dEWEy’s Logic: r EviEWs
L a LógiCa
de
dewey:
and
CritiCisMs
reseñas y críticas
Larry A. Hickman1
10.26754/ojs_arif/arif.202227303
aBstraCt
I draw attention to some common misunderstandings among Dewey’s critics, as well
as to some significant interpretive clarifications by commentators who viewed his
work in a positive light. I have found it instructive to look back at two sources as an
aid to understanding what his critics found so puzzling about his work. First, there
are the reviews in professional journals that appeared in the wake of the publication
of the Logic. Second, there are essays by some of his critics included in the Library of
Living Philosophers volume published as a part of the celebration of his 80th birthday in
1939. In addition, I occasionally call on ancillary remarks and interpretations from
other sources when I think they will help to clarify a point.
K EyWords: Dewey, logic, pragmatism, realism, idealism, philosophical fallacy,
propositions, naturalism, fallibilism, truth, inquiry
r EsuMEn
En este artículo señalo algunos malentendidos comunes en los críticos de Dewey
al igual que algunas aclaraciones interpretativas significativas de comentadores que
contemplaron su trabajo bajo una luz más favorable. He considerado que sería esclarecedor recordar dos fuentes que ayudarían a comprender lo que sus críticos veían
tan desconcertante en su trabajo. Primero, están las reseñas en revistas profesionales
que aparecieron tras la publicación de la Lógica. Segundo, hay ensayos de algunos de
sus críticos incluidos en el volumen de la Library of Living Philosophers que fue publicado como parte de la celebración de su 80º cumpleaños en 1939. Además, en ocasiones
I am grateful for Professor Faerna’s invitation to present some general remarks on Dewey’s
1938 Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. This publication is part of the Grant FFI2017-84781-P funded
by MCIN / AEI / 10.13039 / 501100011033 / “ERDF A way of making Europe”
1
Recibido: 08/09/2022. Aceptado: 29/09/2022
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
ISSNe: 2386-8066
Copyright: Este es un artículo de acceso abierto distribuido bajo una licencia de uso y distribución “Creative
Commons Reconocimiento No-Comercial Sin-Obra-Derivada 4.0 Internacional" (CC BY NC ND 4.0)
190
Larry A. Hickman
recurro a argumentos e interpretaciones adicionales que provienen de otras fuentes
cuando creo que ayudarán a dejar más clara una idea.
PaLaBras CLavE: Dewey, lógica, pragmatismo, realismo, idealismo, falacia filosófica, proposiciones, naturalismo, falibilismo, verdad, investigación
Dewey’s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry is arguably one of his most difficult
works. Viewed through the lens of its reviewers, it is also arguably one of his
most misunderstood. I here draw attention to some common misunderstandings
among Dewey’s critics, as well as to some significant interpretive clarifications by
commentators who viewed his work in a positive light. I have found it instructive
to look back at three sources as an aid to understanding what his critics found
so puzzling about his work. First, there are the reviews in professional journals
that appeared in the wake of the publication of the Logic. Second, there are
essays by several of his critics included in the Library of Living Philosophers volume
published as a part of the celebration of his 80th birthday in 1939. In addition, I
will occasionally call on ancillary remarks and interpretations from other sources
when I think they will help to clarify a point. All references to Dewey’s published
work will be to the critical edition edited by JoAnn Boydston and published by
Southern Illinois University Press. References to his Correspondence will be to the
four volumes edited at the Center for Dewey Studies and published online by
InteLex Corp.
r EaList CritiCs
In general, as a feature of their commitment to philosophical realism, some
of Dewey’s critics embraced the “spectator” theory of knowledge. According to
this view, knowledge is conceived as a passive relationship between a knower and
what is known, and the knower is said to conceptually “mirror” the known object.
These reviewers consequently had difficulty with the implications of Dewey’s
“philosophical fallacy,” that is, his criticism of the idea that eventual functions of
inquiry could legitimately be converted into antecedent existences. Avoidance of
the philosophical fallacy is an essential component of Dewey’s Logic.
There were other realist critics who were concerned with what they regarded
as Dewey’s neglect, or even undercutting, of formal validity. They tended to take
offence at Dewey’s treatment of propositions as neither true nor false, but instead
valid or invalid, relevant or irrelevant, with respect to the context of inquiry.
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
191
They failed to see that Dewey had broken with the Aristotelian tradition of
logic that threaded itself through medieval European scholasticism, Bolzano,
Brentano, Frege, Russell and beyond as a part of his commitment to an alternative
biological / cultural approach to the foundations of logic and other problems of
philosophy. Departing from the Aristotelian tradition, Dewey’s propositions did
not bear truth values because they were means, or proposals, to be tried out with
a view to the resolution of perceived difficulties.
Dewey’s approach is both radical and complex, but I suggest that three
aspects stand out. First, Dewey’s work in the psychology of the reflex arc
demonstrated the importance of selective interest–put another way, the intimate
connections between meaning and action–that informs the adjustments of
organisms to environing conditions, thus framing the basis for his formulation
of the philosophical fallacy. Second, Dewey wanted to do for philosophy what
Darwin had done for the notion of fixed species: he therefore treated logical
objects, and concepts more generally, that is, contextually and functionally rather
than as fixed and timeless (as they are presented in many logic texts). Third,
drawing on the work of william James, he reconstructed the tradition of British
empiricism by further developing James’ idea of a radical, immediate empiricism
which avoids the problems of sense data theories and other versions of what he
called a “traditional particularistic empiricism.” Although I will not discuss them
directly here, I suggest that three of Dewey’s early essays are among the basic
guides to understanding the radical nature of his logic, or what C. I. Lewis called
his “analysis of the constructive thought-process”: The Reflex Arc Concept in
Philosophy” (1896), “The Postulate of Immediate Empiricism” (1905), and “The
Influence of Darwin on Philosophy” (1909).
BErtrand russELL
In his essay on Dewey’s Logic in the 1939 Library of Living Philosophers volume,
Bertrand Russell appeared to be straining to grasp the details of Dewey’s work
in terms of his own project. Russell’s logical atomism is arguably a version of
what Dewey termed “traditional particularistic empiricism.” (Dewey 1988: 20;
Lw14:20) It is not necessary to look far to discern the source of Russell’s difficulty.
He was still working with a pre-Darwinian model whose central element was
formal validity, whereas Dewey’s project was in part a genetic account of the ways
in which logical tools emerge from a biological / cultural matrix and function
as significant factors in ongoing organic adjustment to environing conditions.
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
192
Larry A. Hickman
As Dewey put the matter in his discussion of forms accruing to materials by
means of production in the arts, “… logic itself had to wait until various arts had
instituted operations by means of which crude materials took on new forms to
adapt them to the function of serving as means to consequences.” (Dewey 1986:
370; Lw12:370)
Although the development of Russell’s thought is complex and remains a
subject of considerable debate, as late as 1959 he was apparently still defending
a version of logical atomism. (Pears 2010: ix-x) The development of his various
accounts of propositions is also a matter of continuing discussion among
historians of logic.
