Reasons: Right and Wrong
Sean Aas
Draft of 10/16/14
Comments welcome at
[email protected]
Please do t uote o
ite ithout pe
issio .
I. The Wrong-Kinds-of-Reasons Problem
A demon threatens catastrophic destructio if ou do t alue his toe ail lippi gs. “o ou ha e e
good easo to do so. Yet that does t
espe t ou
ake the
alua le. You a t get ahead at o k u less ou
oss he s a asshole, ut he a tell if ou e faki g it . That does t
ake hi
respe ta le. You f ie d s dep essed and could really use a win. Even if letting him win is the right thing
to do, that does t
ake it a show of good sportsmanship. You e got
by believing in God—but that does t
u h to gai a d othi g to lose
ake that belief credible.
In each of these cases, a normative concept which seems to be defined in terms of a certain kind of
activity is t definable, simply, as doing that thing or having that attitude as you have most reason to do
it. Some reasons which seem to bear on valuing/ espe ti g/spo ti g/ elie i g, do t see
to ea o
whether some instances of these things in question are respectable/valuable/sportsmanlike/credible.
These easo s a e, as it s so eti es said, of the wrong kind to do so.
This notion is important to our understanding of the role of reasons in the normative domain in at
least two ways. Some, notably Pamela Hieronymi, think that distinguishing right-kind reasons from
wrong-kind reasons requires, ultimately, revisiting our notion of a reason itself; wrong-kind reasons
1
clearly count in favor of the things they are reasons for, but yet, so the thought goes, are not reasons for
them; thus being a reason for is not a matter of counting in favor.1 And some think that the existence of
wrong-kind reasons constitutes a decisive objection to philosophical accounts that try to understand all
normativity in terms of the idea of a normative reason. Some clearly normative concepts, like the
concept of value, involve an unanalyzable notion fittingness; and a corresponding metaphysics of
normative facts for the relevant actions and attitudes to fit.2 These views are bolstered by the inability
of any existing account to distinguish wrong-kind reasons from right-kind reasons without, either,
substantial modification of our account of the reason-providing relation; or, substantial appeal to
normative notions not analyzable in terms of reason-provision.
My goal here is to give a general account of the wrong-kind/right-kind distinction that is prima facie
consistent with the view that all normative concepts can be analyzed using only non-normative concepts
and the concept of a normative reason, where that is understood as a consideration counting in favor of
an action or attitude.
The first step is to properly understand the scope of the problem. In the next section, I argue that
the WKR (for: wrong-kind-of-reason) problem arises not just for attitudes, but also more broadly for any
activity where it makes sense to talk about there being a right way and a wrong way to engage in the
activity—any practice, as I will say.3 In all such cases there is a question as to whether considerations
which count in favor of doing something within a practice count in favor of the conclusion that doing
that thing would be the right way to engage in that practice. But there is also the converse question: do
1
Cf. he e The W o g Ki d of ‘easo Journal of Philosophy 102 (2005): 437-457; The Use of Reasons in
Thought (and the Use of Earmarks in Arguments), Ethics, no. 1 (2013): 114–27.
2
Wlodek Rabinowicz and Toni Rønnow-‘as usse , The Strike of the Demon: On Fitting Pro-Attitudes and
Value*, Ethics 114 (2004): 391–423.
3
This idea is a ge e alizatio of the idea of ‘a ls s idea of a p a ti e, e pli ated at Joh ‘a ls, T o Co epts
of ‘ules, The Philosophical Review 64, no. 1 (1955): 3–32.
2
considerations which bear on what counts as the right way to engage in a practice always bear on
whether one ought to perform the moves of that practice? In the following section I argue that they do
ot; a d he e that ei g a easo of the ight ki d to ϕ does not always entail being a reason,
simpliciter, to ϕ. In the concluding section I sketch an account which makes sense of this feature of the
wrong kinds of reasons problem: on which, very roughly, reasons are of the right kind with respect to a
practice if they are appropriately responsive to the characteristic goals and normal methods of that
practice. This, I argue, is at least prima facie consistent with giving reasons-as-considerations-in-favor-of
a fundamental role in our normative conceptual framework; thus there is no direct argument from
o g ki d of easo
phe o e o to the eed fo a fu da e tal ethi ki g of ou o ept of a
normative reason or of its possibly unique fundamentality to our normative conceptual framework.
