What Is A Nation State For? – By Yehudah Mirsky
marginalia.lareviewofbooks.org /nation-state-yehudah-mirsky/
Yehudah Mirsky
Yehudah Mirsky in Defining Israel: A Forum on Recent Attempts to
Determine Israel’s Character
[This essay is part of Defining Israel: A Forum on Recent Attempts to Determine Israel’s Character. The
forum’s home page can be found here.]
What Is A Nation State For?
An odd and simple-minded question, perhaps, given the ubiquity and
centrality of nation states in our world, but still worth asking, especially
when first principles are on the table.
“A state,” Max Weber lucidly said, “is a human community that
(successfully) claims the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical
force within a given territory.” It is the prerequisite for survival beyond
the clan, within one’s society and beyond the state’s territory. More
than just the guarantor of survival, the state is, in its illiberal forms, the
ensemble of legal instruments for political and socio-cultural practices
through which the majority, or at least the ruling elites, impose their will
on everyone else. It is, in its liberal forms, the ensemble of legal
instruments and genuinely democratic frameworks for political and
socio-cultural practices through which citizens, qua individuals, work
out their respective claims for power and freedom. This freedom in turn can take many forms, from, for
instance, freedom for one’s own ethnic group, to freedom from one’s own ethnic group.
Broadly autocratic, oligarchic and repressive governance has been with us for a very long time as has the
state’s monopoly of legitimate coercion within a given territory. Liberalism, on the other hand, and the
nation state both arose in the West at the same point in history, and in some respects, arose together.
Both responded to deep changes in the nature of identity — of meaningful belonging.
The late Shmuel Noah Eisenstadt wrote that identity takes three forms — primordial (we could say ethnic,
or kinship), civic (or social), and transcendent (the realm of ultimate values). Eisentsadt, in a sense,
restates Aristotle’s reconstruction of the concentric emergence of the polis from the family to village to citystate, but he replaces Aristotle’s serene teleology with the structural and existential anxieties of modern
sociology. In a stable group or individual, the three dimensions of belonging more or less work together, or
at least not too much at cross-purposes with one another. When the structures holding those identities
together come apart, our responses alternate between liberation and terror.
So it was when, in Western Europe, the Catholic Church gave way in the Protestant Reformation,
followed, after much bloodshed, by the Westphalian order of semi-nation states that after 1648 came to
provide the framework for meaningful and hopefully secure collective belonging. In this prying loose from
the c/Catholic framework, salvation was now something to be attained by the believer’s own relationship
with God rather than via participation in the Church qua Body of Christ. This was accompanied by the
corresponding end of the identification of the body of the monarch with the body politic. These
developments had deep implications for the individual, as person, and as a unit of meaning in his (for
centuries, his) own right. Meaningful collective belonging now sought an anchor sunk deep in the territory
of the state and the linguistic and cultural inheritances of its inhabitants.
There are, needless to say, many stories to be told here; many more than can be encompassed in a broadbrush essay such as this. But the one that concerns us is a story of the collapse of transcendence and
immanence into one another — with the ultimate meanings of the religious order now being instantiated in
the state and the subjectivity of the individual coming to be seen as one with the subjectivity of the nation.
These processes moved in tandem with the other crucial dimensions of the ending of pre-modern
corporate life, namely the rethinking of social and political life in terms of equality and freedom.
freedom can take many forms, from freedom for one’s own ethnic group, to freedom
from one’s own ethnic group
What has any of this to do with the Jews? Quite a bit.
Relieving or at least coming to terms with the civil inequality of the Jews was central to the new meaning of
statehood in modernity — quite literally a stumbling block to the Jews, and, often enough, a foolishness to
the Gentiles. In the new, modernizing nation-states, the limited but genuine forms of Jewish collective life,
as lived in the pre-modern self-governing Jewish community known as the Kehilla, no longer made sense.
Beyond the technical sticking points of Jews’ collective perdurance as pockets within the nation state and
the persistence of the Jews’ distinctive integration of primordial identity and transcendence in a universal
key, was an unresolved structural conundrum in the emergence of that new statehood itself.
