The Self in Historical Light
Iamblichus versus Porphyry
Mats Winther
http://www.two-paths.com/iamblichus.htm
Red and blue composition . Serge Poliakoff (1965).
Abstract: The article investigates the Neoplatonic Self notion. In the
historical record the ideal of personality and the psychological notion
of Self have taken many forms. Also the modern ideals of Self are
discussed and criticized, such as the puer aeternus (eternal youth)
and the primal or uroboric Self. The author argues that Carl Jung s
Self archetype is one-sidedly immanent there is also a
transcendental aspect of Self. In the heated debate between
Porphyry and Iamblichus, both were right in their own way.
Keywords: Plotinus, Neoplatonism, primary narcissism, grandiose
self, ego-Self axis, Erich Neumann, Michael Fordham,
psychoanalysis, puer aeternus, Romantic era.
Part I: Antique concepts of Self
In Neoplatonism, the realization of individual existence depends on a process of
authupostata (self-constitution). It means that the thing generated is becoming
conscious of its separation from the source. (It applies to everything created
since, in Plotinus, also stones, mountains, etc., are ensouled.) The source is the
transcendental One the goodness, unity, harmony and continuity from which all
being has emanated through consecutive levels (cf. Remes, 2008, p.52). In
Neoplatonism, the perceived world and its entities are regarded as derived.
Individuation means the fall or descent of the soul. Says Pauliina Remes:
As a part of the Intellect, each of us would have no true individual
existence. The human striving towards individual existence, towards
being oneself, separates the souls from the original togetherness
within the Intellect. This urge and audacity (tolma) creates token
souls and ultimately brings them to the utmost individuation: to an
existence as embodied, individual human beings. Our home and
origin is the intelligible universe, gazing closely at the One or God,
yet becoming a human being with a personality, individual
characteristics and body, as well as a place and task in the universe,
unrelentingly ties us to the realm below perfection. Thus belonging
to something high and perfect, without any individualizing
characteristics, is contrasted with being an individual with one s
particular existence and personal features. Personality and
individuality are understood as essential to our nature, yet connected
with imperfection. The same move that makes us what we are,
embodied individuals, creates problems for the human claim to truth,
perfect goodness and paradigmatic unity. (pp.112-13)
The desire towards the source is awakened when there is a realization of
separateness from wholeness and unity. Separateness is what awakens the
individual, and as a result the production acknowledges itself as a
distinguishable thing. Says Remes: The claim is that an entity becomes itself
only through a reversion towards and a vision of its cause (ibid. p.68).
Translated to modern psychological language, as long as personality cannot see
itself as distinct from the Self, there is no true individuality. It is well-known that
the neurotic personality, entertaining a grandiose-exhibitionistic self-image ,
must take defensive measures to protect the feeble ego. On the other hand, the
strong and independent ego harbours a feeling of separateness from longed-for
wholeness and unity. In religious thought, it is known as the longing for God or
love of God.
In Plotinian thought, this is when conversion takes place and
reversion (epistrophê) ensues (cf. Plotinus, Enneads I.6.9.7 25). Individuation,
that is, worldly generation of multiplicity, comes to an end and the philosopher
begins the ascension to the One . It is accomplished through worldly denial (selfcontrol, ascetic practices, prayer, etc.) and contemplation of the Platonic Forms
(anamnêsis). Thus, in Plotinus s days, the ideal of Self was transcendental,
simple, and unitarian. (Notably, the Neoplatonists distinguish the self notion from
notions of human being and soul .)
Plotinus and Porphyry regarded the soul as partly undescended, which means
that the soul through its higher faculties has direct access to the Nous the
realm of Platonic Forms. Porphyry held that the true human Self is identical to
the divine Nous. Their view that objects of knowledge are internal and innate to
the soul gives rise to the famous Neoplatonic inward turn . The reversal of life is
a turn inwards (cf. Remes, p.167).
Iamblichus (c.245 c.325 AD) took issue with this view and argued, against his
teacher Porphyry (c.234 c.305 AD), that individuation may continue in parallel
with reversion by means of theurgy. It is a creative ritual practice performed with
the intention of evoking diverse divinities, which are prone to descend. It seems
to compare with the theory around integration of archetypes, central to our
present-day psychological form of individuation.
On this view, nature s striving for wholeness, perfection, completeness and
continuation becomes identified with its eternal Platonic origin at the top of the
hierarchy. In other words, the horizontal striving of living beings becomes
identified with vertical striving (cf. Remes, pp.8-9). In contrast to his teacher
Porphyry, Iamblichus viewed the soul as wholly descended, that is, as wholly
immanent. He also became an advocate of an immanent ideal of Self as opposed
to the former transcendental ideal. Remes says:
[The] later Neoplatonists reject Plotinus doctrine of the unfallen part
of the soul. For them, the human soul is entirely psychic, with no
divine or unfallen parts. Thereby its perfection, too, is not
assimilation to something foreign to itself, like the nous, but a
psychic and human event. (p.185)
Rather than undertaking the upward journey to the gods, the theurgist must
make preparations for the opposite to occur. The soul must be rendered pure and
suitable for the god to enter. The lower gods (benign daimons that are prone to
descend) may be received through theurgic means. The impersonal and
transcendental ideal (as in Plotinus) lacks relevance to the theurgist, because
God is per definition beyond reach. Instead, the personal daimon (Lord of
daimons) becomes his focus of attention. It gives rise to an individual ideal for
each human being (cf. p.130). Iamblichus says:
It is the accomplishment of acts not to be divulged and beyond all
conception, and the power of unutterable symbols, understood solely
by the gods, that establishes theurgic union. (Iamblichus, On the
Mysteries of the Egyptians [ De Mysteriis ], II.11, 96 7)
Iamblichus postulates an immanent version of the One, which he calls the one of
the soul ( to hen tês psuchês ). He also uses the term helmsman (from Plato s
Phaedrus ). It has a predecessor in Plotinus s concept of the we of the soul.
Gregory Shaw says:
Iamblichus s doctrine of the one of the soul provided important
theoretical support for the practice of theurgy. Because the soul
carried the presence of the One it had the capacity to rise above
itself, be homologized to the cosmos and united with its divine
cause. The fact that the soul possessed correspondences to the
entire cosmos meant that, like the cosmos, it possessed a principle
that preceded its multiplicity [...] [The] helmsman joined the
disembodied soul to the supercelestial realm. Iamblichus said that
the soul was capable of this unification [because] there subsists in
its very essence an innate knowledge (emphutos gnôsis) of the
Gods (DM 7, 13-14). (Shaw, 1995, p.118-19)
The one of the soul was ineffable and inaccessible to understanding. Its
function was to coordinate the multiplicity of the soul, including the many
attractions of embodied life, into a whole. As a consequence, the soul s vertical
ascent was determined by its horizontal extension (cf. p.121). Since a
correspondence of the One is present in the psyche, it allows for the coalescence
of the worldly and the spiritual. Shaw says:
[First], however, the soul had to coordinate its passions with
material daimons. The affectations that enslaved the soul to daimons
had to be purified and aligned with sunthêmata [symbolic tokens] in
nature before the soul could reach the simpler and more unified
levels of the gods. Without this collaboration with daimons the soul
lacked the foundation necessary to homologize itself to the material
gods. (ibid. p.155)
Iamblichus explains that despite the prima facie meaning of the
term, invocations do not, in fact, invoke the gods or call them
down. On the contrary, they evoke the divine sunthêmata lying in
the human soul... (p.177)
The gods were mediated to the soul by means of sunthêmata and the goal was
the integration of the psychic, which in a paradoxical way leads to henôsis with
the noetic Father. Says Shaw:
Iamblichus explicitly states that the soul has only one ruling daimon
and that he is good (DM 282, 1-5). To fulfill the charges of its
guardian, however, the soul first had to recognize him and then
develop a rapport [...] The soul s freedom from the daimon like its
freedom from the law was determined, paradoxically, by its degree
of identity with it. The daimon was not left behind but was, as it
were, digested and incorporated by the theurgist. (ibid. pp.218-19)
Iamblichus s embodied psychology has its modern counterpart in Carl Jung s
psychology and his notion of the Self the archetype of wholeness transcending
ego consciousness. Jung puts emphasis on the psychic Self, which approximates
Iamblichus s notion of the one of the soul . The Self is the symbol of multiplicity
in unison, a complexio oppositorum . As it represents the goal of integration of
personality, it demands active participation in the manifoldness of reality, which
includes symbolic activity. Jung s archetypal concept rhymes with Iamblichus s
notion of the divine sunthêmata lying in the human soul .