Although it has had an important place in mainstream philosophy, Russell’s
logical atomism and his treatment of propositions had very little in common
with Dewey’s richer and more comprehensive project. In its most basic form,
Russell argued that truths are dependent on atomic facts, and that those facts are
dependent on individual entities that have certain properties, either individually
or in relation to other entities. The task of logical atomism would be analysis of
these entities and their complexes. Propositions in logic would be true if they
corresponded to those entities and complexes, and false if they did not. Russell’s
logic was thus analytic and relied on a form of representational realism whereas
Dewey’s logic was genetic, organic, and pragmatic.
Faced with this disconnect, Russell settled on ridiculing what he called
Dewey’s “holism” (his characterization of what Dewey called a “situation”) as so
broad (Russell 1939: 139) that it is unable to “give rise to science or to any empirical
knowledge.” (id. 142) He accused Dewey of holding a type of idealism. In his
response, Dewey focused on one of Russell’s remarks as “almost humorous.”
(Dewey 1988: 31; Lw14:31). Russell: “we are told very little about the nature of
things before they are inquired into…” (Russell 1939: 139).
Russell scoffed at Dewey’s notion of ongoing organic adjustment by attention
to the relation of means to ends as a basis of logic, complaining that he, Dewey,
had abandoned the notion of truth. “There is therefore no end to the process of
inquiry, and no dish that can be called ‘absolute truth.’” (id. 147) He was correct,
of course, that Dewey’s logic had no place for absolute truth. But he failed to see
that for Dewey processes of inquiry have legitimate termination points defined as
the settlement of belief. At those nodes there is no further inquiry required until
novel factors intervene to unsettle the situation. Since in Dewey’s view the raw
material of inquiry is “unknowable,” Russell wrote, “so, in Dr. Dewey’s system,
nothing can be fully known except the ultimate result of ‘inquiry.’” (id. 154) This
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
193
statement is all the more remarkable because, putting aside some of the more
exotic details, the limited sense in which the “raw materials” of Dewey’s inquiry
are “known” is similar to Russell’s “knowledge by acquaintance.” In neither case
is there knowing in its more robust sense.
Russell’s remarks on knowledge by acquaintance recall Dewey’s postulate of
immediate empiricism. Russell writes: “Acquaintance, which is what we derive
from sense, does not, theoretically at least, imply even the smallest ‘knowledge
about,’ i.e., it does not imply knowledge of any proposition concerning the object
with which we are acquainted. It is a mistake to speak as if acquaintance had
degrees: there is merely acquaintance and non-acquaintance.” (Russell 1929: 157)
This similarity should hardly come as a surprise, however, since as Russell points
out, languages such German and English distinguish between wissen and kennen:
knowing and being acquainted with.
Finally, failing to get any real purchase on the problem, Russell appeared
to just throw up his hands. He concluded that Dewey’s views and his own must
ultimately be based on “values” that were neither compatible nor even debatable
“without begging the question.” (Russell 1939: 156) In his review of Dewey’s
1916 Essays in Experimental Logic, Russell had been more specific: “what he calls
‘logic’ does not seem to me to be part of logic at all; I should call it part of
psychology.” (Russell 1919: 5) Moreover, “the subject which I call ‘logic’ is one
which apparently does not seem to Professor Dewey a very important one.” (id. 6)
Russell’ reading of what Dewey termed a “situation” is particularly obtuse:
“I do not see how, on Dr. Dewey’s principles, a ‘situation’ can embrace less than
the whole universe; this is an inevitable consequence of the insistence upon
continuity.” (Russell 1939:139) But a careful reading of the Logic would have
revealed an extensive discussion of “the denotative force of the word situation”
as an alternative to Russell’s logical atomism. (Dewey 1986:72-73; Lw12:72-73) In
the next paragraph I offer a condensed version of Dewey’s extended discussion
of the way a “situation” functions in his theory of inquiry.
Briefly, a “situation is not a single object or event, or even a set of objects and
events, for we never experience nor form judgments about objects and events
in isolation, but only in connection with a contextual whole. This… is what
is called a ‘situation.’” (id. 72; Lw12:72) Moreover, “There is always a field in
which observation of this or that object or event occurs. Observation… is made
for the sake of some active adaptive response in carrying forward the course
of behavior.” As discriminatingly noticed, the perceived object “is an object of
knowledge, but not of knowledge as ultimate and self-sufficient… It is noted or
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
194
Larry A. Hickman
‘known’ only so far as guidance is thereby given to direction of behavior… [I]t is
rightly (validly) perceived if and when it acts as clew and guide in use enjoyment.”
(id. 72-73; Lw12:72-73)
In sum, it appears that Dewey and Russell were so far apart that he, Russell,
was unable to get a purchase on Dewey’s project in the Logic.
t Wo M arxist r EviEWs: v. j MCgiLL
and
hErBErt M arCusE
According to a letter from Sidney Hook to Paul Schilpp (Dewey 2008:
1939.06.12), V. J. McGill, a professor at Hunter College in New York, used his
Communist Party name Philip Carter to review Dewey’s Logic in the February
1939 issue of The Communist (the official monthly organ of the Communist Party
in the United States). He first criticizes Dewey’s writing style (thus joining a long
list of those who have done so) and warns the reader that Dewey is a bit guarded
(unsure? tentative?) in his approach to his subject matter. But he admits that there
is a “fighting edge [to] his polemic” and compliments him on his construction of
a “logic of inquiry remarkably rich in suggestions.” (Carter 1929: 163) He then
proceeds to attack Dewey on several fronts.
First, he faults Dewey for rejecting the correspondence theory of truth. “The
deficiency of [Dewey’s] view has been clearly shown by Marxism, which recognizes
that truth as a correspondence of knowledge with reality, is progressively attained
through the dialectical materialist advance of science.” (id. 164) He does, however,
agree (on the authority of Engels–who he says made the point much more clearly)
that “isolated propositions are neither true nor false apart from the series and
systems to which they belong.” (Ibid.) But he objects to Dewey’s “description
of a universal proposition as a mere stage of inquiry… or as a mere logical aid
to the solution of problems… and [he argues] to deny that truth and falsity
are properties of propositions, it is clear that he has pushed his theory to the
brink of absurdity.” (Ibid.) Following that he criticizes Dewey’s treatment of
propositions as “mere means to an end, that is, to another proposition,” adding
that “truth, which Marxism has shown to be a reflection of reality, drops out of
the picture.” (Ibid.) Next, he takes offence at Dewey’s philosophical fallacy. “But
inquiry as such does not transform its subject matter. If it did, it could never
arrive at knowledge.” (Id. 165) For McGill / Carter, Dewey’s alleged subjectivism
seemed to be among its many flaws.
Frankfurt School Marxist Herbert Marcuse mounted a more sophisticated
criticism of Dewey’s Logic in the 1939-40 volume of the Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung.
