Pessoa Heteronymic Machine
Pessoa Heteronymic Machine
Pessoa Heteronymic Machine
Adam Morris
Com uma tal falta de literatura, como h hoje, que pode um homem de
gnio fazer seno converter-se, ele s, em uma literatura?
Fernando Pessoa1
as when they list him among writers they call half -philosophers but also
much more than philosophers:
There is such force in those unhinged works of Hlderlin, Kleist, Rimbaud,
Mallarm, Kafka, Michaux, Pessoa, Artaud, and many English and American
novelists, from Melville to Lawrence or Miller, in which the reader discovers
admiringly that they have written the novel of Spinozism. To be sure, they do
not produce a synthesis of art and philosophy. They branch out and do not
stop branching out. They are hybrid geniuses who neither erase nor cover
over differences in kind, but on the contrary, use all the resources of their
athleticism to install themselves within this very difference, like acrobats
torn apart in a perpetual show of strength. (What is Philosophy?67)
What seems like a near-miss between Pessoa and Deleuze and Guattari is
attributable less to the philosophers disinterest than to historical contingen-
cies: Fernando Pessoa died when Deleuze and Guattari were still children,
and Deleuze and Guattari developed their revolutionary philosophy of rhi-
zomatics and schizoanalysis2 in the 1970s, years before much of Pessoas volu-
minous writings were finally edited, published, and translated.
My objective here is to offer a reading of Pessoa not as a philosopher, but
as a philosophical thinker. This reading is based less on Pessoas poetry than
on the sprawling system in and for which it was produced: a system I call
the heteronymic machine. Of course, there have always been thinkers who
evoked rhizomatic design, as Deleuze and Guattari point out. My objective
is not simply to defend Pessoas position on their list, but rather to show the
strong resonance between two conceptual projects. The ingenious system
that Pessoa conceived to disseminate (and not contain) his thought articu-
lates the philosophical move later described in different terms by Deleuze and
Guattari, most extensively in A Thousand Plateaus. And so although poems
like Ode Triunfal by heteronym lvaro de Campos have led to Pessoas
poetic reputation as a Portuguese analog of the British and Irish modernisms
that influenced him, we can also regard Pessoas literary machineand the
confusion of identities and ontological genesis3 that attends itas one of the
first stirrings of what is today considered postmodern thought.4
Viewed in the light of theories developed after his death, Pessoa (1888
1935) indeed appears a curious anachronism. At times his descriptions of
heteronymity resemble a post-Deleuzo-guattarian schizoid manifesto, as
when he writes, O que sentimos somente o que sentimos. O que pensamos
somente o que pensamos. Porm o que, sentido ou pensado, novamente
pensamos como outrem isso que se transmuta naturalmente em arte, e,
esfriando, atinge forma (Teoria 235). Pessoas 25,000 manuscripts and ap-
proximately eighty heteronyms were his way of pursuing this art. The urge to
consider and reconsider perceptions as experienced by the other, including
128 Luso-Brazilian Review51:2
the impossible exercise of imagining the experience and reality of the schizo-
phrenic, also lies at the core of the Deleuzo-guattarian strain of postmodern
theory. Though some critics find it convenient to resort to Deleuzo-guattarian
concepts to explain certain elements of heteronymity, few take the trouble
of identifying the specific ways in which Pessoa realizes the schizoanalytic
project of creating a rhizome and not simply creating-rhizomatically.5 This
is amusing, since it is rather tempting to read Deleuze and Guattaris chapter
on Conceptual Personae in What as Philosophy? as a bit of a rip-off of Pes-
soa: Conceptual personae are the philosophers heteronyms, Deleuze and
Guattari write, and the philosophers name is the simple pseudonym of his
personae (64). This of course will sound familiar to anyone who has studied
Pessoa and his heteronyms. And it is why I suggest that we consider the epis-
temological questions and philosophical concepts raised by Pessoas system
of heteronymity equally as important as his poetic feats.
