The Great Philosophers-1 - Nodrm
The Great Philosophers-1 - Nodrm
The Great Philosophers-1 - Nodrm
The Great
Philosophers
Volume III
Karl Jaspers
The Great
Philosophers
Volume III
ogi
PHILLIPS-ACADEMY #
o§3
f O LI VER-WENDELL HOLMES
I LIB RARY
# i\
# ._,_.
gj ^er ajnphcra [ 7c*-f'A§ a£ altiora. g
#
v*! ## 1gjjOigugiffi
r>
t
\
Other worlds by Karl Jaspers available in English translation
VOLUME 3: METAPHYSICS
PHILOSOPHY OF EXISTENCE
WAY TO WISDOM
History of Philosophy
NIETZSCHE: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE UNDERSTANDING
OF HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ACTIVITY
Psychology
GENERAL PSYCHOPATHOLOGY
'■ *'»«
'
-»
1
KARL JASPERS
f-
THE GREAT
PHILOSOPHERS
XENOPHANES DEMOCRITUS EMPEDOCLES BRUNO
EPICURUS
BOEHME SCHELLING
LEIBNIZ
ARISTOTLE HEGEL
JAN 24 1995
\
Requests for permission to make copies of any part of the work should be mailed to:
Permissions Department, Harcourt Brace & Company, 8th Floor, Orlando, Florida 32887.
XENOPHANES
I. Life 9
IV. God 12
V. The Ethos /5
VIII. Characterization 18
DEMOCRITUS
I. Democritus’ Atomism 21
1. The Theory in Outline 21
2. The Solution of the Difficulties 22
vii
Contents
Dignity 30
IV. Characterization 31 \
EMPEDOCLES
I. The Theory 36
1. The World-Vision as a Whole 36
2. Specific Natural Phenomena 40
3. The Significance of This Conception of Nature 42
V. Empedocles’ Self-consciousness 52
BRUNO
EPICURUS
Introduction 67
Life and Works 67
Survey 69
1. What Is Pleasure? 70
Introduction 113
BOEHME
I. Life 117
SCHELLING
Work 143
LEIBNIZ
Introduction i8y
ARISTOTLE
8. Philosophy 275
HEGEL
A. Sense-Certainty 222
Exposition 222
Reflections 225
Comment 23/
B. The Becoming of Self-consciousness; Mastery and
Servitude; the Further Progress of Self-consciousness 23/
1. The Becoming of Self-consciousness 231
Fragments 288
BIBLIOGRAPHY 299
INDEX OF NAMES 3° 5
« 1
H,
-
“The reader reveals himself in the process of understanding.
—Karl Jaspers
Foreword
xv
XVI Foreword
along indirect and often unfamiliar byways, working our way through
others’ efforts toward such wisdom. Jaspers’s “way of wisdom”—to use
the title of one of his most celebrated works—is not solitary inner
reflection, freewheeling speculation, or abstract word-watching. It is only
through communication with others that we come to ourselves.
Jaspers would take satisfaction from the fact that he has remained a
controversial thinker, for such contested status would attest to the un¬
settling function of philosophy itself, while confirming his role at its vital
core. His writings have been translated into more than twenty languages
and have gone through many editions all over the world. He is widely
and popularly known, perhaps to an extent that does not always enhance
his reputation as an academic philosopher. For readers in many countries
and cultural traditions, he has assumed a secure place in the company
of the great philosophers he wrote about; he is present in many an¬
thologies of modern thought.
Yet he is also sometimes considered a throwback to philosophy’s
grand but faded past, rather than a decisive force in its present and
future. Despite his own strictures against much of metaphysics and the
philosophy of history, he is branded by some a nostalgic metaphysician
or philosopher of history in disguise. It has been said that he is more a
relic-bound historian of philosophy than an original philosopher in the
genuine sense.
He would have observed that these critical, even nullifying charac¬
terizations say as much about their source, and the orientation of that
source in the larger tradition of philosophy, as they do about him. He
was given to quoting Kierkegaard’s warning about popularity and its
price (“When it is fashionable to read my books, then I will be mis¬
understood”); but he also constantly emphasized that even misunder¬
standing can be productive in shedding light on what we strive to
understand.
His thinking remains both timely and perennial, both time-bound
and time-conscious in a way difficult to convey. The reader will come
to feel a tensile relationship between his commitments: between an abid¬
ing past and an urgent present; between respect for the metaphysical
heritage of philosophy and for modern scientific rigor; between regard
for religion, myth, and poetry and concern about current issues in politics,
international affairs, and educational reform.
He was in his age but not wholly of it. He stood “athwart his age,
like a rock in a stream,” to use the image of his contemporary Golo
Mann. Such was the posture Jaspers attributed to the ancient sages,
Foreword XVII
more and more for granted, including its forms of understanding, and
therefore blocking off many sources of philosophical thinking. Philos¬
ophy then becomes doubly undermined, from within and from without,
as its radical questioning comes to be deployed against itself, converging
with indictments from other modes of thinking. Philosophy thereby
comes to be suspected rather than expected in the modern world. Jaspers’s
path through this quandary was to retrace its stages in a world-history
of philosophy—not through the tortured deconstructive etymologies of
Heidegger, but in dialogue with the great thinkers of the past.
The history of philosophy remains integral to its essential task and
is especially important today precisely because we pride ourselves on
self-surpassing novelty. This history shows, not progress, but openness;
it serves to keep questions open rather than to resolve them or dissolve
them. The axial ideas of the past are still with us, although often un-
reflectively; the history of philosophy retrieves these ideas without sur¬
rendering their activating power. As Jaspers says over and over: “The
deeper our foundations in the past, the more outstanding our partici¬
pation in the present.”
His histories remain as controversial as his systematic philosophy
(with which they are co-eval), because they engage the reader in a
strenuous dialogue, in which textual refinements are subordinated to the
issue under discussion. Through his long career as professor of philos¬
ophy, Jaspers was impatient with what he called “professors’ philosophy,”
which vested primary questions in cumbersome commentary and qual¬
ifications. The Great Philosophers treats Socrates, Buddha, Confucius, and
Jesus together as “paradigmatic individuals,” for example, allowing no
neat line between sages and philosophers, between lives and ideas.
Jaspers does not try to find an inner logic in a temporal sequence of
before and after; he is more inclined to step outside historical chronology
altogether. He takes history and actual historical dialectic seriously, but
not to the point of intellectual self-evisceration or denial of the possibility
of communication across time. He says of the great philosophers as a
whole that “in their suprahistorical character they are like eternal
contemporaries.”
His world-history of philosophy was intended to revitalize and de-
provincialize European and Western thought by setting it in a wider
context and approaching it from outside its customary categories and
ingrained classifications. With present tendencies toward globalization
on many fronts, especially in cultural and intellectual suppositions, Jas¬
pers’s efforts take on crucial significance. The Great Philosophers includes,
for example, studies of Nagarjuna, Lao-Tzu, Buddha, and Confucius,
XXII Foreword
Jaspers held that “the procedure for understanding texts is a simile for
all comprehension of being.” In such a view texts must retain fun¬
damental—indeed originary—significance for all thinking, but they
should not therefore be allowed to become idols of the mind. This edition,
Volumes III and IV of The Great Philosophers, aspires to convey, with a
minimum of interference, Jaspers’s understanding of other thinkers and
their texts, especially his way of addressing them through the entire
tradition of philosophy. It presents those thinkers with a deep and abiding
relation to Jaspers himself. It includes Lessing, Weber, and Einstein,
who were not philosophers in the strict sense, and excludes Aquinas and
Hobbes, among others, who were of undoubted importance.
The text has been drawn from Die grossen Philosophen: Nachlass i,
Darstellungen und Fragmente and Nachlass 2, Fragmente, Ammerlpungen,
Inventar, edited by Hans Saner, published in German in 1981. The
selections were translated by Edith Ehrlich and Leonard Ehrlich, who
have drawn upon a collaborative lifetime of close study of Karl Jaspers,
their former teacher. In format and style, the selections are in keeping
Foreword xxiii
with the earlier two volumes in English. Illuminating sections from the
large volume of Jaspers’s supplemental notes (“Zusatze”) have been in¬
corporated in the text without special note. A short bibliography has
been supplied for each volume.
/ '
Michael Ermarth
" * »
i
/
Translators’ Acknowledgments
—Edith Ehrlich
Leonard H. Ehrlich
\
v *
. *
'
'
The Projective Metaphysicians
* «i.
I
/
INTRODUCTION
Editors’ Note
3
4 The Projective Metaphysicians
XENOPHANES
DEMOCRITUS
EMPEDOCLES
BRUNO
%
■
.
*
/
7
8 Piety toward the World
lucid and vivid, seems illuminated by a light that emanates from else¬
where. Their thinking then touches upon transcendence, upon specu¬
lation, upon existential freedom. There is no classification that locks
philosophers or even human beings into compartments. Our conscious¬
ness is primarily struck by what is typical, but that does not exhaust the
human being’s potential. According to his pdtentiality, each human being
encompasses everything. In actuality no one is everything.
3. I am speaking here of something to be found in all ages. The
individual persons in the garb of the eras in which they live and think
demonstrate enduring problems of philosophy. We are interested in them
because they may concern us at any time.
XENOPHANES
The fragments of Xenophanes come from lost poetic works, from elegies,
satires, and epic poems.1 Even though the Milesians and Heraclitus
considered prose to be the more suitable form of imparting philosophy,
Xenophanes chose metrical language. Up to Hesiod and the cosmogonic
writers, poetry had been the vessel of myth possessing philosophic con¬
tent. Xenophanes made it the vessel of philosophy itself. He was followed
in this by Parmenides, Empedocles, and, later, Lucretius.
I. LIFE
Xenophanes (between 570 and 465 b.c.) is the first from the early Greek
period whose person and life we can envision, even if only in a few of
its features.
In his youth he left his home polis of Colophon because he was not
prepared to live under the hegemony of the Persians, who after 546 b.c.
had subjugated all Greek cities on the coast of Asia Minor. He went to
Sicily and Greater Greece (Southern Italy). Throughout his life he mi¬
grated from polis to polis. At the age of ninety-two, he wrote: “By now,
seven-and-sixty years have been tossing my care-filled heart over the
land of Hellas” (F8). He glorified his native country in a lost epic about
the founding of Colophon. But he also leveled critical accusations: “(The
men of Colophon), having learnt useless forms of luxury from the Lydians
as long as they were free from hateful tyranny, used to go to the place
of assembly wearing all-purple robes, not less than a thousand of them
in all: haughty, adorned with well-dressed hair, steeped in the scent of
skillfully-prepared unguents” (F3). The catastrophe brought about by
the Persians (Medes) was the great event of his life. “Talking by the fire
in winter,” he relates, the questions are: “Who are you among men and
1 Wherever this volume uses Kathleen Freeman’s translation of Diels’s Die Fragmente, the
fragment number is preceded by an F. Numbers alone in parentheses refer to B fragments in Diels;
A fragment references are preceded by an A.
9
io Piety toward the World
where from? How old are you, my friend? What age were you when
the Mede came?” (F22).
Having become homeless, Xenophanes journeyed alone through the
world, receptive to his fellowmen, rich in information about cities and
countries. His plight awakened his inner independence. Neither an aris¬
tocrat nor a citizen of a polls, he was dependent on patrons or on earning
his livelihood; was nowhere at home, yet he found the point whence he
proclaimed his wisdom (sophia).
Xenophanes has been denigrated as a rhapsodist who in public recited
the Homeric poems as a means of livelihood while in private he recited
his own poetry, which rejected Homer. An anecdote reported by Plutarch
(Reg. apophth., 175e) was quoted: Xenophanes, they said, pointed out to
his patron, the tyrant Hieron of Syracuse, that his income was too small;
he could keep but two slaves; Hieron is said to have answered: And yet
you make derisive remarks about Homer, who even after his death feeds
a great number of people—that is, rhapsodists such as Xenophanes.
must praise is he who after drinking expresses thoughts that are noble,
as well as his memory [mnemosyne] (and his endeavour) [arete] concerning
virtue allows . . . always to have respect for the gods, that is Good”
(Fn).
In this early period something is peculiar to Xenophanes that becomes
prevalent only much later, and is then turned into its opposite. Within
the solemn form in which he speaks to us there appears the enlightened
view that whatever happens in the world is natural (as against magic
and prophecies), that there is one God (as against the invention of myths
opposed to God), that there is a moral, natural way of life appropriate
to man (as against the high value set on victory at the Olympic Games
and on the fighting spirit generally), that there is an awareness of the
limitations of human cognition (as against the false claims of human
knowledge and ability).
as rain and produce the winds. “The mighty ocean is the womb of
clouds, winds and rivers” (30).
“All things that come into being and grow are earth and water”
(F29). “For everything comes from earth and everything goes back to
earth at last” (F27). “We all have our origin from earth and water”
(f 33}- '
From time to time ocean and earth have intermingled. The proof
for this is “that inland and on the mountains seashells have been found;
in Syracuse, in the rock quarries, impressions of fish and seals; in Malta,
impressions of all kinds of ocean creatures.” Xenophanes concludes that
at one time everything had turned to mud and that the impressions in
the mud had then hardened. This event can be expected to recur. “All
people would perish if the earth slid into the ocean and then became
mud. But afterwards the earth would start again to come into being,
and all worlds would be subject to this alternation” (A33).
In spite of the individual instances of sound observation, Xenophanes
represents neither the Milesian mode of thinking in systematic constructs
nor the methods of inquiry in the natural sciences. It is all a matter of
ad hoc inspiration or accidental observation or borrowings from the
Milesians or the monotonous repetition of explanations based on
“clouds.” Xenophanes did not, as was ascribed to him in analogy to
other pre-Socratics, write a book “On Nature.”
Something else was decisive for him: the mode of comprehension as
such, the rejection of mythical explanations that could not be verified.
Perhaps it did not matter to him whether this or that natural explanation
was correct or wrong. He rejected divination but admired Thales because
he predicted a solar eclipse in a natural way. According to Cicero, he
was the only one of the philosophers who, although he believed in the
presence of gods, radically rejected the belief in prophecy (On divination,
I, 3, 5). God, however, was of primary importance for him.
IV. GOD
do. But God is “similar to mortals neither in body nor in thoughts” (23).
Hence Xenophanes ridicules the adoration of the gods in the shape given
to them by Greek sculptors: “If oxen and horses and lions had hands
and could paint and sculpt with them like the humans, then the horses
would paint horselike, the oxen oxlike figures of the gods and would
form such bodies as each species itself inhabited” (15). “The Ethiopians
maintain that their gods have snub noses and are black; the Thracians
that their gods are blue-eyed and red-haired” (16).
Mortals believe that gods are born. But God did not become and is
eternal.
It seems that Xenophanes thought the fundamental thoughts of West¬
ern monotheism: oneness as opposed to the multiplicity of gods, incor¬
poreality as opposed to the representations of human and other figures,
eternity as opposed to the coming-to-be and birth of gods; God as
thought, as presence, as all-powerful efficacy; unborn, eternal, infinite,
but in ways that are beyond human imagination. What do these early
simple notions of God mean?
They are, first of all, the thoughts of the much later so-called negative
theology. By saying what God is not, he rises to his exalted height. Man
attains a level of self-consciousness by reference to this wholly incom¬
prehensible, yet actual, deity.
But Xenophanes does not stop at this negative theology. The incor¬
poreal deity achieves a rudiment of form through graphic ciphers. God
is “all eye, all spirit, all ear” (24); he needs no organs in order to see
and to know everything, but he sees and knows everything. He governs
irresistibly, without physical force. “With only the spirit’s power of
thought, He effects effortlessly the revolution of the universe” (25). He
is perfect majestic serenity. “He always remains in the same place, not
moving at all, and it is not fitting for him to go back and forth, now
here and now there” (26); that means he is everywhere.
The following seems to contradict the notion of one God: Xenophanes
speaks not only about God but also about gods. “One God is the greatest
among gods and men” (23). He speaks about gods when he describes
the solemn symposium introduced by ritual. Solemnity and ritual are
tied to the gods. For him, the one God has no cult; all cults of the gods
are directed toward him without drawing nearer to him. The symposium
as described by Xenophanes cannot be interpreted as the founding of
something like a new cult of the one God. There is no trace of a religious
founder in Xenophanes. His goal is purification, not foundation. His
piety lies in polytheistic concreteness joined to all-pervading awe before
M Piety toward the World
the encompassing One. His radicality turns against the destructive rep¬
resentations of gods, not against the many gods. The one God, however,
who eschews all shape, appears in the shapes of the gods.
This whole problem of the one^God and the many gods is not
explicitly thought through but for Xenophanes is a natural presuppo¬
sition. The great battle of the one God of the Bible against heathen
polytheism is not as yet a possibility. Hence the passion is lacking which,
in the cipher of the one exclusive Biblical God, this personal God, turns
against all false gods and all of polytheism (though not without restoring
it in another form).
One analogy remains. In the Bible: For the sake of the one God, the
world is stripped of its magic, which now becomes the object of rational
comprehension. God’s actions take place in the world, in history, which
God commands and guides through the actions of man. In Xenophanes:
For the sake of the one omnipresent God, the whole world is opened
up to rational comprehension.
The crucial difference: Xenophanes’ thinking does not include God’s
otherworldliness, or the gulf (;tmema, Plato) between God and the world.
He has no knowledge as yet of what will make its appearance with
Plato’s agathon and then with the Biblical God. Without saying so ex¬
pressly, he regards the deity as congruent with the universe. The later
One and All (hen \ai pan) is the thought of piety toward the world, with
its certainty of the one God.
Even in antiquity there was confusion in understanding Xenophanes,
confusion that has been corrected only in our times." Xenophanes cannot
be regarded as the teacher of Parmenides. Parmenides’ greatness could
not have been stimulated by Xenophanes’ mode of philosophizing. On
the other hand, the idea that the aging Xenophanes derived his conception
of God from the younger Parmenides is traceable only to the work of
an anonymous author of the Hellenistic period who wrote about Xe¬
nophanes, Melissus, and Gorgias, and was falsely regarded as a reliable
source.2 3 In this work the thinking of Parmenides and Xenophanes has
been combined in a patently absurd manner. Parmenides directs his
thought toward Being and carries out speculative thoughts, but nowhere
does he call Being God. Xenophanes, by contrast, directs his thought
toward God in his majesty and does not carry out any speculative
thoughts; by God he means neither Being''nor a concept. Parmenides
2 See Karl Reinhardt, Parmenides und die Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie. Bonn, 1916,
I26ff., I52ff.
3 Jaeger, 51-52.
XENOPHANES
*5
carries out philosophical thinking in its depth. Xenophanes exhibits the
depth of a pious consciousness of God, which excludes from his repre¬
sentation of God all that is unworthy. Parmenides’ thoughts could later
be used by speculative theology because he developed concepts. This is
not tho chse with Xenophanes because his thinking remains on the level
of mere intellect.
It is doubtful whether Xenophanes, as was said at a later time, became
a citizen of Elea. He wrote a poem about the founding of Elea, just as
he did about the founding of Colophon. What is said about him as an
Eleatic probably arose through the erroneous combination of the phi¬
losophy of Xenophanes and of Parmenides.
V. THE ETHOS
4 Jaeger, 70.
5Tr. W. Arrowsmith. Lines 1341-46.
18 Piety toward the World
VIII. CHARACTERIZATION
claims such suprahuman status for himself. For him, there is no su¬
premacy of one human being over another. Each person remains a human
being, in spite of the tremendous differences in rank.
Xenophanes addresses himself to an audience, namely, to everyman.
He did pot isolate himself to pursue lonely truth in a small circle. He
participated in human affairs, eager to enlighten and morally to purify
himself and his fellowmen.
DEMOCRITUS
Democritus (c. 460-370 b.c.) was born and lived in Abdera, on the coast
of Thrace, where he was a member of a school of philosophy. He
undertook journeys of long duration to Greece, Egypt, and the Near
East. The thought of Leukippus—the originator of atomism—was
known to Democritus through his work Megas Diakosmos (The Great
World-Order). Democritus had some contact with the Sophist Protag¬
oras, who was his senior by twenty years, possibly also with the physician
Hippocrates. He was held in high regard by his countrymen.