Jung took exception to trinitarian mysticism, which in the tradition of Porphyry
searches to achieve unio mystica by a direct route of worldly denial and
contemplation. To Jung, it is crucial to acquire a wholeness of personality
before allowing room for spiritual ambition. To achieve this, the integration
of psychological complexes plays a central role. Failure to fulfil the requirement
of psychological wholeness would lead to neurotic consequences. Interestingly,
Shaw says that Iamblichus had a similar concept:
Noetic worship was useless without this foundation. Yet, in the view
of Iamblichus, such premature noetic worship was being encouraged
in Platonic schools, and Porphyry, his chief rival, was a prime
example of one who attempted to short-circuit the material gods and
daimons. Although Porphyry had spoken of his henôsis with the One,
he was subject to severe bouts of depression, even to the point of
suicide. Such emotions would suggest that Porphyry neglected to
honor the god and daimons associated with his depression and thus
failed to homologize himself to the material gods, gatekeepers of the
immaterial gods and true union with the One [...] From Iamblichus s
perspective Porphyry s henôsis had to have been false: if someone
were still dominated by worldly passions (e.g., suicidal depression),
he could not presume to pass beyond the material gods [...]
To reach the One, the soul had to be assimilated to the Whole, and
this was accomplished only by honoring all the gods (ibid. pp.15556)
[A]ccording to Iamblichus, the soul may return to the One only if it
has been homologized to the All. The soul must first see itself in all
things before it enters the immortal body measured by the gods.
(ibid. pp.227-28)
It corresponds to Jung s demand of integration of personality and emphasis on
worldly adaptation. Yet, judging from the historical record, Porphyry has come
out on top. His Introduction (to philosophy) remained the standard textbook on
logic throughout the Middle Ages. Despite his strong critique of Christianity,
Porphyry s view of mystical ascent was adopted by the Christian mystics. The
emphasis on rationality and contempt of superstition is still the leading star of
Western science.
Moreover, Iamblichus severely underestimated the capacity of consciousness and
logical reasoning. History has proved this wrong. In spite of all this, the
Iamblichean paradigm (late Neoplatonism) has resurfaced in modern times, in
the form of Carl Jung s psychology.
The conclusion is that our view of the human Self, as well as our view of the
spiritual path and man s relation to existence, split into two competing paradigms
before the onset of the Middle Ages. This conflict has still not been resolved. One
could argue that Porhyry represents the spiritual, rational, and impersonal ideal
whereas Iamblichus represents the psychological, individual, and this-worldly
ideal.
Both paths, taken by themselves, are connected with serious difficulties.
Iamblichus s soteriological cult may easily degenerate into an unconscious form
of pagan religiosity, such as fetish worship. Conversely, Plotinus s model may sire
a sterile intellectuality a form of elitism remote from worldly engagement. In
De Mysteriis , Iamblichus criticizes it as a form of intellectual hubris (cf. Shaw,
pp.240-41).
Iamblichus held that the goal of direct worship of the One came only at the very
end of life and to very few ( On the Mysteries of the Egyptians 230, 18-231, 1).
Carl Jung said essentially the same; that the Self was really an unattainable goal.
We are only able to approximate the complete wholeness of personality during
lifetime.
The devoted spiritual searcher has good reason to argue that it is a defeatist
standpoint. The immanent and psychological paradigm could be accused of
making too much out of the material gods : before the soul may enter the
immortal body it must be homologized to the All . It must see itself in all
things . Allegedly, the spiritual pilgrim can only achieve this goal by honouring
all the gods . Arguably, this is overreaching oneself.
Much in the same way, constant horizontal expansion is at the heart of Jungian
psychology. The archetypal complexes are focus of a ceaseless work of
integration. Yet, the process will not, after all, lead to the goal of the Self.
What s behind the theoretical and soteriological split is that the two models are
mutually exclusive. It is not possible to combine Porphyry and Iamblichus to
create a balanced model. However, should one remain devoted to either one, it is
bound to give rise to problems; of the personal kind as well as the theoretical.
Today, we can observe that Jungian psychology is bogged down by degenerate
pagan and obsolete Freudian notions. The material gods have taken possession
of the followers, while it should be the other way round.
To resolve this dilemma we are forced to regard both paradigms as true, despite
the fact that they rely on discordant doctrines. Following the principle of
complementarity, they may be viewed as complementary to each other.
According to a complementarian view, either path is right up to a certain point,
when it is time to change perspective. If correct, it s not necessary to honour all
the gods . Rather, it suffices to become moderately integrated as a person, when
it is time to adopt the vertical perspective of the divine.
Which shall be regarded the true human Self, Porhyry s transcendental Nous or
Iamblichus s psychic helmsman ? In my view, it is necessary to entertain both
models, since there are really two complementarian aspects of the human Self.
The Self is both vertical and horizontal; both impersonal and personal. However,
since they are mutually exclusive there is no way that they can function
simultaneously as ideals in a person s life. While both models of Self are
complete in themselves, neither of them is quite sufficient to encompass the
paradoxical nature of the Self. Either one of the two wholenesses is like a circle
that isn t quite closed.
The Self cannot be put in a nutshell. Thus, we must have recourse to two models
of Self that are mutually exclusive. It follows the principle of complementarity
defined by Niels Bohr, who applied it to the nature of light. So the Self has
something in common with light. In order to get the whole picture, it is necessary
to endorse both Porphyry and Iamblichus, even though the theoretical
contradictions are insurmountable.
Discussion
What is the consequence if personality remains unaware of the origin and
therefore persists in an undifferentiated state? In that case it s not possible to
develop a true relation to society and to other people. The result is a mass man
who adjusts himself to the collective, and he becomes part of the machine. To
such people, the ideal takes form as the totalitarian society. The group mind,
which builds on collective identification, is an anti-Self .
The traditional notions of Self, the transcendental and the personal, are both
effective in differentiating the individual from collective identity. As long as the
individual is mindful of the Self, it is an effective remedy against projection and
projective identification. As a consequence, the individual is less prone to project
the Self on great personalities, such as Hitler, Mussolini, or Mohammed. An
awareness of a center of personality, whether immanent or transcendent, serves
to promote psychic health because it alleviates our obsession with the outer
world. Thanks to a heightened level of consciousness we may avoid horrors such
as collectivism, war, as well as personal tragedies. To this end, it is necessary to
acquire a certain degree of wholeness.