II. The Scope of the Problem
The wrong kinds of reasons problem arose, originally, in the debate over so-called buck-passing or
fitting-attitudes theories of value.4 At a first pass, these theories say that to think that something is
valuable is to think that one has most reason to value it; they thus attempt to analyze one central
normative concept, the concept of value, in terms of the concept of a reason – thereby supporting the
general hypothesis that the fundamental normative notion is the notion of a normative reason. But
so e easo s hi h ea o
alui g do t see
to ea o
alue—demon-given reasons, say. As this
problem arose, theorists immediately noticed a similarity to a problem, familiar in epistemology,
concerning the relevance of broadly practical reasons to the justification of beliefs.5 Even if the fact that
it ould
ake
e happ to elie e a pleasa t falsehood is a easo to do so, it is t, to any extent, a
4
Or anyway arose under that name; as was soon recognized, and as I discuss below, similar issues had long
since been raised concerning pragmatic reasons for belief.
5
Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen, op cit.
3
o side atio that episte i all justifies that elief, o
easo s fo
elief, these theo ists thought, is that the
akes it edi le. What s
e ot suita l
the belief in question: that it ould e i e to elie e that p does t
o g ith p a ti al
elated to the o je t/ o te t of
ake it a
o e likel that p is
true. And perhaps we could say the same thing about demon-given reasons for valuing: my reason to
alue the de o s toe ail lippi gs, afte all, does t see
to ha e a thi g much to do with the
clippings themselves.
As a defense of the fitting-attitudes account of value, this move has its problems.6 But following a
suggestio of Ma k “ h ode s, e should suspe t i a
ase that it is ot suita le as a
odel fo a
general distinction between doing things the right way and doing them as we have most reason to do
them.7 Clearly, it applies only to intentional attitudes; and that distinction applies to many other things
besides. There is a right way and a wrong way to value, to be sure— ut the e s also a ight a a d a
wrong way to tie a four-in-hand, or to play a game of basketball. And in all three cases, doing the thing
i
uestio as e ha e
ost easo to do it is t the sa e as doi g it the ight a : i ea h ase so e
reasons are of the wrong kind, while some are of the right. If something like the state-given/object-given
disti tio is ight fo the ase of alui g, o
elie i g, the , the e s easo to thi k it s a spe ial ase of
a more general account which covers non-intentional attitudes and activities as well.
Schroeder suggests that the relevant general class is the class of things that can be done correctly or
incorrectly. This is not implausible. We can believe correctly or incorrectly; plausibly, we can value
correctly or incorrectly too. And reasons do seem to be of the right kind to ground a judgment of
6
Notably, that it seems likely to be circular: in the case of belief, the RK-reasons need to be related to the
truth of the proposition believed. But e d etter not say, analogously, that RK-reasons for valuing need to be
related to the value of the valued object—that would be circular in the context of the buck-passing account. Cf.
here Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen, ibid.
7
Value and the Right Kind of Reaso s Oxford Studies in Metaethics 5: 25-55, September 2010. Schroeder
seems to have changed his view on these matters since then, for reasons I examine and reject below (n10).
“ h oede as used he e efe s to “ h oede -ca.-2010.
4
credibility/value just when they go to the correctness of believing or valuing. Similarly, it seems like we
can tie a knot or set a table correctly or incorrectly; and that this fact enforces a distinction between
reasons which bear on how to engage in that activity on any particular occasion, and reasons which bear
o ho to get it ight. “o “ h oede s a ou t of the s ope of the WK‘ p o le
is e tai l
oader, and
correspondingly more plausible, than some extant alternatives.
But it s ot
oad e ough. To see h , o side so e p edi a e ts ou
pla i g poke . You e et
o e tha
ou a affo d to lose o a ga e—so
ight fi d ou self i
hile
u h that ou re family will
be destitute if you lose. An opportunity arises to cheat and win—you get a minute where you think you
a deal ou self a i
i g a df o
the otto
of the de k. You e p ett su e ou a get a a
it. A d the pla e s ou e pla i g ith, let s sa , a e ho i le
o ste s, ho ill use thei
i
ith
i gs i
terrible ways if they win.) So you have overwhelming reason to deal from the bottom of the deck. But
that does t
ake it the o e t a to deal.
