Eighteenthcentur 0000 Will
Eighteenthcentur 0000 Will
Eighteenthcentur 0000 Will
SfJCTOHlA
VICTORIA. B. C-
VICTORIA C®UOT U*RAM1
VICTORIA. B.C.
THE EIGHTEENTH
CENTURY BACKGROUND
By the same Author
The
Eighteenth Century
Background
Studies on the Idea of Nature
in the Thought of the Period
By
Basil Willey
FELLOW OF PEMBROKE COLLEGE
KING EDWARD VII PROFESSOR OF ENGLISH LITERATURE
IN THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
1950
CHATTO & WINDUS
LONDON
VICTORIA COLLEGE.
L13RAK (
VICTORIA O
iLLEGC
LIBRARY
VICTORIA, B. C.
PUBLISHED BY
Chatto & Windus
LONDON
*
\\ J ) . 1
Preface
IKE its predecessor The Seventeenth Century Background
(1934), this book is the outcome of lectures delivered
1 in the Faculty of English at Cambridge. It is in-
B. W.
Pembroke College, Cambridge,
November 1939.
VI
Contents
Preface ^aie v
2. Butler as Moralist 84
VI ‘NATURE’ IN SATIRE 95
1. Mandeville 95
2. A Note on Swift
• •
100 /
Vll
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
VII DAVID HUME, DEFENDER
OF ‘NATURE’
AGAINST ‘REASON’ Page iio
i. Metaphysics: ‘Nature’ as a Habit of the
Mind
IIO
2 . Ethics: Morality as a Sentiment of the Heart
119
3- Religion: Based on ‘Faith’, not
on ‘Reason’ 126
205
(i) Natura Naturata and Natura
Naturans 205
(ii) Nonconformity and Moral Inculcation
212
(**"*) Political Justice
2I 7
The Twilight
(ivj
of a Doubtful Immortality
2 35
2. Edmund Burke
240
XII ‘NATURE’ IN WORDSWORTH
2
'• The Evolutionary
Phase: the Uneasy Heart
2. A Never-failing Principle of
Joy ^
INDEX
2 95
Vlll
CHAPTER I
HE eighteenth century
—
‘the silver age of the
T —
European Renaissance’ virtually begins in the
final decades of the seventeenth. When we enter
those decades we recognize on all sides the familiar
eighteenth century landmarks, lit by the familiar illumin-
ation of the time. Glory and loveliness may have passed
away, but so also have the fogs and glooms of history
the common daylight which now descends upon a dis-
tracted world may be prosaic, but at least it is steady and
serene, and has not yet become dark with excessive light.
One meets everywhere a sense of relief and escape, relief
from the strain of living in a mysterious universe, and
escape from the ignorance and barbarism of the Gothic
centuries. Nature’s laws had been explained by the New
Philosophy; sanity, culture, and civilization had revived;
and at last, across the vast gulf of the monkish and deluded
past, one could salute the ancients from an eminence per-
haps as lofty as their own. In England there was added to
the general feeling of emancipation from historic spectres
a sense of security from the upheavals of the Civil War
period. ‘We have been so long together bad English-
men’, wrote Dryden in 1668, ‘that we had not leisure to
be good poets’ but now, ‘with the restoration of our hap-
;
A 1
;
2
THE TURN OF THE CENTURY
3
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
and occult explanations of natural phenomena ceased to
satisfy, and the universe came more and more to be re-
garded as the Great Machine, working by rigidly deter-
mined laws of material causation. The supernatural, in
both its divine and its diabolical forms, was banished from
Nature. But, if one may put it so, Satan was banished on
harsher terms than his divine Antagonist! and this brings
us to the second point, namely, that though the new
philo-
sophy was anti-supernaturalist, it was not at first anti-
religious. Most of the great scientists just mentioned
conceived that they had rendered the highest services
to
religion as well as to science, and Descartes,
Boyle, and
Newton, as is well known, were notable theists. As Bacon
had said (and Sir Fhomas More before him), science
was
the study of the works of God, and this should
be almost,
ifnot quite, as pious a pursuit as the study of his
word.
A little learning might be a dangerous
thing, but deeper
draughts of philosophy would bring us back to sober
faith.
This view involved a changed attitude towards Nature
and
natural science; meant that Nature was rescued from
it
danger to profound
these mysteries’, and that God prefers a ‘devout and
4
, :
5
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Secondly, how did the religious conflicts of the sixteenth
and seventeenth centuries lead up to the growth of natural
religion in our period? Briefly, by calling in doubt all
the points of the faith, and reducing them to the level
of
controversy. Christianity, instead of producing Christian
individuals and societies, seemed for so long to have
been
producing disputes, persecutions, and wars, and had, in
the Protestant countries, not only renounced the
Holy See
but split up further into so many sects, that a
desire
arose during the seventeenth century to formulate
a creed
which should be acceptable to all good and reasonable
men. Christianity was based upon Revelation: well
and
good, but what had in been revealed ? No one seemed
facj:
to know, or rather —
which was worse everybody seemed
to know that his own version was
—
the only correct one.
As Anthony Collins complained in his Discourse oj
Free-
thinking the Bible might be divinely inspired,
,
but this had
not prevented its official interpreters from
disagreeing on
all fundamentals; there was hardly in those days one
clergyman that has consider’d and examin’d
things with
care, that believes all the
Thirty-Nine Articles, in their
proper ^and original meaning’. ‘All Faiths have been
shaken writes Charles Blount, ‘but those only
,
which
stand upon the Basis of Common Reason .’ 1
What then ?
Must we abandon religion itself along with the meta-
physical jargon bequeathed by our uncouth
forefathers?
By no means there were ways of escape. The
;
Cambridge
Platomsts, for example, adopted the technique
of setting
religion in a new framework, and changing
the vocabulary
of exhortation. The Platonic and neo-Platonic tradition
was ready at hand to supply them with both.
To platonize
was to avoid the controversial danger-zone;
it was to sug-
gest that salvation did not depend upon
the correct solution
of the credal puzzles. Platonism had after
all been, if not
the Church’s one foundation, at any
rate (as John Smith
observed) the Church’s loving Nurse ’.
‘
tian side. But above all, there was the Grand Alternative,
Nature; that proclaimed its divine Original un-
at least
mistakably. The works of Nature everywhere sufficiently
‘
7
:
1
op. cit., p. 136.
2 La Crise de la Conscience Europdenne (Paris, 1935), vol. ii, p. 93.
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Meanwhile significant confirmatory evidence for natural
religion and natural morality had for some time been pour-
ing in from the accounts of voyagers, both real and im-
aginary, to non-Christian lands in distant parts of the
earth. The noble savage had made an important entry
upon the European stage in the sixteenth century, when
Pigafetta, who voyaged round the world with Magellan,
wrote that the Brazilians followed Nature, wore no clothes,
lived to be 140 years of age, and were free from
the
civilized vices.Montaigne, whose essay Of Cannibals is
best known as the source of Gonzalo’s Utopian
speech
in The Tempest describes therein the conduct
, of three
savages at the court of Charles IX, and declares
that
what he had seen of their manners surpassed ‘all the
pictures with which poets had adorned the golden
age’.
In the seventeenth century a host of travellers
repeated
the same tale. Most remarkable of all, perhaps, not
only merchants and philosophic dreamers, but even
Jesuit missionaries to Paraguay, Brazil, Canada,
China,
and elsewhere agreed to praise the virtues of the unspoilt
natural man, whose physique and whose morals
every-
where, it seemed, put those of Christendom to
shame.
The Utopian method of satirizing or criticizing one’s
own civilization was of course a well-established conven-
tion, and many Utopias appeared during
this time: for
example, Foigny’s Terre Australe Connue(i 6 6 )
j
ing an ideal island in the Southern Seas inhabited
—describ-
by
hermaphroditic deists enjoying perfect liberty and
equality
or La Betique in Fenelon’s Telemaque
(1699). Put
the interesting point is that so many actual
travellers and
missionaries wrote in like fashion. Evidently they
wrote
rather as moralists and satirists than as
anthropologists.
Noting what seemed to be the absence from savage
society
of the characteristic institutions of Europe, especially
pro-
perty, inequality, coercive government
and the Church,
they concluded that the primitives lived in the
Paradise
lost long since for us by Adam.
In any case such ac-
counts provided a safe means of indirectly
attacking the
12
: :
On the whole, this was in fact very much what the age
wanted to believe. For centuries Christian kings and
Christian priests had been spreading the dark blight of
tyranny and superstition over a portion of the world’s sur-
1 Les Relations de Voyages du i y e Siecle et l’ Evolution des ldies (Paris, 1926),
p. 40. I am indebted, for the above references, to this work and to the same
13
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
face: only pass beyond that shadow, and you would find
unspoilt Nature, still apparelled in celestial light. These
generations, especially in France, were anxious to escape
from the tragic glooms of history, and they willingly
adopted the touching belief that la-bas on etait bien. La-bas
,
2. Natural Law
Samuel Pufendorf was the first to occupy a Chair as Pro-
fessor of the Law of Nature and of Nations (at Heidelberg,
c. 1662), but the idea which he
expounded had behind it
a long and venerable history. In antiquity the cry
Follow ‘
14
:
‘Nations and princes may make laws, but they are without the
true character of law if they are not derived from the original
source of law, which existed before the State was established .’ 1
l6
THE TURN OF THE CENTURY
the brave new world could feel that the world was all
1
of Nature
.'’
1 Apology for Heroic Poetry and Poetic Licence (1677), in Ker’s edition of
Dryden’s Essays, vol. i, p. 183. (My italics.)
19
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
what is analogous to the mind and
,
is, therefore, in the highest and
1
best sense of the word, natural .’
1
Discourse VII, pp. 193 and 197 in Roger Fry’s edition. (My italics.)
2
Of the Laiv of Warre and Peace, Eng. trans., London, 1655, First Part,
sect. v.
3
Rapin, op. cit., p. 158. The ensuing quotations are from the same treatise.
20
—
THE TURN OF THE CENTURY
Singular enters to corrupt them’. In this theory the two
meanings of ‘Natural’ (a) what is ‘true’ and (b) what is
‘pleasing’ — are harmonized. We are in j act -pleased by
what is true\ but‘
‘true’ here means the universal, not the
particular. ‘Nature’ for the poet is the idea, the form,
the potentiality which in history, and in ‘fact’, strive to
realize themselves in refractory matter. Art completes
what Nature leaves imperfect; Nature offers a brazen
—
world the poets only deliver a golden. The problem
was that which has exercised poets and critics in all ages,
namely, how to intensify Nature without distorting it;
how to attain the universal without abandoning the parti-
cular; how to ‘subject the shows of things to the desires
of the mind’ without producing chimaeras; how to be
poetical without ceasing to be natural; how to be natural
without becoming mean or insipid. The critics of the
neo-classic age could solve the problem in their own way
because they knew what pleased them, and they surmised
that this corresponded with Nature’s own intentions. A
play, says Dryden, ‘to be like Nature, is to be set above
it’ ;
indeed the representation of Nature,
a serious play ‘is
2 I
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
must be ‘Apt, Clear, Natural, Splendid, and Numerous '; 1
one must be simple, but nobly simple not base, dull, or —
without sinew; one should aim at the grand manner, but
without conceit or extravagance. Decorum is the most
universal of all the Rules.
All this decorum —
this propriety of thoughts and words,
this unity and proportionableness, this mending of Nature
by Nature herself — to what purpose is it? For delight,
certainly, Dryden and others will say; but Rapin’s state-
ment is sufficiently representative:
‘’Tis true, Delight is the end Poetry aims at, but not the prin-
cipal End, as others pretend.
In effect, Poetry being an Art,
ought to be profitable by the quality of its own Nature, and by
the essential Subordination 'that all Arts should have to Polity,
whose end in general is the publick Good. Heroick Poesie
. . .
craindre f 3
’
Fontenelle echoes such writers as Thomas
Sprat, and anticipates Johnson and Wordsworth, in his
opinion that the fabulous’ images of poetry have
now
—
worn very thin -they are ‘extremement usees’, though he
admits that they mettent de dans tout cet umvers’
la vie
this universe which is becoming so mechanical. Nothing
1
Fontenelle, Digression sur les Anciens et les Modernes: Works, vol
’ v’
V
p. 287. (My italics.)
2
ibid., pp. 290-1. (My italics.)
3
Fontenelle, Sur la Poesie en gdndral: Works, vol. iii, p. 195.
24
THE TURN OF THE CENTURY
else exempt from the touch of cold philosophy, and it
is
because it was too fabulous, and cut off (in spite of all that
Perrault and Dryden 3 could urge) from Christian material
because it was too sacred, the poets of the new century
may well seem to have stood shivering in a spiritual east
wind. Boileau is reported to have said that Descartes had
cut the throat of poetry; however, it was only pseudo-
poetry that he helped to destroy. Great new subterranean
forces — political, social, and economic —were indeed to be
required in order to break the glittering surface of the
silver age; but meanwhile, by shifting off the dead weight
26
CHAPTER II
28
THE WISDOM OF GOD IN THE CREATION
whole surface of it, or the whole Exteriour Region, ’tis as a broken
and confus’d heap of bodies, plac’d in no order to one another, nor
with any correspondency or regularity of parts: And such a body
as the Moon appears to us, when ’tis look’d upon with a good
Glass, rude and ragged. They are both in my judgment the
. . .
‘If the Sea had been drawn round the Earth in regular figures
and borders, might have been a great Beauty to our Globe, and
it
And the very idea of the ocean-bed, with all its slimy cir-
cumstance, fills Burnet with disgust; such things must
not be put down to divine omnipotence. ‘Nature doth
not fall into disorder till mankind be first degenerate and
leads the way.’ Occasionally, it is true, Burnet slips into
a mood of admiration even of our lost planet, and he
1 2
ibid., p. 125. ibid., p. 129.
29
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
writes then more in the tone of a Spectator-reverie on the
Sublime or on the ruins of antiquity. Mountains, for
example, move him strongly (and perhaps rather un-
expectedly), and he gives us a passage which Derham
could quote in support of his own very different argument:
30
;
ocean-beds, and the rest the dry land with its fretted coast-
linesand broken surfaces. The blend, in Burnet, of the
theologian and the follower of the ‘new philosophy’, is
well seen in his ingenious way of linking together
the laws
of matter and the decrees of God. How
was the world
ruined? By the operation of natural causes which, one
might suppose, would have produced their result even if
man had retained his first innocence. But the things
1 ibid., p. 249.
32
:
c 33
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
orthodoxy into suspicion, and lost him his Clerkship to
William III. For instance, how does he account for the
diffusion of Noah’s progeny after the Flood ? How was
America peopled from Ararat? Perhaps each continent
had its Noah’s Ark, he replies; we may only have been
apprised by Moses of the particular Ark which concerns
our own part of the world. He is excused by his own
theory from assuming more than one Adam, though he is
ready to surmise that other planets have had their floods,
and so, presumably, their original sins. But the point
which, when later developed in his Archaeologiae Philo-
sophicae (1692), cost him his preferment, is already touched
upon in the Review of the Theory (dated 1690). What
explanation was to be offered to anyone who should object
that, after all, Moses described a terraqueous globe, and
not Burnet’s paradise? Moses, replies Burnet, did not
‘Philosophize or Astronomize in that description’; ‘’tis
a narration suited to the capacity of the people, and not
to the strict and physical nature of things’. Moses must
be interpreted so as not to be ‘repugnant to clear and un-
‘
34
THE WISDOM OF GOD IN THE CREATION
surprising to find that he took orders (1660), though he
resigned them two years later over the question of the
‘Bartholomew’ Act, remaining, however, in lay com-
munion all his life. His Wisdom of God in the Creation ,
35
: —
?
36
—
THE WISDOM OF GOD IN THE CREATION
4
37
:
38
:
39
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Boyle’s own writings and in his life; they are evident,
says Derham,
‘from his constant Deportment in never mentioning the Name of
God without a Pause, and visible Stop in his Discourse; and from
the noble Foundation of his Lectures for the Honour of God, and
the generous Stipend he allowed for the same.’
‘Let us cast our Eyes here and there, let us ransack all the
Globe, let us with the greatest accuracy inspect every Part thereof,
search out the inmost Secrets of any of the Creatures; let us ex-
amine them with all our Gauges, measure them with our nicest
Rules, pry into them with our Microscopes, and most exquisite
Instruments, still we find them to bear Testimony to their in-
finite Workman; and that they exceed all humane Skill so far,
as that the most exquisite Copies and Imitations of the best
Artists, are no other than rude bungling Pieces to them .’ 1
1 ibid.,
p. 38.
40
THE WISDOM OF GOD IN THE CREATION
that ‘whatever Natural, doth by that appear adorned
is
41
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Derham knows enough about these very ends and
purposes.
‘All the Works of the Lord, from the most regarded, admired,
and praised, to the meanest and most slighted, are great and glorious
Works, incomparably contrived, and as admirably made, fitted
up, and placed in the World .’ 1
1 ibid., p. 465.