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
195
He first presents several pages of an admirably accurate summary of Dewey’s
book. He recognizes, for example, that Dewey’s logic is both material (Marcuse
1939: 221) and temporal (id. 224), and he does not seem at all bothered by Dewey’s
view that “truth and falsity are not qualities of propositions. Propositions are only
mediating steps to reach a judgment with a context of research.” (id. 225)
He does, however, criticize Dewey’s treatment of the continuity of common
sense and science. “Such a hasty unification of theory and praxis must deliver
theory in the whole over to a theory-less praxis. Theory is in truth more than
methodological doctrine for scientific research. It always transcends the given
praxis of what can be–can be not according to the ruling of research alone, but to
Reason, Freedom, Right and similar ‘metaphysical’ authorities… The shriveling
of theory to the methodology of scientific experimentation and of praxis to the
experimentation itself encroaches onto the theory of society. (id. 226) Given
Dewey’s profound concern with social issues, it may be that Marcuse has missed
Dewey’s point that theory and praxis are partners in inquiry in the broad sense of
the term, both having their own roles, but both necessary. Marcuse in fact seems
to be charging Dewey with a scientistic approach to social issues.
whereas McGill / Carter had charged Dewey with subjectivism, Marcuse’s
criticism is that Dewey’s Logic is “in its decisive moment idealistic.” (id. 227)
Dewey’s inquiry, he writes, “‘produces’ the world which stands in question for
logic. It is a world by grace of science…” what exists, says Dewey, “is in itself
indifferent to the demarcations of beginning and end, origin and decline. All
whence and whither is ‘strictly relative to the objective intent set to inquiry by the
problematic quality of a given situation.’” (Ibid.)
In this vein he criticizes Dewey’s argument that “event” is a term of judgment
and not of existence, as well as his concept of causal law as a figure of speech.
Marcuse thinks that Dewey had just ignored some of the epistemological and
metaphysical problems that his “idealism” had raised, but he does admit that the
Logic was naturalistic. In a final shot, Marcuse faults Dewey for not filling in the
developmental history of the “organic behavior” that he thinks provides the basis
for his logic. (id. 228) I suppose Dewey might have responded that such a project
would be the remit not of philosophy, but of biology, sociology, psychology, and
anthropology, and that from the standpoint of logic, philosophy was for the most
part just a consumer in this regard (or perhaps a partner with those fields in
developing new tools of inquiry). He does in fact say something like that in the
tenth chapter of Experience and Nature. Marcuse touches lightly on the issue of
praxis, but some readers of these two reviews may have found it surprising that
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
196
Larry A. Hickman
since Marxism and pragmatism are both understood as “praxis” philosophies
there is not more discussion of that important feature of Dewey’s pragmatism.
EvandEr BradLEy MCgiLvary
Evander Bradley McGilvary’s contribution to “A Symposium of Reviews of
John Dewey’s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry” published in The Journal of Philosophy,
reports that Dewey’s philosophic fallacy, left him “perplexed.” McGilvary cites
Einstein’s idea of gravity deflecting light, arguing that once tested by existential
means, it produced the judgment that “existentially the path of such light is so
deflected.” (McGilvary 1939: 564) If this was not an instance of “conversion of
eventual functions into antecedent existence,” he writes, “then I must confess I
do not know what the quoted phrase means.” (Ibid.)
Dewey was familiar with this type of criticism. “Instead of denying that
unperceived antecedent conditions are objectives of knowledge… I have very
explicitly stated that no problem as to existential matters can be resolved except
by inquiries which ascertain antecedent conditions not previously observed. I have also then
pointed out that such objects do not fulfill the conditions which must be satisfied
in a philosophical logical theory as to the generalized meaning of the category
‘object of knowledge.’” (Dewey 1988: 49; Lw14:49)
For Dewey, the data of Einstein’s theory is not a pre-inquirential fact in the
sense alleged by the realists. It is instead developed by tools of inquiry and capable
of being utilized in the context of further relevant inquiries. Dewey makes this
clear in his discussion of two types of universal propositions in the Logic. “A
physical law, such as expressed by a relation of abstract characters, is a universal
hypothetical proposition.” His example is the law of gravitation. Since the law
is expressed as a hypothetical proposition, and since hypothetical propositions
do not exhaust all their possible existential conditions, they may have to be
modified or even abandoned at some point. Such was the case in the shift from
the Newtonian to the Einsteinian theories. The implication here is that in that
particular case of inquiry, which involved the ascertainment of certain antecedent
conditions not previously observed, there was a re-distribution of the antecedent
data, some of which may have been unobserved up to the point that they were
required for further inquiry. Inquiry thus produced new data as well as a new
theory of gravity, expressed by a new universal hypothetical proposition. It would
have been a mistake, therefore, to have treated the eventual function, the new data
and a new universal hypothetical proposition expressing a new physical law, as if
they had been there all along, prior to inquiry. (Dewey 1938: 394-95; Lw12:394-95)
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
197
Since this issue has been so widely misunderstood, it is probably worthwhile
to highlight Dewey’s extensive remarks in response to criticism by his Columbia
University colleague Frederick woodbridge of his position on the conversion of
eventual functions into antecedent conditions. woodbridge’s argument appears
similar to the one made by McGilvary. Here is Dewey:
Mr. woodbridge goes on to say, “I conceive the object to exist prior to its being
known.” I, too, conceive that things had in direct experience exist prior to
being known. But I deny the identity of things had in direct experience with the
object of knowledge qua object of knowledge. Things that are had in experience
exist prior to reflection and its eventuation in an object of knowledge; but the
latter, as such, is a deliberately effected re-arrangement or re-disposition, by
means of overt operations, of such antecedent existences. The difference between
Mr. woodbridge and myself, as I see it, is not that he believes in the existence of
things antecedent to knowledge and I do not; we differ in our beliefs as to what
the character of the antecedent existences with respect to knowledge is. while
Mr. woodbridge says “the object exists prior to its being known,” I say that “the
object” is the eventual product of reflection, the prior or antecedent existences
being subject-matter for knowledge, not the objects of knowledge at all. (Dewey
1984: 211-12; Lw5:211-12)
McGilvary appears to miss the point of Dewey’s fallibilism, which holds that
scientific conclusions may at one point in time or in one context be invaluable
tools for ordering inquiry, but at a later time or in a different context fall into
relative disuse because they have been replaced by better tools, or better versions
of them have replaced earlier versions. It would a mistake, however, to charge
Dewey with idealism pure and simple in this regard, as McGilvary apparently
does, since at a particular time Einstein’s theory is warranted and is assertable in
relevantly similar situations. But it is not a free-standing thing. It is rather a tool
that is context-dependent, depending on the nature of the inquiry in which it is
employed as tool.
It is important to put realist criticisms of Dewey’s Logic into historical context.
when Dewey was writing about logic in the early decades of the twentieth century,
many of his opponents were idealists. By the time of the publication of the 1938
Logic, however, idealism had lost much of its influence within American philosophy
and elsewhere. The major ongoing philosophical debates then tended to be among
proponents of various types of realism or between realists and pragmatists. That
Dewey’s realist critics continued to accuse him of idealism, however, can be
read as a misunderstanding of the “paradigm shift” that pragmatism brought
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
198
Larry A. Hickman
to the traditional debates between realism and idealism. They failed to see that
pragmatism was a philosophical tertium quid which incorporated elements of both
idealism and realism. In his essay in the Library of Living Philosophers volume on
Dewey Donald A. Piatt provided an insightful way of understanding this shift.