So far, so good, for Schroeder. But compare the following case. Same card game, same stakes, same
o ste s. But ou e a a ged fo a f ie d, ho s at hi g f o
a oss the oo , to o the ga e a d
split the winnings with you, when he observes you fold your hand in a certain way, at a certain time. As
it happens, at the appointed time, (without cheating) you draw a fantastic hand—one that would
po a l
i , if ou did t fold it. You ha e o e
would, after all—also ou ll get the
ould t e heati g—it ould, fo
o e i the
hel i g easo to fold ou p o ised ou f ie d ou
o ste s allets, too . Foldi g i this i u sta e
all speaki g, ot e a i o e t
o e i the ga e of poke . But
it s ot the right way to play: to play poker right, you have to play to win.
It seems, then, that there are two sorts of normative concepts that engender wrong-kinds of
reasons problems: concepts of correct conduct in an activity narrowly construed, and something more
5
general, like the idea of doing an activity right. The poker case shows this, but we should have suspected
it anyway: concepts like the concept sportsmanship and the idea of fidelity to promises seem to
ge e ate WK‘ p o le s, e e though the do t see
to ha e a thi g o iousl to do ith
correctness. It seems clear, then, that the scope of the problem is broader still than the set of concepts
that serve to judge correct or incorrect engagement in an activity: broad enough to include concepts
which encode the looser norms that go with the idea of there being a right way and a wrong way to do
something.
Pa ela Hie o o
i has e e tl a gued, agai st ie s like “ h oede s a d
i e, that the
o g
kinds of reasons problem as such only arises for (only some) attitudes. The thought is that we only have
a loose intuitive grip on the problem to start with – there seems to be some general problem involved in
distinguishing pragmatic from evidential reason to believe, value-relevant from value-irrelevant reasons
to value, and so forth. Schroder and I offer reasons to add things to this list; but all we have to go on in
doing so, really, is felt similarity. Hieronymi maintain that if we have a clear way of drawing the
disti tio i so e of these ases, that does t o e othe s, that ould e a fault i ou i itial a of
posing the problem rather than a flaw in our solution.
She proposes, in particular, a solution to the problem that seems quite convincing for the wrongkinds-of-reasons problem as it arises for certain attitudes; but which (like the object-given/state-given
distinction, of which it is perhaps a descendant) does not apply at all to activities, like dealing a poker
hand or playing basketball. The intuitive thought is that forming certain attitudes is in some sense
equivalent to answering certain corresponding questions. So, to take the clearest case, to come to
believe that p is to affirmatively answer the question: is p true? A right-kind reason for believing, or any
other attitude, is one that bears on the relevant corresponding question. A wrong-kind reason bears
6
instead only on some other, related question – that believing in God is a good bet bears on whether is it
good for me to believe in god, not on whether there is a god.
This is a very plausible account of the wrong-kind/right-kind distinction as that applies to belief, at
least. It offers an elegant, informative account of what distinguishes right-kind from wrong-kind reasons
for belief, in terms of a plausible and illuminating account of what believing is. It is somewhat less clear,
however, that it works for valuing, or for other related attitudes. There does seem to be some intimate
elatio
et ee
o i g to elie e so ethi g a d o i g to affi
it s t uth; so e e ui ale e
between coming to believe that p a d o i g to a s e the uestio : is p t ue , ith a es . But it is
less clear what questions will correspond analogously to attitudes like valuing, or admiring. One might
be tempted to say: to value something is to determine that, yes, it is valuable; to admire someone is to
determine that, yes, they are admirable. But this temptation should, probably, be resisted, as it links
these attitudes too closely to the corresponding judgments. I can judge that opera is valuable without
self alui g it. I a judge that
i al s o k is ad i a le, ithout the e
a tually admiring it.