42
CHAPTER III
Cosmic Toryism
‘
Tous les evenements sont encha'tnes dans le meilleur des
mondes possibles' [Pangloss.]
[Pope.]
But, above
Those superstitious horrors that enslave
The fond sequacious herd, to mystic faith
And blind amazement prone, the enlighten’d few.
Whose godlike minds Philosophy exalts.
The glorious stranger hail .
1
And, elsewhere:
While thus laborious crowds
Ply the tough oar, Philosophy directs
The ruling helm ... 2
2
1
Summer, 1 . 1710. ibid., 1. 1776.
45
:
1
Spectator, 381. 2 387.
46
COSMIC TORYISM
In that case, might seem, we need no longer foster any
it
angels; one man and one monkey than two men, and so
on. The realization of a ‘full’ universe is the greatest of
all ‘goods’.
1
On the topic of the next few pages see Prof. A. O. Lovejoy’s admirable
work The Great Chain of Being (Harvard, 1936), to which I am here much
indebted.
47
, :
If we
don’t like the rank or position assigned to us, we
must console ourselves by reflecting that there would be
a gap in the chain without us, and that, after all, we are
fairly high up in the scale of creation, having all the
animals below us, and probably only the conjectural angels
or ‘superior beings’ between us and God. Man may be
unhappily unique, ‘plac’d on this isthmus of a middle
state’ between animal and angel, but this uniqueness is
due, not to the Fall or to Satan, but to the requirements
of plenitude.
Eighteenth century optimism was thus not essentially
a joyous or hopeful creed, though it may well have suited
the complacent and the shallow. It was in essence an
apologia for the status quo, presenting you with a God
who loved abundance and variety better than happiness
or progress, and a universe whose ‘goodness’ consisted in
its containing the greatest possible range of phenomena,
48
:
COSMIC TORYISM
As Leslie Stephen has remarked, in an age of shallow
optimism the deeper natures are apt to be pessimists, and
Johnson, who though
not a profound thinker had deep
convictions, had been taught by hard experience that
human life is a.state in which there is little to be enjoyed,
and much to be endured. Even Voltaire, who in dealing
with Pascal seems an optimist, reacted into pessimism
when confronted with the philosophy of Dr Pangloss, and
Candide teaches much the same moral as Rasselas. I give
here, by way of illustration, an outline of some of Jenyns’s
arguments, together with a few extracts from Johnson’s
review.
Speaking of ‘evil’ in general, Jenyns maintains at the
outset that all evils owe their existence to ‘the necessity
of their own natures ’
Pain, poverty, toil, and the rest, Jenyns argues, are merely
instances in our own sphere of the imperfection inhering in
all created things, of which he has already demonstrated
5°
COSMIC TORYISM
Tories, to ‘entail irreversible poverty upon generation
after generation’? But Jenyns has no misgivings; the
‘world’ (meaning eighteenth century society?) could not
subsist without poverty, though of course by charity we
m ay — —
and indeed must try to mitigate the evils ‘now
and then pinching a few’. ‘We are therefore little en-
lightened’, Johnson concludes, ‘by a writer who tells us,
that any being in the state of man must suffer what man
suffers, when the only question that requires to be resolved
T
is, \\ hy any being is in this state?’
We now come most notorious passage in the
to the
book, the passage on which Johnson poured his choicest
scorn. Jenyns professes to be persuaded
and that,
1
op. at., pp. 67-8.
51
,
—
who enjoy the universal happiness it is for their pleasure
that man agonizes. Do not our own pleasures depend
upon the sufferings of other creatures ? Are not empires
and flourishing cities founded upon slavery and degrada-
tion ? Must not the pheasant or the deer yield up their
lives to furnish us with sport, and the pleasures of the
banquet ?
*
Man one link of that vast chain, descending by insensible
is
52
COSMIC TORYISM
vindicate the ways of God to man : that themore you de-
monstrate the rightness of whatever is, the more desperate,
because the more inescapable, the plight of man appears.
Johnson, who looked to literature not for explanations of
the riddle of existence, but for moral and religious support,
was roused to satire by Jenyns’s theory:
‘
Many
a merry bout have these frolick beings at the vicissi-
tudes of an ague, and good sport it is to see a man tumble with
an epilepsy, and revive and tumble again, and all this he knows
not why. As they are wiser and more powerful than we, they
have more exquisite diversions, for we have no way of procuring
any sport so brisk and so lasting, as the paroxysms of the gout and
stone, which undoubtedly must make high mirth, especially if the
play be a little diversified with the blunders and puzzles of the
blind and deaf.’
‘
Many of the books which now croud the world, may be j ustly
suspected to be written for the sake of some invisible order of
beings, for surely they are of no use to any of the corporeal in-
habitants of the world. The only end of writing, is to enable the
readers better to enjoy life , or better to endure it: and how will
either of those be putmore in our power by him who tells us, that
we are puppets, of which some creature not much wiser than our-
1
selves manages the wires ?’
53
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
be another justification for moral evil: natural evil once
admitted, some men ‘must’ be created bad enough to
deserve it!
54
COSMIC TORYISM
can long stand their ground; for it is with old establish-
ments as with old houses, their deformities are commonly
their support, and these can never be removed without
endangering the whole fabric’. These considerations
apply also to Christianity, which (without derogation !)
lacks authenticity and perspicuity, and is subject, like all
other human institutions, secular or religious, to corrup-
tion. The deists, like the political reformers, are intel-
lectually right in their criticisms, but practically wrong in
their conclusions. They are wrong in thinking that the
really divine religion would be perfectly plain and ration-
ally convincing. No
such religion is possible, and we
must therefore not pretend that Christianity is such. The
argument somewhat resembles Butler’s in the Analogy ,
‘All our effort ends in belief, that for the Evils of life there is
some good reason, and in confession, that the reason cannot be
found. This is all that has been produced by the revival of
Chrysippus’s untractableness of matter, and the Arabian scale of
existence.’
I
CHAPTER IV
Natural Morality
I. SHAFTESBURY (1671-1713)
signalized him
the precursor of the
as Rousseauist ‘
62
NATURAL MORALITY —SHAFTESBURY
‘ [Theories] Ye Fields and Woods, my Refuge from the toil-
2
1
Works, vol. ii (1727 ed.), pp. 344-5. ibid., vol. ii, p. 370.
63
,, ,
1
ibid., vol. ii, pp. 393-4. 2
Letter Concerning Enthusiasm
(1708).
64
:
This would only prove that there were certain Powers cap-
able of producing these effects, not that they were wise or
foolish, good or bad Powers. ‘Power can never serve as
a Proof for Goodness and Goodness is the only Pledg of
;
‘good’, and—
in opposition to the view of Hobbes
naturally social. Shaftesbury faces up to Hobbes with
the gestures of one who is so confident of victory that he
need do little more than sport with his opponent. How
shall we most effectively deal with so ‘Gothick’
a philo-
sopher? Not, assuredly, by holding up hands in horror:
If we fall presently into Horrors, and Consternation, upon
the
hearing Maxims which are thought poisonous we are in
, no dis-
position to use that familiar and easy Part of Reason, which is the
best Antidote .’ 2
1
Works, vol. i, p. 358.
2 Essay on the Freedom of Wit and Humour: Works, vol. i,
p. 91.
67
:
69
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
occasion, in the course of these studies, to remark upon
the ambiguities arising from these two leading senses of
‘Nature’.
1
Works, vol. ii, p. 31.
70
—
NATURAL MORALITY SHAFTESBURY
which is to ‘secure a right application of the Affections’.
But we are not truly virtuous unless feeling coincides with
reason; reluctant or merely dutiful well-doing is not
genuine virtue. He Moral Sense as ‘a real
defines the
Affection or Love towards Equity and Right for its own ,
71
:
72
NATURAL MORALITY —SHAFTESBURY
nature not only ‘morose, rancorous and malignant’, but
is
74
;
75
CHAPTER V
Natural Morality
(continued)
grounds
‘
Others had established the historical and prophetical
that sure testimony of its truth
of the Christian Religion , and
which is found in its perfect adaptation to the heart of
Man .It
Constitution
was reserved for him to develope its Analogy to the
in the
and Course of Nature; and laying his strong foundations
another and irre-
depth of that great argument there to construct
subservient to Faith ,
fragable proof: thus rendering Philosophy
andfinding in outward and visible things the type and
evidence of
why God was wise to include it in his plan. But his dis-
tinction is that he looks it more directly in the face, and
with a more disillusioned eye, than the optimists of the
time.
Butler’s method of argument depended upon the fact
(for us highly significant) that he could assume, as a matter
of almost universal consent, the existence of a divine Author
of Nature. It was here that one stood on firm ground in
the early eighteenth century: the natural evidences for
the Divine Original were, as we have seen, felt to be over-
whelming; it was ‘Revelation’ which had to be sub-
stantiated by analogy. The deists found God in Nature
and in the heart of man, but denied Revelation. If God
had really revealed himself in the Hebrew Scriptures, they
argued, he would not have left us in any doubt or per-
plexity; we should find none of the historical, textual, and
which in fact we do find there, and
spiritual difficulties
the God so revealed would correspond with our highest
spiritual and moral conceptions, which, however, is not
always actually the case. To all thisButler replies that
there are just as many difficulties in proving God from the
constitution and course of Nature as there are in accepting
Revelation, and they are difficulties of the same kind. If,
then, in spite of these difficulties, we admit the sufficiency
of the natural evidence, may we not learn to expect ana-
logous difficulties in the sphere of revealed religion, and
to accept them with as good a grace ? For how does God
in fact operate in Nature, and in the moral government of
78
NATURAL MORALITY — BUTLER
the world? It is not Butler’s concern to demonstrate the
wisdom of God in the Creation, after the manner of Ray or
Derham; it is enough for him Nature is
to reaffirm that
an organized whole, working according to general laws
without regard to particular persons or things (so that,
e -g-> gravitation will not cease if you should
happen to step
over a cliff). Natural evils’ of course result from
such a
system, yet the system is admitted to be of divine
work-
manship. And how of the moral government of the world
?
Experience teaches that God’s method of moral govern-
ment does not always correspond with human expectations
or desires. We might, for instance, have
supposed that a
Creator as omnipotent as he is benevolent would only
have
created beings entirely happy, virtuous, and safe
from all
physical and moral harm, whereas we know that
men are
not so created. (We are not certain, however,
that either
happiness or virtue would exist in such circumstances.)
Evil is often used by God for his own inscrutable
pur-
poses; God
works, not directly, but indirectly, always
using subordinate means and agents, and these are
often
disagreeable to us. This, whether we like it or
not, is the
actual state of affairs, and Butler does not
defend it with
any glib assurance. He merely intimates that,
on the
analogy of what we observe in the ‘scheme of
the natural
world’, ‘the things objected to may be, upon
the whole,
friendly and assistant to virtue, and productive
of an over-
balance of happiness ’. 1 But Butler is quite certain, how-
ever, that we can see enough evidences of a moral govern-
ment to be assured that God
governing the world
is
righteously. The
weightiest evidence is to be found in
our own conscience: we know, that is, that
‘upon the
whole ’, virtue produces happiness and vice misery.
There
is enough evidence
for this to justify us in regarding
happi-
ness as the reward bestowed upon us for right
conduct,
and misery as the punishment for vice. In spite
of many
appearances to the contrary, therefore, it is
possible to
hold that all may very well be for the best, or at
least that
1
Analogy, ch. vii, sect. ii.
79
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
there nothing ridiculous in so thinking. In thus stress-
is
BUTLER AS MORALIST
Butler’s ethical writings have been spoken of with uni-
form respect by all the historians of ethics I have met with.
He is regarded, by most, as the greatest English moralist
of the eighteenth century. In the middle of the nine-
teenth century, as we learn from Whewell, Butler’s Fifteen
NATURAL MORALITY — BUTLER
Sermons and particularly the Three Sermons on Human
,
to a careful examination.
and sub- —
it In Butler’s deistical and
1 3
op. cit., p. 83. Preface to Three Sermons , 3rd ed.,
1855, p v
: \
‘plainly bears upon it marks of authority over all the rest, and
claims the absolute direction of them all, to allow or forbid their
gratification.’ 2
86
NATURAL MORALITY — BUTLER
We are therefore not acting according to our nature if we
allow no more weight to this principle than to the various
impulses —
it we allow first one and then another to deter-
after his own time represented the evil principle for all
orthodox moralists —which consists in regarding the whole
of human life as ‘one continued exercise of self-love’.
Butler distinguishes two grades of ‘selfishness’ (i) Cool
:
But of course Butler does not accept the analysis of all our
actions into some form of self-love. Human nature, for
him, is as clearly ordered for public as for private good.
There is a ‘natural principle of benevolence in man’,
which has the same relation to society as self-love has to
the individual. At this point Butler seems to resume
common ground with Shaftesbury, or even with Mande-
ville: the social and the self-affections, he agrees, are so
intimately connected, that we cannot procure self-satis-
faction without having some benevolence, and conversely
self-love is the great security for our correct social be-
haviour. Even our passions, those which are neither
benevolent nor self-loving, have de facto (as Mandeville
had said) a tendency to promote both public and private
—
good such is the wisdom with which Providence has
designed the universe. Man is naturally united to his
fellows, and the same principles which would lead him to
injure society lead also to self-injury. The frantic pursuit
of riches and power and honour (the current travesty of
‘self-interested’ action) demonstrably and admittedly fails
to lead to happiness. The fact is that men are commonly
as lacking in reasonable or ‘cool’ self-love as they are in
88
?
89
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
‘Nature’. The facthe sees, that ‘Nature’ is used in
is,
the
different senses. In one sense our ‘Nature’ implies
in another
notion of ‘that which is a law unto itself ;
It is not this
sense, we are by Nature’ children of wrath.
‘
90
—
NATURAL MORALITY — BUTLER
Christian as Bishop Butler, to ground
their case firmly
upon Nature, before appealing to Revelation!),
man is
demonstrably not a creature of the moment,
left by his
Maker to act at random. And if it be asked: even
if the
moral law be thus written upon our
hearts, what obligation
is there to obey it? Butler answers
(relying implicitly on
the numinous quality of the idea
of Nature) Your obliga-
:
‘
91
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
sure, or from the motives of even though an
self-love,
he writes,
‘have, I think, expressed themselves in a manner, which may
occasion some danger to careless readers, of imagining the whole
of virtue to consist in singly aiming, according to the best of their
judgment, at promoting the happiness of mankind in the present
state; and the whole of vice, in doing what they
foresee, or
94
CHAPTER VI
r 9
Nature in Satire
MANDEVILLE
WO chief views about
T the moral order of the uni-
verse are to be found in the
(often held simultaneously by the
one, that the world is a system
eighteenth century
same thinkers):
which automatically works
together for good, and the other, that
in order to secure
good results we must make good efforts. Associated with
the first of these, as we have seen, is the view
that there is
a natural identity of interest between
the individual and
society (self-love and social are the
same), so that each man
in following his own interest js in fact thereby
promoting
that of the whole. This view, as we see particularly in
_
is with
an even better place without any vice at all, than it
into good.
vice being constantly turned, by divine alchemy,
Mandeville alone had the audacity to declare that the
re-
vices.
existed not in spite of, but because of, the private
In the Fable itself, which is a short satire in
Hudibrastic
verse, Society is as a Bee-hive.
shown This hive is pros-
perous and great as long as pride, selfishness, coiruption,
luxury, hypocrisy, fraud, injustice, and every
conceivable
rid the
vice are freely practised. One day, however, Jove
bawling Hive of fraud’, with what result? Trade and the
professions languished, unemployment and depopulation
set in, and the few surviving bees deserted their
hive for a
hollow tree, where they took up their abode, Blest with
Content and Honesty’. The moral, as Mandeville draws
it, is:
Then Fools only strive
leave complaints:
To make a Great an Honest Hive.
T’enjoy the World’s Conveniences,
Be famed in War, yet live in Ease,
Without great Vices, is a vain ,
In Splendor.
G
97
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
‘virtue of
but don’t us pretend that this is due to any
let
of virtue prevents
ours. Similarly, Mandeville’s definition
Io any
him from adopting the utilitarian standpoint,
liberal utilitarian who demands how any conduct which
Mandeville replies
benefits society can be called ‘vice’,
the consequences o
that virtue is to be judged, not by
motives are aimos
actions, but by their motives , and human
invariably impure. This is not to deny,
°f course, that it
is these very ‘consequences that interest Mande\i e, ^or
motives can and do
his whole argument is that impure
produce beneficial results. If we should enquire further,
public good.
how can private vices work together for
manner,
Mandeville will refer us, in quite the approved
to the Divine Wisdom:
render the unsearchable depth of the Divine
Wis-
‘nothing can
had
dom more conspicuous, than that Man, whom Providence
designed for Society, should not only by his
own Frailties and
Happiness, but
Imperfections be led into the Road to Temporal
likewise receive, from a seeming Necessity
of Natural Causes, a
to be
Tincture of that Knowledge, in which he was afterwards
1
by the True Religion, to his Eternal Welfare .’
made perfect
1
ibid., vol.