Pragmatism can be read in part as a synthesis of the best features of both realism
and idealism.
The enduring truth of idealism is that factuality must be qualified by meanings
before we can make judgments about it. The enduring truth of realism is that
factuality must have a brute quality and articulate structure of its own before
judgments can have relevance and validity. The enduring truth of pragmatism
is that, as active organisms, we are in the world and of it, we don’t altogether
have to acquiesce in facts as they come, we can alter the facts as they affect us by
operationally applying our purposes and meanings to them so that they become
data for knowledge by becoming data for successful action.” (Piatt 1939: 126)
In short, Piatt argues that realists are correct to recognize an idealist strand
in Dewey’s Pragmatism. what they fail to recognize, however, is that there is also
a realist strand and that together the two strands work together to motivate some
of the central strategies of Dewey’s pragmatism as something new, as it takes
account of adjustive activities of organisms.
thE PhiLosoPhiCaL FaLLaCy: a tEChnoLogiCaL anaLogy
One way of addressing what bothered some of Dewey’s critics about Dewey’s
philosophical fallacy requires a review of the introduction of the 1916 Essays in
Experimental Logic, where his narrative is informed by technological metaphors.
He begins by pointing out that his position is “frankly realistic” in the sense that
“brute existences,” when they are detected, both set the problem for inquiry and
also serve as its test. Then he invites us to consider three things: mineral rock in
place (iron ore), refined materials or intermediate stock parts (such as pig iron),
and a manufactured article such as a watch spring. Put in terms of a sequence of
inquiry, the iron ore would be the raw materials, the “data” that are denominated
from the “situation” that occasions inquiry. There are also the refined materials,
tools, and intermediate stock parts–habits, previously used tools, blue prints,
previously produced objects, etc.–and, finally, the manufactured article, the
objective of knowledge that is the (relatively) final product, the knowledge object.
And “just as the manufacturer always has a lot of already extracted ore on hand
for use in machine processes as it is wanted, so every person of any maturity…
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
199
has a lot of extracted data–or… of ready-made tools of extraction–for use as they
are required.” (Dewey 1980: 341-42; Mw10:341-42)
It would, of course, be a mistake to argue that the conclusion (or product)
of a sequence of inquiry (in this case the watch spring), existed antecedently to
the sequence of inquiry. what did exist were the raw materials and the refined
products, tools, and intermediate stock parts. As for the intermediate stock parts,
they are “known,” but in an inferior sense. They are acknowledged, or perhaps
better, we are acquainted with them in the sense that they are potentially available
as tools, or means, to the end we are pursuing. “The ‘objects’ of ordinary life,
stones, plants, cats, rocks, moon, etc., are neither the data of science nor the objects
at which science arrives.” (id. 343; Mw10:343)
It would be a fallacy, also, to suppose “that pigs of iron pre-existed as pigs in
the mine. There is no falsifying analysis because the analysis is carried on within a
situation which controls it. The fallacy… is on the part of the philosopher who
ignores the contextual situation and who transfers the properties which things
have as dependable evidential signs over to things in other modes of behavior.”
(id. 343-44; Mw10:343-44)
h ans r EiChEnBaCh
Hans Reichenbach had many positive things to say about Dewey’s work. He
even thought that his version of logical empiricism and Dewey’s pragmatism had
a lot in common, suggesting that they should work together. For Reichenbach,
however, only scientific concepts could be real. He was especially critical of
Dewey’s portrayal of secondary and tertiary qualities in the early pages of the Logic.
“If the pragmatist considers secondary and tertiary qualities as real, he does so
because he wants to establish esthetics and ethics as aspects of reality comparable
to physics.” (Reichenbach 1939: 178) He allows, however, that “secondary and
tertiary qualities may be characterized as objective if we include the observer into
the description… with this interpretation as objective however the secondary
and tertiary qualities are no longer qualities of things, but relations between thing
and observer, varying therefore with the nature of the observer.” (id. 179) This
is the objective basis of psychology, for example, since we can speak of certain
persons under certain conditions observing the same subjective things. In one
world, then, in the immediate world of experience, we have to call secondary and
tertiary qualities subjective. But a second world, the world of inferred relations, is
a world in which the qualities will vary with the nature of the observer. In neither
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Larry A. Hickman
200
case, Reichenbach argues, can the pragmatist claim to furnish a “compulsory
character of esthetic and ethical judgments.” (id. 180)
It appears that Reichenbach missed the point of Dewey’s discussion of tertiary
qualities in the early pages of the Logic. In the condensed passage below, which I
include at length because it offers an excellent insight into the biological / cultural
foundations of his theory of inquiry, Dewey provides a thumbnail sketch of the
development of the sciences from awareness of a “tertiary” quality, that is, a felt
quality that pervades an entire situation, to its expression in aesthetically pleasing
products such as pots or textiles, for example, to their objectification in discourse
that identifies and manages those aesthetic elements, at which point discourse
moves from the aesthetic to the reflective, and thence little by little to technology
and the sciences. But, as he points out, “the intended force of the illustration
would be lost if esthetic experience as such were supposed to exhaust the scope
and significance of a ‘situation.’ As has been said, a qualitative and qualifying
situation is present as the background and the control of every experience.”
(Dewey 1986: 75-76; Lw12:75-76)
The phrase “tertiary qualities,” happily introduced by Santayana, does not refer to
a third quality like in kind to the “primary” and “secondary” qualities of Locke
and merely happening to differ in content. For a tertiary quality qualifies all the
constituents to which it applies in thoroughgoing fashion. (id. 75; Lw12:75)
It is more or less a commonplace that it is possible to carry on observations that
amass facts tirelessly and yet the observed “facts” lead nowhere. On the other
hand, it is possible to have the work of observation so controlled by a conceptual
framework fixed in advance that the very things which are genuinely decisive in
the problem in hand and its solution, are completely overlooked. Everything is
forced into the predetermined conceptual and theoretical scheme. [This would,
arguably, apply to Reichenbach’s characterization of Dewey’s “tertiary qualities.]
The way, and the only way, to escape these two evils, is sensitivity to the quality
of a situation as a whole. In ordinary language, a problem must be felt before it
can be stated. If the unique quality of the situation is had immediately, then there
is something that regulates the selection and the weighing of observed facts and
their conceptual ordering.