Democritus had no connection to Athenian philosophy. He ridiculed
Anaxagoras, who was older than he by four decades, because of his
cosmic order (dia^osmesis) and his doctrine of the mind {nous) (5). Unlike
his older compatriot Protagoras, Democritus ignored Sophist thought,
the grandiose, disintegrative mentality without which neither Socrates
nor Plato would have been possible. He knew as little about these con¬
temporaries as they about him. He is reported to have said, “I came to
Athens and no one knew me” (116). Plato never mentions him, but must
have known about his atomic theory when, in his old age, he wrote his
Timaeus. Only Aristotle mentions him, often and with great respect. The
contemplative life of discovery in the natural sciences and the ethos that
went with it could not interest Socrates or Plato. One root of their
thinking lay in practice, in the responsibility and frustration of politics,
in activism; it went beyond observation of nature, far into the supra-
sensory realm, which, in turn, would have seemed sheer nonsense to
Democritus. Aristotle says: “In Socrates’ times inquiry into nature was
abandoned and philosophers turned to the examination of practical virtue
and of politics” {De animalium partibus, I/t). But nature as well as the
sciences dealing with it were Democritus’ concern, as later on they would
be that of Aristotle, who gives as the reason for his high esteem: “De¬
mocritus seems to have speculated about everything” (A35). These were
two philosophical worlds, which did not touch and which—if they know
20
DEMOCRITUS 21
I. DEMOCRITUS’ ATOMISM
With his atomism, Democritus did not create a philosophical system that
would explain everything that exists. His areas of scientific inquiry and
realms of thought bear little relationship to atomism. What makes it all
cohesive is not atomism, but a mode of thinking that in the model of
atomism bears witness to, among other things, the totality of natural
events.
There are certain difficulties connected with the theory of the atoms if
it is to explain everything there is, difficulties that can be overcome only
by adding further presuppositions. i
a) Whence comes the suitability of living things to their purpose} In the
universe of atomic motion there is no purpose and no meaning and no
1 Wilhelm Capelle, Die Vorsoktatper, Fragmente und Quellenberichte. Leipzig, Kroner, 1935,
396ff.
DEMOCRITUS 23
order, but solely motion and mutual chance encounter. Order and, par¬
ticularly, the formation of living things come to be because only that
which is purposive achieves permanence. What has come to be by chance
vanishes quickly if it does not assume a configuration that, through
special,,unplanned accident, is capable of permanence. There are only
efficient causes, no final causes.
Democritus calls such events logos and anan\e (necessity). All that
occurs does so for a cogent reason—namely, the motion of the atoms
—and is accidental only when measured against purpose and meaning.
As letters come together to form words and sentences, so atoms come
together to become things. Just as all works of poetry and of thought
consist of just the letters of the alphabet, so all efficacious actualities in
the world, the living beings, consist of innumerable atoms.
Something else has to be added so that we may understand purpose
and meaning in accordance with their origin.
b) What is the soul? The soul consists of round atoms, the smoothest
and finest, the most mobile, like the floating atoms of fire. Aristotle tells
us that a writer of comedies maintains that Daedalus had made it possible
for the wooden Aphrodite to move by pouring mercury into her. Sim¬
ilarly, Democritus maintains, according to Aristotle, that the spherical
atoms activate the whole body through their motion, since, as is their
nature, they are never at rest (A104).
Even thinking is a bodily state and occurs when the atoms are
properly mixed. It changes when the mixture becomes too cold (A135).
In perception and in dreams, images (eidola) penetrate into the soul
as projections of themselves from all kinds of things. This is how house¬
hold utensils, clothes, plants, living things are seen in a dream (A77).
Something more, however, is needed for us to comprehend the in¬
wardness of psychic experience according to its origin. The outwardness
of atoms, no matter how fine, mobile, or fiery they may be, is not
sufficient.
c) What is cognition ? If atoms and empty space alone are constitutive
of Being, then what we perceive are appearances. Our senses do not
show us reality itself. We do not know through perception, but through
thought. This, in fact, is what Democritus says. But now he has to
explain what perception and cognition are.
What we know is never actuality itself, for only atoms and the void
are reality-in-itself and permanent. The combinations of atoms change.
All that is, is such a compound of the infinitely various atoms: things,
living beings, stars, souls, and gods. Information about all of these is
received by way of perception. Perception is due to images (eidola) pro-
24 Piety toward the World
jected from objects making contact with the senses. Hence the senses
show us only these appearances and not the actuality of the atoms and
the compounds of atoms themselves. Sense perception never shows us
atoms; only, according to customary opinion (nomos), black or yellow or
red, bitter or sweet, cold or warm, and hence never that which corre¬
sponds to the nature of things.
This essence of things—atoms and the void—manifests itself only
to thinking. Hence thinking has preeminence when it comes to truth.
There are two sorts of knowledge. To the obscure one belong sight,
hearing, smell, taste, and touch. Genuine cognition arises when obscure
cognition can do no more. When it can “neither see more minutely, nor
hear, nor smell, nor taste, nor perceive by touch—and a finer investi¬
gation is needed, then the genuine comes in . . .” (Fn), that is, thought.
According to Democritus, there are three criteria of truth. First: In
order to grasp the invisible things one has to consider the visible ones.
Second: Investigating the road is thinking. Third: For choosing and
avoiding, one listens to the emotions (pathe). “For we are to choose that
toward which we are well disposed and avoid that which is alien to us”
(Am). (We shall not deal with this third criterion here; it applies to
ethics.)
Democritus lets the senses speak: “ ‘Miserable Mind, you get your
evidence from us, and do you try to overthrow us? The overthrow will
be your downfall’ ” (F125). But this is by no means his last word. The
senses are the point of departure at every step of cognition, even though
thought surmounts the nature of appearance proper to the entire sensible
world. But the progression does not, as in Plato, move from becoming
to the eternal ideas as the primal images and to the power of the idea
of the Good which effects all and illuminates all; rather, it moves from
the sensory qualities to the everlasting forms of the atoms (also called
“ideas” by Democritus, since idea equals form).
For Democritus there are two limits of cognition. First: “We know
nothing in reality; for truth lies in the depth” (117). Our interpretation:
To be sure, thinking advances as far as actuality itself, to the atoms; yet
thinking is not able to bring about sensations; for fundamental cognition
permits only the fundamental deduction of a world of appearances and
not its complete explanation encompassing the concreteness of realities
open to experience. '
Second: “Our knowledge of actuality is never safe from deception
but changeable according to the constitution of our bodies and of those
things that flow toward and impinge upon it.” No matter how far we
DEMOCRITUS 25
progress, we remain tied not only to our senses but also to our natural
proclivities.2
d) Are there gods and what are they ? In distinction from all other pre-
Socratic schemes of Being, the atoms of Leucippus could not be termed
divine because the crude image of a spatiality replete with incompressible
little lumps made this impossible. Thus Democritus too never used the
term divine as an attribute of the atoms; that designation was given by
Anaximander, Heraclitus, and Empedocles to the ground of Being as
they conceived it. It was also possible with the Being of Parmenides and
the nous of Anaxagoras. What Democritus called divine was the nature
granted to Homer, the endowments of the soul (37) in distinction to
those of the body (21). “It is the mark of the divine intellect to be always
calculating something noble” (F112). The poets “think divine thoughts
with their mind” (F129). Democritus did not deny the gods.
In the first place, he sought to explain certain phenomena within the
framework of his theory of atoms: Demons are eidola, and these—as is
the case with sense perceptions—are thin clusters of atoms detaching
themselves from objects and pouring into the soul, in both the waking
and the dreaming state. They can be either beneficent or harmful. De¬
mocritus wished to meet auspicious images (166). These, he said, are of
supernatural size, do not pass away easily, but are not imperishable. They
make known to man the future in advance. Just as there are premonitions,
there are also tangible signs of things to come. For this reason Democritus
believed in the wisdom of inspecting the entrails of sacrificial animals,
in order to recognize the signs of health, epidemics, bountiful harvests,
or crop failure (A138).
For Democritus these belong to the realm of natural realities that
properly do not concern God or the great gods; they are explicable within
the framework of nature as it is conceived in accordance with the theory
of atoms.
In the second place, Democritus sought to derive the fact that men
believe in gods from the nature of man. If the gods are put in doubt,
and if, as with nature generally, the nature of man is the subject of
thought and investigation, then the question arises how the belief in
gods originated. For this belief in itself constitutes a reality even if gods
did not exist.
When prehistoric men saw what happened in the space above, such
as thunder and lightning, the conjunction of stars, and the eclipse of sun
2 Capelle, 428ff.
26 Piety toward the World
and moon, they were struck by fear, since they believed that divine
beings were the originators, of these phenomena. Hence Democritus
began to explain the ideas about gods as being based on natural phe¬
nomena: Ambrosia, the food of the gods, is the vapor that nourishes the
sun (25).
Other sources are the sense of guilt and the fear of punishment,
which, added to the belief in an afterlife (a belief that Democritus
repudiates), turn into fear of the gods.
In the third place, however, Democritus has an entirely different
conception of God, which is neither confirmed by the eidolon theory nor
in any way relates to the theory postulating a psychological origin of
belief in gods. Rather, it has its origin in his philosophizing, in which
the theory of atoms and encyclopedic scientific inquiry are only partial
areas.
Democritus speaks of the early sages (the logoi, thinking men) as
though they were still valid prototypes for the philosopher of his day—
his own prototypes. They did what was essential: “Of reasoning men,
a few raised their hands toward the place which we Greeks now call
‘air’ and said: Zeus considers all things, he knows all and gives and takes
away all and is king over everything altogether” (30). These early sages
prophesied as individuals to the nations. It is an image that makes us
think of the actuality of Moses but simultaneously reveals the dim dis¬
tance from this historic reality. Yet this precisely is philosophy: the trust
in insight in view of the all-embracing divinity, the will to become
authentically human on this path, and the expectation that all men can
enter upon it. Democritus clothed divine efficacy in the language of
popular religion:
“But the gods are the givers of all good things, both in the past
and now. They are not, however, the givers of things which are bad,
harmful or non-beneficial, either in the past or now, but men them¬
selves fall into these through blindness of mind and lack of sense”
(agnomosyne) (F175).
At this point, at the very inception, it becomes quite evident—though
not as a conscious element in Democritus’ thought—that the theory of
atoms as such does not necessarily lead to materialism and godlessness.
This can happen only when the atoms usurp the place of divinity. But
at the same time the unresolved contradictoriness in Democritus’ overall
conception of world and man is made evident. This is resolved only
when the theory of atoms, in a particular science, is taken to be merely
a thought-pattern for inquiry into matter, a pattern that does not de¬
termine faith or philosophy in any decisive way.
DEMOCRITUS 27
i. Overview
Democritus’ focus is the human being. His ethos has man as its origin
and goal.
What is man? Democritus repeats the dictum of the ancients: Man
is a small universe (micros kpsmos) (34).
He does not offer an interpretation of this universe. He asks what
is best for man, wherein lies his salvation. Salvation is not found in
something outward for which man exists, but in himself.
To find the solution, man must be seen according to his nature, hence
the need for psychological and physiological observation. He is body and
soul, subject to the necessities imposed on him by nature in his drives,
conditions, and situations. But man cannot be exhaustively investigated
by exclusively objective means. What he makes of what he is, is his own
responsibility. He himself is answerable for many ills, for his actions,
for his entire inner constitution. In short: As the object of inquiry, man
is a natural being; through the nature peculiar to him, he is his own
task.
What man will become is of his own choosing; it depends on his natural
endowment, which varies among individuals; he himself determines his
own goal in his substance, his dignity, his salvation.
Observation teaches us that inclination and aversion are man’s mo¬
tivating forces. “Pleasure [terpsis\ and absence of pleasure [aterpia] are
the criteria of what is profitable and what is not” (F4). Our feelings
(pathe) move us “to choose that which we like and to turn from that
which is alien to us” (Am).
But critical examination shows that it is not a matter of inclination
as such, but of the object of inclination.
3. The goal
life. The davmon does not dwell in gold and possessions but in the soul
only. “The soul is the dwelling place of the daimon” (171). This daimon
may be a good or evil genius. Democritus, in his ethical advice, postulates
the potential efficacy of a good daimon.
ForTiim, the goal is an ordering of life, a state of the soul. He does
not use the term eudaimonia but designates it by a variety of terms:
joyousness (euthymia), well-being (euesto), imperturbability (ataraxia),
steadfastness (athambia), a state free of apprehension (athaumastia), se¬
renity (galene), harmony (symmetria) of the soul.
There are two ways to reach the goal (telos).
One might see the desired state of the soul as a consequence of
inclination away from perishable things toward things exalted and eter¬
nal, in the purity of motives, in the fulfillment of obligations. This advice
to seek after noble things might easily be interpreted as not posited for
its own sake but because of its influence on the state of the soul (hence
as a means to an end).
The other way points to psychological motivation and seems to cal¬
culate what would further a tranquil state of the soul.
Our own question to Democritus might be whether the state of the
soul as such should be given this ultimate value. Does this calculated
purpose not throw a shadow over whatever great and beautiful aims
men set themselves? Is it not self-limiting in scope, regressive?
An ethical mode of thought such as this is shot through with am¬
biguity. It allows psychological motivation derived from natural attri¬
butes to intermingle with ethical motivation based on substantial
meaning. The nobility of the true is damaged by psychological advice
(such as comparing oneself with those who are worse off); in such
borderline cases this amounts to advice to adopt a base attitude as ad¬
vantageous to our well-being.
Thus there evolves a mode of thinking restricted to the aim of
achieving purely human tranquillity. The goal here is the condition of
the individual, his cheerfulness, not an elevation of spirit whether in fear
or in bravery, or in facing one’s destiny with the powers of love and
reason. The tragic element of life disappears from our range of vision.
Destiny is eliminated. The contentment of contemplation is sufficient
unto itself. The trials and dangers inherent in life are to be expunged,
risk is to be avoided. The meaning of life finds its fulfillment in the
private sphere, or, rather, in that of the single individual, in his peace
of mind. We shall see how this ambiguity manifests itself in further
developments as they are particularized: the excellent insights and the
disconcerting absolutization of the banality of existence.
Piety toward the World
\
Rarely does Democritus mention a god by name. But the title of one of
his works is Athene (Tritogeneia, thrice-born) (2). He calls this goddess
“prudence” (phronesis). “However, out of this prudence arises this triad:
thinking well (halos), speaking appropriately, and doing one’s duty.”
Thinking, intellect, reason (logis, logismos, nous, phronesis) is the
wellspring of the good, the means for shaping one’s life, the goal reached
by way of disinterested cognition. This is philosophy (still called sophia),
and philosophy produces joyousness.
The goal of the ethos is euthymia, the tranquil state of the soul, which
is well-being, pure happiness in contemplation of the beautiful, inde¬
pendence and freedom.
This happiness is in harmony with nature. It is characteristic of how
Democritus views the ages of man and death.
He compares the ages of man without regrets, without yearning for
the past, and without impatience for the future. To each age he apportions
what is proper to it, and refrains from comparing them.
For Democritus, death is not an object of dread, but a fact of life.
There is no life after death. This is a mere fable invented out of fear
about what follows death. It is foolish to avoid thinking about death
because of fear, and to want to quicken the pleasures before death comes
upon us unawares (ia).
Yet whoever studies Democritus has to become aware of the shadow
that darkens these insights, as the soul’s state of euthymia becomes the
ultimate goal.
Democritus nowhere asks whether this very state he postulates for
each human being does not require something beyond it, whether it can
be attained in this world without fulfillment through something else.
This something, it is true, leads to peace of soul, but again and again
breaks through tranquillity in a movement that allows us to rise above
ourselves by the force of restlessness. According to Democritus, neither
pleasure nor tranquillity as a state of mind is the ultimate goal. Instead,
the question is always not only pleasure in what, but also tranquillity
through what.
In his concrete value judgments it is evident that Democritus does
not address this question in its substance: vide his fundamentally apo¬
litical attitude, his comments on women and children. Even friendship,
DEMOCRITUS 31
IV. CHARACTERIZATION
to live, without God, in tranquillity, serene and active, without fear and
without a trace of despair. '
Alongside all this we discover a plenitude of posited problems with
regard to questions of knowledge, Tut an absence of problems in the
existential realm. Such reasonableness does not correspond to the great
matter-of-factness of reason, but reveals an obliviousness of man’s con¬
cern in the face of his limits. This thinking contains a tendency to banality
even as we view the pinnacles fleetingly attained by him along his way.
Though deeply moved by a notion of the dignity of man, Democritus
touches on it only marginally, that is, without making it an integral part
of the totality of his thinking. Here too, as with everything else, he brings
openness to his contemplation; similar in this, perhaps, to the early sages
who looked up to divinity and proclaimed it. When he touches on delight
in the beautiful and the great, on duty recognized and fulfilled, on self-
examination and the notion of inner purity, he does not inquire into
their origin. Their ground lies solely in themselves. As an autonomous
being, the person sufficient unto himself sees the beautiful, recognizes
the ought, and has commerce solely with himself. He does not need
transcendence and does not inquire after it. Thinking so blatantly and
exclusively rooted in nature leaves beyond the horizon the mystery of
perplexities, the possibility of higher orders through which those natural
orders are fulfilled, their insufficiency revealed, and in the end penetrated
and transcended.
We see here the fundamental mind-set of piety toward nature. All
that is human is nature and conceived as nature. Tranquillity lies in
contemplating the fullness of a world without end.
This interpretation of nature is based on the following principle: As
the world is conceived as arising from the atoms, so the sublime from
the lowly: rationality grows from necessity, culture from necessity and
need, religion from fear. Everything in the world comes to be through
the motion of the smallest parts (the atoms); everything among men, out
of the attributes and actions of individuals. All becoming is development:
all that has come into being and to completion, everything large is derived
from the smallest that did not come to be, from the simple, the incom¬
plete, the insignificant. This kind of thinking denies meaning and pur¬
pose to what occurs. Everything is accessible to natural causal explanation.
The relationship of the three origins (theory of atoms, encyclopedic
knowledge, ethos) seems to be the following: Perfect tranquillity resides
in knowledge; it brings about man’s absorption in the unchanging, in
the things that are “not mortal.”
This knowledge finds its perfection in the theory of atoms, which is
DEMOCRITUS 33
the cognition of what authentically is and of all there is. The fundamental
mind-set of the person who philosophizes in this manner finds sufficient
satisfaction in the theory of atoms.
This is a rich world-philosophy, a highly disciplined individualistic
ethos. But this self-satisfied thinking breaks down again and again,
astonishingly, pitifully obtrusive—symbolized by the theory of atoms as
the authentic knowledge of Being.
EMPEDOCLES
The span of Empedocles’ life is usually given as sixty years, the date of
his birth supposed to be around 490 b.c. (cf. Diog. Laertius, VIII, 52,
74). His native city was Akragas (today Girgenti), at that time one of
the wealthiest and most splendid cities of Sicily. He was of noble birth
and a member of the democratic faction. It is said that he was exiled in
his old age and that he died in the Peloponnese following an accident
(a fall from a carriage).
Sicily was then at its historical apex. Following the victory over the
Carthaginians at Himera in 481 b.c. (contemporaneous with the Greeks’
victory over the Persians at Salamis), rapid colonial development in the
sixth century led to its highest flowering. The catastrophe began in
409 b.c. with the destruction of Selinus and Himera by the Carthaginians,
the saving of Syracuse by Dionysius, a series of wars. The risky nature
of life lived in great insecurity and among rapid changes engendered a
tendency toward excess. Temples of enormous size, only partially com¬
pleted, were in keeping with the pride of the citizens and the merciless
exploitation of the vanquished, like the captive Athenians who perished
in 413 b.c. from working in the stone quarries of Syracuse. It was believed
that protection of the gods could be gained through the splendor of
religious worship. The style of Sicilian life presented itself to the Greek
world in its grandiose participation in the Olympic Games, in splendid
festivities, in the development of a sophisticated culinary art, ostentatious
dress, and every kind of gratification.
The true greatness of this Sicily, however, was owed to the spirit of
its poetry, its rhetoric, its thought. A high-mindedness towering above
the ordinary found expression there. As an example: a heroon (monu¬
ment) erected by his Sicilian enemies honored a youth killed in battle,
celebrating his beauty, according to Herodotus. But among all the won¬
ders that Sicily produced, says Lucretius, the most splendid is Empedocles
(De rerum natura, I, 716fF.).
34
EMPEDOCLES 35
I. THE THEORY
a) Love and strife; the four roots of all things. The state of the world varies.
There are periods in which things are better or worse than today.
Two fundamental forces are the cause of motion: love and strife
(philia and neifos). They contend with each other. If love achieves preem¬
inence, the perfect state of harmony, of the sphere (“sphairos”) prevails.
EMPEDOCLES 37
Thus, what is endures. Thus, what endures are the four roots of things
(elements) and the two forces, love and strife: “in so far as they never
cease their continuous exchange, in this sense they remain always un¬
moved (unaltered) as they follow the cyclic process” (F17); but in so far
as things arise out of them, these things have no constant time (empedos
aion). Never shall love and strife cease to be; they were before and also
will be and never will for ineffably long time (aspetos aion) be free of
them. The whole of the time that returns in the %yf{los is Being that is
no longer enclosed. If, as it were, time in the sphatros stops for a moment,
then strife “has reached the outermost limits of the kyklos” (35), but it
is and remains there. At the turning point at which it could be completed,
the kyklos begins anew.
2) The other fundamental idea underlying Empedocles’ world-vision
is the following: Being as a whole does not remain constantly the same.
