1988, ‘Legal Formalism: On the Immanent Rationality of Law’, Yale
Law Journal, Vol. 97, No 6. pp. 949–1016.
Wilchins, Riki Anne, 2014, Queer Theory, Gender Theory, New York, NY: Riverdale
Avenue Books Publishers.
Williams, Aiden, 2005, ‘Albert Einstein’ (slide player). Slideplayer.com. (https://slideplayer.
com/slide/8133884/). 7 October 2021.
Williams, Raymond, 1961, The Long Revolution, New York, NY: Columbia University
Press.
Wood, J.G., 2013, ‘Model of Dialectical Learning’, in E.G. Carayannis, ed.,
Encyclopedia of Creativity, Invention, Innovation and Entrepreneurship, New York,
NY: Springer.
Zimmerman, Dominik, 2014, Can the ‘Peace through Law’ Approach Work?, Staffordshire,
UK: Staffordshire University Press.
Online Sources
https://plus.maths.org/content/maths-minute-einsteins-general-theory-relativity
https://plus.maths.org/content/whats-so-special-about-special-relativity
www.activeforpeace.org/no/fred/Positive_Negative_Peace.pdf
7
Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and
Sexuality/Gender
Doctoral Scholars
Here, the brief explorations comprise six on politics, two on race and ethnicity,
five on religion and nine on sexuality/gender theories. The first category
deals with activities associated with the governance of a country or other
area, especially the debates or conflicts among individuals or parties having
or hoping to achieve power. The second category looks at theories around
the major divisions of humankind (i.e. Australian Aborigine and Papuan/
Australoid, Black/Negroid, Oriental or Amerindian/Mongoloid, and White/
Caucasoid) having distinct physical characteristics, and state of belonging to
a social group that has a common national or cultural tradition. The third
category is about postulates on the belief in and worship of a superhuman
controlling power, especially a personal God or gods. The fourth category is
related to theories dealing with a person’s sexual orientation or preference –
i.e. relating to the instincts, physiological processes, and activities connected
with physical attraction or intimate physical contact between individuals – or
attributes dealing with two sexes (male and female), especially when considered
with reference to social and cultural differences rather than biological ones. The
term is also now used more broadly to denote a range of identities that do not
correspond to established ideas of male and female.
Politics
Idealist Theory
Idealist Theory is a normative approach that upholds moral values in
international relations through reason, science, and education. It opposes war,
violence, inequality and force at the global level, with the goal of reforming the
188
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
international system by exploring morality as a mechanism for states in securing
their development. This theory is attributed to Woodrow Wilson, Hugo Grotius
and others who thought that politics could be a medium for advancing good life
and respect for all humans at the domestic and international levels. Proponents
of this theory do not support the realist view of international politics centred
on power and national interest; rather, the theory posits that human welfare is a
general concern.
Significantly, Idealist Theory shares some features with African cultural
ideology. The African communal system, which emphasises morality and values
as a means of achieving a harmonious society, is one of the major characteristics
of pre-colonial Africa. In an African sense, this theory informs the numerous
memberships of African nations in international organisations. An idealist view
of the African Continental Free Trade Agreement (AfCFTA ), for example,
suggests that an African unity through economic prosperity is possible. The
AfCFTA is pegged on the growing interdependence and unity of persons and
institutions globally, which cannot be ignored in Africa. The assumption is that
all Africans desire the same thing in terms of security, welfare, recognition, and
respect (Wilson 2011). An idealist perspective presents a cosmopolitan approach
to addressing Africa’s long-term problems, starting with economic relevance.
Intra-African trade is less than 13 per cent, while trade in regional organisations
like the European Union stands at around approximately 60 per cent (African
Union 2019). The idealist perspective of African unity would strengthen African
economies, especially by boosting small and mid-size enterprises (SMEs), thereby
advancing prosperity and development.
An advantage of this theory is that it is anchored in the morality guiding
the formation of international organisations as a way to solve global issues.
Through this value principle, the United Nations and some other international
organisations have averted possible conflicts. Nonetheless, there appears to be a
somewhat incoherent approach to how the ideal can be maintained in practice.
Idealist Theory emphasises the importance of universal bodies as a way to
harmonise the conflicting interest of states and governments in the international
system. However, there is insufficient evidence on why or how conflict can be
eliminated without resorting to war and violence. The theory also does not
take cognisance of the assumed interest underlying every perceived good. Most
United Nations decisions do not reflect the interests of the entire United Nations
membership; rather they reflect the interests of the five permanent members of
the United Nations Security Council (i.e. China, France, the Russian Federation,
the United Kingdom and the United States).
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
189
Marxist Theory
The central variable of the Marxist Theory is power relations. The theory
argues that the location of humans in the class hierarchy is dependent on their
contributions to the processes of production (Parkin 1979). In Das Kapital, Karl
Marx (1818–1883) groups all human relations into two classes:
1. the capitalists – i.e. owners of the businesses and the means of production, and
on the other hand
2. the proletariat – i.e. the labour hands who account for the larger proportion
of the population.
This philosophy, propagated by Karl Marx and followers such as Friedrich Engels,
Max Weber, Walter Rodney and Antonio Gramsci, has at its centre a specific focus
on the activities of capitalism and their attendant manifestations in socio-political
and economic processes. Marx introduced the idea of Base and Superstructure
to explain the relationship between the social classes. The Base comprises the
forces of production and various divisions of labour (employer-employee
relationship, clergy-worshipper relationship, etc.) all of which engage production.
The Superstructure refers to the immaterial: the policies, the state, the various
regulatory institutions and ideology. In orthodox Marxism, the relationship
between the Base and the Superstructure is often unidirectional. Raymond
Williams, on the other hand, attempts to explore economic determinism in a
cycle – in that as much as the base affects the superstructure, the superstructure
also affects the base (Parkin 1979).
The French philosopher Louis Althusser (1918–1990) offers insights into the
level of control that the Superstructure asserts over the Base through the various
agencies of the state. In his engagement on ‘Ideological and Repressive State
Apparatuses’, Althusser demonstrates how the state through its various agencies
wields both brutish and subtle power through repressive and ideological state
apparatuses in the control of the Superstructure. His term ‘interpellation’ (in
other words, ‘hailing’), quoted by Vincent Leitch, explains the process by which
the state turns individuals into subjects (Leitch 2001).
In looking at the manifestations of religion (especially Western religions)
in Africa, which Karl Marx describes as the opium of the masses, one sees in
varying degrees how the Superstructure determines the Base and, on some rare
occasions, vice versa. The volatility of the African political space in postcolonial
dispensations also illustrates Althusser’s thoughts on repressive and ideological
state apparatuses.
The dominance of the Superstructure is exemplified by the way Malawian
literature was affected by the censorship regime of President Kamuzu Banda.
Malawian poets Jack Mapanje, Frank Chipasula and Steve Chimombo faced
repression of various magnitudes (Mthatiwa 2012). Mthatiwa writes:
190
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
During the reign of Banda in Malawi, the dominant political discourse was
shaped by what is called Kamuzuism, an ideology that produced a powerful myth
of Banda as the ‘fountain of all wisdom’ and a leader who always knew what was
best for the nation, that is, an individual who possessed supernatural or divine
wisdom (Mthatiwa 2012:98).
Marxist Theory is a relevant tool for unravelling how the various dimensions of
class play out in both private and public life.
Marxism seeks to curtail the excesses of capitalism and entrench a society of
social equality. But critics like Geoffrey Hodgson have depicted the applicability
of the Marxist doctrine of equality as a farce that only exists in the human
imagination (Hodgson 1995). Critiqued from a different perspective, it can be
said that the goal of Marxism is to achieve a socialist world in which individual
agency is taken away.
Rational Choice Theory or New Political Economy
Rational Choice Theory or New Political Economy is a social science methodology
associated with the works of Gary Becker (1976), along with many other scholars.
This theory is based on the idea that individuals have preferences and make choices
based on these preferences. The theory also holds that collective behaviour in a
society reflects the choices made by individuals. For Wittek et al. (2013), the basis
of all rational choices is individual preference and belief, informed by individual
constraints. The theory identifies three major assumptions:
1. individuals have selfish preferences,
2. they maximise their personal utility, and
3. the preferences act independently (Wittek et al. 2013).
This theory predicts the outcome of choices made and choice patterns, rather
than the choice processes as people try to maximise their benefits and minimise
their costs. The theory is important in analysing the political and economic effects
of individual choices in societies across the globe.
Vote-buying has sadly become an integral part of politics in Africa’s elections.
Adopting the Rational Choice Theory in examining voters’ behaviours in Nigeria,
the theory assumes that voters’ choices are premised on a maximised cost-benefit
analysis with the objective of self-gratification. Citizens’ behaviours during voting
are influenced by several factors, including vote-buying. Most electorates assume
that the election period is the only time they can benefit from the national cake,
since most of the promises made by politicians are never met. According to
Jensen and Justesen (2012), poor voters are significantly more likely to be targets
of vote-buying than wealthier voters. Vote-buying rather than the competence of
the electoral candidate becomes a rationale for voters’ preferences in developing
regions like Africa.
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
191
The theory expects an optimal decision output derived from a rigorous
approach which emphasises logic and problem definition in making ideal choices.
But this can be time-consuming, which makes this an unsuitable method for
addressing short-term issues given the processes required for a careful decision.
Also, the theory assumes that decision-makers have accurate information and
skills on which to base their choices (Jensen & Justesen 2012); this, however, is
not usually the case. For instance, in the case of vote-buying in Africa, electorates
may be unaware of their rights and privileges in the state.
Realist Theory
Realist Theory is defined as an approach employed to study how politics is
practiced and how powerful actors in the game of politics engage in battle. In
other words, it claims to explain the reality of international politics by examining
on the constraints on politics that result from humankind’s egoistic nature and
the absence of a central authority above the state. Realism can be discussed based
on the traditional thoughts of classical and neorealists. Classical realists look at the
role of power and self-interest in determining state behaviours. Classical realists
such as George Kennan and Hans Morgenthau, among many others, believe that
human nature causes people to serve their own interests, rather than ideology, to
rule a state. Neorealists agree but discard human interest and replace it with the
anarchic structure of the state. They believe that the state is the main actor in
deciding how society operates (Hodgson 1995).
Realist Theory is associated with thinkers such as Niccolò di Bernardo dei
Machiavelli, Thomas Hobbes, Robert Art, Robert Gilpin and Barry Posen.
Thinkers associated with classical realism include Carl von Clausewitz and
Reinhold Niebuhr (Hodgson 1995).
A good example of the application of the Realist Theory is the study of the
relationship between the International Criminal Court (ICC) and the African
Union. African leaders and scholars have called for a complete African withdrawal
from the ICC because all the leaders that have been prosecuted at The Hague are
Africans. Leaders and allies of major Western powers accused of major human
rights violations have not been prosecuted by the ICC. This causes a loss of
credibility for ICC, and a lack of cooperation with it.
Some important issues in contemporary world politics have been analysed
through the lens of Realist Theory. They include the refugee crisis in Europe
and the Middle East, the rise of China as a major power, and human rights and
humanitarian law. These issues also provide insights into some of the theoretical
tenets of classical and structural realism. Overall, the issues show that realism
offers a multifaceted understanding of world politics and enlightens us about the
challenges of world politics. The theory also recognises the similarity between
international and domestic politics in different states (Hodgson 1995).
192
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Realist Theory is adjudged weak in that it does not agree on the nature of
factors that produce the global system in which we live. Even though it offers
an objective approach for investigating many phenomena occurring throughout
the world, its vision is limited by its own boundaries, since its major focus is on
power politics and materialism. Also, it is difficult to evaluate how power and
interest work in individual countries, where ideologies differ.
Social Contract Theory
Social Contract Theory is based on the premise that in the beginning, humans
lived in a state of nature, with no government or laws to regulate them, resulting
in chaos and hardship. Humans then agreed on two things: first, they sought
the protection of their lives and properties; and, second, they came together and
agreed to surrender their freedoms to the rule of a supreme authority (Elahi 2005).
The theory was pioneered by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) and then built
upon by John Locke (1632–1704) and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778).
Hobbes believed that in a world characterised by a state of anarchy, people will
act in their personal best interests. He described the natural state as that wherein
morality is non-existent and every individual lives in fear, especially of death. He
said humans attempted to ensure self-protection and self-preservation, and to
avoid misery and pain, by voluntarily surrendering all their rights and freedoms
to an authority. This authority could use force to get people to be it subject
to it – and is installed to enforce the renunciation of violence by the people
(Laskar 2013).
Locke said that in the natural state might be chaotic, but people live in
ultimate freedom. He opined that people decided to abandon some of their
freedoms to limit chaos and regulate life. People surrender their power to a
ruler or government, which functions to enforce the safety and possessions of its
subjects. In Locke’s natural state, the government can and should be overthrown
when it is no longer capable of fulfilling its task (Laskar 2013).
Rousseau’s view of the natural state is based on the idea of humans as noble
savages. He describes a state in which people are inclined to cooperate rather than
engage in conflict. He also argues that society has corrupted humans and that
politics brings violence. He therefore advocated for direct democracy, wherein
the will of the people and what is best for them should be pursued by the state
(Laskar 2013). Table 7.1 is a summary of the positions and limitations of the
postulates of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau on Social Contract Theory.
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
193
Table 7.1: Positions and Limitations of the Postulates of Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau
on Social Contract Theory
Pioneer
Position on the Theory
Limitation of the Postulates
Hobbes
Hobbes held a realist perspective of the
evil nature of humans.
Very pessimistic about the nature of
humans: egocentricity and aggression.
Humans need to be protected against
themselves by the state through force,
if needed. People do not have to be
represented by the government or ruler,
if the government fulfils its primary
task of protection. Hobbes posits a
ruler who has the absolute power over
his subjects since their alternative is the
‘brutish and short’ life of the state of
nature. The government or ruler is an
almighty entity.
Locke
Locke had a more positive view of
human nature. He maintained that
government power should be limited
to protecting natural rights, including
the life, liberty, and happiness of
each individual. He believed that the
individual rights of citizens should be
preserved from the tyranny of social
rulers. He was confident that the
state of nature is reasonable and that
a government or ruler should be a
representation of the people in order
to prevent suppression. He placed
emphasis on the protection of life,
liberty and property.
Portrays equality among humans and
an atmosphere of liberty in which
individuals can do what they perceive
to be in their individual interests.
While this may appear good, it can
lead to selfish living, which can incite
oppression and suppression. There is
bound to be havoc because one ‘person’s
meat may be another person’s poison’.
Rousseau
According to Rousseau, justice cannot
be defined as the right of the stronger.
If justice were so defined, the most
powerful individuals will always be
better served by justice. Rousseau’s
justice consists in individual acts of
harmony with civil authority. But
individuals are forced to act as if the
authority is legitimate. He suggested
that pity indeed exists in the state
of nature and has an advantage over
the laws of civil society. The political
process should not be dominated by the
state but should be actively participated
in by the population.
Emphasis placed on general will
presupposes that the decision of the
majority is superior to that of the
minority. Rousseau believed that one
individual is not subject to another but
rather to the general or majority will.
Source: Self-generated by the authors based on the works of Elahi (2005), Mouritz (2010),
Hickey (2011) and Laskar (2013)
194
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Social Contract Theory suggests a state of monarchy: i.e. one in which the
authority has absolute power and the subjects have no rights against the absolute
authority, and he or she is to be obeyed in all situations, no matter how bad the
authority may be. There is monopoly of power. Mouritz compares Hobbes Social
Contract Theory with that of Locke and concludes that Locke’s state of nature is
free of Hobbes’ ‘…force and fraud, with men, instead living together according
to reason, they live without a guiding authority to follow. Naturally, individuals
are inclined to avoid a solitary life and, inevitably, start a family; this situation
eventually leads to the formation of political society’ (Mouritz 2010:126).
Systems Analysis Theory
Systems Analysis Theory is an empirically oriented approach to political life. David
Easton (1957) sought to understand political life by viewing each of its aspects
piecemeal. For instance, if we examine the operation of political parties, interest
groups, government, and voting, we can analyse the nature of and consequences
of such political practices as manipulation, propaganda, and violence; we can also
reveal the structure within which these practices occur. Therefore, if we compute
the results, we can obtain an overview of what is contained in any human political
unit. It should be noted that the implicit notion exists that each part of the larger
political canvas cannot stand alone but is related to each other part. Better put, a
unit in a system is interrelated to other units in that system (Easton 1957).
The basic unit of analysis of Easton’s System Analysis Theory is ‘interaction’,
which is generated from the behaviours of the members of the system when they
play their roles. When these myriad interactions in the perception of a scholar
become a ‘set of interrelations’ they are considered as a ‘system’. Easton’s subject
matter is confined to political interactions (Easton 1957), which are evident in the
African context. For example, Hadland (2007) applied Systems Analysis Theory
to investigate state-media relations in post-apartheid South Africa, augmented
with an application of comparative media systems strategy. He focused on the
relationship between the state and the media, an interconnection of profound
significance in the South African context, as the aspect has not been explored
sufficiently by other scholars. Hadland found that South Africa’s media system
falls largely into the Polarised Pluralist Model, although it retains strong liberal
model traits.
Easton’s framework of Systems Analysis Theory is conceptual and analytical.
His ‘political system’ is born of concepts and is ‘constructivist’, using a set of
variables for description, explanation, and research. It is different from and not
a concrete or natural system. An actual, concrete or natural system, also called
membership-system, consists of human beings or actual individuals. Easton’s
analytic system is made of abstractions that focus on selected elements of human
behaviour (Easton 1957).
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
195
There are four major premises to Easton’s flow-model or input-output analysis:
1.
2.
3.
4.
System,
Environment,
Response, and
Feedback.
Easton calls them an ‘authoritative allocation of values’, ‘binding decisions and
actions’, or ‘exchange between the system and its environment’ (Easton 1957:1).
Output – an outcome or a production made by the political authorities – affects
the political environment and triggers feedback that leads to the generation of
new input that starts the political system all over again. This allows for a feedback
mechanism (Easton 1957).
Whatever happens in a subsystem is explained by the contradictions that
appear in the system. Liberation movements are seen, for example, as ‘arising out
of the structural contradictions of the capitalist world economy. Consequently,
the external forces – i.e. those external to the subsystem – are the determinant
forces of what happens within each subsystem’ (Easton 1957:3). Class structure
and class struggle within a country, for example, are determined by the position
which the country occupies within the global system. Some autonomy is granted
to the interior forces; but in an exterior/interior relationship, the former is
determinant over the latter (Easton 1957).
Race and Ethnicity
Darwinian Theory
Darwinian Theory, also referred to simply as Darwinism, is a biologically based
evolution theory credited to British naturalist Charles Darwin (1809–1882) and
others like British naturalist Alfred Russell Wallace (1823–1913) who came to
the same conclusion as Darwin did. However, Darwin was widely known and
honoured for the theory even before his well-cited book titled On the Origin of
Species was first published in 1859.
The theory states that the natural selection process is responsible for how all
organisms evolve and develop, and the selection, which happens through small,
inherited variations tends to aid an individual’s capability to compete, survive and
reproduce. The term Darwinism was coined by English biologist Thomas Henry
Huxley (April 1860), and later was called Modern Evolutionary Theory. Scholars
like Olivia Judson (2008) and Eugenie C. Scott and Glenn Branch (2009) have
criticised the use of the term Darwinism.
The theory has been much debated (Segerstrale 2000; Richerson & Boyd
2001), both negatively and positively. This may be due to its two main emphases.
First, the theory believes that the evolution of various animals is from one or few
common ancestors; and, second, that evolution occurs as a result of a natural
selection mechanism (for more on this, see Wilkins 1998).
196
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Evolution Theory is based on the idea of natural selection which has been
established in various scientific disciplines such as developmental biology,
geology, palaeontology and genetics. This focuses on behavioural and physical
changes in organisms over time resulting from heredity; these changes are integral
to how organisms survive their environment and are able to produce offspring
(Than & Taylor 2021). Cell differentiation, which causes metabolic constraints
and adaptation inside organisms, has been established as one of the ways in which
natural selection drives evolution (Kupiec 1997).
Ideas from Darwinian Theory were raised from the point of view of the
proponents’ disciplines up till the earlier part of the twentieth century, meaning the
theory had little applicability to the social sciences. The latter part of the twentieth
century saw some concerted efforts to adapt and apply Darwinian Theory to people’s
behaviours and to the study of cultural evolution (Richerson & Boyd 2001).
Darwinian Theory has been used to explain the interrelatedness and
interconnectedness of all life forms on Earth. The theory is applicable to how
ethnic groups evolved, as well as the comparative advantages one may have over
the other due to natural selection processes. The characteristics of ethnic groups
in Africa can be viewed as modifications occurring in a population through
natural selection. This may offer an explanation for the inequality that persists
among organisms, even of the same species. For instance, an organism behaves
altruistically when its behaviour benefits other organisms, at a cost to itself. It
may also be said that traits of some individuals or groups may be more suited to
their environments than others, and that this will affect their ability to procreate
and survive (Than & Taylor 2021).
Some weaknesses of this theory include Darwin’s unsubstantiated and
ambiguous explanations concerning evolutionary progress, and the inability to
make it a central focus of his theory (Richerson & Boyd 2001).
Genesis Theory
Adherents of the Abrahamic faiths (Judaism, Christianity, and Islam) believe that
God created all things, while science has other theories to account for how the
Earth was made. The Bible states that humans were created on the sixth day of
creation (Genesis 1:1–23), but the scientific response is that this is wrong (Wolper
2011). An understanding of Genesis Theory must take into account the fact that
there are different Christian creation theories which are prone to change. (Janse
van Rensburg 2012). There are many creation theories; so, only a small number
of the Christian creation theories are discussed here for the sake of brevity. They
are the Young Earth Creation Theory, the Progressive Creation Theory, the
Theistic Evolution Theory, and the Gap Theory. References are made to their
subjective contexts, theological or main views, and meta-theoretical frameworks
or theological principles (for more on these, see Janse van Rensburg 2012).
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
197
The Young Earth Creation Theory (YECT) centres on literal and historical
readings and interpretations of Genesis according to the propositions of
Archbishop James Ussher (1581–1656) in the mid-seventeenth century. More
recently, it posits that the Darwinian Theory of evolution contradicts Genesis
regarding the creation of Earth and humanity (Manthei, referenced in Janse van
Rensburg 2011). In addition, YECT maintains that bids to reconcile the creation
account in Genesis Theory with Darwinian Theory led to the unification of the
Gap Theory and Day-Age Theory. This development was made possible in the later
part of the eighteenth Century by the belief that the findings of modern science
would align with biblical text. Thus, when it became evident that the Earth was
millions of years old, Protestant thinkers quickly started to interpret Genesis 1
to align with the scientific explanation. From these core theological perspectives,
YECT sees God as the Creator of everything and says Christians especially should
be educated to read and interpret the creation account historically and literally
(see Janse van Rensburg 2012).
Progressive Creation Theory believes in the all-powerful and loving God as
behind the creation account in Genesis. This serves as an inerrant, progressive
dual-revelation as well as a historical-metaphorical view concerning the Genesis
creation account with ‘underlying meta-theoretical theological principles’ (Janse
van Rensburg 2012:17). Stated differently, there is a need for a higher order
(meta) theory of theories on existing theological postulates in order to develop a
strong ethical or normative foundation for theological explication.
Theistic Evolution Theory emerged from the liberalist creation movement. It
says the creation account is based on mythology. Kenton Sparks (2011, referenced
in Janse van Rensburg 2012) explains that proponents of this theory are thinking
along the lines of scientists and, in most cases, believe that God started creation
(for details, see Janse van Rensburg 2012).
Gap Theory, also known as the Ruin-Reconstruction Interpretation, is often
credited to Thomas Chalmers’ work from the early nineteenth century (Janse van
Rensburg 2012). This theory suggests that there was a gap of billions of years
between Genesis 1:1 (original creation) and Genesis 1:2 (reconstructed creation),
and in line with the scientific beliefs of modern mainstream, the theory promotes
an Old Earth historical framework (Janse van Rensburg 2012). This framework
is an amalgamation of
1. ‘day-age creationism’, which refers to the creation accounts in Genesis;
2. ‘gap creationism’, which denotes the six-yom creation era described in Genesis; and
3. ‘theistic creation’, which describes tenets about God being compatible with
modern scientific findings on biological evolution.
Genesis Theory in general is useful to account for human evolution from an
Abrahamic point of view. The theory puts Adam and Eve at the centre of humanity
which spread across the planet due to (re)procreations over the centuries. This is
198
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
in sharp contrast with the biological human evolution explanations offered by
Darwinian Theory and others.
This theory is applicable to the study of the existence of humankind in terms
of creation and (re)procreation by descendants. African descendants nowadays
occupy a unique position in the world’s population stage, as there is not a country
in the world in which one will not find an African or a descendant of Africa. This
suggests that Africans cannot be overlooked in terms of heritage, culture, values
and norms. The theory serves as a basis to challenge the elevation of one race,
culture, or personality above others because it offers Abrahamic, supernatural, or
divine explanations that all humans originated from the same source.
Theories associated with the Genesis Theory (i.e. Young Earth Creation,
Reasons Progressive Creation, Theistic Evolution, and Gap Theory) have no
critical or systematic account for how humans developed into different ethnic
groupings, with diverse cultures, languages, norms and values (see Janse van
Rensburg 2012).
Religion
Culture Theory
A number of works on culture exist but they offer conflicting definitions of
the concept. According to Alfred Kroeber and Clyde Kluckhohn in Culture: A
Critical Review of Concepts and Definitions (1952, cited in Jensen 2016), no fewer
than 146 definitions of culture exist, and this may be said of religion as well. The
complexity of the subject has made contextualising of and theorising about culture
and religion, and acceptance of their assumptions, difficult. Culture or Cultural
Theory is traceable to the launching of the Centre for Contemporary Cultural
Studies at the University of Birmingham in 1964 by Stuart Hall and Richard
Hoggart, as well as efforts by Raymond Williams. Sociological pioneers such as
Max Weber, Karl Marx, Émile Durkheim and Georg Simmel have demonstrated
the interrelationships between social, sociological and cultural theories, and their
paradigms have moved from structuralism to poststructuralism and then to
postmodernism (Oswell 2010).
Culture Theory, like many social science theories, points to religion as a
promoter of in-group solidarity and social cohesion (Durkheim 1995 cited in
Wilson 2002; Sosis & Alcorta 2003). In relation to religion, Culture Theory
emphasises how symbols, communities, and religious institutions interconnect
with and embody other aspects of society. In other words, most theories of
culture focus on meaning construction and cultural boundaries, and how they
are interpreted by communities, and how social interactions and mediated
communications are arrived at using the institutions and symbols of religion
(Hall, Neitz & Battani 2003). Importantly, Culture Theory as advocated by
Durkheim (see next section) holds that culture and religion may be in conflict
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
199
but not all the time, and that depends on religious types (e.g., axial – i.e. the
period of ancient history from the eighth to the third centuries BCE, or pre-axial
i.e. the period before that) being practiced (Jensen 2016). In addition, religion is
not detachable from culture (Geertz 1973; Boyer 2001; Ramadan 2010; Beyers
2017). Religion may be based on tradition rather than conviction (Jensen 2016).
The crux of Culture Theory from the perspective of Durkheim is that culture
functions like religion within society by providing certain guidelines on the
location of identity (Beyers 2017).
Africa is a centre of culture and religion, and the interconnectedness and
social functions of both have been described by Cultural Theory, but many
contemporary Africans have allowed religion to negatively affect their cultural
identity and the functionality of their culture. This may be a social problem as the
people’s potential may not be realised. This is in opposition to Durkheim’s view
that culture tends to help people function through collective representation as well
as systems of class. From another point of view, many contemporary Africans are
dropping their pre-colonial cultural practices and moving to Western religions.
Cultural Theory from Durkheim’s sociological and functional viewpoint suggests
that people’s social lives (what is wrong and what is right) are then regulated
by classificatory systems derived from Western religions. These systems help to
explain concepts such as collective space and time, kinship and family, what
is sanctified or not, and so on. Cultural Theory stimulates the understanding
that symbols and rituals are collective representations with certain values and
meanings purposed for a social group; an example being the totem pole, according
to Durkheim (Durkheim 1912/1995).
Culture theory as advocated by Durkheim looks exclusively at certain
cultures and religions without looking at the varieties of rituals and symbols
whose meanings and applications to certain societies may differ. This may lead
to labelling some cultures, religions and social actions as primitive, or nonconforming, or ‘outsider, uncultured and irreligious’ (MacKay 2000:98).
Durkheimian Theory
The pioneer of Durkheimian Theory is of course the person after whom it is
named, Émile Durkheim (1858–1917), who was born in France and was a
popular secular sociologist whose theories focused on social issues. Durkheim’s
The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life was published in 1912, based on a
study of totemic societies in Australia. During the nineteenth century, researchers
and theorists like Durkheim, Max Weber (1864–1920) and Karl Marx (1818–
1883) focused on what makes society function. Durkheimian Theory on religion
focused on the nature and effects of religion on people and how religion permeates
people’s daily lives (Simpson & Conklin 1989). According to Durkheim, social
cohesion is attained through religion; it is a part of what unifies society.
200
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The Durkheimian Theory of religion postulates that religion is society’s
product; no divine or supernatural influence creates it. The theory suggests a
functional definition of religion in terms of what constitutes sacred and profane
objects, symbols, ceremonies, and rituals, and how those who adhere to a
religion, especially in a church setting, view them. Sacred objects and symbols
are considered divine and are viewed and used with respect and awe, separating
them from other things that are considered profane. The theory identifies and
examines various common elements which religion emphasises and analyses the
effects of religious beliefs on the lives of people in a society. The theory holds that
religion is a source of an individual’s solidarity and identity in a society and helps
the individual to affirm his/her common values and beliefs. The theory proposes
that the influence of religion will weaken as modernity and technology increase
in a society, which will lead to religious thinking giving way to scientific thinking,
with a reduction in religious rituals and ceremonies.
In Africa, religion is a notable part of people’s lives and a strong element
of African culture and society. But religion (from traditional to Protestant) can
be used to oppress and deceive people, particularly those with socioeconomic
problems. In Africa, religion is largely seen as divine rather than sociological
as the Durkheimian Theory believes. Religion in Africa is claimed to be sacred
in doctrine but there is blasphemous language from both religious leaders and
their followers. This suggests that African religious systems do not regard sacred
objects, beliefs and practices, or individuals in the way as Western religions do.
The negative aspects of religion can harm individuals, communities and African
society at large.
Evan Pritchard and many other philosophers have raised several substantial
issues concerning the theory (Priya 2018). To start with, among the shortcomings
of Durkheimian Theory on religion is the non-exactness of what is sacred; profane
and sacredness are not always antithetical to each other. The theory emphasises
societal religion and not individuals. Another shortcoming of the theory is that
its assumptions have failed to manifest in society. An example is the assumption
that the concept of ‘God’ is about to die, and that society will begin to promote
civil religion instead. This is far from what is happening in Africa where religion
continues to grow. All of this notwithstanding, Durkheimian Theory still has
a profound and positive influence on the general understanding of the social
function of religion and its connection to both extraordinary and ordinary aspects
of people’s lives.
Social Change Theory
Strasser and Randall (1981) state that change can be defined a modification
in the state of any phenomenon observed over a period of time. They add that
social change involves an alteration in the structure and functioning of social
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
201
forms or processes – a modification in the established patterns of inter-human
relationships and standards of conduct. The authors point out that since the
inception of sociology as a discipline, sociologists, have drawn from several
other disciplines and philosophical perspectives to examine historical data
pertaining to social change (Strasser & Randall 1981). There are three basic
theories of social change:
1. Evolutionary Theory,
2. Functionalist Theory, and
3. Conflict Theory.
Social evolutionists in the nineteenth century drew from Darwin’s theory of
biological evolution to theorise that society progresses over time to a higher level
(Strasser & Randall 1981). A precursor to Darwin, Auguste Comte (1798–1857),
described as the father of sociology, and Herbert Spencer (1820–1903) posited
unilineal evolutionary theories which said that all societies move through the
same order in the stages of evolution to attain a common end.
Functionalist theorists place emphasis not on what changes a society but on
what maintains it. Talcott Parsons (1902–1979), in his Equilibrium Theory,
posits that a society will tend towards homeostasis. Furthermore, rifts in a social
order constitute social change in one aspect of a society and require adjustments
in other aspects of another society to create stability (Strasser & Randall 1981).
Conflict theorists advocate change because it is important for addressing
injustices and inequalities in a society (Strasser & Randall 1981). Although
Karl Marx adopted the evolutionary notion of societies progressing along a
specific direction, he disputed the notion that every successive stage presents an
improvement over the prior. He argued that history proceeds in stages in which
the powerful and wealthy in a society maintain the status quo of institutions
(such as religion) and social practices that continue to favour the exploitation
of the poorer class. He also maintained that religion as a powerful institution in
the society hinders social change and serves to maintain existing class structures
by espousing beliefs and ideologies that make poverty and suffering a virtue,
while subverting a society’s need for revolution under the pretext of rewards
being available in other supernatural spaces of existence such as ‘heaven’. Marx’s
notion of social change in Das Kapital is that ‘it will drive a society to its last
stage of development: i.e. a classless, free and communist society’ (Strasser &
Randall 1981:5).
These theories aid in our understanding of the significant role religion plays in
most African countries (Agbiji & Swart 2015) as religion pervades institutions and
government apparatuses. For example, religion has been the primary influencing
factor in the Nigerian government’s reluctance to legitimise same-sex marriage,
pushing against the current legal trend.
202
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Religion is also instrumental in initiating and sustaining social change. For
instance, Reverend Martin Luther King Jr. (who was greatly inspired by Gandhi’s
religious practice of non-violence) and the broader Baptist Church in the southern
United States initiated social change through their role and activities in the Civil
Rights Movement of the 1960s (McKinnon 2005). The ‘Arab Spring’ that began
in Tunisia in 2010–2011 and swept across the Middle East, which saw Islamic
groups using the Internet and social media to highlight the political injustices
in their countries, is a contemporary instance of religion’s role in precipitating
social change. Here, the functionalist fails to consider the fact that an impression
of stability in a society can be established by a powerful group using force.
Although conflict theorists might applaud the use of protest and riots in revolting
against the ‘oppressive regime’ of Zine El Abidine Ben Ali and that of Muammar
Gaddafi, the theory fails to account for social upheavals which lead to negative
and unexpected social transformation as in the case of Libya where the country
has seen a record level of unemployment and social unrest since Gaddafi’s death.
Social Ecology Theory
Social Ecology Theory is an approach used to study the interconnection of the
natural world and social institutions. The term ‘social ecology’, sometimes referred
to ‘urban ecology’, was first developed at the University of Chicago in the 1920s.
According to the Better Worlds blog (2018), Social Ecology Theory is concerned
with social roots and implications of ‘ecological dislocation’.
A popular contemporary proponent on social ecology theory is Murray
Bookchin. He was an American historian and political scientist who situated
Social Ecology Theory within anarchist, libertarian socialist and ecological
thought. It is essentially a multidisciplinary field which begins with scientific
notions of ecological issues, and follows that by seeking solutions to the issues
through the comprehension of their origins in society.
Social Ecology Theory attempts to demonstrate that ecological issues on the
global, regional and local levels are a product of hierarchical, exploitative and
authoritarian social institutions (Clark 1997). The theory is at the forefront
of contemporary ecology theories which demand a radical change in existing
spiritual values. According to this theory, religion establishes an authoritarian
and hierarchical social class structure with deep social issues (Clark 1997). These
social issues such as industrial expansion, trade for profit and economic, ethnic,
gender and cultural conflicts lie at the heart of serious ecological dislocations
(Better Worlds Blog 2012). This is because these issues raise serious conflicts
between personal desires and community needs.
In Bookchin’s earlier works, he posited that many religious and spiritual
traditions are compatible with ecological objectives. He commended the nondualistic worldview some traditional societies – including many in African and
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
203
Native American cultures – employed to unify nature, morality, and custom.
Some social ecologists are critical of the Christian religion. This is captured in the
claim by Biehl (1991) that Christianity is the most anthropogenic religion in the
world. Social Ecology Theory advocates for the replacement of the domination
mentality found in Christianity with one which regards human life as a mere
intelligent primate; as such, the role of the human in the natural world should be
appreciative and supportive of non-human life (Clark 1997).
Some religions have strong respect for the natural world – Hinduism is an
example. In the eastern part of Nigeria, some traditional religions and practices
have reverence for the interrelationship between human and human life. There is
a belief that nature is part of the divine and the natural environment is constantly
communicating with humans. There is always the need to safeguard and revere
nature as it is the mouthpiece of the gods.
Social Structure Theory
The contemporary usage of the Social Structure Theory to study religion, especially
in the field of sociology, can be traced to Emile Durkheim and Herbert Spencer.
Durkheim posited that society is segmented and the different segments are
interdependent, giving a structure to the behaviours and interactions of members
and institutions within that society. Put simply, Durkheim claimed that human
behaviour is externally influenced. In the study of social structures, sociologists
analyse social categories in order to explicate matters such as inequality and
integration in society (Nadel 2009).
Social structure can be categorised in terms of micro, meso and macro levels.
On the micro level, social structure denotes the way norms mould an individual’s
behaviour within a social system. The meso level is the system of social network
links between individuals and organisations in society. The macro level looks at
the ordering of social institutions according to a socioeconomic classification:
i.e. class structure or other organised relationship among large social groups in
society (Nadel 2009).
One of the theoretical approaches used to analyse the concept of social
structure is structural functionalism. British social anthropologist A.R. RadcliffeBrown is the foremost proponent of this approach. He views society as an organic
integrated entity which is dependent on the various components of its social
structure (the existence of one component is dependent on the existence of
another component). He defines social structure as a pattern, or as ‘normal’ social
relations (Wilterdink & Form 2019). Talcott Parsons regards social structure as
normative. He argues that social behaviour conforms to rules, values, and norms
that control individual behaviour in certain situations. The norms delineate
various roles that differ according to the positions of individuals (Nadel 2009).
Radcliffe-Brown’s and Parsons’ approaches and definitions have been criticised
204
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
for lacking empirical and methodological confirmation; being too abstract; and
not accounting for change and conflict and the complexities of power, wealth and
social rewards (Nadel 2009).
Robert K. Merton contends that social structure contains normative patterns,
and that these patterns contain status, material and power inequalities, providing
members of a society with varying choices and opportunities. The inequalities that
exist in complex societies can be seen in stratification systems or class structures
(Wilterdink & Form 2019).
The preceding perspectives on social structure provide a valuable lens for
understanding the structures of religious groups as well as the role of religion
as a social institution in establishing social structures in an African society. The
structural-functionalist Radcliffe-Brown says the existence of one component of
a society is dependent on the existence of another component. Functionalists
argue that religion and society are interdependent for their values, significance,
and existence. This justifies the claims of scholars such as Deng (1998) and
Schuurman (2011) that religion makes up the key fabric of African societies.
It is intertwined with general existence as well as with the socio-political and
economic development of African societies. Social Structure Theory explains
the existence of structure in the Catholic Church, for instance, where there are
different organs – the Pope, Cardinals, Bishops, Reverend Fathers, Reverend
Sisters, altar boys and parishioners – that play different roles in the church and
society at large. Additionally, the roles of women and men in the church are
structured and different. Christian ideology places women below men; thus, the
societal role of a woman, in comparison to a man, in many societies in Africa is
regarded as inferior.
Sexuality/Gender
Africancentric and Third World Theory
Africancentric and Third World Theory, as expounded by Mwalimu Molefi Kete
Asante and Mambo Ama Mazama (both members of the Temple Circle—a
group of scholars with a connection to the Department of Africology at Temple
University in Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, United States of America) in the late
l970s, is a general approach used to study all cultural, economic, political and
social questions related to African people. It is a brand of Social Change Theory
which proposed the first full argument of the concept of Africancentricity/
Afrocentricity and, thus, has been employed to investigate sexuality/gender issues.
The pioneering theorists and scholars in the Temple Circle of Africancentrists
are Mwalimu Molefi Kete Asante, Tsehloane Keto, Kariamu Welsh Asante, Abu
Abarry, Mambo Ama Mazama, Theophile Obenga, and Terry Kershaw (Verharen
2000). The Africancentric paradigm is a revolutionary move in thinking proposed
as a constructive change to Black disorientation, decentredness, and inaction. The
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
205
Africancentrist asks the following question: ‘What would African people do if
there were no White people?’ (Chawane 2016). In other words, what ordinary
reactions would occur in the interactions and attitudes toward the environment,
affinity patterns, inclinations for colours, types of religion, and historic referent
points for African people if there had not been any interference by slavery,
colonialism or dependency? Africancentricity answers this question by stressing
the central role of the African subject within the context of African history,
thereby eliminating Europe from the centre of African representativeness. In this
way, it becomes a ground-breaking idea that studies notions, concepts, events,
dispositions, and political and economic progressions from the stance of Black
people as subjects and not as objects. The approach suggests that Black people
(at home and abroad) must look at information from an African viewpoint. It
also calls for looking at matters at hand from an African perspective; that we
misconstrue Africa when we use perspectives and terms other than that of the
African to study Africa (Chawane 2016).
Africancentricity does not call for the replacement but rather for the alteration
of existing Eurocentric views that seek to eliminate or tone down the influence of
Africans in the advancement of the world (Chawane 2016). There is a need for
a modification of the educational curriculum in most of our institutions. Apart
from not giving recognition to African authors, most curriculum content also
does not speak to the problems of the African countries and, thus, the knowledge
gained cannot be applied to meeting or solving the problems of African societies.
How best to learn about one’s society and solve societal problems if not when the
knowledge being acquired is rooted in the ideologies and philosophies of African
society? Africancentricity theorists are not saying that Europeanism is not good;
what they are saying is that there is an urgent need for what speaks Africa, denotes
Africa, and pictures Africa. This is the core strength of the theory.
When employed to investigate sexuality/gender issues, Africancentric and Third
World Theory emphasise that the influence of Africans in all areas of development
should be reflected in world history. It focuses on achieving the precise end of
ensuring that African tradition and culture, and its history and impact on world
civilisation and scholarship, are echoed in the curricula on every level of academic
instruction when dealing with sexuality/gender and other issues. Africancentricity
allows other cultures to interpret the history of such issues from their own outlook.
Africancentric and Third World Theory is labelled as an antithesis, a selfprotective countermove to Eurocentricity. Critics argue that many of the
discipline’s findings are arrived at in unscholarly fashion, stating that the
educational qualifications of many Africancentrists are in fields other than African
Studies. The theory has also been criticised for the lack of a collective language
spoken by Africans and for class variances which hamper Africans reaching
agreement about their collective methodology of knowledge production. But, of
course, these same criticisms can apply to just about any intellectual discipline.
206
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Biological Theory
Biological Theory, from the perspective of sexuality/gender, addresses issues
surrounding sex – the quality of being male or female – in terms of the possession
of distinctively different sexual and reproductive organs and of living the
experience of that gender. In recent times, conversations surrounding this topic
have taken on a complex turn given that new knowledges and experiences have
shown that individuals manifest traits that are conventionally not associated with
their gender. Influenced by the works of Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961)
and the feminist Simone de Beauvoir (1908–1986), Judith Butler, a genderfeminist theorist, draws a ‘distinction between sex as biological facility and gender
as the cultural signification of that facility’ (Butler 1988:25). In other words,
gender, to Butler, is largely performative – a process by which a woman or man
acts in conformity with social rules rather than in accordance with her/his daily
lived-experience. Butler’s ideas, like De Beauvoir’s, are woman-centred; however,
they can be applied to men too (Butler 1988:25).
The existential thoughts of Merleau-Ponty are significant in understanding these
seemingly contradictory situations or experiences. His notion of phenomenology
points to the human body as the frame through which one perceives the world
(rather than the existing orthodox notion of ‘consciousness’ in which gender is
socially interpreted and constructed). Merleau-Ponty’s episteme is more genderinclusive and sees the human body (the anatomical features) and the emotional
activities going on within it as inseparable concepts. According to Butler, Simone
de Beauvoir in her book The Second Sex contends that the female physiognomy
must be reviewed in terms of how female sexualised bodies are barred from
ontology (1988:46), validating the radical views of Shulamith Firestone on the
often cultural signification of sex (Firestone 1970:11).
In traditional knowledge, the construction of an ‘expected gender behaviour’
(performativity) for every gender provides a means for nonconformists to express
social defiance. New knowledge and social awareness in this regard help to put in
perspective the various misconceptions surrounding gender, sexuality and human
biology. Despite the lively debates on the politics of gender and sexuality, an
obvious gap lies in the blurred line between socially influenced gender identity
and hormonally based gender identity. This disparity often leads to an upsetting
generalisation that all gender variants are hormonally inclined.