The discussion has reached the point where the basic problem of the relation of
common sense material and methods to that of scientific subject-material and
method, can be explicitly discussed. In the first place, science takes its departure of
necessity from the qualitative objects, processes, and instruments of the common
sense world of use and concrete enjoyments and sufferings… Colors [e.g.] are signs
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
201
of what can be done and of how it should be done in some inclusive situation–
such as, judging the prospects of the morrow’s weather; selection of appropriate
clothing for various occasions; dyeing, making rugs, baskets and jars; and so on in
diverse ways too obvious and tedious to enumerate… Gradually and by processes
that are more or less tortuous and originally unplanned, definite technical
processes and instrumentalities are formed and transmitted. Information about
things, their properties and behaviors, is amassed, independently of any particular
immediate application. It becomes increasingly remote from the situations of use
and enjoyment in which it originated. There is then a background of materials and
operations available for the development of what we term science, although there
is still no sharp dividing line between common sense and science… (id. 76-77;
Lw 12: 76-77)
It should by now be obvious that Reichenbach’s understanding of tertiary
qualities has little in common with what Dewey has in mind. First, Dewey writes
of tertiary qualities as different in kind from secondary qualities. Reichenbach
lumps the two together. Second, Reichenbach treats tertiary qualities as subjective
properties of individuals, or else objective properties of relations between thing
and observer, which varies with the individual. For Dewey on the other hand,
tertiary qualities are the background in all situations, regulating “the selection
and the weighing of observed facts and their conceptual ordering” that eventuate
in technology and science. (id. 75; Lw12:75)
There were also areas where Reichenbach thought that Dewey was on the
right track. In terms of formal logic, he writes, it is proper to start with a twovalued logic –of true and false. But in the real world things are more complex. we
correctly speak of more or less true, and there are even multivalued logics. “Now
it is very interesting to note that this very idea of probability replacing truth is
one of the fundamental ideas of Dewey… [He] knows that inquiry into existence
can only arrive at conclusions having a coefficient of some order of probability…
Dewey’s emphasis upon the fact that empirical knowledge is written in terms of
probability and not of truth is one of the great merits of this thoroughly empiricist
philosopher, placing him in to one line with C. S. Peirce in the struggle for a
theory of science free from the preoccupations of traditional rationalism and
absolutism.” (Reichenbach 1939: 176-77)
For his part, Dewey rejected what he regarded as the positivists’ reductionism,
which he characterized as “traditional particularistic empiricism.” (Dewey 1988:20;
Lw14:20) He read Reichenbach as having made some progress beyond “traditional
psychological empiricism to the point of admitting things as material of direct
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Larry A. Hickman
202
experience instead of just separate qualities.” (Ibid.) But he thought that Reichenbach had not gone far enough: he had not admitted actions, ways of operating,
ways of behavior, as also directly experienced. The problem was his starting point.
Reichenbach’s stripped-down empiricism was not sufficiently radical. His starting
point had not been the well-rooted “biological / cultural approach to the theory
of experiencing” according to which “general ways of behavior is an unescapable
datum.” (id. 536-37) In short, Reichenbach was a logical empiricist, but Dewey was
an immediate or radical empiricist.
a dEFEnsE
oF
ForMaL LogiC: M arCus singEr
Marcus Singer’s review in 1951 in The Philosophical Review properly noted
that Dewey claimed to be constructing a theory of inquiry that is able to “order
and account for” the proximate subject matter of logic, viz. “the domain of the
relations of propositions to one another.” This theory of inquiry would address
the “ultimate” subject-matter” of logic, which would be an account of its
proximate subject-matter. “Thus Dewey’s Logic contains, among other things, a
philosophical theory about formal logic.” (Singer 1951, 375) Singer argued that
Dewey had not only not done this, but that his project, if taken seriously, would
undermine formal logic. He proceeded to quote Dewey at length on the role of
propositions as means, but then he suggested that if propositions are neither
true nor false, as Dewey claimed, but means that are valid or invalid, relevant or
irrelevant, then it “would be impossible to distinguish between a valid deduction,
or argument, and an invalid one. (id. 375)
Although Singer noted that Dewey had denied “that the terms ‘true’ and
‘false’ are applicable to propositions,” he nevertheless attempted to demonstrate
that if the terms “relevant” and “irrelevant” were substituted into a valid argument
in formal logic, then “it would seem that we have to say that an argument is valid
or ‘formally correct’ if and only if it is impossible for the premises to be effective
and the conclusion ineffective. But then how are we to specify what ‘impossible’
means here?” (id. 378)
Singer thus took on the unenviable task of trying to fit Dewey’s logic as a
theory of inquiry, which incorporates both empirical and conceptual material (for
example generic and universal propositions), into a formal system, the canons
of which are abstract and have no empirical content. The case of contradiction
provides a convenient example. For Dewey, contradiction is essential for
scientific, and even commonplace, decision making. when propositions that are
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
203
valid and relevant to a case contradict propositions that are invalid and irrelevant
with respect to that case, that is an indication that the invalid propositions should
be discarded and that the problem should be reformulated. we do not say that
inquiry has failed, but that certain proposals that would not lead to a successful
conclusion have been discarded or reformulated and that inquiry must therefore
take a different course. Contradiction is thus an important stage on the way to the
settlement of belief, whether in science or quotidian life. “In no case of controlled
inquiry is a flat negation of a generalization taken to be final. If it were so taken,
a former generalization would simply be abandoned and that would be the end of
the matter. what actually happens is that the prior generalization is modified and
revised by discovery of the contradictory instance.” (Dewey 1986: 197; Lw12:197)
For Singer, however, it makes no sense to speak of contradiction without
relying on the tools of formal logic, more specifically, the properties true and
false. He thinks that Dewey had to do this covertly: “the difficulty in Dewey’s
theory… has been obscured by certain unconscious shifts in the use of this key
term [‘valid’]. Sometimes ‘valid’ is used in the sense of true, and at other times
in the sense explicitly given it, namely, relevant or effective.” (Singer 1951: 384)
To interpret “valid” as “relevant,” Singer says, undercuts the whole notion of
contradiction, since both contradictory propositions in Dewey’s logic might well
be relevant to a particular inquiry.
But unlike formal logic, Dewey’s logic does not treat contradiction as “an
inherent relational property.” (Dewey 1986: 344; Lw12:344) It is instead a condition
to be satisfied.
Contradiction is not then just an unfortunate accident which sometimes happens
to come about. Complete exclusion, resulting in grounded disjunction, is not
effected until propositions are determined as pairs such that if one is valid
the other is invalid, and if one is invalid the other is valid. The principle of
contradiction thus represents a condition to be satisfied. Direct inspection of two
propositions does not determine whether or not they are related as contradictories,
as would be the case if contradiction were an inherent relational property. The
contrary doctrine is often affirmed, as when it is said that the two propositions
A is M and A is not M directly contradict each other. But unless A has already
been determined conjunctively-disjunctively, by prior inquiry, some part of A,
or A in some relation, may be M, and some other part of A, or A in some other
relation, may be not M. The relation of A to M and not M can be determined
only by operations of exclusion which reach their logical limit in the relation of
contradiction. (id. 344; Lw12:344)
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
204
Larry A. Hickman
There is no indication that Dewey set out to “undermine” formal logic,
nor is there any evidence in his Logic that his analysis of logical forms would
do so. what he was keen to do, however, was to demonstrate that his logic of
experience, and ultimately, even systems of abstract formal logic, are grounded
in biological / cultural considerations that are pragmatic because they are, and
always have been, based on adjustment through selective interest, meaning,
and action. The formulae that Singer uses as examples are elements of a strictly
intensional formal language whose operations are strictly defined and that
may be of help in a particular scientific investigation. Ralph Sleeper put it well
in the introduction to volume 14 of Dewey’s Later Works when he wrote that
“Dewey was not trying to deprive the sciences of access to the norms and
criteria of formal logic. He was not an antiformalist in that sense at all. It is
just that he wanted us to realize how much the norms and criteria of formal
analysis owe to the biological and cultural matrix from which they arise. He
wanted us to see how little they owe to ‘apart thought.’” (Sleeper 1988: xvii)
Since the truth tables and formulae of formal logic are part of a purely intensional
logic, with absolutely no bearing on empirical affairs (unless interpreted), it seems
odd that Singer would wish to hold the aforesaid formal logic as the standard by
which to measure a much richer logic as the theory of inquiry, a logic of experience
that takes account not only of conceptual but also material aspects of inquiry,
which incorporates the best insights of traditional idealism and traditional realism,
and which, as Piatt suggested, might provide important insights into how we
actually think.