The perceived failure of Western European nation states to accommodate the Jews gave rise to the
political Zionism of Theodor Herzl and others. To the East, even those (to put it mildly) compromised
efforts at liberalization were too much for the Russian Empire to attempt; so it was that the precarious
sense of insecurity and regular misery among so the much of the masses of the Pale of Settlement, and
the emerging nationalism of those around them, gave Zionism its most pressing moral (and much
demographic) heft. It was, moreover, the Eastern European struggle to rethink and reconstitute the
tradition that gave rise to a different Zionism, as a project of cultural renaissance and, for others, of cultural
and political revolution, not only against exile but also against Jewish history.
To be sure, Zionism was not the only program on offer to ameliorate Jewish disability. It was one set of
answers to the multiple crises of politics, culture, and religion that wracked European Jewry through the
19 th century. Others included liberalism, socialist revolution, Jewish diaspora nationalism, assimilationism,
and, in its own way, Orthodoxy, in which a more or less organic tradition was reconfigured as one ideology
competing with others within the distinctively modern dispensation by which society and history are not
givens, but artifacts, to be unmade and made anew. These ideological possibilities mixed and matched
within Zionism itself, yielding varieties of Zionism — secular and religious, left and right, universalist and
nationalist — in staggering array, too often lost in the fog and willed forgetfulness on all sides of
contemporary polemics. The Holocaust raised the stakes of all these arguments to a pitch of unnerving
intensity.
At the State of Israel’s creation in 1948, it was, above all, the Labor Zionism of Ben-Gurion’s Mapai Party
that emerged ascendant. Labor Zionism’s sheer skill at institution-building; its ability to square the circles
of nationalism and class, as well as of nationalism and universalism, within a program of Jewish socialist
revolution; and the creation by its leaders and thinkers, steeped in the classical Jewish tradition against
which they rose in full-fledged, but deeply dialectical, rebellion, became a new interpretation of Jewish
history and of Judaism itself, as radical as it was compelling, and enshrined in the Declaration of
Independence. These are but a few of the reasons why Labor Zionism triumphed.
※
The other contributors to this symposium have marvelously explicated the ways in which the Declaration
of Independence deftly synthesized questions of national identity and civic equality in the new state. I
would just add one crucial element. God, to whom all pre-modern and even many modern Jews ascribed
not only the universe but their own souls and survival, appears nowhere in the official language of the
Declaration save for a delightfully oblique reference to The Rock of Israel (a venerable liturgical phrase
taken from 2 Samuel 23:3). This near-total omission of the Creator was not lost on the religious
signatories, one of whom, Rabbi Judah Leib Maimon, a significant scholar as well as head of the Religious
Zionist Mizrachi Party (flown in by Ben-Gurion for the signing from Jerusalem, then under siege),
appended to his signature a squiggly three Hebrew characters, b’h, a traditional acronym for be’ezrat Hashem, “by the grace of God.”
Much of Israel’s recent history is the gradual movement of Rabbi Maimon’s squiggle — and of other
historical squiggles — from the margins of the founding Document, and the ethos it meant to enshrine, to
the center.
In other words, the nation-state laws, the controversies they engender, and the processes they visibly
enact, simply cannot be understood outside the context of the steady decline of Mapai and its ethos from
the mid-1970s to today. Ever since the still-traumatic Yom Kippur War of 1973, the hegemony of Mapai and
the overwhelmingly secular Ashkenazi leadership elites of the state has been in steady decline — and with
it the Zionist civil religion it created. Secular Ashkenazi Israel has, to be sure, not gone away, but it has
steadily been shunted aside and made to yield in one sector after another to groups who either were not
present at the creation of the state or came to prominence only years after.