Popular perceptions toward gender variants across human histories have
sparked both intellectual and popular debates often to the disadvantage of variant
subjects. Accordingly, one may engage Biological Theory to question the strict
gender binaries constructed in religious climes, where no consideration is given
to rationality.
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
207
Conservative/Stand-up Theory
The sources of the Conservative or Stand-up Feminist Theory (the latter term used
mostly in Europe and a little in North America) are classical political thought;
however, the terms were not used in a political context until the start of nineteenth
century. Conservative Theory emerged from the political thought of Edmund
Burke (1729–1797). In his 1790 work, Reflection on the Revolution in France,
Burke, drawing from the teachings of Aristotle, regards society as an illusion, an
organic whole characterised by an unclear multitude of interrelationships. He
believes that every society is unique, having evolved over time in totally different
circumstances, giving rise to distinctive traditions, beliefs, and relationships
(Burke & Pocock 1987). Conservative Theory embraces the notion that reforms
should be established in the matrix of a society’s social history, with due regard
for its tradition, rules and prejudices, whether they be philosophic or otherwise
(Burke & Pocock 1987).
Conservative Theory calls for upholding and preserving of traditions, norms,
and culture. The idea affirms the importance of protecting existing traditions
(Huntington 1957; Claassen 2011). Huntington (1957) declares that the
foremost aim of Conservative Theory is to preserve existing traditions. Nichols
defines tradition as ‘established practices of concepts or thought and action that
do not seem to be merely habits; as a result, they are consciously valued and
endorsed’ (Nichols 1997:1). Conservative Theory then for Nichols is the body
of concepts that maintains the worth of existing tradition by highlighting the
protective mode of cultural practices (Nichols 1997). Political orientation is
connected to authority which enforces traditions through dogma. Conservative
Theory is seen as a political morality. It is political in the sense that it aspires to
political structures that build a decent society and supports morality as it claims
that a society should permit inhabitants to live lives that are personally satisfying
and useful for others (Nichols 1997).
In the African context, Conservative Theory can be employed to examine the
preservation of existing traditions, governance, or chieftaincies. Governance by
chieftancy in African societies is still valid. The attainment of political leadership
in the continent remains mostly characterised by a ruthless struggle for power
that frequently involves armed conflict.
Conservative Theory is difficult to classify. For some scholars, it is simply
a practical response to radical feminism, which proponents of Conservative
Theory perceive to be undesirable, whereas for several others (principally the
new generation of scholars) the theory is adopted on philosophic grounds. The
latter see Conservative Theory as a fully fledged counter-thought to Liberal
Theory (see later section in this chapter). Nonetheless, does Conservative Theory
really signify something special, or is it simply an orthodox worldview? To the
208
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
extent that Conservative Theory could be a coherent approach for explaining
the actuality of women’s roles in society, is the value which supports its main
tenets merely wrong? The answers to these questions, of course, will depend on a
responder’s ideology.
Political orientations like Liberal Theory have totally different perspectives,
partially as a result of conservatives typically challenging one another regarding
the actual political arrangements that get to be preserved. While conservative
feminists argue for the maintenance of traditional gender roles, with the
recommendation that they be respected and celebrated, liberal feminists argue
that those roles be amended to allow women to gain access to what are regarded
as traditional male roles. Radical feminists, as we will see later, call for a complete
dismantling of the traditional gender roles and the establishment of new ones
that would facilitate total equality among the genders.
There is no clear representation of the application of the Conservative Theory;
it is unlikely to succeed in Africa owing to the dynamic and immediate nature
of African problems that need practical solutions. The theory is incapable of
providing any guidance for addressing long term problems. In its roughest version,
it does not check up on the past to spot those social arrangements that are helpful
to advocate for its protection. Conservative Theory overlooks the fact that the
very set of traditions, values, and customs whose revival it demands is itself the
result of explicit innovations within the past – innovations that, to an identical
conservative, could be seen as an attack on an older tradition. A contradiction
like this at the heart of a political orientation could paralyse it. The solution is not
simple; conservatives seem to be defensive of an arbitrary freezing of time. Some
conservative theorists are well conversant of the contradiction and have offered
arguments to keep their theories alive. An organic process twist argues that the
theory must aim at protecting solely those traditions that have been capable of
evolving and adapting, since their survival purportedly evidences that they serve
a valuable function in society (Nichols 1997).
Conservative Theory is limited in terms of content, since it lacks criteria
to assess what is feasible and what is not. This obstacle cannot be overcome,
although we have a tendency to settle for the claim of Oakeshott (1962) that
Conservative Theory, even though it is not a scientific, political, or philosophical
system, remains necessary to bringing about change. Conservative Theory has
long been faced with an unresolvable enigma in terms of what makes a longlasting tradition productive or valuable. What Conservative Theory is missing,
then, is a superimposed principle that justifies its adherence to cautious
perspectives. Lastly, and most significantly, Conservative Theory will ultimately
carry intolerable consequences. Its rejection of forceful, hasty, and uncontrolled
modification is really an ambiguous weapon, for only too typically it incorporates
the adherence to otherwise unacceptable traditions (Oakeshott 1962).
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
209
(De)/(Re)/(Post)Constructivist Theories
The main argument of scholars who propound Constructivist Gender Theory,
which birthed Deconstructivist, Reconstructivist and Post-constructivist Gender
Theories, is that there is no ineradicable verity to gender; it is constructed by
social expectations and gender performance. Deconstruction Theory, developed
by French philosopher Jacques Derrida (1930–2004), is a post-structuralist
approach. The word ‘deconstruction’ is derived from the French verb deconstuire,
meaning ‘to undo the development of, to take to fragments’. Derrida, who
was born at El-Biar close to French Algiers, came to be renowned through his
publication of three works on the subject in 1967:
1. Voice and Phenomenon (2010);
2. Speech and Phenomena: And Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of Signs and
Grammatology (1973); and
3. Writing and Difference (2021).
Derrida considers the text to be the theme and item of enquiry. A deconstructionist
has the strong opinion there is no sole meaning to be derived from the content
of a script. According to Derrida who took his motivation from Ferdinand
de Saussure (1959), language as an arrangement of signs and words only has
implications because of the dissimilarities between these signs (Brooks 1995).
Gnanasekaran (2015) describes the deconstructionist as a reader of the text,
a decipherer, an investigator, and a critic. He or she can take several of these
positions concurrently. The deconstructive reader is an observer who is essentially
separated from the content; however, resolutely incorporated inside of a text, he
identifies certain fissures or blanks or blind spots and ends them off by taking the
different, unforgettable and social ideals that are relevant to the content before
decrypting the text (Gnanasekaran 2015). He bonds the semantics of the text,
the past, the notion of structure, and the occurrences of style. As a decipherer,
he holds the deconstructive methodology of conveying the content instead of
echoing what the author said in the book. He categorizes inferences in sequential
order based on the delineation of the text. The investigator searches for reasons
for discord in the written content at the oral and semantic levels. He finds both
factual and theoretical methods that the author incorporated to express his/her
opinions and adds to the scheme by using unaccustomed tools or devices. The
critic understands that the consequence of the text is enormous. He finds the
irregularities in the application of the words or the arrangements of sentences
(Gnanasekaran 2015). It is not just the outward constituents of the words that
the person who reads acts upon so as to highlight their worth in the content, but
s/he also concentrates on the clashes and struggles, insufficiencies, exclusions,
and semantic features while breaking down the idea of the writing by the author
(Mantzavinos 2016).
210
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Applying Deconstructivist Theory to an African situation might be challenging.
This is because African culture (its varieties notwithstanding) itself gives different
meanings and interpretations to words depending on the situation. For example,
in Africa, the word ‘revolution’ has been in the minds and on the tongues of
many people. The original context meant people disagreeing to continue in an
uncomfortable or straining situation – i.e. the ‘sign’. The mental picture depends
on the background and belief of the people concerned (the ‘signified’). To some,
it meant peaceful protest, to others it means riot, blood-shedding or destruction
of property.
Derrida’s challenges flow from a contention that texts outlast their writers and
become a portion of a set of cultural habits identical to, if not greater than, the
significance of authorial intent (Brooks 1995). Deconstruction is a style that may
be used in a viewpoint, in literary enquiry, and even in the analysis of scientific
writings (Hobson 2012). Its approach is also employed by postmodernists to
discover sense in a text rather than determine meaning, the latter being difficult
because a text can generate many understandings.
Nonetheless, there have been problems defining deconstruction since
it actively criticises the very language needed to explain it. It cannot thus be
explained or described as a method, an analysis, or a critique.
Liberal Theory
Liberal Gender Theory, as briefly mentioned earlier, focuses on women being
subordinated via traditional gender roles. Theorists promoting this school of
thought argue that in order to change the status quo, women should enter
the so-called ‘public world’ and strive for gender equality through legal and
political reforms.
Liberal Theory was first conceived by people such as Immanuel Kant, Adam
Smith, John Stuart Mill, John Hobson, Woodrow Wilson, and John Maynard
Keynes writing well before the deep causes (independent variables) they stress
(e.g., democratisation, industrialisation, nationalism, and welfare provision) were
widespread (Scott 2009). Liberal Theory is one of the constitutive elements of
modern society. The theory promotes the ideals of freedom, equality, and strict
separation between the public and private realms in matters concerning sexuality/
gender.
Liberal Theory is founded on a belief in the natural goodness of humans and
the autonomy of the individual. It favours civil and political liberties, government
by law with the consent of the governed, and protection from arbitrary authority
(Gray 1995). Liberal theorists are committed to individualism, liberty, and
equal rights on sexuality/gender and other matters. They also believe that these
aspects require a free economy with minimal government interference (Manent
& Seigel 1996).
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
211
In its application to power relations, Liberal Theory is founded on two basic
assumptions:
1. disorder and
2. rationality.
Specifically, states (or alternative political actors) usually act in a generally
rational manner in establishing choices. The disorder assumption would imply
that political actors within a distinctive setting like Africa would fail to navigate
power shifts under anarchy (Amin 2004). They need to interact in assisting one
another. The rationality assumption implies that state leaders and their domestic
supporters interact in policymaking for the instrumental purpose of securing
advantages provided by actors outside of their borders. And, in developing such
calculations, states deploy cost-efficient mechanisms in order to realise their goals.
Liberal Theory shares the primary (anarchy) assumption with most negotiation
theories, and it shares the second (rationality) assumption with realism and
institutionalism but shares no assumption with non-rationalist method theories
(Hobhouse 1911).
Liberal theories link state behaviour to varied conceptions of desirable
forms of cultural, political and socioeconomic orders. These theories stress
economic interdependence, including many variants of Endogenous Policy
Theory. Liberal Theory stresses the role of domestic representative institutions,
elites and leadership dynamics, and executive-legislative relations (Bell 2014).
Liberal Theory also houses a family of theories that share common assumptions
about international relations. Such theories explain not only cooperation among
liberal states, but also liberal and non-liberal policies, conflictual and cooperative
situations, security and political economy issues, as well as both individual foreign
policy and aggregate behaviours (Freeden 1978).
Liberal theorists believe in democratic systems and international cooperation
along with a ‘harmony of interests assuming that international politics is not
a zero-sum game, with automatic winners and losers. Democratic states could
always find peaceful solutions to apparent clashes of interest. The first assumption
shared by Liberal Theory is that African states represent some set of domestic
societies, whose views represent state preferences’ (Hobhouse 1994).
For liberals, the state may be representative establishments perpetually subject
to capture and recapture, construction and reconstruction, by domestic social
coalitions. This is a good description of African states. These social coalitions
embody state preferences at any point in time: the tastes, ends, basic interests,
or fundamental social purposes that underlie policy. Political establishments
represent a vital transmission belt by which the interests of African people and
teams in civil society get involved in the political realm (Freeden 1978). All
people and teams do not wield equal influence over state policy. On the contrary,
212
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
their powers vary widely, depending on the context. Variations in the nature
of representative establishments and practices help form a team’s influence on
the national interest. Some African states might represent, ideal-typically, the
preferences of one tyrannical individual; others afford opportunities for broad
democratic participation. The precise preferences of social teams, weighted by
their domestic powers, form the underlying goals (state preferences) that states
pursue. Sometimes, non-governmental organisations (NGOs) and alternative
actors might have international alliances to help social forces. State-society
relations – the relationship between a state and its domestic (and transnational)
society in which it is embedded – are at the heart of the Liberal Theory.
Postmodernist Theory
The focus of Postmodernist Theory is on the ideas that gave rise to and accelerated
gender inequality in society. Its proponents investigate these ideas and seek to
promote gender equality by evaluating logocentrism (i.e. the use of words and
language as a fundamental expression of an external reality, especially applied
as a negative term to traditional Western thought) in an analytical and detailed
manner, buttressing competing discourses, deconstructing texts, and advancing
subjectivity. Postmodernist Theory is a late twentieth century movement that
generally questions the basic assumptions of Western philosophy in the modern
period. Postmodernism literally means ‘after the modernist movement’ (Jencks
1986). While ‘modern’ itself refers to something related to the present, the
movement of modernism and the subsequent Postmodernist Theory are defined
by a set of perspectives. In Critical Theory, Postmodernist Theory refers to a
point of departure for works of literature, drama, architecture, and design, as
well as the interpretation of history, law and culture in the late twentieth century
(Grenz 1996). Postmodernist Theory is therefore an aesthetic, literary, political or
social philosophy which attempts to describe a condition, or a state of being, or
something concerned with changes to institutions and conditions, as postmodern
(Graff 1973).
In other words, as Eagleton puts it, Postmodernist Theory is the ‘cultural and
intellectual phenomenon, especially since the 1920s’ new movements in the arts,
while postmodernity focuses on social and political outworkings and innovations
globally’ (Eagleton 1986:1). Also, quoting the Merriam-Webster Dictionary,
Docker says ‘postmodern’:
…is either of, relating to, or being an era after a modern one or of, relating to,
or being any of various movements in reaction to modernism that are typically
characterised by a return to traditional materials and forms or by ironic selfreference and absurdity (as in literature), or finally of, relating to, or being a theory
that involves a radical reappraisal of modern assumptions about culture, identity,
history, or language (Docker 1994:1).
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
213
Postmodernist Theory originated as a reaction to modernism and was largely
influenced by the Western European ‘disillusionment’ induced by World War II.
Despite the fact that postmodernism tends to refer to a cultural, intellectual, or
artistic state, it lacks a clear central hierarchy or organising principle and embodies
extreme complexity, contradiction, ambiguity, diversity, interconnectedness or
inter-referentiality in a way that is often indistinguishable from a parody of itself
(Docherty 1993). This has given rise to charges of fraudulence. Postmodernist
Theory is characterised as a derivative, referring to non-art aspects of history that
are influenced by the new movement, namely developments in society, economy
and culture since the 1960s (Bielskis 2005). When the idea of a reaction or
rejection of modernism is borrowed by other fields, it becomes synonymous in
some contexts with postmodernity.
Notable initiators of Postmodernist Theory include Laurence Sterne via his
novel Tristram Shandy (initially published in 1759 and republished in 2005),
Alfred Jarry through his Pataphysics (2011), and Lewis Carroll via several works
(Wheale 1995). Art and literature of the early part of the twentieth century
played a significant role in shaping the character of postmodern culture. Other
significant contributors to postmodern culture from literary circles include Jorge
Luis Borges, William S. Burroughs, and Samuel Beckett (Pinkney 1989).
The term Postmodernist Theory when used pejoratively describes tendencies
perceived as relativist, counter-enlightenment, or anti-modern, particularly
in relation to critiques of rationalism and universalism (Palmeri 2001). It
is also sometimes used to describe tendencies in a society, as in the case of
sexuality /gender roles, that are held to be antithetical to traditional systems
of morality. Elements of the Christian Right, in particular, have interpreted
postmodern society to be synonymous with moral relativism and contributing to
deviant behaviours.
Criticisms of Postmodernist Theory are often complicated by the still
fluid nature of the term, and in many cases the criticisms are clearly directed
at the philosophical and academic movements that it has spawned rather than
the broader term Postmodernist Theory. As meaningless or disingenuous as
it may appear, criticism of elements of Postmodernist Theory as ‘sophism’ or
‘obscurantism’ played out in the Sokal Affair/Hoax. An article about interpreting
physics and mathematics in terms of the theory, which Alan Sokal had deliberately
written to mock postmodern theorists’ views on objectivity, determinism, and the
social construction of scientific truth, was submitted for publication, and then
published (Lipovetsky 2005).
The linguist Noam Chomsky has suggested that postmodernism is
meaningless because it adds nothing to analytical or empirical knowledge. He
asks why postmodernist intellectuals would not respond as ‘people in physics,
math, biology, linguistics, and other fields are happy to do when someone asks
214
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
them, seriously, what are the principles of their theories; on what evidence are
they based; and what do they explain that was not already obvious? To him
these are fair requests for anyone to make’ (Docker 1994). If they cannot be
met, then he has suggested recourse to Hume’s advice in similar circumstances:
to the flames.
French philosopher Michel Foucault rejects the label of Postmodernist Theory
explicitly but is seen by many to advocate a form of critique that is ‘postmodern’
in that it breaks with the utopian and transcendental nature of ‘modern’ critique
by calling universal norms of the Enlightenment into question (Bielskis 2005).
Docherty (1993) rejects this characterisation of modern critique by pointing
out that the critiques of Enlightenment universals are central to philosophers of
the modern period. What counts as ‘postmodern’ is a stake in political struggles
where the method of critique is at issue. The recurring debates are between
essentialism and anti-foundationalism, universalism and relativism, where
Enlightenment thinking is seen to represent the former while Postmodernist
Theory represents the latter. This is why theorists as diverse as Nietzsche, Lacan,
Foucault, Derrida, and Butler have been labelled postmodernists, not because
they formed a historical intellectual grouping but because they are seen by their
critics to reject the possibility of universal, normative and ethical judgments
(Docherty 1993). With some exceptions, many thinkers who are considered
postmodern see these characterisations merely as labels of convenience and
reject them altogether.
Radical Feminist Theory
Radical Feminist Theory analyses the structures of power which oppress the female
sex. Its central tenet is that women as a biological class are globally oppressed
by men as a biological class. It is believed that male power is constructed and
maintained through institutional and cultural practices that aim to bolster male
superiority through the reinforcement of female inferiority. As radical feminist
Ti-Grace Atkinson wrote in her foundational work Radical Feminism (2000, first
published in 1969):
The first dichotomous division of this mass [humankind] is said to have been
on the grounds of sex: male and female. It is because half the human race bears
the burden of the reproductive process and because man, the ‘rational’ animal,
has the wit to take advantage of that, the childbearers, or the ‘beasts of burden’,
are corralled into a political class: equivocating the biologically contingent burden
into a political (or necessary) penalty, thereby modifying these individuals’
definition from the human to the functional, or animal (Atkinson 2000:1).
One manifestation of the patriarchy is gender, which is believed to be a
socially constructed hierarchy which functions to repress female autonomy and
has no basis in biology.
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
215
Radical feminists critique all religions and their institutions, and other practices
that promote violence against women such as prostitution and pornography. The
subjugation of women is a social process that has no basis in biology or in any
other pretext and, thus, can and should be challenged and dismantled. Radical
feminists see the oppression of women as closely linked to, and bound up in, their
roles as the bearers of new life and male hatred of female reproductive power.
Radical feminists take an unequivocal stance on the right to female reproductive
justice. They believe in an autonomous women’s movement as the path to
women’s liberation. They also believe in the importance of women-only spaces
where theory and action are developed from the lived reality of females who have
been socialised into womanhood (Atkinson 2000).
Giving women a voice is a key strength of Radical Feminist Theory; prior to the
feminist movement, sociology was regarded as ‘male-stream’ (male-dominated).
The theory raises awareness of gender issues. Through the growth of the Marxist,
liberal and radical strands, the subjugation of women by their male counterparts
has been highlighted, making an enormous contribution to the emancipation
of women. Marxists look at how capitalism affects women’s position in society
and has greatly contributed to our understanding of women’s work and made it
more visible, clearly highlighting the exploitation of women in society. Liberals’
enormous contribution to the emancipation of women is still considered radical
in some countries that do not offer basic rights to women. Such efforts include,
for instance, improved quality of life due to educational and legal reforms and
useful insights on how capitalism affects women’s position in society.
But Radical Feminist Theory fails to see the bigger picture of inequality, such
as the class system and other social categories like disability, race, religion and
nationality. For instance, the theory fails to recognise how working class or Black
women experience barriers to advancement than White, middle-class women, and
this is why some have dismissed it as a White bourgeoisie movement. Feminism
has met this criticism by introducing the idea of intersectional feminism, which
recognises that class, race and disability have systematic structural impacts on
women’s lives in different toxic combinations. The theory fails to explain why it
is specifically women who occupy low status employment and women workers
who are paid less (capitalism still benefits male workers disproportionately),
and it does not analyse the way social class interacts with patriarchy (i.e. the big
difference between the degree of sexism experienced by bourgeosie women in
comparison to proletariat women).
Sexual Difference Theory
The hermeneutic enterprise called Sexual Difference Theory takes its entry point
from the psychoanalytic works of Sigmund Freud (1856–1939) and Jacques Lacan
(1901–1981), both of whom explore issues of gender and sexuality differentiation
216
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
vis-à-vis the salient sexual patterns that embody the individual sexes. Freud’s idea
of the man and woman gender/sexuality binary, many feminist critics would say, is
laden with misogynistic sentiments, especially in his insistence that women suffer
from ‘a castration that has been carried out’ (Freud, quoted in Kaplan 1994:1).
These epistemological efforts, regardless of the flaws attributed to them by
their critics, offer a convenient standpoint for further theorising on sexuality.
Luce Irigaray, in a more contemporary sense and from a feminist-lesbian
perspective, posits that sexual hierarchy and not sexual difference (as one might
have erroneously imagined) occupies the very nucleus of the Western symbolic
order as undertaken by Freud and Lacan. Irigaray is upset by the positions of
Freud and Lacan which project femaleness through the lenses of masculinity.
She insists that the clitoris is not a ‘little penis pleasant to masturbate’ (Irigaray
1977:23). Some of Freud’s assumptions on male-female sexuality (especially his
thoughts on the ‘Oedipus Complex’) are influenced by his belief in gendered
roles. To exemplify this, he established value around the phallus with his concept
of ‘penis envy’ – an organ to be desired by the female and one to be treasured by
the male, an instrument of control and a metaphor for masculine dominance.
Freud’s stance on sexuality poses certain challenges in that it not only denies the
uniqueness of the female, but also attempts to enforce, albeit subliminally, the
exercise of her agency through the male (Irigaray 1977).
In her This Sex Which Is Not One (1977), there is a radical attempt by Irigaray
to pull down all prior hierarchical constructions by highlighting femininity as a
unique status, independent of masculine involvement. The idea of female agency
is affirmed through Irigaray’s description of the vagina as the lips in ‘When Our
Lips Speak Together’.
In the investigation of religion and culture, especially as they obtain in Africa,
one may evoke Irigaray’s notions on sexuality to question the various Biblical
positions and sharp cultural practices that place the woman as an appendage
of the man to whom she must look up for reproductive life, sexual fulfilment,
among other emotional gratifications. Given the various breakthroughs in the
field of gynaecology and the efflorescence of alternative lifestyles around the
world, the idea of an indispensable phallus is dismantled, thereby validating
Irigaray’s point. On the other hand, one may insist, using the Freudian lenses, that
the circumstances that give rise to female subjectivity are based on performance,
rather than being biological.
The seminal explorations of Sexuality Theory by Freud and Lacan enrich the
discourse of sexuality and gender differentiation in the field of psychoanalysis
and provide unique ways of knowing. Nonetheless, Irigaray is guilty of the
very crime which she accuses Freud and Lacan of, for while the works of these
two establish a male subject on the one hand and a female object on the other,
Irigaray’s work literally obliterates the existence of the male by creating the image
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
217
of a self-sufficient female. Again, critical reactions to different approaches to
sexuality hinge on the sociological experiences of the readers, as the positions
of all theorists reflect their various gender and sexuality biases and worldviews.
The global South, for instance, is more likely to have a broader embrace for the
Freudian and Lacanian notions of sexuality than the West.
Sociological Theory
The locus of Sociological Theory on sexuality/gender is the social ascription of
gender roles and the general narratives on gender stereotyping, perceptions, norms,
body image, belief systems, cultural expectations and socially (and sometimes
culturally) generated gender privileges. The Structural Functionalist school of
thought believes that every gender has been naturally configured or wired to play
specific domestic and public roles. These sociologically scripted performances of
gender, based on the perceived gender status of maleness or femaleness, have
a weighty impact on socioeconomic functionality and productivity, more than
they enjoy an effortless generational spread. Gender roles, a term first used by
the American psychologist John Money, are often predicated upon the idea of
femininity and masculinity (Alters & Schiff 2009). In the wake of the global
feminist revolution in the 1960s and 1970s, the ideas of supposedly providential
gender roles are debated with serious intent to enforce a paradigmatic shift.
According to DeFrancisco et al., gender roles are ‘performed according to social
norms’ and ‘social norms determine the privileges and responsibilities a person
possesses’ (2014:2).
The idea of the binary categorisation of humans into genders which naturally
precedes the assignment of social roles is becoming even more complicated as
there are new and alternative ways of (re)reading gender. The discourse of gender
identity in the new millennium continues to flourish with wider possibilities
being proposed. Androgyny, for instance, being a ‘newly’ constructed gender
group, seeks to accommodate in a third gender individuals who combine both
male and female features (Maccoby 1966). This invariably alters the primordial
binary construction of gender. Again, while the term androgyny describes a third
gender, new evidence abounds that gender categorisation encompasses as many
as five genders in certain countries of the world (Graham 2001; Richard et al.
2016). This invariably calls into question the traditional binary constructions of
gender as known to many societies.
According to Linda Lindsey (2015), the four basic sociological perspectives to
gender and sexuality are
1.
2.
3.
4.
Structural Functionalist Theory,
Conflict Theory,
Feminist Theory, and
Symbolic Interactionist Theory.
218
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Structural functionalists focus on family values and the social and communal
equilibrium enhanced by strict alignment with normative gender roles. Conflict
theorists read gender and sexuality from the perspective of the dominance of a
gender group over the other. Borrowing from conflict theorists, feminist theorists
address the menace of endemic patriarchy with its attendant gender inequality.
In Symbolic Interactionism, the social codes that define human interactions are
examined (Lindsey 2015).
One important merit of the Sociological Theory is that it opens new vistas
to the understanding of the sociological underpinnings of gender and sexuality.
Through these, one understands and appreciates the social transitions that have
over time reordered gender priorities, stereotypical patterns, and eliminated
gender-based inequalities. Nevertheless, it is important to note that conversations
such as these often foist an unhealthy rivalry and agitation between (or among)
(un)gendered people having a capacity to lead to war of sexes, even if subtle.
Gender and sexuality conversations appear endless and more and more
complicated from these various perspectives. The stances taken by the different
critics are reflective of their personal biases and often the rhetoric is laden with
underlying dominance and counter-dominance. Indeed, Sociological Theory on
gender and sexuality can be deployed to investigate the complexities of gender
transitioning and de-transitioning and identity crises and disillusionment.
References
African Union (AU), 2019, ‘Action Plan for Boosting Intra–African Trade’. (https://
au.int/web/sites/default/files/newsevents/pressreleases/26498-pr-action_plan_for_
boosting_intra-african_trade_f-english.pdf ). 1 November 2021.
Agbiji, Obaji M. and Swart, Ignatius, 2015, ‘Religion and Social Transformation in
Africa: A Critical and Appreciative Perspective’, Scriptura, Vol. 114, pp. 1–20.
Alters, Sandra and Schiff, Wendy, 2009, Essential Concepts for Healthy Living, Burlington,
MA: Jones & Bartlett Publishers.
Amin, Samir 2004, The Liberal Virus: Permanent War and the Americanization of the
World, New York, NY: Monthly Review Press.
Asante, Molefi, Kete, 1987/1998, The Afrocentric Idea, Philadelphia, PA: Temple
University Press.
Atkinson, Ti-Grace, 2000, ‘Radical Feminism’, in B.A. Crow, ed., Radical Feminism:
A Documentary Reader, New York, NY: New York University Press.
Barkin, J. Samuel, 2003, ‘Realist Constructivism’, International Studies Review, Vol. 5,
No. 3, pp. 325–342.
Becker, Gary, 1976, The Economic Approach to Human Behavior, Chicago, IL:
The University of Chicago Press.
Bell, Duncan, 2014, ‘What is Liberalism?’, Political Theory, Vol. 42, No. 6, pp. 682–715.
Bellah, Robert Neelly, 1973, Religious Evolution, North Stratford, NH: Irvington
Publishers.
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
219
Better Worlds Blog, 2018, ‘In Search of a Broad, Coherent, Social Ecology’. (https://
betterworldsblog.com/broad-social-ecology). 16 October 2021.
Beyers, Jaco, 2017, ‘Religion and Culture: Revisiting a close relative’, HTS Teologiese
Studies/Theological Studies, Vol. 73, No. 1, pp. 1–9. (https://doi.org/10.4102/hts.
v73i1.3864). 16 October 2021.
Biehl, Jane, 1991, Rethinking Ecofeminist Politics, Boston, MA: South End Press.
Bielskis, Andrius, 2005, Towards a Post-Modern Understanding of the Political: From
Genealogy to Hermeneutics, New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Bookchin, Murray, 1982, The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution of
Hierarchy, Palo Alto, CA: Cheshire Books.
Boyer, Pascals, 2001, Religion Explained, New York, NY: Basic Books.
Brooks, Peter, 1995, The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: From Formalism to
Poststructuralism, 1st edition, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Burke, E. and Pocock, J.G.A., 1987, Reflections on the Revolution in France, Indianapolis,
IN: Hackett Pub. Co.
Butler, Judith, 1988, ‘Performative Acts and Gender Constitution: An Essay in
Phenomenology and Feminist Theory’, Theatre Journal, Vol. 40, No. 4, pp. 519–531.
Chawane, Midas, 2016, ‘The Development of Afrocentricity: A Historical Survey’,
Yesterday & Today, No. 16, pp. 78–99. (http://www.scielo.org.za/pdf/yt/n16/06.
pdf ). 18 October 2021.
Claassen, Rutger, 2011, ‘The Conservative Challenge to Liberalism’, Critical Review of
International Social and Political Philosophy, Vol. 14, No. 4, pp. 465–485
Clark, John, 1997, ‘A Social Ecology’, Capitalism Nature Socialism, Vol. 8, No. 3,
pp. 3–33.
DeFrancisco, Victoria; Palczewski, Catherine and McGeough, Danielle, 2014, Gender
in Communication: A Critical Introduction, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
Deng, Lual A., 1998, Rethinking African Development: Towards a Framework for Social
Integration and Ecological Harmony, Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press.
Derrida, Jacques, 1973, Speech and Phenomena: And Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of
Signs, translated by David B. Allison, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Derrida, Jacques, 2010, Voice and Phenomenon, translated by Leonard Lawlor, Evanston,
IL: Northwestern University Press.
Derrida, Jacques, 2021, Writing and Difference, translated by Alan Bass, Chicago, IL: The
University of Chicago Press.
Docherty, Thomas, ed., 1993, Postmodernism: A Reader, New York, NY: Harvester
Wheatsheaf.
Docker, John, 1994, Postmodernism and Popular Culture: A Cultural History, Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Durkheim, Emile, 1995 [1915], The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life, New York,
NY: Free Press.
Eagleton, Terry, 1986, Capitalism, Modernism and Postmodernism against the Grain: Essays
1975–1985, London, UK: Verso.
220
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Easton, David, 1957, ‘An Approach to the Analysis of Political Systems’, World Politics,
Vol. 9, No. 3, pp. 383–400.
Elahi, Manzoor, 2005, ‘What Is Social Contract Theory’, Philosophy Archives, Sophia Project.
(http://www.sophia-project.org/uploads/1/3/9/5/13955288/elahi_socialcontract.
pdf ). 13 October 2021.
Fawcett, Edmund, 2014, Liberalism: The Life of an Idea, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Firestone, Shulamith, 2003 [1970], The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution,
New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Freeden, Michael, 1978, The New Liberalism: An Ideology of Social Reform, Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press.
Geertz, Clifford, 1973, The Interpretation of Cultures, New York, NY: Basic Books.
Gnanasekaran, R., 2015, ‘An Introduction to Derrida, Deconstruction and PostStructuralism’, International Journal of English Literature and Culture, Vol. 3, No. 7,
pp. 211–214. (https://www.academicresearchjournals.org/IJELC/PDF/2015/July/
Gnanasekaran.pdf ). 19 October 2021.
Graff, Gerald, 1973, ‘The Myth of the Postmodernist Breakthrough’, Triquarterly, Vol.
26, pp. 383–417.
Graham, Sharyn, April–June 2001, ‘Sulawesi’s Fifth Gender’, Inside Indonesia. (https://
www.insideindonesia.org/sulawesis-fifth-gender-2). 20 October 2021.
Gray, John, 1995, Liberalism, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Grenz, Stanley J., 1996, A Primer on Postmodernism, Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans
Publishing Company.
Grieco, Joseph M., 1988, ‘Realist Theory and the Problem of International Cooperation:
Analysis with an Amended Prisoner’s Dilemma Model’, The Journal of Politics,
Vol. 50, No. 3, pp. 600–624.
Hadland, A., 2007, ‘State-Media Relations in Post-apartheid South Africa: An Application
of Comparative Media Systems Theory’, Communicate: Journal for Communication
Sciences in Southern Africa, Vol. 26, No. 2, pp. 1–17.
Hall, John; Neitz, Mary Jo and Battani, Marshall, 2003, Sociology on Culture, London,
UK: Routledge.
Hamm, Bernd, 1992, Progress in Sociology, New Delhi, India: Mittal Publications.
Hamm, Bernd, 1992, Progress in Social Ecology, New Delhi, India: Mittal Publications.
Hickey, S., 2011, ‘The Politics of Social Protection: What Do We Get from a Social
Contract Approach’, Canadian Journal of Development Studies, Vol. 32, No. 4,
pp. 426–438.
Hobhouse, L.T., 1911, Liberalism, London, UK: Williams and Norgate.
Hobhouse, L.T., 1994. ‘Liberalism’, in J. Meadowcroft, ed., Liberalism and Other Writings,
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hobson, Marian, 2012, Jacques Derrida: Opening Lines, London, UK: Routledge.
Hodgson, Geoffrey, 1995, ‘The Political Economy of Utopia’, Review of Social Economy,
Vol. 59, No. 2, pp. 195–214.
Huntington, Samuel P., 1957, ‘Conservatism as an Ideology’, The American Political
Science Review, Vol. 51, No. 2, pp. 454–473.
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
221
Irigaray, Luce, 1977, This Sex Which Is Not One, translated by Catherine Porter, Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
Janse van Rensburg, Michael , 2012, ‘Christian Creation Theories rooted in the Genesis
Account and Their Underlying Assumptions’, mini-thesis submitted for the degree
of Master of Theology at the South African Theological Seminary.
Jencks, Charles, 1986, What is Post-Modernism?, New York, NY: St. Martin’s Press.
Jensen, Hans J.L., 2016, ‘Culture, Society, Religion: What do we learn from theories
of religion? (Herodotus, Durkheim, Grundtvig)’, Seminar om Kultur, samfund og
religion, Det Teologiske Fakultet, Københavns Universitet. (https://pure.au.dk/
portal/files/99050099/Culture_Rel_studies_of_rel_2016_03_29FINAL.pdf ).
16 October 2021.
Jensen, Peter S. and Justesen, Mogens K., 2014, ‘Poverty and vote buying: Surveybased evidence from Africa’, Electoral Studies, Vol. 33, pp. 220–232. (https://www.
researchgate.net/publication/259992513_Poverty_and_vote_buying_Surveybased_evidence_from_Africa). 11 October 2021.
Judson, Olivia, 2008, ‘Optimism in Evolution’, New York Times. (https://www.nytimes.
com/2008/08/13/opinion/13judson.html). 11 October 2021.
Kaplan, L.J., 1994, ‘Female Castration Anxiety’, American Imago, Vol. 51, No. 4,
pp. 471–489.
Kupiec, J.J., 1997, ‘A Darwinian Theory for the Origin of Cellular Differentiation’,
Molecular Genetics and Genomics, Vol. 255, pp. 201–208.
Laskar, Manzoor Elahi, 2013, ‘Summary of Social Contract Theory by Hobbes, Locke
and Rousseau’, Social Science Research Network. (doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2410525).
30 September 2021.
Leitch, Vincent, ed., 2001, The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism, New York, NY:
W.W. Norton & Company.
Lindsey, L.L., 2015, Gender Roles: A Sociological Perspective, London, UK: Routledge.
Lipovetsky, Gilles, 2005, Hypermodern Times, Cornwall, UK: Polity Press.
Locke, John, 1960, Two Treatises of Government, edited by Peter Laslett, Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Maccoby, Eleanor E., 1966, ‘Sex Differences in Intellectual Functioning’, in E.E.
Maccoby, ed., The Development of Sex Differences, Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
MacKay, D.B., 2000, ‘Ethnicity’, in W. Braun and R.T. McCutcheon, eds., Guide to the
Study of Religion, London, UK: Bloomsbury Press.
Manent, Pierre and Seigel, Jerrold, 1996, An Intellectual History of Liberalism, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Mantzavinos, C., 2016, ‘Hermeneutics’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (http://
plato.stanford.edu/entries/hermeneutics/#Semiotics). 20 October 2019.
Marx, Karl and Engels, Friedrich, 1967, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, New
York, NY: Penguin Books.
Mazama, Ama, ed., 2003, The Afrocentric Paradigm, Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press.
McKinnon, Andrew M., 2005, ‘Reading “Opium of the People”: Expression, Protest and
the Dialectics of Religion’, Critical Sociology, Vol. 31, pp. 1–2; 15–38.
222
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Mouritz, T., 2010, ‘Comparing the Social Contracts of Hobbes and Locke’, The Western
Australian Jurist, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 123–127.
Mthatiwa, Syned, 2012, ‘The “Rhetoric of Animality”, Animal Imagery and Dr. Kamuzu
Banda’s Dictatorship in the Poetry of Jack Mapanje’, Nordic Journal of African
Studies, Vol. 21, No. 2, pp. 95–117. (https://www.njas.fi/njas/article/view/176/167).
11 October 2021.
Nadel, S.F., 2009, The Theory of Social Structure, London, UK: Routledge.
Nichols, Ray, 1997, ‘“Conservatism” and “the Right” in America: Ideological Conflict,
Categories and Language’, Journal of Political Ideologies, Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 42–56.
Nkwede, Joseph Okwesili, 2019, ‘Political Parties, Citizen Participation and Voter
Behaviour in Africa: A Study of Nigeria’, European Journal of Scientific Research,
Vol. 152, No. 1, pp. 83–92.
Oakeshott, Michael, 1962, Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays, Indianapolis, IN:
Liberty Fund.
Oswell, David, 2010, ‘Cultural Theory: Genealogies, Orientations and Territories’, in D.
Oswell, ed., Cultural Theory, Volume I: Legacies and Innovations, Los Angeles, CA:
Sage Publication.
Palmeri, Frank, 2001, ‘Other than Postmodern?--Foucault, Pynchon, Hybridity, Ethics’,
Postmodern Culture, Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 1-39.
Parkin, Frank, 1979, Marx’s Theory of History: A Bourgeois Critique, New York,
NY: Columbia University Press.
Pinkney, Tony, 1989, ‘Editor’s Introduction: Modernism and Cultural Theory’, in R.
Williams, ed., The Politics of Modernism: Against the New Conformists, London,
UK: Verso.
Priya, Rashmi, 2018, ‘The Durkheim’s Sociology of Religion and Its Function’, Your
Article Library. (http://www.yourarticlelibrary.com/sociology/the-durkheimssociology-of-religion-and-its-function/43749). 16 October 2021.
Ramadan, Tariq, 2010, What I believe, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Richard, Jocelyn M.; Ambroggi, Frederic; Janak, Patricia H. and Fields, Howard L.,
2016, ‘Ventral Pallidum Neurons Encode Incentive Value and Promote Cueelicited Instrumental Actions’, Neuron, Vol. 90, No. 6, pp. 1165–1173. (https://doi.
org/10.1016/j.neuron.2016.04.037). 13 October 2021.
Richerson, Peter J. and Robert, Boyd, 2001, ‘Built For Speed, Not For Comfort: Darwinian
Theory and Human Culture’, History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, Vol. 23,
No. 3/4, pp. 425–465. (https://www.jstor.org/stable/23332522). 13 October 2021.
Saussure, Ferdinand de, 1959 [1916], Course in General Linguistics, New York,
NY: Philosophical Library.
Schuurman, E., 2011, ‘Technology and Religion: Islam, Christianity and Materialism’,
Koers: (Online), Vol. 76, No. 2, pp. 373–386. (http://www.scielo.org.za/scielo.
php?script=sci_arttext&pid=S2304-85572011000400008). 18 October 2021.
Scott, Arnold N., 2009, Imposing Values: An Essay on Liberalism and Regulation, New
York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Scott, E.C. and Branch, G., 2009, ‘Don’t Call it “Darwinism”’, Evolution: Education
and Outreach, Vol. 2, pp. 90–94. (https://doi.org/10.1007/s12052-008-0111-2).
13 October 2021.
Doctoral Scholars: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender
223
Segerstrale, Ullica, 2000, Defenders of the Truth: The Battle for Science in the Sociobiology
Debate and Beyond, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Sen, Amartya K., ed., 2011, ‘Why Do Respect and Understanding Matter?’ in Peace
and Democratic Society, Cambridge, UK: Open Book Publishers. (https://books.
openedition.org/obp/138?lang=en). 21 October 2021.
Simpson, Miles E., and Conklin, George H., 1989, ‘Socioeconomic Development,
Suicide and Religion: A Test of Durkheim’s Theory of Religion and Suicide’, Social
Forces, Vol. 67, No. 4, pp. 945–964.
Sosis, Richard and Alcorta, Candace, 2003, ‘Signaling, solidarity and the sacred:
The evolution of religious behavior’, Evolutionary Antropology, Vol. 12, No. 6,
pp. 264–274.
Strasser, Hermann and Randall, Susan C., 1981, Introduction to Theories of Social Change,
London, UK: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Thakur, Ramesh, 2019, Reviewing the Responsibility to Protect: Origins, Implementation
and Controversies, London, UK: Routledge.
Than, Ker and Taylor, Ashley, P., 2021, ‘What is Darwin’s Theory of Evolution?’, Live
Science,
(https://www.livescience.com/474-controversy-evolution-works.html).
13 October 2021.
Thompson, J.A. and Hart, D.W., 2006, ‘Psychological Contracts: A Nano-level Perspective
on Social Contract Theory’, Journal of Business Ethics, Vol. 68, No. 3, pp. 229–241.
Verharen, Charles C., 2000, ‘Molefi Asante and an Afrocentric Curriculum’, The Western
Journal of Black Studies, Vol. 24, No. 4, pp. 223–238.
Waldron, Jeremy, 1989, ‘John Locke: Social Contract versus Political Anthropology’,
The Review of Politics, Vol. 51, No. 1, pp. 3–28.
Wheale, Nigel, ed., 1995, The Postmodern Arts: An Introductory Reader, New York,
NY: Routledge.
Wilkins, John, 1998, ‘So You Want to Be an Anti-Darwinian: Varieties of Opposition to
Darwinism’, Talk Origins Archive, Houston, TX: The Talk Origins Foundation, Inc.
(http://www.talkorigins.org/faqs/anti-darwin.html). 13 October 2021.
Wilson, David Sloan, 2002, Darwin’s Cathedral: Evolution, Religion and the Nature of
Society, Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Wilson, Peter, 2011, Idealism in International Relations, London, UK: Sage Publications.
Wilterdink, Nico and Form, William, ‘Social Change’, Encyclopedia Britannica. (https://
www.britannica.com/topic/social-change). 15 October 2021.
Wittek, Raphael; Snijders, Tom A.B. and Nee, Victor, eds., 2013, The Handbook of
Rational Choice Social Research, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Wolper, David L., 2011, ‘Genesis and Science: More Aligned Than You Think?’,
Huffington
Post
Blog.
(https://www.huffpost.com/entry/genesis-and-scie
nce_b_500201?ncid=engmodushpmg00000005&guccounter=1&guce_
referrer=aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZ29vZ2xlLmNvbS8&guce). 15 October 2021.
8
Social Movements
and Change, Social Stratification, and War
Doctoral Scholars
In this chapter, we present succinct discussions on three theories concerning social
movements and change, three on social stratification, and five on war. The first
category deals with ideas about large, in some cases informal, groupings of people
or organisations that focus on particular political or social matters. The second
category refers to notions about a system by which a society ranks divisions of
people regarded as having particular shared characteristics in a hierarchy. And the
third category concerns thoughts on a state of armed conflict between different
nations or states or different groups within a nation or state.