Finally, Dewey makes it clear that formal two-valued logical systems have
their place, but that it is a mistake to think that per se they will be of help to
the empirically minded. “For the technical purposes of strictly formal logic
an assumption that every proposition is of itself, or intrinsically, either true or
false may not do harm. But it is the last view an empiricist can possibly take
who is concerned with truth and falsity as having existential application, and as
something determined by means of inquiry into material existence. For in the
latter case the question of truth or falsity is the very thing to be determined.”
(Dewey 1939: 574; Lw14: 58)
C. i. LEWis
Given Singer’s concern to defend the propositional calculus from Dewey,
this seems the appropriate point at which to discuss the review of one of the most
important logicians of the twentieth century, C. I. Lewis.
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
205
Lewis is well known for making major contributions to systems of formal
logic. His criticism of the theory of material implication, for example, led him
to develop a theory of strict implication. Lewis does not express the type of
concern that would be raised by Singer twelve years later. That is, he does not
seem bothered that Dewey’s logic does not exhibit the rules of formal validity as
they are found in abstract systems of formal logic. This is because at one level he
knows that he and Dewey were engaged in different projects. whereas he was
primarily interested in what he called “exact” logic, Dewey was interested in a
logic as theory of inquiry. In his brief quasi-autobiographical essay published in
1930, he made this clear.
I had long been attracted to certain theses of Dewey’s logic–if only he would not
miscall ‘logic’ what is rightly a much wider thing, the analysis of the constructive
thought-process! The study of exact logic itself had revealed unmistakably that in
every process of reasoning there must be an extra-logical element. This cannot but
be so, since from any premise or set of premises whatever an infinite number of
valid inferences can be drawn… what is called “the conclusion” must be selected
from this infinity by psychological obviousness or by some purpose or interest;
certainly logic does not dictate it. The direction of thought inevitably belongs,
then, to such an extra-logical factor. (Lewis 1970: 12)
It is that “extra-logical factor” that takes Lewis to a deeper level where he
expresses his philosophical kinship with Dewey. The title of his review, “Meaning
and Action,” already indicates that he intends to discuss that factor as pragmatic.
He reminds his readers that Dewey rejects the “spectator” theory of knowledge.
For Dewey, “[t]he cognitive or meaning situation does not admit of bifurcation
into an activity of the knower and a preformed object, which is contemplated.”
(Lewis 1939: 572) Moreover, “knowing or meaning is integral with other activities
which shape the objects to which they are addressed; that meanings themselves
serve to frame the situations of action into which they enter, and exercise an
operational force upon what they serve to formulate.” (Ibid.)
Lewis admits that Dewey’s rejection of the spectator theory has appeared to
many as a kind of indeterminacy principle, i.e., that “thought itself displaces or
transforms that which it means or inquires about.” (id. 573) But, he adds, “there
are no such [future] verifying or confirming experiences which can be predicted
without reference to the activity of the subject.” (Ibid.) Lewis thus confirms that he
is on the same page with Dewey about some of the central features of pragmatism
and joins Dewey in his criticism those who commit the philosophical fallacy.
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
206
Larry A. Hickman
Lewis reminds his readers that for pragmatists empirical knowledge is implicitly
predictive, and that the meaning of our predictions “must include the significance
of the knower’s activity.” (id. 574) For pragmatists, the application of a substantive
meaning or the truth or falsity of a proposition must be capable of being tested, and
“what tests are pertinent, must be implicit in the meanings themselves.” (Ibid.) It
would be meaningless to assert some proposition without specifying how its truth
could be determined. Such a prediction must be found in future experience. “But
there are no such verifying or confirming experiences which can be predicted without reference to
the activity of the subject.” (id. 575) Lewis thus makes explicit the connection between
knowing and doing that is a core element in Dewey’s pragmatism.
In her excellent commentary on Lewis, Sandra Rosenthal goes further afield
in his writings to expand on his pragmatism, and thus his agreements with Dewey
on the biological / cultural basis even of “exact” logic. “As the canon of deductive
inference, Lewis grounds logic, and logical laws such as that of excluded middle
and the very necessity of consistency itself in his pragmatism, which reaches down
into the very core of his thought… As he summarizes, ‘Practical consistency
cannot be reduced to or defined in terms of merely logical consistency. But logical
consistency can be considered as simply one species of practical consistency.’”
(Rosenthal 2002: 76)
The two previous sentences seem almost tailored to respond to Singer’s
concerns about the relation of Dewey’s logic to the logic of formal validity. If we
ask about the relation of “exact” logic to Dewey’s “analysis of the constructive
thought-process,” the answer is that Dewey’s genetic analysis is informed by the
history of biological / cultural organisms who continually adjust themselves to
environing conditions, both altering and accommodating themselves to those
conditions. In order for such adjustments to work, they must be forward looking
and they therefore require practical consistency. what is called the “logical
consistency” of formal systems slowly emerged and was developed as a special
case of practical consistency.
Rosenthal continues. “Meanings that mind entertains, the logic that explicates such meanings, and mind itself emerge from behavioral responses to the
environment in which humans find themselves. Our ways of behaving toward the
world around us, which are made explicit in our accepted logic, are those ways of
behaving which have lasted because they work. The final ground of the validity
of the principle of consistency, as well as the validity of ordinary inference which
explicates our meanings in accordance with the principle of consistency, is rooted
in a ‘pragmatic imperative.’” (Rosenthal Ibid.)
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
207
Lewis thus addresses both of the issues on which I have focused in this essay
and that occupied Dewey’s critics: the philosophical fallacy and formal validity.
ErnEst nagEL
At least from 1936 Dewey turned to Ernest Nagel for comments on the
manuscript of his 1938 Logic. (Dewey, 2008: 1936.10.23; Dewey, 2008: 1938.01.22;
Dewey, 2008: 1938.03.16) Nagel had attended Dewey’s graduate course at Columbia
on Types of Logical Theory, and from 1930 he taught courses on formal logic and
the philosophy of the natural sciences there. Nagel was a book editor for Journal of
Philosophy ca. 1934-39 and editor 1939-51. He was also a contributor to the Journal
of Philosophy review-symposium on Dewey’s Logic. Among all the reviewers and
critics presented here he is perhaps the most familiar with the details that work.