Instead, within the chronological sequence, the opposites that bring about
this sequence themselves become different phenomena.
Heraclitus, says Plato {Sophist, 242d), sees the opposites coming to¬
gether and separating. Compared with this stricter understanding, the
gentler one of Empedocles (the “Sicilian Muse”) has weakened the state¬
ment that it is such for all eternity by the assertion that, in turn, the
universe is either united in love under the influence of Aphrodite, or,
in a state of enmity against itself, it becomes a multiple. The strict view
holds to the combined action of the opposites; the gentle view envisions
a successive process implying distress and restoration. In Empedocles
unity resides only in sphairos or in the world-process as a whole, whereas
in Heraclitus it resides in every present moment. In Empedocles unity
is lost to the extent that harmony does not embrace its opposite but is
brought about by elimination of the opposing calamitous divine power
of the nei\os. Hence Heraclitus is able to call strife the father and king
of all things; but Empedocles calls it calamity.
Being can be understood in the phenomena of the world only through
the power of the One, of love. Yet it contains a counter force as the
ground of the multiple and as that which does not allow the work of
love, the sphairos, to endure; but, instead, destroys it.
The doctrine of the migration of the soul states that the soul assumes
one body after another, entering into many forms of life. “I have been
born as boy, girl, plant, bird, and mute sea fish” (117).
2. Guilt
become lions . . . but among the trees [they become] laurel” (127). “But
ultimately they become seers and bards and healers and princes among
men on earth, from which they grow upward as gods, those richest in
honor” (146). Finally they are again “companions of the hearth of the
other imfnortals, fellow partakers at table, exempt from human suffering,
indestructible” (147), the image of the community of the blessed.
Quite different is the fate of the guilt-ridden daimones. “It is the
decree of necessity, a decision of the gods, ancient, arch-eternal, sealed
with broad oaths: if one . . . sullied himself with the blood of murder
. . . committed perjury,” then he must “roam for thrice ten thousand
horae far from the company of the blessed, being born, in the course of
time, in all possible shapes of mortal creatures that tread the laborious
paths of life. For the powerful air chases him to the sea, the sea spews
him onto the earth, the earth to the rays of the blazing sun, and the sun
throws him into the whirlwind. One takes him over from the other but
all hate him. Now I am one of those, too, a man banished by god and
erring, since I put my trust in raging strife” (115).
What should you do in order to put your daimon back on the right path?
“To sober up from evil” (144). For if you are “torn this way and that
by vile evildoing you will never free your heart from wretched torment”
(i45)-
The main commandment: Do not kill animals, eat no meat, and
make no bloody sacrifice. Because these beings lacking reason are related
to us, we stand in communion with them as we do with the gods. “Will
you never cease from this clashing slaughter? Do you not see how you
tear each other to pieces in the thoughtlessness of your minds?” (136).
Empedocles also prescribes certain rites peculiar to the Orphics and
Pythagoreans: Keep away from beans; do not touch the leaves of the
laurel tree, which belongs to Apollo (140, 141).
4. Immortality
For Empedocles, man, as a natural being, is mortal, as are all things put
together by mixing and later dissolved (15). Immortality is the attribute
of whatever neither comes to be nor passes away as phenomena change,
but endures as foundation. Immortal in this sense are the four elements
and love and strife. For being to become nothing is unthinkable (12).
There is only mixing and exchange of what has been mixed (8). Birth
46 Piety toward the World
and death are merely names for these processes. As things circulate
through each other, they become different things at different times, and
thus it goes in all eternity (17).
There is an entirely different irfimortality, the immortality of the
daimones which we are. We have fallen out of the bliss of their company
and strive to return there, being, in this world, merely “clad in the alien
cloak of the flesh” (126).
Empedocles’ theory of the world and his message of salvation did not
fully satisfy him. In his questioning, he goes further: By what means do
I know? What is cognition and what is its effect? Which cognition is
true? It is only through reflecting on cognition that Empedocles achieves
self-awareness.
1. The senses
cognize in purity with our whole being do we become one with things
as we cognize. The relation of the knower to the known is a relationship
between equals grounded in world-being.
/ '
“If the eye were not sun-like, it could never see the sun.” In Goethe’s
dictum we find again a theme that, originating with Empedocles and
continuing with Plotinus, runs through the ages.
In man there is everything. Hence the statements: “We see Earth by
means of Earth, Water by means of Water, divine Air by means of Air,
and destructive Fire by means of Fire; Love by means of Love; Strife
by means of baneful Strife” (109).
This corresponds to the view that there is an unrestricted relationship
between man and everything else. Empedocles maintains that we have
something in common not only with fellowmen and the gods but also
with the nonrational animals.
Things in the world are held together through the love (philia) that
unites all. She is “believed to be implanted in mortal limbs also; through
her they think friendly thoughts and perform harmonious actions, calling
her Joy [gethosyne] and Aphrodite” (F17).
Even though men are related to all things animate and inanimate
(even plants know longing and sorrow and joy); even though everything
in the world shares “in breathing and smell” (102), “in consciousness
(phronesis) and in thought (noema)” (no), Empedocles speaks of cognition
only in reference to human beings.
Since man resembles the object of his cognition and bears resemblance
to all, the elements as well as the gods, his cognition appears to be
unlimited. But since, being human, he is limited, his cognition is subject
to the condition imposed by his finiteness. From this arise his great
opportunities as well as his great errors. Empedocles shows us both.
a) The whole. Truth is the whole; untruth is the result of division
and narrowness and of exaggerating the particular to be everything.
Hence Empedocles, “. . . Touching on summit after summit, does not
want to follow a single path of discourse to the end” (F24).
But the whole “cannot be grasped by eye or ear, nor can it be
encompassed by man’s mind” (2). This extraordinary feat was possible
48 Piety toward the World
only to men of the early ages who, using all their mental powers, saw
with ease each particular of all that is (129).
b) Lif{e strengthens li\e. I am, or become, what I cognize because like
is awakened when it encounters like. Hence Empedocles warns us of
that which dulls: the paltry, lowly, and false. Cognition possesses “truth
in a sense other than mere accuracy: through its object and through the
appropriateness of the thought to this object. Hence: “Greatly blessed is
he who earned a treasure of divine thoughts for himself, but wretched
he in whom dwells a dark delusion about the gods” (132).
c) The power of cognition. True cognition confers power. “If you,”
Empedocles says to Pausanias, “take these teachings deep into your firm
mind and view them, well-disposed, with your pure effort,” only then
does thinking become power. Otherwise it would be no more than a
diverting intellectual occupation. What we cognize is not only at our
disposal for a lifetime, but man himself is changed: this cognition grows
into the ethos of man “according to each man’s nature” (no).
The power of cognition and of what is cognized is not there for the
taking. It must be earned: “Friends, I know that Truth is present in
the story that I shall tell; but it is actually very difficult for men, and
the impact of conviction on their minds is unwelcome” (F114).
d) The limits of man. Empedocles recognizes the limits of human
cognition with modesty and awe. When he promises Pausanias that he
will discover the truth, he adds immediately, “not more than mortal
intellect can attain” (F2). He calls out to the muse: “I beseech thee also,
much-wooed white-armed maiden Muse, convey (to me) such knowledge
as divine law allows us [ephemeral] creatures to hear, driving the well-
harnessed car [of song] from (the realm of) Piety!” And, as a warning,
he adds: “Nor shall the flowers of honour paid to fame by mortals force
you at least to accept them on condition that you rashly say more than
is holy—and are thereupon enthroned on the heights of wisdom!” (F3).
e) The promises. In his book On Nature, Empedocles promises Pau¬
sanias powers arising from his cognition that seem to contradict his
earlier teachings: “You shall learn all the drugs that exist as a defence
against illness and old age; for you alone will I accomplish all this. You
shall check the force of the unwearying winds. . . . And again, if you
wish, you shall conduct the breezes back again. You shall create a sea¬
sonable dryness after the dark rain for mankind, and again you shall
create after summer drought the streams that nourish the trees. . . . And
you shall bring out of Hades a dead man restored to strength” (Fin).
What does this mean? Obviously magic, that is, power through
knowledge of nature by means of cognition, without causational me-
EMPEDOCLES 49
diation. These verses were thought to be a parody. But more likely they
need a different interpretation.
Contemplation of that which is has an effect on the contemplator.
The experience that, through knowledge, I myself become effective tes¬
tifies to fhe power of thinking. Another, highly dubious experience is
added to this obvious one. My experience of being linked to and at one
with all nature turns into the belief that I participate in effecting what
nature has brought about—moreover, in a manner heightened by my
consciousness of such knowledge. This grandiose error of man’s union
with the processes of nature, experienced in thinking, runs through all
the ages.
Within his view of the whole, Empedocles arrived at his methods
of healing. Magical-cognitive consciousness is linked to specific medical
operations as the theory of the world-vision is linked to the understanding
of specific natural phenomena. This world-vision together with the mag¬
ical knowledge grounded in it becomes the means of medical practice.
The world-vision itself arose in a way quite distinct from that of
theoretical knowledge. The universal linkage of all beings is supposed
to create a knowledge that, in the end, amounts to an illusion. This
illusion indulges itself in unfounded metaphysical assertions. It had been
radically rejected already by the contemporary empirical physicians of
the school of Hippocrates, whose methods were built by piling obser¬
vation upon observation.
4. Not a system
1) In the sphairos of love the mighty battle begins anew. Why? Be¬
cause “the time was fulfilled.that is laid down for each of them in turn
in a tightly bound sworn covenant” (30).
2) Four elements and two forces'constitute the aspects of the world.
But then, where is the ground of the whole, the one that orders and
rules them? Empedocles’ answer: They “are all equally strong and
equally ancient in their origin but each of them has a different function,
each its specific manner, and each in its turn gains ascendancy in the
revolution of time” (17). Expressed in political analogy: The world is
not a despotism of the One, but is engaged in a mutual, eternally ordained
battle of the powers that brings about an alternating predominance.
3) Why guilt? There is something universally valid that has no
further grounding, the contravening of which brings about guilt. “The
law valid for all stretches far throughout the widely dominant ether and
through the boundless light” (135).
These thoughts at the limit mean: All events in the world are guided
by an all-embracing law, which itself is not formulated but determines
when “time is fulfilled.” All fundamental forces are integrated into a
whole that assigns to each in turn its “office” in its time and does not
permit preeminence or domination by one of these forces. All action
on the part of the daimones is subject to judgment based on the all¬
permeating, all-present law.
Is guilt itself a necessary component in the totality of subordinate
necessities? True, we are told why it is to be judged as guilt, but not
why it has occurred. Is guilt built inescapably into necessity itself? Em¬
pedocles is silent.
V. EMPEDOCLES’ SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS
Empedocles takes philosophy into the streets. He does not close himself
off from the multitudes in order to be with a few like-minded people.
“Democratically,” he addresses everybody. Crowds of enthusiasts follow
him. Let us consider his roles as political activist, as religious savior, as
helpful physician.
Politically, Empedocles did not become active as a statesman. He did
not participate in the founding of a polis. He did not establish a political
party, as was done by the Pythagoreans, who strove for government of
the polis, off and on with success, until a political catastrophe swept away
their regime.
Nor did Empedocles found an apolitical mystery religion. Though
his claim to be a savior is evident, he is also the lone individualist
unwilling to take upon himself the obligations of a founder. He proclaims
sophia as the road to salvation. This savior is himself a man steeped in
guilt and suffering like his fellowmen.
Being a physician, he wanted to help, but he did not join the scientific
and research-oriented medical community of the Hippocratics.
Empedocles was familiar with the great philosophical thought of his
predecessors: the Milesians, Pythagoras, Xenophanes, Parmenides, and
Heraclitus, as well as the religious movements. His thinking was influ¬
enced by an already developed philosophy. He was the first to summarize
a great inheritance through new fundamental ideas. These enabled him
to reconcile opposites, to accept nothing as absolute, but to assign each
54 Piety toward the World
view its proper place, as it were. The specific stringency peculiar to what
he appropriated was lost. The plasticity of a thinking open in all directions
was de facto repudiated, although Empedocles did not realize this. Par¬
menides’ thoughts about Being were; lost in the four ineradicable roots
and the sphairos, as was Xenophanes’ unconditional idea of God. The
religious movements ended in the individualization of a specific man.
Milesian-Ionian inquiry into nature disappeared in sketches which were
plausible but distractive. Empedocles is the poetizing philosopher who
cultivates many fields of expression and different impulses of faith.
Empedocles did not arrive on the scene as the late fruit of the priests
of purification and the soothsayers of the sixth century. In him operated
that mythic force which endures in the metaphysical attempts of phi¬
losophy. As itinerant savior, he performed miracles but absorbed them
into the continuity of philosophical self-consciousness. Renan said of
Empedocles that he was “Newton and Cagliostro” in one. But in his
mode of thinking he was in no way a precursor of Newton and not at
all a deceiver. Eduard Meyer called him “thinker and charlatan.”
“Thinker”—a well-chosen term if one knows what is to be understood
by it. But “charlatan”? The use of this word is incomprehensible in light
of Empedocles’ deep seriousness. It is comprehensible only as an out¬
growth of the modern scholar’s arrogance and lack of respect.
In Empedocles there operates the mythical mode of thinking that
absorbs the rational as its instrument. He carries out magical procedures,
which, in an undifferentiated way, make use of technical means. He has
visions that lack rational grounding, but also acknowledges ingenuous
discoveries and observations in nature, as well as rational mechanistic
explanations. In him is found an ever-recurring seduction: rationalized
mythical and magical thinking combined uncritically with cognition and
technique.
Aristotle speaks of Empedocles’ “clumsy manner of expression,” since
it lacks the clarity of logical deduction and does not correspond to
Aristotelian categories (.Metaphysics, 985a, 5ff). Conversely, this lack can
be interpreted favorably. In Empedocles, phenomena still emerge as the
language of eternal Being without being robbed of their mythic power
by logical-systematic thought. Wherever this happens they become empty
but gain, simultaneously, a false form of truth that fits them for doctrinal
and scholastic use. To the extent that later metaphysics has substance—
that is, considers, in its ideas, phenomena out of the ground of things
—it is closer, in its transformations, to self-interpreting and reinter¬
preting myth than to our science, which, from the standpoint of Aris¬
totelian philosophy, is pseudoscience.
EMPEDOCLES 55
/
/
Editors’ Note
57
58 Piety toward the World
perientially and applied); only later will it find its clear and final
actualization in Kepler and Galileo.
The natural philosophy of the age is essentially mythical, but it
considers itself rightly to be experiential science. Its representatives keep
their eyes open, observe and collect ad infinitum, without, however, a
guiding principle: everything marvelous and curious, all inner experi¬
ences which we understand only psychologically and subjectively, such
as apparitions, are taken to be objective substance and treated as expe¬
rience. Whatever any persons active in a practical field report about their
sphere is quickly appropriated. Thus there evolves, to be sure, a great
difference in relation to a merely deductive mythic construction, an
abstract natural philosophy; but the mass of experience remains in chaos
and experience has not yet become critical in any way. It is not yet able
to separate actuality from appearance. It falls prey to any deception. It
does not know any methods of proof. Hence it combines with the endless
supply of individual items of actual and supposed knowledge a deductive
picture of the whole, or, rather, a vision developed a priori in concepts
and then filled in everywhere with that mass of material. This natural
philosophy gives an impression of richness and fullness through concrete
intuitions of personal experience as well as through the incorporation of
all myths and fairy tales. A mysterious life is shown to us in which poetic
abundance alternates with sterile discussions of concepts which are sup¬
posed to signify cognition. It is something which endures through the
millennia, does not progress, always seems new but is actually ancient.
The modes of observing nature are still intermingled here, which is
detrimental to the progress of cogent insight. Fantasy and opinion still
smother actual cognition, which as yet cannot be differentiated from it.
This separation will occur later. But there persists the idea of a synthesis
without intermingling; the question remains whether mythic natural
philosophy is totally meaningless or what its meaning is. For this reason
it has reawakened time and again up to the present, most effectively in
Schelling and his school. To this day no such synthesis has been found.
Instead, so far only two alternatives proved to be possible: As a distinct
feature of the great and successful achievement of disciplined, truly
scientific cognition mythic natural philosophy has been completely set
aside by modern science. Or it has been reconstituted as a mere opposition
to modern science, fantastic and uncritical, romantic and ineffectual.
When we consider the natural philosophy of the Renaissance, we come
to know a world which poses problems that may concern us even today.
It is a world of thoughts and intuitions, coherent in itself, which as a
creation of the human spirit deserves to be brought to our knowledge.
BRUNO 59
1 Wilhelm Dilthey, Weltanschauung und Analyse des Menschen seit Renaissance und Reformation,
Gesammelte Schriften. Leipzig, Berlin, B. Teubner, 1921, II, 340-41.
64 Piety toward the World
Somehow the lover reaches the goal at each moment, yet remains in
motion. He always lives in,vital concrete configurations, but is always
urged beyond them, onward on the ladder into the infinite.
The infinite end of taking hold 6»f the object with love is the mystical
union. Bruno reminds us explicitly of the teachings of Plotinus and the
mystics.
The mark of heroic love is self-sacrifice, being consumed, and not
merely putting oneself at risk.
Thus the One in the lover and the One in the beloved give structure
and hierarchy to beings. The enthusiastic attitude contains a “sense of
the One” that goes beyond all rational assumptions of a monistic kind.
It is the root, the “Nothing” of the striving for unity—so empty in its
rational formulation—which is no longer a “monistic prejudice” but the
power of enthusiasm and love. This unity recurs in all realms of love;
in sexual love it receives its most concrete and paradoxical configuration.
What matters is the intention, determination, and decision that turn
the soul toward the One and toward the ultimate goal.
For enthusiasm itself contains unity. It is creative in the genius.
EPICURUS
\
" , - *
\
EPICURUS
i
/
INTRODUCTION
Epicurus (342-270 b.c.), the son of an Athenian, was born on the island
of Samos. When, after completing his military service in Athens, he
wanted to return home, the Athenians had been driven off Samos. His
father had fled to Colophon, and he followed him there.
He declared himself to be a self-taught philosopher. He did not
belong to any philosophical school but was well-versed in the writings
67
68 Tranquillity without Transcendence
1 The Fragments of Epicurus are cited in accordance with Cyril Bailey’s numbering. Where
his translations are used, the numbers or titles are preceded by a B.
EPICURUS 69
SURVEY
1. WHAT IS PLEASURE?
a) We call happiness (eudaimonia) the life of a man that has turned out
well, is in harmony with itself, is present in every moment and as a
whole. Epicurus’ fundamental question is: How does this happiness come
about? His answer: Through pleasure (,hedone).
In order to comprehend the way of salvation and to understand the
thesis that happiness lies in pleasure, we must know what Epicurus
means by “pleasure.”
b) Pleasure is baseless. It is the pure consciousness of existence as
such. Pleasure, as such, is always present but under cover and interfered
with. Hence it cannot be brought about, but can only be liberated and
restored.
For this reason pleasure is determined by negatives: freedom from
displeasure, absence of pain (alypia). “We feel a need for pleasure only
when, due to its absence, we experience pain. But if we do not feel pain,
pleasure is not needed any longer, either” (Letter to Menoikeus). Thus
the greatest pleasure does not lie, for example, in the strong, overpower¬
ing pleasure of intoxication, which is never pure, but carries displeasure
with it or has it as a consequence. Pleasure is to be increased only to the
point where pain is dissolved. It cannot rise to a higher degree.
c) As soon as pleasure has reached the point where displeasure ceases,
EPICURUS
7i
it assumes various forms by manifesting itself not only in repose but also
in motion. “Serenity of the soul and the absence of pain are quiet pleasure
experiences. For joy, on the other hand, and for gaiety motion is the
distinguishing characteristic” (Diog. Laert., X, 136). Serenity of the soul
is motionless stillness; bodily pleasure is pleasure in motion. Serenity of
soul flourishes and is grounded in the appropriate manner in which these
motions take place. Bodily pleasure is precious as such; it is essential for
the pleasure of the painless serenity of soul. Epicurus expresses this quite
boldly: “I know not how I can conceive the good if I withdraw the
pleasures of taste and withdraw the pleasures of love and those of hearing
and withdraw the pleasurable emotions caused to sight by beautiful form”
(B123).
“The beginning and the root of all good is the pleasure of the stomach;
even wisdom and culture must be referred to it” (B135). “The stable
condition of well-being in the body and the sure hope of its continuance
holds the fullest and surest joy for those who can rightly calculate it”
(B123).
d) However, bodily pleasure too is a state of the soul, and its purity
is serenity. Bodily pleasure also becomes serenity in borderline cases:
“Nothing so gladdens the soul naturally and nothing puts it into a state
of tranquillity akin to an ocean becalmed as does bodily pleasure either
present or anticipated” (N206).