Social Movements and Change
Le Bon’s Mob Psychology Theory
Le Bon’s Mob Psychology Theory is an approach used for the broad study of the
human mind and how individual behaviour is impacted when large crowds group
together. The father of the theory, Charles-Marie Gustave Le Bon (1841–1931),
was a French social scientist and philosopher. Le Bon was originally trained as
a physician but his primary contribution was in the field of sociology where he
developed major theories on crowd behaviour. He believed that crowds maintain
a collective mind and that the group mind is not simply a summary of traits of
the individual persons. Instead, a new distillation of traits emerges, primarily
unconscious in nature, which reflects racially inherited, innate characteristics.
The consequence is a regression in the direction of more primitive, instinctual
determinants of behaviour, in contrast to more rational intellectual determinants.
Le Bon expanded on these ideas in three main concepts. The first concept is
anonymity – i.e. people behave irrationally when they are in the crowd, as they
lose their fear of consequences, and they lose moral responsibility, self-control,
226
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
and conscious personality. This temporary feeling of invincibility causes them to
be unable to restrain certain instincts that they otherwise would have restrained
if they were alone (Merton 1968).
The second concept is suggestibility. This basic principle became the core
foundation of this theory: i.e. individuals tend to lose their sense of self and
responsibility (hypnotic state) simply by being a part of ‘the crowd’ (Merton
1968). Dictators like Hitler and Mussolini gained power, influence and strength
by using the suggestibility technique. They transformed nations of individuals,
most of whom had no intention for murdering a human being, into people who
were prepared to act ruthlessly and inhumanely. The mob mentality that arose
turned crowds into genocidal hordes.
The third and final concept is contagion – i.e. people bond in a a crowd to
the point that each individual will sacrifice his/her interest for the interest of
the crowd; thus, ‘acts’ become contagious. Le Bon indicated that crowds are also
capable of engaging in positive social actions (Merton 1968).
Le Bon’s theory rests on three concepts which explain why the psychology of a
crowd can be different from and interact with the psychologies of the individuals
within it:
Dissocialised concept of identity: there is no link between the self and the society.
Only self is rational and controls human behaviour not society and self. Denial
voice: if we see the crowd as irrational we are making their actions meaningless.
Their voices mean nothing because they are mad. Denial of responsibility: the crowd
members cannot be held responsible for their actions because they are not under
their own control due to their irrational behaviour but society is also not held
responsible because if the crowd is not acting or reacting to anything tangible or
concrete, their behaviours are meaningless; therefore, their protests can be denied.
The denial legitimates the repression of discord and protest in society, so both the
crowd and the society can be repressed (Merton 1968:3).
Le Bon’s idea examines the use of the power of the crowd to harness the goals
of the state, more specifically political goals. His belief with respect to political
behaviour consistently revealed a basic mistrust of the masses. His theory therefore
provides a decontextualised account of human and social actions. It ignores the
social context and it ignores those participating in the actions. It gives no account
of why there is a mass action in the first place or who else might be involved. He
portrays the crowd as inherently mad and inherently meaningless (Merton 1968).
Neil Smelser’s Value-Added Model Theory
American sociologist Neil Smelser’s Value-Added Model Theory emphasises the
social causes of collective behaviour. To Smelser, collective behaviour is driven by
strain experienced by participants in a social setting. He explained that people
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
227
react and behave collectively based on their belief about a situation and the belief
that stems from their interpretation of the situation and the meaning given to it
(Locher 2002).
This theory, which was developed by Smelser in 1962, has its basis in the
Functionalism Theory. The key social conditions (determinants) for collective
behaviour to happen include structural conduciveness, structural strain,
generalised belief, precipitating factors, mobilisation of participants, and societal
control (Locher 2002). Smelser used the phrase ‘value‐added’ to describe how
collective actions occur in a process where determinants build on each other in
a manner that increases the likelihood of a collective action (Heath, Johansen &
Saffer 2018).
When people behave in ways in which they should behave in a situation, it is
seen as normal and as a social behaviour; but when they behave in ways opposite
to how they should behave, it is seen as abnormal and as a collective behaviour.
Smelser believed that collective behaviour serves as valve or outlet for pent-up
strain or tension in a society. When tension is being built up, strain is produced
which over time, along with other determinants, increases the possibility of
release. When this pent-up tension is generally felt by the majority of the people
and its interpretation is accepted by many with no societal control for it, there is
a collective behaviour to release the tension (Marx 2012).
Smelser’s Value-Added Model Theory is applicable to many societal problems.
For example, an increase in the fuel price in Nigeria resulted in a collective uproar.
The situation put many people under financial strain. This, coupled with the
general belief that the increase in fuel price was needed to provide money to pay
politicians’ salaries, resulted in a collective action: people rioting. This behaviour
was also precipitated by police beating people who were queuing for fuel. The
process was determined by the actions of the leaders of the event. During the fuel
scarcity riot in Nigeria, the then union leaders were trusted. Their directives were
widely accepted by the people, leading to the rioting which almost paralysed the
economy of the country.
Smelser’s theory is widely applicable as it speaks to social situations and
factors, rather than taking its origin from psychological factors. It delineates a
sequence of determinants that must be present for a collective behaviour to occur.
It can be used to analyse situations or events that occur in a society, and to predict
what might occur once certain predisposing factors are present. This can help to
forestall problems if attention is duly paid and needed actions taken.
The theory is, however, limited. If some of the elements are not present, the
behaviour might not occur. Also, it can only work where the strain is greater than
people can bear and where people’s wills, thoughts, and actions are not suppressed
by force. It sees all strains as being disruptive, when some might not be.
228
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Resource Mobilisation Theory
Resource Mobilisation Theory was developed in the early 1970s to challenge
social breakdown and relative deprivation theories that identify individual
grievances as the primary stimulus for collective action (Edwards & McCarthy
2004). Its theorists argued that the success of social movements depends on
resources (time, money, skills, etc.) and the ability to use them (Jenkins 1982).
They stressed that mobilisation requires a variety of resources and linkages of
social movements to other groups, that there is a dependence of movements upon
external support for success, and that the tactics used by authorities to control or
incorporate movements need to be factored in (McCarthy & Zald 1973 & 1977;
Jenkins 1982).
John D. McCarthy and Mayer Zald are the originators and major advocates
of the classic entrepreneurial (economic) version of this theory, while Charles
Tilly and Doug McAdam are proponents of the political version of resource
mobilisation called Political Process Theory. McCarthy and Zald (1977) argue
that grievances are necessary but not enough to stimulate the rise of a movement
because grievances and social conflicts are inherent and enduring in every society.
The application the Resource Mobilisation Theory is popular in the examination
of the formation of social movements. It argues that social movements are
dependent on the ability of organisations to mobilise resources – both labour and
money, which are the critical factors in movement mobilisation – from potential
supporters (Walsh 1981).
Resource Mobilisation Theory is used to analyse protest mobilisation, when
information from social media filters from the networks of political activists
(Eltantawy & Wiest 2011). Mobilised protests and industrial actions have been
recent social phenomena across developing economies in both private and public
organisations (Breuer, Landman & Farquhar 2015). As posited by Eltantawy, &
Wiest (2011), social movement leaders use bargaining, persuasion, or violence to
influence authorities to change. The focus on the interaction between movements
and authorities is accepted, but it is also noted that social movement organisations
have a number of strategic tasks. These include mobilising supporters, transforming
mass and elite publics into sympathisers, and achieving change in targets (Breuer,
Landman & Farquhar 2015). It is argued that the most serious challengers of
autocrats come from their own ruling coalitions: i.e. the security forces and the
ruling parties (Diaz-Cayeros et al. 2011).
The social scientific study of riots has amply demonstrated that even in the
most anarchic protest there are ‘leaders’ who retain a consciousness of themselves
apart from the action and who are, for that reason, capable of calculating and
‘directing’ action (Auyero & Moran 2007). These ‘leaders’ who may well be
‘leaders’ in only a single protest event, as well as the ‘opinion leaders’ who mould
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
229
opinion in all kinds of communities, operate on the basis of the understandings
of the situation that depend upon knowledge which is itself shaped by theory
(Breuer, Landman & Farquhar 2015).
Critics (e.g. Gursoy & Kendall 2006) point out that Resource Mobilisation
Theory fails to explain social movement communities, which are large networks
of individuals. The theory is also said to fail in explaining how groups with
limited resources can succeed in bringing about social change, and that it does
not assign sufficient weight to grievances, identity and culture as well as many
macro-sociological issues. The theory is criticised for being overly concerned
with processes internal to social movements themselves and for neglecting factors
arguably more crucial to their successes (Gursoy & Kendall 2006).
Social Stratification
Class Theory
As it relates to social stratification, Class Theory seeks to describe and explain
groups of people within a society who possess different socioeconomic statuses.
This theory conceives the concept of class as a collection of individuals sharing
similar economic circumstances, particularly in industrial society (Kreckel 1980).
It is important to note here that social classes are based on economic perspectives
rather than status groups which are constituted based on honour or the prestige
of an occupation, cultural position, or family background.
Two of the pioneering theorists of Class Theory are Karl Marx (1818–1883)
and Max Weber (1864–1920). Marx distinguished between owners of the modes
of production and their employees. He focused on the conflicts between social
classes as represented by industrial workers and the owners of factories and
businesses. He said that society is fundamentally divided between classes which
clash in pursuit of their own class interests. Despite the fact that Weber also
employed the term class, he used a multidimensional approach in his perspective
by distinguishing and analysing the following concepts:
1. Class as economic position,
2. Status as position and prestige independent of economic situation, and
3. Power as access to authority structures (Bell & Cleaver 1982; Muller 2015).
The preceding explanation suggests that, despite some limitations from Africa’s
political democratisation perspective, Class Theory has increasingly become
highly applicable to some African issues. It enables theorists to describe and
explain the characteristics of the principal contemporary social classes:
1. upper,
2. working or lower, and
3. middle.
230
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The upper class in modern African capitalist societies is often distinguished
by the possession of largely inherited wealth. The ownership of large amounts
of property and the income derived from it confer many advantages upon the
members of the upper class. They are able to develop a distinctive lifestyle based
on extensive cultural pursuits and leisure activities, to exert considerable influence
on economic policy and political decisions, and to obtain high quality education
and economic opportunities for their children, thus perpetuating family wealth.
As its key strength, Class Theory is notable for providing useful insights as to
how the class positions of individuals and groups in societies can be distinguished
from a socioeconomic perspective. This may provide useful input for differential
policy interventions tailored to address embedded inequalities among different
segments of societies. Despite this, the key weakness of the Class Theory is that it
views class differentiations as a source of antagonism and conflicts between classes
and proposes revolution and socialist interventions as viable solutions.
Elite Theory
Elite Theory, which is also known as a theory of the state, emerged in order to
describe and explain power relationships in society. The pioneering theorists are
Vilfredo Pareto (1848–1923), Gaetano Mosca (1858–1941) and Robert Michels
(1876–1936), who significantly influenced subsequent postulates on the theory.
Pareto viewed power as a dichotomy between rulers (elite) and ruled. He identifies
two types of elites:
1. the elite of ‘lions’ who are fundamentally conservative, preservative, and
addicted to forceful action; and
2. the ‘foxes’ who possess the instinct for combination and are less rigid
intellectually, more innovative and reflective, but much less decisive in action.
Pareto also asserted that there exists the succession of ruling groups (circulation
of elites) as a law of history. A similar view of power was adopted by Mosca and
Michels. Mosca stated that the elite comprise an organised minority while the
masses are an unorganised majority. The elite are esteemed and influential owing
to their intellectual, moral and material superiority. Michels, notable for his Iron
Law of Oligarchy, asserted that social and political organisations are run by a few
individuals, social organisations and labour divisions which are key to consolidating
the bureaucratic structure of political organisation (Bottomore 1993).
The elite are privileged upper-class individuals. Broadly, the ruling class
comprises three types of elites:
1. the economic elite represent the top strata of big business and corporation
management,
2. the political elite represent key figures in the formal apparatus of government, and
3. the military elite represent those at the top strata of state military structures
(Sorel & Schwartz 1989).
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
231
These elite pursue key strategies to maintain their power status. Most of them, if
not all, seek to establish
1. a dynamic network of the leaders of the military, corporate, and political
entities;
2. increasingly interchangeable leadership in the elite groups (individuals switch
from one position of institutional power to another; for example, a prominent
military officer becomes a political adviser or a powerful politician also
becomes a corporate executive); and
3. a system of interlocking directorates of economic, political and military elite.
All the three groups mix with one another in different ways via both informal
and official contacts.
These ensure the cohesion and impermeability of the hierarchy of the elite in
the forms of power (wealth, civil authority, influence, and opinion) which are
autonomous, irreducible and independent of democratic elections. The elite use
such power positions as instruments to exert significant power over corporate
and government decisions, policy planning and political election processes
(Dahrendorf 1990; Gilens & Page 2014).
Elite Theory is applicable to Africa in the sense that it explains the ground
realities of social and political organisations in contemporary Africa. The theory
informs us that in cases where certain groups are entirely excluded from a state’s
power networks on the basis of arbitrary criteria (nobility, race, gender, ethnicity,
or religion), such groups emerge as the counter-elite. In essence, the old elite can
be replaced by a new one as in the case of Zimbabwe and Ethiopia.
One of the strengths of the Elite Theory is that it provides a full-fledged
theoretical framework to analyse and understand power relationships and the
influence of the elite in a contemporary society. The theory warns the ruling elite
about the danger of political exclusion leading to the emergence of a counterelite. As to its weaknesses, the theory underestimates the value of pluralism,
multi-partyism and a checks-and-balance system, which are the underpinnings of
modern democracy. The potential outcomes may be ethnic conflict, dictatorship,
corruption and coups d’état. Given the diverse ethnic and cultural contexts
that are common in most African countries, the promotion of pluralism and
multipartyism is imperative.
Stratification Theory
Stratification Theory asserts that social inequality is the basis of social stratification
(Wani et al. 2014). The theory is concerned with socially embedded inequalities
and emerged in the social science disciplines to describe and explain individuals’
positions in hierarchies in a given social group, category, geographical region or
other social unit. The process of hierarchical delineations (determining relative
social position) of social strata for individuals and groups based on diverse
232
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
indicator variables about various characteristics of persons and peoples is called
social stratification. Generally, this involves two types of variables: (1) economic
variables like income and wealth at household level and per capita gross domestic
product [GDP] (Parsons 1951) especially at the international level; and (2) social
status indicator variables such as gender, race, ethnicity, occupation and skill levels,
age, education level, education level of parents, kinship ties or caste relations and
geographic area (Parsons 1951; Wani et al. 2014). These socially defined criteria
serve to place individuals and groups within various strata of society. All societies
exhibit some system of hierarchy whereby members are placed in positions that
are higher or lower, superior or inferior, in relation to each other.
Karl Marx (1818–1883) is the originator of the Social Stratification Theory.
He asserted that an individual’s position within a class hierarchy is determined
by his/her role in the production process (Kreckel 1980). Later critics felt that
Marx overemphasised the economic factor. Max Weber (1864–1920) is another
key theorist of Social Stratification Theory. He built upon Marx’s view of social
stratification (economic factors), adding a multi-dimensional view (class, status,
and power) which allows for a comprehensive way of understanding the complex
nature of social stratification (Parsons 1951; Wani et al. 2014).
Stratification Theory can be applied to African issues to explain structured
inequalities so as to make informed development decisions to remedy those
inequalities. The functions of stratification include:
A means of accomplishing essential jobs in society: Stratification in society is a way for
a society to get some of its essential jobs done by distributing different amounts
of prestige and privilege to various strata. A typical example may be a health
institution, in which doctors, nurses, laboratory technologists, security personnel
and gardeners differ hierarchically from top to bottom while meeting societies’
health needs. The rewards (economic, aesthetic or symbolic, and material or
psychological satisfaction) which society gives serve as incentives to get the various
essential jobs accomplished.
Regulation and control of individual and group relationships and participation:
Through prescribed roles and role expectations, norms and standards of behaviour
are expected in relationships at intra-stratum and inter-stratum levels. This also
regulates participation of groups and individuals in the total life of society and
may even give them access to certain areas and restrict them from others: for
example, limiting the number of students going to universities.
Simplification: Categorising people into different strata simplifies a human
being’s world in respect to his/her relations with other people. For example, the
criterion of age as an identification of adulthood, while not always valid in specific
instances, serves a purpose when dealing with the entire population. There is a
practical justification in the practice of categorising people and responding to each
category differently, but responding identically to all persons within a category.
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
233
This theory’s weaknesses may be that stratification can lead to intergenerational
stigma and stereotypes within broader social structures: Black vs white, poor vs
rich, and so on.
War
Idealist/Lockean Theory
In a sociological sense, Idealism emphasises how human ideas, especially beliefs
and values, shape society. As an ontological doctrine, idealism asserts that all
entities are composed of mind or spirit. An idealist is someone who envisions an
ideal world rather than the real one. Some people consider idealists to be naive,
impractical, and out of touch with reality, while idealists think that striving for
perfection makes the world a better place. The main root of the term idealist is
‘ideal,’ which is derived from the Latin word idea and theoretically conceptualised
by John Locke (1632–1704), who was an English philosopher in the early Age of
Enlightenment. His ideas had enormous influence on the development of mainly
European Epistemology and Political Philosophy, and he is widely regarded as
one of the most influential early Enlightenment thinkers. He postulates that at
birth, the mind is a blank slate or tabula rasa: i.e. we are born without innate
ideas, and that knowledge is instead determined only by experience derived from
sense perception. This is now known as empiricism (Thompson 2003).
For Locke, in the state of nature all humans are free ‘to order their actions, and
dispose of their possessions and persons, as they think fit, within the bounds of
the law of nature. The state of Nature has a law of Nature to govern it’ (Thompson
2003:83), and that law is reason. Locke declared that under natural law, all
people have the right to life, liberty, and estate; under the social contract, the
people could instigate a revolution against the government when it acts against
the interests of citizens, and replace the government with one that serves the
interests of citizens (Thompson 2003).
Locke’s Idealist Theory is applicable in Africa in that it could help check
leaders whose main interest is what they gain for themselves, rather than the
welfare of the citizens. The democratic form of government proposed by Locke
allows the expression of the voices of the people. If, as Locke proposed, most
people are inherently peace-loving, then governments that express the desire of
the people will be less warlike. This could play out on the international stage,
where global institutions can establish fora in which nation states can discuss
their disagreements in ways that will reinforce cooperation. The Idealist concept
of the social contract is the key to overthrowing any government that acts against
the interests of the citizens. This can be seen in a modern democrary like Ghana
where the power of the thumb (voting in elections) is key to maintaining or
changing a government.
234
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The theory has inspired thought in the mental and spiritual domains, in
literature and arts, and in studies of culture and the past. Liberal Idealism views
history as the progressive advancement of human society. The idea promotes
cooperation among states for the common the goal of the advancement of
humanity, assuming that this is a rational choice which would always be made. It
has also led to fulfilment in the area of education by highlighting the important
role of the teacher and highlighting values such as truth, goodness, and beauty
(Thompson 2003).
Just War Theory
Just War Theory is a largely Christian philosophy that attempts to reconcile three
things:
1. taking human life is wrong,
2. states have a duty to defend their citizens, and
3. defending justice, protecting innocent human lives and defending important
moral values sometimes require willingness to use force.
The Just War theory was first developed by St Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274),
who suggested that the following conditions must be satisfied for a war to be
considered just (Neu 2011):
First is that the war must be for a just cause. Any other intention – e.g., material
gain – undermines the justice of the war. Secondly, the decision to go to war must
be made with the proper authority (usually laid down in the state’s constitution)
and by a public declaration. Thirdly, the declaration of war must be a last resort,
following the exhaustion of all plausible alternatives means to resolving the
conflict. Fourthly, a declaration of war can only be just if the state can foresee
a probability of success in resolving the conflict through war. Violence without
likely gain cannot be justified. And, finally, the response of declaring war must
be proportionate: i.e. the good that can be secured through war must outweigh
the evil that will most likely occur. The end must justify the means. And in this
calculation, the state must take into account not just the costs and benefits to
itself, but those that will affect everyone involved in the war: e.g., including enemy
casualties (Neu 2011:413–434, passim).
Just War Theory breaks down in three types of justice:
1. jus ad bellum – the justice of resorting to war;
2. jus in bello – just conduct in war; and
3. jus post bellum – justice at the end of war (Neu 2011).
Africa is confronted by indigenous, religious, neocolonial and liberation wars
which emanate from greed for power, profit and property. The jus post bellum –
justice at the end of war can be achieved when we distinguish between justice and
fairness, effective laws and lasting peace (forgiveness and repentance from greed),
and development of affected societies and reconciliation.
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
235
Like any other theory, the Just War Theory has strengths and limitations. The
following are some of the strengths of the theory: (a) it maintains the central
importance of the dignity of each human being, (b) it encourages combatants to
think about the moral implications of their actions, and (c) it rejects the view that
there are no rules of conduct in war situations (Neu 2011).
The main problem with the theory is that any war can be justified as a just
war and it is open to great abuse. Any side can provide a list of reasons why its
involvement in a war is just, as was clear from the onset of the Iraq War. The idea
behind that lie was to provide the justification needed to invade Iraq; and, by the
time the world acknowledged that there were no weapons of mass destruction
as claimed by the United States, it was already too late. Also, the theory’s tenets
of discrimination and proportionality have come under criticism in the last
century, particularly after the absolute carnage of World Wars I and II. Far too
many innocent civilians die in modern warfare to justify any war; and, yet, many
justifications for war are proffered.
Pacifist Theory
The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (IEP) (2019) describes Pacifism as a
broader theory incorporating doctrines of non-violence, passive resistance, and
moral purity. The IEP defines Pacifism as the theory of peaceful rather than violent
or aggressive relations. It is believed that Pacifism should govern human intercourse,
and that arbitration, surrender, or migration should be used to resolve disputes
(IEP 2019). All forms of violence, war, and/or killing are unconditionally wrong.
The proposed ideal is that social intercourse should be completely nonviolent and
peaceful, and conflicts which may arise should be dealt with through arbitration
and compromise rather than with recourse to violent means.
According to Keith Robbins (1976), the term Pacifism was coined by the
French peace campaigner Émile Arnaud (1864–1921) and adopted by other
peace activists at the tenth Universal Peace Congress in Glasgow in 1901. Other
outstanding pacifists include Oscar Wilde (1854–1900), Mahatma Gandhi
(1869–1948), Helen Keller (1880–1968), Albert Einstein (1879–1955) and John
Lennon (1940–1980) (Bevel et al. 2016). The related term to Pacifism is ‘ahimsa’
which implies ‘do no harm’, and is a core philosophy in Hinduism, Buddhism,
and Jainism (Bevel et al. 2016).
In terms of how Pacifism is used in contemporary times, Holmes (2013) posits
that ‘pacifism’ is used interchangeably with ‘nonviolence’. It is associated with
different methods and techniques of nonviolent actions (Atack 2012; Holmes
2013; Dudouet 2015). Examples of nonviolent techniques include:
• protest and persuasion through petitions, slogans, cartoons, banners, posters,
radio and television shows, delegations and pressure groups, picketing, acts of
undressing in public, and protest art;
236
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
•
•
•
•
non-cooperation;
industrial actions and strikes, civil disobedience, the search for asylum,
collective emigration, consumer boycotts, non-payment of rent, refusal to pay
fees and taxes;
nonviolent intervention;
fasting, hunger strikes, occupation of public places, nonviolent obstruction,
oral intervention at events, guerrilla theatre, and the creation of alternative
social institutions (Dudouet 2015).
The strength of Pacifist Theory lies in its rejection of all forms of war and violence,
though some pacifists make distinctions between types of violence (Holmes 2013).
The nature and success of nonviolent movements has become a major focus of
research within the field of Peace and Conflict Resolution Studies (see Chapter
6). There are activist sectors of society where nonviolence is studied and practiced
as a form of politics, including the anti-war movement, the environmental
movement, large parts of the anti-capitalist and anarchist movements, and others.
Pacifists’ beliefs emphasise the sanctity of human life, according it a special moral
status that necessitates strong justifications for the injuring, harming, restraining,
or killing of another (Holmes 2013).
The shortcomings of the Pacifist Theory are evident in different sociopolitical
events. The most intricate difficulty facing the general pacifist is the link between
personal pacifism and international pacifism, which is not very clear-cut in most
writings. Some pacifists may admit the use of internal aggression to sustain law
and order but be set against the use of aggression for resolving international
disputes (Neu 2011).
Realist/Hobbesian Theory
Realist/Hobbesian Theory (or Realism, for short) is an approach that regards
external objects as the most fundamentally real things, with perceptions or ideas
as secondary. Realism is opposed to idealism. A realist is someone who sees the
world the way it is and is not afraid to speak the truth as seen. Realists think
that humankind is not permanently kind but rather self-centred and competitive.
Thomas Hobbes (1588–1683) viewed human nature as egocentric and conflictual.
He propounded the notion that an individual’s innate nature is anarchic, selfinterested and power-seeking. In his view, because people are reasonable, they can
see their way out of such a state (a place where everyone behaves any way and any
how) by recognising the laws of nature, which show them the way to establish a
civil society (Hobbes 1994; Yurdusev 2006).
According to Hobbes (1994), the most important law of nature commands
that each person be willing to pursue peace when others are willing to do the
same, all the while retaining the right to continue to pursue war when others do
not pursue peace. Being reasonable and recognising the rationality of this basic
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
237
precept of reason, people can be expected to construct a social contract that will
afford them a life other than that available to them in the state of nature. In
Hobbes’ view, this contract is constituted by two distinguishable contracts. First,
they must agree to establish society by collectively and reciprocally renouncing
the rights they had against one another in the state of nature. Second, they must
imbue some one person or assembly of persons with the authority and power to
enforce the initial contract. In other words, to ensure their escape from the state
of nature, they must agree to live together under common laws and establish an
enforcement mechanism for the social contract and the laws that constitute it
(Hobbes 1994; Yurdusev 2006).
Since the sovereign is invested with the authority and power to mete out
punishments (which need to be worse than not being able to act as one pleases)
for breaches of the social contract, people have good, albeit self-interested, reason
to adjust themselves to the artifice of morality in general and justice in particular.
Society becomes possible. Whereas in the state of nature there was no power able
to ‘overawe them all’, there is now an artificially superior and more powerful
person who can force people to cooperate. While living under the authority of
a sovereign can be harsh (Hobbes argued that because people’s passions can be
expected to overwhelm their reason, the sovereign must have absolute authority
in order for the contract to be successful), it is at least better than living in
the state of nature. And, no matter how much we may object to how poorly a
sovereign manages the affairs of the state and regulates our own lives, we are never
justified in resisting his or her power because it is the only thing which stands
between us and what we most want to avoid, the state of nature (Hobbes 1994;
Yurdusev 2006).
In the African context, the Realist/Hobbesian Theory helps in the study of
countries like Uganda and Rwanda, where there are strict authoritarian leaders
(compared to countries like Ghana and Nigeria with democratic leadership).
These leaders ensure laws are strictly enforced, on the basis that this social contract
ostensibly aids the development of the country.
One of the principal strengths of the Realist/Hobbesian Theory is related to
the law of social contract which helps theorists to understand international
relations due to its simplicity, practicality and rationality. But realists are unable
to explain aspects of contemporary international relations, especially the rise of
state conflicts, the rise of dependency between states, and the increased power
and influence of non-state actors in international relations. Others contend that
the theory is a loose framework (Rosenthal 1991:7) rather than a structured
theory. It does not offer solutions to problems but rather explains them. Hobbes’
recommendation of deposing authoritians without the suggestion of a peaceful
means of doing so is also a shortcoming in his work in that authoritarians are not
easily removed from office without the loss of lives.
238
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Social Contract/Rousseauian Theory
Apropos the issue of war, the central tenet of Social Contract/Rousseauian Theory
is that when a country decides to engage in a war, the series of actions or steps it
takes in order to achieve a particular end and to gain the consent of the populace
must be stated more explicitly than under ordinary peacetime conditions. As such,
the perspective aligns with the philosophy’s conjectured ‘compact’, or ‘agreement’,
between the ruled and their rulers, thereby defining the rights and duties of each
entity. Social Contract/Rousseauian Theory is derived from the belief that in
the beginning, human beings lived in nature without a government and laws to
govern them. The emergence of hardships and oppression in sections of society
caused humans to enter into agreements with each other. The agreements took
two forms:
1. Pactum Subjectionis and
2. Pactum Unionis.
Pactum Subjectionis was one in which people were to respect one another and
live in peace and harmony. In Pactum Unionis, people were to unite and pledge
to obey authority. The authority was to guarantee every one’s protection of life,
property and, to a certain extent, liberty (Elahi 2005). The theory is based on the
idea that each person implicitly agrees to the rules, morals, and general impulses
of a particular society and the government under which s/he lives. All civilised
behaviour flows from this (Hobbes 1994; Thompson 2003; Castiglione 2015).
Joshua Foa Dienstag (1996) lists the founding theorists of Social Contract
Theory to include Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679), John Locke (1632–1704), JeanJacques Rousseau (1712–1778), Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) and John Rawls
(1921–2002). Locke is said to have believed that when people transfer their rights
to a government, a social contract is entered into. In subjecting themselves to a
sovereign ruler or other form of government, people gain security. Locke is also
noted to have expressed the belief that people had certain basic rights that must be
supplied by the government as a result of its contract with the people. Rousseau
asserted that individuals cede their powers to the community, and live under the
direction of the general will (Cheng 2018). Rousseau said that in a state of nature
people were separated enough not to come into serious conflict (Rousseau 1984).
Hobbes believed that in the ‘State of Nature’, the establishment of moral rules
to govern relations among citizens is imperative for ensuring the government’s
capability of enforcing these rules. Hobbes suggested that a person in his/her
natural state would have unlimited freedoms and a right to all things. And, Kant
is considered to have believed that humans are selfish by nature, but that they
can control themselves through rational, universalised thinking (Yurdusev 2006;
Donelson 2017).
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
239
Social Contract Theory is important specifically for describing ways in which
a sense of civic duty can be created among individuals in relation to society as a
whole. A sense of community and basic, unchallengeable rules are established.
The application of the theory is evident in the functions and responsibilities
of three main organs of government:
1. the Executive,
2. the Legislative, and
3. the Judiciary.
Adherence to the theory, for example, compels the executive arm of the government
to ensure the laws are implemented and to maintain law and order with the help
of police. The legislature makes the laws and carries out investigations on issues
of public interest. The judiciary interprets the constitution (where it exists) and
arbitrates and settles conflicts in the society, protecting the rights of individuals.
The theory has been criticised on several grounds. First, the concept of
absolutism advanced by Hobbes is considered vague and inapplicable in a
dynamic society. Second, the idea of a sovereign having absolute authority is
against the rule of law.
References
Arnold, N. Scott, 2009, Imposing Values: An Essay on Liberalism and Regulation,
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Atack, Ian, 2012, Non-violence in Political Theory, Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University
Press.
Auyero, J. and Moran, T.P, 2007, ‘The Dynamics of Collective Violence: Dissecting Food
Riots in Contemporary Argentina’, Social Forces, Vol. 85, No. 3, pp. 1341–1367.
(https://www.jstor.org/stable/4494976). 27 October 2021.
Bell, P. and Cleaver, H, 1982, ‘Marx’s crisis theory as a theory of class struggle’, Research
in Political Economy, Vol. 5, pp. 189–261.
Bevel, James L.; Crowe, Larry F. and Stearns, Scott, 2016, ‘The HistoryMakers video oral
history with Reverend James Bevel’, Chicago, IL: The HistoryMakers.
Bottomore, Tom, 1993, Elite and Society, London, UK: Routledge.
Breuer, Anita; Landman, Todd and Farquhar, Dorothea, 2015, ‘Social Media and Protest
Mobilization: Evidence from the Tunisian Revolution’, Democratization, Vol. 22,
No. 4, pp. 764–792.
Cady, Duane, 2010, From Warism to Pacifism: A Moral Continuum, 2nd edition,
Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
Castiglione, D., 2015, ‘Introduction: the Logic of Social Cooperation for Mutual
Advantage: The Democratic Contract’, Political Studies Review, Vol. 13, No. 2,
pp. 161–175.
Cheng, C., 2018, Extralegal Groups in Post-conflict Liberia: How Trade Makes the State,
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
240
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Claassen, Rutger, 2011, ‘The Conservative Challenge to Liberalism’, Critical Review of
International Social and Political Philosophy, Vol. 14, No. 4, pp. 465–485.
Curti, G.H., 2008, ‘From a Wall of Bodies to a Body of Walls: Politics of Affect, Politics
of Memory, Politics of War’, Emotion, Space and Society, Vol. 1, No. 2, 106–118.
Dahrendorf, Ralf, 1990, Reflections on the Revolution in Europe, London: Chatto
& Windus.
Diaz-Cayeros, Alberto; Magaloni, Beatriz; Matanock, Aila and Romero, Vidal, 2011,
‘Living in Fear: Mapping the Social Embeddedness of Drug Gangs and Violence
in Mexico’, SSRN Electronic Journal. (10.2139/ssrn.1963836). 27 October 2021.
Dienstag, Joshua Foa, 1996, “Between History and Nature: Social Contract Theory in
Locke and the Founders’, Journal of Politics, Vol. 58, pp. 985–1009.
Donelson, Raff, 2017, ‘Blacks, Cops, and the State of Nature’, Ohio State Journal of
Criminal Law, Vol. 15, No. 1, pp. 183–192.
Dudouet, Véronique, 2015, Civil Resistance and Conflict Transformation: Transitions from
Armed to Non-violent Struggle, London, UK: Routledge.
Edwards, Bob and McCarthy, John D., 2004, The Blackwell Companion to Social
Movements, London, UK: Blackwell Publishing.
Eltantawy, Nahed and Wiest, Julie B., 2011, ‘The Arab Spring| Social Media in the
Egyptian Revolution: Reconsidering Resource Mobilization Theory’, International
Journal of Communication, Vol. 5, p. 18.
Gilens, Martin and Page, Benjamin I., 2014, ‘Testing Theories of American Politics:
Elites, Interest Groups, and Average Citizens’, Perspectives on Politics, Vol. 12,
No. 3, pp. 564–581.
Guriev, Sergey and Sonin, Konstantin, 2009, ‘Dictators and Oligarchs: A Dynamic
Theory of Contested Property Rights’, Journal of Public Economics, Vol. 93,
No. 1–2, pp. 1–13.
Gursoy, D. and Kendall, K. W., 2006, ‘Hosting mega events: Modeling locals’
support’, Annals of Tourism Research, Vol. 33, No. 3, pp. 603–623. (doi:10.1016/j.
annals.2006.01.005). 27 October 2021.
Heath, R.L.; Johansen, W. and Saffer, A.J., 2018, ‘Value-Added Theory’, in R.L. Heath
and W. Johansen, eds., The International Encyclopedia of Strategic Communication.
(https://doi.org/10.1002/9781119010722.iesc0197). 27 October 2021.
Hobbes, Thomas, 1994, Leviathan: With Selected Variants from the Latin Edition of 1668,
edited by Edwin Curley, Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.
Holmes, Robert, 2013. The Ethics of Nonviolence: Essays by Robert L. Holmes, edited by
P. Cicovacki, New York, NY: Bloomsbury.
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (IEP), 2019, ‘Pacifism’. (https://www.iep.utm.edu/
pacifism/). 23 October 2021.
Jenkins, J. Craig, 1982, ‘Resource Mobilization Theory and the Movements of the 1960s’,
paper presented at 77th Annual Meeting of the American Sociological Association,
San Francisco, California.
Jenkins, J. Craig, 1983, ‘Resource Mobilization Theory and the Study of Social Movements’,
Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 9, pp. 527–553. (https://www.annualreviews.org/
doi/pdf/10.1146/annurev.so.09.080183.002523). 22 October 2021.
Doctoral Scholars: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War
241
Kelly, John, 2011, ‘Theories of Collective Action and Union Power’, in G.G. Hurd
and A. Wilkinson, eds., The International Handbook of Labour Unions: Responses to
Neo-Liberalism, Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
Knol, Maaike, 2011, ‘Constructivism and post-constructivism: The methodological
implications of employing a post-constructivist research approach’, trial lecture
(as part of the fulfilments for a PhD degree). (https://munin.uit.no/bitstream/
handle/10037/4106/article.pdf?sequence=4&isAllowed=y ). 23 October 2021.
Kreckel, R., 1980, ‘UNEQUAL OPPORTUNITY STRUCTURE AND LABOUR
MARKET SEGMENTATION’, Sociology, Vol. 14, No. 4, pp. 525–550. (http://
www.jstor.org/stable/42852233). 27 October 2021.
Locher, David A., 2002, Collective Behavior, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Magaloni, Beatriz, 2006, Voting for Autocracy: The Politics of Party Hegemony and its
Demise, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Magaloni, Beatriz, 2008, ‘Credible Power-Sharing and the Longevity of Authoritarian
Rule’, Comparative Political Studies, Vol. 41, No. 4–5, pp. 715–741.
Magaloni, Beatriz, 2010, ‘The Game of Electoral Fraud and the Ousting of Authoritarian
Rule’, American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 54, No. 3, pp. 751–765.
Martin, Brian, 2015, ‘The Dynamics of Nonviolence Knowledge’, Mobilization, Vol. 21,
No. 4, pp. 533–545.
Marx, Gary, 2012, ‘Looking at Smelser’s Theory of Collective Behaviour After Almost
50 Years: A Review and Appreciation’, The American Sociologist, Vol. 43, No. 2,
pp. 135–152.
May, Todd, 2015, Nonviolent Resistance: A Philosophical Introduction, Cambridge,
UK: Polity Books.
McCarthy, John D. and Zald, Mayer N., 1973, The Trend of Social Movements in America:
Professionalization and Resource Mobilization, Morristown, NJ: General Learning
Corporation.
McCarthy, John D. and Zald, Mayer N., 1977, ‘Resource Mobilization and Social
Movements: A Partial Theory’, The American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 82, No. 6,
pp. 1212–1241.
Merton, Robert, 1968, Social Theory and Social Structure, New York, NY: The Free Press.
Müller, Martin, 2015, ‘Assemblages and Actor-networks: Rethinking Socio-material
Power, Politics and Space’, Geography Compass, Vol. 9, No. 1, pp. 27–41. (https://
doi.org/10.1111/gec3.12192). 27 October 2021.
Neu, Michael, 2011, ‘Why There Is No Such Thing as Just War Pacifism and Why
Just War Theorists and Pacifists Can Talk Nonetheless’, Social Theory and Practice,
Vol. 37, No. 3, pp. 413–434.
Norman, Richard, 1998. ‘The Case for Pacifism’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, Vol. 5,
No. 2, pp. 197–210.
Ogburn, William F. and Nimkoff, Meyer F., 1940/1947, A Handbook of Sociology,
London, UK: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Company.
Parsons, T., 1951, The Social System, New York, NY: The Free Press.
Robbins, Keith, 1976, The Abolition of War: the ‘Peace Movement’ in Britain, 1914–1919,
Cardiff: University of Wales Press.
242
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Rosenthal, J.H., 1991, Righteous Realists, Political Realism, Responsible Power, and American
Culture in the Nuclear Age, Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1998, The Social Contract, translated by J.J. Tozer and D.
Matravers, Chatham, Kent, UK: Wordsworth Editions Ltd.
Sahoo, Ajaya Kumar; Sahoo, Sadanand and Nagaraju, G., eds., Trends in Sociology:
Education, Development, and Diaspora, New Delhi, India: Abhijeet Publisher.
Sorel, Michael and Schwartz, Michael, 1989, ‘The Structure of Power in America: The
Corporate Elite As a Ruling Class’, Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 18, No. 2, p. 181.
Thompson, Martyn P., 2003, ‘Locke’s Contract in Context’, in D. Boucher and P. Kelly,
eds., The Social Contract from Hobbes to Rawls, London, UK: Routledge.
Walsh, Edward J., 1981, ‘Resource Mobilization and Citizen Protest in Communities
around Three Mile Island’, Social Problems, Vol. 29, pp. 1–21.
Wani, I A.; Bhat, M.A.; Ahmad, T. and Ahrar, A., 2012, ‘Evaluation of social stratification
in Kashmir Valley in the light of classical sociological theory’, International Journal
of Advanced Research, Vol. 2, No. 1, pp.1–18.
Yurdusev, Ahmet Nuri, 2006, ‘Thomas Hobbes and International Relations: From
Realism to Rationalism’, Australian Journal of International Affairs, Vol. 60, No. 2,
pp. 305–321.
II
APPLICATIONS
OF A SAMPLE OF THEORIES
9
Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
Abdul Karim Bangura
This chapter is about how Mandelaism – generally defined as the philosophy
of the leadership style of Madiba Tatamkhulu Rolihlahla Nelson Mandela –
can be employed to investigate leadership in Africa. As Tokyo Sexwale puts it,
‘Mandelaism [is] the spirit of selflessness, sacrifice, people’s soldier, prisoner,
president, freedom fighter, philanthropist, dedicated democrat, scholar, lawyer,
revolutionary, visionary, reconciler, unifier, nationalist and internationalist’
(News24 2012). The subject is important because while the leadership styles
of a small number of African leaders have been characterised as good, the
majority have been portrayed as employing modes of mismanagement and gross
inhumanity, of irresponsibility and official pillaging, alongside experimentation,
disappointment, vacillation, and ongoing confrontation. In addition, instances
of inefficient management and lack of responsiveness are the making of widely
accepted notions of political behaviour. In each of these styles, political processes
have taken definite shapes and possessed recognisable dynamics.
An important question that should be addressed here then is this: What is
leadership? As Ercüment Yildirim recounts, over the course of history, thousands
of denotations have been proffered for the concept and numerous studies have
been done on the subject of ‘leadership.’ In the past century alone, more than 400
definitions have been suggested for the concept and about 5,000 studies have been
conducted. From a Western historical perspective, Yildirim notes that prominent
early Greek philosophers talked about the concept of ‘leadership’ in terms of how
government was passed down to others via election or by despotism. He adds that
in his effort to systematise the governing logic, Socrates asserted that the most
important attribute a leader should have is ‘the ability to distinguish the good
from the bad and to know what to do or not to do’ (Socrates quoted by Yildirim
2016:712). Yildirim also mentions that Plato, a student of Socrates who in turn
246
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
taught Aristotle, stated that the fundamental requirement for becoming a leader
is to be a philosopher. As Plato put it, ‘Either philosophers should be kings or
kings should be philosophers’ (Plato quoted by Yildirim 2016:712). In addition,
Yildirim tells us that Plato described the high moral standards a philosopher
possesses which would make him suitable to be a king and why it is imperative for
a king to possess the same high moral standards as a philosopher (Yildirim 2016).
As will be seen later, these notions and more are evident in the Ancient Kemetian/
Egyptian conceptualisation of ‘leadership.’ It is now well known that these early
Greek philosophers learned from Ancient Kemetian philosophers; their ideas on
the subject must have been influenced by the Kemetians.
In my chapter on the fractal complexity in Mandela’s autobiography Long Walk
to Freedom: The Autobiography of Nelson Mandela (1994), I discuss the discovery
that the framing of his experience is reminiscent of African ways: i.e. despite the
challenges and hardship he encountered, his thought processes did not at any
time become chaotic as one would have anticipated. This is quite remarkable
because most of the book was written secretly while Mandela was imprisoned for
27 years on Robben Island by South Africa’s apartheid government. The book
also discloses the story of a generous spirit that never capitulated under extremely
trying circumstances. The most revealing aspect of the book is Mandela’s
ambivalence toward his lifetime of devotion to public service (Bangura 2012).
More specifically, a total of 7,178 topic entries were teased out of Mandela’s
text. Of these, I categorise 3,017, or 42 per cent, as presuppositions of order (i.e.
presuppositions that suggest a condition or place of logical or comprehensible
arrangement among the separate elements of a group), and 4,161, or 58 per cent,
as presuppositions of disorder (i.e. presuppositions that suggest a condition or
place of confusion, mess, disturbance, disarray, or muddle). The first two parts of
the book dealing with Mandela’s life as a youth in Qunu and Mqhekezweni and
his excitement and fear about going to Johannesburg entail more presuppositions
of order than those of disorder, while the other nine parts of the book have more
presuppositions of disorder than those of order. Even the part of the book dealing
with his freedom has more presuppositions of disorder than those of order. As
Mandela himself realised immediately after his release from prison, he had an
‘inkling that things might not go as calmly as [he] had imagined’ (Mandela
1994:562; Bangura 2012).