Among these were the Revisionist Zionists, whose forcible exclusion not just from political power and
patronage but from national memory and ethos engendered a bitter politics of resentment; Sephardi Jews,
who in their countries of origin experienced modernity differently, less conflictually, and for whom it was
precisely their very emigration to the new Jewish state of Israel that made for their traumatic encounter
with modernity, wearing a secular Jewish face; Jews of the former Soviet Union, who, on their mass
arrival, turned out not to be multitudes of Sharanskys and Nudels, dissident refusenik heroes, yearning to
breathe free, but normal human beings seeking to improve their lives after having lived in forced
estrangement from Jewish life for the better part of a century. And new generations of religious Zionists,
whose youth rebellion was directed as much against moderates like Rabbi Maimon, as against the elites of
Mapai, came forward to press their own idealism against what they saw as a tired elite, supplanted with a
new vision of Zionism as the paradoxical engine of the Messianic redemption that would, by extending
Israeli sovereignty to the Biblical heartlands of Judea and Samaria, redeem the Jewish people and save
the human race. For their part, Israel’s ultra-Orthodox Jews, rather than accepting Labor Zionism’s
preferred role for them as inhabitants of a Judaic Colonial Williamsburg, have grown in numbers and in
social and political clout, proving once again that people who answer to a higher religious authority
nonetheless have their own ideas.
Taken together with the decline and widespread discrediting of socialism, Israel’s Labor Zionism has been
driven to the ropes for decades.
※
The basic laws of 1992, as well as the constitutional revolution of Justice Aharon Barak, which form the
backdrop to the present discussion, must be seen in this light — as has been marvelously demonstrated in
Menachem Mautner’s Law and the Culture of Israel. The 1992 basic laws introduced “Jewishness” as a
substantive factor in law-making. The constitutional revolution of Justice Barak not only established
American-style constitutionalism and judicial review in the absence of a constitution, but also went even
farther than the most activist of American judges in its wholesale erasure of political question doctrine, the
idea, fundamental to American jurisprudence, that courts cannot rule on issues constitutionally delegated
to the executive or those involving policy judgments.
In many ways, Barak came to see the judiciary as the last ditch of Israeli democracy — and yet that very
defense, in the great backlash that it enabled, may have helped weaken that democratic edifice. (In a
sense, Barak and his chief sparring partner in public debate, Ruth Gavison, both of whom spent significant
time at Yale Law School, each internalized one of the poles of the debates over judicial activism and
restraint that have wracked, and in some ways disfigured, American jurisprudence for decades.) One case
that emerged as a flash-point was the so-called Katzir decision of 2000, ruling that state resources could
not be used to establish Jewish-only communities. This, taken with the tenor of the Court generally,
unwittingly fed into a perception in more right-wing circles that the judiciary did not recognize the legitimacy
of the Zionist enterprise as a whole.
Overwrought though much of the criticism of the court has been, it is crucial to note that in some respects
the new religious critics of the Mapai hegemons were not wrong. Israel’s secular elites had quite
deliberately estranged themselves from, and weaned their children off, their own Jewish cultural
resources, succumbing to the fate of revolutionaries who give their children an education as different as
they can get from their own. Ben-Gurion and his peers had no trouble arguing to religious Zionists that the
Labor Zionist ethos was not only the better defense of Jewish interests but the better interpretation of its
values. The successors of Ben-Gurion’s generation could not make that argument if for no other reason
than that they no longer share with their religious interlocutors the same language or the same basic
understandings of who they are and what they are doing in their own state.
Israel’s secular elites quite deliberately estranged themselves from, and weaned their
children off, their own Jewish cultural resources
Not that the new would-be elites have all that many answers. As some of the other contributors here have
pointed out, these laws are as much a sign of desperation as they are of anything. (They have been the
occasion for extraordinary political opportunism on the part of Prime Minister Netanyahu and others,
though that opportunism was made possible by genuine and unanswered questions.) They represent a
flailing away both at the increasingly complex picture of Israeli democracy, and at a growing recognition
that Israel’s conflict with the Palestinians is at bottom not about how to divide the land between two
national groups but whether the Jews rightly deserve to have a state at all. That latter impasse has been
made exponentially more complex by Israel’s settlements in Judea and Samaria but would have been
there even without them.