Pure serenity of the soul is much more than mere bodily pleasure.
The state of the soul in this serenity is called imperturbability (ataraxia),
effortlessness (aponia), self-sufficiency (autarJ^eia). “Just as one under¬
stands, when one speaks of the stillness of the ocean, that not even the
faintest breeze ripples the waters, so does the state of the soul appear
serene and still when all disturbance ceases that might excite it.” Once
this state has been achieved it is master over the body and also a match
for physical pain. The high value ascribed to the pleasure and pain of
the body seems to be changed into its neutralization: “The sage is happy
even when he is being tortured and he moans and laments” (N211).
e) He still retains the pleasure of remembering. “We are all un¬
grateful toward the past insofar as we do not recall all the good that we
have received, whereas, after all, no pleasure is more certain than one
that cannot be taken from us any more” (N206).
But all life is lived in the present. The future is uncertain. What
matters is the present moment and hence the enduring philosophic stance
that always takes hold of what is present as the actual and certain. Horace,
the poet attuned to Epicureanism, expressed this in two words: carpe
72 Tranquillity without Transcendence
diem! Every day, at every moment pluck the fruit that life holds out to
you {Odes, I, 11, 8).-
f) Pleasure is the absolute: Since it is not grounded in something
else, it cannot be questioned further. Since it is always present, it is
timeless. Therefore, it is a matter of indifference how long it lasts,
whether for one moment, a short or a long lifetime.
Because pleasure is the absolute, it is the state of the gods. Hence
mortals who achieve the freedom of their pleasure are akin to gods.
Gods and men differ in that gods possess the perfect purity of painless
pleasure and possess it for a long stretch of time.
Philosophy “transports us into a godlike mood and lets us discover
that, in spite of our mortality, we need not fall short of the immortal
and blissful nature of the gods. For as long as we are alive we are happy
just like the gods” (Diogenes of Oinoanda; N294). “The flesh cries out
to be saved from hunger, thirst, and cold. For if a man possess this safety
or hopes to possess it, he might rival even Zeus in his happiness” (Frag¬
ments, B33).
Three paths:
the existence of the gods, he differs in regard to their nature. Most people
harbor a false picture of the gods. “For gods there are. . . . But they are
not such as the many believe them to be.” When accused of godlessness,
Epicurus replies: “And the impious man is not he who denies the gods
of the mdny, but he who attaches to the gods the beliefs of the many”
(B83, Letter to Menoikeus).
For the philosopher, the following perceptions of the gods are of
decisive import:
First: The gods are immortal and blissful beings. They do not con¬
cern themselves with human beings. They become known to men
through their eidola and man’s thinking about them. If the gods were
to concern themselves with the world and men, this would be inconsistent
with their life of sublime bliss and draw them into pain and care. Their
perfect blissful tranquillity would be disturbed.
Therefore all fear of the gods is groundless. “One must not let man
continue to believe that God is the cause of either his injury or his
advantage” (N185).
Second: The world was not created by gods, for it is full of wicked¬
ness and in this state would be unworthy of a god. Nor is it altogether
bad; rather, it is full of instances of beauty, and was not by any means
brought forth by a devil. It has come about through chance and necessity,
and happened through the motion of atoms; thus it is comprehensible
in principle in its very detail.
A god cannot have created the world. Why should he have done so?
Why should there be something novel? Was he bored? Or for the sake
of man? But man had not yet appeared on the scene, and the world
today displays so much calamity and menace for man and indifference
toward him that it cannot have been created for his sake.
If God were involved with the world, we would have to ask, in view
of all the badness and evil in it: Does God want to liberate the world
of its ills (the bad, the evil), but is unable to do so, or is he able but not
willing, or neither of the two? If he wants to and is unable, he is weak,
which is not in his nature. If he is able and unwilling, then he is envious
(malevolent), which is alien to God. If he neither wants to nor is able
to, then he is both malevolent and envious, hence again not God. If he
is willing and able, which is proper only to God, then why do these ills
exist? Why does he not do away with them? Answer: Because the world
does not exist through God, nor does he rule over it. It exists out of
itself and is left to its own devices. By its very state, the actual world
proves that God or gods have nothing to do with it.
Third: The gods live effortlessly, without work, without passions.
76
Tranquillity without Transcendence
“We are born once and cannot be born twice and life must come to an
end” (N215; Fragments, 14). The inevitability of death causes fear. But
whoever cannot find peace as he contemplates death cannot find peace
at all. Insight into the nature of death can be helpful.
1) What is death? In death the soul-atoms also are dispersed. Then
the soul, a combination of the finer soul-atoms with the organism, ceases
to be stimulated and to convey sensations. It is unthinkable that soul-
atoms are capable of feeling without organs, and organs to feel without
being part of the whole living organism. Only because the soul is enclosed
by the organism can it feel and operate, can it remember and have
consciousness.
To achieve Epicurean tranquillity, a crucial insight is necessary: With
the death of the body, the soul too passes out of existence; there is no
“after death” for the soul. This insight, once accepted, does away with
the questioning anxiety over whether nothingness is truly nothing.
The Epicurean Philodemos writes: A corpse has no feeling. The
corpse left behind after death does not contain my soul. To mistreat it
means “to mistreat mute earth” (N245). There is no difference whether
we lack sensation above or below the earth, whether we are devoured
by fishes, eaten by worms or maggots, or destroyed by fire; in each
instance we are equally insensate.
2) The consequence of this insight: Death “is nothing to us” because
what does not feel does not concern us. And it is nothing to us since
EPICURUS
77
“so long as we exist, death is not with us; but when death comes, then
we do not exist. It does not then concern either the living or the dead”
(B85, Letter to Menoikeus). There is nothing dreadful inherent in not
being alive.
It is dnfy this understanding “that makes the mortality of life en¬
joyable” (B85, Letter to Menoikeus). The wonderful thing is that I am
alive. I no longer yearn for immortality.
3) The lives of fools are wrong because they do not achieve clarity
regarding death. They neglect what there is in the present because they
are thinking about the tomorrow over which they have as yet no control.
They are consumed by vacillation and “die” in the midst of their active
lives. Now they flee death as the greatest of evils, now they seek it in
their flight from the evils of life. “It is ridiculous to throw oneself into
the arms of death because one is tired of living” (N208). “Yet much
worse still is the man who says it is good not to be born” (B87 and
Letter to Menoikeus).
4) How different the life of the sage! He neither scorns life nor fears
its cessation. He loves life.
“And just as with food he does not seek simply the larger share, but
instead the most pleasant, so he seeks to enjoy not the longest period of
time, but the most pleasant.” When he thinks of the future he is mindful
“that it is neither ours nor yet wholly not ours, so that we may not
altogether expect it as sure to come nor abandon hope of it if it will
certainly not come” (B85, 87, Letter to Menoikeus).
Metrodorus, a personal disciple of Epicurus, expresses the triumph
of the philosopher over death: “I have anticipated you, chance . . . we
shall not submit to being your prisoner nor that of any kind of circum¬
stance. But when it is time for us to leave we shall scorn life and those
who cleave to it in vain. We shall make our exit with a beautiful hymn
of praise, proclaiming how well we have lived our lives” (Fragments,
B47; Metrodorus, No. 222). The Epicurean Philodemus (first century
b.c.) gives this description of the sage’s attitude toward death: It is
impossible for death to pounce upon the wise man suddenly, like an
enemy. He knows that man is a creature that lives for a day, for whom
not only the tomorrow but even the next moment is shrouded in darkness.
He will not consider the timing of his death unreasonable or unexpected,
but will deem it miraculous should he live to an old age. He who has
become inwardly independent “counts each individual day as if he had
gained an eternity.” He accepts “every accretion of time like an unex¬
pected stroke of luck and is accordingly grateful for the course of things”
(N251). He breathes his last, when death comes, “in the knowledge that
7»
Tranquillity without Transcendence
he has enjoyed everything and will now enter a state of complete absence
of feeling” (N252). ' .
also the physical, if they bring no harm to us, but sternly reject the
harmful” (Fragments, B21).
3) Reasonable calculation—^‘weighing the beautiful against the
harmful (Letter to Menoikeus)—considers which pleasure is to be chosen
and which avoided, and even what pain to choose in order to arrive, by
paying this price, at the greatest pleasure. For it is sensible to forgo
pleasure in order to avoid greater pain, to take pain upon oneself to
achieve greater pleasure. Even though “every pleasure because of its
natural kinship to us is good,” we do not choose every pleasure. Even
though “every pain also is an evil, yet not all are always of a nature to
be avoided.” We forgo much that gives pleasure if its result would be
“a greater discomfort . . . and similarly we think many pains better than
pleasures, if a greater pleasure comes to us when we have endured pain
for a long time” (Fragments, B21).
4) The life that grows out of such considerations is not an unbridled
life of pleasure. Rather, Epicurus, without disapproving of any pleasure
as such, leads us actually to an ascetic though nonviolent life.
“We consider being content with little a great good.” “Simple food
gives the same pleasure as a fancy meal.” “Bread and water give us the
greatest pleasure if we ingest them out of a need for food.” “Becoming
accustomed to a simple and inexpensive way of life takes away appre¬
hension of fate and heightens our spirits if for once, as an exception, we
enjoy luxurious pleasures.” For he who least needs luxury knows how
to enjoy it with the greatest pleasure. In addition, “all that is natural is
easily obtained and only the superfluous is hard to procure” (Fragments,
B21).
Hence pleasure is not at all “the pleasures of the gourmandizer nor
that which is based on sensual gratification.” Not carousing, not opulent
meals, “not the enjoyment of youths and women” are, though pleasures,
the highest good. “All pleasure is subject to being judged by the yardstick
of pure pleasure” (Fragments, B21).
Thus the sage contents himself with what he possesses. Only the fool
“always whines about what he does not have.” Only “poorly endowed
souls always feel deprived” (N207).
5) Erotic joys are considered the height of pleasure. Time and again
it has been assumed that these are central to Epicurus, who is thus
changed from a philosopher of pleasure to one of lust. Not at all. Epicurus
permits them as long as they do not lead to exhaustion, do not consume
what is necessary to maintain life, and do not infringe upon laws and
morals. All that would cause more displeasure than the pleasure given
by the joys of love. Epicurus does not wholly trust them. “For the
8o Tranquillity without Transcendence
C. The Canonics
regarded, then all of the ground is lost. In denying them, we lose the
reasons for our assertions.
Feelings: The feelings (pathe) attendant on sensory perceptions are
the criteria of pleasure. In sensory perception and pleasure we find the
pure preserttness of Being. Here is the point of absolute trust. If it were
to totter, cognition and tranquillity would be lost at the same time.
Concepts: By a concept Epicurus understands “an internally preserved
representation of a general cognition, i.e., the memory of something that
has often made its appearance externally, as, for example, ‘something
like a human being.’ As soon as I say ‘human being,’ its type is represented
to me conceptually, guided by my preceding sensory perceptions” (N184).
We “would be entirely unable to examine what we do examine if
we were not already familiar with it, e.g., ‘Is the animal standing over
there at a distance a horse or a cow?’ ” This question can be answered
only if the shape of the horse and the cow is already known conceptually.
“Neither could we ever give a name to anything unless we had already
made conceptual acquaintance with its type” (N184).
The concept anticipates (that is why it is called prolepsis) what is
fulfilled in sensory perception, yet has its origin in sensory perceptions.
“All thoughts arise on the basis of sensory perception through accidental
cause, analogy, similarity, combination, to which, of course, thinking
also contributes something” (N183).
3. From phenomena (phainomena) to the nonevident (adela): Sensory
perceptions, feelings, concepts are what is evident. They make present
and evident all that exists. In this immediate evidence everything is
phenomenon, appearance. There is no visible sign of atoms anywhere.
“Hence one must draw conclusions from the visible to the invisible”
(N183). The road leads from the appearances (phainomena) to the non¬
evident, unknown things {adela).
Epicurus’ attitude toward the world is two-sided. Everything is pres¬
ence; there is nothing beyond it, no purpose, no goal. Yet, beyond every¬
thing tangible lies that which is uniquely nonevident: the atoms, that is,
something utterly indestructible, imperishably enduring; also their mo¬
tion in the void, and the infinity of their numbers and of the extension
of space.
4) Truth and falsehood: all sensory perceptions are true: “All perception
is devoid of reason. . . . Furthermore, there is nothing that perception
could refute. . . . Neither can one perception refute another” (N182).
“Even the imaginings of demented persons and images in dreams are
true; for they act as stimulants; if they did not exist, they could not bring
about such stimulation” (N183).
86 Tranquillity without Transcendence
D. Bios theoretikos
has come powerfully to the fore since the Renaissance. For Pico, man’s
dignity lies in his having been created by God so that he may know the
laws of the universe, and love and admire its greatness and beauty.
In this knowledge imbued with piety toward the world, the moral
life is inextricably bound to awe before such order. “The starry skies
above me and the moral law within me” {Critique of Practical Reason,
Conclusion) are still complementary for Kant.
For Epicurus it is a matter of neither a discriminating, constantly
probing scientific will to truth, nor of blissful, reverent contemplation.
Scientifically, he is wholly uncritical and in no way an investigative
scientist. As to the universe as a whole, he knows no reverence, neither
love and admiration nor aversion and disdain.
He actualizes the possibility of detached observation when faced with
matters of indifference to him. He does not react emotionally. He knows
what the All is. It has no signification, no meaning beyond itself. All
one needs to know is what it is. Observing in complete detachment leads
to independence and peace of mind. Virgil is right in saying of Lucretius:
“Happy is he who has been able to win knowledge of the causes of
things, and has cast beneath his feet all fear and unyielding Fate and
the howls of hungry Acheron” (Georgies, II, 1.49off.).5
Neither the object nor the All and its order deserve our admiration;
rather, it is the thinker who, by way of his alleged knowledge, triumphs
over all adversity that might—but now no longer can—befall him. Truth
as such or the content of actuality does not compel his interest.
But then, observation is satisfying in itself, a noble pursuit in our
leisure time, since it is unalloyed pleasure without painful consequences;
it is an activity providing a singular intellectual pleasure, in which content
is a matter of indifference.
Yet the connection of reverent observation with the moral life takes
on a form that, examined for its meaning, is somewhat less weighty and
more trivial: “The greatest good is reason ... it teaches that one cannot
live pleasantly without, at the same time, living rationally, honorably,
and morally; nor can one live rationally, honorably, and morally without
living pleasurably” (B, Letter to Menoikeus).
Epicurus is neither scientist nor metaphysician. He belongs within
the ranks of those pious toward the world, by virtue of his affirmation
of his own existence within it—a world bereft of transparency or tran¬
scendence.
follows the free impulse. The spirit within us is not hampered by inner
compulsion. The fact that it is not condemned to endure and suffer is
due to the deviation of the atoms, “which, no matter how minute, is not
restricted in place or in time” (Lucretius, De rerum natura, II, 293).
Absolute Necessity would be ineluctable were it not for atoms breaking
through it by virtue of their deviation.
3) The concepts of the deviation of atoms, the spontaneity of living
beings, and the freedom of rational acts, though different in origin, seem
to converge. However, Epicurus also differentiates chance and intent:
“Everything happens according to necessity, chance, intent” (N195).
Three reasons for the course of events are at play; the third is intent,
our freedom, that which we make out of that which we encounter.
Hence the wise man is superior through his insight, which he proves
and which at the same time he secures for himself in life and in action:
first, in that he can laugh at “fate (necessity), which many would admit
as lord over all” because he has “explained” it; second, in “that only
some things happen necessarily, others by chance”; third, in that “some
things happen through us, because, while necessity is irresponsible, chance
is unstable, and hence it lies in our hands not to submit to any lord”
(N181, Letter to Menoikeus).
Chance, itself deprived of power, serves Epicurus to deny the power
of natural necessity, which is unbearable to his consciousness of freedom.
“It would be better to follow the fables about the gods than to be slave
to natural law; at least the former grant the hope that one’s prayers will
be heard . . . while natural necessity is implacable” (N181).
The course of events partly follows from necessities and partly orig¬
inates in chance. Epicurus seeks to ground himself in neither comforting
necessities nor significant chance happenings. Both lack grandeur. Nei¬
ther the divine necessity of an eternal order nor the miracle of divine
intercession exists. The wise man relates to both by soberly compre¬
hending their nature; he will then not let himself be disturbed by either.
He realizes there is a third factor: freedom. This consists not only of
intent—-that is, practical decisions based on rational insight—but also
of a condition that becomes a steady, reliable fundamental attitude.
4) Such freedom (eleutheria) is identical with purest joy, with tran¬
quillity, with a state beyond confusion. It is the consequence of a life of
self-sufficiency: “The greatest fruit of self-sufficiency is freedom” (N220;
Fragments, 77). Necessity, chance, and freedom as intent are the three
moments of existence that, if grasped correctly and followed correctly,
permit the actualization of a condition that is the freedom of the wise.
5) Once such freedom is achieved, neither necessity nor chance can
92 Tranquillity without Transcendence
Schooling oneself in the principles is the path “for you alone and together
with your peers” (N181, Letter to Menoikeus). The noble man “concerns
himself most about wisdom and friendship” (N220; Fragments, 78):
94
Tranquillity without Transcendence
State, religion, wealth and poverty are realities within which man on
earth has been placed. For the philosopher they present the danger of
disturbing/ His tranquillity. He cannot altogether withdraw, but must
seek a way of reacting that makes him immune to them. Epicurus
presupposes that only a tiny number of people are capable of philosophy.
He does not mean that human beings and their institutions should be
made philosophical. Rather, he ponders how, in this unalterable world,
those few could actually be philosophers.
i) The State. Epicurus’ advice is to stay away from politics.
“The wise man will not participate in politics and will not want to
be a ruler” (N199). “Whoever is wise does not pursue politics”
(N208).
His further advice is: Stay clear of the many! Limit your contact
with them to a minimum in order to be safe from them! “I never strove
for the approbation of the many; for I did not learn what pleases them;
but what I do know is far removed from their understanding” (N210).
“Especially if you must live among the many, you must withdraw into
yourself” (N210).
It might be thought that, according to Epicurus, the philosopher
would have to strive for security in order to actualize his life in the
world. The means of acquiring security in the world are power and
prosperity. But this conception confuses two kinds of security.
To be sure, it is correct that power and wealth provide a certain
security of existence, but it is paid for by a state of unrest in the gaining
and maintaining of it; hence it is coupled with constant insecurity. Ep¬
icurus, however, has an entirely different security in mind, namely, the
tranquillity central to his attitude toward life. This he is most likely to
achieve under conditions of remoteness from the many and from the
state.
Outward security of existence, not possible as such but even when
achieved to a high degree, would not obviate the terrible insecurity that
arises from the false representations of things above and below the earth,
of the world and of gods. The philosopher desires the security of inner
tranquillity. This is within his reach. He is responsible only to himself.
Whether he is recognized by the world is no concern of his.
The material security of existence, which Epicurus by no means
disdains even though he has no need for it, has nothing in common with
the philosophical tranquillity of soul. But both are promoted if this advice
is followed: “One must liberate oneself from the prison of daily routine
c)6 Tranquillity without Transcendence
regard to the sages, the purpose of the laws is not to restrain them from
committing an injustice, but to prevent injustice being done to them”
(N209). In his apolitical life, the philosopher acknowledges the require¬
ments for operating a state; but, for him, the state’s ultimate purpose is
to secure die philosophers’ right to live and think in freedom.
2) Religion. Epicurus says: “The sage will venerate the gods” (N199).
By this he means the contemplation of the blessed figures who, between
and beyond the worlds, lead their lives of immortality, oblivious of any
of the worlds. The gods are nothing other than the self-sufficing condition
of unalloyed pleasure. This condition the sage wants to achieve for
himself. In the gods, he contemplates his own goal. Thus Epicurus
promises to him who thinks, practices, and testifies to his philosophy:
“Nothing, whether in your sleeping or waking state, shall be able to
disturb you; rather, you shall live like a god among men. For the man
who lives among imperishable goods is not like a mortal being” (N181;
Letter to Menoikeus).
Such a view, however, is not to be mistaken for a religious one. No
Epicurean religion exists. He has no wish whatsoever for ritual and
prayer, for mysteries, for a religious-priestly community. He does not
desire a community that is contingent on a god, but one that is philo¬
sophical and self-sufficient.
He combats state and national religion only in conjunction with his
followers, whom he wants to liberate from the fears engendered by all
deceptive religious representations. The actual religion of the people, he
leaves untouched. Since he must live in the world as it is, he has to adapt
himself outwardly, for the sake of peace. Epicurus does not take up
cudgels other than in a combat of minds in the interest of his friends.
Security and tranquillity in a withdrawn life is all he asks for. Hence
he can participate in public rites without unease.