For Caeiro, this thing that we call Nature lacks oneness, which is merely
a chimera brought on by a disease of our ideas. What Caeiro rejects is the
sort of oneness imputed to nature as a transcendental whole to which all
belongs.8 His oft-quoted line A Natureza partes sem um todo discards the
ontological priority of the One over the Many, a position that is also funda-
mental in Deleuze and Guattaris work.9 Oneness, for Caeiro, is that of a dis-
crete, singular thing (flower, stone), of a haecceity. Though a codified concept
of Nature continues to exist, even for Caeiro (who cannot avoid reifying
the concept even as he rejects it), it is a concept that only exists as the result
of false constructions and diseased ideas. Nature is thus artificial, inor-
ganic, man-made. Bernardo Soares, a semi-heteronym who demonstrates
knowledge of Caeiros work in his own writings, agrees: Ignoro como estes
telhados, he writes, while gazing out the window at rooftops, Falhei, como
a natureza inteira.10 For Soares, the notion of a unified nature is illusory. Jos
Gil cites similar passages to support his claim that Pessoa and Deleuze shared
a goal: to do away with transcendental metaphysics (acabar com a tran-
scendncia metafsica, Diferena,14). Dr. Antnio Mora, the theorist among
the neopagan heteronyms and philosophical follower of Caeiro, expands
Caeiros and Soaress impressions in his attempt to arrive at a pagan response
to dominant metaphysical thinking, one that would rethink human experi-
ence without falling into what Deleuze and Guattari call the illusion of tran-
scendence or the illusion of universals (What Is Philosophy?49), such as
the human construction of a unified transcendental, whether called Nature
or Reality. These errors, Mora writes, result from the anthropomorphizing
tendencies of philosophy: Toda a filosofia um antropomorfismo. O erro
fundamental admitir como real a alma do indivduo, o erigir a conscin-
cia do indivduo em conscincia absoluta e a Realidade em individualidade.
Individuar a Realidadeeis o primeiro grande erro. Individuar a Conscin-
ciaeis o segundo grande erro.11 Direct sensory contact with something, the
neopagan heteronyms believe, is the only way to experience it as real.
This claim distills various ideas posed by the neo-pagan heteronyms, as
well as their contemporaries the Portuguese Sensationists, a poetic move-
ment intimately related to the Pessoan project. According to heteronym and
scholar of Sensationism Thomas Crosse, the Sensationist movement was
begun by Pessoa and his friend Mrio S Carneiro and also included het-
eronym lvaro de Campos. Procedural thought is antithetical to the Sen-
sationist project. As Crosse explains in his Preface to an Anthology of the
Portuguese Sensationsts:
All sensations are good, as long as we dont try to reduce them to action. An
action is a sensation thrown away. Act on the inside, using only the hands of
your spirit to pluck flowers on lifes periphery. Learn not to associate ideas
130 Luso-Brazilian Review51:2
but to break your soul into pieces instead. Learn how to experience sensa-
tions simultaneously, to scatter your spirit through your own scattered self.
(Prose64)
relatively unformed, molecules and particles of all kinds. There are only haec
ceities, affects, subjectless individuations that constitute collective assem-
blages. Nothing develops, but things arrive late or early, and form this or that
assemblage depending on their compositions of speed. Nothing subjectifies,
but haecceities form according to compositions of nonsubjectified powers or
affects. We call this plane, which knows only longitudes and latitudes, speeds
and haecceities, the plane of consistency and composition (as opposed to the
plane of organization or development). It is necessarily a plane of immanence
and univocality. We therefore call it the plane of Nature, although nature has
nothing to do with it, since on this plane there is no distinction between the
natural and the artificial. (A Thousand Plateaus 266)
drawn from each of these orders, so that a book has no sequel nor the world as
its object nor one or several authors as its subject. In short, we think that one
cannot write sufficiently in the name of an outside. The outside has no image,
no signification, no subjectivity. (A Thousand Plateaus23)
tree. This black-box strategy for escaping the anxiety of influence is neces-
sarily non-linear. And this nonlinearity is integral to the Deleuzo-guattarian
variety of post-structuralist thought, writing, and conceptual arrangement:
Schizoanalysis rejects any idea of pretraced destiny, whatever name is given
to itdivine, anagogic, historical, economic, structural, hereditary, or syn-
tagmatic (A Thousand Plateaus13).