But desperate measures can lead to disastrous results. To be sure, as Gideon Sapir wrote, building on the
terrific work of Alex Yakobson and Amnon Rubinstein, liberal democracies certainly can have strong
national identities. And it must be said that a number of the nation-state laws’ sponsors and supporters, far
from being illiberal revanchists, are classic liberals, genuinely fearful of relentless attempts from multiple
quarters to deny Israel’s very legitimacy as a Jewish state. And it must also be said that Israel is a polity
created not only to provide the physical security of sovereignty but to reconstitute affective ties of
community. Staking the legitimate bounds of the latter will be a perennial conversation. Nonetheless, there
is no denying that these current proposed laws, in both design and intent, aim to put in place Israel’s
Jewishness as such (as though such a thing were easily defined in this day and age), as the defining
interpretive lens through which all other laws, including those governing Israel’s Arab minority, are to be
scrutinized — even perhaps per the broad terms of judicial scrutiny ironically fashioned by a true champion
of civil liberty, Justice Barak. Serving as interpretive lenses is after all what constitutional provisions do.
There is, in addition, a curious slippage at work in the very wording of these laws. The literal translation of
medinat Yisrael ki-medinat ha-leom shel ha-‘am ha-yehudi, translates as “Israel is the nation state of the
Jewish people.” In one and the same breath, the warm, historical resonances of “people” are yoked to the
hard edges of the modern “nation,” in which peoplehood is tied to the coercive power of the state. This
illustrates, if nothing else, the uneasy and still unresolved relationship between the new Israeli nationalist
dispensation and the very historical identity it is seeking to preserve and protect.
Which brings us full circle, to Weber. States are meant to provide security — and the ideational terms of
meaningful belonging in and through which those states understand themselves are inextricably tied to
security. It is all one package, and there are no easy ways out.
What’s more, this Israeli story belongs to some larger trends, both regional and global.
Regionally — we are, finally, witnessing the collapse of the nation state order put together after World War I
as the Allies tried to sort out the contradictory promises scattered in all directions under the press of
wartime. Middle Eastern states are imploding and exploding all around, and what is coming to replace
them is, interestingly, not nationalism. Rather, we are seeing people in Iraq, Syria, Libya and elsewhere
turning increasingly to clan-based organization for security, or to a new dispensation of illiberal
universalism, namely radical Islam, or, in Egypt, to authoritarians who promise to rein the Islamists in.
Liberalism faces competition from many quarters and not just ethnic nationalism. Universalism comes in
many forms, not all of them benign. This is so not only in the Middle East. To take a malign example, much
of Western anti-Semitism rests on a kind of exclusionary universalism — as does radical Islam — in which
rights are denied to those who do not accept our version of what is good for them and humanity. These
exclusions, whether they derive from Athens, St. Paul, or Sayyid Qutb have no room for Jews.
Globally, we are witnessing the liberal recession. If once there was a liberal order underwritten by
American power, that order is increasingly called into question. As America is unable to impose its will or
make full use of its soft power, as demonstrated inter alia by its inability to do much regarding ISIS (out of a
mix of healthy caution, diplomatic incompetence, and a sense of impotence), the suasion — soft and hard
— of a liberal order diminishes accordingly.
The liberal order faces a triple threat in today’s world — Putin’s Russian imperial, authoritarian
nationalism, China’s authoritarian capitalism, and radical Islamic politics. And the ongoing lesson of the
unraveling of the European Union is that nationalism cannot be erased or wished away. Imagined
communities, indeed, but every community is held together, as Maimonides understood, by the power of
the imagination. Islamist politics is unlikely to win adherents in the West but, like the other two, deepens
the Western crisis of faith in its own values.
every community is held together, as Maimonides understood, by the power of the
imagination
The End of History was always a fantasy; history doesn’t end just because we can’t see where it — or we
— are going. And in good Hegelian fashion, things generate their opposites. Or more precisely, the next
stage comes to compensate for the liberal state’s deficiencies, its difficulty with giving expression to strong
affective ties of kinship, its dependence on religious mind-frames and notions of transcendence that
sooner or later will challenge it.