The e is othi g st a ge a out e p essi g these attitudes, eithe : Ope a is e
self do t alue it ; He
o k is ad i a l
ead it ; eithe so st a ge as the lassi
alua le i deed; ut I
igo ous; ho e e , I feel othi g ut ese t e t he I
It is t ue that … the at is o the
at, ut I do t elie e it .
Perhaps, however, the account could be extended to cover attitudes apart from belief – perhaps,
e.g., as Hieronomyi suggest, these correspond to some more complex set of questions, affirmative
answers to which really do constitute valuing, admiring, etc. In any case the account clearly does not
extend to distinguishing wrong-kind from right-kind reasons for engaging in activities, as well. One does
not deal a hand of poker, or play a game of basketball, or set a table, by answering a question. So the
plausi ilit of Hie o
i s solutio to the
o g-kinds-of-reasons problem, where it is plausible,
7
o stitutes a halle ge to “ h oede s so e hat a d
et
o e e pa si e eading of the scope of
that problem.
Here I want, simply, to accept this challenge. My response will be to offer a solution to the problem
that is
oad e ough to
at h
ie of its s ope; a solutio
hi h, I hope, e plai s h Hie o
s
solution is for persuasive when it is persuasive, while doing at least as good a job in the cases which are
harder for her to account for.
III. One Proposed Solution
‘etu i g to “ h oede : his u de sta di g of the p o le
is
oade tha Hie o
i s; still, it is
probably too narrow to cover all the cases that seem to raise an intuitive problem of distinguishing
doi g so ethi g the ight a f o
doi g it as e ha e
ost easo to do it.
This is not in itself a decisive objection. Perhaps, per Hieronymi, the appearance that all these cases
raise a similar problem needs to be, not explained, but explained away, by a solution to the problem
that is good enough in some cases to convince us that something else must be going on in the others.
What matters in the end, then, is what Schroeder has to say in the way of solving the problem as he
understands it.
Schroeder thinks that WKR problems arise in basically two ways. They arise, first, in cases where
so eo e has a easo
hi h does t see
to appl to e e
od
ho e gages i an activity—robbery
schemes for poker players, or demon threats for valuers. Second, they arise in cases where, though
e e o e ho e gages i a p a ti e has the ele a t easo s, that s o l
e ause e e
od pe se has
the relevant reasons—say, when there are categorical moral reasons not to laugh at a joke. The ensuing
8
thought is that these easo s a e of the
o g ki d ith espe t to a a ti it
e ause the do t ha e
enough to do with the nature of that activity itself.
This is a good thought. But I
less su e a out “ h oede s
o e spe ifi i te p etatio of it:
RKR: The right kind of reasons with respect to an activity A, are all and only those reasons which are shared
by necessarily every able person engaging in A, because they are engaged in A, together with all reasons which
are derivative from such reasons. 39 .
The idea here is that reasons are of the right kind with respect to an activity iff they are (a) general
with respect to that activity, in the sense that anyone who engages in that activity has them; but also (b)
specific to engagement in that activity, in the sense that such engagement explains why people have
them when they have them. It seems to me that there are problems with both conditions:
The idea of the second, specificity, condition is to rule out reasons which are, as it were, too general
to be reasons of the right kind with respect to an activity—paradigmatically, moral reasons which bear
on conduct within an activity but not on whether that conduct is correct with respect to the standards of
that activity. In those cases the reasons in question apply for whatever reason moral reason apply more
ge e all ; he e, the do t appl to o du t ithi a a ti it just e ause o e is e gaged i that
activity. There is, I think, reaso to e o e ed that this ules out too
u h. He e s o e easo : a t
moral reasons sometimes be reasons of the right kind? So, e.g., perhaps moral reasons are, at least
sometimes, the wrong kind of reasons to determine whether a joke is funny. But are t the so eti es
the ight ki d of easo s? It see s to
e that the so eti es a e: so e jokes, a e t fu
e ause
they are so morally objectionable.