2 T. S. Eliot, Lancelot Andre<wes, pp. 62-4.
i, p. 57-
98
NATURE IN SATIRE — MANDEVILLE
advantageous Some have supposed that his satire drove
“ J*
°PP° slte direction
cendental
; that he was exposing the trans-
notion of virtue that he ostensibly
accepts, by
revealing its astronomical 1
remoteness Perhaps .
we may
uggest that his aim (it was certainly the outcome of his
work) was to show
the incompatibility between
traditional
:andard s and actual ways of living,
°L the
.? and that he dis-
,
lked
;|
cant of virtue more than the
reality of vice— that
r h n sh °rt. there lived more faith
,
in honest vice than
f° ‘l'>‘
““f i ts
li 6
!
moral weeds. One may add
he was also prepared at times
that like other
to use the loftiest
moral ideals purely as a standard
of satirical reference, and
without implicating himself with
them. His main plea
and herein lies such moral strength
honesty and realism; like
as he has was* for
Machiavelli, he thought we
—
should learn more by looking at
what men are than by en-
larging upon what they should
be. Here we are, honour-
g n Set Fmciples and acting upon another: what
Hto k° i
be done? f
Recognize and accept the facts, and
is
don’t
imagine you are practising virtue
when you are really only
following the promptings of your
egoism, and when the
real practice of virtue (however
admirable in the sight of
heaven) would lead to such
inconvenient consequfnces.
Mandeville belongs to our story only
because he shared
the eighteenth century belief
in Nature— because he
be-
lieved that is to say, that you
had only to accept, to let
natural causes produce their natural
effects, in order to
arrive at a very tolerable state
of affairs. To get a eood
7 U £d 0n y g ° ° n be ng aS Wicked
as you >ike.
’
TWmS, H
ut Mandevillem stands
! ,
queerly poised between several
flicting schools of thought; he
con-
is not of pure
eighteenth
century extraction. Remove his
‘Hobbist’ or ‘cynical'
view of human nature and you get an
eighteenth century
laissez-faire liberal. Remove his
complacent acceptance
of the splendid hive, and you get
a misanthrope or an
austere Christian moralist. As it is, he remains an ob-
stinate amalgam, irreducible to any
simple formula, though
1
Cf. Kaye’s Introduction op.
, cit., vol. i, p. xlix.
99
«
A NOTE ON SWIFT
moral
traditional
‘
To show the incompatibility between
phrase used a few
standards and actual ways of living’ (the
lines above)— this is of course the
general aim and end ot
Satire, and it cannot escape notice
that the age we are con-
a E ge
vicTO
u% r ary''
y cron a coll lg
\ \
LJ Bin ARY
;
102
‘nature* IN SATIRE —SWIFT
where he advises the Romans, all in a body, to leave their city, and
seek a new seat in some remote part of
the world, by way of cure
for the corruption of their manners .’ 1
1
Argument Against Abolishing Christianity {ad init).
103
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
bury all in universal darkness, and the few friends of
Nature and of civilization must be continually vigilant in
their defence. The crooked designs of statesmen, the
subtleties of divines and lawyers, the follies of
projectors
IO4
NATURE IN SATIRE SWIFT
Persia, Mars, etc., and to give us, through his artless com-
ments, a glimpse of how we
look to the eyes of first
innocence Or the satirist may prefer simply to depict a
Utopia where all is rationally
ordered, and leave us to
make the required application to actuality.
Swift occasion-
ally drops into the
Utopian method, as in the passage
where he tells us that the Lilliputians,
in choosing public
ofhcers^had more regard to good
morals than to great
a ilities , since Providence
^
never intended to make the
management of Public affairs a mystery,
to be compre-
nded only by a few persons of sublime
genius, of which
there seldom are three born
in an age; but they suppose
truth, justice, temperance,
and the like, to be in every
man s power .1 Swift adds, it is true,
that in describing
these and other Utopian
regulations in Lilliput he ‘would
on y be understood to mean the
original institutions, and
not the most scandalous
corruptions into which these
people are fallen by the degenerate
nature of man’. He
is thinking here of
their political corruptions, for,
as Sir
Charles Firth has pointed out, ‘as
soon as Swift turns to
describe the politics of Lilliput it
ceases to be Utopia and
ecomes ngland itself, instead of being an
example to
Lngland .It is consoling to our
national pride to re-
member, in this connexion, that the greatest
French satirist
of the eighteenth century found
in the same England a
norm of Nature and Reason whereby to
measure the aber-
rations of the ancten regime in
France. It would doubtless
v
g
,°T
g t0° h n t0 su Sgest that Voltaire’s Letters on the
„
English Nation (better known in
the French version as
Genres Fhdosofhtques are an example
) of the Utopian
method of satire; Voltaire’s clear sight
did not overlook
the many deviations from reason
on this side of the Channel
as well and we find them duly
noted—as in his remarks
on Shakespeare, and on the English
temperament (its sus-
ceptibility to the effects of an east
wind). But England
seemed sufficiently Utopian in 1726-9 to serve his^pre-
sent purpose. It was a convenient method of
1
attacking
Gulliver, bk. i, ch. 6. * Essays Historical and Literary (x 93 8) .
p 2I
IO5
:
to describe
convenient means of attacking scholasticism
the rise of English philosophy from
Bacon to its culmina-
of philosophers,
tion in that most modern and reasonable
Mr Locke, and to enlarge upon the triumphs of the scien-
tific method in Newton’s work.
Similarly he; could con-
impressed
was present at Newton’s funeral, and was deeply
paid to men ot
by this, and by other signs of the honour
served many
genius in England. China, as is well known,
writers of this period as a symbol of
Nature and Reason,
also; but
and it is made use of in this way by Voltaire
that for once
readers of Swift may be gratified to find
since England
Voltaire had no occasion to appeal to China,
was closer to hand.
Whatever technique the satirist uses (there are many
gradations of irony, in Swift, for instance, which
I am not
to strip the object
to examine here ), his effort is always
x
near.
so he must decline
to understand all and explain
all. Satire is by nature non-
constructive, since to construct
effectively— to educate, for
example, to reform, or to evangelize
actual situations and actual
—
one must study
persons in their historical set
ing, and thiskind of study destroys the satiric
approach.
This is not to say that satire is not
or has not been
often amost valuable weapon for the moralist.
pardon I have spoken of means the
the When
toleration of avoid-
able evil, satire has an important
function. But ‘pardon’
is not the only or the
inevitable attitude engendered
by a
7
historical study of persons and institutions
; one may if
one is a moralist, an educator, an apostle
or a revolutionary
desire to alter and amend things
after having explained
them. Satire seems to occur somewhere
between accept-
ance and revolution, and it is not
surprising, if this is so,
that the early eighteenth century
should have been its most
Letters on the English Nation
2
(17V1), p. io
Gulliver, bk. ii, ch. 7.
107
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
high and palmy time. Swift himself, for all his discontent
his satire,
(divine or pathological), was no revolutionary ;
to standards which
as we have suggested, always refers
with-
existready-made, and which would become operative
out need for subversive change, if only
men would not
standards, how-
perversely depart from them. To these
ever, Yahoo man will not adhere, and
Swift seems at last
to throw up the sponge —
to abandon hope of ever lessen-
actual. Instead,
ing the disparity between the ideal and the
reason, and
he barricades himself within his ivory tower of
there ‘enjoys’ the bitter satisfaction of
knowing himself
world, or, at
the only wise being in an insane or bestial
(Pope or
most, of sharing, with a few kindred spirits
Arbuthnot), his own consciousness of superiority.
Other
satirists — Cervantes, Fielding, Dickens —have been known
to fall in lovewith their abstractions, and Don Quixote,
full-formed
Joseph Andrews, and Pickwick have emerged
and
from the satiric shadow-world. But Swift fell more
more out of love with man, and the result his final tragedy
was the total dissociation of Houyhnhnm from Yahoo.
symbolize
So remote became his ideal that he could not
his disembodied rationals as men at all, but
only as horses.
Man delighted him not, no, nor woman neither, so lie
108
‘nature’ in satire
feding which unanalysable.
is Burke announced that
politics ought to be adapted, not to human reason, but
to human nature, of which
reason is but a part, and that by
no means the greatest part’. Wesley and Whitefield
range
the world, converting their ten
thousands, not by rational
ethical suasion, but by impassioned appeals to the heart.
hen we reach this phase satire declines, and ceases
to be
the normal reaction of representative
minds to existence.
It survives mainly in minds
(jane Austen, Byron, Peacock,
bamuel Butler, Anatole France) which retain an
affinity
with the early eighteenth century.
109
,
CHAPTER VII
David Hume
*
D only because he is
if the fine flower of the English
(or shall we say the Anglo-Scottish) eighteenth
century mind, but more specifically (since the present
volume does not pretend to be a history of eighteenth
century thought) because he can be represented as the
defender of Nature against Reason.
Hume is usually, and rightly, regarded as the arch-
sceptic who overturned the philosophic card-castle erected
by Descartes and his successors. He did, indeed, destroy
all traditional certainties matter, the soul, God, Nature,
:
DAVID HUME
century) there can be no
question ; it is enough to say that
e writes philosophy with
an exquisite decorum which
pu s us a to shame. As for the
1
‘indispensability’ of the
eighteenth century, it may be said
that that century repre-
sented a necessary stage or
climacteric in the life-cycle of
es ern civilization, so that
a
country like Russia can be
diagnosed by a modern historian as
one that has never had
an eighteenth century. It was
‘indispensable’ as a period
in which the dry light of reason was free to
penetrate to
the furthest limits of the
universe, scattering the yellow-
skirted fays and all the last
enchantments of the Middle
Ages. It was perhaps not least indispensable as a time
w en, as in Hume,
the illumination became dark
with
excessive light, and reason was
used to reveal the limita-
10 ns of reason. Before Hume: empiricism and sensa-
ona ism a ter him, the Copernican revolution of ‘
’
constructive
side, and it is this that am
mainly concerned to em-
I
phasize. Hume desired,
not merely to destroy the flimsy
superstructures of pure reason,
but also to show (in
Halevy s words) that it is a good thing
to trust to instinct,
t0 NatUre> With0Ut bein du ed
lo°|cd musion’T S P * “7
I 12
DAVID HUME
S’ m
A correct Sr CUSt ° haS rendered too familiar
to it.
'™*f » wXugh
;££;s?
“
?=«ii n
”““ S o^c^Iati^ToTK
^
sembUc
5
°' der
C0nt 'S mt y ln Ti ™
’
or Place, and Cause
Effecl and
^
S
found
fou^d'::
From
nd ° f ATTR
to have
h
0N
as extraordinary 4 ^^2* >
world v^ll be
effects as in the natural.’ 2
Substances. Here I
li fe’
illonly quote a few characteristic
substance for example, we
pronouncements Of
have no idea ‘dis“ from
that of a collection of
particular qualities’; and
idea of a substance Te & ‘crnlH ’l again
~~ ‘the >
d J aS Wel1 n
L g as that of a mode
i
Te
Le.g.
P- heantv’l
beauty ] Jo
‘
f u'-
is nothing ? '
happen-
can we know Things-in-Themselves ? or what is
ing when we suppose that we do ? Hume replies,
‘Let us fix our attention out of ourselves as
much as possible:
let us chace our imagination to
the heavens, or to the utmost
limits of the universe; we never really
advance a step beyond
existence, but those per-
ourselves, nor can conceive any kind of
compass. This is
ceptions, which have appear’d in that narrow
of the imagination, nor have we any idea but
what is
the universe
3
there produc’d.’
DAVID HUME
1S lllusi ° n fiction > poetry,
or faith ? As Carr
>
r^r? /^
3 6
^
01'^ "
8 Le ' bniz > <the order in ^ich we
hmgS T1USt h ave its reason in an ord
1
eXt! Kb V
” tk reals re P res ented 1
!
er which ,
’
the r M representing ’
; W
l
en We are merel y constructing private
worldTi H UmC s ans er
!"
the S^
virtual]*
existence of
h
h
f an
1
?
63
mpUgn the common-sense belief in the
eternal order— indeed, no one
'
.
does not in
t0
Ycomrnon~
,
sen se’. He
to be
in 1, y tHan he
believed
He mcrel >' denies that this
bel efTs fn ded T -
£
t
r SOn ’ an< that reason alone can
account
c .
t n?°r.
. !
'
?
Belief , he says, ‘is more
properly an act
f
e S 1V e
and onr K r f
o? radonal H
n °f
u6
C0 S itative part of our natures’,
° f Nature though not capable
^ >
0nStrat 0
?’
15
P racdcall 7 valid because it
arises from1 ‘T
rises ?mn
!
the principles of human
nature’. But the
WCen rUC d falS6 ideaa remains sub- ’
‘ ’
lectivl^it
jective. it consists, Vhe tells ,f us, in
the ‘superior force or
r '
d7edT‘t°
eS
-’ ° r S
^-T
dea “ Slmpl
dinC1S 2 ° f the tme ; deas.
’in-
idea having these character-
T“
stics, to h
fstks r
believe ‘ >;
is simply to
feel this ‘vivacity’. Belief
s .omething felt by the mind, which
distinguishes the
deas of the judgment from the
fictions of the imagina-
Sented different from a fictitious
idea’— d tb
p
® s an
invoking end on t. Hume is here
the f
famous Principles of Constant Conjunction,
,
constant
nothing has happened save that a feeling of their
conjunction has been set up in our minds.
‘All ideas are deriv’d from, and represent,
impressions. We
never have any impression, that contains any
power or efficacy
[e.g.‘power’ of fire to burn, or of a magnet to attract].
We
never therefore have any idea of power. ...
‘The several instances of resembling conjunctions leads us into
instances are in them-
the notion of power and necessity. These
selves totally distinct from each other, and
have no union but in
3
the mind, which observes them, and collects
their ideas.’
I l6
DAVID HUME
th SenSitiVe ’ than of the c
nature/x M °g itative part of our
.
He means > presumably, that this customary
connexion in our minds, though
it may refer to no cor-
responding external order, is
yet as important for us as if
dlC a d at a man ° f correct
r ^ u ^
regard the vivacity of his
judgment may therefore
‘beliefs' as a reliable index that
hey are just representations
of Nature (or, if we prefer
°
py
SO he
’
?y
m
exc sabl give the name of
V y ‘Nature’
to that, pattern of vivacious
ideas which he shares with
^reasonable mdivid Is )' Hume can pose as
sceptic because it is not human f an anti-
reason that primarily con-
cerns him, but human nature—
of which reason is but a
part, and perhaps not the
greatest part. What custom
has
no man P ut sunder; and Hume
antled!%
,
1
ibid., bk. i, pt. iv, sect. i.
”7
8
1 1
DAVID HUME
and ridiculous
7 that he can hardly find
it in his heart to
enter into them any further.
Indeed, there is no particular
reason why Hume or anybody
else should philosophize,
un ess they feel a serious
good-humour’d disposition’ to
ao so. We
ought to preserve a ‘careless disposition’
in
our studies; and Hume
goes to the length of prescribing
this attitude as the cure
for sceptical doubt:
1
ibid., bk. i, pt. iv, sect. 7. 2
ibid., bk. i,.pt. iv,
3 sect. 2.
op. cit., p. 10.
I 19
.
120
DAVID HUME
bit f ° Ur ° Wn S n0W he
’ reduces morality to
s^ntimllf
sentiment. R°
Reason ?
is not the source of moral judgments
° f belief ; k is kerned w
‘
affLTV*
affairs and affirmations
'th states of
of; ‘is’ or ‘is not’, and no contem-
plation of a state of affairs
as such is a moral judgment
Such a judgment only occurs
when a sentiment of approval
or disapproval is aroused, or
in other words, when
pleasure
n 3 £ P roduced We know
^f*
•
j
-
nothing but our own
minds and hearts; what can we reason
but from what we
know? In ethics therefore, the
proper method is to en-
6 SUb8tan Ce of men s moral ’
, judgments, and
sTe what ihp
aCt com ose d of. His conclusion
briefly Ts
annrrLti
h
approbation and disapprobation.