3) Wealth and poverty. Society allows for great disparities in property
and wealth. These do not concern the philosopher. For, Epicurus says,
the happy condition of man puts all that is truly necessary within easy
reach, while making it difficult to obtain the superfluous. The wealth
required for our natural needs is limited; that demanded for idle whims
is limitless.
The philosopher should keep as remote from money-making as from
politics: “When living a free life, one cannot acquire many possessions,
since this cannot be done easily without subservience to the vulgar masses
or the powerful. . . .” However, Epicurus in no way disdains riches:
“But should one happen to accrue riches, it is easy to use them for the
benefit of one’s neighbors” (N219; Fragments, 67).
98 Tranquillity without Transcendence
The philosopher who has become godlike represents the ideal. This ideal
is attainable to man. Perfected wisdom is reached through practice. The
following are the hallmarks of the sage:
First, unshakable certitude: “Only the wise man can maintain an
unshakable certitude” (N211); second, the impossibility of his backslid¬
ing: “Whoever has become wise cannot lapse into the opposite mood of
soul and cannot deliberately imagine it” (ibid.); third, freedom from
anger and favor in his life with others: “The blessed and immortal nature
knows no trouble itself nor causes it in others, so that it is never con¬
strained by anger or favor. For all such things exist only in the weak”
(B95); fourth, his life in the world: “We must laugh and philosophize
at the same time, keep house and exercise our other faculties and never
cease to give voice to the right philosophy” (N217; Fragments, 41).
Does such a sage exist? All Epicureans have recognized him in
Epicurus himself. He was the realization and the ideal. The gods are
distant, unapproachable beings, but Epicurus, the wise one in this world,
is a palpable actuality. When gods do not care about us and we have no
access to them, man alone remains. v
Epicurus himself pointed this way: “We should choose an able man
and keep him before us so that we live, as it were, within his vision and
act as though he saw everything” (N210). “The admiration of the wise
is of great benefit to the admirer” (N216; Fragments, 32).
EPICURUS 99
7. CRITICAL CHARACTERIZATION OF
EPICUREAN THOUGHT AND LIFE
1. Against the premise that pleasure is the highest good and the only goal:
What makes life worth living? Epicurus answers: Nothing other than
this life itself. What is this life which is worth living? Epicurus: It is
pure pleasure in existence. But is life not fulfilled by something more
than life, by something that takes meaning from our willingness to
sacrifice our very life for it? To this, Epicurus answers: These are fictions
from which we must liberate ourselves so as to obtain the imperturbable
tranquillity of the pure pleasure of existence.
To be sure, only that which is present in our existence becomes real
for us. Life is diminished if it is considered as something completely
divorced from its presence. We must not lose ourselves in the past or
100 Tranquillity without Transcendence
the future, must not adopt a life based on fictitious imaginings if our
life is to be actual and true.
But is such presentness pure pleasure? What is decisive, pleasure as
such or that which gives this pleasure? Is not pleasure so abstract a
concept that in its generality it signifies no more than simply a “yes,”
whereas what matters is what we say “yes” to?
Epicurus answers: Pleasure is peace of mind, absence of pain,
ataraxia—but devoid of content. Instead of saying “yes” to what is
historically concrete, Epicurus holds to a vague notion of pure pleasure
which is supposed to be happiness. Do I want to live in such a way that
I make pleasure the ultimate goal of my efforts? Or is not “pure pleasure”
much too little and, moreover, impossible?
2. Against ataraxia as the meaning of life: The tranquillity of pure
pleasure allows all that to wither which normally is part and parcel of
human life. Epicurus is not prepared to expose himself to calamity, to
pain, to upheaval. He wants to deny their ineluctability. Though their
causes are embedded in the natural course of things, they themselves are
not inescapable. Epicurus refuses to accept them for himself; rather, by
distancing himself, he endeavors to shut them out. Instead of entrusting
himself to upheaval, he wants to escape it and thus avoid the experience
of crisis, of limit situations, of shipwreck. He thinks them away. He
refuses the experience that “suffering is the quickest way to truth,” a
thought that informs Greek tragedy as well as Christian mysticism. He
has no inkling that man’s greatness may lie precisely in the degree to
which he rises to meet calamity rather than letting it overwhelm him
in unawareness.
Independence, for him, means to remain untouched by what is ter¬
rifying. He is unaware of another independence, which, precisely because
we do not hold back, makes us experience the possibility of our being
given to ourselves as a gift. There is something heartless in Epicurus’
imperturbability, as also, though in a different way, in that of the Stoics
and Skeptics. Even friendship, for him, is conceived as a tranquil state;
he forgets that friendship is a constantly active bond between human
beings, who mature in loving struggle, enhancing in the process their
capacity for true amity.
Epicurus does not want to assume risk. He teaches the peace of mind
reached by detachment and not that peace based on being sheltered in
the Encompassing by way of loving immersion in the world.
3. Against seceding from the world: Distancing oneself from all that
is worldly is the precondition of ataraxia. Do not get involved with the
real world, with affairs of state, or the amassing of wealth, but live apart
EPICURUS IOI
7Tr. H. Rackham. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press; London, William HeinCmann,
i960.
102 Tranquillity without Transcendence
by statesmen. Epicureans are not guilty per se, but bear the burden of
their nonparticipation, since, in the event of political or economic ca¬
tastrophe, their own existence is also affected and destroyed. Political
action against Epicureanism is not necessary, because Epicureans neither
strive for nor possess political power in the world but live in obscurity.
They should be left in peace.
5. Against peace of mind as reached by the idea of annihilation in death:
When Epicurus brushes off death as something that does not concern
us, it cannot be interpreted as a means to comfort us. According to his
philosophy, such comforting is not at all necessary. Epicurus does not
take death seriously. There is no need to be deeply affected by death,
be it the death of a friend or the thought of our own death.
Much of what Epicurus has to say about death is correct. But he
eschews an essential element, namely, the fact that man living in his
temporality is made desolate by the prospect of dying. Epicurus lacks
any vision that goes beyond death, ignoring what he might have found
in Socratic thought, and what, with insight into the phenomenality of
space and time, had been thought in every age through the ciphers of
immortality. Epicurus recognizes embodied representations of death as
fictions, and rightly so. But his negations lead to banalities whose cor¬
rectness has to be acknowledged, of course, but which, in the way he
establishes them, do away with the point of departure for any transcend¬
ing experience.
6. Against the presupposition that true knowledge brings happiness: For
Epicurus, knowledge of the truth is the means to tranquillity because
such knowledge eradicates fear and is itself the tranquillity of contem¬
plating that which is. However, this presupposition of his does not have
truth as its aim, but, rather, a posited truth asserted dogmatically, sugges¬
tive by virtue of an unexamined plausibility, and confirmed by means
of rules. This “theoria” as calming contemplation is not cognition in the
sense of scientific inquiry, but, in the garb of proofs, basically an un¬
questioning acceptance in the manner of faith.
The presupposition “knowledge is happiness” stands in contradiction
to the proposition “He who increases knowledge increases pain.” Hence
the erroneous presupposition has to be changed into the by no means
Epicurean decision: I do not want any happiness without truth.
Epicurus makes it the goal of science to do away with unease. This
we could accept as correct only in the sense that knowledge of what
presently is and what is potentially threatening does away with the unease
of not knowing, and thus forces us to experience and to accept what is
most terrifying as something we know. But Epicurus sees this quite
EPICURUS I03
Against the way of explaining the higher out of the lower, Cassius writes
to Cicero (Ep., XV.19): “It is difficult to persuade men that one has to
strive for the beautiful for its own sake”; but it is evident to them that
pleasure and imperturbability are the fruits of virtue, justice, and the
beautiful. According to Cassius, Epicurus teaches that there is no pleasure
without a beautiful and just life. Hence those who love pleasure are
indeed lovers of beauty and justice. In its result, says Cassius, the life of
the Epicureans is as noble as, for example, that of the Stoics. Yet their
argument is paradoxical: The higher is explained as proceeding from
the lower. In fact, this paradox pervades all of Epicurus’ thought.
Some examples:
All things come to be out of the atoms and the void, but then become
the magnificent configurations of the world, of living beings, of the soul,
of reason, of the gods. Cognition comes to be a requisite for our happiness,
104 Tranquillity without Transcendence
is at the same time impressively powerful and yet paltry: the mere
pleasure in an existence that is reduced as much as possible and without
illusions (except the illusion that tranquillity and the absence of pain are
possible), without the historical continuity of a life filled with content.
Such^a life is reduced to an existence between the void that was and the
void that will be; it is the instant of pure pleasure.
Some features were taken out of context, robbed of their original sense,
and thereby estranged from Epicurus, but count as “Epicureanism.”
Physical pleasure becomes the main issue. A life of excess grounds
itself in Epicurus, counter to his explicit teaching and life.
Abstaining from politics and advocation of the reclusive life that
avoids the many are turned into the comfort of the philistine, who, in
his private pleasures, yields to passivity.
Liberation from fear of the gods is turned into hostility toward
religion, now practiced with a joyous aggressiveness that in this form is
alien to Epicurus.
The pleasure of theoria is broadened to include the pleasure of spir¬
itual life as it is found in the study of beautiful forms in poetry, literature,
and art. Epicurus himself had no interest in this. But such broadening
of his theoria, the basis for evaluating Epicurus—as was done by one
faction within humanism since the Renaissance—was incompatible with
his cast of mind. Nothing could be more alien to Epicurus, with his
gravity of mind that informed every emotion, than the noncommittal
character, the lack of consequences implicit in a spiritual world devoted
uniquely to self-cultivation.
The ambiguous development of Epicurean philosophy began early.
Epicurus was a contemporary and possibly a friend of the poet Menander.
There exists an epigram by the latter (referring to the name of the fathers
of Themistocles and Epicurus, both of whom were called Neocles):
C. Epicurus’ polemics
Are we now, too, with our critical remarks, part of the almost universal
battle line drawn up against Epicurus by the history of philosophy? It
would seem so, since we consider Epicurus’ scientific knowledge to be
only allegedly scientific; indeed, completely contrary to science. Also, it
might appear as though we were saying that Epicurus’ life of detached
equanimity necessarily neglected all that gives human life substantive
content. The tranquillity of pure joy brings ^with it a withering of the
humanity of human beings. Epicurus refuses to accept the part of pain
that reveals depth. He refuses to take the risk implicit in the historic
immersion of Existenz. Instead of a richly fulfilled Existenz, we are left
with the barrenness of a life of pleasure and tranquillity. By refusing to
EPICURUS 111
follow his road, to choose him as guide for our life, we appear to oppose
him altogether.
But there are limits imposed on naysaying. The objection of a lack
of clarity on matters of science applies, in some sense, to almost all
philosophies; it has been only two centuries since insight, based on mental
discipline, began to draw a line between science and other disciplines.
The accusation of paucity of content is mitigated when we contemplate,
in all its grandeur, this thought and practice, how consequentially it was
carried out, its radicality, its harmony with itself. Epicurus will be a
guidepost forever. Even if he is rejected as a permanent guide, there are
moments in life when his philosophy can serve us as a refuge in times
of weariness, as a respite in our weakness, as a transitory means to keep
us going (as does, at other times, Stoic philosophy). This also always
implies a shortcoming, the nature of which is brought home to us through
Epicurus in all the seductive power of his reasoning and its consequences.
Counter to his intention, Epicurus can help us by increasing our strength
in the battle against the very tendencies whose nature he illuminated on
the highest level. We enter the garden of Epicurus in order, overcoming
ourselves, to abandon it once again.
*
' ■
*
v < - *mh
.
Gnostic Dreamers
BOEHME
SCHELLING
\
" V
V
/
i INTRODUCTION
“5
116 Gnostic Dreamers
I. LIFE
1 Citations of Boehme’s work are to Jal^ob Boehme’s Sdmmtliche Werfe, ed. K. W. Schiebler.
Leipzig, 1831-1847.
118 Gnostic Dreamers
I3)-
Boehme found God in the radical changes of his melancholic and
euphoric moods. Out of these agitated states he read in the book of
nature, recognized the signatura rerum, grasped the boundlessly terrible
and the overwhelmingly magnificent.
The u>oi\. The work “Sunrise”—“Aurora”—stands by itself. All his
other works were written in the brief space of his last six years, often
in simultaneous production. Boehme believed that in his later writings
he had achieved greater clarity than in “Sunrise.” Although in Boehme
periods of development hardly play a role (the expression “unground”
[Ungrund] seems to have appeared first in the treatise “On the Incarnation
of Christ”), a change becomes noticeable. What is considered greater
clarity is also increasing schematization. The originality, the imaginative
force of his language seems to wane. We might think here of an analogy
to typically schizophrenic change. But we lack sufficient biographical
material for such a diagnosis.
Though they deal with a variety of specific themes, all his many
writings aim at the whole. This whole, however, is the vision in its
120 Gnostic Dreamers
a) The astonishing answer. “The Nothing is God” (VII, 191), and “God
has made all things out of the Nothing and is the self-same Nothing”
(IV, 309).
But this Nothing is a strange Nothing. It is not Nothing altogether.
What then? God Himself is “the seeing and feeling of the Nothing . . .
and is called a Nothing (even though it is God himself) for the reason
that it is incomprehensible and ineffable” (VI, 597).
This Nothing is touched by us in thinking when we think of God.
God is the “unground.” “The unground is an eternal Nothing” (VI,
413). There, within the eternity of the unground, there is nothing but
stillness, an eternal quiet, no beginning and no end, no searching or
BOEHME 121
look. In the unground God would not be manifest to himself. “But his
wisdom has become his ground in eternity” (VI, 251). Sophia is the virgin
who in the dawn of eternity speaks before God, makes possible for him
the revelation of himself before himself. She is called virgin because she
does not give birth but merely receives the images and reflects them.
She is selfless, without desire.
b) Sophia is—I list here only some of the images and concepts by
means of which Boehme depicts her—the mirror of God. God sees
himself in it as in a mirror. Through it, He is able to confront himself.
Cognition first grows out of such a confrontation. Hence Sophia is called
the image of God. In the image the incomprehensible becomes compre¬
hensible. Sophia is called, further, the ob-ject [der Gegenwurf], the exhaled
[das Ausgehauchte\, the egressed [das Ausgegangene\, the emanated [das
Ausgeflossene], the found, the uttered (cf. Benz, nff.).
However, Sophia is not an abstraction. For Boehme, there is nothing
spiritual without the corporeal, even if it is a suprasensory corporeality.
Hence it is the corporeal form of the overarching will of God, the
body of God, embodied configuration. It is “not a being which is
conceivable as bodily ... as we humans are, yet is essencelike and
visual” (IV, 71).
Since it is the body of the whole triune God, it is also called the
“house of the Holy Trinity” (VI, 340).
It is the garment in which God manifests himself to man. Without
it his configuration would not be recognized. “For we human beings
cannot, in all eternity, see more of the spirit of God than the splendor
of his majesty” (IV, 71).
Through Sophia there becomes effective in God the principle of all
revelation, of all becoming and life, the principle of opposites.
As the unity devoid of opposites, the unground is like the Nothing
but is filled by an infinite plenitude and the urge to manifest itself. The
will of the unground “is neither evil nor good but is merely a will, that
is, a knowing without understanding for anything or in anything . . .
and is neither desire nor joy; rather, it is surging or willing” (IV, 500-
01).
But God is not the Nothing resulting from an absence of opposites;
He is the unity of opposites. This is the mysterium magnum of Boehme.
Duality in the unity, unity in the duality. God himself is the unity of
opposites, is darkness and light, love and wrath, fire and light. Yea and
nay are One Thing.
The sensing of its own self is the eye of eternal seeing, the eternal
yea, the eternal unity. In the will it contracts into itself, is the eternal
BOEHME I23
nay, the eternal ownness. The center of the yea is love, of the nay wrath
(cf. Benz, 128-29).
In regard to oppositeness Sophia is the first principle of separability.
This likeness “is the separator'in the emanation of the will which makes
the will pf the eternal One separable: it is the separability in the will
out of which forces and properties come to be.” Hence “arises the mul¬
tiplicity of the wills, and out of it also came to be the creaturely life of
the eternal ones such as angels and souls” (VI, 469).
The will of the eternal One is without feeling, without bent toward
anything; for it has nothing toward which it could incline except in itself
(VI, 469-70). “Desire is the ground and beginning of the nature of
sensitivity of one’s own will . . . out of it the separabilities of the wills
are brought to the sensitivity of a selfsameness” (VI, 469).
In summarizing his thoughts, Boehme expresses time and again what
God is; for example: God “is the One vis-a-vis the creature, as an eternal
Nothing; he has neither ground, beginning nor abode; and possesses
nothing save himself; he is the will of the Unground, is in himself only
One; he needs neither space nor place: from eternity in eternity he gives
birth to himself in himself: he is like or similar to no thing, and has no
special place where he abides: eternal wisdom ... is his abode: he is the
will of wisdom, wisdom is his revelation” (V, 7).
The reflection in Sophia allows the groundless will of God to find
and grasp itself, but only as in an early-morning dream of eternity. It
shows him the wealth of possible splendors but in outline only.
c) Nature. God becomes actual only through eternal nature. As a
means of revelation it stands in opposition to the virgin, the eternal idea.
God, who sees himself in the mirror, desires what he sees. It is to become
actual. The pleasure of beholding and desire allow nature hidden in God
to break forth.
But God remains as yet in the eternity of his life with this nature.
It is not the nature present to us but the nature prior to creation. As
this nature, will separates itself from the unity. It multiplies itself into
an infinity of particular wills.
Concomitant with this breakthrough of nature, a darkening occurs.
This is the condition for light to reveal its brilliance. All opposites now
actualize themselves to full revelation. The yea of all things becomes
manifest only through the eternal nay. Even though yea and nay are not
two things adjacent to each other, but one thing that drives itself forth
in the dynamism of its contrariety, they divide into two beginnings or
two centers, each of which wills and works in itself (cf. Martensen,
49-50).
124 Gnostic Dreamers
These two “centra” are the will of nature and the will of spirit, or
the individual will and the universal will. In the eternal process of
revelation, the will of nature subordinates itself to the will of spirit. It
proceeds in seven configurations of nature. In the first three configu¬
rations there is a hostile relationship between nature and spirit; in the
last three nature is the willing servant. The first dark triad (1-3) is
followed by lightning (fright [Schracbf), and then by the light triad (5—
7) (cf. Martensen, 51-52).
In the dark triad, nature shows what it is capable of doing through
itself. Despite its tremendous power it still remains unsatiated, in wild
unrest. It moves in three stages (cf. Martensen, 52ff.).
1) Contraction: It is the first act of will out of the Nothing. It is cold,
hard, sharp, strict—it is salt, the power that is locked in itself, craving
exclusivity and not tolerating anything beside itself.
2) Expansion: It wants to spread out, is desire directed outward, is
urge into diversity—it is mercury. These two qualities are opposing
desires: the one wants to include everything in itself, the other wants to
pour itself out; the one to withdraw austerely into itself, the other fleeing
out of itself. The one wants greater stillness, the other clamors and rages.
These warring powers are inseparable, cannot let go of each other, but
must wrestle one with the other. In the end this struggle turns into an
oscillation comparable to the turning of a wheel.
3) Rotation: It is movement that cannot come to an end, because it
has no goal; it is terrible restlessness and fear. It cannot remain where
it is and yet does not move from the spot—it is sulphur. It is also called
centrum naturae, wheel of nature, wheel of life, wheel of fear, the wheel
of birth, of eternal fire.
4) There now awakens, in the fear of nature, the yearning for
freedom. The immeasurable suffering yearns for deliverance. Before
this yearning, love manifests itself, but becomes manifest only when
there is something that desires it. Love lets its light shine into the
darkness. A tremor, a terror (Schracki) passes through nature—
lightning.
Fear is afraid of the fiery lightning. The darkness, the selfishness of
natural desire is consumed by it. The dark and the light world, wrath
and love separate. The configurations of nature turn gentle. Thus, what¬
ever in God’s life before creation is a prototype will return in all Being:
Each life must be born twice, as is nature through lightning. The new
light triad has these configurations (cf. Martensen, 54ff.).
5) The light water spirit: In it the powers are concentrated into a
unity. Hostility has vanished, one power takes pleasure in the others, a
BOEHME I25
gentle love reigns, the strictness and sharpness of nature are muted and
reshaped. Here lies the birthplace and the seed of all things.
6) The comprehensible sound, the resonance: The powers just collected
are led forth in a comprehensible separation. They give sound and
become dear. But no human ear can hear these celestial sounds.
7) The harmonious whole: It is the wisdom that has become actuality,
life, and corporeality. It is called the uncreated heaven, the celestial hall,
the kingdom.