Mora overthrows literary genealogy when he dislodges the term pagan
from a teleological linearity:
Mas ns, que somos pagos, no podemos usar um nome que indique que
o somos como modernos, ou que viemos reformar, ou reconstruir o
paganismo dos gregos. Viemos ser pagos. Renasceu em ns, o paganismo.
Mas o paganismo que renasceu em ns o paganismo que sempre houvea
subordinao aos deuses como a justia da Terra para consigo mesma.31
For Reis, paganism is not a concept that follows a historical path of refine-
ment, improvement, or evolution towards a telos. The variations in its reoc-
currences are not for better or worse; its different instantiations are not the
result of evolution, but involution, a process in which evolution does not
go from something less differentiated to something more differentiated, in
which it ceases to be a hereditary filiative evolution, becoming communica-
tive or contagious (A Thousand Plateaus 238).
The sort of self-generation and self-births that Soares describes as his two-
word philosophy is similar to one of Deleuze and Guattaris descriptions of
becoming. Becoming is not an evolution, at least not an evolution by descent
and filiation, Deleuze and Guattari explain (A Thousand Plateaus 238). It is
not a synonym for invention. Nor can it be adequately explained with a bio-
logical metaphor: becoming is a verb with a consistency all its own; it does
not reduce to, or lead back to, appearing, being, equaling, or producing
(A Thousand Plateaus 239). Self-births are as close as Pessoa can get to de-
scribing the process of his becoming-heteronym. Although the analogy is a
crude one, his propagation and peopling of the space of heteronymity is
one that insistently rejects hereditary production. Soaress term for this prop-
agation is perversion. It is an action, as Richard Zeniths translation makes
evident, similar to contagion:
Ah, mas como eu desejaria lanar ao menos numa alma alguma coisa de ve-
neno, de desassossego e de inquietao. Isso consolar-me-ia um pouco da
nulidade de aco em que vivo. Perverter seria o fim da minha vida.38
How Id love to infect at least one soul with some kind of poison, worry or
disquiet! (Disquiet65).
For reasons that should be obvious by this point, I caution against the use of
the word totality, preferring instead the Deleuzo-guattarian term literary
machine.39
never found a physical medium to transmit their full production. Like Caeiro,
who according to Campos was estragado simblicamente pela forma hu-
mana (Notas 161), Pessoa was constrained by the available media. How
ever to give heteronymity a form beyond abstraction that would not short-
change it conceptually? A book is physical and confined in form: There is
no difference between what a book talks about and how it is made, Deleuze
and Guattari assert, a claim that reminds us of the incompatibility between
books and the heteronymic machine (A Thousand Plateaus). A book would
territorialize Pessoas nomadic literary machine; the books three dimensions
are more limiting than the two-dimensional plane of composition. Books
quantify writing, Deleuze and Guattari observe (A Thousand Plateaus4),
and this was never Pessoas objective. Instead of producing books, which are
machines for containing ideas, what Pessoa wrotepoetry, prose, correspon-
dence, fragments, and otherwisewas not written for this type of capture
and consumption. So Pessoa did not publish the vast majority of his writing.
As lvaro de Campos reasons in the case of Antnio Moras unpublished
work, Um sistema filosfico precisa um pouco de prendre date, pois que nele
a substncia consubstancial com a forma; uma obra literria, vivendo como
vive s da forma (no sentido completo) pode ficar indita durante muito
tempo (Notas 167). Deleuze and Guattari make a similar point about phi-
losophy, remarking that philosophical concepts require conceptual personae
to become actualized. They describe conceptual personae as the becoming
or the subject of a philosophy, such as Platos Socrates, Nietzsches Dionysus
and Zarathustra (What Is Philosophy64). Crucially, they make this argument
in Pessoan terms: Conceptual personae are the philosophers heteronyms,
and the philosophers name is the simple pseudonym of his personae (What
is Philosophy 64). But the concept of heteronymity itself required many of
these personae, perhaps too many for Pessoa to corral in his lifetime.