The theory around the Self allows for many ways to improve one s character. The
one-sided intellectual, for example, simply isn t aware that his feeling function is
inferior and that it causes damage to relations. It would suffice that he becomes
aware of his inferiority and that he tries to improve himself. In such case, a
notion of the Self as the wholeness of personality has a healing function.
History is full of brilliant people that have gone under as a consequence of their
one-sidedness. Evariste Galois was a French mathematician, born in 1811. His
work laid the foundations for Galois theory and group theory of abstract algebra.
On account of his great mathematical talent he became arrogant and haughty
since he neglected other sides of personality and of learning. He even had to
repeat a class in school. Eventually, his inferior function took over. Toward the
end of his life he said: My heart revolted against my brain . Despite this
realization he died in a pistol duel at only 20 years of age (cf. Hall, 1977, ch.1).
What if he had had wholeness of personality as ideal instead of worldly
recognition? Then he would have had time to make many more mathematical
discoveries. Iamblichus s notion that it s necessary to take charge of one s
daimons has much to recommend it.
Divine dualism and soul dualism
Traditional societies often had two projective ideals of Self: the medicine man
and the king. Interestingly, Jung characterized Mussolini as the king whereas he
saw Hitler as personifying the shaman (medicine man). Despite this dual
definition of Self, Jung maintained that the Self was one. His ideal is akin to the
spiritually enlightened king. The shamanic Self, in the form of Jesus Christ, did
not appeal to him. Jung is adamant in his rejection of the transcendental
tradition, despite the fact that it has always had an enormous following in all
parts of the world. After all, Jesus was extremely otherworldly. He told people to
get rid of their money. They ought to give it back to the emperor, or to the poor,
and lead life like the birds, not worrying about tomorrow.
On the surface, it doesn t make sense, and thus Jung saw it as an incomplete
image of Self. Instead he developed a conglomerative ideal of Self, much the
same as Iamblichus s doctrine. The Jungian Self is like a worldly king enveloped
in pagan spirituality. In pagan societies, such as the Celtic, the spiritual realm
was always nigh a view that runs counter to the Christian transcendental view
of spirit. A conglomerative view of Self gives rise to a certain pagan naiveté, in
the way of New Age. Arguably, this is what underlies the process of
romantification during which the concept acquires qualities of a pagan deity.
Yet, to lead life according to a chiefly this-worldly ideal has damaging
consequences, too. Jung s Self is paradoxical, antinomial, and ambivalent. In
order to realize such an ideal, the average individual is required to adopt a moral
consciousness of the primitive kind. He has to remain naive in order not to be
torn apart. So naive unconsciousness can save him. Yet this is damaging because
it paves the way for collectivism and a pagan regress. That s how I see it. Jung,
however, thinks that heroic consciousness can sit astride the ambivalent monster
and control it. But the average individual cannot.
There is a serene and otherworldly Self of perfection, too, as well as a reclusive
way of individuation. Jung rightly finds that this ideal is irreconcilable with the
Self of completeness. His thinking is essentially Hegelian, that is, it builds on the
synthesis of opposites. If thesis and antithesis cannot be combined in a synthesis
(because they are mutually exclusive), then either opposite must be wrong. So
he throws out the trinitarian Self.
However, complementarian thinking is profoundly anti-Hegelian, as
Arkady Plotnitsky (1994) explains. My argument is that this is the right place to
apply complementarian thinking. Both models are true, and both are necessary
to fully represent the phenomenon of the Self. Thus we arrive at a
complementarian model of the Self which includes irreconcilable opposites, and
not only dialectical opposites. It stands to reason that a truly exhaustive model of
the Self should include both perfect man and complete man. Arguably, Jung s
Self ideal does not provide the whole picture. In fact, there is in him an inner
conflict between the ideals of complete man and spiritual man , as Jung s
dreams give evidence to (see below).
I hold that the partition of Self as shaman and king ought to be preserved (cf.
Winther, 2011, here). The Self is like the god Janus or the duplex Mercurius. On
this view, the Christ is indeed a complete image of Self. It must not be
repudiated as an incomplete or defective image. Rather, it represents the one out
of two adequate ideals of personality. Yet, while these ideals are both beneficial,
the conglomerative Self risks leading personality astray.
The conclusion is that the reclusive mystic, or the sequestered artist, mustn t be
seen as pursuing an incomplete and defective ideal, in the way of imitatio
Christi . The Jungian notion of Self can be repaired by adding to it the notion of a
transcendental Self. It would relieve the pressure on the worldly Self of
completeness, which is overburdened. Not only does it represent the demands of
worldly adaptation as well as the integrative work on personality, involving the
withdrawal of projections and development of consciousness. It also stands for
spiritual development, which risks taking a pagan turn.
The integration of the unconscious, combined with worldly engagement, is a good
enough investment. It suffices that the king partakes in religious ritual, in
whatever form (partaking of nature, for instance). He need not risk his mental
sanity by diving headlong into the unconscious, in the sense of Jung s own crisis.
Such a crisis is likely to result from the conflicting drives of the world and the
spirit. It is impossible to satisfy both these drives, to the utmost, at the same
time. In terms of a complementarian Self , the spiritual and the worldly paths
ought to be pursued consecutively, and not at the same time. While following the
worldly Self of completeness, the spiritual path must remain formal, i.e.,
religious .
In Neoplatonism and in Gnosticism there were two primary gods: the One (the
Monad, etc.) and the Demiurge. (In Neoplatonism the Demiurge was a
personification of the Nous the first hypostasis.) The former was characterized
by unity, simpleness, and transcendence. The latter stood for multiplicity and
worldly generation. The Gnostics rejected the latter as evil whereas the
Neoplatonics saw worldly generation as a means to a higher end. One may
speculate that this dual perception of the divine reflects on two irreconcilable
aspects of human personality: one Self that strives upwards and one Self that
expands horizontally in the worldly realm.
The notion of soul dualism is well-known in comparative religion. According to
the ancient Chinese, every human being has a hun soul ( cloud soul ) and a po
soul ( white soul / moon soul ). The hun soul belongs to the spiritual and
heavenly Yang principle whereas the po soul is an indwelling Yin spirit that makes
it abode in the material and the bodily.
Among the Australian aborigines human beings have a dream-time soul that may
reincarnate. There is also a free soul that may become a malevolent ghost.
Protective measures may be required against the latter. Amerindians believed in
dual souls. The first of these is the free soul , which might leave the body in a
state of sleep or trance. The second soul is the life-soul, i.e., a vegetative soul
corresponding to the po of the Chinese. It was believed that the free soul
travelled to the afterworld, whereas the other was capable of reincarnation.
According to the Dogon of West Africa only the jackal (the trickster) was created
single. All the other beings, including the twin demiurges, were created double.
Humans beings have double souls, too. Human twins become the object of a cult
as soon as they are born, since they manifest a divine principle.
Carl Jung s dream
I do not know if it s relevant to interpret soul dualism in modern terms as two
incommensurate forms of wholeness, a worldly and spiritual. Yet, it seems that
Jung s dream about kneeling before the highest presence revolves around this
very theme (cf. Jung, 1989, pp.217-220, excerpt here). The dream featured a
steep flight of stairs that ascended to a spot high up on the wall which no
longer corresponded to reality . Here lived the faithful Uriah who had been
murdered by order of King David.