The hardening of Israel’s nationalism is, among other things, a harbinger of how the West will respond to
the further dangers of Islamist politics, by digging in — a reaction that is paradoxically furthered by
Western liberalism’s own feebleness in articulating and defending its own values. Western European
governments who have continued to support the Palestinians and especially Hamas, no matter their
depredations, have done liberalism no favors. In Europe, multiculturalism looks increasingly to have been
a dodge to get off the hook of building a genuinely shared civic culture. Nobody is off the hook here. As
always when it comes to Israel there is plenty of blame to go around, including in my own mini-camp of
Religious Zionist liberals who have been unable to make political traction over the years.
At the same time, we have to accept the fact of American exceptionalism, the ways in which the American
model of religious neutrality is in many ways non-transferrable abroad, and then decide what to do after
that recognition has sunk in.
Is there a way forward?
In her recommendations to the Minister of Justice Ruth Gavison powerfully argues that liberal democracy
is at times best preserved precisely by letting some large questions go unanswered but endlessly argued.
Perhaps the instruments and practices of liberal democracy — and the package of rights that complements
it — are best seen as principles of procedure rather than substance. They aim to facilitate life in common
with a minimum of coercion and violence. Yet that latter proviso is matter of both procedure and
substance. Violent polities are not internally stable in the long haul (admittedly, at times a very long haul).
And if being human means anything, it means there are things that other humans should do to one
another only with the greatest reluctance and as a last resort.
There are of course, as many devils here, as there are details.
The advantage of thinking about these constitutional arrangements in procedural terms is that they place
to the side the thick questions of substantive belief and identity, or at least bracket them as much as
possible, and create some sort of standard of review. If there is a whiff of theology here, it is along the
lines of John Courtney Murray’s characterization of the religion clauses of the First Amendment as the
Articles of Peace
Those wishing for a more Hegelian state, or any state that perfectly embodies and realizes our ultimate
communal ideals and our most far-reaching aspirations, are, sooner or later, calling for a bloodbath. Yet
states cannot simply function as, in Emerson’s phrase, joint-insurance companies, because they will not
thereby generate the common concern, solidarity, and mutual sacrifice required to sustain them. For that
something more is needed, some sort of thick civic culture (and, if we seek to inspire self-sacrifice, civil
religion). And the Israeli problem is that the old civil religion formulated by Mapai is gone and nothing new
has yet arisen to take its place.
Writing recently about the postwar nation states of Africa, Samuel Moyn has said the following:
The nation-state has always been exclusionary and often been violent, offending the
cosmopolitanism of the liberals and the desire of Marxists for solidarity beyond borders. The
nation-state has also been a severe disappointment for postcolonialists, who believe that
new nations succeeded mainly in creating new elites and perpetuating the suffering of their
populations at large…But that is no cause to underestimate — just as many anticolonialists
overstated — the possibilities of nationalism, with all its flaws, for progressive politics. While
it may seem foolhardy to propose to rescue the nation-state form the enormous
condescension of posterity, it is critical all the same to understand why so many of our
ancestors chose it.
Why did they choose it? Because in order for statehood to survive, to be able to bring forth the bonds of
solidarity and collective responsibility without which even the most solitary life is at the end unlivable, and
to endure through anything more than mere brutality and fear, it must speak to some meaningful forms of
belonging; managing the necessary ties and nearly inevitable contradictions of the primordial bonds, civic
associations and shared pursuits, and ultimate values and ideals which together shape the lived
experience of our lives. Political, social, and even legal institutions are answers not only to instrumental
needs but to existential questions. The deep and tangled intermingling of instrumentality and existence, of
our own human finitude, will always be with us. What defines us as humans is our need to make some
sense of that finitude for the sake of our very survival, and to take heed of the needs, claims, danger, and
sufferings of other human beings.
The human person, the figure at the center of the very idea of human rights, is not a person in general but
a concrete figure, embedded in time and place, and yet dis-embedded and capable of seeing beyond
one’s own horizon; able to see in the people of other times and places a reflection of ourselves. The
dynamic tension of the particular and the universal is woven into the very fabric of being human. Living and
working that tension to the fullest is the burden, and blessing, of the Jews.
[Go to the previous essay in the forum by Nir Kedar, “On the Dangers of Enshrining National Character in
the Law”]