Deleuze and Guattari understood philosophical concepts as centers of
vibrations that are points of condensation of all their component parts
(What Is Philosophy, 2223) that must always be renewed. They suggest that
in some cases, as with the cogito in Descartes, concepts sometimes have very
close predecessors. Everything seems ready, and yet something is missing
(What Is Philosophy?26). Antnio Moras words suggest that Pessoa under-
stood artistic production in the same way: there are some works of genius
that cannot be conveyed in their contemporary moment. Something is miss-
ing. The artists who create these works, conscious of the anachronism of their
genius, must wait. Defiantly unpublished, but patient with the confidence of
her own genius, this artist awaits the state of affairs that will produce just the
right resonance between concepts; she goes in search of the conceptual per-
sona who will do justice to her thought. This is no doubt the case with Pessoa,
whose literary machine was an exercise in endless becoming-heteronym.
144 Luso-Brazilian Review51:2
History allowed Pessoa the cold comfort that men of genius are seldom ap-
preciated in their age: O genio sente antes dos outros homens a direo de
uma sociedade, he wrote, O genio est na sua philosophia emquanto tal e
alli (nas theorias politicas) apenas ha attitude critica (Escritos71). Or as he
wrote in English in one of his other notebooks, Whether the present age
is favourable or not to the detection of genius, is a point to be amply mis-
understood. No age is favourable, in the terms of the case, to the detection
of genius (Escritos 426). True genius, Pessoa believed, is only recognized
historically.
Although something is missing, there are many respects in which Pes-
soa proposes concepts that anticipate Deleuze and Guattari by half a century,
making him more a contemporary of their age than his own. The philosoph-
ical and epistemological intervention of the Deleuzo-guattarian rhizomatic
revolutionthe smashing of linear, teleological methodologies into splin-
tering lines of flight and the rejection of individual subject-based reason in
favor of the schizos shifting multiplicities and flowsis well-articulated in
Pessoas texts. Indeed, Pessoas literary machine supports Jean-Franois Ly-
otards claim that [a] work can become modern only if it is first postmod-
ern (79). Lyotards insight, however, is only useful insofar as it indicates the
limitations of the practice of periodization. Postmodernism thus under-
stood is not modernism at its end but in the nascent state, and this state is
constant, Lyotard continues (79). Deleuze and Guattari might likewise un-
derstand modernism as a plateau, not an epoch with a beginning or an end,
but a becoming-modern that is always au milieu. By identifying resemblances
to poststructuralist heuristics such as the rhizome, the plane of consistency,
macro and micro multiplicities, and other components of schizoanalysis in
Pessoas pre-structuralist writings, we learn that epistemological and aes-
thetic periodization can be a limiting, deceiving practice (as it is hereditary,
unidirectional, one-dimensional). Like Pessoas heteronyms, the tendencies
or symptoms often attributed to postmodernism and post-structuralism do
not fit so nicely into a hereditary framework of tradition, influence, or prog-
ress. Neither does any other exercise in philosophical thought or epistemol-
ogy. As with the constant nascent state of modernism that Lyotard observes,
human thought has always resembled Deleuze and Guattaris plateau: it is
always au milieu, never beginning or ending, and extending in all directions.
Generic divisions are as artificial and misleading as periodizations. Pes-
soa is primarily considered a poet, and secondarily as a prose writer; his work
is not given the philosophical attention it deserves, despite the symmetries
between his poetic project and the philosophical project undertaken by
Deleuze and Guattari.40 Though acknowledged as a feat of literature, his po-
etry and the planning of the heteronymic system also sketch the blueprint for
a philosophical upheaval, to be carried out decades later in the more discrete
Morris 145
Notes
1.The Arquivo Pessoa, a free, online database of Pessoas work, provides citations
to the original published editions of Pessoas work, along with an estimated date [in
brackets] of when the cited piece was written, when available. The Arquivo Pessoa al-
lows researchers without access to a comprehensive bibliography of Pessoas original
sources to consult transcriptions of them online. Though no standard formatting ex-
ists for such citations, I have made an effort to provide that information in this other
end-noted citations to the Arquivo in a manner congruent to the one I use here. Page
numbers in the Arquivo Pessoa refer to the page on which the document cited begins.