Jung was compelled to bow down before The Highest Presence , but he never
quite touches the floor with his head. His ego would remain defiant and that s
why he is not doing it properly. In the dream he is portrayed as maliciously
stupid whereas his father, the clergyman, makes a brilliant exegesis of a biblical
passage. Evidently, Jung has underestimated the message of the bible, which
speaks in the voice of the Ultimate God Image.
Arguably, his ego is equatable with King David, responsible for the death of
Uriah. Instead, sultan Akbar would come to occupy the centre of the mandala.
Yet, had he refrained from killing (repressing) Uriah (the transcendent
personality), then he would not have made the achievements comparable to
King David s. It s no wonder that his conscience is plagued by his betrayal of
Uriah and why the play and counterplay between the two personalities has run
through his whole life. It is the same theme as King Oedipus who, in order to
become king, kills his own father. But, unlike Jung, his crime finally dawned on
him. As he becomes aware of his guilt, he bows down fully to the ground, covers
himself in ashes, and leads the rest of his life as a blind beggar.
The via negativa and the transcendental form of mysticism is a central theme in
religion. Yet, Jung thinks that trinitarian tradition is predicated on the trinity as
an incomplete wholeness , and that s why it is simply wrong. But we might have
to accept that there are two discordant principles governing personality. Theology
has two principles at work, namely incarnation and apotheosis. Jungian
psychology recognizes only one, namely incarnation. It corresponds to
integration, when the unconscious takes root in conscious reality. Psychology
stands in need of a notion that corresponds to apotheosis, which relates to the
trinitarian Self. I have suggested the term complementation (cf. Winther, 2014,
here).
Part II: Modern concepts of Self
(1) Puerile Narcissism and (2) Primary Narcissism
1. The puer aeternus
Modern psychology has formulated concepts of Self building on observations of
the neurotic personality. These have been appropriated as models for the sound
personality; the difference being that the healthy mind lives them out to the full
in a self-aware and informed way.
James Hillman ( Archetypal Psychology ) has adopted the puer aeternus as ideal
for personality. It is the eternal youth of fairy tale who lives in an eternal dreamstate, resistant to growing up. Whereas Marie-Louise von Franz regards
identification with the puer aeternus as a neurosis belonging to the narcissistic
spectrum, Hillman has argued that the puer is not under the sway of a mother
complex but that it represents a sound way of adaptation to life. M-L von Franz
uses the notion puer aeternus to denote individuals that suffer from a puerile
neurosis, in the same way as Freudian psychologists connect the Oedipal
complex with the Oedipal personality .
They generally do not like sports which require patience and long
training, for the puer aeternus, in the negative sense of the word, is
usually very impatient by disposition, so that such sports do not
appeal to them (von Franz, 2000, p.8).
A man who has a mother complex will always have to contend with
his tendencies toward becoming a puer aeternus (ibid. p.10).
Von Franz explains that the puer aeternus wants to hover above the earth, to get
away from reality and from ordinary life. In general, the man who is identified
with the archetypal adolescent remains too long in adolescent psychology. This is
also how Hillman portrays the puerile ideal in his books:
The calling from the eternal world demands that this world here be
turned upside down, to restore its nearness to the moon; lunacy,
love, poetics [...] A puer-inspired theory will also limp among the
facts, even collapse when met with the questioning inquiries of socalled reality [...] an archetypal psychology is obliged to show its
own mythical premises... (Hillman, 1996, pp.282-83)
Hillman repudiates the Jungian notion of Self, claiming that it is an offshoot of
Christian theology, an expression of Jung s monotheistic theological
temperament . Allegedly, the Jungian definition of Self only reinforces
individualism . It makes you stay indoors, off the streets, out of the party (cf.
Hillman, 1992, p.180). Instead, Hillman redefines the Self as the interiorization
of community (ibid. p.40). The ideal is to become one with the collective. It
follows from the puerile and unrealistic image of life as a grand party . Hillman s
notion of the Self as the introjected image of the collective is antithetical to a
notion of Self it s an anti-Self that promotes collectivism. According to
M-L von Franz this is also the consequence of the puerile ideal:
The strange thing is that it is mainly the pueri aeterni who are the
torturers and establish tyrannical and murderous police systems. So
the puer and the police-state have a secret connection with each
other; the one constellates the other. Nazism and Communism have
been created by men of this type. The real tyrant and the real
organizer of torture and of suppression of the individual are
therefore revealed as originating in the not-worked out mother
complex of such men (von Franz, 2000, p.164).
Philosopher Paul Roubiczek (1968) has investigated the 19th century s Romantic
period the high point for the puer aeternus. He explains that Romantic
subjectivist delusion has propagated into the modern era and paved the way for
reactionary movements, such as Nazism. The fact that the Romantic idealists are
unconcerned with reality and ignore the actual world, has such consequences.
When reality is side-stepped and the imagination of egoic consciousness takes
precedence, it has dire political consequences.
The Romantics are so intoxicated by their discovery of the
omnipotence of the mind that, in other respects too, they will have
nothing to do with reality. It is not only that in their philosophical
writings they ignore the existing world, but that they always build up
in their imaginations a world as it should be, without considering in
the least whether this world of the imagination can be translated into
reality. Imagination is the highest and most original faculty of man,
and everything else only reflection upon it [...] This flight not only
from necessity, but also from reality, is considered as the highest
duty of man: [...] the arbitrariness of the poet must not
acknowledge any law above itself. (Roubiczek, 1968, pp.69-75,
here)
According to Roubiczek, Romanticism represents a flight from necessity , by
which he implies an escape from the coercive forces of life that can lead to a
mechanized and spiritless condition. He holds that it underlies the overestimation
of the power of consciousness and the flight from reality into extreme
individualism, which leads to an equally extreme materialistic reaction in the
collectivistic ideologies of the 20th century. Roubizcek s views are substantiated
by later research in Romanticism. Ira Livingston (1997) says:
As such, Romanticism is allowed to emerge and mutate with
capitalism and modernity, assuming various avatars for example, in
Fascism and Nazism (with their militantly nostalgic appeals to a
prealienated, organic society), in modernist culturism (where
culture is located as the privileged site of resistance to
commodification)... (p.11).
The aestheticism of Hillman and the Romantics implies that egoic consciousness
dresses up in the beautiful mythological clothes of the puer aeternus. It s evident
from the following excerpt from The Oldest System Programme of German
Idealism :
We must have a new mythology, but this mythology must be in
service of the ideas; it must be a mythology of reason. Before we
make ideas aesthetic, i.e. mythological, they will have no interest for
the people. (Beiser, 1995, p.5)
If mythology lacks its roots in the unconscious, it is chimerical and merely the
products of a short-circuited ego consciousness. Nazi mythology was created in
this way conscious political ideas were subjected to mythologization and were
made to comply with Aryan aesthetic ideals. Thus, a false mythology of one-sided
and quixotic consciousness served to foil the true unconscious spirit. In this way,
mythology was put in the service of destructive and megalomaniacal
consciousness.
It exemplifies how Romanticism and phenomenological idealism has put the cart
before the horse, as they portray consciousness as the wellspring of myth. This is
the Romantic fallacy: to dress up conscious ideas in mythic language. J.G. Fichte
is the founder of the Jena school of Romanticism. His notion of the primacy of the
self, i.e. that the ego is world-creating, is at the root of the Romantic movement,
according to which mythic and poetic consciousness is to replace the Cartesian
scientific worldview. Romantic philosophy has its modern successors in
postmodernism and in phenomenological philosophy (Heidegger, Husserl, etc.).