The mean for the order category is about 274 presuppositions, with a standard
deviation of approximately 94 presuppositions; the mean for the disorder category
is about 378 presuppositions, with a standard deviation of approximately 130
propositions. The range for the order category is 283 presuppositions and that for
the disorder category is 437 presuppositions. This means that there are more, albeit
not statistically significant, topic entries for presuppositions of disorder than there
are of those for order. Nonetheless, there are significant variations within and
between the presupposition categories in terms of topic entries (Bangura 2012).
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
247
In addition, I illustrate the fractal dimension of the two-dimensionality of the
variable. Mandela’s text begins with complete order, moves downward, and then
vacillates between disorder and order. The binary logistic statistics reveal that the
relationship between the two dimensions is not statistically significant at the 0.05
level. In sum, Mandela’s text is typically a periodic fractal (possessing an ordered
structure that is infinitely periodic in the three spatial dimensions or 3D – i.e.
breadth, height, and width), rather than stretching all the way to pure disorder
(Bangura 2012).
Based on the preceding results, I argue that it is not farfetched to designate
Mandela as a khęperu in Ancient Egyptian/Hieroglyphics or Kubadilisha in
Kiswahili or Reformist in English. For Ancient Egyptians, the word khęperu
described those who sought change in form, manifestation, shape, similitude,
or image. These types of leaders are unlike the åtenu in Ancient Egyptian/
Hieroglyphics or Mapinduzi in Kiswahili or Revolutionary in English, and
the åtenu m’ţen in Ancient Egyptian/Hieroglyphics or Mapinduzi ya Malazi in
Kiswahili or Revolutionary-Accommodationist in English. The term åtenu was
employed by Ancient Egyptians to describe revolutionaries, rebels, or fiends who
wanted radical change. Such people were perceived as Mesti, the divine parents of
the God of Sun or Day Rā; Mesu, the gods who begat their own fathers or divine
beings; and Mesut, children of God Osiris or divine beings. The concept of åtenu
m’ţen was employed by Ancient Egyptians to refer to those who wanted change
but would accept things, listen, obey or be content with things as long as their
burdens were assuaged (for the Ancient Egyptian translations of these concepts,
see Budge 1978; Bangura 2012).
In his speech titled, ‘We Are Committed to Building a Single Nation in Our
Country’, prepared for and delivered at a rally in Durban, South Africa, on
February 25, 1990, Mandela stated that the past is a rich resource upon which
we can draw in order to make decisions for the future, but it does not dictate
our choices. He urged that we look back at the past and select what is good, and
leave behind what is bad. The issue of chiefship, he noted, was one such question.
According to him, not only in (the then) Natal province but throughout South
Africa there were chiefs who had been good and honest leaders, who had piloted
their people through the dark days of the oppression of Blacks with great skill;
these were the chiefs who had looked after the interests of their people and who
enjoyed the support of their people and, thus, should be saluted. Nonetheless,
as he pointed out, there were many bad chiefs who had profited from apartheid
and who had increased the burden of their people. These chiefs, he said, must be
denounced (Hord & Lee 1995:110; Bangura 2012).
I note that on the issue of apartheid, Mandela said it was the real enemy of
the people, as a great deal of energy had been wasted by people in violent actions
across the towns and villages to fight the evil system. He added that Blacks had
already waited for their freedom for far too long and, therefore, could no longer
248
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
wait. He called upon Indians, coloureds, Africans, and freedom-loving whites
to join forces in order to give apartheid its final blow. He then urged that in the
process, people must develop an active democracy with democratic structures
which would serve people in every school, township, village, factory, and farm
(Hord & Lee 1995:114 –115; Bangura 2012).
Mandela iterated his long-held position that the African National Congress
(ANC) would offer a home to all who ascribed to the principles of a free,
democratic, nonracial, and united South Africa. He declared that the ANC was
committed to building a single nation, one that would include Blacks and whites,
Zulus and Afrikaners, and speakers of every other language. He then quoted
ANC president-general Chief Albert Luthuli who said that ‘I personally believe
that here in South Africa, with all of our diversities of colour and race, we will
show the world a new pattern for democracy … I think that there is a challenge
to us in South Africa, to set a new example for the world’ (Hord & Lee 1995:111;
Bangura 2012).
What is evident from the text is that Mandela seemed to have a strong belief
in the concept of ubuntu. As I discuss it in my essay titled ‘Ubuntugogy: An
African Educational Paradigm That Transcends Pedagogy, Andragogy, Ergonagy,
and ‘Heutagogy’’ (Bangura 2005) and my book titled African Peace Paradigms
(Bangura 2008), ubuntu is a word from the southern African Nguni language
family (IsiNdebele, IsiSwati/Swazi, IsiXhosa, and IsiZulu), meaning humanity or
fellow feeling; kindness. By drawing from many works that have dealt with the
concept of ubuntu and similar African thoughts on communalism, I deduced that
ubuntu serves as the spiritual foundation of African societies. It is a unifying vision
or worldview enshrined in the maxim umuntu ngumuntu ngabantu: i.e., ‘a person
is a person through other persons.’ This traditional African aphorism articulates
a basic respect and compassion for others. It can be interpreted as both a factual
description and a rule of conduct or social ethic. It both describes the human
being as ‘beingwithothers’ and prescribes what that should be (Bangura 2012).
A profitable question that emerges here then is the following: What are the
attributes and principles of Mandela’s leadership style? A careful examination of
the literature on these aspects makes it possible to delineate five attributes and six
principles of Mandelaism which can serve as a theoretical framework to analyse
the leadership styles of other African leaders and to determine the presence or
absence of each aspect. These aspects are discussed sequentially in the next two
sections for the sake of lucidity. But before doing this, makes sense to end this
section with a discussion of the theoretical framework.
As can be seen in Figure 9.1, Mandelaism is postulated to have five attributes:
• Attribute 1, render services in the name of democracy and human rights,
•
Attribute 2, to dissent against institutionalised racism (in other African
countries, it would be ethnicism) and bigoted governance,
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
•
•
•
249
Attribute 3, to lead by example,
Attribute 4, to engage in erudition as a lifelong journey; and
Attribute 5, to employ forgiveness and reconciliation as a conflict resolution
doctrine.
These attributes led him to these principles:
•
•
•
•
•
•
anticipate – regard as probable; expect or predict;
challenge – dispute the truth or validity of certain claims and policies;
interpret – explain the meaning of information, words, or actions;
decide – come to a resolution in the mind as a result of consideration;
align – bring together in agreement or alliance; and
learn – gain or acquire knowledge of something by study and experience.
The continuous block process of Figure 9.1 indicates a progression or sequential
steps in the process. This theoretical framework is conceptual in nature in that,
as Chava Frankfort-Nachmias and David Nachmias point out, in a conceptual
framework, which constitutes ‘the third level of theory, descriptive categories are
systematically placed in a broad structure of explicit propositions, statements
of relationships between two or more empirical properties, to be accepted or
rejected’ (Frankfort-Nachmias & Nachmias 1996:38).
Figure 9.1: Theoretical Framework of Mandelaism
Source: Self-generated by author
Attributes of Mandelaism
As stated earlier, Mandela’s leadership philosophy encompasses five attributes.
These attributes have been discerned and discussed by several authors. The first
attribute involves evincing services in honour of democracy and human rights.
250
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
This feature reflects the physical properties and phenomenon of Mandela’s
wisdom which homogenised in his leadership and reverberated well in his style of
governance which put the needs of the masses first (Nagra 2018).
The second attribute concerns opposition against racism (in other African
countries, it would be ethnicism) and against a discriminatory manner of governing
established in practice or custom. This is evident in Mandela’s persistent struggle
against the apartheid system’s denial of South African Blacks political and social
equality with whites. The struggle lasted for more than 40 years, with 27 years of
incarceration of which 18 were spent at the notorious prison on Robben Island
(Nagra 2018).
The third attribute is about leading by example. This element is manifest
in the way Mandela balanced his approach to leadership towards life itself. He
understood that he had to lead by example in order for the masses to adhere to
his exhortations. This is the reason he shifted his stance from the earlier strategy
of an armed struggle to a non-violent one based on the belief that the chances
of a peaceful resolution to the South African conflict would be jeopardised by
opportunists and by rage. He was so determined to rid the country of the apartheid
system that when he was offered personal freedom by the then South African
president Pieter Willem Botha in exchange for his repudiation of resistance to
apartheid rule, Mandela rebuked Botha by stating ‘What freedom am I being
offered while the organisation of people remains banned?’ (Nagra 2018:2). Thus,
instead of sacrificing his commitment to birthing a racially equal South Africa
for his personal freedom, Mandela chose to serve his full imprisonment, thereby
sending a clear message to the masses that it was their freedom that meant the
most to him (Nagra 2018).
The fourth attribute deals with learning as a lifelong peregrination. Mandela
displayed this feature many times during his leadership. An example of this
is when he decided to endorse privatisation after meeting with the leaders of
China and Vietnam in order to revive South Africa’s oscillating economy. The
decision was a shift from his strong endorsement of the policy of nationalisation
which, as Mandela had put it, was ‘inconceivable’ to alter. Throughout his life
and as a leader of ANC during the 1990s, he had advocated anti-privatisation
economic policies. Thus, to champion a pro-privatisation policy meant that he
was to face a blowback from the Black masses. But after careful study of the
economic shortcomings of South Africa and coming to grips with the reality that
it required a conscious economic revamp, he opted for privatisation rather than
nationalisation (Nagra 2018).
The fifth and final attribute relates to employing forgiveness and reconciliation
as a conflict resolution doctrine. Mandela believed that in order to avoid
undermining the social advancement of South Africa, the ghastly deeds of the
past must be forgiven. His magnanimity was demonstrated during a 1998 visit
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
251
to South Africa by then President Bill Clinton of the United States. Showing
Clinton the cramped space at the prison on Robben Island where he had endured
years of hard labour and physical tyranny, Mandela told Clinton that he felt no
rage or a need for vengeance. To feel that way, he asserted, would have placed him
‘in a prison of his own making’ (Nagra 2018). He did add, however, that while
the horrendous deeds of the past ‘must be forgiven’, they must ‘not be forgotten’
and ‘need to be discussed and analysed’. This is also the position of George Bizos,
who was Mandela’s personal lawyer, who stated that the atrocities of the apartheid
regime are ‘still eating away at me’ (Sampson 1994:1).
Mandela’s conflict resolution doctrine was anchored by the belief that
inclusivity is imperative for the development and sustainability of a progressive
South African society. Having been treated as insignificant and peripheral, and
designated as a racially inferior Black person by the apartheid system, Mandela
learned that compartmentalising humanity so that people are given and refused
sets of circumstances that make it possible for them to do something, as well as
gain dignity based on the colour and texture of their skin, is equivalent to an insult
to human self-worth. Accordingly, his vision of inclusiveness made it possible for
him to discover propitiating ways to straddle the political and social divisions that
existed between white and Black South Africans, despite the hideous violence
that had been meted out to Blacks by whites (Nagra 2018) officially for almost
five decades (from 1948 to 1991).
Having observed that ‘sports has the power to unite people in a way little
else does’, Mandela supported the South African Olympics team for the 1992
games, even though the team was composed of 95 white and only eight Black
athletes. His support was based on the conviction that for the country to move
forward, it must ‘start somewhere.’ Likewise, in 1994, when he was delivering
his inaugural address as the first all-inclusive democratically elected president of
South Africa, he was quite aware that the more than one billion people across the
globe watching and listening to him were interested not only in what he had to
say but also how to gauge his leadership. True to his conflict resolution doctrine,
Mandela made a clarion call for a ‘rainbow coalition’ and for national and social
unity that would foster a common vision for South Africa, emphasising the fact
that no one group ‘can achieve anything alone’ and that in order to ‘birth a new
world,’ all of the groups ‘must act together’ (Nagra 2018).
Furthermore, Mandela’s conflict resolution doctrine allowed him to be
persistent and magnanimous when he engaged in peaceful negotiations, in
spite of past hostilities toward him and other Black South Africans. It made it
possible for him to gain freedom for and forge unity among Blacks, coloureds,
Indians and whites underpinned by equal rights guaranteed by the constitution
(Babjee 2013).
252
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Even in the latter years of Mandela’s life, after stepping down from the South
African presidency, it was his conflict resolution doctrine that established him as
a paragon of human rights, peacemaking and reconciliation, and social justice
across the globe. It is this recognition that propelled the United Nations General
Assembly in 2009 to proclaim July 18 as Nelson Mandela International Day
and echo the call by the Nelson Mandela Foundation to devote 67 minutes to
assisting others on that day every year (Munusamy 2014). Ranjeni Munusamy
describes the United Nations’ pledge comprehensively as follows:
The UN resolution, adopted in 2009, recognises Mandela’s values and dedication
to the service of humanity in the fields of conflict resolution, race relations, the
promotion and protection of human rights, reconciliation, gender equality and
the rights of children and other vulnerable groups, as well as the upliftment of
poor and underdeveloped communities. It acknowledges his contribution to the
struggle for democracy internationally and the promotion of a culture of peace
throughout the world (Munusamy 2014:1).
Paul Schoemaker (2013) alludes to three decisions in which the foregoing
attributes were manifested. The first decision pertains to Mandela turning down
Botha’s offer of conditional amnesty in 1985. That year, in a nationally broadcasted
speech, Botha proposed to Mandela personal freedom in exchange of repudiating
violent and other unlawful actions. While Mandela must have very much wanted
his freedom after many years of hard labour and being confined in an eight-byeight feet cell, he did not succumb to Botha’s ruse. Putting his principles, his
leadership, and the ANC’s prolonged struggle first, Mandela responded to Botha’s
duplicitous proposition as follows: ‘What freedom am I being offered while the
organization of the people remains banned?...What freedom am I being offered
if I must ask permission to live in an urban area?...Only free men can negotiate.
Prisoners cannot enter into contracts’ (Schoemaker 2013:2).
Prepared to serve the rest of his life sentence in a gloomy and chilly prison cell
instead of selling out his principles and the cause of the Black masses, Mandela
spurned Botha’s deal. This judicious decision was so cogent that it boosted
Mandela’s position within the ANC and beyond and highlighted his fidelity to
self-sacrifice (Schoemaker 2013).
The second decision relates to Mandela finding the means to make peace in
the aftermath of the murder of the popular Black leader Chris Hani by a rightwing white extremist in 1993. Hani’s murderer pointed out in a line-up by a
white Afrikaner woman. The cold-blooded murder sparked sweeping rage and
precipitated enormous protest marches. With many Blacks calling for vengeance,
the climate was suitable for plunder, ferocity and pandemonium. But, Mandela,
fresh out of prison, performed very well in response to the tense situation by
calling for tranquillity (Schoemaker 2013). Part of his statement reads as follows:
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
253
Tonight, I am reaching out to every single South African, black and white,
from the very depths of my being. A white man, full of prejudice and hate, came
to our country and committed a deed so foul that our whole nation now teeters
on the brink of disaster. A white woman, of Afrikaner origin, risked her life so
that we may know and bring to justice, this assassin. The cold-blooded murder of
Chris Hani has sent shock waves throughout the country and the world…Now
is the time for all South Africans to stand together against those who, from any
quarter, wish to destroy what Chris Hani gave his life for – the freedom of all of
us (Schoemaker 2013:3).
The third decision concerns Mandela making it very clear very early in his
presidency in 1994 that he would not run for the presidency of South Africa
for a second term as allowed by the constitution. This decision was exceptional
in a world where leaders seek longevity in office. Cognisant of the fact that
approximately a billion people would be watching and listening to his speech
across the globe, he vowed that his desire was the promotion of democracy and
to represent everyone in South Africa, no matter the colour of his/her skin. What
follows is a portion of his speech inscribed in stone on Robben Island: ‘We have,
at last, achieved our political emancipation. We pledge ourselves to liberate all our
people from the continuing bondage of poverty, deprivation, suffering, gender
and other discriminations. Never, never and never again shall this beautiful land
experience the oppression of one by another…’ (Schoemaker 2013:3).
Indeed, as Schoemaker points out, Mandela’s outstanding accomplishment was
how he inspired concord among the races, absolution without oblivion, sharing
of power, and greater concentration on the future than the past. Undergirding his
leadership approach was his munificence toward former foes. The following are
just a few of the deeds that underscored Mandela’s magnanimous and peaceful
disposition:
1. Mandela visited Betsie Verwoerd, the widow of former South African Prime
Minister Hendrik Verwoerd, the designer of the apartheid machinery that put
Mandela in prison;
2. Mandela rejoiced when the South African rugby team, a symbol of Afrikaner
racism and power for many decades, won the world championship in 1995.
During the championship match, he gratifyingly donned the team’s shirt and
gestured in support of the team – a clear signal that his vision and mission
for South Africa were for the emergence of a lasting rainbow nation. Thus,
Schoemaker’s concluding statement is quite fitting when he says that Mandela’s
type of ‘leadership is as precious as it is rare’ (Schoemaker 2013).
The preceding attributes are important for at least a couple of reasons,
following Marria Qibtia Sikandar Nagra (2018). To begin with, the attributes
reflect a longing to arouse the masses to the egregiousness of an existing situation
254
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
that emerges from the consequence of political and social elements. Thus, good
leadership will evoke the reawakening of the cognitive contexts and redirection
of the psychological attitudes, beliefs or feelings of the masses. With a desire to
stimulate lasting change, good leadership will transcend the game of gaining the
support of the masses by deriding the opposition. Instead, good leadership would
establish its trustworthiness by attesting and working to meet the necessities of
the masses as early as possible (Nagra 2018).
Next, considering the current calamities in our world, which range from
the refugee cataclysm to undisguised exhibitions of violence, Mandela’s good
leadership attributes are much needed. He provided a framework for leaders
across the globe to emulate by exhibiting resoluteness during very difficult times,
by exercising absolution, and by invigorating the politics of rapprochement
(Nagra 2018).
Principles of Mandelaism
As mentioned, six principles undergird Mandela’s leadership philosophy. These
principles are very well explicated by Paul J.H. Schoemaker and Steven Krupp
(2014). Principle one is that Mandela anticipated what was to come. With the
conviction that the apartheid system would not last into the future, Mandela
focused on what was to follow. That is the reason he rebuffed Botha’s conditional
offer of freedom. Mandela’s intuition proved to be correct; as the outside world’s
continued rejection of the apartheid system allied with pressure from local
business leaders and progressive young whites led to changes in South Africa
(Schoemaker & Krupp 2014).
Principle two is that Mandela challenged the status quo. His willingness to give
up his life for his principles made him prominent among his fellow prisoners and
the guards. He challenged his incarcerators, rejecting the ways things were. His
presence on Robben Island exposed the faces of the architects of apartheid to the
world. He challenged the system that denied him his freedom through his words,
actions, and symbolism (Schoemaker & Krupp 2014).
These developments propelled Frederik Willem de Klerk, Botha’s successor as
president of South Africa, to call for democratic elections. Mandela and De Klerk
were awarded the Nobel Peace Prize ‘for their work for the peaceful termination of
the apartheid regime, and for laying the foundations for a new democratic South
Africa’ (Schoemaker & Krupp 2014: 2). In 1994, Mandela won the presidential
election and a peaceful transfer of power from white-minority to Black-majority
rule occurred.
Principle three is that Mandela interpreted events and their consequences.
Western sanctions against Zimbabwe following President Robert Gabriel Mugabe’s
land reform policy, which returned lands stolen by whites back to their Black
owners, crippled that country’s economy. Mandela decided not to follow Mugabe’s
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
255
footsteps on the issue. Instead, as Schoemaker and Krupp point out, Mandela
decided to pursue his forgiveness-without-forgetting approach. They quote
Mandela as saying the following: ‘We have to surprise [the white minority] with
restraints and generosity’ (Mandela quoted by Schoemaker & Krupp 2014:3).
The authors add that in the spirit of forgiveness-without-forgetting, Mandela
even invited his former prison guards to his presidential swearing-in ceremony
(Schoemaker & Krupp 2014). (It behooves me to add here that the land issue in
South Africa remains a powder keg that is bound to explode at any time.)
Principle four is that Mandela decided to take on matters from which many
other leaders would have shied away. A case in point is that of the assassination
of Chris Hani by a white racist that precipitated widespread riots against the De
Klerk administration. Fresh out of prison, Mandela decided to take on the issue
and called for peace when many Blacks were insisting on vengeance (Schoemaker
& Krupp 2014).
As referred to earlier, Mandela boldly decided to use sport as a healing tool.
When the ban on South Africa’s participation in the Olympics Games was lifted
in 1992, Mandela decided to let go his opposition to the decision, even though
the overwhelming majority of the country’s team comprised white athletes – only
eight Blacks were members of the 95 person delegation. As he said:
‘There is no doubt in my mind this is the correct decision. I would have liked [the
team] to be a reflection of our population, but there has to be a starting point’
(Mandela quoted by Schoemaker & Krupp 2014:3).
Principle five is that Mandela aligned his views to those of all racial groups in
South Africa. For him, Black supremacy would have been just as perverted as
white supremacy. To allow him the freedom to bridge the interests of the various
races and rally them toward peaceful coexistence, Mandela decided early in his
presidency that he had no intention of running for a second term as permitted
by the constitution. Buttressing his inaugural address with the African-centred
inclusive pronouns of our, us, and we to align a greatly segregated country around
a shared goal, Mandela said the following:
‘We understand it still that there is no easy road to freedom…none of us acting
alone can achieve success. We must therefore act together as a united people,
for national reconciliation, for nation building, for the birth of a new world’
(Mandela quoted by Schoemaker & Krupp 2014:4).
Principle six is that Mandela learned from the history of other nations. As noted
earlier, when Mandela was released from prison, he was confronted with the
very challenging issue of what to be done about the floundering South African
economy. Having been a socialist for most of his life and observing how monopoly
and free markets had exploited the masses, Mandela averred: ‘The nationalization
of the mines, banks and monopoly industries is the policy of the ANC, and a
256
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
change or modification of our views in this regard is inconceivable’ (Mandela
quoted by Schoemaker & Krupp 2014:4). But learning from what the Soviet
Union had endured through many decades of socialism, Mandela, after his visits
to China and Vietnam, stated the following to his biographer: ‘They changed my
view altogether’ (Mandela quoted by Schoemaker & Krupp 2014:4).
Based on the foregoing six principles, Schoemaker and Krupp conclude that
Mandela typified how a judicious leader calibrates policy and implementation
in the middle of complicated economic, legal, political and social forces without
imperilling strongly held principles. What all this says about Mandela’s leadership,
they add, is that leadership is more than just ‘motivating people and creating
political support for a strategy’; it is ‘also about maintaining broad support
through successive adjustments to the plan’ (Schoemaker & Krupp 2014:4).
A fruitful question that can be engendered here is this: What lessons and
qualities can discerned in Mandela’s leadership principles? Starting with the lessons,
Richard Stengel (2008) and Kevin Freiberg and Jackie Freiberg (2018) together
proffer 13. These are presented in the order they are discussed by these authors.
First, ‘Courage is not the absence of fear – it’s inspiring others to move beyond it’
(Stengel 2008:2). While on the campaign trail for the 1994 presidential election,
one of the engines of the small propeller plane in which Mandela was flying to go
address his Zulu supporters in the killing fields of the then Natal province gave
out 20 minutes away from landing. As some of the people in the plane became
alarmed, they noticed that Mandela was sitting quietly reading his newspaper.
The airport was made ready for an emergency landing and the pilot was able to
land the plane safely. Upon disembarkation, Mandela confessed that he was afraid
while the plane was in the sky but that as a leader, he could not let the others to
know about it, as that would have led to pandemonium. He also acknowledged
that he was afraid during his years underground and while on Robben Island but
that he put a brave front so that people didn’t know about his fear. Knowing that
his mien emboldened other people gave him the fortitude to conquer his fright
(Stengel 2008).
Second, ‘Lead from the front – but don’t leave your base behind’ (Stengel 2008:2).
Mandela’s cautiousness of Mandela was evident when he was operated on for an
enlarged prostate in 1985. For the first time in 21 years, he was separated from
his fellow inmates when he was sent away from the Robben Island prison. When
his friends raised objections, Mandela told them that some good might emerge
from the separation. The good was that he began negotiations with the apartheid
regime on his own. Mandela’s initiative did not sit well with the other leaders and
the rank and file of the ANC who had called for an armed struggle as the means
to end the apartheid regime. With his reputation at stake, he began the effort to
convince the ANC members that it was the right thing to do. With great deal of
patience, he was able to convince them that it was a prudent strategy. According
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
257
to Stengel, ‘For Mandela refusing to negotiate was about tactics, not principles.
Throughout his life, he…always made that distinction. His unwavering principle
– the overthrow of apartheid and the achievement of one man, one vote – was
immutable, but almost anything that helped him get to that goal he regarded as a
tactic. He [was] the most pragmatic of idealists’ (Stengel 2008:3).
Third, ‘Lead from the back – and let others believe they are in front’ (Stengel
2008:3). One thing Mandela cherished doing was to recall memories of his
childhood taking care of cattle. He recollected that during his childhood, the
Jongintaba – i.e. the king of his ethnic group, who raised Mandela – had a great
impact on him. When the Jongintaba conducted meetings at his court, the men
would sit in a circle; the king would say something only after everyone else had
had his say. The Jongintaba did not tell the men in the court what to do but
helped them reach a consensus. When Mandela held meetings in his home with
his ‘kitchen cabinet’, he used the same approach as the Jongintaba. Believing that
the stratagem of leadership is for one to allow himself/herself to be led as well,
Mandela was quoted as saying: ‘It is wise to persuade people to do things and
make them think that it was their own idea’ (Stengel 2008:3–4).
Fourth, ‘Know your enemy – and learn about his favourite sport’ (Stengel
2008:4). Early in the 1960s, Mandela started learning Afrikaans, the mother
tongue of the architects of the apartheid machinery so as to get a sense of their
philosophy. While his fellow ANC members poked fun at him for learning
the language, Mandela had no doubt that he would eventually have to fight
the Afrikaners, or bargain with them, since his fate and theirs were conjoined.
There were two advantages: (1) speaking the language of his oppressors allowed
Mandela to get a sense of their resilience and deficiencies, thereby developing
the appropriate strategies to deal with them; (2) it allowed him to intermix with
the enemy, as Botha and even the common prison guards admired Mandela’s
disposition to speak Afrikaans and knowledge of the history of the Afrikaners. In
order to contrast notes on players and teams, Mandela also sharpened his grasp
of rugby, a sport that is greatly adored by Afrikaners. Since he was trained in the
law, Mandela was able to assist the Afrikaner prison guards, who were ‘far less
educated than him and the most ruthless and brutal of the apartheid regime’s
characters’, with their legal problems. The guards were quite impressed that a
Black man was capable and inclined to assist them (Stengel 2008:4).
Fifth, ‘Keep your friends close – and your rivals even closer’ (Stengel 2008). Even
though Mandela did not trust many of the people he invited to dinner at his
house in Qunu, he still served them dinner, sought their opinions, complimented
them, and gave them presents. He employed his hidden charm on his competitors
as effectively as he did on his comrades. He would always keep within his circle
on Robben Island men he neither liked nor on whom he relied. One person
to whom Mandela became very close was Chris Hani, the chief of staff of the
258
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
ANC military wing who was believed to have been plotting against Mandela.
He extended his friendship and courtesy to rich industrialists, mining families,
prison guards, opponents, and others, even calling them on their birthdays.
In his first cabinet, Mandela even included leaders who had put him in prison
(Stengel 2008).
There were times when Mandela allowed himself to be charmed by other
people, but he also knew when to give up on some people. For instance, Mandela
at first developed an expeditious affinity with De Klerk; but after De Klerk
castigated him in public, Mandela distanced himself from him. As Stengel notes,
for Mandela, ‘embracing his rivals was a way of controlling them: they were
more dangerous on their own than within his circle of influence. He cherished
loyalty, but he was never obsessed by it. After all, he used to say, ‘people act in
their own interest.’ It was simply a fact of human nature, not a flaw or defect
(Stengel 2008:5).
Sixth, ‘Appearances matter – and remember to smile’ (Stengel 2008:5). During
his days as a poor law student in Johannesburg, with only one ‘threadbare suit’,
Mandela was taken to meet Walter Sisulu, who was at the time a youth leader of
the ANC and a real estate agent. While Mandela saw a Black role model in Sisulu
to emulate, Sisulu saw in Mandela the future of the ANC. As Stengel recalls,
Sisulu once told him that his aspiration was to make the ANC a mass movement
and then one day a ‘mass leader’ in the person of Mandela walked into his office.
Mandela’s aura came from him being ‘tall and handsome, an amateur boxer who
carried himself with the regal air of a chief ’s son…and a smile that was like the
sun coming out on a cloudy day’ (Stengel 2008:5). Stengel goes on to cite many
other examples when Mandela dressed appropriately for his position and carried
a big smile even when dealing with issues about which he was bitter, knowing
that a positive disposition is the only way to convert the enemies of the masses to
the cause of equality and harmony.
Seventh, ‘Nothing is black or white’ (Stengel 2008:6). For Mandela, life could
not be easily adjudged as ‘either/or’. Resolutions to any issue can be intricate and
there always exist contesting elements. Consequently, he was not uneasy with
conflict. Life as a Black man under the apartheid regime has presented agonising
ethical options every day. Mandela became a practical politician who perceived
the world as immensely modulated (Stengel 2008). By way of example, Stengel
states the following:
As a statesman, Mandela was uncommonly loyal to Muammar Gaddafi and
Fidel Castro. They had helped the ANC when the U.S. still branded Mandela
as a terrorist. When I asked him about Gaddafi and Castro, he suggested that
Americans tend to see things in black and white, and he would upbraid me for
my lack of nuance. Every problem has many causes. While he was indisputably
and clearly against apartheid, the causes of apartheid were complex. They
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
259
were historical, sociological and psychological. Mandela’s calculus was always,
‘What is the end that I seek, and what is the most practical way to get there?’
(Stengel 2008:6).
Eighth, ‘Quitting is leading too’ (Stengel 2008:7). In 1993, Mandela went on
South African national television and suggested that the country’s minimum
voting age be lowered from 18 to 14, as is the case in Cuba, Indonesia, Iran,
Nicaragua, and North Korea. But, watching how the opposition to his idea
continued to grow, instead of brood, Mandela accepted the reality and dropped
the idea with great modesty. As mentioned earlier, Mandela chose not to run
for the South African presidency a second term as permitted by the country’s
constitution (Stengel 2008).
Ninth, ‘Passion produces perseverance’ (Freiberg & Freiberg 2018:2). Mandela
found the policies of South Africa’s white minority regime to be racist and
inhumane. This belief moved him to become passionate about and determined
to change the status quo in that country. His decision to challenge the apartheid
government and its policies prompted the regime to imprison him for 27 years.
He was only able to vote for the first time in South Africa when he came out of
prison to run for the presidency of the country, which he won, making him the
country’s first Black president. He encountered monumental challenges in his
path toward change. Because of these challenges, Mandela taught us that when a
person takes on a cause in which s/he strongly believes, his/her energy increases
and s/he will attract like-minded people who share the same belief (Freiberg &
Freiberg 2018).
Tenth, ‘Expect change to be messy’ (Freiberg & Freiberg 2018:2). Mandela
could have lived a quite comfortable life as a partner with Oliver Tambo in the
only law firm run by Blacks in South Africa. Complaints from antagonised clients
who wanted recompense from the actions of the apartheid government that
discriminated against Black people economically, legally and politically deluged
the law firm. The lesson here, according to Freiberg and Freiberg, is that ‘Solving
a problem that really matters, change that is truly worthwhile is hard to come
by. It requires nerve to push through the trials and ultimately make your vision a
reality. This is why many change efforts that fail can be traced back to a “failure
of nerve”’ (Freiberg & Freiberg 2018:3).
Eleventh, ‘Forgiveness is key to focusing forward’ (Freiberg & Freiberg 2018:3).
When they were both presidents of their respective countries, Mandela and Bill
Clinton had a conversation during which Clinton asked about what he and his
family has observed on television when Mandela came out of his prison cell:
i.e. Mandela’s facial expression which first exhibited ‘anger and hatred’ and then
suddenly the anger disappeared (Freiberg & Freiberg 2018). Mandela responded
as follows:
260
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
I’m surprised that you saw that, and I regret that the cameras caught my anger.
Yes, you are right. When I was in prison the son of a guard started a Bible study
and I attended. That day when I stepped out of prison and looked at the people
observing, a flush of anger hit me with the thought that they had robbed me of
27 years. Then the Spirit of Jesus said to me, ‘Nelson, while you were in prison
you were free, now that you are free don’t become a prisoner’ (Mandela quoted by
Freiberg & Freiberg 2018:4).
The lesson from Mandela, as Freiberg and Freiberg point out, is that in life, each
of us is a victim of something, but it is up to us to allow someone to victimise us
(Freiberg & Freiberg 2018).
Twelfth, ‘End right vs. being right’ (Freiberg & Freiberg 2018:4). Mandela
never crouched down in fear because of his firmness of purpose and resolve.
While he fought vigorously for his beliefs, he was also, nonetheless, good-natured
and unassuming. He understood that in order to make peace with an enemy, one
must be willing to work with that enemy and treat him/her with dignity. It is this
belief that undergirded Mandela’s working relationship with De Klerk which led
to both being jointly awarded the Nobel Peace Prize in 1993. In essence, Mandela
instructs us that only when we work together can we make our world a better
place (Freiberg & Freiberg 2018).
Thirteenth and finally, ‘Change begins from the inside-out’ (Freiberg &
Freiberg 2018:6). Mandela teaches us that if there was anything good about being
in prison is that it allowed him to develop within himself what he desired the
most for every South African: i.e. equality, freedom, harmony, and reconciliation.
The lesson here is that great leadership hinges upon self-awareness (Freiberg &
Freiberg 2018).
Next, apropos the qualities of Mandela’s leadership principles, Skip Prichard
(2014) delineates 11 of them. They are as follows:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
‘a man of peace’;
‘a powerful presence and disarmed enemies with his smile’;
‘showed the world what forgiveness looks like’;
‘positive, thinking about what could be’;
‘a visionary and could see the big picture’;
‘focused on goals and a mission beyond himself ’;
‘remarkable endurance’;
‘showed grit and determination’;
‘humble’;
‘full of hope, not hate’; and
‘patient’ (Prichard 2014:3–4).
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
261
But even more significant, according to Prichard, is what Mandela did not do:
1.
2.
3.
4.
‘held no bitterness,’
sought no ‘revenge’,
sought no ‘self-glory’, and
‘did not hide his faults or feelings’ (Prichard 2014:4–5).
Thus, Prichard says, Mandela made him feel a changed person as he was ‘motivated
and inspired by an imperfect man, who suffered for his dreams and yet never lost
hope’ (Prichard 2014:5).
A Caveat
Like any theory, Mandelaism is not without limitations. Prince Mashele makes this
point very well when he posits that ‘the triumphalism of Mandelaism has lulled
most South Africans into a slumber induced by a deceptive sense of exceptionalism’
(Mashele 2017:3). He adds that Archbishop Desmond Tutu may not have known
the gestation of his rainbow nation metaphor. Akin to how a rainbow conveys a
compatible mélange of colours, Tutu appears to have been ensnared by the idea of
a South Africa united in distinctiveness. In reality, however, Mashele points out,
a rainbow is transient. Thus, according to him, ‘The bright sky promised by the
rainbow is a seductive temporariness’ (Mashele 2017:3).
According to Mashele, South Africa is undergoing political turmoil, with
citizens wondering when and how it will end. What is certain. based on historical
experience, Mashele says, is that neither stability nor disorder is perpetual. It is in
such turbulent times, he adds, that societies display their capability to reinvent
themselves by showing their concealed wealth of leadership (Mashele 2017).
Conclusion
In the acknowledgments section of the book titled Mandela: Tributes to a Global
Icon (2014), Mwalimu Toyin Falola, who edited the text, says the following about
the leadership traits of Mandela:
‘Mandela’s life reinforces the adage that character makes a person. A courageous
fighter, an honest and tireless worker, an original thinker, the Madiba, as he
was popularly called, put people at the center of his activities. It was clear that
the progress of his country and its people was the motivation for his behaviour,
actions, and decisions’ (Falola 2014: ix).
Among the 111 eulogies that follow the acknowledgments and the introduction
chapter of the book, five speak directly to Mandela as a leader. The following
is a listing of the adjectives employed to describe him as a leader, with their
definitions provided by me:
1. Tony Blair, former Prime Minister of the United Kingdom, and Bessie HouseSorenekun, Professor of Political Science and Africana Studies and Director of
262
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
2.
3.
4.
5.
Africana Studies at Indiana University Purdue University in the United States:
great – a leader with the ability, quality, or eminence considerably above the
normal or average leader.
William Hague, First Secretary of State of the United Kingdom, and Benjamin
Netanyahu, Prime Minister of Israel: moral – a leader concerned with the
principles of right and wrong behaviour and the goodness or badness of
human character.
Thomas McClendon Professor Emeritus of History at Southwestern University
in the United States: transformational – a leader who makes a thorough or
dramatic change in the form, appearance, or character of a phenomenon.
Victor Oguejiofor Professor of Africology and African American Studies at
Eastern Michigan University in the United States: world – a leader who reflects
all the people, societies, and institutions on the earth.
Justice Malala, Political Journalist and Analyst in South Africa: courageous – a
leader who is not deterred by danger or pain.
Indeed, the preceding adjectives do mirror the attributes and principles of
Mandelaism broached in the preceding two sections. Also interesting is that
they are akin to the notions of a leader in Ancient Kemetian thought. Ancient
Kemetians had many terms for leader(s) that also denote many important entities.
They are as follows:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
åui – leader, comer;
åmi-ha-t – leader, he who is in front, peasant;
up – leader, chief;
umt – leaders, chiefs, men, a dense mass of people;
utu – leader, commander;
m’tenu – leaders, guide;
nuu – leader, guide, director;
hau-ti – leader, Åmen (also referred to as Amun, Amon, or Ammo, he was the
Ancient Kemetian god of the sun and air; he was one of the most important
gods who rose to prominence at Thebes at the beginning of the period of the
New Kingdom, c. 1570-1069 BCE), the first one, the foremost one, the finest
or best thing in a class, the chief captain, leaders, chiefs, captains;
khenti – leader, the first, one who is at the head, chief, in the first rank,
foremost;
kherpu – leaders, director, governor, overseer, chief, master, president, divine
chief, landlord, overseer of the landlords, chiefs, foremen, bailiffs, wardens,
superiors;
senni – leader, officer, chief, fighter in the van of an army;
seshmu – leaders, guides;
sesha – leader, guide;
seshmi – leader, guide, director, leader of peace (i.e. peacemaker), divide guides;
sta (sthi) – leader, guide, dealer in vegetables;
qeru – leader; and
Bangura: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
263
17. tepi – leader; he who is on, over, or above someone or something; he who is or
that which is preeminent, foremost, first, best; chief, captain, officer, governor,
first or elder son (for these translations, see Budge 1978).
As Yildirim informs us, Ancient Kemet established its social and political
structure under Pharaohs serving as sole leaders who inspired the construction
of magnificent cities and works of architecture. In addition, the emergence of
Pharaohs to motivate people through the institution of centralised authority for
many centuries was pivotal for the advancement of Kemetian civilisation. The
Pharaohs as leaders perceived their existence as a source of dominance. They also
proclaimed themselves as gods so that their authority could not be questioned by
the masses (Yildirim 2016).
Yildirim adds that by not limiting their exaltation to being priests of gods
but declaring themselves as gods, the Pharaohs were privileged in several ways.
One way is that it thwarted the establishment of a religious class with which
the Pharaohs would have had to struggle for power and prevent from fighting
against them. Another way has to do with the capacity of the Pharaohs to spread
fear among the masses in order to succumb to their dictates. This is one reason
the Pharaohs were able to construct magnificent monuments for themselves, as
the masses working on these edifices were convinced that they were building
them for gods. The other way concerns the understanding of god-king ushered
in by the Pharaohs, the first in world history, which allowed them to monopolise
both political and religious power. This aspect rendered obsolete the possibility
of objecting to the demands or a religious class questioning the authority of the
Pharaohs (Yildirim 2016).
In essence, Mandela was a Pharaoh, with one attribute that was different vis-àvis those of the Kemetian Pharaohs: i.e. he sought neither to dominate others nor
perceived himself as a god. Instead, Mandela promoted equality and harmony
among people and between himself and everyone.
References
Babjee, A. Mustaffa, 2013, ‘“Mandelaism” – A Doctrine for Conflict Resolution’, The Star
Online. (https://www.thestar.com.my/opinion/letters/2013/12/24/mandelaism-adoctrine-for-conflict-resolution). 8 September 2021.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2002, Sojourner-Douglass College’s Philosophy in Action: An
African-Centered Creed, San Jose, CA: Writers Club Press.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 2005, ‘Ubuntugogy: An African Educational Paradigm that
Transcends Pedagogy, Andragogy, Ergonagy, and Heutagogy’, Journal of Third World
Studies, Vol. 22, No. 2, pp. 13–53.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, ed., 2008, African Peace Paradigms, Dubuque, IA: Kendall/Hunt
Publishing Company.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, ed., 2012, Fractal Complexity in the Works of Major Black Thinkers,
Volume One, San Diego, CA: Cognella Publishing.
264
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Budge, E. A. Wallis, 1978, An Egyptian Hieroglyphic Dictionary, 2 volumes, New York:
Dover Publications, Inc.
Falola, Toyin, ed., 2014. Mandela: Tributes to a Global Icon, Durham, NC: Carolina
Academic Press.
Frankfort-Nachmias, Chava and David Nachmias, 1996, Research Methods in the Social
Sciences, New York, NY: St. Martin’s Press.
Freiberg, Kevin and Freiberg, Jackie, 2018, ‘Madiba Leadership: 5 Lessons Nelson
Mandela Taught the World about Change’, Forbes. (https://www.forbes.com/sites/
kevinandjackiefreiberg/2018/07/19/madiba-leadership-5-lessons-nelson-mandelataught-the-world-about-change/#74a8d30d41ba). 4 November 2021.
Hord, Fred Lee (Mzee Lasana Okpara) and Lee, Jonathan Scott, eds., 1995, I Am Because
We Are: Readings in Black Philosophy, Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.
Mandela, Nelson, 1994, LongWalk to Freedom: The Autobiography of Nelson Mandela, Boston,
MA: Little Brown and Company; Randburg, South Africa: Macdonald Purnell.
Munusamy, Ranjeni, 2014, ‘The 20 Years from Mandela to Zuma’. (https://www.
dailymaverick.co.za/article/2014-03-12-sas-20-year-review-from-mandela-tozuma/). 8 September 2021.
Mashele, Prince, 2017, ‘Opinion: A New and Credible Leadership Must Emerge from the
Chaos’, Sowetan Live. (https://www.sowetanlive.co.za/news/2017-05-08-opinion-anew-and-credible-leadership-must-emerge-from-the-chaos/). 4 November 2021.
Nagra, Marria Qibtia Sikandar, 2018, ‘Mandela-ism: Intellect Coalesced into Leadership’,
The Nation. (https://nation.com.pk/22-Jul-2018/mandela-ism-intellect-coalescedinto-leadership). 3 November 2021.
Prichard, Skip, 2014, ‘11 Leadership Qualities of Nelson Mandela’, Leadership Insights.
(https://www.skipprichard.com/11-leadership-qualities-of-nelson-mandela/).
4 November 2021.
Sampson, Anthony, 1994. ‘The Evil Must Be Forgiven, Not Forgotten’, The Guardian.
(https://www.theguardian.com/world/1994/may/01/nelsonmandela.southafrica).
3 November 2021.
Schoemaker, Paul, 2013, ‘The 3 Decisions that Made Mandela a Truly Great Leader’,
Inc.. (https://www.inc.com/paul-schoemaker/what-made-nelson-mandela-such-agreat-leader.html). 3 November 2021.
Schoemaker, Paul J.H. and Steven Krupp, 2014, ‘6 Principles that Made Nelson Mandela
a Renowned Leader’, Fortune. (https://fortune.com/2014/12/05/6-principles-thatmade-nelson-mandela-a-renowned-leader/). 4 November 2021.
News24, 2012, ‘Long Live Mandela-ism’. (https://www.news24.com/SouthAfrica/News/
Long-live-Mandela-ism-20120718-2). 3 November 2021.
Stengel, Richard, 2008, ‘Mandela: His 8 Lessons of Leadership’, Time. (http://content.
time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,1821659,00.html). 4 November 2021.
Yildirim, Ercüment, 2016, ‘Concept of Leadership in the Ancient History and Its Effects
on the Middle East’, Sociology and Anthropology, Vol. 4, No. 8, pp. 710–718.
