Journal of Philosophy of Education, Vol. 35, No. 2, 2001
Teaching to Lie and Obey: Nietzsche on
Education
STEFAN RAMAEKERS
To understand Nietzsche's view of education requires us to
grasp the importance Nietzsche attaches to being embedded
in a particular historical and cultural frame. Education is,
at least in the early stages, a matter of teaching the child
to see and to value particular things or, in Nietzsche's way
of putting this, teaching the child to lie. Here I develop
an interpretation contrary to those who emphasise
Nietzsche's radical individualism and thus view his
Overman in subjectivistic terms. I argue that Nietzsche's
most important lesson is not that we are to create anything
radically new, but rather that we are to take up a serious
engagement with respect to what we stand for.
INTRODUCTION
Our contemporary postmodern conditionÐthe condition we are supposed
to find ourselves in, and which we read and hear about all the timeÐ
teaches us that there is a multiplicity of viewpoints on what is to be
considered good. In this so-called pluralist society convincing arguments
for the objectivity of the good, while perhaps possible, are seldom wholly
unproblematical. In consequence of this the traditional picture of
education, as a relation between the educator on the one hand and the
child who is to be raised in the light of a particular goal or end on the
other, becomes unsettled. A pluralist society is a source of reservations
about the idea that education can be conceived as a matter of making
the child familiar with, and initiating her into, a cultural heritage. Here
education undergoes a radical shift: the child herself, her creativity and
spontaneity, is valued more than the act of bestowal on the part of the
educator. The educator in this view should step down as the
representative of a particular view of life, and content himself with
the role of facilitator of the education of the child, who is thought to be
capable of discovering within herself what she really wants and capable
therefore of giving meaning to her own life. Self-education, conceived
in terms of the child's choice of goods with the help of the educatoras-facilitator, thus moves to centre-stage. This shift of educational
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001. Published by Blackwell Publishers, 108
Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
256
S. Ramaekers
emphasis appears to allow a break with the cultural heritageÐfor the
educator does not any longer aim, explicitly or implicitly, at preserving
the past; it seems to create possibilities beyond any existing culture's
entrenched ways and customs.
This philosophical problematising of tradition can be said to have
started with Nietzsche. By deconstructing and destroying modernity's
pride in reason as the unquestionable ground for truth and value,
Nietzsche provided the outlines of what we now call postmodernity.
What has been in this respect exercising many minds in the context
of education is Nietzsche's Overman: the individual who razes predominant values and meanings to the ground (hence breaking with
tradition) and puts his own radically alternative values and meanings in
their place. In an article in Educational Theory Johnston argues that
Nietzsche's self-imposed task is not to reconstruct culture, but is `to
point the way to the possibility of a new individual, a self-overcoming
individual, one able to create and live within his or her own valuations'.1
The educational attraction of this is obvious: the child who asserts her
own self thereby guarantees educational and cultural renewal. However,
without elucidation of such superficially appealing ideas as that of
`creating one's own values and meanings', and without clarification
of how one is to understand the concept of the self, this particular use of
Nietzsche can be very problematical. For solipsism, subjectivism and
interpretations ex nihilo are never far away.
In this paper I argue that a subjectivistic understanding of Nietzsche is
incorrect, since it fits ill with Nietzsche's view of the importance of being
culturally and historically embedded. In the first section I will examine
this by giving an account of what Nietzsche means by `obedience' and by
`lying'. In the second section it will be necessary to deal with his
perspectivism. From an educational point of view the importance of
being embedded is that the self-development and self-education of the
child or, to put it differently, the path on which she has to go to become
a true individual, can only be properly understood starting from that
cultural and historical embeddedness. This will be explored in the third
section. In the fourth section this exploration will be extended and
nuanced through an account of Nietzsche's anti-essentialist conception
of human being. In the final section I will argue that the important
lesson to learn from Nietzsche concerns the business of taking up a
serious engagement with what one stands for.
OBEDIENCE, OR THE IMPORTANCE OF EMBEDDEDNESS
Much as one values Nietzsche for his cultural criticism and for his
culturally innovative ideas, it would be a mistake to overlook the
importance he attaches to obedience. Johnston argues that one cannot
infer an anarchistic account of education from Nietzsche's writings
because of his emphasis on obedience and discipline in the primary
school.2 However, Johnston fails to give obedience its rightful place. For
Nietzsche's account of morality (particularly in Beyond Good and Evil,
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Teaching to Lie and Obey: Nietzsche on Education
257
and more specifically in the chapter `The Natural History of Morals')
shows that obedience is not just about keeping pupils in line, but means
obedience to cultural and historical rules, and as such is a moral
imperative for all of humankind. The most important thing about every
system of morals for Nietzsche is that it is `a long constraint', a `tyranny
of arbitrary laws'.3 For such cultural and historical phenomena as
virtue, art, music, dancing, reason, spirituality, philosophy, politics and
so on the creative act requires not absolute freedom or spontaneous
unconstrained development but subordination to what is or at least
appears to be `arbitrary'. It entails a long bondage of the spirit.