^P
c om Posed of the
,
sentiments of
‘This is good’ means
sion’
|S
In
PP y
is bad me a nT Th
a
rde V ^
S dlsa
is
!
object of estfem’; ‘This
PP roved of; this arouses aver-
° dlscover the na ture of the
se",,:
J’ I r
the bad , therefore, we
have not to embark upon any
‘good’ and
kctical enqmnes; we have dia-
only to collect statistics,
method was so simple that nothing, The
have prevented mankind from
Hume believed, could
hitting upon it long before
except theological and ’
metaphysical presuppositions.
r
[
> that hen
u Pronounce any action
y°
rtuous or]7vicious, you
or character to be
mean nothing, but that from the
stitution of your nature con
you have a feeling or sentiment
proval or] blame from the of raD -
contemplation of it. Vice and
fferefore, may be compar’d virtue
to sounds, colours,
heat and cold’
which’ according to modern
philosophy, are not qualities
ijects but perceptions in
in the mind: And
this discovery in
morals, like tnat other in physics,
is to be regarded
as a consider-
able advancement of the
speculative sciences] tho’
like that too
'
Y
real, 01
htt,e or influence on practice.
concern us more, than our own
Nothing
sentimentsof pleasure or
be mo r
’
in
uneasiness; and if these be
favourable to virtue, andinfavour-
able to vice, no more can be requisite to the regulation of o
conduct and behaviour ’ i our
I 2 I
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
regarded his Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals
his writings.
(1751) as ‘incomparably the best’ of all
Perhaps this was because his solution satisfied his deepest
instincts, which were also those of his time and of his class.
‘This is good’ means ‘This is approved’, but approved —
by whom ? The fact that Hume does not feel called upon
to raise and answer this question indicates how complete
was his acceptance of current values. He is aware, indeed,
and races have approved different things,
that different ages
but for his purpose it is sufficient to make a catalogue of
the qualities approved and condemned by his own age
and social group. The moral judgments of this group, he
evidently feels, are sufficiently representative to be taken
as those of average humanity. It is worth noting that in
1 No. xxm.
2 He allows, however, that the taste for moral beauty, as for aesthetic, may
be cultivated. ( Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals , sect, i.)
122
,
DAVID HUME
ei” phasis
n ‘approbation’ and ‘esteem’ is
htghly characteristic, ? both of himself and of his
age—
be
Sf’S
L
tile
1
j
e shou d
was also the age of Lord Chef fer-
P lease excite the approbation of
,
,
’
—
t he hei ht °f
for hk
& Chesterfield’s ambition
' m
And s lar ly with Hume, we hear little
'
,
,
about
«/ftnnr
^//-approval, or of the morality of living
|
SLctt't a -iT.
l ‘
T h7
v,Vf ue
Ura 0
™!
"i.
1S definition one which gives
pleasure to
Se "? e ° f those who contemplate
it. Your
may be described as ‘my approval
of you’- mv
virtue ,s ‘your approval
of me’/ file's moral world if
and nt< r 0Ck ed SyS em ° f mUtUal
‘
admiration and
°cLm very ilike
criiticism— [ the
k
society’ of
. -
Chesterfield’s Letters.
j-‘
ee n observes, ‘respectability’, the virtue of
* „ .
12 3
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
e.g., insuch matters as unwise alms-giving, tyrannicide,
etc.). ‘Justice', again, derives its merit solely from its
usefulness as the foundation and support of society; this
can be shown by imagining either a Golden Age in which
every possible human need was satisfied, or a state of war
or extreme destitution —
in both of which justice would be
useless, and therefore no longer a virtue. This truth is so ‘
1
Hume refers here in a footnote to Hobbes, who, he says, was not the first
so to depict it, for Plato has tried to refute ‘an hypothesis very like it in the
2nd, 3rd arid 4th books de republica,’ while Cicero (in one passage at least)
assumes it to be universally acknowledged. ( Enquiry , sect, iii, pt. 1.)
124
DAVID HUME
mediaeval or seventeenth century religious
frenzy, and
they could be confidently dismissed,
together with every-
t Gothic, as destructive to that power and
authority,
and that due subordination of class to
class, on which the
social order depends.
Now since
on account of their ‘utility’ that we
it is
approve of the above-mentioned virtues,
‘utility’ itself
must please us. Why is this? must be
It either from
considerations of self-interest, or from
more generous or
a truistic motives; and Hume’s
opinion is that our ap-
probation of the useful extends beyond
ourselves, and
includes the interest of others. We
have within us a
natural tendency to sympathize with
the joy or sorrow
of others; we are even pleased
by the virtue of a
magnanimous foe. This principle of human
nature
.accounts in great part, for the origin of
morality’. It
is even the source of our
enjoyment in the theatre, where
we rejoice with the hero in his success, or weep with
hirn in his adversity, while ‘our breasts are affected
with the liveliest resentment against the author of these
calamities’. We experience pain when we hear a person
stutter and, so delicate is our sympathy’, that
y it is
a rule in literary criticism, that a
harsh collocation of
syllables is to be avoided, because of
the pain it would
give to anyone pronouncing it.
Would any man, how-
ever selfish, tread as willingly upon another’s gouty toes,
whom he has no quarrel with, as upon the
"hard flint
and pavement’? Hume elaborates this
argument by
showing that there are many qualities of
which we ap-
prove simply because they are useful or
agreeable to their
possessors, because they conduce to his
happiness, and to
ours only through ‘sympathy’. Such are industry, dis-
cretion, frugality, personal beauty,
‘chearfulness’, mag-
nanimity, tranquillity of mind. Even
poetic talent is a
very considerable merit’ of this type, and
so is delicacy
of taste. Lastly, of course, there are all
the qualities
associated with social success and the
arts of pleasing-
good manners (which restrain our self-love in social
inter-
125
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
course), wit, eloquence, modesty, decency, cleanliness,
and the je ne sais quoi , qui plait.
In conclusion Hume professes to be amazed that it
should be necessary, in so late an age’, to prove by lengthy
‘
amounts to a
proof. Now
miracle is a violation of the laws
‘a
of
^
nature and as ‘a firm and unalterable experience
,
has
established these Jaws’, we are confronted
here with
proof against proof, of which the strongest
must pre-
1
Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding,
sect. x.
127
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
vail’. There must, he continues, be a uniform experi-
ence against
‘every miraculous event, otherwise the event would not merit
that appellation. And as a uniform experience amounts to a
proof, there is here a full and direct proof, from the nature of the
the existence of any miracle; nor can such a proof be
fact, against
destroyed, or the miracle rendered credible, but by an opposite
1
proof, which is superior .’
129
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
the
If read the Pentateuch in any other way than as
we
word of God himself, would the falsehood of such a book
be more miraculous than all the miracles it relates ?
the Christian
‘So that, upon the whole, we may conclude that
Religion not only was at first attended with miracles,
but even at
this day cannot be believed by any reasonable
person without one.
Mere reason is insufficient to convince us of its veracity. And
whoever is moved by Faith to assent to it, is conscious of a con-
principles
tinued miracle in his own person, which subverts all the
believe
of his understanding, and gives him a determination to
.’ 1
what is most contrary to custom and experience
1
Natural History of Religion , Introduction. 2
ibid., sect. i.
131
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
which it was destined. To these he has been long accustomed;
and he beholds them with listlessness and unconcern. He
will
132
,
DAVID HUME
and the century’s awakening of the import-
to a realization
ance of historical explanations. But history has seldom
been without a purpose ’, and the eighteenth century wrote
‘
1
Cf. Hume’s remark: ‘History’s chief use is only to discover the constant
and universal principles of human nature’ (quoted by C. L. Becker, The
Heavenly City of the Eighteenth Century Philosophers pp. 85 ff., q.v.).
2 Essays, pt. i, xxi :
Of National Characters.
r
33
,
134
DAVID HUME
yet ‘the cause or causes of order in the universe probably
bear some remote analogy to human intelligence’. And
what is still more remarkable, Philo adds that ‘the most
natural sentiment which a well-disposed mind will feel’
when confronted with this vague and vestigial theism is
‘a longing desire and expectation, that heaven would be pleased
to dissipate, at least to alleviate this profound ignorance, by afford-
ing some particular revelation to mankind, and making dis-
coveries of the nature, attributes, and operations of the divine
1
object of our faith .’
*35
CHAPTER VIII
136
;
DAVID HARTLEY
near the close of the century. It is Hartley’s distinction
till
137
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Hartley takes as his starting-point certain suggestions
of Newton, Locke, and the Rev. John Gay. Newton fur-
nished him with the doctrine of vibrations Locke and Gay :
‘
I offer this work as the mathematical principles of philosophy,
1
Motte’s (1729) translation, ed. Cajoli (California, 1934).
2 Opticks , bk. iii, pt. 1, qu. 31 (1st ed., 1704; reprint, ed. E. T. Whittaker,
1931).
3 Roger Cotes.
138
DAVID HARTLEY
peripatetics (‘that useless
medley of words’), and to that
of Descartes, whose ‘vortices’ are disproved by the be-
haviour of comets. He then proclaims its religious tend-
ency in the following terms:
1
op. cit., p. xxxii.
r
39
\
I4O
DAVID HARTLEY
We shall see how Hartley combined and elaborated these
suggestions.
The part of the Observations on Man need not
first
detain us long. It consists of an elaborate description
(admittedly conjectural) of the mechanism of sensation,
and may be said to develop, in much greater detail, the
views of Hobbes on this subject. The white medullary
substance of the brain, he says, is ‘the immediate Instru-
ment of Sensation’; it is also the ‘immediate Instrument,
by which Ideas are presented to the Mind: or in other
words, whatever Changes are made in this Substance, cor-
responding Changes are made in our Ideas, and vice versa’
(Propositions I and II). The minute particles of this sub-
stance receive, and can reproduce, vibrations from sensible
objects. ‘Sensory Vibrations, by being often repeated,
beget in the medullary Substance of the Brain, a Dis-
position to diminutive Vibrations, which may also be
called Vibratiuncles and Miniatures, corresponding to
themselves respectively’ (Prop. IX). Further
I42
,
DAVID HARTLEY
doctrine, as expressed by J. S. Mill, is ‘the formation of
all human character by circumstances, through the uni-
1
Autobiography p. 91 (‘World’s Classics’ ed.).
2 3
Hartley, op. cit., pp. 82-3. ibid., vol. ii, p. 245
4 6
ibid., vol. i, p. 82. ibid., vol. i, p. 368.
H3
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
of themselves our minds impress’, and we need only cul-
tivate ‘wise passiveness’ in order to proceed from child-
hood, through youth, to the ‘years that bring the philo-
sophic mind’.
i. We
begin, then, with Sensation, and proceed, by
associating pleasure with ever loftier and wider objects,
until we reach the stage when God is All in All:
We
and our Father one [R.M., 42.] ! ’
1
Observations on Man , vol. i, p. 81.
2 3
1. 1093. Observations on Man vol.
, ii, p. 214
K H5
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
2 . Next after Sensation comes Imagination:
‘The Recurrence of and audible ones,
Ideas, especially visible
in a vivid manner, but without any regard to the
Order observed
in past Facts, is ascribed to the Power of Imagination or Fancy.
fcn*
^1 e ^°P ment as a poet, is an interesting topic
°fl t*
H7
3 ibid< vo ,
p ^
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
must not be made a lifelong pursuit, if only because they
‘come to their Height early in Life, and decline in old
Age ’. 1 If we do not some day sing our Ode to Duty, if
years do not at last bring the philosophic mind, the benign
workings of Association are somehow being hindered.
‘The Pleasures of the Imagination are the next remove above
the sensible ones, and have, in their proper Place and Degree, a
great Efficacy in improving and perfecting our Natures. They
are to Men in the early Part of their adult Age, what Playthings
are to Children; they teach them a love for Regularity, Exact-
ness, Truth, Simplicity; they lead them to the knowledge of
many important Truths relating to themselves, the external
World, and its Author; they habituate to invent, and reason by
Analogy and Induction; and when the social, moral, and re-
ligious Affections begin to be generated in us, we may make a
much quicker Progress towards the Perfection of our Natures by
having a due Stock, and no more than a due Stock, of Knowledge
in natural and artificial Things, of a relish for naturaland artificial
Beauty.’ 2
ship and even devotion are cultivated for the sake of their
‘ ’
Thus all things work together for good under the kindly
superintendence of the laws of Association.
1
ibid., vol. i, pp. 497-8.
l l
5
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
according to Leibnitz. However, this is not supposing Matter to
be endued with Sensation, or any way explaining what the Soul
is; but only taking its Existence and Connexion
2 with the bodily
Organs in the most simple Case, for granted, in order to make
farther Inquiries .’ 1
1 ibid., vol. 2
i, p. 51 1. ibid., vol. i,
p. 504.
3 ibid., vol. i, p. 510.
152
—
DAVID HARTLEY
secure for these laws the attainment of their own end. But
what are we in this proposition ? The theory seems to
me to reintroduce free-will by imputing to us the power
of originating such arrangements, whereas Hartley
has
expressly disallowed any power in us to begin motion.
According to his associationism, we are passive all along
the line; as he has said, the moral sense ‘is’ generated
in
us mechanically. Yet he goes on to describe the trans-
formation of sensuality into spirituality as the great busi-
ness of life: we must not rest content with the pleasures
of the senses or of the imagination we ought never to
;
*
be
’
T
54
s , J
CHAPTER IX
156
HOLBACH’s SrSTEME DE LA NATURE
long lament over man’s perversions of Nature’s holy plan.
How comes it, then, that Nature engenders such ‘un-
natural’ offspring? Or if all is ‘Nature’, and there is
nothing unnatural, our unhappiness -‘natural’ ? The
is all
is heterogeneous in texture.
‘If, by “Nature”, we
understand a mass of dead material,
devoid of all properties and entirely passive, we shall doubtless be
compelled to search outside this Nature for the principle of its
movements. But if by Nature we understand that which it really
is, a whole of which the various parts have various properties,
only because they are not founded upon nature, expediency and
the general utility, but on the passions, caprices and particular
utility of those who govern society .’ 1
1
ibid., vol. i, p. 141. 2 ibid., vol. ii, p. 15.
l6o
HOLBACh’s STSTEME DE LA NATURE
earth. . . . "They are made to hope that if they agree to being
unhappy in this world, they will be happier
in the next .’ 1
by it
1
Christianisme Dfivoilt, quoted by Wickwar, Baron d' Holbach
y 5 ’
n ri0
2
Wickwar, op. cit., p. 127.
L l6l
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
every moment of our lives. Of incomprehensible non-
matter we know just nothing, and we may therefore regard
it as nothing. Movement is as much a necessary attribute
of matter as extension or figure, so why should we seek for
a ‘motor’ outside Nature? For Holbach, the impulse to
seek some supernatural first cause is the last infirmity of
noble mind, and he remarks that even the great, the im-
mortal Newton, as soon as he leaves geometry and physics,
becomes a child. As for Descartes’ ‘ontological’ argu-
ment, this would equally prove the existence of hippogriffs.
‘
Nature ’, then, is all and produces all. Nor does this mean
that effects are produced ‘by chance’, for Nature acts in-
variably by fixed laws. It does mean, however, that we
must base our lives on ‘experience’, and fear no ghosts.
Holbach accepts quite cheerfully the idea that matter,
existing from eternity, having certain properties and sub-
ject to certain laws, could spontaneously generate such a
system as our universe. He condemns ‘
Spinozistic’ pan-
theism, but it may well seem that his own ‘
Matter’, having
so many wonderful ‘attributes’ and ‘potentialities’ and
‘principles’ within it, becomes, after all, something toler-
ably godlike before he has finished with it. It is of the
‘
—whereas ‘religion’
from this, their true end, by bidding them turn their gaze
towards heaven. Holbach appends here one of those foot-
notes which are sometimes more graphic than his text:
‘In 1725, the city of Paris was afflicted by a famine which was
considered likely to cause a popular rising, so they brought down
the casket of St Genevieve, patron and tutelary goddess of the
Parisians, and carried it round in procession in order to end this
calamity, which was caused by monopolies in which the mistress
of the first minister of those days was interested.’ 2
*
The priests have good reason to be the enemies of science,
1 2
ibid., vol. ii, p. 277. ibid., vol. ii, p. 289.
164
HOLBACH’s SrSTEME DE LA NATURE
for the progress of light will put an end, sooner
or later,
to the ideas of superstition/
What, finally, is be said of this atheism of whose ne-
to
cessity Holbach is so firmly persuaded? Will it, as is
often suggested, produce moral monsters ? No: it is super-
stition that releases all the evil passions, while atheism,
by
confining our views to this life, promotes the social virtues.
Holbach admits that a man may embrace atheism because
he wrongly thinks it will enable him to drink on and defy
the parson; there are admittedly vicious men who will
attack the gods because they think them enemies of their
passions. The good man attacks them because he finds
them enemies of virtue. Atheism will not make a good
man bad, or a bad man good, but
if an atheist chances to
be a wicked man he can at least not- pretend that his mis-
deeds are authorized by God. An atheist who reasons
aright will probably be good, and meanwhile let us re-
member those illustrious ‘atheists’ who have been peace-
able and studious men: Epicurus, Lucretius, Bodin,
Spinoza. ‘Hobbes did not cause bloodshed in England,
where in his lifetime religious fanaticism put a king to
death on the scaffold 1
Atheism is not a creed for ‘the
.’
people ,
so we need not fear its political consequences.