Aspectos [1930?]. Arquivo Pessoa. <http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/4233>. Original
source: Fernando Pessoa, Pginas ntimas e de Auto-Interpretao. Ed. Georg Rudolf
Lind and Jacinto do Prado Coelho. Lisboa: tica, 1966. p.95.
2. If I use the terms rhizomatics, schizoanalysis, stratoanalysis, pragmatics,
and micropolitics interchangeably as synonyms for what I am calling Deleuzo-
guattarian theory, it is because Deleuze and Guattari emphasize this in the introduction
to A Thousand Plateaus: RHIZOMATICS = SCHIZOANALYSIS = STRATOANALY-
SIS = PRAGMATICS = MICROPOLITICS. A Thousand Plateaus,22.
3. Deleuze identifies three elements of ontological genesis: persons, individuals,
and the multiplicity of classes and properties that constitute them and are constituted
by them. A passage from The Logic of Sense helps clarify the relation of the question
of ontological genesis to Pessoas genesis of heteronyms: Individuals are infinite an-
alytic propositions. But while they are infinite with respect to what they express, they
are finite with respect to their clear expression, with respect to their corporeal zone
of expression. Persons are finite synthetic propositions: finite with respect to their
definition, indefinite with respect to their application. Individuals and persons are, in
themselves, ontological propositionspersons being grounded on individuals (and
conversely, individuals being grounded by the person), 118.
4. I am preceded in my consideration of Pessoa as a postmodern writer by Pes-
soas prominent translator Richard Zenith, who writes, if Postmodernism implies
personal actions and behaviors born out of its discourse, then even before the word
existed Pessoa was one of its practitioners. Fernando Pessoa & Co.,31. In particular,
Zenith understands Pessoa as precocious deconstructionist (28,33).
5. Jos Gils Fernando Pessoa, ou, La mtaphysique des sensations (1988) and Dif-
erena e negao na poesia de Fernando Pessoa (2000) are notable exceptions, in that
both works go beyond the convenient terminology of the rhizome to explore the
146 Luso-Brazilian Review51:2
similarities between Pessoas project and Deleuzo-guattarian thought. Gils first work
is heavily indebted to Deleuzo-guattarian concepts, but he avoids citing their work,
a strategy that weakens the sort of direct parallels between Pessoas and Deleuze and
Guattaris philosophicaltheoretical positions that Gil goes on to make in the latter
work, where he writes, muitas vezes, o que aparece sob o modo implcito em Pessoa,
ganha contornos explcitos em Deleuze, o que era simples noo no Livro do desas-
sossego, por exemplo, torna-se conceito claro em Mille plateaux (Diferena,9).
6. A theory of multiplicities permeates the entire work. Specifically, refer to the
second plateau, 1914: One or Several Wolves?
7. Fernando Pessoa, O Guardador de Rebanhos. First published in Athena 4
(Jan.1925), Lisbon.
8. Translation borrowed from A Centenary Pessoa, 60. With this reference to dis-
eased ideas we can begin to hear the resonance of Nietzsche in Caeiro. The latters
distrust of philosophers and philosophies is born out of the same scorn for eternal
transcendentals. As Nietzsche writes, All philosophers share this common error:
they proceed from contemporary man and think they can reach their goal through
an analysis of this man. Automatically they think of man as an eternal verity, as
something abiding in the whirlpool, as a sure measure of things. Everything that the
philosopher says about man, however, is at bottom no more than a testimony about
the man of a very limited period. Lack of a historical sense is the original error of all
philosophers.... Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All too Human. Trans. R. J. Holling-
dale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989. pp.1213. Nietzsche, of course, is
also one of the practitioners of so-called nomadic thought that inspired Deleuze and
Guattaris A Thousand Plateaus.