The singular fact remains . . . that everything of the nature of freedom,
elegance, boldness, dance, and masterly certainty, which exists or has
existed, whether it be in thought itself, or in administration, or in speaking
and persuading, in art just as in conduct, has only developed by means of
the tyranny of such arbitrary law; and in all seriousness, it is not at all
improbable that precisely this is `nature' and `natural'Ðand not laisseraller!4
The nature of morality inspires us to stay far from an excessive freedom
and cultivates the need for restricted horizons. This narrowing of perspective is for Nietzsche a condition of life and growth.5 It is interesting
to see how this is prefigured in Nietzsche's second Unfashionable
Observation (On the Utility and Liability of History for Life). The cure
for what he there calls `the historical sickness',6 i.e. an excess of history
which attacks the shaping power of life and no longer understands how
to utilise the past as a powerful source of nourishment, is (among others)
the ahistorical: `the art and power to be able to forget and to enclose
oneself in a limited horizon'.7 Human beings cannot live without a belief
in something lasting and eternal.8
Subordination to the rules of a system of morality should not be
understood as a deplorable restriction of an individual's possibilities and
creative freedom; on the contrary, it is the necessary determination and
limitation of the conditions under which anything can be conceived as
possible. Only from within a particular and arbitrary framework can
freedom itself be interpreted as freedom. In other words, Nietzsche
points to the necessity of being embedded in a particular cultural and
historical frame. The pervasiveness of this embeddedness can be shown
in at least four aspects of Nietzsche's writings.
First, in his critique of morality Nietzsche realises all too well that it is
impossible to criticise a system of morals from outside, as a view from
nowhere. Instead a particular concretisation is required. Beyond Good
and Evil may very well, as a prelude to a philosophy of the future, excite
dreams about unlooked-for horizons and unknown possibilities. In
The Genealogy of Morals, however, written by Nietzsche as further
elaboration and elucidation of the same themes, he explicitly states that
Beyond Good and Evil does not imply going beyond good and bad.9
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
258
S. Ramaekers
Criticising a system of morals inevitably means judging from a particular
point of view.
Second, in his representation of the true philosopher Nietzsche insists
on not confounding philosophers with philosophical labourers and
scientists, for the philosopher's task is the most noble of all tasks: to
create values. `The real philosophers . . . are commanders and lawgivers;
they say: ``Thus shall it be'' '!10 The true philosopher's inspiration to
determine the whither and the why of humankind does not however
emerge out of nothing. Nietzsche makes it unambiguously clear that in
order to `grasp at the future with a creative hand'11 the philosopher must
himself have stood upon the steps of the scientist, of the critic, of the
dogmatist, of the moralist and so on. These steps are the basis for the
preliminary labour that has to be done before the real act of creation,
they are the means, the instruments, the hammer,12 in short `a foundation
and scaffolding'.13 The real philosopher hammers on the existing bastion
of values, but nonetheless needs the pieces to create his own bastion.
Third, Nietzsche has important things to say about the role language
plays in constituting truth. As early as On Truth and Lies in a Non-moral
Sense, one of his earliest philosophical writings, he urges that what one
normally understands by truth is essentially constituted by language:
`[the] legislation of language likewise establishes the first laws of truth'.14
For Nietzsche, speaking a language is a matter of using certain images
and metaphors, and hence speaking a language is a subordination of the
individual to the general. Speaking the truth then means using customary
metaphors, thus signifying the set of common conventions to which one
has to subordinate oneself (language is constraint)15 on pain of being
incomprehensible. In Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche specifies this
commonness as a conformity in `groups of sensations'. In order to
understand each other it is not sufficient just to use the same words, one
also needs `to employ the same words for the same kind of internal
experiences', that is to say, one `must in the end have experiences in
common'.16 In other words, individuals understand each other, speak the
truth when having lived together for a fairly long time under similar
conditions and as a consequence speak the same language.