Post-structuralism, which underlies much of today s societal discourse, implies
that truth is merely the conscious structures that we have chosen to impose on
reality. It gives rise to an extreme form of relativism. Thinkers of this ilk are
impervious to arguments that rely on hard facts. The Romantic paradigm has
destructive moral consequences. Nicholas Mason says:
At the heart of the Romantic project, Campbell explains, are two
interconnected impulses: to seek pleasure and to imagine future
pleasures. Not surprisingly, then, when Romanticism gained cultural
preeminence in the late eighteenth and early Consumer Culture
nineteenth centuries, heeding these impulses became increasingly
socially acceptable, nowhere more so than in the marketplace. What
resulted was a distinctively modern form of pleasure-seeking, a
sort of autonomous, self-illusory hedonism. In contrast to
traditional hedonism, which turns to material goods to alleviate life s
discomforts, modern Romantic hedonism produces an endless series
of imagined desires, none of which once attained offers more than
fleeting pleasure. Hence, the modern consumer-cum-hedonist is
continually withdrawing from reality as fast as he encounters it,
ever-casting his day-dreams forward in time, attaching them to
objects of desire, and then subsequently unhooking them from
these objects as and when they are attained and
experienced. (Klancher, 2009, pp.197-98)
The Romantic mythopoetic worldview continued into modern times. The negation
of individuation (i.e., to remain in boyhood) must needs lead to an immersion in
the collective, with the consequence that the individuative demand is projected
on the spirit of the collective, as in Hegel s philosophy.
2. Primary narcissism
According to Freud s theory (1914), in the beginning, all of the infant s libido is
invested in the self and libidinal attachment to the surrounding ( objectcathexis ) has not yet occurred. Freud refers to this as primary narcissism .
Psychoanalyst Heinz Kohut developed Freud s stage of primary narcissism to
paradigmatic status as underlying our notion of self. The archaic configuration of
primary narcissism the grandiose Self and the idealized parent image is
moulded into a well-adapted sense of self with sound self-esteem and a set of
mature goals, values and ideals (cf. Leeming, 2010, p.608).
It means that the stage of primary narcissism will always remain in the
background and that the mature personality is merely an improved version of the
archaic Self. In this model, the original and grandiose Self (which personality
longs to reunite with) is not properly detached as in the Neoplatonic model.
Rather, the individual remains attached to it as if by an umbilical cord. The notion
has gathered numerous followers in both the Freudian and Jungian school.
The problem is that the classical theory of primary and secondary narcissism is
today regarded as obsolete by most authors on the subject. Otto Kernberg
(1975, ch.10) says that the concept of primary narcissism (love of self which
precedes loving others) is no longer justified, because libidinal object-investment
and primary self-investment of libido go hand in hand. From a metapsychological
perspective, they are wholly coincident. Therefore it s improper to say that all
psychological motivation is ultimately based on narcissism. The notion of primary
narcissism is regarded as obsolescent, whereas adult narcissistic strategy is
viewed as a form of lingering and deep-rooted immaturity, sometimes dependent
on hereditary factors.
It s easy to see that the Freudian notion of primary narcissism is faulty because it
builds on the idea of the child s narcissistic self-investment in a private ego,
which however remains undeveloped a self-refuting idea. However, theories
that center upon primary narcissism actually reckon with an innate self,
subsisting in the uterus a uterine Self .
The problem is that it relates a pathological picture of human psychology. Certain
Freudians authors, most notably Heinz Kohut and Donald W. Winnicott, claim
that normal human psychology is narcissistic and that normalcy is merely a form
of mitigated narcissism. Winnicott says that the normal human personality moves
back and forth between omnipotence and the aggressive destructive urge; back
and forth between symbiosis and alienation. The reason why Jung s model does
not relate this picture, Winnicott claims, is because Jung suffered from a severe
pathology since childhood (cf. Winther, 2003, here).
In classic Jungian psychology the narcissistic dynamic (eminently portrayed by
Winnicott) is a pathological condition. According to Nathan Schwartz-Salant, the
grandiose-exhibitionistic self a merger of ego functions and archetypal
dynamics dominates the narcissistic character. It corresponds to what in
alchemy is called a premature coniunctio a monstrosity. It has a strong
defensive quality and lacks the numinosity of the Self in Jungian terms. The
narcissistic character instead carries a forced, power-oriented, copy. In fact, the
subject is forced to defend against the numinosity of the Self. As a power far
superior, it could easily defeat the grandiose identity. It is crucial to understand
that the narcissistic character not only defends against outer object relations, but
equally against the inner world of archetypal reality. Both are a great threat. The
subject is in fear of the Self because the Self is always a defeat for the ego,
especially in the event of a grandiose ego-Self merger (cf. Schwartz-Salant,
1982, p.19).
On this view, the ego and the grandiose Self remain a conjugate pair.
Comparatively, according to the Jungian view, the ego remains distinct from the
Self, which is a time-transcendent goal for personality. There is a sense of the
Self as an inner, guiding centre whose energies can manifest symbolically. Jung
maintains that when this healthy condition no longer applies, and the ego gets
assimilated to the Self, a mystical, dreamlike state ensues. The subject feels he
is immersed in a space-time continuum that is characteristic of the unconscious
as such. Secondly, the Self may become assimilated to the ego. This also results
in inflation, as the world of collective consciousness is overvalued (cf. Jung,
1979, par.45-47). Studies of narcissistic pathology have shown that, in many a
case, there is a pendulum movement between the two conditions.
Theorists of primary narcissism postulate a variable bond between ego and Self
(which are regarded as essentially the same). Erich Neumann introduces the
ego-Self axis (see below), symbolic of an umbilical cord between ego and Self.
In case of a static bond, the ego would become assimilated to the Self, or vice
versa, which in either case leads to severe pathological consequences. Against
this, Jung s picture of the relation is like a planet circulating around the sun. The
relation is best portrayed by a movement of circumambulation , and not by a
static link, because the Jungian Self is not stationary. It is not a person with a
fixed personality and therefore cannot uphold such a relation. Since it is
kaleidoscopic it can only be grasped by circulating around it. This is reminiscent
of Iamblichus s view, who said that the soul s ideal form was spherical, and it
must be moved circularly. Shaw says:
To move in a circle was to embrace at once the contraries of
embodied life, and the translation of the theurgist to his aetheric
body was manifest by his symptoms in the generated world: the
apatheia [equanimity] and ataraxia [tranquility] of a sage whose will
revealed the will of the gods. (Shaw, p.92)
Jungian psychologist Erich Neumann (1905 1960), who drew on Freud,
translates primary narcissism to uroboric incest and claims that adults have a
tendency to revert to the primal condition. The movement in the other direction
(ego-formation) is termed centroversion . Thus, it is obsolete Freudian thought
that underlies Neumann s notion of an ego-Self axis, and the movement to-andfro. This is essentially the same as all the other theories who view primary
narcissism and ego-Self fusion as central. Neumann employs the term uroboric
Self for the prenatal grandiose Self.