9. Though Deleuze and Guattari make some readers suspicious about the exis-
tence of a transcendental universal or of something resembling Heideggerian Be-
ingsuch as their identification of chaos as the milieu of all milieus (A Thousand
Plateaus, 313)one should not mistake the chaotic milieu of milieus for a transcen-
dental field. As they write, multiplicity escapes the abstract opposition between the
multiple and the one (A Thousand Plateaus32). A useful interpretation of this point
is provided by Manuel de Landa, who further develops the concepts of flat multi-
plicities and relations of interiority and exteriority posed by Deleuze and Guattari in
What Is Philosophy? See De Landas A New Philosophy of Society: Assemblage Theory
and Social Complexity. London: Continuum, 2006.
10. Bernardo Soares Muitos tm definido o homem from O Livro de Desas-
sossego. Arquivo Pessoa. <http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/4531>.
11.Teoria do dualismo [1916?] Arquivo Pessoa. <http://arquivopessoa.net/
textos/2167>. Fernando Pessoa. Textos Filosficos. Vol. I. Ed. Antnio de Pina Coelho.
Lisboa: tica, 1968. p.32.
12. To whom can Caeiro be compared? [1917?] English original. Arquivo Pessoa.
<http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/3088>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa. Pginas
ntimas e de Auto-Interpretao,343.
13. To whom can Caeiro be compared? [1917?] English original. Arquivo Pessoa.
<http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/3088>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa. Pginas
ntimas e de Auto-Interpretao,343.
Morris 147
14. Manuel de Landas book, cited in note9, is also useful for understanding the
distinction between relations of exteriority and relations of interiority in the Deleuzo-
guattarian ontological framework.
15. lvaro de Campos, Passagem das horas [a] [1916], Arquivo Pessoa <http://
arquivopessoa.net/textos/814>. Original source: Passagem das horas, Fernando
Pessoa, lvaro de CamposLivro de Versos. Ed. Teresa Rita Lopes. Lisbon: Estampa,
1993. p.26a.
16.Schizoanalysis, or pragmatics, has no other meaning: Make a rhizome.
Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, 251.
17.[Carta a Adolfo Casais Monteiro20 Jan. 1935.] Arquivo Pessoa. <http://
arquivopessoa.net/textos/3014>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa, Textos de Crtica
e de Interveno. Lisboa: tica, 1980. p.211.
18. Notas para a recordao do meu mestre Caeiro, 169.
19. Notas, 158.
20. Por detrs de todas as variaes permanece Arquivo Pessoa <http://arquivo
pessoa.net/textos/1799>. Original source: Comentrio de Ricardo Reis. Poemas
Completos de Alberto Caeiro. Ed. Teresa Sobral Cunha. Lisboa: Editorial Presena,
1994. p.183.
21. See note3.
22. Uma das conversas mais interessantes, em que entrou o meu mestre Caeiro,
[1931] Arquivo Pessoa. <http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/893>. Pessoa por Conhecer
Textos para um Novo Mapa. Ed. Teresa Rita Lopes. Lisboa: Estampa, 1990. p.373.
23. Uma das conversas mais interessantes, em que entrou o meu mestre Caeiro,
[1931] Arquivo Pessoa. <http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/893>. Pessoa por Conhecer
Textos para um Novo Mapa. Ed. Teresa Rita Lopes. Lisboa: Estampa, 1990. p.373.
24.Plato, Philebus, trans. R. Hackforth; Parmenides, trans. F. M. Cornforth; cited
in Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p.2.
25. In this context, the terms consistency and composition are used with rel-
ative interchangeability: We call this plane, which knows only longitudes and lati-
tudes, speeds and haecceities, the plane of consistency or composition (as opposed to
the plan(e) of organization or development). A Thousand Plateaus, 266.