He notes that for Dewey logic does not start with abstract canons, but the
reverse: “subject-matter acquires logical traits on being subjected to the differential
physical transformations of inquiry.” (Nagel 1939: 577) He also notes that Dewey
presents his logical theory as an hypothesis, that is, as an outline of the logical
principles that operate on a larger stage than their more limited place in selfcontained systems of logic and mathematics. It will be up to others to test this
hypothesis and to enlarge the project that Dewey has initiated.
Dewey writes about the conditions under which logical forms developed, he
suggests, as a biologist might write about the development of various organs of
life. Dewey is interested in “the conditions under which the logical forms occur
and are developed, their specific functions, their dependence upon and their
transformation of their environment, and their own interrelations on the basis of
their contributions to the achievement of their objectives.” (Ibid.)
For Dewey’s naturalism, subject matter acquires its logical traits within
inquiry and not a priori, or what Dewey called “apart thought.” Nagel thinks it
important to clarify Dewey’s terms “logical form” and “logical principles.” “‘[L]
ogical form’ stands for the way in which selected features of a situation in which
inquiry occurs function in it, while the phrase ‘logical principles’ denotes a mode of
operation–and not, as is sometimes the case among students of formal validity, for
quasi-grammatical forms or rules.” (Ibid.) This is an important distinction, since,
contrary to the way the principles of logic are usually presented, in Dewey’s logic
they receive their “adequate theoretical interpretation only by being exhibited
in the roles they play within the process of inquiry.” (Ibid.) Once again we get
a statement of the philosophical fallacy: objects of knowledge as outcomes of
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
208
Larry A. Hickman
sequences of inquiry cannot be identified as existing (as known) antecedently. It
might have been good, however, if Nagel had provided some examples.
Nagel notes that some of Dewey’s critics have accused him of committing
a genetic fallacy, that is, confusing origin and development with validity and
logical order. But he dismisses this criticism: it is just that Dewey refuses to treat
logical principles as residing in textbooks. He insists, rather, that logical principles
receive their sole meaning from their function in inquiry.
He thinks that most other writers on logic have confounded generic and
universal propositions. For Dewey, the relation between generic propositions as
expressing existential relations and universal propositions as expressing necessary
connections parallels his functional correlation between perceptual and
conceptual material. He rehearses Dewey’s point that the linguistic forms of these
propositions do not indicate that distinction, i.e., between generic and universal
propositions. They are instead distinguished by their function in inquiry.
Dewey is chided for apparently violating his own rule by using as examples
propositions that have been taken out of their functional context. He also
complains that Dewey has not been clear about “the force of ‘necessary’ in the
account of universals as involving necessary relations between characters.” (id. 579)
In addition, he warns his readers against identifying generic propositions as
synthetic” and universal propositions as “analytic” as, he says, some of Dewey’s
readers have already done. He suggests that Dewey has further confused the
issue by differentiating between two types of universal propositions: “one kind
being exemplified by propositions of mathematical physics (e.g. Newton’s law
of gravitation), and the other by propositions of mathematics (e.g., two plus
two equals four); and he recognizes that the former kind do not exhaust the
possibilities, so that they may have to be abandoned under the stress of actual
demands, while the latter are apparently free from such limitation.” (id. 580) He
then suggests that Dewey should clean up this confusion, and he makes some
suggestions about how this can be achieved.
First, some propositions “suggested but not derived from empirical material,
may be asserted with confidence because the conditions for warranted assertion
have been approximated for them. These propositions do not enter integrally
into the theoretical framework of science, and their correction or even total
abandonment does not involve a radical recasting of that framework; such
propositions, [he suggests], may be Professor Dewey’s generic ones.” (id. 580)
On the other hand there are propositions that gradually acquire a “commanding
position in the set of warranted assertions” such that they “reach the status of
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
209
leading principles” and “control the general direction of research.” To challenge
them would “involve a fundamental overhaul of the theoretical systems of
science.” They thus function as “procedural principles, no longer at the mercy of
random experiments because suitable devices are provided for obviating apparent
contradictions.” (Ibid.) He suggests that these propositions are Dewey’s first kind
of universals.
Nagel ends his review by challenging Dewey readers to “contribute their share
toward completing the fundamental task with Professor Dewey has envisaged.”
(id. 581)
a ddEnduM: M atEriaL LogiC
in
17th CEntury sPain
As we have seen, Bertrand Russell thought that Dewey was doing nothing he
could recognize as logic. “what he calls ‘logic’ does not seem to me to be part of
logic at all; I should call it part of psychology.” (Russell 1919: 5) Moreover, “the
subject which I call ‘logic’ is one which apparently does not seem to Professor
Dewey a very important one.” (id. 6) Even C. I. Lewis hesitated to refer to
Dewey’s project “logic,” preferring to call it “a much wider thing, the analysis of
the constructive thought-process.” (Lewis 1970: 12)
But Lewis also acknowledges that systems of formal logic are completely
intensional, empty of existential import until interpreted, and in an important
sense circular. He also acknowledges that he shares Dewey’s insight that human
inquiry–problem solving or organic adjustment–is hypothetical, forward-looking,
and therefore pragmatic in nature.
The very fact that we qualify abstract systems of logic as “formal,” is a tacit
recognition that the term is redundant if there is no “material” logic. One of the
reasons that Dewey’s Logic was a source of puzzlement, and even offence among
his critics was their failure to recognize this point. They did not understand what
Lewis called Dewey’s “analysis of the constructive thought-process” as logic
because they did not recognize a part of logic as being material.
Dewey was not the first to develop a material logic. An earlier version, inspired
by the work of Thomas Aquinas, was developed in seventeenth century Spain by
John of St. Thomas (1589-1644, born John Poinsot), at the famous University of
Alcala de Henares. A portion of his massive work on logic was translated by Yves
R. Simon, John J. Glanville and G. Donald Hollenhorst and published as The
Material Logic of John of St. Thomas in 1955.
In his Foreword to that volume, Simon reminds his readers that formal
logic is generally held to deal with consistency alone. Formal logics usually have
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
210
Larry A. Hickman
transitivity rules, but if one is asked about the truth of the sentence “Chicago is
north of St. Louis and St. Louis is north of New Orleans, therefore Chicago
is north of New Orleans,” for example, transitivity rules will not help. The truth
of the statement is not a matter of formal logic (alone).
For John of St. Thomas, as for other scholastic logicians influenced by the
work of Aquinas, there are things that are understood as they exist in nature.
These are “first intentions.” But there are also “second intentions,” which
are “properties which accrue to things by reason of the new existences that
they enjoy as objects of the human mind.” (Simon 1955: xi) It is among these
second intentions that we find material logic. “Intentions belonging to terms of
propositions are considered formal or material according as they are preparatory
to the consistency of reasoning or to its demonstrative power.” (id. xv)
Simon argues that Aristotle has been widely misread as having constructed
only a purely formal logic that deals with the rules of syllogistic inference. The
“perfection” of his syllogistic logic, however, as Simon put it, is found in his
much-neglected Posterior Analytics, which offers a demonstrative, or material logic.