10
Dialectics: Its Theorisation
and Application to Africa’s Development
Joseph Mensah
It was Kwame Nkrumah who made the following instructive observation in one
of his seminal works, entitled Consciencism:
There is a fundamental law of the evolution of matter to higher forms. This
evolution is dialectical. And it is also the fundamental law of society. It is out of
tension that being is born. Becoming is a tension, and being is the child of that
tension of opposed forces and tendencies (1964:103).
Indeed, for centuries now, ‘dialectics’ has been deployed as a mode of reasoning
in virtually all aspects of the social sciences and humanities, with disciplines such
as philosophy, political science, cultural studies, sociology, semiotics, and literary
studies taking the lead in this intellectual endeavour. Perhaps the most striking
feature of the growing literature on dialectics is neither the diversity of issues
to which it is applied nor the characteristic opacity of some of the writings on
it, but rather the dearth of its application to the discourse on Africa in general
and African development in particular. Noteworthy exceptions here come in
the works of Frantz Fanon (1967), Samir Amin (1990), and Kwame Nkrumah,
especially in Consciencism (1964), from which much more insight is later drawn
to enrich the discussion in this chapter.
Perhaps the lack dialectical reasoning on African development in particular
is not that surprising, since many are those who dogmatically see Africa as the
indisputable epitome of underdevelopment, or the unambiguous polar opposite
of the developed world, if not ‘development’ in its entirety. For instance, The
Economist once had a cover story that depicted Africa as ‘the Hopeless Continent’
and argued that African societies are ‘especially susceptible to…brutality,
despotism and corruption…for reasons buried deep in their cultures’ (The
266
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Economist 2000:15). In a similar vein, Oswaldo de Rivero writes that Africa is
made up of nothing more than dysfunctional, ‘non-viable economies’ (2001:1),
imbued with insurmountable corruption and tribal conflicts. Such derogatory
views about Africa(ns) are nothing new; indeed, they go back to the writings of
the pre-eminent nineteenth century German philosopher G.W.F. Hegel (1770–
1831) who, in his The Philosophy of History (1821), excluded Africa from world
history. In his view Africans, then, did not have the ability to think critically,
objectively, or abstractly (Kuykendall 1993).
With such pessimistic outlooks on Africa, for that long a period, it is
unsurprising that scholars have generally steered clear of nuanced, dialectical
reasoning when it comes to discussions on Africa’s development.1 Not only
that, due to the racism-laced power imbalance in knowledge production, the
contributions of Africans to theorisations of dialectics are routinely overlooked in
some circles of the academy. For instance, Paul Kisak (2021), in his recent book,
Dialectics, draws on writings from across the world, except Africa, to discuss the
methods and history of dialectics. An excerpt from the back cover of Kisak’s book
hints of this omission: ‘Different forms of dialectical reasoning have emerged
throughout history from the Indosphere (Greater India) and the West (Europe).
These forms include the Socratic method, Hindu, Buddhist, medieval, Hegelian
dialectics, Marxist, Talmudic, and neo-orthodoxy.’ Achille Mbembe, for one,
observed in his On the Postcolony that ‘[s]peaking rationally about Africa is not
something that has ever come naturally (at least to some people)’ (2001:1; note
in parenthesis is mine).
The present chapter sheds light on dialectics and demonstrates how it could
help us understand the complex dynamics of African development. The intent
here is to evince the power of dialectical reasoning, especially as it pertains to
explanations of African development. The chapter conceptualises development as a
dialectical process; accordingly, the tendency to set one region of the world, notably
Africa, against other parts in strict binary opposition is deemed theoretically
unsustainable. As the works of Nkrumah (1964) and other development theorists
suggest, development is an internally heterogeneous and contradictory process,
which emanates from many different sources and exhibits a variety of forms that
are not amenable to simplistic explanations and characterisations.
Dialectics: Nature and Characteristics
It is widely believed that Plato coined the term ‘dialectics,’ which originally
referred to the method of argumentation used by Socrates in Plato’s dialogues,
including Phaedo, Meno, Euthyphro, Theaetetus, and Protagoras (Schiappa
1991:44; Nikulin 2010:2). Socrates in these dialogues would expose the
weaknesses and inconsistencies in the answers provided by his followers without
providing an adequate answer of his own. With this approach, he was able to
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
267
steer his followers clear of arguments that appear valid on the surface, but lead to
illogical conclusions upon scrutiny. In Theaetetus, Socrates likens his approach,
which later became known as the Socratic method, to that of a midwife who is
past childbearing herself, but helps others to deliver babies.2 Thus, according to
this analogy, Socrates was delivering not babies, but knowledge and thought.
Socrates in his epistemology of Anamnesis posited that we acquire knowledge
primarily through recollection (Cornford 1957:24). For him, we humans possess
innate knowledge, and that which we call learning is merely an effort to recollect
what we knew from an earlier life and lost through the trauma of rebirth. His
efforts, by way of the Socratic method, were only to help us remember or give
birth to the knowledge that was already in us – more specifically in our immortal
soul. Socrates used his theory of Anamnesis to resolve the sophistic paradox in the
dialogue Meno, wherein Socrates was asked how one can search for the nature
of virtue if one does not know at all what virtue is in the first place (Cooper &
Hutchinson 1997). The conundrum here is how one would know if he or she
comes across virtue (or anything for that matter) if one does not already know
what virtue is. And, if one knows what virtue is, then why look for it – therein lie
the sophistic paradox or the paradox of knowledge.
While dialectics has taken on many different forms over the years, its most
common characterisation comes in a triad formulation, which begins with a
thesis against which is set an antithesis before reaching a final synthesis (Mensah
2006:60). Of course, dialectics is far more rigorous than this common depiction
would have us believe. In fact, Jameson (2010), for one, calls for the jettison of this
idea of dialectics with his (arguably) dramatic observation that ‘our only rule…
will be a strict avoidance of the old pseudo-Hegelian caricature of the thesis/
antithesis/synthesis; while our only presupposition will be the assumption that
any opposition can be the starting point for a dialectic in its own right’ (2010:19).
During the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, dialectics was
popularised by many German scholars, including Kant, Fichte, Schleiermacher,
and Hegel, with the latter producing its most comprehensive and characteristically
idealist account to date. While Hegel’s dialectics also comes in three stages, it is
more subtle, complex and historical.
The first, or ‘universal,’ stage of Hegelian dialectics is one of ‘naïve selfcertainty’: a stage in which only a single, complacent, secure entity exists in a
world of ‘pure subjectivity or universality’ (Edgar 1999:113–14). According to
Edgar, what occurs at this first stage is akin to the mindset of a newborn baby
who knows nothing of the world other than its own existence, or to the naivety
of the creatures of the Garden of Eden ‘who were well-fed and cared for, but
ignorant of themselves and their potential’ (1999:114). In this first stage, people
are ignorant because of the lack of differentiation. Hegel, in his The Philosophy of
History (1821), placed Africans mostly in this early stage of his dialectical schema.
268
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The second, the ‘particular’ stage, is where humanity (or the child) encounters
the external world, which invariably yields friction, resistance, and contestation,
leading to the creation of the ‘Other’. Thus, the universal breaks up, or
particularises, into subject and object, and the pure subjectivity or universality
of the subject (or the child) comes into contact with the ‘Other’, or the object.
The encounter between the subject and the object, though conflictual and
contradictory, is still a fruitful source of progress and discovery, not only of the
self but also of human and natural history as a whole.
In the third and final stage – dubbed the ‘individual’ stage – the subject
comes to see itself in the object, leading to a return to the universality of the first
stage, but this time with a better understanding of the self – a better insight of
the complex unity of the subject and the object. The fact that tension, conflict
and contradictions are deemed a source of growth and prescience is canonical in
dialectics, as we shall see throughout the rest of this chapter.
Marx used essentially the same dialectical model in his account of the
development of human history through a series of epochs. According to Marx,
history began when humans broke out of the ‘naïve universality’ of tribal society
or primitive communism, characterised by a unity that excluded differences, into
a second stage of a class society (Edgar 1999:113–14). This class society involves
both unity and differences; it is here that humans make history, but not under
conditions of their own choosing because of class conflicts and exploitation at this
stage of human development (Edgar 1999:113–14; Mensah 2006:61). The final
stage in Marx’s dialectics entails communism, where class tensions are lessened,
with the rule of the proletariat. It bears stressing that, whereas Hegelian dialectics
is idealist, giving primacy to the subject position couched in reason or ideas,
Marx’s dialectics is patently materialistic, and turns the Hegelian formulation
on its head by placing its emphasis on material circumstances. To Marx, reason
(or ‘the idea’ in Hegel’s idealism) is a mere epiphenomenon, a reflection of the
material world; life is not determined by consciousness or reason or idea, but
rather consciousness by life.
Like Marx, Nkrumah in his Consciencism espoused a materialistic view of
dialectics and applied it to the liberation and subsequent social development of
Africa. While Nkrumah drew the bulk of his materialism from Marx’s work, there
is little doubt that he also found the anti-idealist writings of yet another Ghanaian
philosopher, Anthony William Amo, very inspirational. Born in Ghana and sent
to Europe in his early formative years, Amo – whose German name was Anton
Wilhelm Amo3 – became an influential philosopher in Europe, going as far as
teaching in the reputable German Universities of Halle, Jena, and Wittenberg in
the eighteenth century (Abraham 1996). Amo was a staunch materialist and did
not hesitate to take on such idealist giants as Rene Descartes in his famous antiidealist thesis De Humanae Mentis Apatheia, [On the Absence of Sensation in the
Human Mind, 1734], to which Nkrumah (1964) duly pays homage.
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
269
In Nkrumah’s dialectics, we see how the tension between positive (or progressive)
action and negative (or reactionary) action towards social development plays out
in post-independent Africa. Nkrumah draws our attention to a similar dialectical
tension and contradiction between what he calls ‘inside’ (i.e., the earthly and
secular) and ‘outside’ (or the heavenly and religious) forces and cautions us not
to use religion to fix our gaze only on that which is spiritual or heavenly, to the
neglect of that which is material or earthly. As he puts it,
In present-day Africa, however, a recognition of the dialectical contradiction
between ‘inside’ and ‘outside’ has a great deal to contribute to the process of
decolonisation and development, for it helps us to anticipate colonialist and
imperialist devices for furthering exploitation by diverting our energies from secular
concerns. The recognition of the dialectical opposition is universally necessary…
People who are most aggressively religious are the poorer people; for, in accordance
with the Marxist analysis, religion is social, and contemporary religious forms
and practices have their main root in the social depression of workers. Quick
confirmation can be found in Africa, Asia, Latin America and among people of
African descent in America and Caribbean (Nkrumah 1964:12– 14).
Nkrumah uses dialectics to solidify his concept of Philosophical Consciencism,
which he sees as a philosophical standpoint which takes its starting position
from the present content of the African conscience, imbued with the traditional
African principles of humanism and egalitarianism and couched in a strong belief
in the absolute and independent existence of matter – i.e., materialism.
Similarly, dwelling on Marx’s exposition, the renowned human geographer
David Harvey has formulated what he calls the principles of dialectics, which
include the following six key propositions (Harvey 1996:49–54):
1. That change and instability are characteristic, if not inherent, features of all
things or systems and all aspects of systems;
2. Dialectical thinking gives priority to the understanding of processes, flows,
fluxes, and relations, rather than to things, elements, and structures;
3. Parts and wholes are mutually constitutive of each other in dialectics; thus,
parts are in wholes and vice versa;
4. Things or elements are always assumed to be internally heterogeneous in
dialectical thinking;
5. Things many researchers treat as irreducible, and, therefore, unproblematic,
are seen in dialectics to be internally contradictory by virtue of the processes
which constitute them; and
6. ‘Subjects’ are interchangeable with ‘objects’ and ‘causes’ with ‘effects’ in dialectics.
The ideas of Nkrumah (1964) and Harvey (1996) on dialectics are not that
different from that which obtains in the long-standing laws of dialectics (Woods
& Grant 2002:42–46), which include the following three propositions:
270
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
1. The law of the transformation of quantity into quality: This law posits that
under certain conditions, a small quantitative change can lead to a big
transformation or a qualitative change. This particular law undergirds the
famous sorites paradox by which small, continuous additions of grains of sand
become a heap of sand without us noticing exactly when the switch to a heap
occurred. It is also the basis for the now common phenomenon of a tipping
point,4 popularised by Malcolm Gladwell (2011) in his book of a similar title.
2. The law of the interpenetration of opposites (or the law of the unity of opposites):
This is the belief that power, motion, life or any effect at all is possible only
when there is unity of opposites as in the unity between light and darkness,
capital and labour, master and slave. This law could be used to illustrate the
literal interpenetration of male and female organisms to yield life or to show
how both positive and negative charges work to project electric charges or
magnetic forces.
3. The law of the negation of the negation: This is what dialecticians call the
second negation or sublation. It contends that life, progress, or development
occurs through a complex transcendence, by which what is already negated
is subject to another negation, but at a higher level. Negation, in dialectics,
implies knowing something through what it is not. The negation of negation
(or the second negation) implies a situation where something is nullified, or
contradicted, and preserved, simultaneously. Thus, sublation occurs when the
contradiction between two opposing positions is mediated and embraced to
facilitate a dialectical self-discovery (Woods & Grant 2002; Nikulin 2010).
From the preceding, we can draw some preliminary conclusions about the nature
of dialectics. First, dialectics is highly sceptical of binary opposites, as things
are seen to be mutually constitutive of each other. Accordingly, for our present
purpose, any strict dichotomy between ‘developed’ and ‘underdeveloped’ worlds
or ‘First’ and ‘Third’ worlds goes against dialectics. Second, dialectics espouses
the primacy of process, change, and relations, as opposed to structures and their
elements. Indeed, in dialectics, entities are constantly in a state of flux; thus,
one cannot step in the same river twice, as Heraclitus, the ancient Greek process
philosopher, once observed (Ollman 2003:64). Third, there is nothing like an
unproblematic phenomenon in dialectics, because things are conceptualised
as being internally heterogeneous and internally contradictory. Fourth, to the
extent that entities are in a constant state of flux, and to the extent that causes
are in effects and vice versa, dialectics is inherently recursive and spiral, rather
than linear. Thus, the course of human progress, life, development, and, indeed,
reality, in general, is never linear from the standpoint of dialectics. Also, since
dialectics entails sublation, or the negation of the negation, phenomena are best
understood from the standpoint of creative destruction or destructive creation.
Put differently, progress, creative efforts, or social development entail some
destructive forces, tension and contradictions, all of which are a source of growth,
motion, prescience, and discovery in dialectics.
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
271
In the next section, I examine the phenomenon of development in general
and African development in particular. The purpose is to show how we could
better understand them through dialectical reasoning.
The Nature of Development and African Development
As with most trendy concepts in the social sciences and humanities, the meaning
of development is difficult to pin down in the available literature. Depending
on one’s perspective or disciplinary tilt, development can be seen as a matter of
economic growth, modernisation, sociocultural progress, distributive justice, human
freedom, empowerment, etc. Historically, neoclassical economists such as Arthur
Lewis (1955) saw development as primarily an issue of economic growth, with
almost nothing to do with distributive justice. By the time of the first United
Nations Development Decade (1960s), it was clear that growth alone was not
enough to capture the essence of development, and issues of distribution and
distributive justice needed to be brought into any reasonable constitution and
theorisation of development. The British development economist Dudley Seers
(1920–1983) was among the first to be critical of the development orthodoxy
during the 1960s. Seers argued that development is more than economic
growth, and that growth without a clear reduction in unemployment, poverty,
or inequality is hardly development. As he puts it in his seminal paper titled ‘The
Meaning of Development’,
What has been happening to poverty? What has been happening to unemployment?
What has been happening to inequality? If all three of these have become less
severe, then beyond doubt this has been a period of development of the country
concerned. If one or two of these central problems have been growing worse,
especially if all three have, it would be strange to call the result ‘development’ even
if per capita income has soared (Seers 1963: 3–4).
With the preceding queries, Seers declared his disillusionment about the prevailing
conception of development as economic growth, which was routinely measured
by gross national product (GNP) or gross national income (GNI) per capita. Seers
lamented the situation where many governments in developing countries used
their ‘growth rates’, reported by international development agencies such as the
International Monetary Fund (IMF) and the World Bank, to hide the extent of
poverty and inequality among their citizens (Seers 1983:6). Still, Seers was keenly
aware of the lack of data on poverty, inequality, and unemployment in most
developing countries then, especially since many of these economies were (and
still are) dominated by either subsistence agriculture or the informal sector with
no reportable income or reliable income tax regimes. At the same time, as Seers
noted, the lack of data even then was not necessarily a matter of incompetence,
rather it was a matter of inadequate political will to collect such data.
272
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Incidentally, it was around the start of the first Development Decade (1960s)
that the Modernisation Theory of development gained currency, especially
through the writing of Walt Whitman Rostow in his Stages of Economic Growth:
A Non-Communist Manifesto (1960).5 According to this theory, conditions in
underdeveloped countries are not that different from those of the earlier stages of
the now-developed countries. If presently underdeveloped countries follow the
development path of the developed countries, then it is just a matter of time for
the former countries to develop. The purported development path was articulated
in the following five stages by Rostow (who was, arguably, the strongest advocate
of the Modernisation Theory):
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
traditional society,
pre-conditions to take off,
take-off,
drive to maturity; and
age of high mass consumption.
Rostow drew many of his ideas from the works of the pre-eminent German
sociologist Max Weber (1864–1920) and, later, the Harvard sociologist Talcott
Parsons (1902–1979), both of whom saw modernisation as a transition from a
traditional or pre-modern society to a modern society. Modernisation theorists
sought to use development assistance, in conjunction with various right-wing
economic ideologies, to integrate African, Asian and Latin American economies
into the advanced capitalist system. Rostow, who was an economics staffer
in the President John F. Kennedy government in the 1960s, promoted such
initiatives as the Food for Peace, the Peace Corps, and the Alliance for Progress
in Latin America to advance the ‘modernisation’ of Africa, Asian and Latin
American economies.
In counterpoint to Modernisation Theory came the decidedly left-wing
Dependency Theory which was spearheaded by scholars such as Andre Gunder
Frank (1929–2005) and Immanuel Wallerstein (1930–2019). According to this
theory, the world system is made up of peripheral, hinterland, or underdeveloped
countries, on the one hand, and core, heartland, or developed countries, on
the other, with the latter exploiting the former. According to the dependency
theorists, countries of the periphery are impoverished to the extent that the core
countries enrich themselves at their expense in a zero-sum framework through
instruments such as international trade and development aid, all of which
exacerbate the dependence of the peripheral countries on the core ones (Frank
1967 & 1979; Wallerstein 1980). To dependency theorists, underdeveloped
countries are not mere incipient or traditional versions of developed countries
and, therefore, cannot simply follow the same development path. In their view,
underdeveloped countries have unique features and structures of their own and
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
273
any attempt to integrate them into the global capitalist system is to make them
subservient, weaker, and dependent partners in the system. With this integration,
the peripheral countries are expected to produce and export raw materials for the
industries of the core countries and, in return, import manufactured goods from
the core countries. The ensuing, rigged core-periphery relationship compels the
peripheral countries to remain dependent on the core countries (Amin 1976;
Frank 1979). It is against this background that dependency theorists advocate
for import substitution industrialisation and centrally planned economies in
the periphery to ward off the unfair influences and exploitative tendencies of
the core. At the same time, dependency theorists have been criticised for their
fondness for government programmes, the protection of infant industries, and
the subsidisation of basic goods and services. Critics argue that such programmes
undermine human agency, personal initiatives, creativity, and entrepreneurship
in developing countries.
By the mid-1980s, blatant disillusionment over both modernisation and
dependency theories plunged development theorisation into a discernible
impasse (Schuurman 2008), which culminated in the proliferation of new
theories, such as neoliberal development, post-development, sustainable development,
and development as freedom, with the latter two being, perhaps, the best received
(Desai & Potter 2008).
Espoused mainly by advocates of the Washington Consensus, neoliberal
development insists on the primacy of the free market, with the belief that with
time economic growth under ‘perfect competition’ will trickle down to the poor
and, ultimately, spur national development without the concerted intervention
of the national government (Harvey 2005).
On their part, sustainable development theorists call for the satisfaction of basic
human needs through people-centred activities that are couched in the principles
of environmental sustainability in pursuance of clean water, food self-reliance,
and shelter for all (Sachs 2015).
Propounded by the Nobel Prize laureate Amartya Sen, in his ground-breaking
book titled Development as Freedom, this theory sees ‘freedom’ as the most
important ethos in the pursuit of human welfare. According to Sen, we are not
free when we live a life of deprivation. In his view, ‘unfreedom’ means life of
hunger, ignorance, unemployment, premature death, poor sanitation, lack of
water, etc. For Sen, to be developed is to have effective freedom to achieve states
of being and doing at our own violation.
Unlike most of the aforementioned development theorists, post-development
theorists are of the view that ‘development’ is a Western ideology, deployed to
control people in the global South under the guise of altruism (Rahnema &
Bawtree 1997; Matthews 2004). Thus, for the proponents of post-development,
the theories and practices of development have promoted Eurocentric, western
274
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
hegemony. In a nutshell, there is nothing good in development, as theorised
and practiced now, for the people of the global South, and it is high time we
abandon it.
With these many different perspectives on development, it is only apposite
that we provide some operational definition of it here before we proceed any
further. For the purposes of the present discussion, development is conceptualised
as a complex, multi-faceted, and dialectical process that seeks to reorient the
socioeconomic and cultural systems of societies to improve the quality of human
life in sustainable ways. Is development really a dialectical process? If so, on
what grounds? How does the dialectics of development play out in the context
of Africa? Put another way, how best can we understand Africa’s development
through dialectics? The next section addresses these pointed questions to show
the utility of dialectics as an analytical construct for explaining the complexities
of Africa’s development.
Understanding Development and African Development
through Dialectics
It is clear from the foregoing section that development is concerned with improving
the lives of people. It is an effort to re-organise and re-orient societies for a positive
change, moving them from their extant situation to something better. Conceived
as such, every region or country of the world has some room for development. It
so happens that over the years many analysts and media reports have discussed
development in bi-polar terms in which countries of Africa, in particular, and the
global South, in general, are seen as ‘underdeveloped’ or ‘the Third World’ and
those of the global North are seen as ‘developed’ or ‘First World’. Even when the
countries of the world are discussed in terms of a spectrum, one invariably finds
African countries in general occupying the worst end of this continuum, with
the so-called advanced capitalist nations positioned at the best end, and the rest
sandwiched somewhere between these polarities. Invariably, Africa is depicted
as the epitome of underdevelopment in much of the prevailing discourse on
international development. Attend any conference having to do with international
development or the social sciences, in general, and the chances are that almost
all the negative examples, illustrations, and hypothetical scenarios, regardless of
the issue under focus, will be tied somehow to Africa. This negative branding
of Africa is often done without any regard to the specificities of the individual
African countries, which are almost always painted with one big, unflattering,
and deleterious brush. Of course, some, if not most, of these attributions are
soaked in myths and stereotypes, with questionable empirical base. We thus find
former United States President Donald Trump – the professed leader of the free
world – for example, alleged to have referred to African countries as shit-hole
countries, a statement he denied making.
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
275
As with many stereotypes, some of these negative portrayals of Africa have
a kernel of truth. Indeed, the development story of Africa has not been pretty
– to put it colloquially – and for obvious reasons. In terms of land resources,
the continent is second to none, and Africa’s physical and population sizes are
second only to those of Asia. Furthermore, of all the continents of the world,
Africa has the youngest population. However, when it comes to development
metrics, including the extent of poverty, infant mortality, violence, hunger,
famine, drought, insecurity, corruption, poor governance, unemployment, and
many more, African countries are often either at the very bottom or racing to the
bottom together with some countries of Asia and Latin America.
Since the mid-2000s, Africa has been making considerable strides in its
development and growth indicators, but the stereotypes of dysfunctionality,
extreme poverty, and unimaginable violence are still etched in the minds of
many analysts. In a 2009 piece, reprinted in the Harvard Business Review in
2013, Jonathan Berman offered some reasons why Africa is on the path to
development. According to him, not only does Africa have most of the world’s
uncultivated land, a large market, and one of the largest workforces, Africa is also
becoming increasingly stable, politically. Additionally, Africa’s mobile technology
is exploding, just as African governments are increasingly spending more on
education.
In what follows, I deploy dialectical reasoning to help us understand Africa’s
development from a different and a more complex angle. The objective for doing
this is twofold: (1) to show the dialectical character of development and (2) to
demonstrate how African development could be analysed by way of dialectics. To
the extent that development is conceived as a dialectical process, it follows that
not only can African development be analysed dialectically, but, indeed, so can
the development of all parts of the world. Consequently, the emphasis on African
development is a matter of interest and meets the need to have an analytical focus
to help us see how variables play out in a specific context, and not in general terms.
African Development: An Exercise in Creative Destruction and the
Negation of the Negation
One of the cruces of dialectics is negation, which extends to the notion of ‘second
negation’ or ‘the negation of the negation,’ also termed ‘sublation’ in the Hegelian
paradigm. In dialectics, negation connotes getting to know a phenomenon
through what it is not. In yet another sense, to negate something is to nullify it.
By sublation or the second negation, the dialectician implies a situation where
an entity is nullified and at the same time transcended in a way that moves it to
a higher plane to be negated yet again. To say that development is a dialectical
process is to imply that it entails sublation. Clearly, then, development in general
(and African development, in particular) is imbued with the second negation,
276
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
which is invariably an exercise in creative destruction. Thus, what is created
comes about only after some form of destruction and vice versa. This is how Hegel
analogises negation and sublation in the preface to his Phenomenology of Mind:
The bud disappears when the blossom breaks through, and we might say that
the former is refuted [i.e., negated] by the latter; in the same way when the fruit
comes, the blossom may be explained to be a false form of the plant’s existence,
for the fruit appears as its true nature in place of the blossom. These stages are not
merely differentiated; they supplant one another as being incompatible with one
another. But the ceaseless activity of their own inherent nature makes them at the
same time moments of an organic unity [i.e. sublation] (Hegel 1967:68).
What have negation and sublation got to do with our understanding of
development in general or African development in particular? At the very least
they point to the fact that development is not a linear, straightforward process;
that development often assumes a spiral trajectory; that development is never
all-positive, and its progressions are inherently inter-mixed with retrogressions,
just as its creations are inter-mingled with destructions and vice versa. A simple
illustration would be useful: Prior to Africans’ encounter with Europeans, we
Africans had our traditional culture(s), many attributes of which left much to be
desired by today’s cultural and development standards. The practices of female
genital mutilation/female circumcision/genital cutting and human or animal
sacrifices come to mind in this regard. During our encounter with Europeans,
some of these cultural practices were discouraged or forced out of the repertoire
of African culture, along with the embrace of some European cultural attributes
which are deemed by many to be progressive, innovative, or positive – e.g., new
ways of industrial production and economic organisation (Nkrumah 1964:106).
Our encounters with Europeans amount to sublation, since some of our
traditional cultural practices were nullified, and out of their ashes emerged many
of the hybridised cultural practices we have today.
It bears stressing, for the avoidance of any doubt, that such nullifications,
creative destructions, sublation and cultural hybridisations between Europeans
and Africans have never been one-way; they have always been a two-way affair,
with both Africans and Europeans copying from each other and gaining and
losing, simultaneously, in the process. Some African scholars, enthralled
by European ideals and intellectualism, have a hard time recognising the
contribution of Africans to European culture in particular and to world history
in general. This is how Nkrumah, for instance, laments this unfortunate and
acquiescent sentiment:
The colonized African student, whose roots in his own society are systematically
starved of sustenance, is introduced to Greek and Roman history, the cradle history
of modern Europe, and he is encouraged to treat this portion of the story of
man [sic] together with the subsequent history of Europe as the only worthwhile
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
277
portion. This history is anointed with a universalist flavouring which titillates the
palate of certain African intellectuals so agreeably that they become alienated from
their own immediate society (1964:5).
Following the earlier encounter with Europeans came the independence
movement, which then negated the enterprises of colonialism and slavery, and
moved Africa forward into yet another dialectical plane of self-determination
towards meaningful social development. Nkrumah (1964) writes about the need
to forge a harmony that allows for the combined presence of traditional African,
Euro-Christian, and Islamic African ideals in our social development efforts.
According to him, this harmony can only emanate from the triumph of positive
action over negative action, borne of the African conscience, but still drawing
useful lessons from other societies, just as others draw from Africans – this, indeed,
is the crux of Nkrumah’s Consciencism. In a true dialectic fashion, our encounters
with outsiders involve creative destruction and purposeful hybridisation of one
form or another. Accordingly, for Nkrumah, Philosophical Consciencism gives
‘the theoretical basis for an ideology whose aim shall be to contain the African
experience of Islamic and Euro-Christian presence as well as the experience of the
traditional African society, and, by gestation, employ them for the harmonious
growth and development of society’ (1964:70).
Given that development entails some tension, some hybridisation, and
some creative destruction, it is never linear; it proceeds in a spiral, rather than
linear, pattern. But this basic fact has been missing in much of the discourse on
development in general and African development in particular. In the case of
African development, analysts have often paid attention to the destructive or
negative forces, relegating the creative or positive ones to the background. This
accounts for the widespread stereotype of Africa as a continent of violence, crime,
poverty, and dysfunctionality. Analysts tend to talk of African development with
expectations of a linear progression, moving from stage one, through two, three,
and four, to five a la Rostow. Any backward movement is considered aberrant
and not an inherent part of development. However, that is not the case, since
development is inherently spiral. It is high time we see African development
in new ways and become receptive of its occasional backward movement and
growing pains. This is not to say that we should be complacent and bury our
heads in the proverbial sand like an ostrich. If the independence movement in
Africa started in earnest in the 1950s and 1960s for most African countries, then
these countries have been independent for only 60 to 70 years. Arguably, in the
grand scheme of national development, this is not that long a timeframe. Still,
Africa could have done better, considering how Asian countries such as Malaysia,
South Korea, and Singapore have moved along the spectrum of development.
Then, again, does it do us any good to compare what Asian countries have gone
through with what Africans have been through by way of colonialisation, slavery,
278
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
international racism, capitalist exploitation, etc.? Frantz Fanon, for example,
cautioned us that ‘[i]t is utopian to try to ascertain in what ways one kind of
inhuman behaviour differs from another kind of inhuman behaviour’ (1967:86).
Undoubtedly, there are worrying levels of famine, poverty, unemployment, etc.
in Africa, making Africa unique – ironically, just like anywhere else. However,
we must note that all is not negative in Africa. For instance, out of the genocidal
ruins and ashes of Rwanda emerged an impressive new society with remarkable
impetuses towards the rule of law, the mobilisation of civil society, and the
empowerment of women in a span of one generation, or so. Meanwhile, there
are indications that significant human rights abuses are occurring in Rwanda (US
Department of State 2020), which speaks to the spiral character of development.
Development and the Interchangeability of Causes and Effects
Among the principles of dialectics itemised by David Harvey (1996), and noted
earlier, is the idea that in dialectics subjects are interchangeable with objects,
just as causes are interchangeable with effects. This dialectical principle is often
overlooked in the African development discourse, with the recursivity implicated
in this causality ignored accordingly. For instance, while analysts are quick to
point out that Africa’s development is hampered by the lack of education among
many Africans, only few are able to draw the recursive connection to see how
the lack of development also hampers education in Africa. Similarly, while many
observers attribute the growing emigration of African youth out of the continent
(mostly via the dangerous Sahara through the Mediterranean to Europe) to
the lack of development in general and job opportunities in particular, few are
able to see the recursive link by which the exodus also becomes the cause of
Africa’s development challenges. The same form of recursive causality applies to
the nexus between poor health care and development in Africa. Just as African
underdevelopment can be seen as the cause of poor health care on the continent,
it (Africa’s underdevelopment) can also be the effect of poor health care. This
basic realisation points to the need to eschew simplistic, unidirectional causal
attributions in the discourse of African development. The need to be more
thorough and sophisticated in our analysis cannot be overemphasised. When
we know, for instance, that some causes can be the effects and vice versa, our
insight becomes deeper and, thus, closer to the realities on the ground, rather
than merely feeding into simplistic mythologies and stereotypes that are so
common in disputations and discourses on African development. Relatedly, with
causes and effects being interchangeable, it is not difficult to see how opposites
would interpenetrate in dialectics. This insight can be illustrated by the fact that
when it comes to international development nowadays the developed world is
in the underdeveloped world and vice versa. Put differently, Africa is in Europe,
just as Europe is in Africa. Not only are African people living in Europe and
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
279
Europeans living in Africa, but the conditions of underdevelopment that are
often associated with Africa are also common in some European and American
cities, just as the conditions of development that are commonly associated with
European and American cities are becoming increasingly common in pockets
of African cities such as Accra, Lagos, Abuja, Addis Ababa, Nairobi and Dakar.
With the interpenetrations of opposites, it comes as no surprise that phenomena
are deemed internally contradictory in dialectics.
African Development and the Transformation of Quantity into Quality
Another important tenet of dialectics with palpable utility for our understanding
of African development is the law of the transformation of quantity into quality.
According to this law, some entities or phenomena can undergo substantive
qualitative change, following small and progressive quantitative increments.
Consider the process of boiling water progressively to a temperature of 99 degrees
Celsius (at one atmospheric pressure); after this, a mere addition of one degree of
temperature can transform the water that has been boiling all along into steam (at
100 degrees Celsius), which then vaporises. As I noted earlier, this law undergirds
the famous sorites paradox and the idea of a tipping point popularised by Malcolm
Gladwell. Applied to development, this law hints of how development, like
the boiling water, can sneak up on us, with a country moving, imperceptibly,
from, say, being categorised as less developed to being seen as part of the lowermiddle income group. We thus find the United Nations Industrial Development
Organization (UNIDO 2018) listing several African countries among its lowermiddle income countries (with GDI of between US$1,006 and US$3955
[for 2018]) and middle-income countries (with GDI of between $3,958 and
$12,235). This list includes such countries as Angola, Botswana, Equatorial
Guinea, Mauritius, Namibia and South Africa within the former category; and
Cameroon, Côte d’Ivoire, Djibouti, Ghana, Kenya, Lesotho, Nigeria, Mauritania
and Zambia within the latter (UNIDO 2018).
The transformation from water to steam is often so imperceptible that
only the trained eye can spot it. Analogously, many African countries are not
‘developed’; yet, according to many international yardsticks, many of these same
countries are gradually getting to the tipping point, with some even tipping over,
quite imperceptibly, and moving into the middle-income status in recent years.
But many in the West – especially the Western media and the powers that be
– still see African countries only in a negative light, given the power dynamics
and mythologies in the prevailing system of global branding and knowledge
production.
Indeed, people who have lived in specific African countries for a long time
might not readily discern the development under way – the maxim familiarity
breeds contempt is applicable here. Meanwhile, to the circular or transnational
280
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
migrants in these countries, such development/changes are likely to be perceptible
during their visits. The same dynamics make it hard to see the extent to which
children are growing when they live with us, but their growth becomes discernible
when they do not live with us and we see them only occasionally. If there is a
tipping point in development, then we implicitly need to improve beyond some
threshold to be developed. Put another way, and quite metaphorically, we cannot
continue to boil our water of ‘underdevelopment’ to 99 degrees Celsius all the
time and expect a transformation into steam, or to a developed country, without
ever adding the requisite one degree Celsius of effort to tip us over.
Therefore, to be developed, we have move beyond the tipping point; without
putting in the extra work, however small that might be, it becomes difficult to
move into the realm of the developed world.
Conclusion: The Way Forward
It is clear from the preceding sections that to better grasp how African countries
in general or in their specificities are faring in terms of development, we first
have to see development as a dialectical process that entails creative destruction
and harbours internal contradictions. Thus, African development, like that of
any other region, is best conceived as a spiral process that involves negation
and sublation. Moreover, African development, like the development of other
regions of the world, exhibits aspects of the sorites paradox by which small
quantitative increments can lead to qualitative transformations. Additionally,
African development, like that of any other region, is best understood from a
multidisciplinary perspective, since it involves complex, cross-cutting processes,
with causes and effects being interchangeable. In the context of such complexities,
heterogeneities, tensions, and contradictions, what is the way forward? What
markers can we use as guideposts to promote socioeconomic and cultural
development in Africa? An appropriate starting point, drawing on the work
of Nkrumah (1964), would be to examine our conscience, and see where the
prospects and gaps in initiatives, ethics, and progressive ethos are, and nurture
a principled knowledge base or an overarching ideology of a sort to guide our
forward movement. As Nkrumah puts it so succinctly, ‘practice without thought
is blind; thought without practice is empty’ (1964:79).
For Nkrumah, there was no better ideology than socialism; and who can
blame him, given the struggles he had to spearhead to help extricate Ghana in
particular and Africa in general from the grip of imperial, capitalist domination
and exploitation by way of (neo)-colonialism? One does not necessarily have
to agree with Nkrumah’s zealous advocacy for socialism. What is important is
to have a knowledge base or an ideology capable of addressing the long-term
needs and welfare of Africans – a knowledge base or an ideology that is duly
informed by appropriate technologies, ethical principles, and progressive
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
281
African traditions such as humanism, egalitarianism, communalism, respect for
the elderly, etc. Conceived as such, the ideology becomes self-referential and,
consequently, authentic. On these principled African traditions, we cannot
entertain compromises, for any compromise on principles is tantamount to their
abandonment, as Nkrumah (1964) points out. Also, with dialectics in mind, the
need to eschew simplistic solutions for African development problems cannot be
overemphasised. Ultimately, a concerted effort is required if our creative forces
or positive actions are to surpass their destructive or negative counterparts in
the development process. The chapter opened with a prologue from Nkrumah
(1964), and what better way to end it than with an epilogue from him that
speaks quite dialectically to the tension between creative and destructive forces in
development, to wit:
Just as in the physical universe, since the moving object is always impressed
upon by external forces, any motion is in fact a resultant, so in society every
development, every progressive motion, is a resultant of unharmonious forces, a
resultant, a triumph of positive action over negative action (Nkrumah 1964:103).
Taking our inspiration from no less a person than Kwame Nkrumah, we need
to do everything it takes to ensure the lasting triumph of progressive forces
over reactionary ones in our quest for germane socio-economic and cultural
development in Africa.
Notes
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
Ironically, Hegel is one of the leading theorists of dialectics, as we shall see in this
chapter.
Interestingly, Socrates’ own mother, Phaenarete, was a midwife (Cornford 1957:24).
The French call him Antoine Guillaume Amo.
This is the point at which a series of small, imperceptible changes becomes significant
enough to cause a larger and readily discernible change.
The sub-title of this book, A Non-Communist Manifesto, was set as the counterpoint
to the famous Communist Manifesto by Marx and Engels.
References
Abraham, William E., 1996, ‘The Life and Times of Anton Wilhelm Amo, the First
African (Black) Philosopher in Europe’, in Molefi Kete Asante and Abu S. Abarry,
eds, African Intellectual Heritage: A Book of Sources, Philadelphia, PA: Temple
University Press, pp. 424–440.
Amin, Samir, 1976, Unequal Development: An Essay on the Social Formation of Peripheral
Capitalism, New York,NY: Monthly Review Press.
Amin, Samir, 1990, Delinking: Toward a Polycentric World, London, UK: Zed Books.
Berman, Jonathan, 2009, ‘Seven Reasons Why Africa’s Time is Now’, reprinted in
Harvard Business Review, October 2013, p.3.
282
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Cooper, John M. and Hutchinson, D.S., eds., 1997, Plato: Complete Works, Indianapolis,
IN and Cambridge, UK: Hackett Publishing Company.
Cornford, Francis. M., 1957, Plato’s Theory of Knowledge, New York, NY: The Liberal
Arts Press.
De Rivero, Oswaldo, 2001, The Myth of Development: The Non-Viable Economies of the
21st Century, London, UK and New York, NY: Zed Books.
Desai, Vandana and Potter, Robert B., 2008, The Companion to Development Studies,
London, UK: Hodder Education.
Economist, The, 2000, ‘Africa: The Hopeless Continent’, 13–19 May, London, UK.
(https://www.economist.com/weeklyedition/2000-05-13). 4 November 2021.
Edgar, Andrew, 1999, ‘Dialectics’, in Andrew Edgar and Peter Sedgwick, eds., Cultural
Theory: The Key Concepts, London, UK: Routledge.
Fanon, Frantz, 1967, Black Skin, White Masks, New York, NY: Grove.
Frank, A.G., 1967, Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America: Historical Studies
of Chile and Brazil, New York, NY and London, UK: Monthly Review Press.
Frank, A.G., 1979, Dependent Accumulation and Underdevelopment, New York,
NY: Monthly Review Press.
Gladwell, Malcolm, 2011, The Tipping Point: How Little Things Can Make a Big Difference,
New York, NY: Back Bay Books.
Harvey, David, 1996, Justice, Nature, and the Geography of Difference, Cambridge,
MA: Blackwell Publishers Inc.
Harvey, David, 2005, A Brief History of Neoliberalism, London, UK and New York,
NY: Oxford University Press.
Hegel, G.W.F., 1956 [1821], The Philosophy of History, translated J.H. Clarke, New York,
NY: Dover.
Hegel, G.W.F., 1967, The Phenomenology of the Mind, New York, NY: Harper & Row.
Jameson, F., 2010, Valences of the Dialectic, London, UK: Verso.
Kisak, P.F., 2021, Dialectics, Monee, IL: Createspace Independent Publishing.
Kuykendall, Ronald, 1993, ‘Hegel and Africa: An evaluation of the treatment of Africa in
the Philosophy of History’, Journal of Black Studies, Vol. 23, No. 4, p. 572.
Lewis, Arthur, W., 1955, The Theory of Economic Growth, London, UK: Routledge.
Matthews, Sally, 2004, ‘Post-development Theory and the Question of Alternatives: A
View from Africa’, Third World Quarterly, Vol 25, No. 2, pp. 373–384.
Mbembe, Achille, 2001, On the Postcolony, Berkeley, CA and London, UK: University of
California Press.
Mensah, J., 2006, ‘Cultural Dimensions of Globalization in Africa: A Dialectical
Interpenetration of the Local and the Global’, Studies in Political Economy, Vol. 77,
pp. 57–82.
Nikulin, D., 2010, Dialectic and Dialogue, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Nkrumah, Kwame, 1964, Consciencism: Philosophy and Ideology for Decolonization
and Development with Particular Reference to the African Revolution, London,
UK: Heinemann.
Ollman, Bertell, 2003, Dance of the Dialectic: Steps in Marx’s Method, Urbana and
Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.
Mensah: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
283
Rahnema, Majid and Bawtree, Victoria, eds., 1997, The Post-Development Reader,
London, UK: Zed Books.
Rostow, Walt Whitman, 1960, The Stages of Economic Growth: A Non-Communist
Manifesto, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Sachs, Jeffrey D., 2015, The Age of Sustainable Development, New York, NY: Columbia
University.
Schiappa, Edward, 1991, Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric,
Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press.
Schuurman, F.J., 2008, ‘The Impasse in Development Studies’ in V. Desai and R. B. Potter,
eds., The Companion to Development Studies, London, UK: Hodder Education,
pp. 12–16.
Seers, Dudley, 1963, ‘The meaning of development’, International Development Review,
Vol. 11, No. 4, pp. 3–4.
Seers, Dudley, 1983, The Political Economy of Nationalism, New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Sen, Amartya K., 1999, Development as Freedom, New York, NY: Alfred A Knopf.
UNIDO, 2018, Industrial Development Report 2018. (https://www.unido.org/resourcespublications-flagship-publications-industrial-development-report-series/industrialdevelopment-report-2018). 11 November 2021.
United States Department of State, 2020, Country Report on Human Rights Practices:
Rwanda. (https://www.state.gov/reports/2020-country-reports-on-human-rightspractices/rwanda/). 10 November 2021.
Wallerstein, Immanuel, 1980, The Modern World System, Vol 2: Mercantilism and
Consolidation of the European World-Economy in the Sixteenth Century, New York,
NY: Academic Press.
Woods, Alan and Grant, Ted, 2002, Dialectical Philosophy and Modern Science: Reason in
Revolt, New York, NY: Algora Publishing.
11
Theorising Norms:
Constructivism and its Application to the Study
of Africa’s International Relations
Anthony Bizos
As a scholar of International Relations (IR) I have always been interested in
the question of why and how norms matter, both in the theory and practice of
international politics. Having been inducted into the discipline via the established
canon of classical realism, I was taught that states are the only relevant actors
in international relations and that the international system is characterised by
anarchy. As a result, in the absence of a centralised authority capable of enforcing
the rule of law, it is assumed by realists that states in the system are conditioned by
self-help and that it is ‘every country for itself ’ in the pursuit of power and security.