But Holbach has been accusing ‘religion’ of baffling ‘the
people’ with its subtleties, while ‘Nature’ is clear and
plain to all. Is religion, then, perhaps, ‘useful’ even if
false? No! Holbach will not have this either, for there
is always most vice where there is most
superstition. He
avoids this difficulty by saying that we cannot convert a
whole people at once to atheism; an enlightened author
writes and works for posterity and for the human race, and
not merely for his own times or his actual fellow-country-
men, for whom his doctrine too advanced. Let it not
is
be supposed, in spite of the great Lord Bacon, that deeper
thinking will bring posterity back to religion; what more
often happens is that shallow thinkers arrive at seeing the
absurdities of religion, but, through being unaccustomed
1
ibid., vol. ii, p. 354.
i6 5
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
to meditation, are plunged by further thought back into
the theological labyrinth.
In the final chapters Holbach’s tone becomes more and
more exalted: ‘chaleur’, ‘attendrissement’, and ‘senti-
ment’ infuse the style increasingly, and finally there is a
hymn or prayer to Nature, from which it seems evident
that he has not outgrown all religious sentiment, but rather
transferred it to another divinity. I shall quote the passage
in the original, in order to convey its quality more pre-
p. 38.
166
HOLBACH’s SrSTEME DE LA NATURE
are pernicious; but still they are better than Christianity,
inasmuch as anarchy is better than despotism’. Shelley
never lost the passion for human improvement which en-
nobled eighteenth century materialism, but his repudia-
tion of that philosophy is typical of the spiritual
reaction
which accompanied, and largely produced, the best poetry
of the next era. We shall see something analogous in
Wordsworth’s rejection of Godwin, and in the modifi-
cations which Godwin himself —
the chief English ex-
—
ponent of Holbach’s ideas afterwards introduced into
his original system.
167
!
CHAPTER X
C
to
again in Priestley, the follower of Hartley, what I
and indeed, for the student of life and thought, his volu-
minous works are mainly important because they show
how the mind of English Dissent matured into an autumn
inflorescence in the chilly climate of eighteenth century
rationalism. In the seventeenth century, before the com-
ing of toleration, the Church was often more ‘liberal’ in
doctrine than the sects, but now that toleration had reduced
the theological temperature and diminished the need for
credal rigidity, the Establishment necessarily remained
1 68
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
nominally orthodox, while the sects were free to follow the
contemporary stream of tendency towards a more and
more explicit liberalism. In orthodox quarters theology
could not develop in genuine harmony with the spirit of
the age; it remained, perforce, a Gothic shrine in a
Palladian basilica. I he Dissenters of this century, on the
other hand, were men Who had accepted the political and
social disabilities of nonconformity, and had therefore
nothing to lose in following, wherever it led, what seemed
to them to be the light of truth. It is for such reasons that
Priestley can illustrate, more completely than Horsley or
Paley, the last developments of religious thought within
the limits of the Nature ’-philosophy of the century.
‘
1
History of the Corruptions of Christianity. Works (ed.
Rutt), vol. v,’ p. 4
2
Quoted by Anne Holt, Joseph Priestley , p. 97.
3
ibid., p. 98.
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
chose on all occasions to appear as a Christian, by some I was told
of them that I was the only person they had ever met with, of
whose understanding they had any opinion, who professed to
believe Christianity. But on interrogating them on the subject,
I soon found that they had given no proper attention to it, and
1
did not really know what Christianity was .’
‘the two gentlemen opposite me were the Bishop of Aix and the
Archbishop of Toulouse, “but”, said he, “they are no more be-
lievers than you or I”. I assured him that I was a believer; but
3 Memoirs, p. 49.
172
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
that no historical evidence and no miracles could prove
such doctrines as the incarnation, the atonement, or the
Trinity:
173
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
composed Caine while he was in the service of Lord
at
Shelburne. Priestley had read Hartley as a youth, and
had been so deeply impressed by him that in 1775
republished the Observations on Man omitting, however,,
174
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
that sensation and thought were always held be irrecon- to
cilable; but matter is neither inert nor impenetrable. It
is not inert, for powers of attraction and repulsion are
1
75
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
materialism. He hoped that materialism, when properly
defined and understood, so far from leading to the atheism
of a Holbach, would enable him to rescue Christianity
from all the accretions which, as a Unitarian, he wished
to be rid of, and especially the doctrine of the pre-existence
of Christ the demiurge. Further, ‘the common opinion
of the soul of man surviving the body was (as will be
shown) introduced in Christianity from the Oriental and
Greek philosophy, which in many respects exceedingly
’. 1
altered and debased the true Christian system Priestley
was a mortalist of the same type as Milton; at death we
die wholly. But here again we must note the eclecticism
of Priestley’s thought; in spite of all his heresies he always
deferred to Scripture as he understood it, and the general
resurrection at the Last Day was one of the teachings
which he took to be incontestably scriptural. Hobbes and
Milton had already used the Resurrection for the same
purpose ; both they, and Priestley after them, found that
by removing immortality to this safe and miraculous dis-
tance they could combine materialism with the faith.
What rises again must have died, and what has died is the
whole man. What has decomposed may be recomposed
by the being who first composed it, and this will probably
be effected, not by a miracle, but by some natural law un-
known to us. This doctrine, he claims, frees us from
many of the traditional difficulties; we are dispensed, for
instance, from enquiring when, exactly, the soul enters the
body, or whether there are unbodied souls waiting their
turn for incarnation, or whether the animals will rise again
at the Last Day (many of them deserve it, he quaintly
adds, after all they have undergone in this life). Priestley,
whose constant use of the historical method is one of his
claims to distinction, does not leave his subject without
offering a historical sketch of the origin and growth of
opinions about the soul and the state of the dead. ‘
Im-
materiality’ in the strict sense is a modern notion: ‘ It is no
article of faith that I am oppugning, but really an upstart
1
ibid., p. 156.
176
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
thing, and a nonentity.’ He sums up in a passage which
may deserve full quotation:
The modernidea of an immaterial being is by no means the
same thing that was so denominated by the ancients; it being
well known to the learned that what the ancients meant by an
. . .
immaterial being, was only a finer kind of what we should now call
matter; something like air or breath which first
, supplied a name
for the soul, or else like fire or
which was probably sug-
flame ,
gested by the warmth of the living body.
Consequently the
ancients did not exclude from mind the property
of extension and
,
local presence. It had, in their idea, some common properties
with matter, was capable of being united to it, of
acting and being
acted upon by it, and of moving from place to place
along with it.
But it was justly considered
by the moderns, that such an
immaterial substance as this was, in fact, no immaterial
substance
at all, but a material one; it being the
opinion of all modern
philosophers (though it was unknown to the ancients)
that all
matter is ultimately the same thing, all kinds of bodies
differing
from one another only in the size or
arrangement of their ultimate
particles, oratoms. It was therefore seen, that if the powers of
sensation or thought could belong to such a material
substance as
the ancients had denominated an immaterial one
... it might be
imparted to the very grossest matter; ... and therefore
that the
soul and body being in reality the same kind
, of substance, must
die together.
To avoid this conclusion,
of which divines entertained a very
unreasonable dread, they refined upon the former notion
of spirit,
excluding from it every property which it held in common
with
matter; making
it, in the strict metaphysical sense
of the term,
an immaterial thing without extension, that is, occupying
,
no
portion of space and therefore bearing no relation to it;
and con-
sequently incapable of motion from one place to another, 1
etc .’
M 1 77
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
can be applied to God, whose ‘essence’ must remain un-
known to us. Meanwhile the evidences for God s exist-
ence and power stand firm:
the foundation that the nature of things admits
of
‘I have all
.
‘S° lon g as we ^
practically believe that there is but one
in the whole universe, that this
will
one will, exclusive of all Chance
,
or the interference of any other will,
disposes of things, even
all
to their minutest circumstances,
and al ways for the best of pur-
poses it is impossible but that we must rejoice in, and be thankful
ror, all events, without distinction .’ 1
It is
interesting to find Priestley comparing
this philo-
sophic creed of his manhood with the
Calvinism in which
he had been brought up. Necessity, he
would persuade
us, makes for morality
where Calvinism undermines it,
since Necessity represents all our
actions as due to our-
selves our susceptibility to ‘motives’), while
(i.e.
Calvinism
removes all into the hands of God. He seems
in fact to
be using, in criticism of predestination,
the very argu-
ments usually brought against Necessitarianism.
Under
Calvinism, he says in effect, you cannot
urge anyone to
turn from his wickedness and live:
under Necessity you
can and must. Why? Because men’s
conduct follows
necessarily from their motives, and you
can supply them
by persuasion, with ever better and better
motives. His
emphasis is thus placed not on the passive
or submissive
aspect of the doctrine —
though he will sometimes use this
as the chief consolation of philosophy
scientific* manipulation of circumstances
but on the active —
so as to produce
1
Philosophical Necessity
(1777), Dedication, p. xii.
O 179
: :
1
ibid., p. 97.
I 80
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
But what he further subjoins on the subject of Cal-
vinism is also, I think, applicable to Necessitarianism:
Icannot, however, conclude this section without acknow-
ledging that though I consider the proper Calvinistic system
. . .
impresses the mind. But this is never, in fact, the case with any
system. If there be in our minds a prevalence
of good principles
and good dispositions, we naturally turn our eyes from everything
in our respective systems that, even by a just
construction,
is unfavourable to virtue and goodness, and we reflect with
pleasure, and act upon, those parts of them only that have a good
tendency .’ 1
3
PRIESTLEY’S RELIGIOUS OUTLOOK
‘I think’, says Coleridge in the Table Talk ‘Priestley
,
i 8 i
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Independent, and Baptist —
in the thousand (or there-
'83
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Keighley, who was responsible for his education, was truly
Calvinistic in principle, but was far from confining salva-
tion to those who thought as she did on religious subjects.
Being left in good circumstances, her home was the resort
of all the Dissenting ministers in the neighbourhood with-
out distinction, and those who were the most obnoxious
on account of their heresy were almost as welcome to her,
if she thought them good and honest men .., as any
.
Dissenting ministers
—
partly at various schools, but also from certain learned
‘a pretty good knowledge’ of
Greek, Latin, Hebrew, French, Italian, ‘High Dutch’,
Chaldee and Syriac, geometry and algebra; and he had
also read some philosophy and logic. Before he left home
he had already shown ‘heretical’ tendencies, and was re-
fused admittance as a communicant in his congregation
because he was unsound on the subject of the sin of Adam.
In spite of his early unorthodoxies and his later changes of
opinion he always acknowledged a great debt to his early
religious training, and the picture he draws of the life of
his congregation may usefully remind us how vigorously
the business of religion was still attended to, in the heart
184
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
of the ‘age of reason*, in Dissenting circles quite un-
touched by Methodism. There were catechizings, almost
daily meetings of some part of the congregation, and great
strictness in the keeping of the Lord’s Day. ‘No victuals
were dressed on that day in. any family. No member of it
was permitted to walk out for recreation, but the whole of
the day was spent at the public meeting, or at home in
reading, meditation, and prayer.’ Priestley was himself
so serious-minded that he had ‘a great aversion to plays
and romances’, and once seeing his brother Timothy
reading a book of Knight-errantry he snatched it out of
’
declares,
186
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
that the apostle s reasoning
4
was many
in places far from
being conclusive’. He had not yet studied the Socinian
doctrine, but his Ananism was enough to antagonize
his
flock, and he removed to Nantwich.
Here he ran a
school as well as a chapel, and earned enough to purchase
his first ‘philosophical instruments’. In 1760 Priestley
was appointed tutor in languages at the famous Warrington
Academy, under the principalship of Dr Aikin, the father
ot Mrs Barbauld. Here he was once again in congenial
society; the tutors were all Arians and Necessitarians,
and
not even some ‘obscure notions’ of Dr Aikin ’s on the sub-
ject of Atonement could disturb their unanimity. It
was
while here, too, that he was introduced to Price
and
Franklin in London, wrote his History of Electricity and
,
became a Fellow of the Royal Society. The next stage in
Priestley’s theological progress was reached during
his
ministry at the Mill Hill chapel, Leeds, where he suc-
ceeded the Rev. Thomas Walker in 1767. Here, by
reading Lardner s Eetter on the Logos he became ‘what
,
scheme’, Scripture —
context playing the part of
in this
—
‘
Nature Although he rejected the plenary inspiration ’,
’. ‘
1
History of the Corruptions : Works, vol. v, p. 19.
190
:
1
Quoted from The Evidences of Revealed Religion by W. Lloyd, Protestant
Dissent and English Unitariariism (1899), p. 184.
a
History of the Corruptions : Works, vol. v,
p. 103.
191
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
did then exist; and accordingly, without any thing more than
their natural operation, all the abuses rose to their full height; and
what is more wonderful still, by the operation of natural causes also ,
its union to the body, which had taken the deepest root in all the
I92
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
is,whether Mr Gibbon or myself, believe in more
numerous, more extraordinary, or more useless miracles.’
Suc h> then, was the faith of a representative
t
English
rational Dissenter at the time of the outbreak of the
French Revolution. In his Memoirs writing in 1787,
,
four years before the Church and King’
riots in Birming-
ham, he records his gratitude for having lived ‘in an
age
and country in which I have been at full liberty
both to
investigate, and by preaching and writing
to propagate,
religious truth The story of those riots is well known,
.
1
Letter to Southey, Sept. 6, I794 (quoted by L. Hanson, Life
Colertdge (1938), p. 52).
J J S
of * T
*
N 1
93
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Priestley was next to Hartley, the special
at this time,
Christian hero of Coleridge, and evidently the emigration
of the ‘patriot, saint and sage’, driven with vain hate from
his loved native land by Statesmen bloodstained and
‘
priests idolatrous’,
1
gave added zest to the pantisocratic
dream. In view of the tone of Coleridge’s later references
to Priestley the following sonnet, composed in December
is of some significance. It illustrates not only the
1794,
quality of Coleridge’s poetry before his intimacy with
Wordsworth, but also the completeness with which
Priestley then personified his religious, political, and in-
tellectual ideals:
4
POLITICS AND HISTORY
(0
be appropriate to consider now, in conclusion,
It will
Priestley’s Essay on the First Principles of Government and on ,
*94
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
the immediate background are Locke,
Russell, and Sidney,
and in the far distance, Harmodius and
Aristogiton.
Hartley also there, to
issupply the psychological basis for
perfectibility a theme —
on which Priestley writes with
more than his accustomed hopefulness. Physical
pains
and pleasures are transformed by association into
intel-
and man attains to larger and larger views, at
lectual ones,
length approaching the angels in scope,
and even dimly
glimpsing the divine standpoint from which all partial
evil
is universal good. Meanwhile
‘The great instrument in the hand of divine providence, of this
progress of society towards improvement, is
society , and conse-
quently government .’ 1
The economic
which Adam
basis is provided by the principle
Smith was so shortly (1776)
—on
to enlarge
authoritatively
gress
—
of the division of labour, whereby pro-
is immensely accelerated. In the same way
‘all knowledge will be subdivided and extended; and
knowledge ,
as Lord Bacon observes, being power
the human powers will, in ,
Priestley s paradise,
be observed, lies in the future,
it will
not in any antique golden age or state of Nature,
and the
contemplation of that prospect, he tells us, ‘always
makes
me happy’. It is a Baconian paradise, based on command
over Nature, that he here expects, not the
Kingdom of
God anticipated by Milton in Of Reformation in England 2
1
Essay on Government (1768), p. 6.
2
Wh th ° U ’ th
?
eternal and
shortl y King . . shah put an end
,; T,
to all earthly tyrannies,
.
J 9S
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
yet there an affinity between these two religious liber-
is
He has a suitable reply for the rich prelate who urges that
‘the powers that be are ordained of God’ :
‘This seems to be the time, when the minds of men are open-
ing to large and generous views of things.’ 2
1 2
ibid., vol. ii, p. 13 1. ibid., vol. ii, p. 188.
3 ibid., vol. 4 ibid.,
ii, p. 137. vol. ii, p. 185.
199
:
(
2)
‘though most of our pupils were young men designed for situa-
tions in civil and active life, every article in the plan of their
education was adapted to the learned professions.’
200
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
the knowledge and perhaps the virtue
of the human race’. 1
If Giobon could still believe
this after describing ‘the
triumph of barbarism and religion ’, and without
Priestley’s
religious grounds for hope,
not surprising that
it is
Priestley could advise his student to
‘attend to every
advantage which the present age enjoys above ancient
times, and see whether he cannot perceive
marks of things
being in a progress towards a state of greater
perfection’. 2
History, like Nature, is a mighty maze, but
not without
a plan;
it is, in reality,
an exhibition of the ways of God, and jointly
with the works of nature (which at first sight,
present a prospect
equally confused and perplexed) leads us to the
knowledge of his
perfections, and his will.’
. little did the Greeks and Romans imagine that the Divtst
1 2 ibid., p. 324.
ibid., p. 270.
8 ibid., p. 372.