The image of an ego-Self axis is relevant to Winnicott s and Kohut s theories,
which elevate narcissism as normal and where normalcy and narcissistic
personality disorder (NPD) are merely the extremes along the ego-Self axis . Yet,
in normal psychology there is no attachment between Self and ego. The Self is
sensed and intuited and we circulate around it like the earth around the sun. The
relation is like in ancient times, when people made offerings and did prayer to
their god. It is an attitude characterized by humbleness. The notion of a constant
and permuting relation between ego and Self is preposterous (and even
sacrilegious). The ego-Self axis has also been appropriated by Jungian
psychologist Edward F. Edinger (see also: Winther, 1999, here).
Neumann s notion conflicts with the Jungian and Neoplatonic view of the Self.
The ego-Self is portrayed as one system with two poles, which elongates and
contracts. Since the ego is seen as an offshoot of the Self, the two will always
remain connected . As a consequence, the ego experiences itself as numinous .
Neumann emphasizes that the ego and the Self are not essentially different from
each other. What s more, unlike Jung who speaks of an ego complex, Neumann
distinguishes between mere ego as a false experience and the ego-Self as a
true experience (cf. Kron, 2013; vid. Neumann, 1989).
In order to accommodate his notions within Jungian theory, it necessitates that
Neumann throws out the whole Jungian edifice and introduces something akin to
quantum field theory. The partition conscious-unconscious is not central
anymore. Instead reality consists of three different fields . The ego is no longer
viewed as a complex and the Self has lost its status as archetype it is a field.
Self and ego are melded in a relation lacking mediating function ( tertium non
datur no third is given).
In my view, it is a great strength that Jungian psychology maintains its roots in
the Platonic and animistic worldview. At least some of the root system is planted
in the age-old soil. It is of great value that theory speaks the same language as
the unconscious, which entertains naive notions. It means that Jungian theory
speaks partly in images, as does the unconscious. Neumann s abstract
conception, on the other hand, lacks all poetic sense. Allegedly, he builds on
phenomenological idealism as well as the existentialism of Martin Buber (in my
regard, a wholly incomprehensible author). To this is added the obsolete
Freudian notion of primary narcissism as central driving force.
Neumann s theoretical edifice is a strange and abstract construct for which he
received harsh criticism at the Psychological Club in Zurich. M-L von Franz has
refuted his Amor and Psyche , since it is really about the anima of the author
and not about female psychology. Somewhat surprising for a Jungian, he hails
Sigmund Freud as the greatest psychologist ever. In his books The Great
Mother and The Origins and History of Consciousness his strange notions are
hidden behind a discussion around the ego s attachment to the Mother in infantile
psychology.
Later, he reveals that the Mother is really the Self, to which the ego always
remains attached. Neumann s analysis suffers from the fact that he views the
mythic struggling heroes as egos , that is, real persons. In fact, they are really
archetypes that attempt to escape from the unconscious Mother in order to
take root in the conscious world (which is similar to the Neoplatonic
interpretation). In The Interpretation of Fairy Tales (1996), M-L von Franz has
criticized the personalistic method of interpretation practiced by Neumann and
certain other Jungians.
Michael Fordham (1905 1995) says that the child, from the very beginning, is
psychologically its own individual. The Self is a totality present at birth, that is,
the child has a preformed personality. Fordham s model of infant psychology
builds on Freud s notion of primary narcissism. The child is regarded
psychologically as a self-contained individual, rather than being at one with the
mother. It means that the small child can be treated as a unit separate from its
parents. From a primary narcissistic condition (libidinal self-investment in
myself ) individuation proceeds in the way of deintegration and
reintegration (a dynamic that is characteristically neurotic). Fordham has also
repudiated the notion of the Self as an archetype (cf. Jacoby, 1991, p.55ff).
In Fordham s model, the ego must deintegrate from the Self in order to come
into being. From a classic standpoint, it would actually mean that the child must
leave its unity with God (the Self is symbolic of the divine) to inaugurate ego
development a bizarre notion. It gives rise to the characteristic narcissistic
dynamic I mentioned earlier, namely deintegration and reintegration along an
ego-Self axis. It is a pathological model, essentially the same as used by
Winnicott, Edinger, and Neumann.
Fordham s reintegration (libidinal self-investment) corresponds to Neumann s
term uroboric incest whereas his deintegration (ego-formation) corresponds to
Neumann s centroversion . Fordham appropriates the term primary Self for the
uterine condition of personality (the uroboric Self in Neumann). Says Jacoby:
In his view infants give every observer a feeling for which the
expression narcissism is very appropriate. He (the infant) seems
self-contained, self-centered or somehow whole and, one might say,
in love with himself (Fordham, 1976:50). But for a variety of
reasons Fordham prefers the idea of a primary self to the concept of
primary narcissism. (ibid. p.55)
So let s look at how Fordham arrives at his conclusions. Jacoby explains that
Fordham sees the feeding situation as a disturbance of the babies unity and
that this represents the principle of deintegration . Says Jacoby:
Once the infant s need for food, body contact, and warmth has been
gratified, the process of reintegration resumes; the infant becomes
once again content, self-contained, and slowly goes back to sleep.
This is a simple example of those processes in which parts
deintegrate from the self and then reintegrate with it once again [...]
Hence deintegration makes possible the life experience that serves
the purposes of differentiation and maturation; this experience is
then reintegrated into the self. Deintegration and reintegration are
thus the basis of maturational processes that are organized in the
self. (ibid. pp.55-56)
So Fordham has extrapolated the instinctual functions of feeding and sleeping
and given it central status, namely that of psychological life characteristic of
adulthood. He claims that this repeated pattern of deintegration and
reintegration is the same as individuation. What s more, Fordham projects a
narcissistic form of self-contentment on the toddler.
Needless to say, such theoretical cerebration around fundamental instinct is
completely unfounded. He certainly hasn t asked the child if it is in love with
himself ; he only says that it seems so. This phenomenon, in psychological
parlance, is known as projection .
Neurotic science
I question if such chockingly inferior theory could be produced by a healthy mind,
even of the lowest intellectual capacity. I hold that such superficial thought can
only be produced by the neurotic personality. A normal person would feel
ashamed of saying such things. The incapacity of questioning themselves, on the
other hand, is characteristic for the neurotic personality with a narcissistic bent.
Nevertheless, such people always gather a great following, which is a
phenomenon that ought to be better analyzed. The neurotics is one thing, but
what about their following? It is not only the branch of psychology that suffers
corruptive consequences. It affects the whole of society. Technical projects often
run aground on account of a neurotic individual whose contributions cannot be
questioned. So why can t people speak up against inferior thinking and corrupted
individuals? Somebody ought to analyze the phenomenon of the elephant in the
room that nobody pretends to see.
We should also take note of the fact that Fordham s clinical experience and his
case studies of children had no rectifying effect whatsoever on the theoretical
work he was doing. It did not bring him closer to the truth. There is a
misconception in the psychotherapeutic community about how science is made.
It is seen as a way of making observations that shall serve as basis for
hyperbolic induction. It bears a similarity to the method of Aristotle (disregarding
his cerebral advantage).