This type of determinism, however, suddenly became incommensurate with my
ability to explain trends in international politics, especially after the end of the
Cold War. Since the early 1990s, it has appeared that states and new international
actors are more prone to observing implicit and explicit rules, and are regulating
their behaviour toward cooperation; even in the absence of a centralised authority
which is capable of enforcing injunctions with these rules. In this chapter, I show
how norms go a long way in accounting for this phenomenon, how norms can
now justifiably be considered to be part of IR’s established toolkit for analysing
and theorising the behaviour of international actors, and why the study of norms
is concomitantly the study of Africa’s international relations.
In Martha Finnemore and Kathryn Sikkink’s classic definition, norms are
‘shared ideas, expectations and beliefs about appropriate behaviour’ which give the
world ‘structure, order and stability’ (1998:894). Charlotte Epstein observes that
‘in the history of the discipline, norms – along with their conceptual counterpart,
identity – have played a crucial role in moving IR beyond its narrow focus upon
286
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
material understandings of power and interest-maximising behaviours’ (2017:2).
She proceeds to say that, ‘whether practically (they sustain co-operation) or for
their theoretical contribution (bringing ideational and social dynamics into
sight), norms, then, would appear to be good things for international politics’
(Epstein 2017:2). In the practice of international relations, norms regulate and
constrain the behaviour of utility-maximising actors by socialising them into an
international society which promotes compliance with standards of acceptable
behaviour. In respect of theory, the presence of norms suggests that the structures
of international politics are not just material, but are also social and ideational.
Through their interactions in international society, actors come to learn about
their identity and interests, so that norms can be said to have a constitutive effect
on actors too.
To be clear, norms are understood differently by scholars of international
law and IR. Whereas legal norms impose binding legal obligations, political
norms establish moral obligations. According to Ramesh Thakur, in regulating
the conduct of actors, both laws and norms provide enabling (license) and
restraining (leash) functions. However, political norms are compelling because
they do not necessarily need to be codified into law – the moral authority of these
norms by themselves exerts a powerful ‘compliance pull’ (Thakur 2019:220).
As standards of appropriate behaviour, political norms either prescribe or
proscribe action to conform to the norm. In this sense, norms matter because
actors care about what others think of them. Therefore, approbation and its
corollary, shaming, are effective in regulating social behaviour. According to
Thakur, ‘to be a member in good standing of a community is to subscribe to its
moral framework and core values, and the behavioural prescription is not Do
X in order to get Y, a la rules, but You should do X because good people do X,
a la norms’ (Thakur 2019:221).
This chapter proceeds in three major sections. The first section shows how
the ‘constructivist turn’ in IR theorising during the 1990s brought the study
of norms squarely into the discipline’s empirical research programme. This
section highlights some of constructivism’s central theoretical assumptions so as
to demonstrate how constructivism’s focus on the role of norms, interests and
identity provides important and distinctive theoretical and empirical insights
for understanding global politics. The second section defines norms so as to
operationalise them, and it makes a case for why norms matter and how they
potentially provide the world with order, structure and stability. It concludes
by showing how conventional constructivists are now endeavouring to theorise
about how norms emerge, how they are diffused in international society, and how
they are internalised by actors. The third section offers some tentative reflections
on how the global power asymmetry continues to marginalise Africa as an object
of subjectivity in international affairs, and how the universalising nature of norms
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
287
theorising potentially erases how norm dynamics are also frequently authored
and structured in important ways by non-Western actors. Thus, the final section
of this chapter is a clarion call for scholars of Africa’s international relations to
critically engage with constructivism and the study of norms and agency, so as to
draw attention to the way in which alternative constitutive norms might form the
basis whereby a future international system might develop.
The ‘Constructivist-Turn’ in International Relations Theorising
It is now generally recognised that constructivism is one of the youngest of
the mainstream theories in IR. It entered into the discipline as a result of the
Third (great inter-paradigm) Debate between rationalists and emerging critical
international theorists during the late 1980s. (In IR theory, the Great Debates
refer to a series of disagreements between scholars, beginning in the 1930s). The
‘reflectivist’ orientation of Critical International Theory served as a progenitor for
the ‘constructivist turn in IR,’ which came to be reinforced by three inter-related
factors. The first factor was that neoliberals and neorealists, who had traditionally
dominated the theoretical ‘turf ’ of the discipline, came to accept that ‘reflectivist’
theories could offer alternative insights into the intersubjective foundations of
IR. The second factor was that the relatively peaceful conclusion of the Cold War
demonstrated the inability of dominant rationalist theories to account for such
dramatic international change, and the third factor was a generational change of
scholars in the discipline who had come to be influenced by the assumptions of
Third Debate critical theories (Price & Reus-Smit 1998).
It was however an influential article by Emanuel Adler titled ‘Seizing the
Middle Ground: Constructivism in World Politics’ published in the European
Journal of International Relations in 1997 which positioned constructivism
squarely into the theoretical mainstream of the discipline. Adler defined
constructivism as the view that ‘the manner in which the material world shapes
and is shaped by human action and interaction depends on dynamic normative
and epistemic interpretations of the material world’ (1997:322). Significantly,
Adler’s article also positioned constructivism as occupying the ‘middle ground’
in IR Theory between materialist theories which see political behaviour as
determined by the physical world alone and individualist theories which treat
collective understandings as simply epiphenomena of individual action and deny
that they have causal power or ontological status (Finnemore & Sikkink 2001).
To be sure, constructivism is not a single unified theory. To be frank, since it
does not present a set of coherent hypotheses a priori, one might wonder about
the extent to which it constitutes a theory at all. Ruggie appropriately suggests that
constructivism is a ‘theoretically informed approach to the study of IR’ (1998:880).
Therefore, it is probably best to use the term theory a lot more ‘loosely’ when
discussing constructivism. I would suggest that constructivism is a compendium
288
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
of different approaches which operate within a series of core assumptions upon
which more specific hypotheses and arguments can be formulated. Social
constructivists, for example, describe their task as ‘understanding’, and they
endeavour to comprehend the subjective motives and worldviews of actors
and how these help to ‘construct’ the social world. Conventional or modernist
constructivists alternately have a cognitive interest in understanding and
explaining social reality, and they are concerned with uncovering the causal
social mechanisms and constitutive social relations which affect the practice of
international relations. Modernist linguistic constructivists attempt to better
understand social reality by uncovering the processes by which social facts are
constituted by rules and language. Critical constructivists associate themselves
with pragmatic realism, as well as an emancipatory agenda, to interrogate the
mechanisms on which social and political orders are based in order to show how
the knowledge/power nexus serves to produce and reproduce the hegemonic
world order.
In the most general sense, constructivism can be said to be an approach to
social analysis which is based on the following basic assumptions:
1. human interaction is not shaped by material factors, but primarily by
ideational ones;
2. the most significant ideational factors in this context are ‘inter-subjective
beliefs as shared collective understanding’; and
3. these beliefs construct the actors’ identities and interests (Finnemore &
Sikkink 2001:393).
Despite its various approaches, one might therefore conclude that constructivism’s
‘value-addition’ to the study of IR is its emphasis on the ontological reality
of intersubjective knowledge and the epistemological and methodological
implications of this reality (Adler 1997).
Ontologically, constructivism sees the social world as being constituted
intersubjectively. Since constructivists do not accept any social features of life
as given, they recognise that actors are always situated in particular contexts
which influence their actions, and that actors reproduce and construct their
‘world’ through their actions. In this sense, material resources and interests only
acquire meaning for human action through the structures of shared knowledge
in which they are embedded. Simply put, social facts are dependent on the ability
of actors to attach collective knowledge to material reality. Social facts are then
reinforced through practice. Over time social facts become reified through social
relations, rules, and routine practices, and appear as an objective reality which
exists independently from those actors who constructed the social facts in the first
place (Flockhart 2012).
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
289
Epistemologically, constructivists are generally skeptical about claims
to ‘all-encompassing truth’. Rather they highlight that ‘understanding’ and
interpretation are central to ascribing valid knowledge to the social sciences. This
is not to suggest that all constructivist approaches reject the methodological and
epistemological tenets of positivism or scientific realism in their enquiry. It is just
that constructivists argue that generalisations about knowledge can at best be
contingent. Conventional constructivists in particular are now interested in how
intersubjective knowledge and ideational phenomena have constitutive effects on
social reality and how this social reality changes. They also attempt to explain how
actors converge around norms, identities and cause-effect understandings; how
actors derive their interests from them; and how, once institutionalised, these
factors become the source of international practice.
Since constructivists endogenise norms, interests and identity into their
research agenda, these aspects become promising explanatory variables in the
study of global politics. Identity, for example, is recognised as a variable which
can account for international behaviour and institutional change. Constructivists
show how actors in international relations are influenced by their identity, as well
as by the historical, political, cultural and social contexts in which they exist.
Identities are therefore said to reflect a particular set of interests and preferences in
respect of an actor’s choice of action. Therefore, because identities are susceptible
to change, so are interests. Constructivists also study norms because they consider
them to be constitutive of social identities and because they provide the content
and meaning of national interests. In other words, the way in which actors apply
norms to classify their world is central to how world politics occurs since actors do
not only act in the context of their capabilities and interests, but also in response
to their normative environment and the normative understandings which they
attach to those interests.
Methodologically, constructivism begins from the premise that explaining
causal processes requires an interpretive activity of uncovering intersubjective
meanings. Constructivists predominantly draw causal or constitutive inferences
using historical narratives. Since social reality is indeterminate and contingent,
these narratives need to be reconstructed because the way in which social facts
become established in the social world is linked to the way in which they exert
their influence. Constructivists therefore endeavour to describe the relationship
between partly indeterminate processes and partly determinate outcomes in order
to isolate specific social structures, social mechanisms, and empirical regularities.
Constructivists are also concerned with explaining change. Nonetheless, rather
than understanding change as a shift in the positioning of material resources,
they focus on the emergence of new constitutive rules, the evolution and
transformation of new social structures, and the role of agents in the origins of
these social processes (Adler 2013).
290
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Thus, according to Steans and colleagues, the main assumptions of
constructivism can best be summarised as follows (Steans et al. 2010:200):
1. The gap between structure and agency-centred theories can be bridged.
Constructivists emphasise that structure and agency are mutually dependent.
Despite the fact that most social relations are relatively stable, the ongoing
reproduction of structures can bring with it the potential for change.
2. Structures are both material and ideational. Since ideational structures are not
immediately observable, constructivists adopt the epistemological view that
we can deduce the existence of these structures from their effects, which they
influence but do not necessarily determine.
3. The societal aspect of international relations is just as important as the
mechanistic qualities of the international system espoused by more structural
and rationalist theories.
4. Norms are important determinants of actor behaviour. In international
relations, interactions among actors are not only a matter of interests, but also
of acceptable behaviour in international society.
5. Interest is a category that needs to be explained, as opposed to being treated as
an explanatory factor.
On Norms, Identity and Behaviour
As perhaps the most influential figure within social constructivism, Alexander
Wendt provides some illuminating insights into how structure and agency are
mutually constitutive of each other; and how collective identities are formed in
international relations in spite of the presence of anarchy. In his article titled
‘The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory’ published
in International Organization in 1987, Wendt demonstrates how Neorealist
Theory and World-Systems Theory came to influence academic discourse
about international relations because of their respective claims that they offered
‘structural’ explanations for how states behave in the international system. Wendt
shows, however, that despite their common commitment to structural analysis,
the two theories differ in respect of their understanding of structure and, thus,
in their structural explanations for behaviour in the international system. He
explicates how neorealists define the structures of the international system in terms
of the observable attributes of member states and the subsequent distribution
of capabilities. In this sense, neorealists understand the explanatory role of
these structures in individualist terms as constraining the choices of preexisting
state actors. Alternately, World-Systems theorists explain the structures in the
international system as a consequence of the fundamental organising principles
of the capitalist world economy which underlie and constitute states, so that
they understand the explanatory role of structures in ‘structuralist’ terms as
predetermining and generating state actors themselves (Wendt 1987).
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
291
Subsequently, Wendt borrows from scholars in the field of sociology, and
especially from Anthony Giddens’ Structuration Theory proffered in 1984 to
propose a symbolic ‘sociological type’ systemic theory to explore how the process
of interaction and learning might actually explain how power politics is socially
constructed under anarchy, and how agency might be reintroduced into the
study of international relations (Wendt 1987). Central to Giddens’ Structuration
Theory is that while action is influenced and constrained by social structures,
these structures are in turn reproduced by agency. Similarly, Wendt suggests
that one needs to conceptualise agents and structures as mutually constitutive,
yet ontologically distinct, entities. He argues that, ‘although each is in some
sense an effect of the other, they are codetermined because social structures are
the result of the intended and unintended consequences of human action, just
as the latter presuppose or are mediated by an irreducible structural context’
(Wendt 1987:360).
Wendt develops many of these ideas in perhaps his most famous article,
published in International Organization in 1992 and titled ‘Anarchy Is What
States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics’. In this article,
Wendt interrogates the extent to which state action is influenced by structure
(anarchy and the distribution of power) versus process (understood as interaction
and learning). As a result, he poses the following two important questions:
1. ‘Does the absence of centralised political authority force states to play
competitive power politics?’
2. ‘What in anarchy is given and immutable, and what is amenable to change?’.
It is important to recognise here that Wendt is responding primarily to
neorealist theorising about international relations. According to the ‘father’ of
neorealism, Kenneth Waltz, who published a seminal book in 1979 titled Theory
of International Politics, the international system is decentralised and anarchic.
For Waltz, the international structure emerged from the coexistence of states; and
while states are not the only international actors, they are the major ones because
they define the structure of international politics and tend not to participate in
the formation of a structure which will constrain them (Waltz 1979).
What follows for Waltz is that anarchy, as a constant, is reproduced as states
seek to protect themselves from the military threats presented by other states. For
Waltz, since the most important characteristic of the structure of the international
system is the distribution of power, states are differentiated based on their material
capabilities in relation to other states. In the absence of an international central
authority, it is therefore only the balancing of power between competing state
alliances, as opposed to the behavioural constraints provided by norms, which
can account for a semblance of international peace and stability.
292
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Wendt (1992) disagrees with Waltz and argues that multiple logics can exist in
anarchic structures, thereby implying that anarchy is amenable to change. Wendt
also pointedly argues that anarchy as understood by neorealists is an empty vessel
with no intrinsic logic. In his analysis, Wendt claims that there are three different
cultures of anarchy:
1. Hobbesian,
2. Lockean, and
3. Kantian.
In each culture, a dissimilar structure of roles determines the international
system – enemy, rival, and friend, respectively. In other words, there actually exist
different ‘anarchies’ which vary substantially, depending on the roles and cultures
that dominate the system (Jung 2019).
Wendt additionally demonstrates how interaction and learning can mitigate
against states playing competitive power politics in the absence of a centralised
political authority. According to him, this has everything to do with socialisation
and collective identity formation. Also, for him, intersubjective understandings
and expectations, coupled with the distribution of knowledge, are the means
by which actors constitute conceptions of self and other. Identities therefore
are relational because actors impute role-specific understandings of the self by
participating in collective meanings with others. The structure of the social
world is therefore not logically constituted by anarchy, but rather by the
theories which actors hold collectively about themselves and one another. In
this way, ‘identities form the basis of interests because actors do not ordinarily
have a portfolio of interests that they carry around independent of social
context; instead, they define their interests in the process of defining situations’
(Wendt 1992:398). In addition, for Wendt, as actors continue to interact, they
contribute to one another’s pool of knowledge through reinforcement and
reciprocal ‘typifications’. Therefore, according to him, this aspect establishes
relatively stable concepts of self and other in relation to a situation or issues
at stake in the interaction. Hence, contrary to neorealist thinking, structures
are not fixed. As a result of reciprocal interaction, actors can transform or
even sustain relatively enduring social structures through which identities and
interests can be defined (Wendt 1992).
Unlike the approaches employed by rationalists and structuralists, social
constructivists perceive actors as social objects, and social identities are essentially
understood as sets of meanings which actors attribute to themselves while taking
the perspective of others into account. By endogenising norms, identities and
interests into the system, social constructivists make provision for an empirical
research agenda to determine how deeply these identities need to be instantiated
in social structures to influence conceptions of self and interests. In a subsequent
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
293
article published in the American Political Science Review in 1994 and titled
‘Collective Identity Formation and the International State’, Wendt suggests that
it stands to reason that the degree to which social identities positively identify
with the fate of the other determines the difference between the propensity for
actor egoism in the pursuit of interests and the possibility of a collective definition
of interests inspired by a high level of social aggregation, diffuse reciprocity, and
the desire to bear costs without selective incentives (Wendt 1994).
Wendt therefore demonstrates that through repeated acts of interaction and
cooperation in the international arena, actors can learn about their interests
and form collective identities by seeing themselves in relation to what others
‘do’. Wendt’s more sociological approach to international relations subsequently
highlights the importance of intersubjective knowledge; since by demonstrating
through cooperative acts that one expects others to be cooperators too, international
actors change the terms by which identities and interests are defined. In other
words, ‘by teaching others and themselves to cooperate, actors are simultaneously
learning to identify with each other and therefore to see themselves as a “we”
bound by certain norms’ (Wendt 1994:390).
It can be said that constructivism makes a significant ontological progression
from rationalist and neorealist understandings of international behaviour.
Rationalists for example adopt a behavioural analytical approach based strictly
on utility maximisation. They assume that given a series of options, actors pick
the option which best serves their objectives and interests. This typically takes the
form of material gains. In this sense, actor knowledge of interests is assumed a
priori, and norms and social structures are perceived to, at most, merely constrain
the choices and behaviour of self-interested actors. For neorealists, however, all
phenomena, with the exception of the state, are exogenised from the system.
They regard the principle of pursuing competitive losses and gains as immutable
to the nature of states, and they also do not account for the way in which the
larger international structure might socialise and adjust the character of these
states. Additionally, Neorealism’s identification with a Hobbesian state of nature
does not allow for further learning, whereby states might learn about the system
of anarchy and potentially change it.
Nonetheless, constructivists do accept the contribution made by neoliberal
regimes analysis to the study of norms and behaviour in IR. The regimes
project came to be associated with Stephen Krasner’s 1982 exploration of the
characteristics of international regimes, which he defined as, ‘social institutions
which are distinguishable by agreed-upon principles, norms, rules and
procedures that regulate the interaction of actors in specific issue areas’ (Krasner
1982:185). Neoliberal regimes analysts were mainly interested in examining
what prompted states to establish institutions, even if the latter (i.e. The General
Agreement on Tariffs and Trade) were ostensibly contrary to the formers’ (i.e.
294
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
industrialised countries acquiescing to a generalised system of trade preferences)
short-term interests. They concluded that regimes persist because even though
intergovernmental cooperation involves negotiation around universally acceptable
norms, norm realisation is left to the discretion of individual sovereign states.
While recognising this contribution, constructivists considered this
promotional approach to norm realisation to be inadequate, since it implied
that states could choose to be part of a regime and increase their international
legitimacy without incurring substantial costs, and they also could remain part of
a regime, even if they did not intend implementing the norms associated with it
(Zwingel 2012). Constructivists also insist that similarly to rationalist accounts,
Regimes Theory views norms as a constraint on states (through institutional
arrangements) as opposed to perceiving norms as being constitutive of state
interests. Therefore, according to constructivists, whereas regimes do combine
regulative and procedural norms to change the environment in which actors
pursue their interests, the latter are still regarded as fixed and, therefore, similarly
to realism, regimes analysis considers norms as separate rather than constitutive
of interests (Klotz 1995).
For constructivists, the social context is rule-governed. Therefore, it is said that
actors may behave according to the logic of appropriateness, whereby reasoning is
metaphorical and not necessarily influenced strictly by utility maximisation. For
constructivists, by interrogating the type of situation and their desired course of
action, actors are constituted by norms and rules, since the latter help to provide
answers and also to develop the agents’ understanding of their interests. Whereas
constructivists might agree with realists and liberalists that actors are also driven
by a logic of consequences, and that they calculate the consequences of a particular
course of action on the basis that it offers them the most utility, they concurrently
allow for the possibility that actors might act from a logic of appropriateness too.
The reasoning here is that as rule followers, actors will attempt to follow rules
that connect particular identities to particular situations. This subsequently
allows actors to consider which action constitutes the most appropriate behaviour
for them.
Hence, constructivists demonstrate that the logic of appropriateness is just
as plausible a predictor of actor and state behaviour as the rationalists’ logic of
consequences. According to James G. March and Johan P. Olsen (1995), the logic
of appropriateness is a sociological perspective that sees human action as driven
by rules of appropriate or exemplary behaviour organised into institutions. Actors
follow rules because they are seen as ‘natural, rightful, expected and legitimate,
and actors seek to fulfill the obligations encapsulated in a role, an identity, a
membership in a political community or group, and the ethos, practices and
expectations of its institutions’ (March & Olsen 1995:3).
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
295
On Norms and Why They Matter
According to constructivists, norms specify the appropriate behaviour for an
agent with a given identity. Whereas constructivists often use the terms ‘ideas’ and
‘norms’ interchangeably, the key distinction is that ideas can be held individually,
whereas norms are collectively shared. For constructivists, norms are cognitive
‘maps’ which allow actors to discern what appropriate or inappropriate behaviour
is. In addition, norms perform a structural function since they have a causal and
constitutive effect on actor identities and interests. In the final analysis, because
norms both constrain behaviour and constitute identities and interests, they are
considered by constructivists to be ‘structures of relevance’ (Flockhart 2012:84).
The constructivist definition of the term ‘norm’ revolves around two related
meanings. On the one hand, norms reflect actual patterns of behaviour, and they
create expectations about what will be done in practice in a particular situation.
On the other hand, norms are more specific, since they reflect patterned behaviour
of a particular kind. This latter type of behaviour is prescribed and gives rise to
normative expectations about what ‘ought’ to be done. As a result, the regularity
of behaviour is connected to an internal attitude which involves self-criticism
or the criticism of others on the basis that a particular norm is being violated.
Norms therefore are prescriptive statements which contain both procedural and
substantive elements. They prescribe action in situations of choice, and they also
carry a sense of obligation and a sense that they ought to be followed (Hurrell
2013). For constructivists, norms can be said to be regulative when they proscribe
and prescribe behaviour that regulates how actors in international society act since
they formally establish or enable certain kinds of activities. Norms, however, can
be said to be constitutive when they define the distinguishing characteristics of
an actor. Constitutive norms are therefore powerful because they establish a sense
of group identification which then allows for the coordination of social power.
Irrespective of whether norms are regulative or constitutive, for constructivists,
both types represent an expression of belief that concurrently provides impetus for
behaviour consistent with that belief. For constructivists, norms are considered
to have intersubjective qualities because they are collective expectations, and
‘proper behaviour presupposes the existence of a community which is able to pass
judgement on appropriateness’ (Risse et al. 1999:7). According to constructivists,
norm-breaking behaviour can be recognised as a result of the stigma and
disapproval it generates within a community or society, whereas norm-compliant
behaviour can be identified because of the praise it elicits, or because a norm has
an established ‘taken for granted’ quality that it requires no reaction whatsoever
(Finnemore & Sikkink 1998). Constructivists do, however, caution that whereas
norms often encourage a certain type of action, they do not always determine
behaviour. Norms assist with shaping the identities and preferences of actors
because they set standards of conduct and define the range of appropriate options
296
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
by correlating deviant actions with negative and moral connotations. According
to Paul Williams, ‘proof of a norm’s existence is not necessarily that members of
the community never violate it… rather the strength of a norm can be measured
by the level of opprobrium members of the community face from their peers for
engaging in behaviour that violates the norm’ (2007:258).
Proceeding from Williams’s point, it follows that constructivists prefer
to speak of an international society as opposed to an international system.
Conceptually, the idea of an international society is derived from the English
School which arose during the 1970s in response to the United States dominance
in IR theorising. Unlike more positivistic approaches which sought to establish
‘mechanistic’ laws and a universally applicable theory of international politics,
the English School sought to interpret international relations as being social and
historical. According to Hedley Bull (1977), who is considered to be the School’s
most famous proponent, an international society can be defined as, ‘a group of
states (or, more generally, a group of independent political communities) which
not merely form a system, in the sense that the behaviour of each is a necessary
factor in the calculations of the others, but also have established dialogue and
consent to common rules and institutions for the conduct of their relations,
and recognise their common interest in maintaining these arrangements’ (Bull
1977:13). Therefore, for the English School, despite the presence of anarchy, and
in spite of the absence of a formal hierarchy governing international relations,
there is a societal aspect to international politics in which international law and
norms can act as guarantors of order.
Borrowing from the English School, constructivists argue that norms are
a central feature in the construction of international society because they help
to constitute the actors in the society by identifying who the actors are and by
conferring rights and responsibilities upon them. Additionally, constructivists say
that norms provide a framework for meaningful communication among actors
in an international society, since norms language frames the way in which states
justify their behaviour, and it provides a means for international society to evaluate
those claims (Bellamy 2004). For constructivists, membership in an international
society also allows for social learning since, through interaction, states have to
learn about the norms and rules of the international society. Constructivists also
suggest that the success of learning processes is contingent on the quality and
quantity of such learning, so that when actors interact within an institutional and
bureaucratic setting, learning tends to be more substantive because it becomes
embedded in a common institutional memory (Bellamy 2004).
Nonetheless, constructivists do continue to debate as to whether norms should
be conflated with institutions. One might argue that this is a consequence of the
way in which the different constructivist approaches operationalise institutions in
concrete studies. Institutions are alternately regarded by constructivists as either
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
297
formal or informal. In a formal sense, institutions are understood as written or
explicitly acknowledged principles, rules and norms; whereas in the informal
sense, institutions are regarded merely as stable patterns of practice which are the
consequence of the same pattern of behaviour over a longer period of time.
Whereas some constructivists argue that norms do not always need to be
institutionalised in one organisational setting or discrete issue area, and that
international norms provide a level of order and predictability to world politics,
there are those constructivists such as Peter Katzenstein who contend that ‘norms
do not float freely in political space’ (1996:21). According to Katzenstein, norms
only acquire domestic and international importance when they are crystallised
through institutionalisation. He also argues that once they are institutionalised,
norms go beyond simply expressing individually-held preferences, values or ideas
because they now become collectively held, and they exist external to actors.
Correspondingly, Katzenstein suggests that institutionalised norms become part
of an objective reality that ‘often, though not always, commands some formal
sanctioning mechanisms’ (Katzenstein 1996:21).
This section of the chapter has thus far shown how constructivism’s theoretical
focus on the relationship between norms, identity, interests and institutions
provides us with distinct ways for understanding social and international reality.
In particular, constructivists demonstrate that ideational phenomena such as
norms not only serve to regulate the behaviour of actors, but also that norms
themselves can in fact become constitutive of power and interests. Constructivism
is therefore a significant theoretical progression from the neorealist and rationalist
explanations of international relations which have traditionally dominated the
discipline. For neorealists, norms only matter to the extent that they reflect, or are
sustained, by the material strength of powerful actors. For rationalists, norms and
institutions are only relevant to the extent that they affect actor strategies, but not
necessarily their underlying preferences. As a result, unlike constructivism, these
approaches merely ‘instrumentalise’ as opposed to ‘endogenise’ norms into their
explanations of international politics.
Constructivist Scholarship and Theorising Norm Diffusion
Here, I want to briefly allude to how conventional (empirical) constructivist
scholars are now attempting to explain how norms emerge, how they are diffused
in international society, and how they are internalised by actors. One can categorise
this scholarship into three discernable chronological waves, whereby each wave
can be distinguished by specific ontological and epistemological assumptions in
respect of the agent-structure debate, what are considered to be causal versus
constitutive explanations for how norms are diffused and internalised, as well as
the nature of agency in international relations.
298
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
The need to now speak of conventional or empirical constructivism arose out
of a major debate among constructivist scholars during the late 1990s which
suggested that constructivism’s study of norms was potentially limiting, since its
theoretical framework overemphasised the role of structures and norms at the
expense of agents who established and changed them in the first place. Jeffrey
Checkel (1999), for example, argued that constructivism failed to explore in a
systematic manner the mechanisms through which international norms reached
the domestic arena and therefore had constitutive effects, and that constructivism
could not account for how the same norm would have a significant constitutive
impact in one state but would fail to achieve this in another. Earlier, Checkel
(1998) had also argued that even though constructivism had shown that social
construction was relevant, it did not clearly address when, how, or why this
occurred. Thus, he suggested that constructivists had developed a reputation for
displaying empirical ‘adhocism’ when describing the actors and mechanisms that
brought about change, the scope conditions under which they behaved, and how
they varied across countries (Checkel 1998).
In response to this criticism, constructivist scholars such as Martha
Finnemore and Kathryn Sikkink (1998) began to caution that research which
developed arguments about norms, culture, and ideas had to be specific about
ideational causal claims and mechanisms; be transparent about the microfoundations on which theoretical claims about norms were based; and should
be capable of evaluating those claims using carefully considered historical and
empirical research. Similarly, Audie Klotz (1995) insisted that research designs
which considered constitutive norms to be independent variables, and which
were capable of determining actor identities and interests, needed to specifically
isolate the mechanisms whereby these norms defined and redefined those
identities and interests.
In an effort to develop a middle-order theory about norms, many constructivist
scholars began to
1. generate more concrete propositions about them,
2. provide greater conceptual precision in the operationalisation of norms,
3. explain the relationship between domestic and international norms, and
4. interrogate whether norms were agents of stability or change.
This is most clearly articulated in the conventional constructivist scholarship on
norm diffusion. For the purposes of this chapter, norm diffusion can be simply
defined as the process whereby norms travel from one political actor to another
and between different places and contexts. Theorising about norm diffusion
therefore requires asking questions about how norms originate, how they travel
between states and other actors, how they are adopted, how they influence
behaviour, and how they change during this process.
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
299
The conventional constructivist scholarship on norm diffusion is rich and
abundant. Space constraints, however, do not allow me to explicate all of the
scholarship in detail here. It suffices to say that the first wave of diffusion scholarship
(throughout the 1990s) focused on how presumably ‘good’ international norms
such as human rights and democracy were diffused internationally to the
national level, as well as the role played by non-governmental, trans-national
and international organisations in this process. The prominent models which
arose to account for norm diffusion during this wave were the norm life-cycle
model (Finnemore & Sikkink 1998), the spiral model (Risse, Ropp & Sikkink
1999), and the boomerang model (Keck & Sikkink 1999). The norm life-cycle
model focuses on the purposive efforts of individual norm entrepreneurs and
groups that endeavour to change existing norms and rules in the area of global
politics or, alternately, that attempt to introduce new norms by persuading a
critical mass of norm leaders to internalise these norms. The spiral model explains
how international human rights norms are diffused to recalcitrant states. This
model sets out five stages to account for this process. These are:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
repression and the activation of network,
denial,
tactical concessions,
prescriptive status, and
rule-consistent behaviour.
The boomerang model focuses on the role played by transnational advocacy
networks in the process of norm diffusion. Since individuals and domestic groups
are often unable to work within a country to stop governments from violating
a certain norm, they seek out international actors to put pressure on the normviolating government from the outside.
The second wave of scholarship (early 2000s) focused predominantly on
explaining how and why international norms were changed by norm-adopting
states in their domestic contexts so as to suit their own prior normative
backgrounds. The most significant models which arose to account for this
phenomenon during the second wave were cultural match (Checkel 1999), norm
localisation (Acharya 2004), and norm vernacularisation (Levitt & Merry 2009).
Cultural match proposes that the internalisation of an international norm is more
probable if it is ‘convergent’ with domestic norms and culture. In cultural match
this convergence operates along a continuum. It can be positive, in which case
the international and domestic norm are compatible; it can be in the middle, in
which case there are few barriers to diffusion; or it could be negative, in which
case there is no congruence between the international and the domestic norm.
Norm localisation examines how domestic actors change foreign norms to ‘fit’
with local beliefs and practices. As a result, domestic actors actively seek out
foreign norms and ideas that can enhance the legitimacy of existing practices
300
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
without altering local identities. The concept of vernacularisation refers to actors
such as non-governmental organisations that intervene between transnational
norms and local populations in the process of diffusion. Vernacularisers take the
ideas of one group and reframe them in a way which the other group will accept.
As a result, transnational norms are presented in a way that resonates with local
beliefs, yet they stay sufficiently different to challenge those beliefs.
The third wave (late-2000s to the present) concentrates on explaining how
materially weaker states can contest and even change international norms, how
they promote their own norms internationally, and how they can reinforce or
outright reject international norms. The most compelling models which have
been developed during this wave of scholarship are norm subsidiarity (Acharya
2011a), norm circulation (Acharya 2013), and norm contestation (Zimmerman,
Deitelhoff & Lesch 2017). Norm subsidiarity focuses on the under-studied
phenomenon of how materially weaker actors are able to resist the norms of
stronger ones, and how weaker actors can reference existing international norms
to expose the hypocrisy of stronger ones. Norm subsidiarity sees weaker actors as
either rejecting foreign norms in favour of their own, or amplifying international
norms so as to constrain the behaviour of powerful actors from violating them.
Norm circulation builds on the concepts of localisation and subsidiarity. This
model contends that there is a need to focus on agency and feedback in norm
dynamics. According to this model, new international norms are more likely to
spread if the responsibility for their development and diffusion is seen to have
been more broadly shared, rather than their origins being accredited to any one
particular group. Since norms are applied in different contexts and locations,
feedback constitutes an important form of agency because it serves to broaden the
legitimacy and appeal of the new norm. Norm contestation highlights how dissent
can lead to a change in the international norm. According to this model, there
are two types of contestation:
1. validity contestation and
2. application contestation.
Validity contestation occurs when the norm itself becomes contested
internationally. If those who dissent against the norm succeed in their endeavour,
then the norm is completely abolished. Application contestation leads to debates
about whether the application of a norm is appropriate in a given situation.
These debates change the norm’s application incrementally, and potentially even
strengthen it, since contestation also serves to clarify what type of behaviour
conforms to the norm.
I will in the rest of this section talk a bit more about the norm life-cycle model,
the norm localisation model, and the norm subsidiarity model. The purpose is to
demonstrate the progression of thought between these three waves as well as to
set the foundation for the final section of this chapter.
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
301
The Norm-life Cycle Model
As part of the first wave of conventional constructivist scholarship on norm
emergence and diffusion, the norm life-cycle model developed by Martha
Finnemore and Kathryn Sikkink (1998) suggests that international norms
evolve in patterned life cycles and that norm influence and diffusion can be
explained as a three-stage process. The first stage is characterised by norm
emergence, whereby norm entrepreneurs have to ‘frame’ new issue areas so that
they resonate with broader public perceptions and understandings (Finnemore
& Sikkink 1998).
During the emergence stage, norm entrepreneurs require an organisational
platform to promote their norms. In this respect, norm entrepreneurs have to
persuade, as opposed to coerce, state actors in these organisations to endorse their
norms and to make them part of the organisation’s norm socialisation agenda.
Finnemore and Sikkink suggest that an emerging norm reaches its threshold
when it has been institutionalised in specific sets of international rules and
organisations. They further argue that institutionalisation implies that there is
clarity as to what exactly the norm is, what constitutes violation (even though this
often remains a contentious issue area), and what specific procedures are offered
whereby norm leaders may express disapproval and sanction for norm violation
(Finnemore & Sikkink 1998).
The second stage of the norm life-cycle model is characterised by norm acceptance
or norm cascade. This stage usually involves the ‘dynamic of imitation’ whereby
norm leaders endeavour to socialise an even larger set of states to become norm
followers. As a consequence of contagion, a greater number of countries begin to
adopt the new norm, irrespective of whether there is domestic pressure to do so or
not. Also, during this stage, an active process of international socialisation occurs
whereby norm breakers are induced to become norm followers.
The final stage is characterised by norm internalisation. During this stage, it
is said that norms have acquired a taken-for-granted quality and are no longer a
matter of broad public debate (Finnemore & Sikkink 1998). Therefore, according
to the norm life-cycle model, socialisation and norm compliance are ultimately
successful when states are influenced to perceive their identity as being linked to
an international society. This is based on the social constructivist assumption that
belonging to and identifying with an international society influences state behaviour
because of reputational enhancement and actual or perceived peer pressure.
Norm Localisation
As part of the second wave of conventional constructivist scholarship, Amitav
Acharya (2004) proposes a dynamic explanation of norm diffusion that describes
how local agents reconstruct foreign norms to ensure that these norms fit with
302
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
the agents’ cognitive priors and identities (Acharya 2004). Acharya subsequently
presents an investigatory framework which prioritises the agency role of normtakers. He suggests that this agency role is facilitated through a dynamic
congruence-building process which he calls localisation. He defines this process
as follows:
A complex process and outcome by which norm-takers build congruence between
transnational norms (including norms previously institutionalised in a region)
and local beliefs and practices. In this process, foreign norms, which may not
initially cohere with the latter, are incorporated into local norms. Therefore, the
success of norm diffusion strategies depends on the extent to which they provide
opportunities for localisation (Acharya 2004:241).
Acharya also suggests that the success of norm localisation is more likely if normtakers are convinced that foreign norms will elevate the status of preexisting local
norms without significantly altering local identities. For Acharya, in localisation,
local agents undertake an active process of pruning or adjustment to find a
better fit between foreign ideas and local practices. In other words, local agents
actively seek out foreign ideas that can instrumentally enhance their legitimacy
and moral authority. Local agents additionally interrogate the shape and content
of foreign ideas so as to ensure that their potential localisation enhances rather
than replaces existing institutions. Acharya further argues that the prospects for
localisation depend on the authority and perceived legitimacy of key norm-takers,
the strength of prior local norms, the credibility and prestige of local agents,
indigenous cultural traits and traditions, and the scope for grafting and pruning
presented by foreign norms (Acharya 2004).
Moreover, Acharya concludes that strong extant norms facilitate the
localisation of foreign norms, since successful norm localisation depends on the
prior existence of a local norm in a similar issue area as that of a new external
norm which makes similar behavioural claims. In localisation, it is said that
the external norm must also be amenable to pruning and adjustments without
necessarily compromising its core attributes, and that it is this very scope for
grafting and pruning presented by a new foreign norm that influences the normtaker’s interest to localise it (Acharya 2004).
Norm Subsidiarity
As part of the third wave of norm diffusion scholarship, Acharya has developed an
additional theoretical framework to explain the phenomenon of norm resistance
and displacement in the process of norm diffusion. He introduces the concept of
norm subsidiarity to investigate the process whereby ‘local actors create rules with
a view to preserve their autonomy from dominance, neglect, violation, or abuse
by more powerful central actors’ (Acharya 2011a:97).
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
303
Acharya contends that peripheral actors have developed subsidiarity norms for
two reasons. First, they have historically sought to challenge their marginalisation
from global norm-making processes. Second, they employ norm subsidiarity as a
result of what they perceive to be great power hypocrisy. According to Acharya,
this is a result of stronger states seemingly violating universally accepted norms
such as sovereignty, territorial integrity, non-intervention, self-determination,
and the equality of states, and the unwillingness of higher level institutions to
punish deviance (Acharya 2011a).
Therefore, for Acharya, there are two major effects of norm subsidiarity. The
first is a challenging/resisting effect whereby local actors reject central actors, great
powers and international institutions by developing subsidiarity norms. In this way,
local actors choose to deny international rules, and they claim a right to resolve their
own issues without higher power authority. The second effect of norm subsidiarity
is a supportive/strengthening one whereby local actors support and invoke global
norms because they consider them to be universal, even though they continue to
question and resist great power-controlled ideas and institutions (Acharya 2011a).
Reflections on Constructivist Norm Theorising:
Prospects and Limitations
In this section, I want to offer some tentative reflections on how the universalising
nature of constructivist norms theorising potentially erases how norm dynamics
are also frequently authored and structured in important ways by nonWestern actors. I also want to make the case for why theorising about norms is
concomitantly the study of Africa’s international relations. At the beginning of
this chapter I intentionally highlighted how Charlotte Epstein emphasised that
constructivism’s study of norms ‘would appear’ to be a good thing for international
politics. This is because she goes on to qualify that ‘constructivism’s shortcoming
is to have neglected the power relations running through these normative
matrices, and the specific exclusions they enact and enable power that is still
understood in its immaterial, relational dimensions’ (Epstein 2017:3). Whereas
I have shown in this chapter that constructivism’s merit is to have opened up the
ideational and social dimension to the study of international relations, what I
have made less clear is that norms constitute powerful ordering mechanisms of
international politics. Indeed, the way we theorise about them also enables and
sustains particular forms of knowledge and praxis.
Since this book is primarily concerned with how to employ African-centred
and Western theories to ground research on Africa or an African phenomenon, I
need to do the following two things at this juncture:
1. briefly state an African perspective on theorising norms in international
relations and the characteristics of norms, and
2. contextualise what is to follow.
304
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
To begin with, as it pertains to the first aspect, I will, for the sake of brevity, limit
my discussion to the ideas of Mwalimu Ali Al’Amin Mazrui, the doyen of Africa’s
International Relations.
Indeed, one can write an entire essay, if not a book, on Mwalimu Mazrui’s
disquisitions on
1. theorising about norms and
2. the characteristics of norm regimes from an African perspective.
For conciseness, I will briefly discuss two of his observations (one on each of
the aforementioned aspects) on the subject here. The first of these observations
concerns theorising about the norm of nuclear proliferation. Mwalimu Mazrui
begins by asserting that the gist of Western research eschews the desire for and
the inevitable spread of nuclear weapons by African and other developing nations
and proffers the view that there has been an exceptional level of nuclear stability
and, thus, the focus should be on how to maintain the existing modest success
of regime maintenance. To counter this perspective, Mwalimu Mazrui then
argues that in order to cure the world of the nuclear malaise, a horizontal nuclear
proliferation might be needed. In essence, the cure may be necessitated by a dose
of the disease itself (Mazrui 1977).
The second observation is about norms of solidarity among Africans which
emerged from the African personality (i.e. the outgrowth of the cultural
uniqueness among Africans as exemplified in their attitudes, behaviours, beliefs,
customs, religious zeal, social norms, values, explanations of the cosmos and the
supernatural, social and political systems historically or in contemporary times)
and, thus, could not be destroyed by the colonial and racial oppression meted by
Europeans. Thus, according to Mwalimu Mazrui,
The image of an ancient, isolated and introverted Africa no longer belongs to
this age: isolation – naturally associated with so-called ‘primitive’ character – only
corresponded to an ideological necessity born out of colonial racism. But these
exchanges with other cultures did not break the unity of the African personality.
On the contrary, they helped to assert and enrich it. The colonial conquest of
almost the whole of the continent strengthened this feeling of unity of Black
Africa (Mazrui 1995:35).
Next, in terms of the second aspect (i.e. contextualising what is to follow), we
recall that in his article titled ‘Dialogue and Discovery: In Search of International
Relations Theories Beyond the West’ published in the Millennium: Journal of
International Studies in 2011, Acharya highlights the following two major areas
of contestation in respect of current IR theorising:
1. whether existing IR theories are already adequate to account for non-Western
experiences and voices, and whether those which have not been are expanding
their analytic scope and reach to issues and concerns of the world as a whole; and
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
305
2. whether attempts to develop indigenous concepts and theories end up simply
mimicking Western theories (Acharya 2011b).
The fact that IR Theory should be inclusive of non-Western voices and realities,
is not to say that Western-derived theories are irrelevant. Additionally, to dismiss
Western theories simply because they are Western can be a slippery slope to
the relativist trap. Undoubtedly, simply testing, extending and revising existing
IR theories will not be helpful in bridging the North-South gap, nor will this
satisfy demands for epistemic change and justice. Alternative theories which
have their origins in the global South and which can account for the practice
of international relations are required too (Acharya 2011b). This section of the
chapter is therefore a clarion call to scholars of Africa’s International Relations to
foreground Africa as the place from which to envision the international system
when employing constructivism to theorise about norms and African agency. It
is also to caution that in some respects, African scholars need to ‘de-naturalise’
and ‘de-centre’ some of the ontological and epistemological assumptions of
constructivism before employing the theory to explain African phenomena.
It becomes immediately apparent that the first wave of conventional
constructivist scholarship on norm diffusion is overtly grounded in universalism,
moral cosmopolitanism, and ‘ethical proselytism’. The ontological assumption
in this wave is that the norms that are being promoted (predominantly) by
Western organisations, transnational agents and individual norm entrepreneurs
are ‘good’ norms which are cosmopolitan and universal in nature. As a result,
the world polity-based models which are subsequently employed by this wave
of scholarship simply assume that actors are uniform cultural constructs who
are embedded in an international society that promotes modernisation, learning,
imitation, and organisational isomorphism. It is also assumed that these ‘good’
norms move uni-directionally and seamlessly from ‘up there’ to ‘down here’. The
world-polity based models also un-problematically suggest that states and other
actors simply comply with norms for reputational enhancement and to align
themselves with international standards. In this respect, Legro (1997) is correct
when he says that the universalistic approaches to norm diffusion generally
mis-specify the impact of international norms because of these conceptual and
methodological biases. Central among these is that not only do these analyses
overemphasise international prescriptions while neglecting norms that are rooted
in other types of social entities, they are also biased towards norms that worked,
thereby allowing for little variation to account for why certain norms have failed
or become obsolete (Legro 1997).