Perhaps these problems with the specificity condition can be finessed. The problems facing the
generality condition are much more serious. The purpose of this condition is to rule out reasons which
are too specific or idiosyncratic to be reasons of the right kind with respect to a given activity. The idea is
that, of all the reasons that might apply to the conduct of an activity, only those that apply to that
9
o du t ge e all a e of the ight ki d . This
akes ei g of the ight ki d est i ti e: if R is a reason of
the right kind to ϕ, it s a easo to ϕ. But it does t look like this is ight, as the following cases show:8
“uppose I
sitti g ith
o ste s agai , pla i g a ga e of poke . I k o
the ll i , a d the ll use the
it s
fault that
o e to do so ethi g ho i le to a f ie d of
o that if I do t heat,
i e. Add, if ou like, that
friend is in this predicament. It seems pretty plausible here to say that whatever
reasons I might have to play the game right are not just swamped or outweighed, but cancelled or
defeated,
the po e of
o al easo s to help
f ie d. But that does t make cheating the right
a to pla a ga e of poke : it s just that the easo s that o t i ute to that e di t do t go to hethe
I should play that way in this case or not.
Or consider a more general class of cases, where terrible people have some unusually impressive
qualities. These qualities, in these people, might sometimes be admirable. But make these people
terrible enough, and it starts to look implausible to think that we have *any* reason to admire them—is
the e a
hethe
easo to ad i e “tali s de isi e ess? I do t thi k so: he
e should ad i e “tali
a eas thi g to de ide
e e t i g to figu e out
e do t ha e to eigh the easo s to
admire his decisiveness against the reason to deplore his murderousness—given the latter, the former
just have no weight at all.
Or: try another case, adapted from Schroeder himself. Suppose that I work at the White House, and,
at the last
i ute, fi d
self alled o to set the ta le fo the P eside t. I dis o e that the se e I
replacing was part of an assassination plot, and that the signal to call the whole thing off is to flout
eti uette a d put the salad fo ks o the i side. “uppose also that I a t safel
that the ll put the pla i
otio
ight a a . Plausi l , I do t ha e a
8
a
a o e, o fea
easo at all to put the salad
A tuall the e e a le pe so
ualifi atio already shows this; what follows shows it in a very different,
and I think much less Schroeder-congenial, way.
10
fo k o the outside if ou dou t this,
odif the ase so I
espo si le so eho fo the hole
situatio . But that s still the o e t a to set the ta le. I sofa as the latte
otio is to e
understood, as Schroeder would have us understand it, in terms of the force of the right kinds of
easo s i fa o of doi g so, it follo that I
e e though I do t ha e a
ust ha e easo s of the ight ki d to set the ta le ight
easo s si pli ite to do so.
Ad ittedl , o e of these ases is a utte l de astati g ou te e a ple to “ h oede s RKR.
“ h oede
ould su el
espo d that the
el o u elia le
egati e e iste tial i tuitio s a out
reasons. In all these cases, he could say, there is some reason to do thi gs the ight o
o e t
a . It
is just too weak to be worth mentioning, in light of the reasons on the other side.9
In response, note that the claim that there is always some easo to do so ethi g the ight o
o e t
a
egi s to look less plausible when we focus our attention on activities and practices that
are not just morally neutral, like table-setting or card-playing, but morally objectionable. There is,
appa e tl , a ight a a d a
su je t s
o g a to
ate oa d so eo e: to do it ight you have to force the
outh ope , so that the ate pou s i to his th oat as ell as his ose. Does a p ospe ti e
waterboarder always have some easo to ope his su je t s
outh, efo e pou i g the ate o e ? M
intuition – yours too, I hope – is that he does not always have some reason to do this. We could be
o g, he e. But e ould eed so e a tual, positi e, easo to elie e that e a e
o g. A d it s ot
at all clear that we have it. Schroeder could say that the other strengths of RKR give us such a reason, in
the absence of a compelling alternative. But of course this response depends on the absence of
compelling alternatives. I will argue, below, that there is one – one that has all the strengths of
“ h oede s a ou t a d othe s besides.
9
Weighti g fo a Plausi le Hu ea Theo
of ‘easo s, Noûs 41, no. 1 (2007): 123–124.
11
IV.
A Different Approach
A asi i sight of “ h oede s a ou t is the thought that o side atio s a e easo s of the ight
kind with respect to an activity when they not idiosyncratic with respect to that activity: when they are,
in some sense, normal for that activity. RKR understands normality in terms of generality: reasons are
normal with respect to an activity because they apply generally, to anyone who engages in that activity.