26. Zenith also observes that by removing himself from himself, Pessoa was able
to make the orthonymalso called Pessoa ele-mesmo or Pessoa himself into in
a certain way the falsest poet of all See Introduction Fernando Pessoa & Co. New
York: Grove Press, 1998. p.27. Pessoa further complicates matters by admitting his
proclivity to falsehood: But since I have consciousness of myself, I have perceived
in myself an inborn tendency to mystification to artistic lying. From The earliest
literary food of my childhood was in the numerous novels... [1906?] Arquivo Pessoa
<http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/2183>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa, Pginas
ntimas e de Auto-Interpretao,11.
27. Elsewhere Deleuze and Guattari call these relations of exteriority. See notes9
and11.
28.[Carta a um editor ingls1916]. Arquivo Pessoa <http://arquivopessoa.
net/textos/1899>. Original source, Fernando Pessoa, Pginas ntimas e de Auto-
Interpretao, 126.
148 Luso-Brazilian Review51:2
29. See Bloom, Agon: Towards a Theory of Revisionism. New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1982.
30. For further analysis on the link between Pessoa and Anglophone poetry, see
Patricia Silva McNeill, Yeats and Pessoa: Parallel Poetic Styles. Oxford: Legenda, 2010.
31. Antnio Mora, from drafts of O Regresso dos Deuses. Arquivo Pessoa. [No
somos, na verdade, neopagos, nem pagos novos1916?] <http://arquivopessoa.
net/textos/871>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa, Pginas ntimas e de Auto-
Interpretao, 286.
32.[Carta a Adolfo Casais Monteiro13 Jan. 1935]. Arquivo Pessoa. <http://
arquivopessoa.net/textos/3007>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa, Escritos ntimos,
Cartas e Pginas Autobiogrficas. Ed. Antnio Quadros. Lisboa: Europa-Amrica,
1986. p.199.
33. PREFCIO(aproveitarparaShakespeare)ArquivoPessoa.<http://arquivopessoa.
net/textos/4435>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa, Pginas ntimas e de Auto-
Interpretao, 27.
34. PREFCIO(aproveitarparaShakespeare)ArquivoPessoa.<http://arquivopessoa.
net/textos/4435>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa, Pginas ntimas e de Auto-
Interpretao,27.
35. Hysteria. Def.1. The Oxford English Dictionary. 2nded. 1989.
36.[Carta a Adolfo Casais Monteiro13 Jan. 1935]. Arquivo Pessoa. <http://
arquivopessoa.net/textos/3007>. Original source: Fernando Pessoa, Escritos ntimos,
Cartas e Pginas Autobiogrficas, 199.
37. Arquivo Pessoa. <http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/388>. Original source: Fer-
nando Pessoa. Livro do Desassossego. Vol. I. Fernando Pessoa. Lisboa: tica, 1982.
p.19.
38. Arquivo Pessoa. <http://arquivopessoa.net/textos/1762>. Original source:
Fernando Pessoa. Livro do Desassossego. Vol.II. Fernando Pessoa. Ed. Teresa Sobral
Cunha. Coimbra: Presena, 1990. p.119.
39. See Deleuze and Guattari, Kafka, p.29.
40. Deleuze and Guattari mention Pessoa directly several times in What Is Phi-
losophy? and also praise the Deleuzo-guattarian reading of Pessoas work conducted
by Jos Gil. See pages67, 167, 197, 22930n5. These references are in addition to the
more oblique, coded influence of Pessoa on their ideas, as evidenced in the quotation
on page64 of What Is Philosophy? in which they define conceptual personae as the
philosophers heteronyms.
Works Cited
Cixous, Hlne. The Laugh of the Medusa. Trans. Keith Cohen and Paula Cohen.
Signs 1 (Summer 1976): 87593. JSTOR. Web. 10August 2010.
Deleuze, Gilles. The Logic of Sense. Trans. Mark Lester with Charles Stivale. Ed. Con-
stantin Boundas. New York: ColumbiaUP, 1990. Print.
Morris 149