In providing a critical conceptual meditation of IR and its theory, Siphamandla
Zondi (2018) reminds us that IR theorising is a ‘monologue’ among White men
from a privileged position in a small part of the world. As a result, the history
and memory of the world that African scholars are expected to ‘remember’ is that
of a region of the world that acquired its status through processes that included
306
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
imperialism, slavery, and colonialism. Subsequently, the Eurocentric designs
employed by IR Theory establish an illusion that ‘the discipline and its claims are
universal in the sense that they represent everyone; it is to constantly claim that
IR is really international relations of everyone when in fact it is IR of European
tradition, a European gaze on the world and a Eurocentric construction of the
international’ (Zondi 2018:22–23).
There is little doubt that the universal and ‘good’ norms which constructivists
take for granted have been complicit in perpetuating the global hierarchies of
political and economic power that were established under imperialism and
colonialism. Similarly to other mainstream theoretical approaches in IR,
constructivism assumes the ‘Westphalian’ world as the historical birthplace of the
idea of statehood, and it simply naturalises the peremptory norms of sovereignty
and non-interference which accompany it. The practice of colonialism itself,
coupled with the imperative of its ‘civilising mission’, intentionally used violence
to achieve a normative ordering function so as to bring the languages, mores and
norms of civilisation to ‘barbarian’ civilisations. Today, in the Euro-American
world, modernity, which is underpinned by a liberal world order, is characterised
as a historical category that promotes norms of individualism, freedom,
technological progress, and formal equality. In many parts of the world, however,
this very modernity with the norms which define it has been experienced as the
slave trade, imperialism, colonialism, apartheid, neoliberalism, and globalisation.
Constructivism’s emphasis on ‘socialisation’ and ‘learning’ in international
society brings to the fore the relationship between identity formation and norms
and explains how the latter can account for structural changes in international
politics. The first wave of constructivist diffusion theorising attempts to show how
actors adopt a new norm based on the ways in which it comes to influence their
identities. It does not attempt to address the promise of the material incentives
which the norm offers. The problem here then is that constructivism potentially
de-politicises the concept of ‘identity’ itself, since the theory does not focus on
the political costs which are associated with socialisation and identity change.
In other words, the first wave does not account for the reality that actors in the
‘subaltern’ world are already socialised, collective actors with preexisting fullyfledged identities. The world-polity models of norm diffusion therefore deny
agency and merely place the socialised at the receiving end of the socialisation
process. As a result, for these models, the socialised is merely expected to ‘react’
to the new norm and is, thus, cast in the position of a ‘child’ in need of ‘learning’
the norms of ‘good’ behaviour. Epstein refers to this as the ‘infantilisation of the
socializee’ and explains it by asking the question: ‘by assuming that the socializee,
like the child, holds no prior legitimate identity, or whose identity is in need
of being molded, can both the analyst and policy-maker come to ignore the
fundamental violence that inheres in the loss of one identity in order to acquire
another?’ (Epstein 2017:82).
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
307
The second wave of conventional constructivist scholarship on norm
emergence and diffusion moves beyond the international prescriptions of moral
cosmopolitanism which are inherent in the first wave. This wave emphasises the
role of domestic, political, organisational and cultural variables in the process
of how new international norms are received. Additionally it demonstrates that
international norms are dynamic and subject to change, reinterpretation and
contestation. Significantly, the second wave also prioritises local agency since it
focuses on the concept of ‘congruence’ to describe the fit between international
and domestic norms. Acharya’s (2004) idea of norm localisation is therefore
distinctive because it argues that the fit between domestic and external identity
norms and institutions cannot be explained neatly by dichotomous outcomes of
acceptance or rejection. Since the process of localisation is not synonymous with
adaptation, diffusion does not require the cognitive priors of norm-takers to be
extinguished. Rather, these cognitive priors are mutually inflected with foreign
norms so that external ideas are actively adopted to meet local practices. However,
most important in norm localisation, agency is reestablished since subsequent
changes in behaviour are better explained in relation to the primacy of the local
normative order as opposed to international prescriptions.
In terms of the third wave of norm diffusion theorising, and by his own
reasoning, Acharya’s conceptual framework of norm subsidiarity develops
significantly on existing constructivist explanations on how norms travel since
it emphasises the need to assess norm creation and diffusion as a ‘bottom-up’
process. Subsequently, this encourages constructivists to now interrogate how
weak local actors might in fact challenge and influence global normative processes.
Acharya suggests that his concept of subsidiarity also serves to bridge the gap
in constructivist scholarship which has traditionally neglected the normative
behaviour of Third World countries and the role of regional institutions in norm
diffusion. This feature of norm subsidiarity ultimately highlights the normative
agency of Third World countries in international relations, thereby enhancing
the theoretical study of global normative order-building beyond an exclusively
Western enterprise (Acharya 2011b).
Charmaine Chua (2017) however is somewhat critical of both localisation
and subsidiarity. She argues that Acharya’s focus on the local sources of
international norms makes the conception of peripheral autonomy thinkable
in one form, but unthinkable in another. On the one hand, localisation and
subsidiarity make it possible that weak and less powerful actors play a central
role in effecting normative change. On the other, by confining his analysis
to elite negotiations within regional and global institutions, Acharya does
not consider forms of local agency and difference that exist outside of these
institutions. Additionally, Chua suggests that the ‘difference’ which Acharya
recognises in Third World agencies is still only made legible through the
308
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
ontological ‘universal’ framework of normative change since he still assumes that
these norms have been ‘scripted’ elsewhere so that despite his best intentions,
Acharya’s advocacy of Southern agency ‘restrictively squashes multi-layered
differences and ideological positions into the narrowly common interests and
values of international society’ (Chua 2017:88).
Scholars of Africa’s International Relations should therefore not view agency
as the sole purview of state elites, nor should they conceptualise universality
as a teleological end-point in which norms need to be enfolded. African
agency is multidimensional and multi-actor in nature. Thus, African scholars
should consider the particular, the local, the historical, and the subjective
when theorising norms. By focusing on African ‘experiences’ which have been
epistemologically dismissed as peculiar and unfamiliar in the past, one might
find new ways to account for contemporary dynamics in international relations,
while also offering an important counterpoint to the universalising ‘pull’
which is inherent in the norms constructivist scholarship in IR. As Charlotte
Epstein says,
‘the challenge, then, is how to mobilise the particular and the local, in their infinite
richness, as sites for deploying a form of theorising that, by way of this grounding,
seeks to avert the pitfalls of a universalisation that was a key historical driver of
colonisation in the first place’ (2017:9).
In his introduction to the Handbook of Africa’s International Relations, Tim
Murithi highlights the fact that Africa’s engagement with the rest of the world has
not always been on the continent’s terms, and that Africa’s international relations
have regularly been defined and influenced by the dominant international and
geopolitical agendas of the day. Therefore, Murithi posits that Africa has more
often than not been the subject of international relations dictated by external
actors and, thus, the chronicles of Africa’s International Relations are also
dominated by the perspectives of those who have invaded, enslaved, colonised
and exploited the continent (Murithi 2014).
Katharina P. Coleman and Thomas K. Tieku (2018), however, remind us
that African individuals, continental organisations, governments and non-state
actors have significantly shaped many prevailing international norms, but that
these contributions have been largely undocumented and unnoticed. It stands
to reason therefore that much of the theorising about norms assumes that
norms originate in advanced industrialised states and societies and, as a result,
the contributions of states and actors from materially less endowed parts of the
world remain under-studied and poorly understood (Coleman & Tieku 2018).
Nonetheless, consistent with the central premise of this chapter, Coleman and
Tieku suggest that by building on existing constructivist scholarship on norms
we can identify four key processes by which international norms are produced,
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
309
thereby allowing us to study how African actors can participate in and affect the
process of international norm development. Concomitantly, Coleman and Tieku
examine how each process represents a potential pathway for African actors to
influence international norms. For the purposes of brevity I will merely highlight
and bullet-point some of the most salient characteristics of each pathway, as
articulated by the authors, in order to indicate how a ‘theoretical grounding’ in
constructivism can assist scholars in analysing and theorising the ways in which
African actors can shape international norms.
Pathway 1: Shaping Global Norm Creation Processes
When international norms emerge as a result of the work conducted by norm
entrepreneurs through persuasion and negotiation at the global level, Coleman
and Tieku (2018) identify the following four mechanisms whereby African actors
can impact the resulting norm:
1. African multi-level actors can act as norm entrepreneurs either independently
or as parts of an international or transnational mobilisation effort.
2. African states can be important early adopters of an emerging norm whose
presence influences subsequent persuasion dynamics.
3. African actors can play the role of ‘norm sceptics’ and can argue against the
formal adoption of a proposed norm.
4. African states can play important roles in international negotiations and treaty
declarations that seek to establish a new norm.
Pathway 2: African Norms that May or May not Diffuse beyond
the Continent
This pathway, also with four mechanisms, would apply to African-centred
and indigenous norms which originate specifically from the continent and
which have domestic salience, but which might or might not necessarily have
international applicability:
1. African norms can be generated through formal or informal continental or
regional inter-state negotiations to manage specific issues or crises.
2. African norms can be developed through a deliberate continental or regional
norm subsidiarity effort so as to counter global norms which are perceived to
be damaging to African actors’ autonomy and sovereignty.
3. African norms can emerge through a ‘coalition of the willing’ where likeminded African governments develop a norm to address shared needs.
4. Continental or regional norms may emerge through the agency of local
non-state actors who work together to develop specific norms with a view to
persuading African states to adopt them.
310
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Pathway 3: Shaping International Norms through Creative Implementation
This pathway challenges the conventional assumption that the content of norms
is static. Thus, it emphasises how norms are dynamic, and it is also concerned
with explaining how norms are constantly being reinterpreted and redefined even
as they continue to exert influence on patterns of social behaviour. African actors
can therefore exert themselves in the following two ways:
1. Through localisation, whereby strategic actors, within a state or region, can
adapt international norms to render them more compatible with local norms
and priorities.
2. Through meaning-in-practice, whereby one can study the material and discursive
practices through which states and other actors shape understandings of how a
norm can (or cannot) be implemented.
Pathway 4: Direct Contestation of Global Norms
In this pathway, African actors can influence global norms by directly contesting
them and, therefore, either force their abandonment or their renegotiation.
Challenging norms can manifest in the following five ways:
1. African actors may argue that a global norm is ‘incongruent’ with African
conditions, and they may develop mechanisms to encourage African states not
to comply with the norm.
2. African contestation and resistance to global norms may occur during
negotiations with non-African states. Here, African public officials may
challenge the appropriateness of a particular global norm in their interactions
with extra-regional actors.
3. African states and African organisations may ‘localise’ the international norm
in such a way that the latter loses its original meaning.
4. African actors can use domestic tools and mechanisms to contest an
international norm.
5. African public intellectuals may challenge a particular international norm
by pointing out the shortcomings in its application through their writings,
speeches, and other public engagements.
Indeed, Coleman and Tieku’s four pathways to account for the emergence,
diffusion and contestation of international norms provide an encouraging
analytical schema for African scholars to use when studying the understated
agency of African actors in international politics. Their analytical schema not
only borrows, but also builds, on existing constructivist theorising on the
dynamic nature on norms, so as to make this theorising more applicable in the
African context. By way of concluding this section, I will briefly demonstrate the
connection between norms theorising and practice by offering four examples to
reflect aspects of the four pathways in action.
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
311
Shaping Global Norm Creation Processes
In my own research, (Bizos 2014, 2015) on the evolving human protection norm
of the Responsibility to Protect (R2P), much of the literature associates this
norm’s emergence with the Canadian-sponsored International Commission on
Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS) Report which was published in 2001.
In its current format, the evolving norm of R2P emphasises a state’s responsibility
not to commit mass atrocity crimes against its people or to allow them to occur,
and it also places a residual responsibility on the international community to
respond timeously and decisively when a state is manifestly failing to meet its
protection responsibilities. In many ways this international norm, which was
ratified by almost all United Nations member states at the General Assembly
Summit in New York in 2005 is ground-breaking, since it challenges the idea that
state sovereignty is ‘absolute’. By doing so, it prioritises human beings, as opposed
to states, as the main referent objects of international peace and security; and
under specific circumstances, it allows for the intervention of the international
community into the domestic affairs of a sovereign state.
What is however often ignored in respect of how this narrative is presented
is that the idea of ‘sovereignty as responsibility’ was initially coined in 1998 by
Francis Deng, a Sudanese Minister of State for Foreign Affairs, and it was an
African Secretary-General of the United Nations, Kofi Annan, who became the
norm’s chief entrepreneur by presenting the challenge to world leaders in 1999 to
find a way of reconciling the peremptory norm of sovereignty with the imperative
of saving populations from mass atrocities committed by their own governments
under the guise of this sovereignty.
African Norms that May or May not Diffuse beyond the Continent
In respect of this pathway, one might make reference to the Pan-African solidarity
norm which emerged during intergovernmental negotiations among newly
independent African states at the level of the Organisation of African Unity
(OAU) from 1960 onwards. This norm can be attached to Acharya’s framework
of subsidiarity, since it is an example of how African governments have developed
norms to protect themselves from the predatory behaviour of more powerful
actors in the international system. Thomas Tieku (2014) explains that the PanAfrican solidarity norm is characterised by a feeling of ‘we-ness’ among African
elites since it encourages them to act in harmony.
Additionally, the Pan-African solidarity norm establishes a collective
expectation that elites should not disagree with one another (at least not in
public), and that rulers of African states should not step out of line over issues
where a broad continental consensus has been established (Tieku 2014). In
many ways, the norm of Pan-African solidarity promotes agency, since it places
312
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
an ethical pressure on African governments to seek compromise positions, to
develop common positions on critical international issues, and to engage in bloc
voting in international and multilateral fora. Recently also, the propensity for
African governments to mobilise this norm so as to protect political elites was
witnessed by collective efforts to shield Sudanese and Kenyan leaders from trial
and prosecution by the International Criminal Court (ICC).
Shaping International Norms through Creative Implementation
A brief example which captures this pathway may be the norms underpinning
the African Union’s (AU’s) Constitutive Act (2000). At first glance, the Act seems
consistent with many of the existing norms which govern international relations
among states. The Act stresses:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
sovereign equality and interdependence among member states;
prohibition of the use of force or threat to use force;
non-interference by any state in the internal affairs of another;
peaceful coexistence of states and their right to live in peace and security;
respect for democratic principles, human rights, the rule of law and good
governance, as well as respect for the sanctity of human life; and
6. condemnation and rejection of impunity.
7. Nonetheless, in respect to the use of force or threat to use it, and non-
interference by any state in the internal affairs of another, Article 4(h)
of the Constitutive Act also specifically stipulates ‘the right of the AU
to intervene in a member state pursuant to a decision of the Assembly
in respect of grave circumstances, namely: war crimes, genocide and
crimes against humanity’ (AU 2002:1).
In this sense, whereas the AU has adopted the international peremptory norm of
non-intervention it has also creatively suggested that non-intervention does not
equate with the African-centred norm of non-indifference. To this day, the AU is
the only international organisation, other than the United Nations, which grants
its member states the prerogative to intervene in a member state on prescribed
grounds, thereby prompting the overarching norm of ‘African solutions for
Africa’s problems’.
Direct Contestation of Global Norms
Here again, I turn to the ‘now contested’ norm of the Responsibility to Protect
after the Libya fiasco of 2011, when the international community invoked R2P
and Chapter VII of the United Nations Charter to employ ‘all necessary means’
against the Muammar Gaddafi regime. What subsequently became clear is that
the North Atlantic Treaty Organization-led intervention (with predominantly
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
313
United States military muscle) extended its mandate and effectively forced
‘regime change’ in Libya. To this end, many African states, as well as other actors
from the global South, who were initially supportive of R2P, now contest the
norm at the level of the United Nations.
Thus, dissenting actors now claim that R2P is susceptible to politicisation
by Great Powers and that the norm suffers from selectivity, misuse and abuse
when it is politically useful for powerful states to do so. Dissenters also accuse the
norm’s supporters of ‘great hypocrisy’ because of double standards in the norms
application and its propensity for unfair discrimination against weaker actors in
the name of mass atrocity prevention.
Conclusion
In this chapter I have endeavoured to demonstrate why and how norms matter
both in the way that we theorise and ‘do’ international relations. In particular,
I have made the case that the ‘constructivist turn’ in IR has brought the study
of norms squarely into the theoretical and empirical concerns of the discipline.
Norms matter because practically they are able to sustain cooperation in
international affairs despite the absence of a higher authority capable of enforcing
compliance with their injunctions. Theoretically, norms matter too because they
demonstrate how social and ideational dynamics are just as important as material
ones in regulating the behaviour of international actors and in constituting their
identities. I have also highlighted that norms are powerful ordering mechanisms
in international affairs that enable and sustain particular forms of knowledge
and praxis. No doubt, much of the conventional constructivist theorising about
norms can be faulted for being too grounded in unfounded universalism, liberal
internationalism and moral cosmopolitanism.
Nonetheless, I have attempted to show how constructivist norm diffusion
scholarship and theorising have progressed and how they now offer promise in
respect to how African scholars might employ the theory to better understand
norm dynamics and agency in an African context. Whereas African scholars
should be encouraged to shift constructivism’s ‘site of enunciation’ to the
particular and local, they should not dismiss constructivism outright in their
endeavours to theorise about norms and African phenomena in general.
References
Acharya, Amitav, 2004, ‘How Ideas Spread: Whose Norms Matter? Norm Localization
and Institutional Change in Asian Regionalism’, International Organization,
Vol. 58, pp. 239–275.
Acharya, Amitav, 2011a, ‘Norm Subsidiarity and Regional Orders: Sovereignty,
Regionalism and Rule-making in the Third World’, International Studies Quarterly,
Vol. 55, No. 1, pp. 95–123.
314
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Acharya, Amitav, 2011b, ‘Dialogue and Discovery: In Search of International Relations
Theories Beyond the West’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, Vol. 39,
No. 3, pp. 619–637.
Acharya, Amitav, 2013, ‘The R2P and Norm Diffusion: Towards a Framework of Norm
Circulation’, Global Responsibility to Protect, Vol. 5, No. 4, pp. 466–479.
Adler, Emanuel, 1997, ‘Seizing the Middle Ground: Constructivism in World Politics’,
European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 3, pp. 319–363.
Adler, Emanuel, 2013, ‘Constructivism and International Relations’, in W. Carlsnaes;
T. Risse and B. Simmons, eds., Handbook of International Relations, London,
UK: Sage Publications.
African Union, 2000, Constitutive Act of the African Union. (https://au.int/sites/default/
files/pages/34873-file-constitutiveact_en.pdf ). 6 November 2021.
Bellamy, Alex, 2004, Security Communities and Their Neighbors: Regional Fortresses or
Global Integrators?, New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Bizos, Anthony, 2014, ‘The Responsibility to Protect: A South African Perspective’,
The Thinker: A Pan-African Quarterly for Thought Leaders, Vol. 2, No. 60, pp. 30–35.
Bizos, Anthony, 2015, ‘To Protect or to Intervene? Contesting R2P as a Norm in South
Africa’s Foreign Policy’, SAIIA Policy Insights Paper, Vol. 17, No. 6, pp. 1–7.
Bull, Hedley, 1977, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, New York,
NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Checkel, Jeffrey T., 1998, ‘The Constructive Turn in International Relations Theory’,
World Politics, Vol. 50, pp. 324–348.
Checkel, Jeffrey T., 1999, ‘Norms, Institutions and National Identity in Contemporary
Europe’, International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 43, pp. 83–114.
Coleman, Katharina P. and Tieku, Thomas K., eds., 2018, African Actors in International
Security: Shaping Contemporary Norms, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
Chua, Charmaine C., 2017, ‘Against Localization: Rethinking Compliance and
Antagonism in Norm Dynamics’, in C. Epstein, ed., Against International Relations
Norms: Postcolonial Perspectives, London, UK: Routledge.
Epstein, Charlotte, ed., 2017, Against International Relations Norms: Postcolonial
Perspectives, London, UK: Routledge.
Finnemore, Martha and Sikkink, Kathryn, 1998, ‘International Norm Dynamics and
Political Change’, International Organization, Vol. 52, pp. 887–917.
Finnemore, Martha and Sikkink, Kathryn, 2001, ‘Taking Stock: The Constructivist
Research Program in International Relations and Comparative Politics’, Annual
Review of Political Science, Vol. 4, pp. 391–416.
Flockhart, Trine, 2012, ‘Constructivism and Foreign Policy’, in S. Smith; A. Hadfield
and T. Dunne, eds., Foreign Policy: Theories, Actors, Cases, Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
Giddens, Anthony, 1984, The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration,
Oxford, UK: Blackwell-Polity Press.
Hurrell, Andrew, 2013, ‘Norms and Ethics in International Relations’, in W. Carlsnaes,
T. Risse and B. Simmons, eds., Handbook of International Relations, London,
UK: Sage Publications.
Anthony Bizos: Theorising Norms
315
International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS), 2001, The
Responsibility to Protect: Report of the International Commission on Intervention
and State Sovereignty, Ottawa, Canada: International Development Research
Centre. (https://www.idrc.ca/en/book/responsibility-protect-report-internationalcommission-intervention-and-state-sovereignty). 6 November 2021.
Jung, Hoyoon, 2019, ‘The Evolution of Social Constructivism in Political Science: Past
to Present’, SAGE Open, Vol. 9, No. 1, pp. 1–10.
Katzenstein, Peter J., 1996, The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World
Politics, New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Keck, Margaret E. and Sikkink, Kathryn, 1999, ‘Transnational Advocacy Networks in
International and Regional Politics’, International Social Science Journal, Vol. 51,
pp. 89–101.
Klotz, Audie, 1995, Norms in International Relations: The Struggle Against Apartheid,
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Krasner, Stephen D., 1982, ‘Structural Causes and Regime Consequences: Regimes as
Intervening Variables’, International Organization, Vol. 36, pp. 185–205.
Legro, Jeffrey W., 1997, ‘Which Norms Matter? Revisiting the “Failure”’ of
Internationalism’, International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 1, pp. 31–63.
Levitt, Peggy and Merry, Sally, 2009, ‘Vernacularization on the Ground: Local Uses of
Women’s Rights in Peru, China, India and the United States’, Global Networks,
Vol. 9, No. 4, pp. 441–461.
March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P., 1995, ‘The Logic of Appropriateness’, Arena
Working Paper, Oslo, Norway: University of Oslo.
Mazrui, Ali Al’Amin, 1977, Africa’s International Relations: The Diplomacy of Dependency
& Change, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Mazrui, Ali Al’Amin, 1995, ‘Pan-Africanism: From Poetry to Power’, Issue: A Journal of
Opinion, Vol. 23, No. 1, pp. 35–38.
Murithi, Tim, ed., 2014, Handbook of Africa’s International Relations, London,
UK: Routledge.
Price, Richard and Reus-Smit, Christian, 1998, ‘Dangerous Liaisons? Constructivism
and Critical International Theory’, European Journal of International Relations,
Vol. 4, pp. 259–294.
Risse, Thomas; Ropp, Christian and Sikkink, Kathryn, 1999, The Power of Human Rights:
International Norms and Domestic Change, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
Ruggie, John G., 1998, ‘What Makes the World Hang Together? Neo-utilitarianism
and the Social Constructivist Challenge’, International Organization, Vol. 52,
pp. 855–885.
Steans, Jill; Pettiford, Lloyd; Diez, Thomas and El-Anis, Imad., eds., 2010, An Introduction
to International Relations Theory: Perspectives and Themes, London, UK: Pearson
Education Limited.
Thakur, Ramesh, 2019, Reviewing the Responsibility to Protect: Origins, Implementation
and Controversies, London, UK: Routledge.
Tieku, Thomas K., 2014, ‘Theoretical Approaches to Africa’s International Relations’, in T.
Murithi, ed., Handbook of Africa’s International Relations, London, UK: Routledge.
316
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Waltz, Kenneth N., 1979, Theory of International Politics, Boston, MA: Addison-Wesley
Publishing Company.
Wendt, Alexander E., 1987, ‘The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations
Theory’, International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 3, pp. 335–370.
Wendt, Alexander E., 1992, ‘Anarchy Is What States Make of It: The Social Construction
of Power Politics’, International Organization, Vol. 46, No. 2, pp. 391–425.
Wendt, Alexander E., 1994, ‘Collective Identity Formation and the International State’,
American Political Science Review, Vol. 88, No. 2, pp. 384–396.
Williams, Paul, 2007, ‘From Non-Intervention to Non-Indifference: The Origins and
Development of the African Union’s Security Culture’, African Affairs, Vol. 106,
No. 423, pp. 353–279.
Zimmerman, L.; Deitelhoff, N. and Lesch, M., 2017, ‘Unlocking the Agency of the
Governed: Contestation and Norm Dynamics’, Third World Thematics: A Third
World Quarterly Journal, Vol. 2, No. 5, pp. 691–708.
Zondi, Siphamandla, 2018, ‘Decolonizing International Relations and Its Theory:
A Critical Conceptual Meditation’, Politikon, Vol. 45, No. 1, pp. 16–31.
Zwingel, Susanne, 2012, ‘How Do Norms Travel? Theorizing International Women’s
Rights in Transnational Perspective’, International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 56,
No. 1, pp. 115–129.
12
Public Choice Theory
and Economic Development in Africa
Abdul Karim Bangura
This chapter examines how Public Choice Theory can be used to study and
promote economic development in Africa. An example of the challenges which
need to be addressed is found in a recent article on Africa’s economic development
by Sam Unom. Unom probes the question of whether the continent is stymied by
irregular legacy institutions inherited from colonialism. He begins by challenging
the dominant perspective that corruption and populism are the sole impediments
to Africa’s economic development. After a lengthy discussion of the merits and
demerits of this prevalent view and evidence on the vagaries of legacy institutions,
he then proffers the notion that while corruption and populism do have negative
impacts on economic development in Africa, so to do the irregular institutions
(Unom 2019).
First, the chapter looks at the various approaches that have been employed to
investigate and promote economic development in Africa since the continent’s
independence explosion in the 1960s and the reasons for their failures. These
approaches include the Simple Growth Model, the Redistribution with Growth
Model, the Import-substitution Model, the Socialist Model, the National Selfreliance Model and the Regional Integration or Collective Self-reliance Model.
Thereafter, Public Choice Theory is suggested as an alternative for studying
and promoting sustainable economic development in Africa. The underlying
presuppositions of this chapter are:
1. if self-interest is a powerful motivator in the marketplace, there is every reason
to believe that it will also be a motivating factor when choices are made
collectively to promote economic development;
318
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
2. if market choices are influenced by changes in projected personal costs relative
to benefits, there is every reason to expect that such changes will also influence
political choices for economic development.
Perhaps the following simple anecdote will serve to illustrate the need for an
alternative approach to study and spur economic development in Africa. During
a recent professional meeting, a notable African scholar presented a paper on
‘Theory of De-development’. At the conclusion of his presentation, a member of
the audience who had travelled all the way from Kenya to attend the conference
in the United States remarked:
‘Enough of the theorising! We need practical answers to make sure that anyone
who drives a straight course on most African roads is not driving drunk. For a
sober person would have to drive zigzag to escape the massive manholes (that is,
potholes) on those roads.’
Almost axiomatic is the notion that each African country presents such a different
mix of economic problems that standard solutions cannot be applied as panacea.
Economics literature offers a variety of models showing the path toward economic
development. Yet, when a developing country pleads for specific answers, these
economists can refer to only partial solutions or states of development so
theoretical and abstract that few have ever really been tested.
By analysing the behaviour of people in the marketplace within an economic
development perspective, one can develop a logically consistent theory of
behaviour that can be tested against reality. Through theory and empirical
testing, the analyst can seek to explain various economic development actions
of decision-makers and, in general, how the market operates. The rest of this
chapter is divided into two major sections that entail discussions of the issues
mentioned earlier:
1. previous development models used in Africa and the reasons for their
failures and
2. Public Choice as an alternative model. These aspects can guide the rational
decision-maker toward avoiding the short-sightedness effect which has
hampered many African economies over the years.
This effect refers to the misallocation of resources that results because public
sector action is biased:
1. in favour of proposals yielding clearly defined current benefits in exchange for
difficult-to-identify future costs and
2. against proposals with clearly identifiable current costs yielding less concrete
and less obvious future benefits.
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
319
Previous Development Models Used in Africa and Reasons for
their Failures
The arrival of independence for most African countries in the 1960s found them
closely tied up in economic relations with their former colonial masters. The
ties were much stronger between Francophone African countries and France.
For instance, France accounted for three-quarters of the external trade of Benin,
Chad, Niger, and Senegal when these countries received their independence.
Most African countries also gave preferential tariff treatment to imports from
the imperialist states. As the imperialists had mostly monopolised foreign
investments and aid donation in the colonies, decolonisation provided the new
African governments with the opportunity to diversify their economic links and
pursue development strategies that could allow them to reduce their economic
dependence on the former imperialists.
In this section of the chapter, the development strategies that African
governments have pursued since independence and the reasons for their
shortcomings are explored. The focus is on the theoretical presuppositions of
these development models and the results yielded after their implementation.
The Simple Growth Model
The Simple Growth Model can be traced to the ‘Western’ model of development.
In the words of Robert A. Nisbet, ‘developmentalism is one of the oldest and most
powerful of all Western ideas’. The central idea engendered in this development
thinking is the metaphor of growth. Thus, development, according to Nisbet
is conceived as being ‘organic, immanent, directional, cumulative, irreversible,
and purposive. Furthermore, it implies structural differentiation and increasing
complexity’ (Nisbet 1969:7).
The early discussion on modern economic development for poorer countries
(that is, in the late 1950s and the early 1960s) had an optimistic tone which
may be difficult to explain today. This optimism was mainly a manifestation
of the dynamic growth experienced by industrialised countries themselves
under the Marshall Plan,1 which was seen as a successful demonstration case of
development, but also arose from the philosophic tradition in the West which
looked upon growth as more or less inevitable. The Keynesian ‘revolution’ in
economics had taught Western economists and Africans trained in Western
economics that the state sometimes had to give a helping hand, but few doubted
that the future of African and other developing countries was generally reflected
in the experience of the industrialised countries. The simple formula was: just
find out the Incremental Capital-Output ratio and the desired rate of growth.
Then one can (after due consideration of the rate of population growth) arrive at
the appropriate level of investment needed for economic growth (Hettne 1978).
320
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Foreign capital inflows were seen as a ‘pump-priming’ mechanism intended to
help a developing country’s savings and tax receipts as well as to help investment
rise steadily (Bangura 1994a).
Sociologically minded theorists emphasised the significance of a leading sector
(private or public) and the emergence of the entrepreneurial elite as stimuli for
economic development. The idea of growth, as proffered by theorists such as
Walt Whitman Rostow (1960), was therefore perceived mainly as a function
of investment, and not too many analysts doubted that a process of economic
growth through a series of ‘stages’ would in the end benefit an entire country. This
is the reason the 1960s were dubbed the First Development Decade in anticipation
of the successes that were expected to follow.
Nonetheless, by the early 1970s, many African countries began to face
difficulties in fulfilling the growth development strategy. Some Western
economists trained in formal theory began to sense new realities. Irma Adelman
and Cynthia Taft Morris, for example, capture this idea well when they state:
‘We had shared the prevailing view among economists that economic growth
was economically beneficial to most nations. We had also greatly questioned the
relevance today of the historical association of successful economic growth with
the spread of parliamentary democracy. Our results proved to be at variance with
our preconceptions’ (Adelman & Morris 1973:vii).
From the preceding quote, one can see that Adelman and Morris display a renewed
interest in the nexus between economic growth and income distribution. A key
factor for this focus was the visible aspects of the extent of poverty: recurrent
starvation, mass unemployment, political unrest, etc. What was taking place in
African countries during the so-called ‘development decade’ was growth with
poverty instead of development.
Employing data from across Africa, Colin Legum and his partners found that
by the mid-1970s, post-colonial African countries had perpetuated or generated
staggering income inequalities and had maintained much of their populations
in conditions of absolute poverty. These economies, moreover, remained geared
toward raw material production and export to their previous metropolitan markets
(namely France, Britain, and Belgium) with some diversification of markets to
include other European Economic Community (EEC) member states, especially
Germany and the Netherlands. In only eight of the 35 independent African states
had a non-EEC country become the major trading partner by the mid-1970s.
Also, only in Mauritius were manufactured goods among the principal products
exported (Legum et al. 1979).
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
321
The Redistribution with Growth Model
A new strategy proposed by theorists of the Redistribution with Growth Model
exemplified a modification of, rather than a clear break with, the Simple Growth
Model. First, the analysis retained much of the optimism of the earlier ‘trickledown’ assumptions in asserting that the benefits of growth, empirically, had
a tendency to be concentrated in the early stages but that further increases in
concentration were by no means inevitable. Secondly, the social engineering
approach to development, as Chenery and his partners (1962, 1966a, 1966b,
1966c, 1970, 1974) purported, was still adhered to, in that they believed that to
deal with the problems of poverty-stricken groups, governments needed to design
overall programmes or policy packages rather than a set of isolated projects. This
is simply a continuation of the old strategy of ‘balanced growth’ extended to
include social development as well (Bangura 1994a).
The core of the shortcoming of the redistribution with growth strategy in
Africa was the fact that most of the continent’s governments could not significantly
raise mass living standards by maintaining their reliance on traditional primary
production exports; yet this reliance was maintained. In extreme cases such as
Ghana, the government’s attempt to increase its reliance on cocoa exports led to
a sharp decline in total revenues received because of the price elasticity associated
with demand conditions for the commodity. Prices for most primary products
exported from Africa were unstable and remain so to the present day. Such price
changes usher in dramatic ups and downs in economic conditions in Africa,
leaving the planning of structural change extremely difficult and the avoidance of
periodic foreign-exchanges practically impossible (Legum et al. 1979).
Another feature of this dilemma was the fact that the purchasing power of
most African commodity exports in the global market declined over much of
the post-independence period. Between 1960 and 1972, overall barter terms
of trade for developing countries in general declined by an annual average
of 0.3 per cent. The purchasing power of those countries’ exports (excluding
petroleum) declined by an annual average of 1.4 per cent during the same period.
The remarkable upsurge in commodity prices during 1973–1974 was quickly
reversed in 1975. African countries were left worse off because of the decline in
prices for their commodities and these economies’ requirements for high-priced
oil imports (Legum et al. 1979). The emergence of new resource exports in the
post-independence period provided a few African countries an escape from these
strains. Petroleum discoveries and development in Gabon and Nigeria, iron ore
in Mauritania, and copper in Botswana provided these countries such escapes.
For a small number of other African countries, possibilities for diversification
hinged upon new agricultural products (for example, cashews in Tanzania) and
expanded peasant cash cropping (for example, tea and pyrethrum in Kenya). But
production of these primary products did not provide the rapid income advances
322
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
intermediary bourgeoisies needed to finance their own embourgeoisement (i.e. the
proliferation in a society of values perceived as characteristic of the middle class,
especially of materialism) and increase standards of living. The outcome, as to be
expected, was political instability (Legum et al. 1979). These developments led
many African countries to promote industrialisation policies based on importsubstitution.
The Import-substitution Model
The underlying tenet of the Import-substitution Model is that in order to
industrialise, developing countries must also decide whether to produce
manufactured goods for export or to replace imports because
1. their manufactured imports indicate the existence of a domestic market for
particular products,
2. barriers against foreign competition could easily be erected, and
3. the strategy is believed to relieve even greater balance of payments problems
later. Import tariffs, which tend to become progressively higher with higher
stages of processing, could provide the needed protection.
For example, Naomi Chazan and her colleagues (1999) in their study of importsubstitution industrialisation in Africa state that the continent’s experience with
the strategy has not, on the whole, been a particularly happy one. These observers
provide a number of reasons for their assertion. To begin with, instead of
conserving scarce foreign exchange, import-substitution industrialisation proved
to be import-sensitive because many of the capital goods and components used
in manufacturing had to be imported. The foreign exchange problem was often
exacerbated where import-substitution industrialisation was conducted by a
subsidiary of a transnational corporation, since its profits, interest, and dividends
were repatriated to its parent company overseas. Instead of reducing dependence,
the strategy simply led to a change in the nature of that dependence – on foreign
technology, for instance.
Chazan et al. add that import-substitution industrialisation led to a
misallocation of resources. As infant industries failed to grow, they continued
to be dependent on high levels of protection from potential competitors. With
this high level of protection came little incentive for industry to become more
efficient. The inevitable consequence was that local consumers were subjected to
unnecessarily high prices. A corollary was that the strategy discriminated directly
against other sectors like agriculture, because they were dependent on inputs
from import-substitution industries. The inefficiency of these industries also
meant that they could not sell their goods on the world market in order to reap
economies of scale (Chazan et al. 1999).
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
323
Chazan and her colleagues also point out that other policies associated
with import-substitution industrialisation caused certain distortions. In order
to reduce the relative cost of inputs needed by industry, governments had to
maintain overvalued exchange rates. Export sectors such as agriculture and mining
suffered because of this policy, as their products became relatively more expensive
for foreigners to buy. State corporations became even more inefficient because
governments demanded that they employ secondary-school graduates and provide
below-cost services to other sectors of the economies (Chazan et al. 1999).
Chazan et al. mention that a number of serious policy errors were also made,
particularly in opting for the latest high-technology processes as opposed to those
appropriate for local conditions. An example was the establishment of six vehicle
assembly plants in Nigeria that were largely dependent on imported materials.
The range of models produced was so wide that production runs were quite short.
The multiplication of plants also led to very low levels of production capacity. As a
consequence, some of the plants recorded a negative value added in manufacturing.
The costs of assembly in Nigeria were actually in excess of the cost of importing
a fully built vehicle from abroad. Another example is a large automated bakery
in Tanzania which was more capital-intensive than the country’s oil refinery. The
bakery became so highly dependent on imported wheat that it displaced a number
of local, more efficient manufacturers (Chazan et al. 1999).
In essence, according to Chazan and company, the import-substitution strategy
failed to bring about a much-anticipated dramatic increase in local manufacturing.
The 7 per cent growth in manufacturing value added in the period 1963–1973
was reduced to 5.7 percent in the period 1973–1981. During this latter period,
14 African countries actually recorded a decrease in the manufacturing value
added. This same period also saw the contribution of manufacturing to total
GDP (Gross Domestic Product) fall in 20 countries in Africa south of the Sahara.
The continent’s share of world manufactured exports fell by almost half over the
years 1970 to 1976 to a low of 0.6 percent (Chazan et al. 1999).
The Socialist Model
As Björn Hettne states, ‘African Socialism is a vague concept, to say the least,
and encompasses many diverse viewpoints’ (1978:52). He goes on to suggest the
following five major groups:
1. ‘Afro Marxists emphasised Marxist-Leninist ideas of economic development
and political structure and included Ahmed Ben Bella of Algeria, Ahmed
Sékou Touré of Guinea, Gamal Abdel Nasser of Egypt, Kwame Nkrumah
of Ghana, Modibo Keita of Mali, Mengistu Haile Mariam of Ethiopia,
Jose Eduardo dos Santos and Agostinho Neto of Angola, Samora Machel
of Mozambique, Mohammed Siad Barre of Somalia, the military leaders of
Benin and Madagascar, Luiz De Almeida Cabral and Joao Bernago Vieira of
Guinea Bissau’ (Hettne 1978:52).
324
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
2. ‘Radical Socialists took a more critical approach and moved toward Marxism.
They included leaders in the Congo Brazzaville – at least before the 1977 coup’
(Hettne 1978:52).
3. ‘Moderate Socialists included Jomo Kenyatta of Kenya and Kenneth Kaunda
of Zambia who favoured a state-controlled socialist economy but were at the
same time anxious to attract foreign investment capital’ (Hettne 1978:52).
4. ‘Social Democrats were closely connected to European socialism and were
frequently pro-Western in outlook. These included Senegal’s Leopold Sedar
Senghor and briefly Zaire’s Mobutu Sese Seko and Chad’s Ngarta Tombalbaye’
(Hettne 1978:52).
5. ‘Agrarian Socialist or Populist was Tanzania’s Julius Nyerere and his Ujamaa
philosophy’ (Hettne 1978:52).
When combined, African Socialism included a wide ideological spectrum ranging
from Marxist-Leninist to populist ideas very similar to the Russian Narodniks
or Gandhi in India. African founding fathers espoused notions of socialism and
shared an aversion to colonialism. They saw independence as the way to build a
new and prosperous Africa.
The early proponents of African Socialism indicated a clear commitment to
the establishment of egalitarian societies, and a just and self-sufficient polity. The
state was envisioned as the mechanism through which these objectives could be
met. These pioneers extolled political centralisation and mobilisation as the tools
for real economic and social transformation on the African continent (Chazan
et al. 1999).
Nonetheless, when it came to implementing the philosophy in governance,
African Socialism barely endured the first decade of independence. By the early
1970s Nkrumah, Ben Bella, and Keita had been deposed, Nasser had died, and
Nyerere and Touré had taken different political paths. Nonetheless, the impact of
these first ideological experiments has outlasted their advocates. African Socialism
as a means of instilling a sense of national pride and African dignity still has
widespread appeal on the continent. The commitment to Pan-Africanism is often
traced back to these leaders because they were the first to attempt the exposition
of a coherent, albeit inconsistent, system of political and economic ideas. Their
concepts emerged as measuring rods for subsequent strategies.
The National Self-reliance Model
Theorists who promoted the National Self-reliance Model suggested a conscious
policy by developing countries to ‘de-link’ from the global economy. As a
concept, self-reliance was inaugurated by the Non-Aligned Countries at their
1970 meeting in Lusaka, Zambia and was further elaborated at their 1972
foreign ministers conference in Georgetown, Guyana. It was seen as an antithesis
to ‘dependency’. The concept emerged just before the concept New International
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
325
Economic Order (NIEO), which sought international co-operation as opposed
to withdrawal from the global economic system. In essence, national self-reliance
did not mean autarky – a complete severance of all economic relations with the
outside world – but the partial disengagement of a country from the dominant
relationship prevailing in the global economic system.
Johan Galtung provided the theoretical logic for national self-reliance as a
somewhat more inclusive development strategy in the following 13 hypotheses
(see Hettne 1978:32):
1. ‘Through SR (self-reliance) priorities will change towards production for basic
needs for those most in need’.
2. ‘Through SR mass participation is ensured’.
3. ‘Through SR local factors are utilised much better’.
4. ‘Through SR creativity is stimulated’.
5. ‘Through SR there will be more compatibility with local conditions’.
6. ‘Through SR there will be much more diversity of development’.
7. ‘Through SR there will be less alienation’.
8. ‘Through SR ecological balance will be more easily attained’.
9. ‘Through SR important externalities are internalised or given to neighbors at
the same level’.
10. ‘Through SR solidarity with others at the same level gets a solid base’.
11. ‘Through SR ability to withstand manipulation due to trade dependency
increases’.
12. ‘Through SR the military defense capability of the country increases’.
13. ‘Through SR as a basic approach today’s Center and Periphery are brought on
a more equal footing’.
As Hettne (1978) so correctly points out, this list of advantages of self-reliance
appears utopian. Galtung is at pains to explain that the 13 propositions should
be conceived as hypotheses about possible effects. The question here, then, is as
follows: How has national self-reliance fared in Africa?
For Mobutu’s government in Zaire (now the Democratic Republic of
Congo), national self-reliance became a central notion in the early 1970s. It
was accompanied by the notion of ‘authenticity’ – the Africanisation of names.
National self-reliance was also emphasised by the Acheampong government
in Ghana in 1972–1975. After 1975, it lost its aura on the African continent.
It was later revived by the populist regimes in Burkina Faso and Ghana in the
mid-1980s. The two countries that have pursued a more consistent national selfreliance policy in Africa are Algeria and Tanzania (Chazan et al. 1999). It is hoped
that a brief examination of how these two countries have employed national selfreliance will give the reader a sampling of how the strategy fared in Africa.