Fourth, a human being experiences difficulties in giving an appropriate place to what is not yet given in her embeddedness. She always
first lets the familiar, the known world affect her, and only later, slowly
and cautiously, admits what is unfamiliar to her, the (to her) unknown
world. Nietzsche writes:
Our eyes ®nd it easier on a given occasion to produce a picture already
often produced, than to seize upon the divergence and novelty of an
impression: the latter requires more force, more `morality'. It is dicult
and painful for the ear to listen to anything new; we hear strange music
badly.17
When confronted with something unfamiliar a human being typically
reacts in a reserved manner, maybe even with a little aversion, since it is
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Teaching to Lie and Obey: Nietzsche on Education
259
painful seeing and hearing things that are hard to conceive or that go
against everything she is accustomed to. `From our fundamental nature
and from remote ages we have beenÐaccustomed to lying',18 Nietzsche
writes: this `lying' should not be understood as a matter of not speaking
the truth, but points to the constellation of a particular cultural and
historical framework that constitutes human beings' necessarily narrow
perspective. This `lying', and the fact that it is taken for granted, are not
deplorable. On the contrary, from the observation that our eyes are hurt
when seeing the unfamiliar and that we can only hear new music with
great difficulty, it follows that `lying' is always presupposed in order that
the unfamiliar can hurt us at all. To explain this it will be necessary to
elaborate on Nietzsche's perspectivism.
PERSPECTIVISM
For Nietzsche the perspectival is the fundamental condition of life.19 It is
however of the uttermost importance not to interpret this perspectivism
in a traditional metaphysical manner, in which reality is understood as
an invariant essence, ready out there to be put in perspective by a human
being, so that human perspectives on the other hand are conceived as
particular variations of that fixed background. Nor does Nietzsche's
perspectivism mean that the multiplicity of perspectives should be
combined to form a kind of universal overview of the world or a
universally valid perspective. Nietzsche makes it unambiguously clear
that there are only perspectives.20 To put it differently, Nietzsche tried to
overcome the opposition between background and foreground, between
`text' and `interpretation',21 between `absolute knowing' and `relative
knowing',22 between the `true world' and the `seeming world'.23
Rejecting the conception of an absolute truth consequently means that
these distinctions no longer make sense. `We have done away with the
true world: which world remains then? the seeming one maybe? . . . But
of course not! together with the true world we have also done away with
the seeming one!'24
The difficulty is that Nietzsche's way of putting this reminds us of the
traditional metaphysical terminology and hence suggests a background
lying behind a foreground. The point however is that all these
expressionsÐ`perspectival', `seeming world', `interpretation', and also
`lie', `exploitation', `mistake'25Ðshould not be understood in the
traditional way. There is nothing there to be interpreted, there is not
something one can tell a lie or be mistaken about. Rather, Nietzsche
means that there is no distinction at all between the true world and the
seeming one. `The opposition between seeming world and true world
converts into the opposition between ``world'' and ``nothing''.'26
Consequently, Nietzsche argues that there is something wrong with
the customary searching for the truth, since it supposes one has to break
through the seeming world in order to attain the real one. Attempting to
free oneself from the seeming world however brings to ruin truth itself:
`if, with the virtuous enthusiasm and stupidity of many philosophers,
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
260
S. Ramaekers
one wished to do away altogether with the ``seeming world''Ðwell,
granted that you could do thatÐat least nothing of your ``truth'' would
thereby remain!'27 In other words, attempting to dispose of the
perspectival is tantamount to giving up the world itself: `As if there
might remain a world, when one had set aside the perspectival!'28
A similar reasoning obtains when Nietzsche speaks of the constitution
of the world by language. When he states that because of language `the
way seems barred against certain other possibilities of world-interpretation',29 that expression in language limits the formulability of the
world,30 this does not mean that there is a background out there waiting
to be nominated by language. That `language has everywhere become an
autonomous force that now clasps human beings in its ghostly arms and
pushes them in directions in which they do not really wish to go'31 does
not mean human beings aspire to something outside the distinctions put
forward by language. Rather it means that language, human beings and
world are entangled with one another in such a manner that it is
impossible to dispense with language (e.g. in the typically traditional
searching for truth), for this would mean at the same time dispensing
with human beings themselves.32
EDUCATION AND THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING EMBEDDED
In Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche says about education:33
Parents involuntarily make something like themselves out of their
childrenÐthey call that `education'; no mother doubts at the bottom of
her heart that the child she has borne is thereby her property, no father
hesitates about his right to subject it to his own ideas and notions of worth.34
In view of the importance Nietzsche attaches to obedience, to being
embedded, one should not be surprised that he considers initiating the
child into a particular constellation of arbitrary laws to be a natural part
of her education. For the child, education means, at least in the early
stages, being subordinated to a particular view of what is worth living
for, and being introduced into a system of beliefs. Education consists
in teaching the child to see and to value particular things, to handle a
perspective: to lie. The argument goes even further. In view of
Nietzsche's perspectivism one must now say that not initiating the
child into a perspective, not teaching him to lie is educationally speaking
not even an option: the child makes himself familiar with a perspective
he cannot ignore since this is the precondition for making sense of
anything and exploring the unfamiliar. Put differently, because of the
necessity of being embedded a human being is moulded into a particular
shape that he cannot do without.