202
JOSEPH PRIESTLEY AND THE SOCINIAN MOONLIGHT
bad; education and enlightenment will teach the wealthy
how to use their riches ‘for the good of the whole’.
Millionaires are, in fact, Nature’s elect those to whom
obedience to natural law has opened the earthly paradise:
—
Men of wealth and influence, who act upon the principles of
virtue, and religion, and conscientiously make their power sub-
servient to the good of their country, are the men
who are the
greatest honoui to human nature, and the greatest
blessing to
human societies .’ 1
203
:
204
—
CHAPTER XI
‘
I. WILLIAM GODWIN
i
205
;
206
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
Godwin who were most anxious to represent man as part
of the mechanism of Nature, and human character as the
product of environment. Moreover, these were also the
men who regarded most of what ‘Nature’ had actually
produced (existing institutions) as ‘unnatural’. Dizzied
by these contradictions, we seem to understand how it
was that at one time Wordsworth was ready to ‘yield up
moral questions in despair’. John Mor ley has said that
Burke was of that class of minds which prefers ‘that which
has grown to that which is made’, and perhaps this dis-
tinction may help us in classifying the doctrines of our
period. Our problem turns upon the degree of human
participation which is supposed needed to produce
to be
the best world. Burke, or the ‘Tory’ Wordsworth,
desires the minimum of this; Nature (history) produces
what is best (most natural), and our part is to realize the
complexity of things, explaining where we can, and rever-
encing where we cannot. The Liberal (Priestley or Adam
Smith) wants us to leave Nature to itself, but first to
remove the ‘artificial’ restrictions with which wicked men
have somehow hampered it. The Revolutionary wants
the maximum of human action to fashion all things fain
‘Nature’ left to itself produces jungles and slums; if we
want better conditions we must make them ourselves.
This view was implicit in Holbach and the Jacobin philo-
sophy generally, but the eighteenth century reverence for
Nature prevented it from reaching full theoretic develop-
ment until the time of Marx.
Another broad distinction may
perhaps be made at this
point: ‘Nature’ may be conceived rationally or emotion-
ally. Indeed the history of the idea in the eighteenth
century can be described in the most general terms as its
development from a rational into an emotional principle.
Nature and Reason are normally associated in the earlier
part of the century, Nature and Feeling in the later. This
change is associated with the growth of the cult of sensi-
bility, the substitution of ‘je sens, doncje suis’ for
‘cogito,
.
ergo sum’, the increasing value attributed to impulse and
207
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
spontaneity, and the decreasing importance attached to
pure reason. It is also peculiarly associated with the name
of Rousseau —
the Rousseau of the Confessions the Nouvelle ,
and to make ‘our Reason’s naked self’ the object of his fer-
vour 1 The great traditions overlap, and the authentic
.
O times,
In which the meagre, stale, forbidding ways
Of custom, law, and statute, took at once
The attraction of a country in romance!
When Reason seemed the most to assert her rights
^ hen most intent on making of herself
A —
prime enchantress to assist the work
Which then was going forward in her name !
1
o 209
: :
or
To every natural form, rock, fruit, or flower,
Even the loose stones that cover the high-way,
I gave a moral saw them feel,
life: I
2
1 Dr Inge’s word. The Seasons ‘ Spring ’.
3 4 ibid., bk.
The Prelude , bk. i, 562. iii, 127.
2 10
—
NATURE IN REVOLUTION AND REACTION
places,and objects, or ‘the country’ (especially picturesque
country), and no longer so much to a
great abstraction, or
to the ‘general properties and large appearances’ of Dr
Johnson. But the transition from ‘abstract’ to ‘concrete’,
concerned by Mill as the overthrow of the
Locke-Hartley
tradition by the Germano-Coleridgean
doctrine’, is best
expressed in the actual development of such
men as
ordsworth, Coleridge, Southey, and even Godwin
him-
self, men who lived through
the revolutionary era and
epitomized its successive phases. In England, emotional
naturalism turned almost inevitably into Toryism,
or some-
thing akin to it. Wordsworth’s development
illustrates
this principlewith peculiar clearness. Greeting the early
days of the Revolution with a purely emotional
dilation,
as if France had suddenly achieved
the spontaneity and
joyous instinctiveness of his own childhood days
. . . the events
Seemed nothing out of nature’s certain course,
A gift that was come rather late than soon 1 —
he came later to feel that it was the ‘meddling intellect’,
not Nature, which was directing the course of
events. So,
after a short but harrowing temptation
in the wilderness
of Godwinism, he made the vital transition of
his life, and
relapsed upon the ‘cool flowery lap of
Earth’. The
Revolution had been made by Man, not evolved by
Nature.
Once he had convinced himself that, owing to the nature
of our being, radical alteration of the status
quo and the
worship of naked Reason were more likely to lead
into the
desert than into the Promised Land, then
how infinitely
preferable seemed things as they are to things as they may
be made, the feelings to the reason, instinctive
living to
thinking, children and rustics to philosophers,
one impulse
from a vernal wood to all the sages, England
to France ’
the Lake District to the rest of England !
212
:
NATURE y
IN REVOLUTION AND REACTION
worship of naked Reason, which for a short time so
dazzled the generation of Wordsworth, Coleridge, Hazlitt,
and the rest, and later the youthful Shelley, was one of the
forms into which eighteenth century rational Dissent was
capable of evolving. The peculiar missionary fervour of
Political "Justice is more explicable when we remember its
religious pedigree. Priestley stopped short at Unitarian-
ism, while Godwin followed Holbach into atheism,
but
thisdivergence seems less important than the heritage
which they received in common from the Dissenting tradi-
tion. In both, Calvinism passed naturally into Necessi-
tarianism and in his passion for reforming the world
; the
atheist even exceeded the believer —
for Priestley’s main
concern was rather with the exposure of error.
Several of Godwin ’s later characteristics were manifested
atan early age, particularly his vanity and self-confidence,
and his exclusive absorption in intellectual concerns. ‘All
my amusements were sedentary; I had scarcely any
pleasure but in reading.’ There is an illustration of
his
self-dramatizing vanity, which somehow falls short of the
Miltonic standard, in the following anecdote from his
autobiography. At the age of thirteen or fourteen he went
one day alone to the Assizes, and placed himself im-
mediately next to the Bench
As I some hours, I at one time relieved my posture by
stayed
leaning my elbow on the corner of the cushion placed
before his
lordship. On one occasion, probably when he was going to
address the jury, he laid his hand gently on my elbowand
removed
it. On this occasion I recollect having silently remarked, if his
lordship knew what the lad beside him will perhaps one day
become, I am not so sure that he would have removed mv
elbow .’ 1 7
213
:
214
nature’ in revolution and reaction
the Socinianism which satisfied Priestley
for life. An
abortive scheme for starting a ‘seminary’ at Epsom re-
sulted only in a Prospectus, consisting largely of
excerpts
from Rousseau and Hoi bach, but looking forward so
clearly to P olitical Justice that a few quotations may be of
interest:
1
Quoted, ibid., p. 17. a i
bid j p> z6
2I 5
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
of Liberty’. The idea of Political 'Justice was conceived in
1
Political Justice (2nd ed., 1796), pp. ix-x.
2
ibid., pp. vi-vii.
2 I 6
‘nature* in revolution and reaction
human mind are in arms’ against the doctrines he is about
to deliver, and even an unguarded word may be punished.
Godwin evidently relished his own Roman virtue; it is
known, however, that, Mr
thought a book published
Pitt
at three guineas a copy not worth suppressing.
and they have at any rate this justification for their attitude,
that much goodpoetry, especially Wordsworth’s, was
written in revolt against Godwin and all that he stood for.
Yet Godwin is worth considering for his own sake, and
perhaps still more as a representative figure: as the writer
who enunciated the extreme conclusions of eighteenth
century rationalism at the very moment of incipient re-
action, and who thereby, in his own life-story and in his
influence upon his contemporaries, acquired a certain sym-
bolic importance. The
reasons for his rapid eclipse may
appear as we proceed, but for the moment we may support
ourselves with the comment of Hazlitt (whose essay on
Godwin in The Spirit of the Age is still the fairest and most
discerning summary I know of):
It may
reasonably be doubted whether error could ever
be formidable or long-lived if government did not lend it
support.’ Now, must we accept this state of affairs as un-
alterable? No! it is precisely because moral causes are
all-important that we may work and hope for amelioration.
If government operates upon mind, mind is first the
foundation of government, or, as Godwin puts it, govern-
ment founded upon ‘opinion’ alone.
is Change the
‘opinion’, therefore, and the government will vanish like
smoke. Slavery exists, not because certain climates or
national characters favour it, but because it is the interest
of tyrants to prevent their subjects from seeing the obvious
advantages of freedom.
In reality the chains
‘
fall off of themselves, when the magic of
opinion is dissolved.’ 2
1
ibid., bk. i, ch. 4 (vol. i, p. 31).
2
ibid., bk. i, ch. 7 (vol. i, p. 64).
219
—
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
imperious voice of government, which bids us reverence and
1
obey .’
‘when the true crisis shall come, not a sword will need to be
drawn, not a finger to be lifted up,’ 2
and Jupiter will simply fall from his throne. But, in spite
of Necessitarianism, we are not to await this crisis with
folded hands ; in the meantime we are to prepare for it
how? The true technique for the overthrow of Jupiter is
to awaken men’s minds by argument and persuasion. The
present order exhibits a perpetual spectacle of unreason
and injustice; very well, show men the possibility of
another kind of spectacle, and they will welcome it with
rapture. ‘It is the inalienable tendency of positive in-
stitution, to retain that with which it is conversant for ever
in the same state’; while, on the other hand, ‘it is one of
the most unquestionable properties of mind to be sus-
ceptible of perpetual improvement’. Therefore,
the dream
Flattered the young, pleased with extremes, nor least
1
ibid., bk. i, ch. 7 (vol. i, p. 70).
2
The Borderers, 1488.
22 I
,
223
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
cessantly urged upon his friends (especially Shelley) the
completeness of his claim to the many hundreds of pounds
of which he was always in want.
example of those whom she has goaded to the breach of order, in-
stead of amending her own institutions which, by straining order
2
into tyranny, produced the mischief?’
shall say how far the whole species might be improved, were they
1
ibid., bk. ii, ch. 6 (vol. i, p. 112).
2
ibid., bk. vii, ch. 3 (vol. ii, p. 713).
224
‘nature" in revolution and reaction
accustomed to despise force in others, and did they refuse to em-
ploy it for themselves. •
For the wise man, ‘wherever there are men who under-
stand the value of political justice and are prepared to
assert it, that is his country’. Do I owe gratitude and
reverence to the British Constitution as such? No: who-
ever wants me to respect it must rely on one of two motives
1 ibid., bk. v, ch. 18 (vol. ii, p. 531).
2 ibid., bk. v, ch. 16 (vol. ii, p. 512).
226
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
ithas a claim upon my support, either because it is
good, or because it is British’. Godwin’s views were here
so advanced’ as to seem, in his own time, merely
per-
verse; and nationalism is to-day, in some countries, more
exorbitant than he would have thought conceivable.
Nevertheless, in his usual way, he is anticipating some of
the most hopeful developments of thought in our own
time- in this case, what is being urged by the supporters
of Federal Union’. He sees clearly that ‘the much-
vaunted independence of the European states is an object
of an equivocal nature the despotism which at present
’
;
‘
able, they will follow it; and they will not only love
the
highest when they see it, but, ‘having thus gained one step
in the acquisition of truth, it cannot be easily conceived
of
as lost’. was from
It this sense of the supreme duty of
broadcasting Truth on occasions that Godwin deduced
all
his celebrated teaching on the importance of Perfect
Sin-
cerity. Here, as elsewhere, he seems to anticipate the
methods and of the ‘Oxford’ Group; he proposes
ideals
that every man should make himself a kind of missionary
Alceste, telling everybody everything about himself and
227
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
themselves, for the purpose of doing them good. Let us
outdo the Papists by turning the whole world into our
v confessional If every man would tell all the truth he
!
228
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
for mankind, we are to regard mind as a chief link in the
chain of causes, and work incessantly upon other minds in
order to release them from their bondage. Once truth is
seen, it must convince: the laws of necessity will ensure
that. But occasionally Godwin relapses into the fatalistic
type of Necessitarianism: ‘the assassin cannot help the
murder he commits any more than the dagger’, he says;
or, to take a more respectable example: ‘our disapproba-
tion of vice will be of the same nature as our disapproba-
tion of an infectious distemper’. The element of resent-
ment in the punishment of criminals should be eliminated
by Necessitarianism (as later in Butler’s Erewhon and a
),
genera] tolerant acceptance of human failings generated.
A ‘virtue’, or a ‘vice’, is not a subject for praise or blame,
it is merely a characteristic, like a knife’s capacity to cut.
A knife is made ‘good’ by sharpening; a man is made
‘virtuous’ by persuasion. In persuading, a necessitarian
will not exhort or threaten, as if the listener were free to
choose; he merely ‘represents’ and ‘elucidates’; Truth
will do the rest. There is in all this the usual strange
blend of active and passive, effort and relaxation. It may
seem queer that the missionary whose main concern, after
all, is in converting men and improving the world,
should
have based his gospel upon the very philosophy which
enables the assassin to excuse himself, and might give
every man a pretext for staying as he is. Necessity, ‘the
tyrant’s plea’, gives the bad man too easy an acquittal, and
good and bad men alike too little incentive to bestir them-
selves. But, as we have
already suggested, ‘necessity’
was an essential part of the intellectual outfit of ‘en-
lightened’ persons at that time; it was too useful a
weapon against religion, superstition, and the super-
natural dogmas and claims of the Church, for its incon-
veniences to be much felt. To acknowledge it was part
of your Roman virtue, your Stoic dignity; it marked your
disdain for the magic of sacrament, holy water or rosary,
and your kinship with Nature. Nevertheless, I doubt
whether Godwin, or any of our necessitarians, would have
229
:
and good sense will not fail to augur ill of that system of
things which is too sacred to be looked into.’ In spite of
his passion for education Godwin opposes state education
as yet another means of rendering permanent the existing
order of things. If every child could receive the educa-
tion of an Emile, all would be well, but ‘public educa-
230
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
tion has always expended its energies in the support of
prejudice’.
1
ibid., bk. vi, ch. 8 (vol. ii, p. 667).
2 ibid., bk. v, ch. 12 (vol. ii, p. 485).
231
— !
‘
Let us length dismiss artificial tastes ’, cries Marguerite
at
to the repentant St Leon (after he has wasted his patrimony
in riotous living at Paris, and retired upon a pittance to a
Swiss fastness):
‘and idle and visionary pursuits, that do not flow in a direct line
from any of the genuine principles of our nature! . Here we . .
232
nature’ in revolution and reaction
be tasted by the sophisticated mind. An
honest plough-
man, he had taught in Political Justice cannot be as
,vir-
tuous as Cato unless he is also an educated man, for
‘virtue
consists in a desire of the benefit of the species’,
and ‘that
desire only can be denominated virtuous, which
flows from
a distinct perception of the value, and
consequently of the
nature, of the thing desired’. ‘Though I love the sight
of peasants, I would not be a peasant’, Marguerite
declares
with commendable frankness I would have a larger stock
‘
;
2
Political Justice, bk. v, ch.
15 (vol. ii, p 503).
233
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
one attempt it. Our present respect for mere pos-
will
sessions will be transferred to intrinsic worth. Men will
have a ‘right’ only to what they need, or can use; any-
thing further, even if made by themselves, will be passed
on. There will still be some division of labour, but much
less than now. Godwin’s equality and fraternity, of course,
must be strictly consistent with Liberty in the bourgeois
sense; he wants no communism — particularly of house
or meals; individuality must at all costs be preserved.
Marriage, however, will disappear, along with other forms
of exclusive appropriation, and so will parental affection,
which is contrary to the principles of Political Justice
(tender care of the young will of course continue, but their
exact parentage will be a matter of no account). Towards
the end of the book Godwin gives the reins to his imagina-
tion, and forecasts a time when, as Franklin had said, mind
will be omnipotent over matter, and men may conquer
disease and even lengthen their lives indefinitely by so
willing. Even now, cheerfulness and serenity of mind
have incalculable physical effects, and a relapse into
vacancy, sleep, or melancholy is so much cut off from
life. Let no one fear that if men become too happy they
will multiply too rapidly; beings who can control death
will be able to control the birth-rate. The first step to-
wards the realization of these visions is the removal of the
present odious governments of Europe. But argument,
writing, and persuasion are to be the means employed,
not incitement to tumult; we must await, in calm con-
fidence, the arrival of the great crisis of human affairs, the
day of ultimate hope for humanity.