In the case of Tanzania, its commitment to national self-reliance, which
is intertwined with a socialist philosophy, can be traced back to the Arusha
Declaration authored by Nyerere in February of 1967. The declaration began with
326
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
a frank assessment of Tanzania’s economic woes and prospects. Nyerere’s major
concern was with the extensive demands his citizens were making for government
services which were becoming difficult to fulfil, even with substantial foreign
economic assistance. Tanzania also learned very quickly just how unreliable
foreign aid could be. Relations between Tanzania and its three largest aid donors
deteriorated: with West Germany because Tanzania had established diplomatic
relations with East Germany; with the United States over accusations that
the Central Intelligence Agency (CIA) was attempting to overthrow Nyerere’s
government; and with Britain because of an inadequate response from the
British over the Unilateral Declaration of Independence by the white minority
in Rhodesia (now Zimbabwe). West Germany and Britain froze their aid to
Tanzania, making it impossible for Tanzania to meet the development targets
outlined in the First Five-Year Plan it had adopted in 1964 (Chazan et al. 1999).
When Tanzania encountered difficulty attracting significant amounts of aid
from the former Eastern bloc countries, it had no other option but to pursue a
policy of national self-reliance if it wanted to continue its independent foreign
policy stance. The Arusha Declaration pointed out that if individuals were selfreliant, then, districts, regions, and the whole country would be self-reliant.
Because the vast majority of the Tanzanian population lived in the rural areas,
Nyerere placed greater emphasis on rural development by providing those areas
with education, health care, and potable water. He reasoned, therefore, that
priority in industrialisation should be given to industries that could service the
needs of the rural population. Greater self-reliance was seen as the way to:
1. necessitate acceptance by the population of (sometimes lower quality) locally
produced goods instead of imported luxuries,
2. reduce imports, and
3. diversify Tanzania’s trade links in order to lessen its dependence on existing
markets and suppliers (Chazan et al. 1999).
While on paper many Ujamaa villages now existed, the reality was that a very
small number of them operated on the collective basis as intended. By 1975,
the government had backed down from the idea of communal production. The
villagisation programme disrupted agricultural production; the situation was
further compounded by the 1974 drought. Thus, Tanzania had to import food
rather than being self-sufficient in agriculture. This, in turn, meant that Tanzania
had to face the major burden of using its scarce resources for foreign exchange.
Most discouraging was that very few villagers even had a clear understanding of
what self-reliance meant in practice (Chazan et al. 1999).
It is quite evident in the case of Tanzania that weak, dependent economies
are powerless when they seek to implement significant changes in the global
economy. While, on the one hand, Tanzania has been successful in pursuing its
foreign policy in the political arena, its economic policy on the other hand has
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
327
been affected by factors beyond its control and by the structural constraints of
the global economy.
Similarly, Algeria’s national self-reliance approach is undergirded by its
socialist development philosophy. Nevertheless, Algeria has plenty of energy
resources. This endowment has allowed Algeria to articulate a self-reliance policy
that stresses national control over natural resources as the major factor of being
‘master in one’s own house’ (Chazan et al. 1999).
Among the key characteristics of Algeria’s self-reliance policy are the
nationalisation of foreign-owned companies, the establishment of many stateowned enterprises, the insistence upon Algerian instead of expatriate managers,
the reinvestment of energy revenues in order to lessen recourse to foreign capital,
and a policy of leadership in the affairs of developing countries. For Algerians,
self-reliance means national control (Chazan et al. 1999).
Algeria’s 1976 National Charter, which is similar to the Arusha Declaration of
Tanzania, emphasises national accumulation of capital for investment as opposed
to becoming dependent on foreign investment and urges other developing
countries to do the same. The rationale is that a country first must count on
itself in order to influence the prices of its raw materials. Nevertheless, during
the period of concentrated investment in industrialisation, Algeria saw its
agricultural production decline. With its population rapidly growing, Algeria
became dependent upon food imports (Chazan et al. 1999).
The self-reliance programme of Algeria, just as that of Tanzania, was struck a
serious blow because of its inability to increase its agricultural production. The
decline of oil prices in the mid-1980s also forced Algeria to tighten its belt and
revise its investment projections. But unlike Tanzania, Algeria, as already stated,
possesses abundant amounts of energy resources which allow it to pursue its goal
of becoming ‘the master in its own house’.
The Regional Integration or Collective Self-reliance Model
Theorists who proposed the Regional Integration Model (or Collective Self-reliance,
as other writers refer to it) posit that in order to realise greater self-reliance, a
country must inevitably depend on cooperation from other countries that
share similar characteristics and goals. African countries learned very quickly
after independence that in order for them to overcome the problems of limited
economic resources, economic cooperation with their neighbours was a sensible
strategy. What, then, has been the result of regional integration in Africa?
The history of the notion of regional integration in Africa is lengthy. Even
before independence, colonial powers instituted regional integration systems for
their own needs instead of those of Africans. Transportation networks linking
peripheral areas and coastal centres were established by colonial administrators
to minimise their financial commitments, coordinate markets, and establish
328
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
common currency areas under their rule. Britain and France even promoted the
formation of federations, common service organisations, and common banking
systems among their colonies (Legum et al. 1979).
Regional integration in Africa after colonialism is different. While international
capital favoured the establishment of free trade areas from which it stood to
benefit, it also sought to undermine those regional integrative systems that
might hamper its freedom of action. Multinational Corporations (MNCs) are
particularly reluctant to encourage regional integration if they have medium- or
large-size markets and some limited local industrial capacity (Legum et al. 1979).
Since significant economic inequalities exist among countries in African
integrative systems, a number of fiscal and planning mechanisms were built into
the systems to compensate less industrialised African partners for the unequal
distribution of gains that generally result from the liberalisation of trade. But
the failure to implement such schemes heightened conflicts over cost-benefit
issues within these integrative systems. In some of the systems (for example, the
Organisation pour la mise en valeur de la Vallée du Fleuve Sénégal, or OMVS),
these conflicts led to the transformation of the associations and their abandonment
of planning objectives. In other systems such the Economic Community of West
African States (ECOWAS), cost-benefit conflicts led to many postponements in
the signing of the treaties and subsequent delays in implementing key harmonising
elements in them. In still others such as the East African Community (EAC),
similar conflicts led to the dissolution of the systems (Legum et al. 1979).
The South African Development Coordination Conference (SADCC),
which was an outgrowth from the Frontline States (Angola, Botswana, Lesotho,
Malawi, Mozambique, Tanzania, Swaziland, Zambia, and Zimbabwe), launched
to promote the transition to majority rule in Zimbabwe, emerged as the most
innovative attempt on the African continent to translate aspirations of regional
integration into reality. The system enjoyed moderate success in its first years
of existence. It was able to attract finance for a number of projects in the
transportation and communications fields. There was an increase in the amount
of trade between some of the member states. The trade was often conducted on
the basis of barter or paid for in local currencies (Chazan et al. 1999).
The SADCC organisation encountered two major problems, despite its initial
moderate success. The first major problem was that the organisation was heavily
dependent on foreign donors for its projects. Its annual donors’ conferences were
able to attract support for some projects, but the total assistance provided fell far
short of the system’s expectations. In several cases, the aid actually represented
the redirection of existing pledges instead of additional finance. Aid donors
demonstrated a marked reluctance to finance SADCC’s agricultural and industrial
projects. Reliance on foreign assistance is somewhat paradoxical since the
organisation’s stated goal is to reduce dependence of foreign aid (Chazan et al. 1999).
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
329
The organisation’s second major problem concerned the Frontline States
nemesis: i.e. apartheid South Africa. Since the apartheid regime believed that
the SADCC was an impediment to its hegemony in the region, it sought to
undermine the organisation. South Africa frequently invaded those states that
share a border with it. It also sponsored guerrilla movements hostile to the
established Frontline governments (such as the Mozambique National Resistance
Movement or RENAMO and the National Union for the Total Independence of
Angola or UNITA) to carry out acts of sabotage in these countries – destruction
of transportation and communication links, blowing up power lines, etc. Other
forms of South Africa’s intransigence were quite subtle:
refusing to provide railroad locomotives to head trains originating in Zimbabwe;
redirecting South Africa’s trade away from the port of Maputo; and offering
reduced tariffs on rail transport through South Africa for Zimbabwe’s main
exports of tobacco and cotton to encourage traders not to use other SADCC
routes (Chazan et al. 1999).
The foregoing review of the economic models African countries have employed
since independence clearly indicates that successful policy reforms and economic
development in Africa call for substantial political will on the part of African
governments. Because the international community has failed to provide the
requisite external support to promote substantive economic development on the
continent, African leaders must shoulder this responsibility by being willing to
make painful policy decisions.
Public Choice as an Alternative Approach
In order to analyse the behaviour of people in the marketplace, economists
develop a logically consistent theory of behaviour that can be tested against
reality. Through theory and empirical testing, they attempt to explain various
economic actions of decision-makers and, in general, how the market works.
This approach is also plausible in analysing the behaviour of people in the public
sphere. To explain how the collective decision-making process actually works, a
logically consistent theory linking individual behaviour to collective action, an
analysis of the implications of the theory, and the testing of these implications
against reality are called for.
Public Choice theorists have made great contributions to our understanding
of resource allocation by the public sector. These social scientists have also
provided a number of basic characteristics that influence outcomes in both the
market (private) and public sectors.2 Gwartney and Stroup (1983) summarise the
differences between these two sectors based on these theorists’ work. These are
examined here in terms of the African context. The first question to be dealt with
here is this: Why is Public Choice Theory relevant for economic development?
330
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
To say that Public Choice Theory is relevant to economic development is
to say that economic development will require some collective decisions, that
those decisions will be made at the national level, and that those participating
in the decisions (Africans, with whose welfare we are concerned) can be viewed
as rational and self-interested actors. It is, of course, impossible to prove that all
Africans, or any other people in any other continent for that matter, are rational
and self-interested actors in the business of life. The issue, however, is not whether
all Africans always behave rationally and self-interestedly. It is, rather, what kind
of behaviour predominates and therefore around which behaviour it makes sense
to design institutions.
Competitive Behaviour in the Market and Public Sectors
Competitive behaviour exists in both the market and public sectors. Just as in
the market sector where businesses compete for consumers’ money, so must
politicians compete for voters’ ballots. Ministers and directors of agencies,
like their counterparts in the private sector, compete for additional funds,
promotions, and additional power. Ethnic groups compete for power and
favourable policies. The nature of the competition and the criteria for success
do differ between the sectors. Nonetheless, both sectors must deal with the
reality of scarcity. The need to ration scarce resources inevitably leads to
competitive behaviour.
In the African context, this means that all countries, particularly those under
personal rule disguised as a democratic dispensation, must adopt true democratic
rule within what has come to be known as the Schumpeterian framework: that
is, the ‘institutional arrangement for arriving at political decisions in which
individuals acquire the power to decide by means of a competitive struggle for
the people’s vote’ (Schumpeter 1950:269).
Of course, the democratic idea is not foreign to the African continent. Morna,
for example, cites a book by a group of academics from Kenya, Tanzania and
Uganda titled Democratic Theory and Practice in Africa (1989) in which it is
clearly documented that democracy was deeply rooted in African traditions and
struggles against colonialism (Morna 1990). Among the Kikuyus, for instance,
government was by ‘committee’. There were no formal chiefs. Every man could
hope to be elected at least once to direct ethnic group policy. The ethnic group
was divided into halves, rather like the American two-party system. Each half
had its full complement of elders, judges, and parliamentarians throughout the
chain of command. While the officials of one half acted, officials of the other side
listened and consulted (Vlahos 1967).
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
331
Public Sector Organisation and the Individual
Consumption-payment Link
A consumer who wants to obtain a commodity must be willing to give up money
for that commodity. There is a one-to-one correspondence between consuming
the commodity and paying the price charged in the market. This is not the case,
however, in collective action. Governments do not usually establish a one-to-one
relationship between the citizen’s tax bill and the amount of political services s/he
receives. A citizen’s tax bill will be the same whether he or she likes or dislikes the
government’s spending policies. In some cases, the citizen could be made worse
off by a government programme and still end up paying for it.
Since many African economies are not fully monetised and records of financial
transactions are rarely kept, direct personal income taxes are difficult to collect.
That means that indirect taxes are the norm. These taxes include residency taxes,
sales taxes, excise taxes and import and export taxes. Indirect taxes like these are
generally regressive because they take away a larger proportion of lower income
as compared to higher income. The absence of progressive personal tax systems,
then, means that taxes are not collected based on a citizen’s ability to pay.
African farmers are relatively highly taxed. Export crops are levied between
40 and 50 per cent. This is in addition to taxation resulting from overvalued
exchange rates or inefficient market systems. Overall, however, very little revenue
is derived from taxation in many African countries due to their failure to exploit
their tax bases fully (The World Bank 1981). The high level of taxation of export
crops through export taxes and marketing board levies has kept export production
in many African countries below what it could be. This, in turn, has contributed
to the steep decline in Africa’s share in the world market.
It is important that African countries impose lighter tax burdens on the
‘motor’ (i.e. manufacturing) sector of their economies. This is necessary because
many state-owned manufacturing entities must now compete with multinational
companies that tend to relocate to countries where they have a lower tax burden.
By shifting heavier taxation toward tradeables, African tax systems will be able to
increase revenues as outputs increase. In the light of present African circumstances,
a single-stage ad valorem sales tax collected at the point of local manufacture
would be more suitable than other tax regimes. Taxation may raise prices, but
from the economic point of view it is superior to inflation as a source of finance
for capital formation because
1. the effect of taxation on prices is likely to be much smaller,
2. the discipline of controlling the money supply is easier to maintain, and
3. the incidence of taxation can be controlled more fairly and efficiently.
332
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Scarcity and Aggregate Consumption-payment Link in the Market
and Public Sectors
Even if a government is able to break the link between payment for a good and
the right of the individual to consume that good, the reality of the aggregate
consumption-aggregate payment link will not disappear. To be able to provide
scarce goods, certain alternatives have to be given up. No matter which sector
(private or public) produces (or distributes) scarce goods, someone must pay the
cost of providing such goods. As the amount of goods provided by a government
increases, so will the total costs of that government. More public goods mean
more taxes. Scarcity means that the link between aggregate consumption and
aggregate costs of production cannot be broken by public sector action.
There has been a notable trend among African governments to increase
overspending over many decades. These governments take more and more
responsibility for the immediate well-being of their citizens. Public expenditure
on education, health, and welfare is rising throughout Africa as citizens come to
expect more social services from their governments. As a result, the planning and
finance ministries in Africa, the key agencies involved in project development
and policy-making, need reinforcement if they are to play the important role
demanded by economic development.
Despite all this, however, in almost every country in Africa the financial and
budgetary instruments of public sectors are overburdened. Add to this the high
turnover that has taken place among statisticians in the planning and finance
ministries (The World Bank 1981) and it becomes challenging to execute
government programmes effectively, or to formulate coherent policies.
Given all this, it is imperative that African planning and finance ministries
develop a greater capacity in policy analysis, particularly in the areas of tax
planning, assessment of budgetary requests, and determination of overall fiscal
and monetary policies. African governments must provide these ministries with
more resources that will allow them to make credible technical contributions to
policy decisions at both the sectoral and macroeconomic levels. Also, incentives
should be provided to help stem the rise in turnover among qualified statisticians
who are desperately needed to provide essential data.
The Element of Compulsion in the Public Sector
The dominant characteristic of market organisation is voluntary exchange. A
minority need not yield to the desires of the majority in the private sector. The
views of the majority do not prevent minority consumers from buying desired
goods and services. Governments have a monopoly on the use of coercion,
whereas large corporations cannot force consumers to buy their products.
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
333
When a majority (either directly elected or through the legislative process)
decides on a particular policy, the minority (even against its will) must accept the
policy and help pay for its costs.
In order to achieve social cooperation, the right to compel is necessary in
certain cases. For instance, legislation compelling drivers not to operate their
vehicles while under the influence of alcohol enhances the safety of others.
In essence, some limitations are sometimes needed in order to increase social
cooperativeness and increase available options in society.
In Africa, however, the issue has been one of excessive compulsion. Chazan
et al. note that authoritarian politics have dominated the domestic scene in
Africa. As they emphasise,
‘competition over access to and control of state resources has nurtured an
instrumental view of politics in which the public domain is seen as a channel for
individual or partisan enrichment. Zero-sum patterns of interaction (one side’s
gain is another side’s loss) have led to the muzzling of loyal oppositions and to an
intolerance of dissenting opinions’ (Chazan et al. 1999:7).
Over the course of many years, these conditions have made the military an
important mechanism of bringing about political change. The overwhelming
majority of African countries have witnessed some form of an attempted coup.
And, as I found after a meta-analysis of 92 studies on Africa’s military intervention
and military rule,
1. economic conditions, the domestic environment for political participation,
social mobilisation, and foreign influence have negative, albeit small, effects
on coup d’état outcomes; and
2. institutional structure, and pluralism have positive, but small, effects on coup
d’état outcomes (Bangura 1994b).
These developments, as to be expected, have not improved governments’
capacities. The top-heavy administrations run by civilian or military leaders
wield very little authority, and the power of their governmental institutions
remains weak. Instability indeed has become the modus operandi throughout
post-colonial Africa. Thus, as argued earlier, real democratic governments are
needed in Africa to help ensure checks and balances on the public sectors’ element
of compulsion. An encouraging sign is that more countries have adopted the
democratic agenda. Whether or not the effort will transcend the conduction of
elections remains to be seen.
Collective Legislative Decision-making
Voters must choose among candidates who represent bundles of positions on
issues when collective decisions are made through the legislative process. A voter
cannot choose the views of Candidate A on certain issues and simultaneously
334
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
choose the views of Candidate B who is opposed to the former’s positions. Unable
to separate a candidate’s views on one issue from his views on another, the voter’s
power to register preferences on specific issues is reduced.
Choosing a representative is a bit like choosing an agent who will both control
a substantial portion of one’s income and at the same time regulate one’s activities.
The voter’s preferred candidate may or may not be elected. The elected candidate
has the responsibility, however, to represent thousands of other persons on each
legislative issue.
Education, then, becomes a key factor for enhancing one’s ability to analyse
each candidate’s positions. In short order, an educated voter is a good political
consumer. Most countries where education is minimal and literacy is severely
limited tend to be undemocratic; they tend to be traditional, adhering to
authoritarian and hierarchical values. The illiterate person increasingly finds
himself/herself disenfranchised from effective political participation. S/he also
becomes barred from social and economic paths toward a better and more secure life.
In the case of Africa, massive investments in education have paid dividends.
By the 1980s, literacy rates had more than doubled in many countries. In
Tanzania, rural adult literacy rose from 10 per cent to 65 per cent between 1961
and 1981. By 1982, primary school enrolments throughout Africa south of the
Sahara averaged 77 per cent of the total primary-school age population. Only a
small number of countries – Chad, Mali, Burkina Faso, Somalia, Niger, Burundi
and Mauritania – had enrolments of less than 50 per cent of the age group.
In a few countries, such as Congo and Gabon, the figures for enrolments were
more than 130 percent, reflecting the fact that large numbers of citizens beyond
the primary-school age groups were going to school. There was also widespread
evidence that traditional prejudice against the education of girls was waning as
indicated by a weighted mean of 60 per cent of the female primary-school age
population in 1982 (Chazan et al. 1999).
Despite these gains in primary education enrolments, the same cannot be said
about secondary and post-secondary education and in other areas like curriculum
reform. A number of constraints have hampered African governments in these
areas. These include
1. financial problems,
2. popular expectations of improved access to all levels of schooling, and
3. lack of employment opportunities for secondary-school graduates and for
some university graduates (especially those with liberal arts degrees).
Some African governments have been reluctant to increase the output of
secondary-school and university-educated students beyond the short-term
personnel needs of their economies for fear of the discontent that would be bred
by frustrated expectations (Chazan et al. 1999).
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
335
Given the common educational imbalances in African countries, governments
may need to shift from existing approaches and recast their educational systems
to meet their specific needs. To be given up are traditional educational approaches
that seek to prepare people for relatively fixed roles and those that are associated
with status. To be pursued are different approaches that are geared toward the
meeting of modes of skill acquisition and self-determination. The integration of
education within their overall development strategies means that governments
need to place greater emphasis on wider participation in the educational process.
This will include both formal and informal processes if education is to be
incorporated more directly into the overall development process itself.
Distribution of Income and Power in Both the Market and Public Sectors
In the marketplace, people who supply more highly valued resources get larger
incomes. The amount of money a person receives in the marketplace hinges
upon his/her abilities, drive, skills, perceptiveness, good fortune, and inheritance,
among other factors. The result is an unequal distribution of consumer power.
Ballots speak when decisions are made democratically in the public arena. The
name of the game is ‘One person, one vote’. This is not to imply that political
goods and services are allocated equally to all citizens by the collective decisionmaking process. Indeed, personal advantages are obtained by citizens who are
more astute than others in using the political process.
Social groups in Africa have become more astute about their own particular
circumstances. According to Chazan and her colleagues (1999), ethnic groupings,
incipient classes and a number of local communities, professional associations,
trade unions, women’s organisations, and religious movements have formed to
pursue their own interests. In some circumstances, patron-client relationships
have emerged to raise demands and to distribute benefits. In other cases,
politicisation has increased while access to the political centre has been severely
curtailed. The opportunity for citizen involvement has thus varied greatly from
country to country and from time to time.
In view of the verity that any attempt to alter the distribution of income and
political power will also affect supply conditions and the political climate, and
in the light of Africa’s multi-ethnic states, the issue is highly complex. Market or
political solutions will lead to unequal distribution of income and power so long
as the preferences and abilities of individuals differ. Incentives must therefore be
provided in order to inspire every citizen to undertake productive activities.
This truism demands effective channels of communication in order to coordinate
the actions of citizens and decision-makers, and to provide the incentive structure
that motivates decision-makers to act. The information provided will instruct
policymakers as to
1. how to use scarce resources and
2. which policies are intensely desired by citizens.
336
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
A reward-penalty system, which induces individuals to cooperate with one
another and motivates them to work efficiently, will help to strengthen the
political system. The efficiency of the system will depend on
1. competitive and fair market and political conditions; and
2. securely defined private and public property rights.
Conclusion
The suggestions in the foregoing analysis may be objectionable to those who
have insisted that the search for new paths to development in Africa demands
that the whole traditional conceptual and theoretical framework of development
as derived from the West be replaced by more indigenous development notions.
These observers may also argue that Public Choice, being a Western theory,
should not be tested in Africa. But herein lies the first problem: How do African
governments implement indigenous development policies when most of them
are dependent on tourism, Western aid, and when even in the villages foreign
products are preferred to locally manufactured ones? These are serious concerns
for social science in Africa.
A second problem involves the relationship between resource endowments and
the sizes of the domestic markets. How, for example, should the great mineral,
oil and other natural resource wealth of African countries be used? An obvious
answer will be export, but this raises the whole issue of dependency.
A third problem is the fact that African political leaders lack the capacity
to propose new forms for society or any kind of strategy for coping with the
challenge of MNCs. In a global economy controlled by a very new form of
oligopoly capital via globalisation (a more or less all-embracing phenomenon),
how can African leaders formulate new strategies to face this serious challenge?
Very often proposals by government officials are criticised by local bourgeoisies
who prefer to be directly associated with the multinational corporations.
The suggestion of Public Choice Theory as a plausible approach for sustained
economic development in Africa hinges on the fact that it begins with two
fundamental assumptions that are relevant to any society:
1. that all individuals act rationally in their own self-interest, and
2. that all interests are individual economic interests.
The two assumptions undoubtedly are objectionable from many points of view.
Moreover, given their individualistic, rationalistic and competitive connotations,
they appear unlikely to allow for a government based on unanimous consent. But
in fact, in conjunction with one another (a much more plausible assumption),
they are sufficient to deduce that such a government can exist.
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
337
Of course, if other human motives and values are mixed into the initial
assumption (the value of political community per se; man is by nature a political
animal, etc.) this conclusion can be reached more directly – indeed too directly to
be particularly interesting. The point is that this conclusion can be reached even
on the basis of these apparently unfruitful assumptions. Essentially, it is necessary
to show that common interests exist and, at the same time, that common interests
are not always realised in the absence of some form of coercive authority.
What, then, does Public Choice Theory teach us about development planning?
Such an endeavour would take a number of forms. Public Choice’s concern
for the motives of decision-makers suggests that policies designed to promote
development can be expected to be adopted for other reasons such as soliciting
support for the government or increasing political control. How will this emerge?
Price and tax policies, for example, designed to encourage investment can be
implemented to enhance the inherent stability of a government. Social overhead
capital projects such as roads, irrigation projects, educational programmes,
etc. can be distributed with a maximum concern for the returns to supporters
of a government and to increase a regime’s ability to deliver coercion among
dissidents. In order to avoid distortions that often lead to wastefulness, sacrifices
of some goals are in order. Indeed, a common saying among some Public Choice
Theory enthusiasts is quite fitting: We cannot have our cake and eat it too!
Notes
1.
2.
On June 5, 1947, at the commencement exercise at Harvard University, Secretary
of State George C. Marshall announced what came to be known as the Marshall
Plan: i.e. America’s intent to make significant financial contributions to rebuild a
war-torn Europe. The major goal of the plan was to promote economic integration
and cooperation among European countries. Between 1948 and 1952 (when the
plan ended), $13.3 billion had been spent, with over half of this amount going to
England, France, and Italy (refer to Nash 1958:42–44 for details).
I am referring here to the contributions of Kenneth Arrow, Duncan Black, James
Buchanan, Charles Bullock, Anthony Downs, David Mayhew, Norman Nicholson,
William Niskanen, Mancur Olson, Clifford Russell, Robert Tollison, and Gordon
Tullock. See full citations in the Reference section.
References
Adelman, Irma, and Taft Morris, Cynthia, 1973, Economic Growth and Social Equity in
Developing Countries, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Arrow, Kenneth J., 1951, Social Choice and Individual Values, New York, NY: Wiley.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 1994a, United States Development Assistance to Egypt, 1957–1987,
San Francisco, CA: Mellen University Research Press.
Bangura, Abdul Karim, 1994b, ‘Explaining and Predicting the Causes of Military Coups
d’État in Africa: A Meta-Analysis’, in A.K. Bangura, ed., Research Methodologies and
African Studies, Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
338
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Black, Duncan, 1951, Committee Decisions with Complementary Valuation, London,
UK: W. Hodge.
Black, Duncan, 1958, The Theory of Committees and Elections, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Buchanan, James M., 1967, Public Finance in Democratic Process, Chapel Hill, NC:
University of North Carolina Press.
Buchanan, James M., 1969, The Demand and Supply of Public Goods, Chicago, IL: Rand
McNally.
Buchanan, James M., and Tullock, Gordon, 1967, Calculus of Consent, Ann Arbor, MI:
University of Michigan Press.
Buchanan, James M., and Tollison, Robert D. eds., 1972, Theory of Public Choice, Ann
Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Bullock III, Charles S., 1972, ‘House Careerists: Changing Patterns of Longevity and
Attrition’, American Political Science Review, Vol. 66, No. 4, pp. 1295–1300.
Chazan, Naomi; Lewis, Peter; Mortimer, Robert; Rothchild, Donald and Stedman,
Stephen John, 1999, Politics and Society in Contemporary Africa, 3rd edition., Boulder,
CO: Lynne Riener Publishers.
Chenery, Hollis. B., and Bruno, Michael, 1962, ‘Development Alternatives in an Open
Economy: The Case of Israel’, The Economic Journal, Vol. 72, No. 285, pp. 79–103.
Chenery, Hollis B., and Adelman, Irma, 1966a, ‘Foreign Aid and Economic Development:
The Case of Greece’, The Review of Economics and Statistics, Vol. 48, No. 1, pp. 1–19.
Chenery, Hollis B. and Adelman, Irma , 1966b, ‘Trade, Aid and Economic Development’,
in S.H. Robock and L.M. Solomon, eds., International Development, Dobbs Ferry,
NY: Oceana Publications.
Chenery, Hollis B., and Strout, Alan M., 1966c, ‘Foreign Assistance and Economic
Development’, The American Economic Review, Vol. 56, No. 4, pp. 679–733.
Chenery, Hollis B., and Peter Eckstein, 1970, ‘Development Alternatives for Latin
America’, Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 78, No. 4, Part 2, pp. 966–1006.
Chenery, Hollis B.; Ahluwalia, Montek S.; Bell, C.L.G., Duloy, John H. and Jolly,
Richard, 1974, Redistribution with Growth, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Coleman, James S., 1966, ‘Individual Interests and Collective Action’, in G. Tullock,
ed., Papers on Non-Market Decision-Making, Charlottesville, VA: Thomas Jefferson
Center for Political Economy, University of Virginia.
Downs, Anthony, 1957, An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York, NY: Harper and Row.
Downs, Anthony, 1960, ‘Why the Government Budget Is Too Small in a Democracy’,
World Politics, Vol. 12, No. 4, pp. 541–563.
Gwartney, James D., and Stroup, Richard L., 1983, Microeconomics: Private and Public
Choice, New York, NY: Academic Press.
Hettne, Björn, 1978, Current Issues in Development Theory, Gothenburg, Sweden: SAREC.
Hettne, Björn and Wallensteen, Peter, 1978, Emerging Trends in Development Theory,
Gothenburg, Sweden: SAREC.
Legum, Colin I.; Zartman, William; Mytelka, Lynn K., and Langdon, Steven., 1979,
Africa in the 1980s: A Continent in Crisis, New York, NY: McGraw-Hill Book
Company.
Bangura: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
339
Mayhew, David R., 1974, Congress: The Electoral Connection, New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Morna, Colleen Lowe, 1990, ‘Africa’s Campuses Lead Pro-Democracy Drives?’, The
Chronicle of Higher Education, Vol. xxxvii, No. 13, pp. A1, A40.
Nash, Henry T., 1958, American Foreign Policy, Homewood, IL: The Dorsey Press.
Nisbet, Robert A., 1969, Social Change and History, New York: Oxford University Press.
Niskanen, William A., 1971, Bureaucracy and Representative Government, New York, NY:
Aldine-Atherton.
Olson, Mancur, 1965 & 1971, The Logic of Collective Action, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Rostow, Walt Whitman, 1960, The Stages of Economic Growth: A Non-Communist
Manifesto, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Russell, Clifford S., and Nicholson, Norman K., eds., 1981, Public Choice and Rural
Development, Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.
Schumpeter, Joseph Alois, 1950, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, New York, NY:
Harper Torchbooks.
Tullock, Gordon, 1965, The Politics of Bureaucracy, Washington, DC: Public Affairs Press.
Tullock, Gordon, 1966, Toward a Mathematics of Politics, Ann Arbor, MI: University of
Michigan Press.
Unom, Sam, 2019, ‘Africa’s Economic Development Is Impeded by Irregular Legacy
Institutions’, Foundation for Economic Education Stories. (https://fee.org/articles/
africas-economic-development-is-impeded-by-irregular-legacy-institutions/).
6 November 2021.
Vlahos, Olivia, 1967, African Beginnings, Greenwich, MN: Pawcett Publications, Inc.
World Bank, 1981, Accelerated Development in Sub-Saharan Africa, Washington, DC:
World Bank Publications.
Appendices
Appendix A: List of CODESRIA Staff and Facilitators
Name
Institutional Affiliation
Murunga, Godwin R.
Executive Secretary, CODESRIA, Dakar,
Senegal
Oanda, Ibrahim
Senior Program Officer and Head of the
Training, Grants and Fellowship Programme,
CODESRIA, Dakar, Senegal
Awah, Leonide Azah
Program Manager in the Department of
Training Grants and Fellowships,
CODESRIA, Dakar, Senegal
Sambou-Tchicaya, Dominique Tania
Bilingual Administrative Assistant in the
Training, Grants and Fellowship Programme,
CODESRIA, Dakar, Senegal
Bangura, Abdul Karim
American University, Washington DC, USA
Bizos, Anthony
University of Pretoria, South Africa
Mensah, Joseph
York University, Toronto, Canada
Appendix B: Table of Contents (General Introduction,
List of Sections and Chapters, with page numbers)
General Introduction ...................................................................................................................................................................1
Theory: What It Is, General Types, Levels, and Import.........................................................................4
Constructing a Theoretical Framework.................................................................................................................7
I
BRIEF DISCUSSIONS OF THE THEORIES
Chapter 1: African-centred.................................................................................................................................................. 13
Afrenaissance.............................................................................................................................................................................. 13
African Essential Dignity ............................................................................................................................................... 14
African Humanism............................................................................................................................................................15
African Nationalism ............................................................................................................................................................ 16
Africana Womanism............................................................................................................................................................ 17
Africanism..................................................................................................................................................................................... 18
Afrocentricity............................................................................................................................................................................. 19
Afropolitanism ......................................................................................................................................................................... 21
Asanteism ...................................................................................................................................................................................... 22
Ben Bellaism............................................................................................................................................................................... 23
Black Feminism ....................................................................................................................................................................... 24
Cabralism ...................................................................................................................................................................................... 25
Consciencism or Nkrumahism ................................................................................................................................ 26
Diopism .......................................................................................................................................................................................... 27
Falolaism ........................................................................................................................................................................................ 28
Gaddafism..................................................................................................................................................................................... 29
Garveyism ..................................................................................................................................................................................... 30
Gnoseology .................................................................................................................................................................................. 31
Kagisano ......................................................................................................................................................................................... 32
Mandelaism................................................................................................................................................................................. 33
Nasserism ...................................................................................................................................................................................34
Négritude....................................................................................................................................................................................... 35
Pan-Africanism ........................................................................................................................................................................ 36
Pan-Blackism ............................................................................................................................................................................. 39
Sankarism ...................................................................................................................................................................................... 40
Ubuntuism ................................................................................................................................................................................... 41
Ujamaa ............................................................................................................................................................................................. 42
Womanism ................................................................................................................................................................................... 43
Zuluism ........................................................................................................................................................................................... 45
344
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Chapter 2: Architecture, Art, Community, and Culture ...................................................................... 53
Architecture ............................................................................................................................................................................53
Abstraction Theory ...................................................................................................................................................... 53
Concretion Theory ...................................................................................................................................................... 55
Phenomenology Theory .......................................................................................................................................... 55
Art ....................................................................................................................................................................................................... 56
Abstraction Theory ..................................................................................................................................................... 56
Divine Principle Theory.......................................................................................................................................... 58
General Theory of Patterns or Meta-Morphology Theory ...................................................... 59
Community .............................................................................................................................................................................60
Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft......................................................................................................................... 60
Independent vs Dependent Communities Theory ........................................................................ 61
Naturalistic Hierarchy Theory .......................................................................................................................... 62
Culture ............................................................................................................................................................................................ 63
Cognitive Theory .......................................................................................................................................................... 63
Cultural Relativity Theory .................................................................................................................................... 65
Cultural Selection Theory ..................................................................................................................................... 66
Ecological Theory ......................................................................................................................................................... 67
High and Low Context Theory........................................................................................................................ 68
Linguistic Relativity Theory ................................................................................................................................ 70
Social Learning Theory ............................................................................................................................................ 71
Chapter 3: Decision-Making, Economics, and Education – Learning/Teaching...... 77
Decision-Making ...............................................................................................................................................................77
Incrementalism/Muddling-Through Theory ....................................................................................... 77
Mixed-Scanning Theory ......................................................................................................................................... 79
Rational Choice Theory .......................................................................................................................................... 80
Economics ................................................................................................................................................................................81
Anarchist Theory ........................................................................................................................................................... 81
Capitalist Theory ........................................................................................................................................................... 82
Communist Theory..................................................................................................................................................... 84
Public Choice Theory................................................................................................................................................ 85
Socialist Theory............................................................................................................................................................... 86
Education – Learning/Teaching .........................................................................................................................87
Andragogy............................................................................................................................................................................ 87
Conflict Theory .............................................................................................................................................................. 89
Ergonagy ............................................................................................................................................................................... 90
Functional Theory ........................................................................................................................................................ 91
Heutagogy............................................................................................................................................................................ 92
Interactionist Theory ................................................................................................................................................. 93
Organisational Theory.............................................................................................................................................. 95
Appendix B
345
Pedagogy................................................................................................................................................................................ 97
Social Closure Theory ............................................................................................................................................... 98
Tirbyi........................................................................................................................................................................................ 99
Ubuntugogy ....................................................................................................................................................................101
Chapter 4: Family, Geography, and Health and Medicine ........................................................... 109
Family.................................................................................................................................................................................... 109
Biological Theory .......................................................................................................................................................109
Cultural Theory ...........................................................................................................................................................111
Geography ............................................................................................................................................................................ 112
Agricultural Land Use Theory ........................................................................................................................112
Agricultural Models and Theories...............................................................................................................113
Culture Theory .............................................................................................................................................................114
Geographic Location Theory ..........................................................................................................................115
Industry and Economic Development Theories............................................................................117
Industrial Location Theory ...............................................................................................................................119
Land Use and Resources Models .................................................................................................................121
Geopolitical Theory .................................................................................................................................................122
Population and Migration Models .............................................................................................................123
Process Theory ..............................................................................................................................................................125
Urban Structure Theory .......................................................................................................................................127
Urbanisation Models ..............................................................................................................................................128
Health and Medicine ................................................................................................................................................. 129
Germ Theory..................................................................................................................................................................129
Hippocratic Theory ..................................................................................................................................................130
Humoral Theory .........................................................................................................................................................131
Chapter 5: Language and Linguistics, and Law and Order ...........................................................139
Language and Linguistics ..................................................................................................................................... 139
Deficit Hypothesis ....................................................................................................................................................139
Guthrie’s Association Theory ..........................................................................................................................140
Metalingual Theory........................................................................................................................................................141
Phatic Communion Theory ..................................................................................................................................142
Rhetic Theory......................................................................................................................................................................143
Rhetorical Theory ......................................................................................................................................................145
Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis ......................................................................................................................................145
Tolman’s Sign-Gestalt Theory .........................................................................................................................146
Variability Concept ..................................................................................................................................................147
Law and Order .....................................................................................................................................................................148
Marxist Theory .............................................................................................................................................................148
Positivist Theory ..........................................................................................................................................................149
Social Contract Theory .........................................................................................................................................150
Utilitarian Theory ......................................................................................................................................................151
346
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
Chapter 6: Literature, Mathematics, and Peace and Conflict Resolution ......................155
Literature ...................................................................................................................................................................................155
Cultural Studies Theory .......................................................................................................................................155
Ethnic Studies and Postcolonial Criticism..........................................................................................156
Formalism and New Criticism ......................................................................................................................158
Gender Studies and Queer Theory ............................................................................................................159
Marxism and Critical Theory..........................................................................................................................160
New Historicism and Cultural Materialism ......................................................................................162
Structuralism and Poststructuralism.........................................................................................................164
Traditional Literary Criticism.........................................................................................................................165
Mathematics ....................................................................................................................................................................... 166
Ethnomathematical Theory ..............................................................................................................................166
Relativity Theory ........................................................................................................................................................167
Ideal-Proof Dialectic Theory............................................................................................................................168
Peace and Conflict Resolution ............................................................................................................................169
Negative Peace vs Positive Peace Paradigm .........................................................................................169
Peace through Communication and Conflict Resolution Paradigm ..........................170
Peace through Law and World Order Paradigm ...........................................................................172
Peace through Nonviolence Paradigm ....................................................................................................173
Peace through Personal and Community Transformation or Love Paradigm .........174
Peace through Power and Coercion Paradigm ................................................................................175
Peace through Respect ...........................................................................................................................................176
Peace through Ubuntu/Communalism Paradigm .......................................................................177
Chapter 7: Politics, Race and Ethnicity, Religion, and Sexuality/Gender ......................187
Politics ..........................................................................................................................................................................................187
Idealist Theory ..............................................................................................................................................................187
Marxist Theory .............................................................................................................................................................189
Rational Choice Theory Or New Political Economy ...............................................................190
Realist Theory................................................................................................................................................................191
Social Contract Theory .........................................................................................................................................192
Systems Analysis Theory ......................................................................................................................................194
Race and Ethnicity...........................................................................................................................................................195
Darwinian Theory .....................................................................................................................................................195
Genesis Theory .............................................................................................................................................................196
Appendix B
347
Religion .......................................................................................................................................................................................198
Culture Theory .............................................................................................................................................................198
Durkheimian Theory ..............................................................................................................................................199
Social Change Theory ............................................................................................................................................200
Social Ecology Theory ...........................................................................................................................................202
Social Structure Theory ........................................................................................................................................202
Sexuality/Gender ...............................................................................................................................................................204
Africancentric and Third World Theory ...............................................................................................204
Biological Theory .......................................................................................................................................................206
Conservative/Stand-Up Theory ....................................................................................................................207
(De)/(Re)/(Post)Constructivist Theories ..............................................................................................209
Liberal Theory ...............................................................................................................................................................210
Postmodernist Theory ............................................................................................................................................212
Radical Feminist Theory......................................................................................................................................214
Sexual Difference Theory ....................................................................................................................................215
Sociological Theory ..................................................................................................................................................217
Chapter 8: Social Movements and Change, Social Stratification, and War...................225
Social Movements and Change........................................................................................................................ 225
Le Bon’s Mob Psychology Theory ...............................................................................................................225
Neil Smelser’s Value-Added Model Theory ........................................................................................226
Resource Mobilisation Theory .......................................................................................................................228
Social Stratification ..................................................................................................................................................... 229
Class Theory ...................................................................................................................................................................229
Elite Theory .....................................................................................................................................................................230
Stratification Theory................................................................................................................................................231
War .............................................................................................................................................................................................. 233
Idealist/Lockean Theory.......................................................................................................................................233
Just War Theory ...........................................................................................................................................................234
Pacifist Theory...............................................................................................................................................................235
Realist/Hobbesian Theory..................................................................................................................................236
Social Contract/Rousseauian Theory .......................................................................................................238
348
Theoretical Grounding in African Research
II
APPLICATIONS OF A SAMPLE OF THEORIES
Chapter 9: Mandelaism and Leadership in Africa
Abdul Karim Bangura.......................................................................................................................................................245
Attributes of Mandelaism.........................................................................................................................................249
Principles of Mandelaism.........................................................................................................................................254
A Caveat ......................................................................................................................................................................................261
Chapter 10: Dialectics – Its Theorisation and Application to Africa’s Development
Joseph Mensah..........................................................................................................................................................................265
Dialectics: Nature and Characteristics........................................................................................................266
The Nature of Development and African Development ...........................................................271
Understanding Development and African Development through Dialectics ........274
African Development: An Exercise in Creative Destruction and
the Negation of the Negation .........................................................................................................................275
Development and the Interchangeability of Causes and Effects ....................................278
African Development and the Transformation of Quantity into Quality .............279
Conclusion: The Way Forward......................................................................................................................280
Chapter 11: Theorising Norms: Constructivism and its Application to the Study
of Africa’s International Relations
Anthony Bizos ...........................................................................................................................................................................285
The ‘Constructivist-Turn’ in International Relations Theorising ...................................287
On Norms, Identity and Behaviour..........................................................................................................290
On Norms and Why They Matter .............................................................................................................295
Constructivist Scholarship and Theorising Norm Diffusion ..............................................297
The Norm-life Cycle Model .............................................................................................................................301
Norm Localisation ....................................................................................................................................................301
Norm Subsidiarity .....................................................................................................................................................302
Reflections on Constructivist Norm Theorising: Prospects
and Limitations .........................................................................................................................................................303
Pathway 1: Shaping Global Norm Creation Processes ............................................................309
Pathway 2: African Norms that May or May not Diffuse beyond the Continent ...309
Pathway 3: Shaping International Norms through Creative Implementation .......310
Pathway 4: Direct Contestation of Global Norms......................................................................310
Shaping Global Norm Creation Processes ..........................................................................................311
African Norms that May or May not Diffuse beyond the Continent .......................311
Shaping International Norms through Creative Implementation ................................312
Appendix B
349
Direct Contestation of Global Norms....................................................................................................312
Chapter 12: Public Choice Theory and Economic Development in Africa
Abdul Karim Bangura.......................................................................................... 317
Previous Development Models Used in Africa and Reasons for their Failures .....319
The Simple Growth Model ...............................................................................................................................319
The Redistribution with Growth Model ..............................................................................................321
The Import-substitution Model ...................................................................................................................322
The Socialist Model..................................................................................................................................................323
The National Self-reliance Model ...............................................................................................................324
The Regional Integration or Collective Self-reliance Model ..............................................327
Public Choice as an Alternative Approach .............................................................................................329
Competitive Behaviour in the Market and Public Sectors...................................................330
Public Sector Organisation and the Individual Consumption-payment Link.......331
Scarcity and Aggregate Consumption-payment Link in the Market
and Public Sectors............................................................................................................................................332
The Element of Compulsion in the Public Sector .......................................................................332
Collective Legislative Decision-making.................................................................................................333
Distribution of Income and Power in Both the Market and Public Sectors .......335