My understanding of Nietzsche is consequently at variance with any
understanding which argues for a radical individualism and takes the
individual to be the point of reference of all values and truths.
Johnston35 for example tilts the scales too strongly towards the
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Teaching to Lie and Obey: Nietzsche on Education
261
individual as a self-affirming autonomous agent and hence disregards
the epistemologically and ethically constitutive importance of the
individual's embeddedness for what she affirms as true and valuable.
He even claims that the individual put forward by Nietzsche is the
antithesis of the social realm. For Nietzsche, Johnston writes, `there is
no question of a reconciliation between the realms of the individual and
the social'.36 Referring to Dewey, he makes it look as if the Nietzschean
individual can withdraw herself from social embeddednes since she
apparently has no need to refer her own action to that of others.37
Adopting a thoroughly Nietzschean stand on education therefore
requires, in Johnston's opinion, a break with education conceived as a
matter of `making familiar with' and of being initiated into a particular
cultural inheritance, that is as a matter of socialisation in this rich sense.
In consequence education becomes essentially self-education.
It is not hard to see that focusing in this manner on the individual is
greatly welcomed by progressive educational movements such as childcentred pedagogies. In their critique of the traditional educational
model, characterised simply as a bestowal of values by the educator,
they show their concern with the child's personal identity. In this view
initiating the child into a particular view of life does injustice to her
personal identity, her true self is suppressed, suffocated and not given
the opportunity to develop into what it `really' is. Education should by
contrast create room for the self-development of the child's true self: this
seems to be the educational lesson to be learned from Rousseau, Rogers,
Steiner and Freinet among others. An emphasis on a particular kind of
experiential learning, supported by a distinctive conception of the nature
of experience, warrants the child giving meaning to her own life.
Now there is nothing wrong with the notion that socialisation in some
sense resembles indoctrination, and is, from a particular point of view, a
kind of injustice; nor is there a problem with concern for the child's
personal identity. The problem however is that the way in which the
child-centred movement conceives the individual only allows a subjectivistic, even solipsistic, interpretation of self-education. Johnston
rightly argues that Nietzsche's critique of the conception of absolute
truth and universal values gives rise to perspectivism. However he treads
on dangerous ground when claiming that for Nietzsche, from an
epistemological point of view, all truths, and from a moral point of view,
all values, exist only `as a matter of individual perspective', that for
Nietzsche `truths are reducible in the last to the individual', and that
`[t]he new system of values provided by and for this individual takes its
point of reference from the individual, and not the outward society,
church, state, nation, or culture'.38
EDUCATION ON THE GROUND OF AN ANTI-ESSENTIALISTIC
CONCEPTION OF HUMAN BEINGS AND WORLD
Emphasising the constitutive importance of being embedded does
not however mean that one cannot give any meaningful sense to
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
262
S. Ramaekers
self-education. For the fact that every human being, because of her
embeddedness, is affected with a particular perspective or moulded into
a particular shape, does not necessarily mean for Nietzsche that she is
limited to that particular perspective or shape. The child's self is not
constituted permanently by her being embedded. Alteration, development, in short self-education, remain possible. Nietzsche does indeed
argue that the merit of every system of morals lies in narrowing human
beings' perspective: nonetheless he is bold in his critique of particular
moral interpretations that are available. To be more precise, the thorn in
his (philosophical) side is not that the system of morals moulds human
beings and their world into a particular shape, but that it absolutises
that particular shape: Nietzsche thus criticises, in the name of
multi-interpretability and multivalence, any fossilisation of moral
interpretation.
For Nietzsche a human being is `the animal not yet determined '.39 She
is an animal, i.e. embodied and driven by instincts, but at the same time
she is distinguished from the animal since her instincts do not limit her to
one particular model.40 Nietzsche has Zarathustra say that a human
being is `a rope, fastened between animal and Superman', she is a bridge,
not a goal, her destiny is to go `up and beyond'.41 Indefiniteness, not
reason, is the crucial distinction between human beings and animals.