Fordham had observed children with his own eyes, a fact that he prided himself
on while he believed that he was doing science proper. But it s evident that he
had no grasp of empirical science and what it stood for. The following example is
Fordham s version of doing science. He relates a case of a 2-1/2-year-old girl
who was sitting on his lap drawing a picture:
The earlier scribbles had been aggressive, and I had concluded that
her apparent acquiescence had been under secret protest; it was
only when the circle appeared, however, that her ego could express
itself in action. It seemed to represent the statement that my power
had become neutralized and that there was now a magical boundary
between herself and me which made her position safe; no aggression
from me was now possible [...] for the child must have seen me as a
danger I would not have pressed her to scribble had she not
acquiesced. The danger was due to a projection of soul , in this
case the father imago. (Fordham, 1957, p.135)
It is surprising what Fordham can see in the soul of the child, as if she were an
open book. But this is just an anecdotal event that lacks scientific value. His
interpretation is a mere projection and those scribbles could be interpreted in
many different ways. He chooses, not surprisingly, to interpret the circle in terms
of deintegration . The mandala shape has thus acquired a wholly different
meaning than in Jungian psychology and in religious tradition. It could just as
well mean that she has repossessed her calm. It could mean anything.
Such observations have no scientific value at all. There is a misconception among
psychotherapists about how science is produced. Just making observations about
patients doesn t produce theory around psychic laws. The theory of gravity
wasn t produced by gathering scientific data about how apples and pears fall to
the ground. Experimental physicists do not produce theory they only try and
verify theories. If they make new findings, they generally leave it to the theorists
to work it out. We cannot develop new theory in the way clinicians tend to do,
making both erratic and far-reaching conclusions from a set of case studies.
The way in which psychoanalysts have misconstrued empirical science has had a
very damaging effect. There is a strange misconception that empirical scientific
research implies making observations that will automatically produce scientific
results, as if it suffices to gather experimental data and theory will grow out of it
like a tree. It doesn t work that way. This view is strengthened by Erich Fromm
(1982). He has observed that many psychologists expect that theories will
develop out of the activity of collecting empirical facts. He says that this view of
science is very primitive and is long ago abandoned among the hard sciences.
Ego development
Children do not emerge out of feelings of omnipotence. If they had been identical
with the Self, they would have had the consciousness of Jesus Christ and had
made the most wondrous statements. But they don t they say silly and naive
things. Babies, as soon as they emerge, are very relational. Their attitude is not
at all narcissistic, because they are very much into the interplay of I and you .
In fact, the ego emerges out of the unconscious earth, like a plant that grows.
There is no ready-made complete personality in the image of God Almighty from
the beginning. Ego-development transpires much like the story of Narcissus: the
archetype enters the realm of consciousness and becomes self-aware. It takes
root in consciousness as a function of the ego. Should any of the Greek muses
suffer the same tragic fate, then the subject is destined to become a musician or
poet.
It depends on both environmental and innate factors. The synthetic function of
consciousness ensures that the acquired functions are experienced as belonging
to me . Should we have a ready-made personality from the beginning, then it
leaves no room for environmental influence or chance. We cannot become either
a musician or an intellectual. Yet, we know that a great variety of minor gods can
land in reality, especially if a certain development is stimulated in the child.
The ego is that which happens to take root in consciousness. Yet, Fordham gets it
backwards: consciousness takes root in innate personality (the primary Self) by
way of a process of deintegration. I hold that it is wholly implausible and depends
on a projection onto the child of a neurotic state of affairs.
The Self in the ego-Self axis is not the real Self; it is a false copy known as the
grandiose-exhibitionistic self. Characteristic of the narcissistic personality is a
strong sense of entitlement. They believe they are entitled to everything good in
life. It is a form of severe egocentrism coupled with a controlled form of
megalomania. Of course, people who suffer from an egoic obsession, or any form
of obsession, is at times overtaken with an urge to get rid of their problem in one
stroke, especially if they have failed in their grandiose endeavour. At least, they
might drench themselves in alcohol and get rid of themselves temporarily.
Evidently, many theorists have substituted the grandiose-exhibitionistic self for
the Jungian definition of Self. What is behind this development? Presumably, they
have identified their own experience of grandiosity with Jung s notion of Self.
Aha, this is what Jung means by the Self! Yet, normal and well-balanced people
do not experience an egocidal urge. Nor do they experience a feeling of
grandiosity or of being the centre of the universe. The edifices of Winnicott,
Neumann, Kohut, Fordham and Edinger, lack relevance to normal psychology,
but are characteristic of the neurotic psyche.
The experience of the true Self is quite different it is transcendental and
detached. It is the sense of wholeness that can be experienced in nature the
same that St John of the Cross experienced when he sat in deep contemplation
listening to the purling brook. It is the feeling of oneness with the whole of
existence when time stands still a feeling that can be conjured by focusing and
writing about the divine presence.
There is nothing threatening about this presence it is like floating in a tropical
sea. However, it is also a presence that may trip the subject up sometimes,
because it demands more attention. Especially in dreams the call of the Self is
heard. The normal personality lacks that instability of moving to-and-fro between
deintegration and reintegration with the Self . There is no identification at all.
There is only a longing for the Elysian fields .
The classic Jungian edifice better approximates normal psychology. However, I
have argued that it is deficient since it is missing the transcendental
part St John s view of Self. Is it the personality experiencing stability and a
spiritual contentment with life (despite life s hardships) that shall serve as
theoretical model for normality? Or is it the people who experience grandiosity
and then give way to self-laceration in a repeated pattern? The neurotic theorist
elevates his own pattern as characteristic of normalcy. The reason for its
notoriety is that scholars who reach prominence are often driven by worldly
ambition, which is generative of the neurotic pattern. Comparatively, the normal
person is moderately detached from the worldly.
It is high time to get rid of the neurotic ideal of personality, because it is evil.
Therapists who subscribe to the destructive and regenerative ideal become
vassals of evil. Winnicott argued that the patient needed to be destroyed in
order to invoke the symbiotic and destructive cycle in the patient. As a
consequence, many of them committed suicide.
The Self as archetype
The Self is the wholeness to which the ego gravitates after midlife, when the Self
becomes the ideal of the ego. The Self is the goal of personality, but it is not the
origin. Yet, Jung has contradicted himself by saying: The self, like the
unconscious, is an a priori existent out of which the ego evolves. It is, so to
speak, an unconscious prefiguration of the ego (Jung, 1969, par.391).
It seems that this notion turns Jungian theory upside-down. A possible
explanation for this statement is Jung s theological temperament . Since the
Lord says that he is alpha and omega (Revelations), Jung must also say so about
the Self. Thus, since Jung s Self is wholly immanent and psychic, the alpha
would also be immanent. Yet, in the Christian and Neoplatonic conception, the
alpha would represent the transcendental wholeness and unity (the One) that
precedes cosmic creation. It is in all respects beyond being . In order to repair
the Jungian conception of Self, which is one-sidedly immanent, we may reinstate
the transcendental aspect of Self as complementary.
It would forestall misconceptions such as an immanent alpha Self . The Self as
unconscious prefiguration of the ego gives the impression that the ego emerges
out of the Self, which cannot be right. In that case, little children have an egoic
power far surpassing that of adults, since the adult ego crumbles in face of the
Self.
Central to Jungian theory is that archetypes constellate from an organizing
principle that initially lies dormant. The Self has typically constellated by midlife
whereas the anima (archetype of the feminine) constellates earlier. Neoplatonism
had a similar notion of organizing principles or reason-principles, called logoi or
logoi spermatikoi (cf. Remes, p.57). These were essentially instantiations in the
soul of Platonic Forms, including the mathematical objects. Shaw says:
[The divine symbols ] remained inactive until awakened in theurgy.