As they are represented, these seven nature-configurations engender
one another in turn. But they are not successive; rather, in movement,
they are life in God, an eternal presentness, a whole (cf. Martensen, 56IT.).
d) This summing up cannot claim to be an accurate presentation of
Boehme’s teaching. He sees, thinks, and writes not only in endless rep¬
etition but also in endless variations and rearrangements. One scheme
is merely one among many. To illustrate what such sketches represent
and what meaning accrues to them, the following needs to be added:
1) Nature furnishes the images. But salt, mercury, sulphur; harsh,
sweet, bitter; oil, water, fire are not ciphers, but the powers that manifest
themselves in these actualities. Light is love, darkness hate, warmth
wrath, salt covetousness, sulphur fear.
2) For Boehme, the method of thinking via images of nature is
coincidental with the divinity of nature. To be sure: “There is nothing
in nature that does not contain good as well as evil” (Richter, 89), but
God himself is the contrariety present in him which, in him, is unity,
is this dual possibility. “When God created this world with all there is
in it, He had no other material to fashion it from than his own being,
than himseif” (III, 9).
Hence nature presents a twofold aspect. As the essence of this world
it is “smoke coagulated from the eternal ether” (Richter, 90). But there
is equally the magnificence of this world. God is in nature although
“nature neither grasps nor comprehends him, just as air cannot grasp
the radiance of the sun” (VI, 5).
3) The seven configurations of nature brought each other forth con¬
secutively. Contraction brought forth its opposite, expansion; both, in
wrestling with each other, brought forth rotation, the eternal wheel of
the fear of nature. The desire for freedom from the wheel and for
deliverance is answered by eternal love, in fiery lightning or fright
(Schrack), in which what is mere nature is consumed. Now the light
movement unfolds. At first the gentle docility of nature confronts the
spirit. But it is spirit only in understanding one for the other, in con¬
sonance. In conclusion, there is total harmony.
126 Gnostic Dreamers
did God create the world? By eternal fiat or his word as expression of
his will, through the “let-there-be! of the Creator” (Martensen, 137)?
But why this act of will? Boehme answered, approximately, that the
triad desired to have children in its likeness; out of love God formed
the idea of another existence which is not-God but is utterly in need of
God. What is decisive is: God created the world not out of necessity but
through free decision. In spite of Boehme’s affirmative formulations, this
decision remains an impenetrable mystery for him. “Even though we
know the fiat, we do not know God’s first move toward creation. We
know no cause to explain how that which had stood in its nature through¬
out eternity (without beginning and unchangeable) has come into motion;
for there is nothing that would have stimulated it” (VI, 50; cf. Martensen,
140). As God moves toward creation a beginning is posited. But how
can something begin in the unchangeable, in which there is no time?
“We are not supposed to know the reason and cause, and God has
reserved it for his power . . . we are also not to reason further about
this for it disturbs us” (VI, 159).
Hence it “is the greatest miracle brought about by eternity that it
has worked the eternal into a corporeal spirit which no reason can grasp
and no sense can find” (VI, 49). “No created spirit can posit itself and
hence it cannot fathom itself, either. To be sure, we see our potter . . .
but we do not see his creating. . . . The soul grows forth like a twig on
a tree of humanity; but the first movement toward creation is not to be
known by us. It is a secret which God has reserved for himself’ (VI,
49ff.; cf. Martensen, 141-42).
a) Exposition: With creation the bond is dissolved that holds together all
forces and configurations in God’s eternity. Each force is set free so that
it may move according to its own will. But as yet there is no strife
between the innumerable particular wills. Everything is still in a state
of balance that is maintained through the unity of eternal wisdom.
The primal state of creation is the life of the angels in a marvelous
natural world that by far surpasses our earthly world in its perfection.
It is a realm of pure spirits of light: within it are the realms of the three
archangels Michael, Lucifer, and Uriel, surrounded by a host of angels.
The lives of these beings are not bound to the limits of space and time.
To be sure, they have locality, but they can be where they wish. They
know neither proximity nor distance. They live in the communality of
BOEHME 129
love in common joy. The content of their lives is the adoration of God
in the cycle of eternity. Though created, they constitute a second eternity,
as it were, a condition they share with all of creation.
But this changes. The angels have to pass a test, with the view of
strengthening their relationship to God. Not all pass this test. Lucifer,
the most powerful of all created spirits, held sway over a—for us—
indeterminate area of natural worlds to which our earth also belonged,
at that time resplendent in beauty and magnificence. Lucifer’s temptation
was: He saw his beauty, for he was wonderfully beautiful; he saw his
power, for he was a most mighty lord. He directed his imagination onto
himself, his ego, and became ill-disposed toward the Son of God, who
was more beautiful and mightier than he. He thought that he could
himself become like God and rule in all things through the power of
fire.
He opened his centrum naturae, his fiery ground, and thus caused
his light to go out. He became dark. The fundament of hell, which had
been hidden since time eternal, was now unveiled. He awakened the
principle of God’s wrath, the first three configurations of nature. His
torment consists in a constant climbing in order to raise himself above
the heart of God; but each time he sinks back once more into the deepest
abyss.
Why did Lucifer fall? Lucifer, says Boehme, knew well that he was
not God, and he foresaw God’s judgment and his fall; but the fall was,
for him, not a feeling, only a knowing. As to his feeling, he had in
himself the fiery lust, the fire-root. The latter now burned in him, goaded
him on to want something totally new, to raise himself above all king¬
doms and above all divinity. He had the illusion of not having been
created. He was conscious that God could not kill him. “But God has
created him into his harmony, such that he wanted to play with him in
his spirit of love as on the stringed instrument of his revealed and formed
word, and this his own will did not want” (V, 41).
Lucifer draws the natural world which is subject to him into his fall.
Previously there existed a magical connection between spirit and nature.
Now a terrible turba (confusion) enters into nature. The bond of the
forces is truly dissolved. Instead of acting together in harmony, the egoism
of all the particulars now falls into conflict and confusion. The conse¬
quence is a state of chaos. God’s wrath becomes manifest in fire, ma¬
terialization, darkness, and death.
This happened at the beginning of creation. This fall within eternity,
which could still contain creation itself, first brings about our temporal
3
r °
Gnostic Dreamers
world. From the beginning the latter has shown itself as a shattered,
broken, disturbed, disordered eternity. The dawn of creation is heralded
by a great catastrophe.
But God does not want the destruction to be final. He initiates the
reaction. He puts everything under water. His purpose is the re-formation
of the earth. Only now does that which is told in the Mosaic story of
the creation begin. The six days of creation are stages in the battle between
the forces of God and those of darkness. Only now does that which we
call time begin.
The earth was unformed and void {tohu wabohu). It was necessary
to rebuild the world that through Lucifer had become a ruin. The end
was the creation of paradise, of the perfect abode of light for the creature
of light, man, the first man. In paradise everything was in a state of
balance, but not so in the rest of the world. Man was destined to extend
paradise over the whole earth. What happened?
To understand this, we must first know what Adam, the first man,
was.
The first man was One, unity without multiplicity.
The first man was endowed with spirit-corporeality as his heavenly
garment, and was not yet clothed in incarnate corporeality. The heavenly
body of Adam could pass through all things, and things through him,
without laceration. His corporeality is that of the angels (cf. V, 47ff.).
External things do not harm him; he is impervious to frost, heat, thorns.
He is free of sickness and death. He neither knows nor needs sleep. He
breathes not air but the divine spirit of life. He has no bowels and needs
no material nourishment. He drinks from the fountain of eternal life
that is hidden in the earthly water source and does not need to drink
water. He is androgynous, without sex; procreation occurs through inner
imaging; this self-imaging takes place by means of loving contemplation
of the divine image. Begetting and giving birth are one and the same
act (cf. V, 54-55).
The first man was microcosm. He contains the three principles of
the macrocosm: first, the principle of fire, the eternal father, as the soul
of man; second, the principle of light, the eternal son, as the spirit of
man; third, the sensuous world of things, as his transitory corporeality.
In Adam the principle of light is dominant. Therefore he possesses the
clear cognition of divine, natural, and human things. He understands
the language of God as well as the language of nature. For him, all that
is visible is irradiated by the invisible. For Sophia is his bride as she is
the bride of God. He is, after all, God’s image. Adam, the first man, is
put to the test and tempted, as was Lucifer before him. He allows himself
BOEHME I3I
Boehme describes heaven and hell, the unchangeable will after death,
the magical state after death in the in-between region of spirits in the
sidereal body, the completion of all things.
Hence the total picture presents itself to him as follows: at the be¬
ginning the pure world of the angels; at the end the complete spirit-
world; in between, temporal existence. The last has eternity behind it
and before it and all around. In this temporal history the angels, who
themselves have no history, play a role as the servants of God.
b) Discussion: This gnostic total view of all things in their ground
requires critical characterization.
First: Any effort to present Boehme’s thoughts in a framework of
order and clarity leads to misrepresentation. Boehme proceeds impre¬
cisely, indeed almost arbitrarily, changing directions, realigning and al¬
tering the configurations of thought. For these reasons a conceptually
more precise exposition must necessarily give a false picture, because of
its very clarity. It separates what converges into one flow. It constructs
an ordered whole which is only partially and at that fleetingly present
in the texts. Nonetheless, the exposition is not altogether false, since such
clear outlines are present in Boehme as possibilities. We are justified in
distilling the core from an impenetrable mass of repetitions and con¬
fusions. This core has appealed to many, but not even this core can be
determined unequivocally.
In this core there appear necessary and relevant contradictions. On
the one side there is the emphasis on ignorance, the rejection of the
desire to know, the awe before the mystery: “for I have never desired
to know about the divine mystery, much less have I known how I might
seek or find it ... I sought only the heart of }esus Christ, in order to
hide myself in it before God’s fierce wrath” (VII, 399-400). On the other
side there is knowledge overreaching itself, with its emphasis on God’s
demand to be cognized, the certainty of knowledge about all Being as
grounded in God himself, the total knowledge of the course of things
from eternity to eternity. On the one side Evil is a necessary aspect of
the process manifest to God, and on the other side Evil is the accidental
moment of Lucifer’s and Adam’s acts of freedom, through which Evil
first breaks into the magnificent creation. In other words, we are gripped
by the intuition of evil in the primal ground of Being (wrath is the root
of all things), and we are constantly called upon to battle for good against
evil and, for our salvation, to participate in the choice of a path that
leads away from evil. And again: The God of heaven and the God of
hell are like two powers, and yet they are not two gods but one God.
Everything, so also God himself, becomes manifest through contrast.
BOEHME *35
Overcoming is joy’ (V, 306). “We recognize . . . that every life arises
in fear, as in a poison that is a dying, and is yet also life itself, as it can
be recognized in man and in all creatures. For without fear or poison
there is no life . . . especially in man” (VI, 254). “For each life comes to
be in tprment of fear. . . . For everything that is in nature is dark and
in fear” (VI, 370).
In considering method in Boehme, we have to realize that it cannot
be grasped by way of reason. But his clarity is astonishing when he
expresses himself on a few decisive points of his procedure which, in its
execution, is so confused and uncontrolled, and equally when he discusses
the origin and meaning of his insight:
1) The source of his insight is not thought but immersion in its
immediacy. “Most likely you say that I was not present at the creation
of the world and hence may not write about it. But the spirit which is
in me was present there and makes it known at this time” (Martensen,
17). Boehme states that he sees the truth inside himself, but at first as
in a chaos where everything is densely packed. Only gradually does it
arrive at greater clarity (cf. ibid.).
This immediate immersion presupposes a rebirth. God cannot be
cognized without God. No matter how natural man may twist and turn,
he cannot escape being caught up in the world. The fall of man brought
about by Adam and his rehabilitation in Christ is a process repeated in
each individual.
2) For Boehme, this occurs wholly in the present and not through
the guidance of a tradition, a doctrine, or a church. For him, Jesus as a
historical figure is of small moment. Boehme abhors the historical view.
It is not the knowing and hearing about something that is helpful; rather,
it deceives: it leads to confusion. One is saved only by one’s own actions
and experiences, by certainty in the manifestation of the divine essence,
by beholding the signatura rerum, without scriptural proof (though
Boehme does quote the Bible occasionally), without dogmatic reference
to the illumination through the holy spirit while reading the Biblical
texts. Only the immediate, which manifests itself unhistorically, eternally,
is valid for him. “Even if I had no other book than my book which I
am myself, I would have books enough; the whole Bible, after all, lies
in me. As long as I have the spirit of Christ... As long as I read myself,
I read in God’s book, and you, my brethren, are all my letters which I
read within me” (VII, 132).
To be sure, Boehme has a positive relationship to the Bible, is at
home in it. But he recognizes the harm of serving the letter. What is
important is not the letter, but the living word. “Letter-brokers” (V,
H8 Gnostic Dreamers
This is how he sees him: God has made man the lord of all creatures,
has endowed him with senses, reason, and intellect, and especially with
language, so that he can differentiate, tame, and utilize all. Still “higher
. . . cognition did God give him so that he can see into the heart of
things / into earth, stones, trees, herbs . . . also into stars and elements
so that he knows their nature and power” (III, i).
Man’s first task is to know himself. Nothing is more useful for him
than “that he learn to know himself properly: i) what is he? 2) out of
what or whom? 3) for what purpose has he been created?” (Ill, 1).
“Without which reflection we are all blind and have no true cognition
of God, but move about like dumb animals and look at ourselves and
God’s creation like a cow at a new barn door” (III, 3). But as man “now
knows hirhself properly he also knows God his creator, together with
all creatures” (III, 7).
Man has his great task because of his extraordinary nature. He feels
in himself God’s “magnificent power” (IV, 71). More than that: “God
is himself the essence of all essences, and we are in him as gods through
which he reveals himself” (IV, 86). But Boehme also writes: “. . . in this
world a man should not crave to know His sanctity” (Elert, 48).
The'great task may be defined as the adoring cognition which is the
wellspring of true life. Man can cognize God “because this visible world
is the expressed and formulated word according to God’s love and wrath
. . . but man’s soul a spark from the eternally speaking word of divine
knowledge and strength, and the body ... a being of heaven after the
manner of the obscured world: he thus has the power to speak of the
mysterium magnum out of which all beings have come to be” (V, 4).
The life growing out of adoring cognition presupposes the authen¬
ticity of the cognition. Knowing adoration brings about inner movement
and action in the world consequent upon it. It is the great question of
all philosophy: What happens to me when I pursue such thoughts and
speculations and visions, when I live in such a vivid world of thought,
when my certainty in it becomes the ground of my consciousness of
Being?
Boehme says: No speculation is of use to man if he does not apply
it for his salvation. “What good is science to me if I do not live in it?
The knowledge must be within me, and also the willing and doing”
(VII, 410). Together with intuition of the depth and the ground of all
Being, there comes also assurance of the ethos. Each being yearns “for
that out of which he first originated” (Richter, 90). If he reaches it, he
attains all truth, that of knowledge as well as of action.
If we ask Boehme why he writes at all, he replies, in accordance
140 Gnostic Dreamers
with this sense of his knowledge, which is also his ethos: I write only
for the purpose that man get to know himself, what he is, what God,
heaven, angels, devil and hell, as well as God’s wrath and hellfire are.
. . . Therefore consider well, you human being, in this time, what you
are! Do not value yourself so little, as so trivial, and do take care that
you remain in paradise and do not put out the divine light in you” (III,
36~37)-
The reader must be ready: “My writings do not serve the full belly,
but a hungry stomach; they belong to the children of the mystery” (VII,
384).
To those who seek guidance he says: I do not know “any better
advice to give you than to show you the path on which I myself travel,
and thereupon the door was opened to me” (VII, 407).
In an age of fanatical religious battles, Boehme was an early proponent
of tolerance, with thoughts that were not new. It is characteristic for his
nature that he stood up for it. God is not only the God of the Christians,
but also that of the Jews, the heathen, the Turks. God reveals himself
to each people according to its peculiar nature. The root of the quarrel
lies in the fact that we cling to images and letters rather than to the
spirit. If one could do away with the images, the one living word would
speak. But it is couched for us in various images. We quarrel about
images.
IV. CHARACTERIZATIONS
V. BOEHME’S INFLUENCE
Boehme, for his part, held fast to the Lutheran Church on principle. He
was not the type of enthusiast who establishes sects. Even though,
throughout the centuries, his adherents formed societies, the Boehmenists
did not become an organized sect even as time went on.
His influence, however, was considerable. The physician Walter, who
in his last year in Dresden became Boehme’s friend, named him the
Philosophus Teutonicus. The name stuck. Hegel confirmed it: “As a matter
of fact, it was first through him that philosophy in Germany emerged
with the character peculiar to it” (Hegel, XIX, 300).
Angelus Silesius, the mystic and poet, responded to Boehme with
love:
The fish lives in water,
the plants in the earth,
the bird in the air,
the sun in the sky;
salamander must keep in the fire.
God’s heart is Boehme’s element.
idea”; “he tosses and turns himself around in several forms because
neither the sensuous nor the religious one can suffice.” “But it is a form
one cannot reconcile oneself to and which does not allow for a definite
picture regarding the details” (Hegel-, XIX, 301-04, 327).
About the deepest content of this thinking Hegel says: “In the back¬
ground there is the most speculative thought, which, however, never
comes to be presented in a manner appropriate to it.” The “content of
the battle is the deepest idea which shows us that the most absolute
opposites are to be reconciled. ... It is a tremendous, wild and rough
exertion from within to pack together what lies so far apart in form and
configuration . . . thus he wrestled to comprehend, to grasp the negative,
the evil, the devil in God” (Hegel, XIX, 303, 327).
About Boehme’s personality: . . his pious nature . . . deep and
tender to the highest degree.” His life was founded in the Protestant
principle “to immerse the world of the intellect in his own heart and to
look at, to know and to feel in his self-awareness all that was beyond it
otherwise.” He represents “the German, the heart’s depth that communes
with the innermost” (Hegel, XIX, 327, 300, 304).
SCHELLING
i
/
Editors’ Note
WORK
1.
1 Citations are to S'dmtliche Wer\e, ed. by K. F. A. Schelling. Stuttgart and Augsburg, 1856-61.
M3
!44 Gnostic Dreamers
2.
Only through metaphysics does the center of the All become present.
Only from there issues true guidance of insight as well as of action.
Without metaphysics there is only dissipation and ruin.
How does philosophy get into this center? Intellect and sensory
perception are not the origin of philosophic insight. These put knowledge
at the disposal of everyday concerns, in a clear form as the knowledge
of the sciences, which is cogent for everyone and equally valid for every
intellect. Philosophic insight has a different source. Only if we feel
confirmed in our innermost being and answer with what Schelling calls
intellectual intuition can we understand philosophy.
What is intellectual intuition? Schelling has a variety of answers.
The most simple approach is to certify intellectual intuition through
the way in which we are conscious of ourselves. In being conscious of
myself I am both subject and object. In the I, that which thinks and
that which is thought are the same. If we consider as clear only that
which is before us as a sensuously intuitable object, then the I is indeed
a mystery. The I is I only because it can never become the object of
sensuous intuition. Hence, Schelling concludes, it can be determinable
only in an intuition which intuits no object at all, which is not at all
sensuous, namely, in an intellectual intuition (I, 181).
This simple undebatable puzzle implied in the fact of the conscious¬
ness of the I was merely Schelling’s starting point. What he means by
intellectual intuition goes much farther. It is a matrix of construction
for speculation, as space is for geometry. It is a condition which he
compares with sleep. It is an act of freedom through which alone I can
be convinced of the authentic existence of whatever is. It is liberation
from being tied to objects. It is, however, not subjective, but is the
“indifference” of subject and object, encompassing both. It is the stand¬
point of “absolute reason,” in which time ceases to be and all things are
seen merely as the expression of absolute reason and not as objects of
reflection. It is the standpoint of the absolute. Whereas in his ordinary
state of consciousness man lives outside the absolute, bound to objects,
146 Gnostic Dreamers
3-
Schelling’s work is pervaded by the age-old fundamental question: What
is Being? In various ways he leads us to a thinking experience of the
most extreme sort, to the place where what is must become manifest. I
shall try to present one of these ways (IX, 214-21):
Schelling almost never takes the direct way of approach. He likes to
proceed from a familiar premise that can be presumed to be shared by
all. Only after this preparatory step can we grasp where he wants to
lead. His preparation takes the following form:
a) In examining the statements about Being which have arisen, I
perceive the contradiction in which each incipient reflection soon finds
itself; next I see the contradiction also of the systems in which such
reflections of the knowledge of Being can each find completion. This
original lack of system in human knowledge impels systems to arise,
albeit as the idea of a higher whole. Within this whole the antagonistic
systems, by their very coexistence, create that superior consciousness in
which man is again free of all systems, stands above all systems.
This higher whole—which is again a system, but the one that pre¬
cludes conflict with any other system—can be realized only in a series
of stages. While the stages conflict with each other, each is true, though
not at the same but at various points of the development. The philosophy
that wants the truth of the whole must become genetic.