Following from this Nietzsche sets himself the task of placing humankind back into nature:
In eect, to translate man back again into nature; to master the many vain
and visionary interpretations and subordinate meanings which have
hitherto been scratched and daubed over the eternal original text, homo
natura.42
One can therefore argue that Nietzsche's view of human beings is of a
naturalistic kind, understanding this however not in an essentialistic or
reductionistic way. The `nature' of a human being is to have no essence;
particular historical manifestations are only an exemplification of this.
Rather this `nature' can be understood as an empty place from which a
multiplicity of possibilities can arise. It is however important to notice
that `empty place' and `nature' merely act as metaphors to criticise the
prevailing uniformity with which human being is represented. De facto
she never is an empty place, she never is indefinite, but always already a
particular possibility, without reduction to which there is no sense at all
in speaking about other potential possibilities. The homo natura is the
original text scratched upon with interpretations and meanings, but
which one cannot speak about at all without those interpretations and
meanings. In this sense, every human being is unique, and irreducible to
a basic pattern since that pattern does not exist.
The world too is for Nietzsche not yet determined. In itself the world
is not good nor evil, no more than the Alps are beautiful in themselves: it
is without essence. If the world carries qualifications, then they do not
belong inherently to the world's essence (`The ``essence'' is lacking')43
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Teaching to Lie and Obey: Nietzsche on Education
263
but are brought about in relation to a human being.44 Concepts like good
and evil only have meaning in reference to human beings. A human
being, whom Nietzsche also denominates as a `revering animal', explains
the world as a function of her own wishes and needs.45 Nietzsche
eventually even argues that a human being `can only understand a world
which she herself has made',46 or rather which she herself has put into
perspective. As with the indefiniteness of a human being one should
notice here too that the world never is indefinite. Without a particular
shape there is no sense at all in speaking of other potential shapes.
EDUCATION AS THE EVERLASTING TASK OF
SELF-OVERCOMING
Nietzsche's view of human being and world sheds additional light on the
concept of education. In view of the importance Nietzsche attaches to
being embedded and in view of his perspectivism, I have argued that
education cannot but be understood as teaching to lie, i.e. as initiating
the child into a particular view of what is valuable and worth living for.
Mindful of Nietzsche's view of human being one should now say that
any particular moulding of the child is detrimental to what the child
really is: not yet determined, unique, irreducible to a basic pattern.
Therefore, the pre-eminently educational taskÐexpressed by Nietzsche
in the powerful dictum `become what you are'47Ðcan be defined as a
never-ending process of self-overcoming. In other words, human beings'
tragic fate is to live their lives in the ambiguity of, on the one hand,
always being of a particular kind without, on the other hand, being
allowed to be reduced to, allowed to settle in, that particularisation.48
It is of the utmost importance to understand that the child's
educational task, `to become what you are', should be understood as a
process that can only get started if a particular mould or pattern is
forced upon her. The child's `true self' is not some sort of nucleus of
essential characteristic features, already there as germs waiting to be
developed. It arises from within and thanks to the moulding that is
offered. In this respect Cooper rightly argues that there is no childcentred pedagogy to be found in Nietzsche because of the importance of
obedience and because there is no nucleus one should not counteract.49
The child's `true self ' lies not deep within herself, but, so to speak, above
her.
Again it is interesting to see how this is prefigured in Nietzsche's
second Unfashionable Observation. Having diagnosed the main problem
of contemporary education as its erroneous aim to produce `the
scientifically oriented person', i.e. `the historically and aesthetically
cultivated philistine, the quickly dated up-to-date babbler about the
state, the church, and art', Nietzsche indicates that to break with this
education one `must help youth express itself, must help illuminate, with
the lucidity of concepts, the path of their unconscious resistance
against this education and transform it into an aware and outspoken
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
264
S. Ramaekers
consciousness'.50 The child only has thoughts for which she has words,
and those words are given to her.51
An important question here is how exactly the child proceeds to selfovercoming, in other words how she discovers the possibility of
transgression and thus succeeds in surpassing the herd. In view of the
importance of being embedded the answer to this question cannot but be
that the impetus to self-overcoming arises from embeddedness itself.
Education as teaching to lie, the necessary precondition for the child to
find her own path, means education as realising that it is merely a lie.
Education as `making something like themselves out of their children',
as teaching the child to put things into perspective, means passing
through what is worth living for without pretending that the perspective
the child is initiated into, is universal and absolute in nature. `I should
think that today we are at least far from the ridiculous immodesty that
would be involved in decreeing from our corner, that perspectives are
permitted only from this corner'.52 Education as merely teaching to lie
then points to evoking the disposition of self-overcoming53Ðwhereby
evoking means arousing as well as provoking.