Thus, when the logoi that constitute the soul s essence were ritually
appropriated and awakened in the life of the soul, these logoi could
then be called sumbôla or sunthêmata. (Shaw, p.165)
So here is a notion similar to the constellation of the archetype from the
archetype-as-such. The notion of a pre-constellated Self, out of which the ego
emerges, doesn t make sense. How is that supposed to occur? Such a notion
doesn t square with a biological worldview. For what purpose has evolution
equipped babies with a complete personality that is manifest already from the
beginning? Nor could Jung have meant that the Self is the archetypal seed from
which the ego constellates. It would imply that the ego and the Self are the same
thing, which contradicts the definition of the Self.
According to the scientific worldview, everything emerges from the unconscious
earth, which is essentially mathematical relations. There is no image of an oak
inside an acorn. There is a molecular program for growth that gives rise to an
oak, i.e., from which the oak slowly constellates.
In a similar manner, the individual termite is programmed to do his little job,
which is easily defined. It consists of a few instructions (in case of this do
that ). That s all he knows. He isn t aware of any greater structures.
Nevertheless, the combined actions of the termites give rise to a remarkable
complexity in the form of a termite mound. The phenomenon is called swarm
intelligence .
The termites divide labour among castes, which all have their own little
responsibilities. The cooperative effect is such that it gives rise to remarkable
sophistication. Human engineers have studied the sophisticated air-conditioning
system in termite mounds, which involves an underground spiral cone that leads
cold air upwards. It is suitable for implementation in tenement buildings in
warmer climates. Nevertheless, the individual termite isn t aware of such
sophisticated structures.
However, should the termites be capable of mentation, we can be certain that
they would entertain notions of building a temple to God , etc. The conical spiral
(seashell) would have been regarded as numinous. In such case, an archetype
has constellated in their psyche.
Complexity is produced from very simple rules. The Mandelbrot set is produced
by plotting, in the complex plane, an iterative function where C is a complex
number (it means that the new value of z, to the left, is always produced from
the former value of z).
zt+1 = zt² + C
The above function gives rise to images such at these, by zooming in on different
areas:
An endless array of simple rules can be plotted in the complex plane (where the
imaginary value is in units of i, that is, the imaginary number). Another example
of fractal imagery is the Julia set (vid. Gleick, 1987).
This is how all of the remarkable complexity of nature is created from simple
rules (the logoi of nature). It is easy to see that the fractal images are relevant
to the theory of archetypal constellation. As far as we know, nothing is preconstellated in nature. In biology, the theory of preformationism (the
homunculus theory, etc.) is obsolete. We have no need for notions of
preformationism in psychology, because modern complexity theory has shown
that advanced structure and sophisticated order may constellate from the
smallest of seeds.
Conclusion
Scholars of antique philosophy have sufficient knowledge about psychology to
make the conclusion that Plotinus resorts to a notion of the unconscious . I have
shown that also their concept of Self accords with a modern Jungian view. The
therapy of the soul was central to Neoplatonism. Unlike its Christian counterpart,
Platonic salvation is primarily a personal matter. There is a commitment to the
psychological as an irreducible explanatory category (Remes, 2008, p.3).
The way in which Porphyry and Iamblichus use the term symbol also coincides
with Jungian use. Proclus takes pains to refute the mimetic and representational
view of art and claims that the highest type of inspired poetry is the symbolic
type. Symbolic poetry has soteriological power and is an inspired vehicle of divine
truth. Material, verbal and literary symbols render invisible entities into visible
form (cf. Struck, 2004, ch.7).
Sometimes the gods are represented as doing impious things. Peter Struck says
that Proclus consistently invokes these infamous scenes as examples of the
poets greatest achievements. They are proofs of their inspired, hyperrational
wisdom (ibid. p.242). Struck explains that [the] symbol is consistently
Proclus s term for that language that defies the prohibition against speaking the
unspeakable (p.244).
Already in this early period, the symbolic unconscious and a sound view of
personality had already taken root. Would that the concept of the Self always
stood on sound Neoplatonic ground! Aren t Jungian psychologists throwing the
golden child out with the bathwater when they refuse to acknowledge the
Neoplatonic connection?
© Mats Winther, 2015 January.
References
Beiser, F. (ed.). (1995). The Early Political Writings of the German Romantics.
Cambridge University Press.
Clarke, E.C. & Dillon, J.M. & Hershbell, J.P. (eds.) (2003) Iamblichus: De
Mysteriis. Society of Biblical Literature. ( On the Mysteries of the Egyptians .)
Fordham, M. (1957). New Developments in Analytical Psychology. Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Franz, M-L von (1996). The Interpretation of Fairy Tales. Shambala.
-----------
(2000). The Problem of the Puer Aeternus. Inner City Books.
Freud, S. (1914). On Narcissism (in The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud.)
Fromm, E. (1982). Greatness and limitations of Freud s thought. London:
Abacus.
Gleick, J. (1987). Chaos - Making a New Science. Viking Penguin Inc. New York.
Hall, T. (1977). En matematisk tragedi. Brombergs.
Hillman, J. (1996). The Soul s Code. Random House.
Hillman, J. & Ventura, M. (1992). We ve had a hundred years of
psychotherapy and the world s getting worse. Harper Collins.
Jacoby, M. (1991). Individuation and Narcissism: The Psychology of Self in Jung
and Kohut. Routledge.
Jung, C.G. (1979). Aion - Researches into the Phenomenology of the Self.
Princeton/Bollingen. (CW 9:2)
------- (1969). Psychology and Religion: West and East. Princeton University
Press. (CW 11)
-------
(1989). Memories, Dreams, Reflections. Vintage.
Kernberg, O. (1975). Borderline Conditions and Pathological Narcissism. Jason
Aronson.
Klancher, J. (ed.). (2009). A Concise Companion to the Romantic Age. Blackwell
Publishing Ltd.
Kron, T. & Wieler, D. (2013). Erich Neumann: A Jungian Dialogical
Existentialist . Israel Institute of Jungian Psychology. (here)
Leeming, D.A. & Madden, K. & Marlan, S. (eds.). (2010). Encyclopedia of
Psychology and Religion. Springer.
Livingston, I. (1997). Arrow of Chaos - Romanticism and Postmodernity.
University of Minnesota Press.
MacKenna, S. & Page, B.S. (transl.) (1930). Plotinus: The Six Enneads. P.L.
Warner, Medici Society. London. (here)
Neumann, E. (1989). The Place of Creation (Vol 3). Princeton/Bollingen.
---------
(1971). Amor and Psyche. Princeton/Bollingen.
---------
(1991). The Great Mother. Princeton/Bollingen.
--------- (1995). The Origins and History of Consciousness.
Princeton/Bollingen.
Plotnitsky, A. (1994). Complementarity - anti-epistemology after Bohr and
Derrida. Duke University Press.
Remes, P. (2008). Neoplatonism. Acumen Publishing Ltd.
Roubiczek, P. (1968). Misinterpretation of Man. Kennikat Press. (1947)
Schwartz-Salant, N. (1982). Narcissism and Character Transformation.
Toronto: Inner City Books.
Shaw, G. (1995). Theurgy and the Soul - The Neoplatonism of Iamblichus. The
Pennsylvania State University Press.
Struck, P.T. (2004). Birth of the Symbol - Ancient Readers at the Limits of Their
Texts. Princeton University Press.
Winther, M. (1999). Edinger - the ego-prophet . (here)
--------- (2003). Winnicott s Dream: A Critique of Winnicott s Thought as a
Form of Mystical Narcissism . (here)
---------
(2011). The Complementarian Self . (here)
---------
(2014). Complementation in Psychology . (here)