In such a genesis all contradictions cease because each position taken
in thinking, each mode of Being has its truth in actuality, hence is
preserved; and each is also overcome because it becomes untrue if it
claims to be the whole. But this genetic movement can, as a whole, be
truth only if the subject of this movement is only a subject that pervades
everything and is not arrested in anything. “For wherever it would
remain, life and development would be inhibited. Pervading everything
and being nothing, that is, being nothing in a way that might allow it
also to be something else: this is what is required.”
Thus the question about Being has become the question about the
one subject that pervades everything, about this subject that is all and
yet is nothing of all that.
b) But we still have not arrived at the question to which we should
now give an answer. A new preparatory step is necessary. Schelling,
148 Gnostic Dreamers
reflecting, says we must first query the question. The question “What
is this subject?” presupposes the question about the meaning of this
question itself. The accepted way of thinking leads to false expectations
when this question is asked. Because in answer to the question “What
is something?” we expect a definition. But here, when the question
applies to the pervasive subject of what is, we must understand from
the outset that there cannot be a definition. A definition as answer would
effectively cancel the meaning of this question. Why?
“Nothing can be defined that is not, by its nature, confined within
definite limits.” But, in any questioning about a pervasive subject, that
which is being asked is not confined within such limits. Hence I must
“make the indefinable, that which cannot be defined in the subject, itself
into the definition.” The subject of philosophy, to all intents and purposes
indefinable, “is nothing—not something . . . but it is also not nothing,
that is, it is everything. It is only nothing singly, in an arrested state,
particularly. . . . There is nothing that it is, and there is nothing that it
is not—the incomprehensible, the truly infinite.”
It is remarkable how Nietzsche answers the question about the Being
that would not be a special Being, not a merely interpreted Being, but
Being itself: “It would have to be something, i.e., not subject, not object,
not power, not matter, not spirit, not soul: —but would I not be told
that something of this nature would be the spitting image of a chimera?
I believe that myself: and a pity if it did not! To be sure: It must also
be the spitting image of everything else there is and could be, and not
only of the chimera! It must have the great family trait in which every¬
thing recognizes itself as related to it —.”2
These are answers to the question as to the meaning of the question
what is, or, what is the subject of all configurations of Being. The
uniqueness of the question, the difference between it and all other ques¬
tions, has first to be made clear.
c) Does Schelling supply the answer? He does not. An answer cannot
be reached by means of a statement involving a concept. What is necessary
is an act of freedom on the part of the entire being of the thinking
person. Something must not only be thought but also be an inward act.
This is how Schelling describes it:
“Whoever wants to master the completely free, self-productive phi¬
losophy must rise up” to the incomprehensible, indefinable. What has
to take place? “Here all finitude, everything that is still something that
is, must be left behind, the last attachment must vanish; here one has
to leave everything—not only, as one is wont to say, wife and child, but
also whatever is, even God, for, seen from this standpoint, even God is
merely something that is. . . .
“The absolute subject is not not-God, and yet is not God; it is also
that which is not God. Hence, in this respect, it is above God. . . .
“Thus he who wants to position himself at the starting point of truly
free philosophy must leave behind even God. . . .
“Only that one has arrived at the ground of his self and has recognized
the whole depth of life who at one time had left everything behind and
had himself been left by everything, for whom everything had gone
under, who had seen himself alone with infinity. . . .
“But he who wants to soar up into that free ether must leave behind
not only the world of objects but even himself. . . .”
Schelling describes the state that now sets in: “He who truly wants
to philosophize must be rid of all hope, all desire, all yearning; he must
want nothing, know nothing, feel himself wholly bare and stripped, must
give everything away in order to gain everything.”
Here too the older Schelling reminds us, as so often at the high
points of his thinking, of the philosopher who had inspired him through¬
out his life: “How high Spinoza rises when he teaches that we are to
sever ourselves from all particular and finite things and rise up to the
infinite.”
d) The preparatory thought operations, followed by the instructions
for “leaving be,” are an appeal to the thinker and a circling around what
is being thought. Now we are ready. Now that which authentically is
should become evident. Might it be sufficient to negate all finiteness, to
have merely negative concepts of the absolute subject? No, says Schelling,
“we strive in all ways possible to attain to its affirmatory concept.” And,
as a matter of fact, he has given us not just a great design, but a series
of designs, a world rich in concepts of Being itself, and of the history
of Being, as well as of our being-human within it. How does he get
there?
After all, the principle was: In that absolute subject nothing is to be
posited in such a manner that its opposite would not also be possible.
That is: Nothing is so indefinable that it cannot also become something
definable, and nothing is so infinite that it might not also be compre¬
hensible. But what is the meaning of these strange sentences? That this
absolute subject is altogether free. It is free to enclose itself in a config¬
uration, or not to enclose itself. It does not lack form or configuration
but does not remain in any configuration, is not chained to any. By
assuming a configuration it can victoriously step out of each one. It
150 Gnostic Dreamers
would not be free if it had not been free from the beginning either to
assume a configuration or not to assume it. Freedom is the essence of
that all-pervasive subject, or it is itself nothing other than eternal freedom.
But if it has assumed a configuration out of freedom, it is not capable
of breaking through again immediately into its eternal freedom, but can
do so only by passing through all configurations that necessarily result.
The content of philosophy is now the process of Being and of the
world: how it is grounded through not-to-be-predicted acts of eternal
freedom and then takes a necessary course; or: how eternal freedom
encloses itself in a configuration and, due to the world-process, finally
breaks through again, back into its eternal freedom. This philosophy
sees, in the whole of the process of Being that leads from eternity back
into eternity, the wrestling power that again consumes every form, rises
up again out of each like a phoenix, is transfigured through fiery death.
Can we be persuaded by this task of philosophizing and by this total
aspect of Being? Up to the moment of the highest question and of the
insight that no determinate answer is possible, we can concur. But when
Schelling answers that it is the “eternal freedom,” at that very moment
a collapse of thinking seems to occur, comparable to Nietzsche’s idea of
the “will to power.” In the objectivizing of freedom, both took a perilous
leap.
Philosophical criticism that draws assurance from the origin runs as
follows: The fundamental experience of freedom takes place in relation
to transcendence, through which it knows itself as a gift to itself. It
amounts to a denial of the essence of existential freedom and to a violation
of transcendence, if freedom is ascribed to the latter as its essence. “There
is no freedom without transcendence”—this is the experience, to be sure,
not of arbitrariness but of every substantial freedom. But what becomes
of transcendence if we attribute to it what only in relation to it is the
essence of finite Existenzen?
I would gladly bring to mind a second example of the great spec¬
ulations of Schelling, namely, his unforgettable question: Why is there
anything at all, why is there not nothing? He posed this question early
and repeated it well into his old age, in various connections and with
varying answers. But such an account would be too space-consuming,
and, in the end, would return to the very same point, namely, the total
intuition of Being, which we reached before. From the sovereignty of
the philosophical thrust toward the ultimate, and from the power of
illumination reached in pushing to the limit, Schelling retreats to narrow
quarters—the intuition ol Being as eternal freedom and its passing into
the world-process. How did this happen?
SCHELLING I5I
(XIII, 7), that, in view of the bleak drama of history, of man who,
unaware of his purpose, is swept away by this never-resting movement
of history toward a goal that he does not know, the experience of a
world that is nothing but vanity inescapably leads us to the conviction
that all Being is ill-fated; and that then and therefore we are forced to
ask the final desperate question: Why is there anything at all, why is
there not nothing? Only the answer to this question can deliver us from
despair. No science other than philosophy can give the answer. “If I
cannot answer that ultimate question, then everything else sinks for me
into the abyss of a bottomless void.”
Is that true? Is it not possible to stand at the limit with this question,
without answer but also without despair, and not plunge into the bot¬
tomless void? This is possible when this question, though not answered,
but thought through in all possible ways, results in the philosophic thrust
into the earnestness of Existenz; when, within the realm of ignorance,
we take hold of life in its relation to transcendence, ambiguously illu¬
minated through a world of possible ciphers.
Here it is not a matter of rational decisions. Schelling’s true insight
that philosophy is volition is inescapable. Our thinking will says: An
answer such as that of Schelling’s gnosticism is untrue for philosophic
cognition and disastrous for Existenz. The resulting calamity must be
shown as the necessary consequence of such a way of thinking. But a
knowledge capable of answering those questions is by no means necessary
for the salvation of man’s Existenz. It is perhaps necessary, however,
that the answer eludes him in time, so that he can walk in honesty. The
path is accessible to him here and now.
I wanted to bring to mind examples of Schelling’s speculation, but
I would need a long time to reproduce this world of thought adequately:
his speculation about unity and duality, his grasp of personality, his
notion of actuality and his illumination of the historicity of all that is
actual, his speculations regarding time (perhaps the most significant
contribution to the subject following Augustine), and especially his phi¬
losophy of mythology. Even today his critical lectures (XI, 1-252) about
all possible ways of interpreting myth are the most beautiful introduction
to the understanding of its historical actuality. He forces us to attain the
height at which alone it is meaningful to speak about myths.
4-
Yet, no matter how philosophically exciting Schelling’s thoughts are, the
descent from peaks always leads to failure. A leap has taken place that
SCHELLING !53
able path. “As infinite science it is, equally, the science of itself” (II, n).
Reflection, at the origin of philosophy, is an act of freedom. It springs
from a dissatisfaction with natural being. Man is not brought to reflection
by nature. He has to desire it. “Naturevdoes not release anyone voluntarily
from its tutelage, and sons of freedom are not born” (II, 12).
But taking hold of reflection by way of freedom presents a risk and
a danger. For if reflection becomes its own purpose and goal, then it is
deadly. This is how Schelling sees it: Reflection confronts man with
himself. The most noble activity, however, is one that does not know
itself. “As soon as man makes himself the object, it is no longer the
whole man who is acting.” The original balance between powers and
consciousness is sublated through the freedom of reflection. “Mere re¬
flection is a mental illness that nips man’s higher existence in the bud
and kills his spiritual life at the root” (II, 12). Schelling poses the task
of overcoming without destroying what must be risked in reflection by
the thinker.
Reflection is, indeed, the means of becoming master of one’s thoughts.
It is by virtue of reflection that Schelling perceived the sovereignty of
philosophy. Philosophy takes its distance, once again, from all thoughts
entertained by it.
Here, then, is the question addressed to Schelling’s philosophy, which
cannot be answered by a thought, only through familiarity with Schell¬
ing’s work and nature. Who is the master of the thoughts—what is
there, where does the guidance come from?
Could it be that Schelling did not become master of reflection because
it arrogated dominance to itself? Did the genius of the spirit replace
original thought in Schelling?
Externalized reflexivity is called gesture. It is actuality, but is inten¬
tional, demanding, unstable actuality. Schelling loves the grand gesture,
the solemnity of appearance, prophetic dignity. He presents himself as
someone unique, as someone endowed with extraordinary knowledge.
This is how Schelling projected himself and how we see him to this
day.
With Schelling, a new tone entered the history of philosophy. This
urgency, this intensification, this emphasis, this heightened sound played
on an organ, as it were, intends effect. We are forced to listen. The
aristocratic gesture is twisted into philosophic demagoguery. He claims
a certain nobility for himself and yet may lack an unfailing nobility of
the heart. He knows about the nobility of the spirit without being truly
noble himself. He presents himself as an exception, yet fails to be so. He
SCHELLING l55
comes into being that sounds even more fantastic than the religion of
the ancient Egyptians” (I, 405).
The old Schelling still reiterates: “It is a contradiction that eternal
freedom is to be cognized; ... as an absolute subject, it cannot possibly
become/object.” Though Schelling later spoke of the absolute subject in
terms of capability, volition, and desire, he says: “Eternal pure capability
evades everything, it is nonobjective, is absolute inwardness. The same
applies to pure volition and desire.”
However, Schelling forgets this clear insight, though on occasion he
recaptures it momentarily, to the very end. The range of his work
presents a cognition that he has declared to be impossible. For he develops
at all times an objectivity, that is, a history in which that which is, is
thought objectively: as the history of self-consciousness in the stages of
knowing and acting consciousness, as the history of nature in its stages
up to man, as the history of Being as a whole, of the theogonic, cos¬
mogonic, mythological, and revelationary process.
Surprisingly Schelling believes he has overcome the ties to the object,
as well as dogmatic thinking, solely by thinking Being not as object but
as becoming. But becoming is no less objective than being-object, the
system of becoming no less objective than the system of unchangeable
Being. To be sure, his philosophizing is genetic, but that which is thought
genetically, although it is not an objective thing, is an objective supra-
sensuous-sensual process.
The pattern of genetic philosophizing remains constant in Schelling,
no matter whether the content is transcendental consciousness or nature
or the being of God or myth. These contents need not contradict one
another. Rather, they come together in Schelling’s last comprehensive
intuition: his negative and positive philosophy.
Again and again Schelling executes his perilous leap. This he can do
only by becoming the “enthusiast” whose principle he himself had un¬
masked. To this corresponds also his early and late profession of loyalty
to the enthusiasts, whether Boehme or Baader or even Swedenborg.
This leap is not an act of volition. It is not immediately noticeable
to the reader. Schelling grounds his actions in intellectual intuition, by
means of which man is in the center and the origin of all things. The
self-recognition of eternal freedom, presented as a process of Being, is
our own consciousness. Reflection is the driving factor in Being itself.
Or, conversely, our consciousness is self-recognition of eternal freedom.
We are ourselves that process (IX, 225ff.). Hence our ability to recognize
it.
i58 Gnostic Dreamers
5-
6.
once and for all, so that it will not be repeated. Because he fell into it,
those coming after him can study in the light of his example what they
are now able to avoid. Again and again we are exposed to the temptations
to which Schelling succumbed. He shows them to us in grandiose style,
aler^ng us to them for all time. His misjudgment accrues to our benefit.
Schelling’s succumbing to temptation has the exemplary character of a
warning.
Philosophy is of such awesome effect and its seriousness so momen¬
tous that I would be despicable if I did not respond in kind. This is the
path to which Schelling guides us and intends to guide us. However, as
I have tried to indicate, the truth he postulates turns to a still indeter¬
minate degree against his own work and even his nature. Hence he
harbors in himself both greatness and undoing, and we have the task
of orienting ourselves by his greatness while resisting what is his undoing.
Criticism of a great thinker must not be regarded as rejection. Crit¬
icism allows what is great to shine all the more brightly, even the
greatness inherent in the error. My presentation here grows from my
sympathy for Schelling over the decades during which I constantly wres¬
tled with this sympathy. What unites us is Schelling’s quality as a great
philosopher who cannot be bypassed. I hope to have demonstrated my
respect for him in the compass of my struggling with him. No one
possesses the truth, the unlimited, complete, unalloyed truth. It suffices
if a portion of it reaches us, reflectedly, as a stirring, glorious radiance.
V
, ••
■
-
Constructive Minds
LEIBNIZ
V
,
LEIBNIZ
i
/
Editors’ Note
i. BASIC THOUGHT
* *•«
from the traditional elements of his overall thinking. But their meta¬
physical importance remains.limited, since the rational premise of this
form of faith in reason comprehending the ground of things lacks, as
such, metaphysical depth. N
The metaphysical impetus of faith in God’s rationality lends a height¬
ened importance to all rational activity. But then the independent interest
in inventing, the pleasure of operating, making, and creating as such
(whether a calculating machine or a mine, whether minting or political
action) gains the upper hand. Leibniz concerns himself with everything,
takes on almost every task, always by rational means, his ratio grounded
in God; but the question arises as to what degree the original motive
remains powerful and effective, to what degree it is lost in constructions
and procedures, or to what degree it is presented in the infinite actuality
of thinking or is flatly contradicted by it, leaving the merely constructive.
Leibniz’s first great development out of the basic motive took place
in Paris from 1672 to 1676. Especially through his contact with Christian
Huygens, he became the great mathematician who, in connection with
the thought of infinity, succeeded, in 1676, in discovering the differential
and the integral calculus. This achievement has remained to this day his
most famous, since it has been of immeasurable importance for the
mathematical sciences. Leibniz never ceased developing new ideas,
though none of them equaled the aforementioned in specific scientific
relevance. He discovered ever new means of promoting his fundamental
task, that is, to grasp the world in its rationality through the instrument
of one’s own reason.
2. THE MONADOLOGY
As a result, such theses as: the mind is always thinking, even when
we sleep without dreaming, unless it is devoid of all consciousness; or,
the body is never without motion; rest is a minimum of motion; or, a
substance is never without activity—all have an ambiguousness that on
the ojie hand expresses mere metaphysical postulates, and on the other
promises application to practical research, without, however, delivering
on this promise. Here Leibniz’s constructivism is akin to that of Descartes
and Hobbes, as opposed to Galileo, Kepler, Newton. In distinction from
these natural scientists, those philosophers think, to be sure, in mathe¬
matical terms, but without the mathematical method, which is considered
fruitful only as it proves itself in experiment or measured observation.
Such constructivism is to be understood as metaphysics and must not
be confused, even in its fundamental attitude, with science, in whose
garb it appears.
2) A superficial indicator of the difference between science and meta¬
physics is that only the natural sciences allow for a genuine battle over
priorities. It is characteristic that Leibniz could claim priority for many
of his thought-constructs without eliciting any reactions. Over the in¬
vention of the differential and the integral calculus, however, a bitter
battle of priority lasting for decades raged between Leibniz and Newton.
For only here had an actual, weighty, solid discovery been made. Con¬
cerning philosophic thoughts there never was a battle of comparable
significance. For in philosophy there is no actual priority, because there
is no actual theft, either—except when texts are copied; here there is
only originality of thinking, which cannot be repeated in identical form
as is possible with the content of a scientific discovery.
3) Leibniz himself called preestablished harmony a hypothesis, even
if an extremely certain one. He treated his monadology like a scientific
theory of underlying Being, of objectively thought Being-as-such. He
constructed this theory in its ramifications. At specific points he illustrated
rather than proved it by means of facts. The whole is neither gnosis as
it is found in theosophic tradition, nor illumination of Existenz as great
philosophers carry it out by referring their metaphysical vision to man’s
entire conduct of life as well as to his decisions. Herder called Leibniz
a “poet in metaphysics,” Schiller spoke of preestablished harmony as a
“humorous idea by an excellent mind, which he himself never believed,”
Hegel spoke of a “metaphysical novel.”2
b) The truths found on the way despite the absurdity of the whole:
2 Johann Gottfried Herder, Andrastea, in Sammtliche Werfc, Berlin, Weidmann, 1885-86, XXIII,
482. Friedrich Schiller, “Philosophic der Physiologic,” ed. by Oskar Walzel, in Samtliche Werke,
Stuttgart and Berlin, J. G. Cotta, 1904, XI, 21-23. H2. Hegel, Sammtliche Wer\e, XIX, 454.
176 Constructive Minds
The very greatness of Leibniz’s mind leaves no room for any doubt
about it. Even a brief reading is convincing, and more protracted study
increases our admiration. It seems as if Leibniz could not write a single
line without immediately being engrossing, inventive, astonishing. His
bent is toward previously unthought possibilities; he discovers proposi¬
tions and categorial determinations which, because of their essential
nature, are indelibly imprinted on our minds. In his constructs the wealth
of ideas seems inexhaustible. Leibniz’s simplicity, clarity, conciseness,
and the rapid yet unbroken progression of his thought are admirable.
His critical sensitivity rejects the trivial and lets even the absurd appear
ingenious. He is always lively; he discusses, develops, modifies, and stays
in motion, refusing to be fettered automatically by his own categories,
allowing everything to be carried along by the fundamentals of thought
and his own unique attitude.
Wherever we open his writings we are met by clear air, the serene
mood of the desire to know and the gratification afforded by the profound
possibilities of thought and questioning, and of the marvelous things in
the world. In whatever he encounters, he immediately discovers an
inherent problem.
Thought, with him, is transmittable; it is everything, is simply explicit
and hence without the slightest tendency to indirect communication. But
the transmission of this overwhelming multitude of ideas raises severe
difficulties once we attempt to gain an overview.
Historians of philosophy have tried to overcome this by an exposition
of the Leibnizian system.3 But the question is precisely whether, in the
case of Leibniz, we have a closed whole, a total knowledge intended as
such and free of contradiction, or whether, taken as a whole, this thinking
is from the very first riddled with insoluble contradictions. Expressed
differently, the question is whether the will to conciliation and to a
universal complementation actually brings all opposites to a unity of
knowledge that is not only grandiose but also convincing, or whether
the will to unity achieves a mere semblance of such unity that is con¬
structed by means of efficacious principles (development, complementing
the one-sided, continuity, infinity, and so on) and their artful combi¬
nation. Expressed still differently: We ask whether in Leibniz an integral
3 Johann Eduard Erdmann, Versuch einer wissenschaftlichen Darstellung der Geschichte der neueren
Philosophic, repr., H. Glockner, ed. Stuttgart, F. Frommann, 1932, Parts 1-2, vol. 4. Kuno Fischer,
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Leben, Wer{e und Lehre, 5th ed. Heidelberg, C. Winter, 1920. Eduard
Zeller, Geschichte der deutschen Philosophic seit Leibniz, 2nd ed. Munich, R. Oldenbourg, 1875.