The child, then, discovers that the cultural and historical shape of
the world and the socialised and culturalised moulding of her own self
are lies. It is important to notice that this does not lead her towards
the truth, as should be clear now from Nietzsche's perspectivism, but
rather, room is made for the appreciation of lying as lying. For
Nietzsche the only truth there possibly can be in the end is this notion
of lying as lying. `I was the first to discover the truth, through the fact
that I was the first to experience the lie as lie'.54 Alteration, renewal,
personal interpretation of the world, freeing oneself from the sociocultural straitjacket and so on, do not take place against the background of a true world or on the ground of an essential nucleus, but
should be understood as `a continuously shifting falseness':55 the child
must make her own lies, again and again. She will be most herself
when continuously acknowledging her own indefiniteness, that is to
say when showing herself to be open to a multiplicity of possibilities.
`It is always more obvious to me that the philosopher, as a man
indispensable for the morrow and the day after the morrow, has ever
found himself, and has been obliged to find himself, in contradiction to
the day in which he lives; his enemy has always been the ideal of his
day'.56 In a certain sense one should therefore say that the true
individual never shall be, but always shall be.
However difficult this task may be, the arrival of the higher human
being is more than welcomed by Nietzsche. For Nietzsche's analysis of
his time leads him to conclude that human beings are living in the
mentality of the herd: `Morality in Europe at present is herding-animal
morality'.57 Human beings become dull under the impulse of, inter alia,
typical modern ideas and Christianity;58 they degenerate into mediocrity
and superficiality and satisfy themselves with the stultifying repetition of
what they have been spoonfedÐwhich is for Nietzsche the greatest
danger for humankind:
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Teaching to Lie and Obey: Nietzsche on Education
265
The leveling and diminution of European man is our greatest danger;
because the sight of him makes us despond . . . We no longer see anything
these days that aspires to grow greater; instead, we have a suspicion that
things will continue to go downhill, becoming even thinner, more placid,
smarter, cosier, more ordinary, more indierent, more Chinese, more
ChristianÐwithout doubt man is getting `better' all the time . . . This is
Europe's true predicament: together with the fear of man we have also
lost the love of man, reverence for man, con®dence in man, indeed the will
to man. Now the sight of man makes us despond. What is nihilism today if
not that?59
That is why, according to Nietzsche, every culture needs individuals who
consciously commit themselves to that culture's values, revalue them
and thus revitalise them. The true individual speaks where the herd fails
to speak, she eases the tightness of the chains with which the herd is
enchained. This individual, `anti-christ and anti-nihilist', frees herself
from her will to nothing, to nihilism.60
RELATIVISM VERSUS DELIBERATE COMMITMENT
Are we at this point obliged to conclude that it does not matter then just
what the individual does? In other words, is relativism the inevitable
outcome? One could answer this in a strictly philosophical way and
argue that the question of relativism does not arise at all for Nietzsche
because of his perspectivism. Nietzsche explicitly intends to settle once
and for all the opposition between absolute and relative: for want of
absolute knowledge and truthÐof a world which is not mediated
through representationsÐthere is no sense at all in speaking about
relative knowledge and truth. Hence the problem of relativism dissolves
naturally with Nietzsche. This answer however may not be convincing
for some. As the matter of relativism is too complex to be fully
developed here, I shall conclude by indicating some relevant issues.
As indicated above, Nietzsche can be seen as the founding designer of
postmodernism since he deconstructs the foundational conceptual
frameworks of modernity and consequently of education along
modernity's lines. However, that there are no objectively justifiable
grounds for an educator's action any more does not tempt Nietzsche to
say that everyone is correct. Nor does he shift the educational burden to
the child (in a final attempt to provide education with firm foundations
again), for as has been made clear, even for Nietzsche meaning does not
arise from within the individual himself or herself. Nietzsche's
perspectivism, the outcome of the lack of objective foundations, can
be understood as an incentive to stop looking for justifications and
instead to articulate clearly what one stands for. For one could say that
it is precisely the belief in objectively justifiable standards in education
that can give rise to stultifying repetition, so feared by Nietzsche. If what
one intends to represent is absolute or final truth, then in the long run a
clear articulation is not needed, so one could say, for in the end the truth
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
266
S. Ramaekers
will prevail. As there are no objective foundations but only perspectives,
it is necessary for the educator, and later on for the child, to articulate
what he or she stands for. So when Nietzsche says `My opinion is my
opinion: another person has not easily a right to it',61 he is not making a
plea for a subjectivist point of view, nor for relativism, but he is
emphasising the importance of a serious engagement with what one
stands for. Making moral decisionsÐand what is education if not thisÐ
is not a matter of plain and simple reenactment of what is logically
entailed and justified by one's culture's expectations, but is in the end
a highly personal matter. ` ``Good'' is no longer good when one's
neighbour takes it into his mouth.'62
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
I am grateful to Paul Smeyers for reading previous versions of this paper
and for commenting on both philosophical argument and language.