Such, in briefest outline, are some of the contents of
that celebrated book, which immediately won for its author
the fame he had thirsted for, and influenced some of the
best heads of the generation. Within a few weeks of its
appearance, and for some years afterwards, Godwin blazed
‘
4
It is not my purpose to follow Godwin through his years
of twilight, but a word may be said about his own crossing
of the dividing watershed between 1793 and 1800. He,
like Wordsworth, came to see ‘Nature’ as ‘Feeling’, and
not merely as Reason ’. ‘I am filled with grief’, he wrote
*
in his memoranda,
‘when I reflect on the possibility that any extravagances or over-
1
Hazlitt, loc cit
. .
235
:
‘The benefits we
can confer upon the world are few. The . . .
benefits we can confer upon those with whom we are closely con-
nected are of great magnitude, or continual occurrence. It is
impossible that we should be continually thinking of the whole
world, or not confer a smile or a kindness but as we are prompted
to it by an abstract principle of philanthropy.’
‘
But it seems equally certain ’, he adds, in a rather pathetic
effort to stick to his old though not the
guns, ‘
that utility,
source, will be the regulator’ of a good man’s actions, and
that ‘however ardent be his parental, domestic, or friendly-
exertions, he will from time to time examine into their
coincidence with the greatest sum of happiness in his
power to produce’. Again, education remains a most
powerful instrument, but he came to allow more weight to
‘differences of the highest importance’ existing between
human beings from their birth.
1 Quoted by F. K. Brown, op. cit., pp. 135-6.
236
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
As early as in the Preiace to the second edition (dated
October 29, 4
237
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
and active sense of justice in the mind of him that cherishes
1
them .’
238
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
system of the mild and persuasive tone of the Gospel ’, and
perhaps the rationalises arguments, addressed exclusively
to the head (and so, to the few who can understand), are
more liable to perversion than the exhortations of religion,
which humble the pride of intellect and use the heart’s
affections in obedience to an absolute command. And
what might not the foolish or unscrupulous do with the
maxims of universal benevolence! ‘There was danger’,
says Hazlitt, ‘that the unseasoned novice might substitute
some pragmatical conceit of his own for the rule of right
reason, and mistake a heartless indifference for a superi-
ority to more and generous feelings’, or the
natural
‘perfectibility code’ might turn out in practice to be a
scheme for the accommodation of the enterprising and
cunning, at the expense of the credulous and honest’. It
might be that average humanity was unequal to the strain
of living the life of pure reason —
as indeed Swift had
hinted by making his ideal creatures, not philosophers, but
horses. Perfected humanity could perhaps dispense with
the poor, irrational ‘virtues’ of gratitude, filial and
parental affection, patriotism, or piety. But supposing we
dispensed with them, and yet failed of perfection, might
we not discover too late that these virtues are what alone
prevent us, not from advancing to perfection, but from
sinking into brutality?
Misgivings of this kind were in Wordsworth’s mind
when he composed The Borderers (1795-6), and similar
fears, though relating to the Jacobin philosophy and not
to Godwin, led Burke to write the Reflexions on the Revolu-
tion in France (1790). In order to show how, in ‘the
revolt of the human mind against the philosophy of the
eighteenth century’, ‘Nature’ in the sense of ‘the his-
torical and the actual’ came to be used in opposition to
‘Nature’ in the sense of ‘the abstract and potential’, I
shall conclude with some observations on these two
representatives of the new way of thought.
239
— — J
1
Mill, Dissertations and Discussions, vol. i, p. 394.
2
Quoted by A. Cobban, Edmund Burke and the Revolt against the Eighteenth
^
Century, p. 77.
243
:
‘the awful Author of our being is the Author of our place in the
order of existence; and .having disposed and marshalled us by
. .
244
—
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
we do, than of any power in us to act back Upon and
modify the very environment that limits us.
‘The nature of man is intricate; the objects of society are of
the greatest possible complexity: and therefore no simple dis-
position or direction of power can be suitable either
to man’s
nature, or to the quality of his affairs. [The revolutionistsJ are
. .
.
so taken up with their theories about the rights of man,
that they
have totally forgotten his nature .’ 1
245
,
246
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
sophisters of France to produce any better plan than we
—
have followed we ‘who have chosen our nature rather
than our speculations, our breasts rather than our in-
ventions, for the great conservatories and magazines of
our rights and privileges \ You think you are combating
‘
‘We are not the converts of Rousseau; we are not the dis-
ciples of Voltaire; Helvetius has made no progress amongst us.
Atheists are not our preachers; madmen are not our lawgivers.
We know that we have made no discoveries, and we think that
no discoveries are to be made, in morality; nor many in the great
principles of government, nor in the ideas of liberty, which were
understood long before we were born, altogether as well as they
will be after the grave has heaped its mould upon our pre-
sumption, and the silent tomb shall have imposed its law on our
1
pert loquacity.
The tone more forensic, the rhythm less subtle, and the
is
1 ibid., p. 83.
247
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
that we knew, and are back amongst the imaginatives,
at the line where men and mountains meet. Burke con-
tinues :
‘We fear God; we look
up with awe to Kings; with affection
to Parliaments; with duty to magistrates; with reverence to
priests; and with respect to nobility. Why? Because when
such ideas are brought before our minds, it is natural to be so
1
affected .’
1 (Burke’s
ibid., pp. 83-4. italics.)
2 ibid., p. 84. (My italics: contrast Godwin’s ‘the genuine and wholesome
state of mind,’ etc., p. 222 above.)
248
‘nature’ in revolution and reaction
percipience on which any sort of impressions may be in-
scribed. Heredity, history, physical environment, count
for nothing. The rules of justice and reason (the laws of
Nature) are therefore applicable to all times and all places.
If history has been for a long time inscribing erroneous
impressions on the blank sheet of the mind, let us 'abolish ’
us, if our affections had not a trick of twining round those old
inferior things —
if the loves and sanctities of our life had no deep
1
immovable roots in memory .’
The ‘truth’, seemed, was not all upon the side of Burke,
it
25 l
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
race-passions and so opposes
becoming the very thing it
252
CHAPTER XII
9
‘ Nature in Wordsworth
254
: — :
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
of his purest thoughts, the guide and guardian of his
heart
For, the Man
Who, in this spirit, communes with the Forms
Of Nature, who with understanding heart
Both knows and loves such objects as excite
No morbid no disquietude,
passions,
No vengeance, and no hatred needs must — feel
The joy of that pure principle of love
So deeply, that, unsatisfied with aught
Less pure and exquisite, he cannot choose
But seek for objects of a kindred love
In fellow-natures and a kindred joy.
Accordingly he by degrees perceives
His feelings of aversion softened down;
A holy tenderness pervade his frame.
His sanity of reason not impaired.
Say rather, all his thoughts now flowing clear,
From a clear fountain flowing, he looks round
And seeks for good; and finds the good he seeks.
‘
devote myself to such works as encroach not on the anti-
I
social passions —
in poetry, to elevate the imagination and set the
affections in right tune by the beauty of the inanimate impreg-
nated as with a living soul by the presence of life in prose to the —
seeking with patience what our faculties are and what they
. . .
1
The Excursion, bk. iv, 1208-66
2 SS
,
256
‘nature* IN WORDSWORTH
observed’ (abalance already reached by Wordsworth in
The Female Vagrant^ in Coleridge’s view) that the
two poets
dedicated themselves during those happy months
of in-
timacy between Alfoxden and Stowey. The
Quantock
Hills, transfigured by the mind’s
‘auxiliar light’, replaced
for them the vanished France and
the impossible Panti-
socracy. Let us then, in the hope of capturing
some faint
echo of the emotions of 1798, briefly retrace the
path that
led Wordsworth from France to Racedown and Alfoxden.
It isneedless to recapitulate in detail the familiar tale,
so graphically told in The Prelude, and
, so amply filled out
by the critics, of Wordsworth’s early enthusiasm
for the
Revolution, at the time when ‘a homeless sound
of joy was
in the air and the political scene took on, for ardent
,
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
From this Rousseauistic Eden man has, of course, been
largely driven by his oppressors:
26l
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
described
ve here see him wrestling with the difficulties
.n The Prelude Book X.
,
This was the period when any
sanguine view of human nature and of human capacity
for freedom and self-rule seemed refuted by
the present
fact of the Terror. Wordsworth admits that probably
every European state is so corrupt that if the original
power of the people should be restored only a change of
tyranny would result*. But what is accountable for this
state of affairs? Not human nature, but customs and
institutions, and in particular the institution of monarchy.
Here we find Wordsworth, like Holbach, Godwin, and
allthe party, refusing to see institutions as the expression
of something in human nature, even if it be only of its
wickedness; while Burke and the traditionalists on their
side over-emphasized the fixity of both, and in insisting
that institutions were fitted to man’s nature if not to his
reason, ignored the possibility that an evolving humanity
might have outgrown its institutions. As a proof of the
capacity of Church and King to debauch the popular mind,
Wordsworth asks: ‘left to the quiet exercise of their own
judgment, do you think that the people would have thought
it necessary to set fire to the house of
the philosophic
Priestley ?’, or that they would now be crying out for a war
which will only increase their already intolerable burdens ?
Like Godwin, he argues that a philosopher should look
beyond such considerations, and not labour to perpetuate
injustice. The terrific reservoir of guilt once emptied
— alas, not without violence and chaos —
the stream of
public affairs will steadily become clearer. In the republic
there will be no Machiavellian diplomacy; all will be con-
ducted in the daylight. It will no longer be the interest
of the governors to keep the people in ignorance, hence
‘a moderate portion of useful knowledge would be univers-
ally disseminated’. penal code, now full of dis-
The
proportionate penalties, will be reformed. As for property,
the present system of fixed inequality is pernicious, and
must go. In protecting property, our laws have forgotten
the property of a labourer, which is his power to support
Mature’ in wordsworth
himself and his family. Wordsworth deplores the im-
mense salaries annexed to useless and hereditary offices,
and points out the debasing effect of titles, stars, ribbons,
—
and garters all the apparatus of ‘nobility’, and the social
hypocrisy and snobbery to which it leads. In his perora-
tion he denounces the Bishop for having ‘aimed an arrow
at liberty and philosophy, the eyes of the human race’,
and for having tried to divert men from fruitful enquiry
by telling them that perfection has already been attained.
Finally, from the Bishop’s silence about the war, Words-
worth assumes that he supports ‘that infatuation which is
now giving up to the sword so large a portion of the poor,
and consigning the rest to the more slow and more painful
consumption of want’.
If any further proof were needed of the extent to which
\\ ordsworth had absorbed Political Justice one might take
these remarks from letters written in 1794 to Mathews, in
which not only the ideas but also the phraseology of
Godwin are echoed:
‘The enlightened friend of mankind should let slip no oppor-
tunity of explaining and enforcing those general principles of
social order which are applicable to all times and places. ... He
should diffuse by every method a knowledge of those rules of
political justice from which the further any government deviates
the more effectually must it defeat the object for which govern-
ment was ordained. ... You know perhaps already that I am of
that odious class of men called democrats, and of that class I shall
for ever continue. ... I disapprove of monarchical and aristo-
cratic governments, however modified. Hereditary distinctions
and privileged orders of every species I think must necessarily
counteract the progress of human improvement: hence it follows
that I am not amongst the admirers of the British Constitution .’ 1
265
3 J
1
See, on this subject, The Later Wordsworth, by E. C. Batho (Cambridge,
1
93 )> e -g • PP- 196 ff-> and p. 200 (‘I have a great deal of the Chartist in
me’).
266
;
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
can be sure that he had renounced France in favour of the
whole Godwinian doctrine. This means that he was only
under the full dominion of Godwin for the first six months
of that year, for by September 1795 h a d already
realized some of the dangers of his doctrine. What were
these teachings which he adopted in disillusionment and
rejected again so soon? One would suppose, from the
brevity of their hold upon him, that they were theories
essentially hostile to his inmost nature, and that is pre-
cisely what we find* As suggested above, what tem-
porarily attracted him were the ‘speculative schemes that
promised to abstract the hopes of man out of his feelings’
it Was Godwin’s abstract individualism, which made ‘our
1
In The Nineteenth Century, Nov. 1926, p. 723.
268
, —
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
a moral sophistry which condemns all human feelings
as weaknesses. ‘His feelings are interested in making
him a moral sceptic*; ‘he disguises from himself his
own malignity by assuming the character of a specu-
lator in morals’. ‘Remorse’, he exclaims,
Remorse
It cannot live with thought; think on, think on.
And it will die .
1
27O
:
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
all mean cares’. 1
In any attempt to understand what
‘Nature’ meant to Wordsworth due weight should be
given, I think, to the healing power of the impersonal over
a sick mind. It was when the ‘fretful stir Unprofitable,
and the fever of the world’ had long ‘hung upon the
beatings of my heart’ that Wordsworth turned to the
sylvan Wye, and found ‘for this uneasy heart of ours a
never-failing principle of joy’. Wordsworth speaks so
often of ‘dim sadness and blind thoughts’, of ‘listlessness
from vain perplexity’ and ‘the heavy weight of many a
weary day Not mine’, and on the other hand of ‘tranquil
restoration’ and ‘renovation’ —
indeed, ‘Despondency
Corrected is so much his central theme
’
that we are left —
in no doubt upon this point. He found, amongst the
‘calm oblivious tendencies of Nature’, both stimulus and
anodyne
I well remember that those very plumes.
Those weeds, and the high spear-grass on that wall,
By mist and silent rain-drops silvered o’er,
As once I passed, into my heart conveyed
So still an image of tranquillity,
So calm and still, and looked so beautiful
Amid the uneasy thoughts which filled my mind.
That what we feel of sorrow and despair
From ruin and from change, and all the grief
That passing shows of Being leave behind.
Appeared an idle dream 2 .
%
made
1
795
*
of the French cause had
later sinkings’
it vain to keep up any longer the unprofitable strife,
the Bible, yet ‘in the mountains did he feel his faith . .
.,
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
M a
but after I had seen
T hat spectacle, for many days, my brain
Worked with a dim and undetermined sense
Of unknown modes of being ; o'er my thoughts
There hung a darkness, call it solitude.
Or blank desertion. No familiar shapes
Remained, no pleasant images of trees.
Of sea or sky, no colours of green fields;
But huge and mighty forms, that do not live
Like living men, moved slowly through the mind
By day, and were a trouble to my dreams.
[ 390 .]
With these may
be taken the passage from Book XII,
which commemorates an experience of similar quality.
Ihe child is lost on the
and is suddenly terrified
hills,
by coming upon a place where a murderer had been
hanged in chains, and seeing his name carved in huge
letters in the grass:
276
:
‘nature* IN WORDSWORTH
—the discipline of fear
and joy through which her benign
Hartleian curriculum has been fulfilled.
The first three
passages quoted above are given by him as examples of
Nature s ‘ministries’ and ‘interventions’, whereby she
re-
proved his childish delinquencies. It is at this point that
we egin to see the cleavage between
experience and be-
le * w hat matters, for us (and, we feel, for
Wordsworth
too), simply that he should have had these
is
moments of
imaginative energy, in which the earth and
every common
sight were apparelled— not only in
celestial light, but also
sometimes in visionary dreariness, and that he
should have
been able, as few others have done, to
remember and com-
municate them. The theory about Nature’s
Education
no doubt attributable to Hartley via Coleridge,
can be dis-
regarded we will. But Wordsworth himself gives other
if
interpretations of his own experiences,
other reasons for
cherishing his recollections, and some of
them give us still
urther confidence in our winnowing
process. One of
them is given at the beginning of the passage
from which
extract (
d ) above is taken
There are in our existence spots of time
Which with distinct
pre-eminence retain
A renovating virtue, whence ... our minds
Are nourished and invisibly repaired.
[Bk. xii, 208 .]
Certain recollections have the power to evoke
in him the
dormant imaginative energy, so that he can literally
fetch
invigorating thoughts from former years’
[Bk. I 620]
At the time when he is writing The Prelude he
appears
already as the historian, rather than the
present possessor
ot the visionary power. The regular action of the world
has already had its effect, and he is turning
for stimulus to
the past. After he has drawn his moral
from passage
r & (J)
v
he continues:
The
days gone by
Return upon me
almost from the dawn
Of life: the hiding-places of man’s power
Open; I would approach them, but they close.
277
:
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
did, from some of Wordsworth’s idealizations of the child
(‘mighty prophet, seer blest’, etc.), but in what has just
been summarized there is otherwise little but introspec-
tion and accurate psychology. Both as child and as man
Wordsworth possessed unusual sensibility, and had
associated his inner life,' far more than most men, with
natural objects; but no ‘dated’ beliefs are involved, and
nothing which need antagonize a modern reader.