But if, as I ha e suggested, ight ki d easo s a
easo s, the ge e alit does t look like a e
e ot only outweighed but cancelled by other
plausi le i te p etatio of o
alit : so e easo s
which apply to the normal conduct of an activity might well fail to apply to it in every case.
Still, I think the idea of understanding the right kind/wrong kind distinction in terms of
normality/abnormality is on the right track. We just need a better understanding of what it is for
reasons to be relevantly normal. To find one, think back to one of the clearer wrong-kind-of-reasons
cases—the ase of p ag ati
to elie e that I
easo s fo
elief. Wh does t the fa t that it d
ake
e feel eall good
supe -good looking make this belief credible? Proponents of the state-based/object-
given approach discussed above will sa that it s e ause this easo does t ha e a thi g to do ith
the o te t of the elief i
uestio . But of ou se it does ha e so ethi g to do ith it: afte all, it s
being good-looki g that I d e happ a out. The p o le , i stead, has to e the o e that Hie o
a ou t di e ts us to: that it does t ha e e ough to do ith the truth of the elief that I
is
eall good-
looking. Belief aims at the truth: representing the truth is what beliefs are for, in some important sense.
That plausibly, is wh
hat e e goi g fo i
elie i g so ethi g is a s e i g the uestio : it is t ue? , i the affi
ati e –
elie i g is the sa e as hat e e goi g fo i a s e i g uestio s a out the
world; and that is, in both cases, getting the world right, saying and believing it to be as it is.
A d, so the thought o ti ues, si e this is hat elief is fo , e d do ell to ha e a o ept hi h
is used to evaluate how well beliefs do this. If this is the role of the concept of credibility (aka: epistemic
12
justification), then it should be no surprise that credibility is immune to non-truth-related reasons: we
use judgments of epistemic-justification/credibility to evaluate beliefs precisely in light of how they help
us get at true picture of the world.
Part of the story, then, seems to be this: some of our concepts are used to evaluate certain kinds of
action or attitudes in light of how these serve certain characteristic purposes. Reasons are of the right
ki d to g ou d the appli atio of these o epts he the
e related in the right way to these
purposes.
But this is o l pa t of the sto . What s the ight a ? Co side
elief agai . “uppose that, as it
happens, I am indeed really, ridiculously, good-looking. But I have lots of really good evidence to the
co t a
to
the people a ou d
e do t i di ate thei ad i atio , si e the do t a t
eaut to go
head . Ma e I should elie e it fo p ag ati easo s, ha i g to do ith ho happ I d e if I
were really good-looking. This time the content is true. But
t uth i
p ag ati easo s a e t elated to its
the ight a : the do t ha e a thi g to do ith the ki d of e ide e I ha e to elie e i that
truth. The problem here would be that my belief, though related to truth, is not related in the way that
believing faculties typically try to relate beliefs to truth: by disposing them to covary systematically with
evidence. So it is important, in the case of belief, that wrong-kind reasons be related , not just to the
characteristic aims of believing, but also to the characteristic methods believers use to achieve these
aims.
Can we generalize from these observations about belief? Wrong-kinds-of-reasons problems arise for
the concept of epistemic justification because it serves to evaluate beliefs in light of a conception of
hat eliefs a e supposed to do ep ese t the t uth a d ho the
e o
all supposed to do it
co-varying systematically with evidence). But consider: they also arise for the concept of sportsmanship,
13
because we use that concept to evaluate athletic performances in light of a conception of what these
ae o
all supposed to do
e fu , uild ha a te , et . a d ho the
e supposed to do it t
to i ,
follow the spirit of the rules in addition to the letter, etc). In both cases, we conceive an attitude or an
activity under a description which takes it to serve some distinctive purpose in some distinctive way—
we conceive it, as I will say, as a practice. The ole of the idea of the e ei g a ight a a d a
o g
a to engage in that activity is to allow us to evaluate instances of it in light of those purposes and
methods.
I d suggest, the , that e epla e “ h oede s ‘K‘ ith so ethi g like:
RKR*: The right kind of reasons with respect to any practice, P, are the reasons that bear on performances
within that practice in light of its characteristic aims and characteristic methods for achieving those aims.