Correspondence: Stefan Ramaekers, Centre for Philosophy of Education,
Faculty of Psychology and Educational Sciences, University of Leuven,
Tiensestraat 102, 3000 Leuven, Belgium.
E-mail:
[email protected]
NOTES
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
Johnston (1998), p. 79.
Cf. Johnston (1998), pp. 71±72.
Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil (BGE), sec. 188.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 188.
Cf. Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 188.
Nietzsche, Unfashionable Observations (UO), p. 163.
Nietzsche, UO, p. 163.
Cf. Nietzsche, UO, p. 164.
Nietzsche, GM, I, sec. 17.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 211.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 211.
Cf. Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 211.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 258.
Nietzsche, On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense (OTLN), p. 81.
Cf. Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 188.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 268.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 192.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 192.
Cf. Nietzsche, e.g. BGE, Preface; Human, All too Human (HAH), I, Preface, sec. 6.
Cf. Nietzsche, GM, III, sec. 12.
Cf. Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 22.; cf. also Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 BaÈnden (KSA), 12, 7[60]
(Translation of his unpublished fragments is not available, so the references to these passages are
to the German text. The ®rst ®gure refers to the volume, the next to a period of time delimited in
that volume, and the number between brackets to the section of that delimited part.)
Nietzsche, KSA, 11, 38[14].
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 34; KSA, 12, 3[106].
Nietzsche, KSA, 6 (GoÈtzendaÈmmerung) (author's translation).
Cf. Nietzsche, e.g. BGE, secs. 34, 230, 259; GM, II, 11; KSA, 11, 25[505].
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Teaching to Lie and Obey: Nietzsche on Education
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
42.
43.
44.
45.
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
51.
52.
53.
54.
55.
56.
57.
58.
59.
60.
61.
62.
267
Nietzsche, KSA, 13, 14[84] (author's translation).
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 34.
Nietzsche, KSA, 13, 14[134] (author's translation).
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 20.
Cf. Nietzsche, KSA, 12, 9[91].
Nietzsche, UO, p. 281.
Nietzsche, OTLN, p. 88±89.
By education I mean child-rearing as well as schooling.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 194.
Cf. Johnston, 1998.
Johnston, 1998, p. 81.
Cf. Johnston, 1998, p. 68.
Johnston, 1998, resp. p. 68, 69, 78.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 63 (author's translation. Zimmern's translation goes as follows: `man is the
animal not yet properly adapted to his environment'. However, this is, I think, de®nitely not what
Nietzsche means by `das noch nicht festgestellte Tier').
Cf. Nietzsche, KSA, 11, sec. 107. See also Van Tongeren, 1994, p. 145.
Nietzsche, Thus spoke Zarathustra (TSZ), sec. 4, 43.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 230.
Nietzsche, KSA, 12, 7[1] (author's translation).
Cf. Nietzsche, HAH, I, sec. 28.
Nietzsche, The Gay Science (GS), V, sec. 346.
Nietzsche, KSA, 11, 25[470] (author's translation).
Cf. Nietzsche, the subtitle of Ecce Homo: `How to become what you are'.
Cf. Van Tongeren, 1994, p. 147.
Cooper, 1983, pp. 122±123.
Nietzsche, UO, p. 160.
To be entirely correct, this matter is not settled ( yet) in his second Unfashionable Observation.
Besides this reference to the fact that experiences can only be talked about after being
intersubjectively conceptualised (e.g. by the educator)Ða private language argument avant la
lettreÐNietzsche does also refer to such a thing as an `individual feeling that does not yet bear
the stamp of words' (p. 162). Furthermore he states that youth, which is the safeguard of a lifeenriching culture, `will be able to use no concepts, no party slogans from among the verbal and
conceptual coins that are currently in circulation, to designate their own being' (p. 165). It is
tempting to interpret this in a subjectivistic manner, or at least to leave it an open question
whether or not Nietzsche thinks there to be such a thing as a `meaning-full' preconceptual
content. However, in view of Nietzsche's other (early) writings, especially On Lies and Truth in a
Nonmoral Sense, this interpretation seems to me to be incorrect. It is more fruitful, in my
opinion, to interpret this as follows: youth cannot use concepts etc. to designate their own being
because every conceptualisation is detrimental to what it really is: impossible to be tied to one
(strain of ) word(s).