It would appear, then, that as long as Wordsworth is
communicating experiences of this kind, and not merely
discussing or rationalizing them, his poetry can still be
read with unabated interest. Sometimes he is doing both
at once, and sometimes, again, one can see the ‘join where ’
28 I
:
ments ’, but with the longing of a sick man for the sources
of health. His dealings with Nature are now those of a
man who has been depressed ‘by false opinion or con-
tentious thought’, who has lived ‘amid the many shapes
of joyless daylight’, and known ‘the dreary intercourse of
daily life’. It is in this spiritual context, and after such
282
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
knowledge, that Nature acquires for him her great sooth-
ing and cheering power, and revives for him with new
significance those dormant emotions which have been
linked with her by long association. Thus Nature’s heal-
ing power, which for some may be merely an outworn
doctrine, was for him a fact of experience, and the rapture
of that experience, which glows through Tinterrt Abbey and
much of his best poetry, can be caught by any reader,
without reference to the ethical and philosophical theories
which Wordsworth evolved from it. Two main charac-
teristics of Wordsworth’s poetry can now perhaps be
viewed with somewhat fuller understanding: his rever-
ence for childhood, and his passion for mergence with
‘mute insensate things’. I will comment briefly on these.
On the passage already referred to, W. H. Hudson
makes these relevant observations:
‘It is difficult, impossible I am
any one to recall his
told, for
boyhood exactly as it was. It could not have been what it seems
to the adult mind, since we cannot escape from what we are, how-
ever great our detachment may be; and in going back we must
take our present selves with us: the mind has taken a different
colour, and this is thrown back upon our past. The poet has
reversed the true order of things when he tells us that we come
of glory, which melt away and are
trailing clouds lost as we pro-
ceed on our journey .’ 1
284
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
which, by shifting back all the ‘glory’ into pre-existence
and super-nature, forces Wordsworth to degrade earth into
a foster-mother, and Nature into a medium to which the
heaven-born visitant is gradually subdued. Is not this a
denial of his most central certainties, that Nature needs no
glory from ‘worlds not quickened by the sun’, and that
the child is in fact exquisitely fitted to its environment by
those firstborn affinities that fit
285
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
here was his sense of vast distance from the sources of
energy and vision. The ‘philosophic mind’ is but con-
solation; it is a poor substitute for the splendour in the
grass and glory in the flower. This sense of estrangement,
of loss, of subjugation by the adult consciousness and the
frost ofcustom, had become so insistent that Wordsworth
could only convey it by ascribing a supernatural endow-
ment to childhood, and a supernatural authority to the
surviving gleams that reached him through recollection.
He had written The Prelude in order to rescue from decay
the essential ‘spots of time’, but that work, both from its
great length and from the circumstance of its being written
for Coleridge, was inevitably couched in a discursive and
analytic style, and represents an effort to give the ‘philo-
sophical’ or ‘scientific’ account of his mind’s growth
(‘Not in a mystical and idle sense, But in the words of
—
Reason deeply weighed’ Book II, 230). But in the Ode
he gathers all his strength together, and in one concentrated
utterance bids farewell to the past which he has so care-
fully explored. What suffuses the Ode almost throughout
with unwonted power and warmth is, I think, this sense
that he is giving final and definitive expression to the most
poignant experience of his poetic life. He is not trying,
as often elsewhere, to convey the ineffable; he is lament-
ing his inability to experience it any more. This is partly
why the poem succeeds ; such sorrow can be uttered, while
the ineffable moments of vision can only be hinted at and
discussed. Moreover, the unique passion behind the Ode
has driven him to adopt, for once, a myth. It happened
that this particular one was available for him, and it was
free from the objectionable associations connected with
most of the classical machinery used by eighteenth century
poets. Itlooks as if Wordsworth had found in this
Platonic or Oriental fiction a symbolism which, though a
falsification of ‘psychological truth’, yet enabled him to
embody his experience objectively, and elevate it to a
degree of impersonality normally beyond his reach. For
by using it he has turned his personal experience into a
286
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
universal journey of man away from the East, and inland
from the sea. The comparative strength and concentra-
tion of the feeling behind this poem can be gauged by the
‘concreteness’ of its diction; the vagueness and abstract-
ness of the ‘psychological’ Prelude here gives place to
a profusion of precise images. In a word, he is creating
or ‘realizing’, not merely describing and analysing; he is
creating a sense of the splendour and inaccessibility of
childhood, when viewed, from within the ‘prison-house’,
by one who remembers how he felt, but can no longer
experience what he had felt.
But even though the Ode be his most ‘splendid’ poem,
its very uniqueness renders it not wholly characteristic of
him. We find the more typical ‘Wordsworthian’ quality
in those passages where he has recorded, not loss of vision,
but his more successful dealings with the world of eye and
ear. And it is here that we meet with the second charac-
teristic mentioned above: his passion for mergence with
impersonal things. As we have seen, his most urgent
needs, when he ‘returned to Nature’, were tranquillity
and restoration. And he could find these best by assimi-
lating himself and other men as closely as possible with
the landscape, and with the goings-on of the elements. He
could best forget his ‘old remembrances’ and ‘all the ways
of men, so vain and melancholy’ by fusing himself, and
mankind in general, with natural backgrounds and pro-
cesses. He loved to think of himself as ‘clothed with the
heavens and crowned with the stars’, and this explains his
need for solitude as a condition of inspiration. Mergence
of the human figure with Nature gave it that degree of
dignity, of separation from the mere social crowd, in
virtue of which alone it could become, for Wordsworth,
a worthy symbol of human life as he understood it. So
viewed, the figures are seen in abstraction from all that in
everyday humanity is disturbing, distressing, or unin-
teresting, and take on something of
the silence and the calm
Of mute insensate things.
287
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Three Tears She Grew (from which this phrase is taken)
communicates with special force this passion for the fusion
of the human with the impersonal a passion which is —
concentrated, perhaps most intensely of all, in the ‘Sub-
lime Epitaph’:
Rolled round in earth’s diurnal course
With rocks, and stones, and trees.
man
Ennobled outwardly before my sight,
288
—
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
thy mind
Shall be a mansion for all lovely forms,
Thy memory be as a dwelling-place
For all sweet sounds and harmonies.
What was amiss with Peter Bell, and made him (in his
unregenerate days) a moral monster, was that
At noon, when by the forest’s edge
He lay beneath the branches high,
The soft blue sky did never melt
Into his heart; he never felt
The witchery of the soft blue sky!
Examples need not be further multiplied; it is recognized
that Wordsworth’s typical human figures The Highland
Girl, Lucy, the Wanderer, the Old Cumberland Beggar
—
are those which are most intimately ‘engaged’ with their
natural background. And
he felt a special exaltation when
he could feel himself, also, mingled with the cosmic pro-
cesses; it gave him a sense of release from responsibility,
from the weight of separate existence; a feeling of
‘grandeur in the beatings of the heart’. It may be re-
marked, as a kindred characteristic in Wordsworth, that
it seems to have been necessary for him to ‘distance’ an
object
space
— particularly a distressing or tragic object in
or time, in order to think and feel freely about it.
—
His need to see man ‘removed to a distance that was fit’ is
analogous to his need to recollect emotion in tranquillity.
The music of humanity comes restoringly to him only
when
can feel
it is still
most
and sad
fully the
—purged by distance, just as he
or the
Sorr.ow barricadoed evermore
Within the walls of cities.
290
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
Mark Rutherford may be quoted once more here; he is
speaking of his discovery of Lyrical Ballads while strug-
gling for release from theological fetters:
1
Autobiography , pp. 18-19.
29I
—
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
of sky and earth, of hill and valley’, but it may be doubted
whether ‘impulses of deeper birth have come to them in
solitude’. With the scientific ‘neutralization’ of Nature
(in Dr Richards’s phrase) the heart of her mystery has been
plucked out, and the joy which she still spreads in wider
commonalty than ever, and will doubtless continue to
spread, is for the most part that of physical and nervous
regeneration rather than of spiritual assurance. As Pascal
long ago saw, Nature proves God only to those who believe
in Him already on other grounds. And the religious roots
from which the Nature-worship of Wordsworth sprang
have, I think it must be admitted, largely withered away.
One further observation of a different order may here be
added: perhaps the healing power of Nature is only felt
to the full, as Ruskin found, by those who return to it
at intervals after being long ‘in populous cities pent .
292
‘nature’ IN WORDSWORTH
to Wordsworth. There is, indeed, a certain pathos in the
circumstance that his most splendidly sustained utterance
should have been a farewell to his own visionary power.
But the power had lasted as long as the best period of most
poets, who in general are not blamed (as Wordsworth has
been) for doing their finest work before the age of forty.
The Ode occurred at a unique climacteric moment in
Wordsworth s history, and in his later work the ‘worlds
not quickened by the sun’ approximate more and more to
the orthodox heaven. But though he may always be valued
as the poet of the first and not the latter phase, this change
is the natural development of
a mystic who wishes to
improve those transient Gleams of Joy into an in-
. . .
1
Addison, Spectator, 393.
293
. , , ,
INDEX
Addison, 5, 27, 30; on ‘Chear- Beaupuy, 258, 260.
fulness,’ 45-6, 74; on the Becker, C. L., The Heavenly
Scale of Being, 51- 2; on the City of the Eighteenth Century
Creation, 65, 241, 292. Philosophers, 133, 140 n.
Aikin, Dr, 187. Bentham, Mill on, 104, 107,
Alfoxden, 255, 257, 278. 209 ; indebted to Priestley,
Ambrose, St, on private prop- 170.
erty, 15. Bentley, 39.
Aquinas, on the Law of Nature, Berkeley, and Hume, no, 1 13.
‘
J5; 47- Bernard, St, Natura codex est
Aristotle, 16; Poetics, 18 ff.; Dei ,’ 42.
eternity of the world, 35; Blackburne, Archdeacon, 187.
Nature and Art, 40; Ethics Blount, Charles, 3, 6, 8n.;
85, 10 1 189.
Arnold, Matthew, 8; on Jo- Bodin, Holbach on, 165.
seph Butler, 85; 189, 272; Boileau, on Descartes, 25.
on Wordsworth, 273. Bolingbroke, 62.
Athanasius, 190. Bougainville, 14, 241.
Atkinson, GeofFroy, works Boyle, Robert, 2, 3, 4, 38, 39-
quoted, 13. 4°, 136.
Austen, Jane, 109. Broad, Prof. C. D., Five Types
of Ethical Theory, on Butler,
Babbitt, Irving, on Shattesbury, 85> 93-
58 . Brooke, Henry, 241.
Bacon, Francis, 3, 4; Voltaire Brown’s Estimate 198, 241.
on, 106; 136; Holbach on, Browne, Sir T., 4,
on 325
165; Priestley on, 195; and ‘Virtue isown Reward,’
her
Burke, 245. 59; on Charity, 60 and ;
295
,
296
; ,. ,
INDEX
De Selincourt, Prof. E., and Franklin, Benjamin, and Priest-
Wordsworth’s Borderers 268. , ley, 169, 187, 188; and
Dickens, 108. Godwin, 234.
Dickinson, G. Lowes, dfter
Two Thousand Tears 104. , Gaius, 15.
Diderot, Supplement au Toy age Galen, 42.
de Bougainville, 14, 241; 55. Galileo, 3, 5.
Dissenting Academies, 1 85- Garrod, Prof., 21 n.
187, 214. Gay, Rev. John, and Hartley,
Doddridge, Philip, 185, 214. 138,140, 143.
Dryden, 1; Religio Laid , 8-9 Gibbon, Priestley on, 172-3,
on Denham, 18; on the 19 1-3; oh Oxford, 185; 188;
‘natural’ in poetic diction, on Progress, 200-01.
19; ‘Nature wrought up to Gibson, Bishop, on Samuel
an higher pitch,’ 21; 25; Clarke, 60.
100; ‘more delightfully than Gilbert, W., 3.
Nature,’ 149. Godwin, and Hartley, 5
1 1
297
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Harper, Prof., on Wordsworth, 276; on recollecting boy-
254 . hood, 283.
Hartley, 112; 136-54; and Hulme, T. E., ‘spilt religion,’
Holbach, 155; and Priestley, 281.
168, 170, 174, 178, 180, Hume, 57, 67, 108; 110-35;
186, 188, 209, 228; and 136, 137; an d Hartley, 149;
Wordsworth, 137, 143, and Holbach, 155; on His-
144 145, 147, 149; and
n., tory, 200; 208.
Coleridge, 136-7, 144 n., Hutcheson, 108, 112, 15 1.
146, 147, 194, 277. Hutchinson, Mary, 279.
Harvey, W., 3. Huxley, Aldous, on Words-
Hastings, Warren, 242. worth, 64, 273; on ‘Behe-
Havers, Clopton, 38. moth and Leviathan,’ 83 n.;
Hazard, Paul, on the Deists,- on Swift, 102, 108 n.; on
1 1. War, 225 n.
on Godwin, 212, 217,
Hazlitt,
221-2, on Inchbald, Mrs, 241.
235, 238-9;
Burke, 240; on Words-
Jebb, Dr J., 178.
worth, 273.
Jenyns, Soame, Free Enquiry
Hegel, 1 61.
into the Nature and Origin
Helvetius, 155; and Godwin,
of Evil, 48-55; IOO.
214, 216; Burke on, 247.
Johnson, Dr, 24, 48-9 on ;
Herbert of Cherbury, Lord, 7,
Soame Jenyns, 50-5; 84;
189.
‘general properties and large
Herder, on Shaftesbury, 57-8.
appearances,’ 21 1.
Hoadly, Bishop, 199.
Jus Gentium 14-15. ,
Hobbes, 54, 57; Shaftesbury
on, 59, 67-9, 72-3, 74; Karnes, Lord, 241.
Butler on, 87; and Mande- Kant, 97; and Hume, 111.
96;
ville, Hume on, 124m; Keats, 267.
and Hartley, 142, 15 1; and Kepler, 3.
Holbach, 159, 160; and Kippis/Dr, 214.
Priestley, 176.
Holbach, 55; and Hartley, 152;
Knight, Prof. G. Wilson, 285 m
Systeme de la Nature , 155- Laing, Prof., on Hume, 1 1 1.
298
INDEX
La Rochefoucauld, 87. Mandeville, 54, 88; Fable of
Lavoisier, 169, 170. the Bees 95-1 00; and Swift,
,
299
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
century views on, 138-40; Pufendorf, 14.
156; Holbach on, 162. Puritanism, and ‘rationalism,’
10; and eighteenth century
Origen, 77. Dissent, 182-3.
‘Oxford’ Group, 227.
Quantock Hills, 257.
Paine, Tom, 205, 216. Quesnay, 198.
Paley, 35; contrasted with Quintana, R., The Mind and
Butler, 85; 128, 169. Art of J. Swift 104 n.,
Spenser, 17.
Spinoza, Omnis existentia est Unitarianism, and
168, 181;
44; Holbach
perfectio, on, Deism, 182-3; Priestley con-
162, 165; 256. verted to, 187; 213.
Spiritual Quixote , 83. Utopias, 12, 104-05; God-
Sprat, Thomas, 24. win’s, 231.
Stephen, Leslie, 2, 227; on
Burke, 240; on Words-
Vespasian, 129.
worth, 273.
Voltaire, 37, 49, 55,
Stillingfleet, Bishop, 35. 77;
Candide 84, 100;
, Lettres
Stoics and Stoicism, 14, 44, Philosophiques , 105-07; icra-
70, 85, 101 , 229.
sez Linfame 120; ‘il est
Streit, Clarence K., Union Now ,
deiste,’
,
and
163; Priestley,
252 n.
202; Burke on, 247.
Swift,100-09; an( i Godwin,
216, 231, 239.
War, Priestley on, 203; God-
Tahiti, 14. win on, 225-6.
Tawney, Prof., Religion and Watson, Bishop, Wordsworth’s
the Rise of Capitalism , 183. Letter to, 261-3.
Taylor, Jeremy, Burke com- Watt, James, 188.
pared with, 247, Wesley, John, 35, 55, 109.
301
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY BACKGROUND
Whewell, on Joseph Butler, Wordsworth, Dorothy, 253>
84-5. 257, 271, 282, 291.
Whichcote, Shaftesbury’s edi- Wordsworth, William, 24, 3°>
tion of Select Sermons , 58- ‘Thought was not,’ 43-4;
61. Aldous Huxley on, 64; and
White, W r
. Hale, see ‘Mark Hartley, 137, 143, 144 n.,
Rutherford.’ 145, 147, 149; 167, 194,
Whitefield, 109. 205-07, 277 compared
;
W r
hitehead, A. N., 126. with Thomson, 210; ‘Be
Whitney, L., on ‘primitivism,’ thankful thou,’ 21 1; and
69 n. Godwin, 212, 213, 217-
Wilkins, Bishop, 35, 38; on 218, 221, 222, 228, 235,
Nature and Art, 40-1, 149 n. 238, 239, 253, 257, 260-
Withering, botanist, 188. 271; and Burke, 240, 242,
Wollaston, 3} Religion of 244, 248, 249, 253, 261,
Nature, 86. 262; and Coleridge, 253,
Wollstonecraft, Mary, 205, 270, 273,
" 274, 278, 286;
216, 238, 241. 253-93*
B1301
WB Willey, Basil
c.l Eighteenth century back-
ground.