Simon’s remarks suggest some affinities with Dewey’s project. He writes that
“Because the second intentions are founded upon the first, the intelligibility of
logical entities, directly or indirectly, flows from the intelligibility of things… The
foundations of the logical world are aspects of the real world, both physical and
mental… [T]here is no a priori restriction on the volume of real inquiry which will
be needed in order to achieve satisfactory explanation of even the most familiar
of logical objects.” (id. xviii) Further, Simon writes of “properties placed beyond
the achievement of consistency, i.e., properties whose laws concern the truth of
our argumentations, their certainty, and their explanatory power… Material logic
is a possibility if and only if some second intentions are so constituted that their
laws be the rules of scientific demonstration.” (id. xi)
The cultural contexts that informed their work were for John of St. Thomas
and Dewey, of course, very different. John worked within the tradition dominated
by the work of Thomas Aquinas, and Dewey was a post-Darwinian naturalist.
Nevertheless, their projects have some interesting things in common. Both see
the rules of formal logic as ultimately based on our understanding of natural
objects. Both view formal logic as a part of a wider project that is concerned with
what Simon calls material logic and what Dewey calls “inquiry into inquiry.” And
both argue that the canons of formal logic must be supplemented by material
considerations if logic is to be capable of scientific demonstration (although they
understood the term “science” differently).
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
Dewey’s Logic: Reviews and Criticisms
211
There are also significant differences. For John of St. Thomas’s project, “logic,
unlike practical command, is not formally concerned with the elicitation of acts, but
rather with the setting in order of known objects.” (John of St. Thomas 1955: 31)
For Dewey’s pragmatic project, however, “Propositional formulation is required
for control of a way of acting that effects discrimination and ordering of existential
material in its function as evidential data.” (Dewey 1986: 263; Lw12:263) Simon
does note, however, with apparent affection, that John had difficulty confining
himself to logic in its formal and material senses. Since he was very much interested
in reality and a generous teacher, he occasionally yielded to the temptation to
digress about interesting issues “in a logical context.” (Simon 1955:. xviii)
Again, I want to thank Professor Faerna for his invitation to contribute to
this volume, and I hope that the foregoing presentation and analysis of some of
the reviews of Dewey’s Logic, both positive and negative, will serve as a worthy
prelude to the important essays that follow.
Larry Hickman
Universidad de Illinois del Sur de Carbondale
[email protected]
r EFErEnCEs
CandLish, S. (1996): “The Unity of the Proposition and Russell’s Theories of Judgment”,
in R. Monk and A. Palmer (eds.), Bertrand Russell and the Origins of Analytical
Philosophy, Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1996, pp. 103-133.
CartEr, P. (1939): “Pitfalls of Pragmatic Logic”, The Communist, no. 18, pp. 163-169. (See
McGill, V. J.)
dEWEy, J. (1980): “Introduction to Essays in Experimental Logic”, in John Dewey:
Middle Works, 1889-1924, vol. 10, Carbondale and Edwardsville, Southern Illinois
University Press, pp. 320-365.
dEWEy, J. (1984): “In Reply to Some Criticisms”, in John Dewey: The Later Works, 19251953, vol. 10, Carbondale and Edwardsville, Southern Illinois University Press,
pp. 210-217.
dEWEy, J. (1986): Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol.
12, Carbondale and Edwardsville, Southern Illinois University Press.
dEWEy, J. (1988): “Experience, Knowledge and Value: A Rejoinder”, in John Dewey: The
Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 14, Carbondale and Edwardsville, Southern Illinois
University Press, pp.3-90.
dEWEy, J. (2008): The Correspondence of John Dewey, 1871-2007, vols. I-IV, InteLex Corp.
john oF st. thoMas (1955): Y. R. Simon, John Glanville, and G. Donald Hollenhorst
(trans.), The Material Logic of John of St. Thomas, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212
212
Larry A. Hickman
LEWis, C. I. (1939): “Meaning and Action”, in “A Symposium of Reviews of John Dewey’s
Logic: The Theory of Inquiry”, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 36, no. 21, pp. 572-576.
LEWis, C. I. (1957): Our Social Inheritance, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
LEWis, C. I. (1969): J. Lang (ed.), Values and Imperatives: Studies in Ethics, Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
LEWis, C. I. (1970): “Logic and Pragmatism”, in J. D. Goheen and J. L Mothershead, Jr.,
(eds.), Collected Papers of Clarence Irving Lewis, Stanford: Stanford University Press,
pp, 3-19.
M arCusE, H. (1939-40): “Review of John Dewey’s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry”,
Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung, vol. 8, 221-28. (trans. Phillip Deen).
MCgiLL , V.J. (writing as P. Carter) (1939): “Pitfalls of Pragmatic Logic”, The Communist,
no. 18, pp. 163-169. (See Carter, P.)
MCgiLvary, E. B. (1939): “Professor Dewey: Logician–Ontologician”, in “A Symposium
of Reviews of John Dewey’s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry”, The Journal of Philosophy,
vol. 36, no. 21, pp. 561-565.
nagEL , E. (1939): “Some Leading Principles of Professor Dewey’s Logical Theory”, in
“A Symposium of Reviews of John Dewey’s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry”, The
Journal of Philosophy, vol. 36, no. 21, pp. 576-581.
PEars, D. (2010) “Introduction to the 1985 Edition”, in Russell, B., The Philosophy of
Logical Atomism, New York: Routledge, pp. vii-xli.
Piatt, D. (1939): “Dewey’s Logical Theory”, in P. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of John
Dewey (Library of Living Philosophers), La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, pp. 105-134.
r EiChEnBaCh, H. (1939): “Dewey’s Theory of Science”, in P. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy
of John Dewey (Library of Living Philosophers), La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, pp. 159-192.
rosEnthaL , S. (2002): “The Logical Reconstruction of Experience: Dewey and Lewis”,
in F. T, Burke, D. M. Hester, and R. B. Talisse (eds.), Dewey’s Logical Theory,
Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, pp. 72-92.
russELL , B. (1919): “Professor Dewey’s ‘Essays in Experimental Logic’”, The Journal of
Philosophy, Psycholog y and Scientific Methods, vol. 16, no.1, pp. 5-26.
russELL , B. (1939): “Dewey’s New Logic”, in P. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of John Dewey
(Library of Living Philosophers), La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, pp. 137-156.
russELL , B. (1961): Our Knowledge of the External World, New York: w. w. Norton.
sChiLPP, P. (1939): The Philosophy of John Dewey (Library of Living Philosophers), La Salle,
Illinois: Open Court.
siMon, Y. R. (1955): “Foreword”, in Y. R. Simon, John Glanville, and G. Donal Hollenhorst
(trans.), The Material Logic of John of St. Thomas, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
singEr, M. (1951): “Formal Logic and Dewey’s Logic”, The Philosophical Review, vol. 60,
no.3, pp 375-385.
sLEEPEr. R. (1988): “Introduction”, in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 14,
pp. ix-xxiv, Carbondale and Edwardsville, Southern Illinois University Press.
Análisis. Revista de investigación filosófica, vol. 9, n.º 2 (2022): 189-212