Nietzsche, GS, V, sec. 374.
I am indebted to Paul Smeyers for this particular way of putting it.
Nietzsche, KSA 6 (Ecce Homo, sec. 1 of chapter Why I am a destiny) (author's translation).
Nietzsche, KSA, 12, 2[108] (author's translation).
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 212.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 202.
Cf. Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 203.
Nietzsche, GM, I, sec. 12.
Cf. Nietzsche, GM, II, sec. 24.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 43.
Nietzsche, BGE, sec. 43.
REFERENCES
Aviram, A. (1991) Nietzsche as educator?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 25, pp. 219±234.
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
268
S. Ramaekers
Colli, G. and Montinari, M. (1980) Friedrich Nietzsche: SaÈmtliche Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe
in 15 BaÈnden (MuÈnchen, Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag).
Cooper, D.E. (1983) On reading Nietzsche on education, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 17,
pp. 119±126.
De Martelaere, P. (1994) De al te menselijke wetenschap [The all too human science], in: O. De
Bleeckere and E. Oger (eds) Landschappen van Nietzsche. Kunst, wetenschap, leven en moraal
[Landscapes of Nietzsche. Art, science, life and morality] (Kampen, Kok Agora).
Golomb, J.J. (1985) Nietzsche's early educational thought, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 19,
pp. 99±109.
Hillesheim, J.W. (1986) Suering and self-cultivation: the case of Nietzsche, Educational Theory, 36,
pp. 171±178.
Johnston, J.S. (1998) Nietzsche as educator, Educational Theory, 48, pp. 67±83.
Moore, G.E. (1955) Wittgenstein's lectures at Cambridge 1930±32, Mind, 64, pp. 1±27.
Nietzsche, F. (1956) The Genealogy of Morals, trans. Francis Golng (New York, Doubleday &
Company).
Nietzsche, F. (1967) Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Helen Zimmern (Edinburgh, T. & A. Constable
Ltd.).
Nietzsche, F. (1969) Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. R.J. Hollingdale (Harmondsworth, Penguin
Books).
Nietzsche, F. (1979) On truth and lies in a nonmoral sense, in: D. Breazeale (ed.) Philosophy and
Truth. Selections from Nietzsche's notebooks of the early 1870s, trans. D. Breazeale (New Jersey,
Humanities Press).
Nietzsche, F. (1980) Die froÈhliche Wissenschaft, in: G. Colli and M. Montinari (eds) Friedrich
Nietzsche: SaÈmtliche Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 BaÈnden, Band 3 (MuÈnchen, Deutscher
Taschenbuch Verlag).
Nietzsche, F. (1980) Ecce Homo, in: G. Colli and M. Montinari (eds) Friedrich Nietzsche: SaÈmtliche
Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 BaÈnden, Band 6 (MuÈnchen, Deutscher Taschenbuch
Verlag).
Nietzsche, F. (1980) GoÈtzendaÈmmerung, in: G. Colli and M. Montinari (eds) Friedrich Nietzsche:
SaÈmtliche Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 BaÈnden, Band 6 (MuÈnchen, Deutscher
Taschenbuch Verlag).
Nietzsche, F. (1995) Human, all too human, in: E. Behler (ed.) The Complete Works of Friedrich
Nietzsche, vol. 3 (Stanford, Stanford University Press).
Nietzsche, F. (1995) Unfashionable observations, in: E. Behler (ed.) The Complete Works of
Friedrich Nietzsche, vol. 2 (Stanford, Stanford University Press).
Rosenow, E. (1973) What is free education? The educational signi®cance of Nietzsche's thought,
Educational Theory, 23, pp. 354±370.
Rosenow, E. (1986) Nietzsche's concept of education, in: Y. Yovel (ed.) Nietzsche as Armative
Thinker (Dordrecht, Martinus Nijho Publishers).
Rosenow, E. (1989) Nietzsche's educational dynamite, Educational Theory, 39, pp. 307±316.
Van Tongeren, P. (1994) Een moraal voor moralisten [A morality for moralists], in: O. De Bleeckere
and E. Oger (eds) Landschappen van Nietzsche. Kunst, wetenschap, leven en moraal [Landscapes of
Nietzsche. Art, science, life and morality] (Kampen, Kok Agora).
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.