This account has se e al ad a tages o e “ h oede s:
First, it gets the intuitive scope of the wrong kinds of reasons problem right. Recall that Schroeder
thinks that the problem arises when activities have correctness-conditions. But the poker-robbery case
suggest that this was too narrow. A single recognizable problem arises whenever doing something the
right way can be distinguished from doing it as one has most reason to do it. RKR* explains this.
Practices define particular ways of pursuing particular aims. Sometimes these methods are definable in
some relatively determinate way—as with the formal rules of a game. Correct performance of an
activity consists in following these methods to the letter. But sometimes—as with the kind of informal
norms that often attach to games, as well—our sense of these methods is not so well-defined. The
o espo di g o
s a e t determinate enough to be correctness-norms, strictly speaking: they have
to do, rather, with the looser idea of consistency with the spirit of the practice in question—of doing it
right, rather than doing it correctly.
14
Second, it has no trouble explaining why moral reasons could sometimes be reasons of the right
kind—sometimes recognizably moral goals are among the goals that characterize a practice. Maybe, for
i sta e, offe si el
a ist jokes a e t fu
e ause joki g a ou d is a out solidif i g o ds of mutual
respect and affection, by showing that these bond can survive minor transgression. If so, jokes that put
so eo e ho should e pa t of the solidified o
u it outside it do t fit the ai s a d
ethods of
joking as a practice; they are, therefore, not just unethical, but also, unfunny.
Thi d, this a ou t is i a positio to i di ate ou i tuitio s that e so eti es do t ha e a
reason at all to do things the right way. Basically, the idea here is that there are cases where it makes
sense to understand an action or attitude as a performance within a practice, even though the norms
ha a te isti of that p a ti e do t a tuall appl . “o, e.g., i the poke - heati g ase, e a t e plai
h I d a t to deal f o
the otto
of the de k ithout eference to the norms of poker; even
though, gi e the da ge to
f ie d, I do t ha e a
easo at all to follo those o
s. “i ila l , i
the table-setti g ase, the e
fa t that I ha e o easo to flout eti uette a t e e plai ed ithout
reference to the norms of etiquette themselves—the terrorists are looking for an incorrect setting of the
ta le as a sig al to set off the o
, a d it s this e
fa t that a els
easo to do so. Attitudi al
cases raise a somewhat more complex set of issues. Still, the basic idea will be that there are cases
where we need to think of a given state as an attitude of a type characterized by certain norms; even
though e thi k those o
s do t a tuall appl i the ase—as he
e thi k that e do t ha e
reason to ad i e a di tato s de isi e ess, e e if e thi k de i e ess per se is admirable.
This a ou t, I a t to sa , also o t asts fa o a l
ith Hie o
i s. It allo s us to: a sa
everything her account plausibly says about wrong-kind and right-kind reasons for belief; (b) extend the
15
truth in those things to cover many other things besides; and (c) do so without thereby changing our
views about the fundamental nature of the reason-providing relation.
Believing that p can be, as she says, a matter of affirmatively answering the question: is p true? And
considerations relevant to that question can be right-kind reasons to believe that p; it is this question,
after all, that point us to the truth-representing purpose believing is supposed to serve in the first place.
This, combined with the proposal advanced here, helps to explain an important feature that wrongkind reasons have in the belief case, and in the case of some other attitudes, but lack in many cases of
performance in non-attitudinal practices. Because forming a belief just is answering a question; and a
wrong-kind reason is not relevant to that question, it is very difficult to consciously and reflectively
believe on the basis of (what you know to be) the wrong kinds of reasons.10 Here the very nature of the
attitude on which a putative reason bears constrains the description under which it can be considered; it
makes it very hard to see something plainly unrelated to the aims and methods of belief as a reason to
believe. There is no such problem when playing poker or setting a table or waterboarding. For the
performances involved in doing this can be seen under multiple descriptions. Putting the fork on the
right side of the plate is setting the table wrong; but in the White House case considered above, it is also
saving many lives. Unlike in the case of belief, there is nothing about how an agent has to understand
himself as he does this that constrains his normative perspective to that of polite table-setting; no
constitutive question that setting a table answers, and therefore, no internal connection between
setting a fork down and promoting the achievement of a certain complex pattern of dinnerware.
