Tradition
Tradition
Tradition
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Polish Sociological
Bulletin
by JERZY SZACKI
Social transmission
nation of "tradition" from the latter as in the fact that in the latter
tradition is "dismembered" following an increased division of lalbour
and growing social stratification.7 Hence the sociologist's task should be
not to confirm the otherwise obvious fact that modern societies are in
a sense less "traditional," but to find out what are the peculiarities of
social transmission in societies where literacy is common, division of
labour is far advanced, society is widely differentiated, and modern
mass media are used. It seems necessary to assume that social trans-
mission is equally important in all stable communities, while its mech-
anisms as well appraisals of dependence on "ancestors" may differ
from case to case. This opens a wide field for historical and comparative
study, which has barely been started. Since the programme of such
a study cannot be discussed here in detail, some problems only will be
indicated in this paper.
The first problem, recently taken up in Literacy in Traditional So-
cieties* is connected with the function of writing in social transmission.
Now it seems that the hypothesis could be advanced that the almost
proverbial "traditionalism" of pre-literate communities is conditioned
by the situation in which transmission of cultural heritage to the younger
generation takes place through face-to-face contacts, so that the values
thus transmitted are associated with definite persons and circumstances.
Only that is remembered and preserved which is actually important to
the group, and the whole rest is irreparably forgotten. In literate socie-
ties cultural heritage loses that linear character. The fact that indirect
transmission is possible calls for an incessant interpretation of that
heritage and at the same time accounts for its different interpretations.
Since many transmitted items are accessible at a time, it happens that
they are contradictory with one another, which necessitates selection,
and also gives rise to skepticism. The image of the past ceases to be
coherent, and hence the present cannot imitate the past as such. "The
content of the cultural tradition grows continually, and in so far as it
affects any particular individual he becomes a palimpsest composed of
layers of beliefs and attitudes belonging to different stages in historical
time. So too, eventually, does society at large, since there is a tendency
for each social group to be particularly influenced by systems of ideas
belonging to different periods in the nation's development; both to the
individual, and to the groups constituting society, the past may mean
very different things." 9
This issue is linked with vast research problems. Consider the dif-
ferences between those societies in which literacy is common and those
in which it is restricted to a small élite. Note that the social consequences
of different types of script - e.g., ideographic and phonetic - are
different. Note also that oral transmission retains, to some extent, its
importance in all literate societies. Now still very little is known about
all these problems.
The second problem, to be discussed here by way of example, is that
of social transmission in internally differentiated societies. This fact may
affect social transmission in many ways. First, there are communities
Social heritage
Tradition
82 "Existence in the past" does not imply that if something is older then
it is ¡better. Diistance in time is not significant, although in some cases traditionalists
pay attention to it, too.
88 E. S h ils, "Tradition and Liberty: Autonomy and Interdependence," Ethics,
Vol. LXJVIII, 1958, No. 3 (April), pp. 154-5.
84 Cf. J. R. Gus'field, "Tradition and Modernity: Misplaced Polarities in
the Study of Social Change," The American Journal of Sociology, »Vol. 72, 1967,
No. 4 (January), pp. 351 - 62.
is certainly controversial. Bo
have contributed to the image of tradition as something irrational and
pre-reflective by its very nature. Many thinkers used to imagine tradi-
tion as something which man uses to replace reason. But it can easily
be noticed that tradition frequently happended to be an object of com-
plex intellectual operations. It is a truism to say that for tradition to
develop such operations are not necessary: that "affirmative attachment
to the past," of which Shils says that it may be "vague, unconscious, and
unspoken," is quite sufficient. Yet the question remains open, how the
intellectualization of the indefinite "sense of existence in the past" takes
place and what are its limits. The question seems to be important, since
beginning more or less with the last 18th century the various advocates
of tradition have been trying to present their standpoint as rationally
valid.
We can as it seems, point to two types of intellectualization of tradi-
tion. One of them is described by E. Husserl, who made a distinction
between "passive" and "active" tradition. Passive tradition is a set of
rules of behaviour which, in the opinion of a member of the group, ought
to guide his own behaviour and that of other members solely because
these rules are proper to the group, i.e., without showing any interest
in whether they have any use at all. But members of the group may
also think about tradition and reveal its "intentional sense." By analysing
the origin of a custom we discover the purpose for which a given be-
haviour was originally being used, and hence we "rationalize" tradition.
Habitual behaviour comes to be observed on a principle other than
thoughtless group conformism.35 Intellectualization of tradition in this
case consists in indicating the functions of old patterns, functions other
than the consolidation of the group by the affirmation of the common
heritage. This procedure can often be found in the sphere of social ideas.
But it seems that tradition, when fully justified in this way, ceases to
be tradition, since if the usefulness of patterns drawn from the past is
uncontested, there is no need to refer to their traditional nature. "Ration-
alization" of tradition, interpreted in this way, eliminates it qua tradi-
tion, since it eliminates that peculiar type of valuations which has been
discussed above.
But another method of intellectualization of tradition is possible, too
It has beeh; pointed to by Bert F. Hoselitz, who describes traditional b
haviour as "a class including widely varying forms of behaviour, rang
from the purely automatic, often not meaningfully oriented, behaviou
a highly self-conscious behaviour whose underlying principles are ref
ed upon and the often highly 'rationalized'." 36 His subclasses are: hab
usages, norms, and ideologies. We need not go into the details. We
to note, however, that the basic criteria of "rationalization" of tradit
(which brings it closer to Max Weber's model of Wertrationalität)
the degree of making conscious the acceptation of its precepts and
degree of their systematization. Intellectualization of tradition con
in the emergence of traditionalism as the ideology based on the ac
ance of existence in the past as the supreme value.
35 R. Toulemont, L'essence de la société selon Husserl, Paris 1962, pp.
202 ff.
36 B. F. Hoselitz, "Tradition and Economie Growth." in: R. Braibanti,
J. J. Spengler (ed.), Tradition , Values, and S oc io- Economie Development,
London 1961, p. 84 - 5.
None of the issues listed in the present paper has been properly
elaborated, not to say solved. This was not the task set himself by the
present author. The point was to bring out the basic aspects of the
relation between the present and the past. These aspects are, to a certain
extent, complementary, and the study of "living history" requires taking
all of them into account. It seems, however, that the lack of a clear
distinction between them adversely affects the scholarly study of "the
pressure of the past" and also journalist controversies over tradition.
When studying the issue of social transmission we are concerned with
something else than when analysing social heritage , and with something
else still than when concentrating attention on tradition . Each of these
standpoints imposes a different set of questions and answers, problems
and solutions. For the time being, questions and problems are much
more numerous than answers and solutions.