10
“ h oede all this oti atio as
et i a late dis ussio tha op. cit.; and takes its status as an
earmark of the right-kind/wrong-kind distinction as a reason to resist expanding the scope to include nonattitudes. The a gu e t i the te t sho s h he eed ot ha e do e this. “ h oede , The U i uit of “tateGi e ‘easo s Ethics 122 (2012): 457-488.
16
So, because actions that constitute performance in practice are not, like beliefs, constitutively linked
to the norms that govern those practices, agents can respond much more easily to wrong-kind reasons
for action than to wrong-kind reason for belief. However, pace Hieronymi, we can understand this
without denying that wrong-kind reasons to believe are (at least sometimes) reasons to believe. Reasons
are, just, considerations counting in favor. Further, that sometimes it is difficult or impossible to respond
to a class of reasons does not mean that they are not reasons after all. Appearances to the contrary can
be explained away, by reference to the resources developed here and by Hieronymi herself. Any given
attitude or action can be seen under multiple descriptions; put, as it were, in more than one space of
reasons. But for some attitudes in particular, the fact that forming the attitude comes to answering a
question makes it very difficult for the attitude-bearer to take up any perspective antithetical to
answering that question when forming that attitude. So there is a principled basis for saying, that some
o side atio s that eall , ge ui el , ou t i fa o of attitudes a t see
to us to do so he
ea e
considering whether or not to form or maintain said attitudes. Thus the fact that some considerations
counting in favor of an attitude cannot be consciously used to form that attitude does not show that
they are not reasons for that attitude after all; thus, the wrong-kinds of reasons problem does not
require us to rethink our conception of reasons as considerations counting in favor.
V. Morals
So, I have proposed: to be a reason of the right kind is to be a reason that bears on an attitude or
practice in light of its characteristic aims and methods. If this is what it is to be a reason of the
right/wrong-kind, why do WKR-problems arise? That is to say: why are there concepts which evaluate
a ti ities a o di g to the fo e of o side atio s hi h a e t all pe the o igi al p o le
a do l
(per the new twist pursued here) the reasons which apply to the conduct of those activities? I think
17
e e o i a positio to sa : e ha e su h o epts e ause e ha e practices—at a first pass,
distinctive ways of recognizing and responding to reasons for actions and attitudes. Practices so defined
bring norms with them; and we need concepts which encode consistency with those norms. Some
things typically fall under the norms of a practice; the practice-given reason which apply to those things
are rarely outweighed or cancelled by other sorts of reasons. But even for these things, there are many
importance exceptions—demon-threat-motivated valuings, cancelled reasons of correctness, etc. These
exceptions point us to the existence of the corresponding practices and their distinctive norms. In so
doing they indicate the existence of normative concepts which are, though in some sense defined in
terms of an activity, not definable simply as performing that activity as we have most reason to perform
it.
But though these concepts are not definable along the simple schema: Xing as we have most reason
to X, there is no obvious reason to think that they must have some kind of normativity outside the
normativity of reasons (construed, per above, as considerations counting in favor). They must be
defined on some instance of the more complex schema: Xing in accord with the characteristic purposes
and methods of the practice of Xing; but it s ot lea
h
e d eed a thi g o
ati e othe tha the
idea of a normative reason to fill this in. To say that something is a purpose seems to be to say that there
are reasons of a certain kind to pursue it; to call something a method of pursing a purpose it to say that
it is a reason because in some defined set of circumstances it is the most effective way of pursuing some
purpose. If the foregoing is correct, then, there seems to be little reason to posit any irreducibly
o
ati e otio of fitti g ess to e plai WK‘-cases: we can do the same work with the (somewhat)
clearer idea of a practice as a distinctively structured set of considerations counting in favor. This shows
that the bare existence of wrong-kinds-of- easo s phe o e o is t i o siste t ith the idea that all
18
normativit is the o
ati it of ou ti g i fa o of —the e s a
ethod fo e plai i g those
phenomena which need not obviously appeal to any other kind of normativity.
19