LEIBNIZ 181
objective one. The diversity of unique individuals, each in its own orig¬
inality, is seen by him purely as an observer. All are monads, not only
the human spirits; they are differentiated only according to the degree
of clarity in their thinking. The only impulse emanating from his teach¬
ing is directed toward rational clarification; he does not address himself
at all to possible Existenz, at risk because it stands between losing itself
and gaining itself. All existential questions lie beyond the range of his
otherwise universal thought.
There is a connection between this existential lack and the absence
in Leibniz of the whole spiritual realm of Verstehen, the great herme¬
neutics of all possibilities of meaning which, later on, would become the
impetus of system building in Hegel’s philosophy. In Leibniz, universality
is specific, not total. For an individual mind, to be sure, the idea of
universality can be only a fundamental task, one that cannot be carried
through. But Leibniz’s great lacuna lies in the very foundation of his
thinking, a lacuna not filled by the manner of his historical investigations.
Creative Orderers
ARISTOTLE
HEGEL
i
/ INTRODUCTION
Editors’ Note
there is. The excogitated order of everything that is actual, that can be
experienced, thought, executed, also presents the factual order of all
things. Tranquillity is the result of everything being in order. Tran¬
quillity in transcendence is transformed into tranquillity in the All of
harmonious order.
I shall attempt to depict the three great systematizers: Aristotle,
Thomas,1 Hegel. Their achievements are almost beyond comprehension.
Their enormous scope, the thoroughness of their information, their con¬
centration on the particular—wherever it was within their reach—are
just as astonishing as their steadfast adherence to the whole. They did
not allow the immensity of material to overwhelm them, but appropriated
it creatively. They managed to live in the tension between the plenitude
of things and the unifying nature of their grasp, or between apparently
abandoning themselves to the plenitude and the center from which the
plenitude was drawn.
The essay on Thomas Aquinas, because of its fragmentary state, is not included in this volume.
190 Creative Orderers
t
/
Editors’ Note
*95
196 Creative Orderers
1. FIRST PHILOSOPHY
All the matter we encounter is already formed, and all that is formed
is, in turn, possible matter for something else. Everything that is in the
world is in one respect actuality as this form, in another respect it is not
yet; it is possibility, that is, matter.
If our thinking progresses to the outermost limits, then we ought to
be able to find there pure form without matter and pure matter without
form, pure actuality and pure possibility. At the limits there seems to
be complete rest, pure actuality that does not have to become, because
it already is, and pure possibility that cannot become, since, out of itself,
it is nothing but possibility.
Between pure matter and pure form stands all there is as a series of
intermediate steps in which the possible as matter and the actual as form
are united with each other: this is the world, the world of becoming, of
nature. The actuality of our world is motion, the motion from matter
toward form and between the two; it is, in the case of every configuration,
a whole consisting of both.
Motion (kinesis)
If all worldly being lies between form (actuality) and matter (possibility),
then becoming is motion from possibility' to actuality. In all worldly
being, motion (kinesis) is the event in which what as potentiality and
disposition is the foundation comes into actuality and existence.
Motion presupposes the mover and the moved. Form does the mov¬
ing, matter is moved. In their constant motion the things in the world
ARISTOTLE 199
seek and develop their form, which is called their eidos, their logos, their
morphe, their entelechy.
Motion is eternal, as are pure form and pure matter, as eternal as
the world, without beginning or end. What the world is in actuality,
what corhes to be and passes away, is in motion between possibility and
actuality.
But the endlessness of motion in its entirety needs an origin. This origin
is pure actuality (actus purus) without possibility, pure form. It is itself
unmoved but is the ground of motion. It is called the unmoved mover.
Out of love for the unmoved mover, the pure spirit, all things, the world
begins to move.
The pure spirit, itself nonspatial, borders on space. That which
touches it immediately, the outermost heavenly sphere, first starts to
move and passes the motion on to the world. For all effect occurs only
in the immediacy of touch and not from a distance. The incorporeality
of the unmoved mover touches the corporeal.
The causes
In the realm of motion, effects occur in different ways, while still ulti¬
mately issuing from pure actuality and pure possibility, from actus purus
and matter. The causes are structured differently. As causes according
to form, they are called final cause, formal cause, conceptual cause,
moving cause; as material causes, they are called necessary cause, passive
cause, material cause.
rather, it is in the things themselves. Ideas are the forms of things, the
forces effective in them, the entelechies.
Concepts refer to universals. However, in their fundamental con¬
ception universals are not meant as abstractions, but as actuality. Only
through'this actuality, intuited in reason (nous), do these concepts have
their meaning. If philosophically considered such thinking is not to be
an idle game with words but the presentation of actuality itself, then
actuality too is an attribute of the universal and not only of the individual.
Aristotle overcomes this difficulty by differentiating a first ousia from
a second one. The first ousia is the individual being; the second ousia is
the universal concepts of genera and species. But this differentiation too
can be turned around, that is, when Aristotle refers to form as the first
ousia.
The origin of these reversals and seeming contradictions is clear: On
the one hand, form is the ground of the actuality of things; however,
taken by itself, as the universal, it is the object of cognition. On the other
hand, the universal, taken as form, is the ground of the actuality of
things; yet there also is no actuality of individual beings without the
ground of matter. Hence the actuality of individual beings is not ac¬
counted for by means of the universal alone.
These obvious inconsistencies must have been apparent to a mind as
extraordinary as Aristotle’s. But for him they were not inconsistencies,
because, quite naturally, he discerned the individual beings in the very
concepts.
The unity of concept and individual being is evident, surprisingly,
in the sole and distinct actuality of pure form, that is, the being of the
unmoved mover, the deity. This pure being of form without matter, this
pure actuality in the Aristotelian sense, is not, however, the sum or the
ordered whole of all universal forms. Rather, it is itself an individual
being, the only one of its kind, yet, as individual being, alongside other
incorporeal individual beings, the spirits of the spheres and the rational
part of man, as well as alongside all the individual beings of the corporeal
world.
Whenever we take up the problem of the relationship of the universal
to the individual, we realize that it is hardly solved today any more than
in the past. The problem surfaces wherever one differentiates between
the universal and the individual.
It can be expressed in various ways, depending on the presuppositions
of a particular mode of cognition. The mystery aroused by the question
simply gathers depth. It is not solved, but more clearly revealed as mys¬
tery.
202 Creative Orderers
Hence the problem has its own history throughout the ages. It became
famous as a central theme in the profound debates over universals waged
during the Middle Ages. Do universal concepts have actuality? Or are
they merely signs or names which point to actualities by means of ab¬
stractions, without ever capturing them, much less being them? Those
who attributed actuality to concepts were cabled realists; those who saw
only names in them, nominalists. From a nominalist standpoint, to be
designated a conceptual realist amounted to an accusation of illusionary
thinking.
Aristotle was unaware of these contrarieties, so he did not defend
himself against nominalism. Viewed with this later developed position
in mind, we would have to call him a conceptual realist. Since by now
all of us are, in a manner of speaking, nominalists, we have some difficulty
in conjuring up the Aristotelian mind-frame. Aristotle knows the sat¬
isfaction derived from conceptions of reasons or principles since he be¬
lieves that with them he possesses authentic actuality. Hence the
comprehension of all things via these basic concepts signifies cognition
for him. We, however, would see a cipher in the interplay of thoughts,
which arises from the intuitability of things and grows into a picture of
what there is. We regard this way of thinking as a specifically philo¬
sophical one whose truth cannot be tested through arguments and coun¬
terarguments, but, rather, through risking its existential significance, that
is, through the power and tendency to mold whoever lives by it. But as
cognition of the world we would have to reject Aristotle’s entire con¬
ceptual structure, for it is not a means of knowledge, but a specific mode
of formalization.
If there were beings who had always lived beneath the earth, in comfortable, well-
lit dwellings, decorated with statues and pictures . . . and who though they had
never come forth above the ground had learned by report and by hearsay of the
existence of certain deities or divine powers, and then if at some time the jaws of
the earth were opened and they were able to escape from their hidden abode and
to come forth into the regions which we inhabit; when they suddenly had sight of
the earth and the seas and the sky, and came to know of the vast clouds and mighty
winds, and beheld the sun and realized not only its size and beauty but also its
potency, in causing day by shedding light over all the sky, and, after night had
darkened the earth, they then saw the whole sky spangled and adorned with stars,
and the changing phases of the moon’s light . . . and the risings and settings of all
these heavenly bodies and their courses, fixed and changeless throughout all
eternity—when they saw these things, surely they would think the gods exist, not
only by reason, but by a reason that is transcendent and divine.4
Aristotle’s God is “distant” and calming for thought. With him there
is no cult, no predestination, no intercession by God, no activity of God;
there is no prayer directed to him, no love of God for mankind.
But the God who is unhuman and exalted, who calms us from a
distancp through his existence, can be fulfilled in this form through an
original certainty of God, such as that of Spinoza.
God is thought as “place” so that there is no “pantheism,” no iden¬
tification with the all-pervasive soul of nature, the force of nature, the
Stoic world-reason. Hence He is suited to be a schema of the intellect
that can be filled with the transcendent God—suitable for the great
configuration of Christian theology.
c) The “personality” of God: It assumes an impersonal character but
does not become mere force.
I have given the basic concepts of the Aristotelian vision of Being: all-
pervasive nature as motion from potentiality to actuality; the modes of
Being and the reference point of all of them in ousia; the deity as the
unmoved mover who alone is complete actuality and the origin of all
motion.
Aristotle’s philosophy also contains the entire intuitable reality of the
world and all that is in it, including man and his thinking and acting.
How does Aristotle see the arrangement of philosophical cognition of
these areas, and what place within the whole is assigned to the previously
discussed first philosophy? The traditional form of this question concerns
the organization of the philosophical disciplines, and of the sciences.
Aristotle’s answer is grounded in the way he sees the being of man.
Man is the location where thought takes place about everything that is
and is thought about. We can call this Aristotle’s great but by no means
narrow sense of anthropologism. The actuality of man shows us the
organs through which he perceives, thinks, produces with his hands, and
acts thinkingly. It is in humanity that what there is becomes manifest.
What is meant here by “humanity” is not the subjective, which has to
be disregarded in order to attain the objective. Rather, it is the unity of
the subjective and the objective, the place of the appearance of all Being.
How does Aristotle visualize humanity in this sense?
208 Creative Orderers
resents the reality of the world itself), so that even today this vision
remains meaningful as a way of representing the cosmos?
And does it not endure because of its configuration, if only in the
guise of memory? It appears to me that for us the chief value of the
Aristotelian world-picture lies in the contrast to the present lack of such
a picture. We reach full consciousness of the world within which we
live. As a result of our knowledge and our technical prowess, we are
always in the presence of something from which, it is true, the Aristo¬
telian immediacy of reality as an absolute has vanished. But that world
picture can be granted a detached recognition, as a moment in our
experience of the splendor of this world. In this guise the Aristotelian
world-picture is exposed as a blissful illusion, an illusion we wish to
know and learn about, but which has lost all compelling power.
In the modern understanding, our knowledge cannot be completed;
it proceeds in directions of inquiry that have opened up the reality of
the cosmos and of all natural things as never before. The last half-century
has brought us such tremendous discoveries in physics, chemistry, as¬
tronomy, and biology that we are conscious of living in a unique age,
one of Promethean creativity.
Hence, for our cognition the world is pulled in several directions,
each demanding a different methodology; it is infinitely investigable but
is uncompleted and uncompletable.
Moreover, our technological advance has taken a step well beyond
Prometheus’s lighting of the torch, leading in principle into a different
dimension. In the early 1920s, Nernst6 said: We live on a powder keg
—a good thing that man does not find the match to blow it up. This
point, it is true, is still far from man’s grasp. But that it—a process that
would let the limited chain reactions of today suddenly extend to the
entire matter of the globe—will be reached no longer belongs to the
absolutely impossible. The Earth would glow and our solar system would
look like a nova for any other beings alive in the cosmos—just as we
observe such novas from time to time in the skies.
Something else has become totally and inescapably certain during
the last few years: by means of radioactive substances man can destroy
all life on Earth and thus also himself.
We know the unique combination of conditions required for life on
Earth to exist. It can be demonstrated how cosmic rays with the capacity
to destroy us are warded off by the Earth’s protective layer, how the
radioactive elements of Earth send out their rays only in amounts that
But what is life? Where does it come from? How can it come to
be? What is man’s position in this coherence of all that is alive? Through
what means did he come to be?
We do not have the answers, no matter how much we know about
things that could perhaps contribute to answers.
Th^re is more in the cosmos than is known or can be known by
present-day investigation.
On the one hand, Aristotle’s picture of the cosmos has become con¬
stricted, full of holes, broken up, and yet, on the other hand, it might
be called broad: It keeps open the space for that which we do not know
but may not deny for that reason; it leaves open the view on what
effected the origin of life and brought human beings into existence, and
for what might be called, following Aristotle, the divine as ground of
all things, mover and creator of the cosmos, bringing us infinitely closer
to the Encompassing.
of life, or science, which, even at that time, owing to its very nature,
exhibited the characteristics of modern science.
3) For our understanding of Aristotelian philosophy this last question
is of decisive importance: What in it pertains to science and what to
philosophy? Are they the same or different, and in what sense can we
speak of science and philosophy in Aristotle?
He himself does not draw this distinction. But he differentiates in¬
dividual sciences, which, to him, are all philosophies, and he differentiates
from them “first philosophy,” which we call metaphysics.
In view of historical development to the present time, two conclusions
have been reached. First: Aristotle is the founder of the sciences in the
modern sense. Second: Aristotle is the founder of scientific philosophy.
We have to see in what sense these two conclusions, which apply con¬
jointly, are appropriate. Let me anticipate the result: The first conclusion
is fallacious if it is meant to refer to what is unique and genuinely great
in modern science, whose beginnings Aristotle actually misunderstood.
The second conclusion is correct, but in the sense that Aristotle is the
founder of that philosophy, which ultimately puts an end to authentic
philosophizing, even while he still carries it on. However, faced with
those two prevailing interpretations, to which I gave such extreme for¬
mulations, the unique and enduring value of Aristotelian thinking has
to be clearly characterized.
Aristotle directs himself toward the totality of the world, including God
and man; his thinking is universal as well as comprehensive in content.
His is the architectonic principle which, directed at the whole, would
not omit anything. He constantly arranges and develops. His thinking
does not reach a final conclusion, yet its fundamental sense is not to
exclude anything but to presuppose everything. In Aristotle the nature
of closure does not consist in an accomplished construction of the whole,
but in the basic schemata of comprehension.
There is something satisfactory in Aristotle’s immediate comprehen¬
sion. All who follow him are included in his schemata of comprehension,
which present themselves naturally and immediately, are instantly un¬
derstandable, and are palpably close at hand.
According to Cicero, he himself had hopes of philosophy’s being
completed in the foreseeable future/
philosophy does not lie between Classicism and Hellenism but between
the Original and the Secondary.
Our understanding
8. PHILOSOPHY
I
/
Editors’ Note
THE DIALECTIC
We shall proceed from examples, from a tiny number out of the tre¬
mendous mass of Hegel’s configurations of thought. Only by participating
in the dialectical movements, and not merely speaking about them, can
we hope to understand what is happening here.
Without the experience gained from the examples of dialectics, the
discussions that follow would be as incomprehensible as a lecture by an
art historian about works the listener has never seen and would not be
shown. Moreover, the picture shown by the historian of philosophy is
not a photocopy of the text itself, but of a reproduction. This reproduction
is an art that already interprets as it reproduces.
All direct formulations about dialectics (including those by Hegel
221
222 Creative Orderers
A. Sense-certainty
Exposition
1 References giving volume and page are to Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegels Werke, ed. by
P. Marnheinecke et al.\ those to Phanomenologie des Geistes are additionally to the edition of
J. Hoffmeister.
HEGEL 223
velopment; nor is it certain of itself because the object might have shown
itself in its rich relationship to itself and in its manifold relation to others.
Without such mediation, the truth of sense-certainty is simple immediacy,
which is really nothing as yet. Consciousness is only this and nothing
beyond tf. 'The singular “I,” the pure “this,” knows the singular thing,
the pure “this.”
2. The “falling-out” of “I” and object. As soon as we speak of im¬
mediacy as “this," more has happened than merely addressing immediacy
itself. There has occurred, right away, the first “mediation,” in that “I”
and object “fell out” of immediacy, a “this” as “I” and a “this” as object.
The philosophical observer sees that pure immediacy has thereby
been sublated. For this consciousness in the split of “I” and object is
already mediated: I have the certainty through an other, namely, the
thing; and the same applies to certainty through an other, namely,
through the “I.”
With this mediation there begins, in sense-certainty, the movement
in which is revealed what it is: first the object, second the “I,” third the
whole, consisting of “I ” and object—all three dissolve in their immediacy.
3. The dissolution of the object. Sense-certainty has to be asked: What
is the “this”? It is the Now and the Here.
To the question What is the Now? the answer is:
The Now is the night. We write down this truth. If now, this noon,
we look again at the truth we have written, it has become stale. The
written truth is treated as being, but it turns out to be a nonbeing
(2, 75-76; Phan., 67).
The Now is preserved, but as something neither night nor day—
a negative as such. Its being something that is permanent and self¬
preserving is determined by the nonbeing of an other, namely, day and
night. A simple thing of this kind, which is, through negation, neither
This nor That, a Not-This, we call a universal. The universal, therefore,
is the truth of sense-certainty. The self-preserving Now is a mediated
one and, as such, a universal.
The same applies to the Here as to the Now. Here is the tree. I turn
around: here is the house. But the Here itself does not vanish. It abides
in the vanishing of house, tree, and so on. Again this shows itself as a
mediated simplicity, a universality of the Here (2, 76-77; Phan., 68).
This pure Being, however, the Now and the Here as such, is not
what is meant by sense-certainty. What is left over is only the most
universal and most abstract, the empty and indifferent Now and Here.
But still left is our opinion, for which the truth of sense-certainty is
not the universal. Now the object has become the nonessential. The true
224 Creative Orderers
Reflections
nature is the same as human nature, and it is this unity that is beheld.
“The absolute Being [Wesen] which exists as an actual self-consciousness
seems to have come down from its eternal simplicity, but by thus coming
down has, in fact, attained for the first time to its own highest essence
[Wesen], . . . What is called sense-consciousness is . . . this thinking for
which Being is the immediate. Thus the lowest is at the same time the
highest; the revealed which has come forward wholly onto the surface
is precisely therein the most profound. That the supreme being is seen,
heard, etc. as an immediately present self-consciousness, this therefore
is, indeed, the consummation of its concept” (2, 569, 570, 571; Phan., 487,
488, 489; Mi, H760).
Once more, at the end of The Phenomenology of Spirit, at the point
where absolute knowledge is attained and where the science of philos¬
ophy takes place, the return to the beginning of phenomenology in sense-
certainty is reached in the following manner: This science of absolute
knowing (developed later on in Hegel’s Logic and continued in the
Realphilosophie of nature and history) “contains within itself this necessity
of stepping out of the form of pure concept and it contains the passage
of the notion into consciousness . . . into the certainty of immediacy
... or sense-consciousness—the beginning from which we started. This
release of itself from the form of its self is the supreme freedom and
assurance of its self-knowledge” (2, 610; Phan., 520; Mi, 1f8o6).
This eternal happening which brings about time and space, this
externalizing into this apartness has the following dialectical basis: The
self-knowing Spirit’s “knowing knows not only itself but also the negative
of itself, or its limit; to know one’s limit is to know how to sacrifice
oneself. This sacrifice is the externalization in which Spirit displays the
process of becoming Spirit in the form of free contingent happening,
intuiting its pure Self as time outside of it, and likewise its Being as
space” (2, 610; Phan., 620; Mi, H807).
Thus, Spirit wends its way through nature and history.
7. On Feuerbach’s criticism. Whoever reads Hegel’s sequences of ideas
for the first time finds himself, in most instances, at a loss. What is it
that Hegel wants to prove, what to refute? What is the outcome? Instead
of being given an unequivocal answer, the reader is driven to go on. He
is not allowed to stop, for only in what is to come will truth become
manifest. The result is not the attainment of a specific knowledge-content,
but the whole of the dialectical road traveled, which is now reaching its
completion.
In order to open our senses to this astonishing procedure, a look at
HEGEL 229
* Ludwig Feuerbach, “Zur Kritik der Hegel’schen Philosophie” (1839), in Samtliche Wer\e, vol.
2. Leipzig, 1846, 185-232.
230 Creative Orderers
It is not reality that is denied to sensuous things (if they were not
real they could not be eaten as food), but absolute actuality. Hegel does
not assert that sense-reality is superfluous (for God himself becomes
sensuous man), but that an aspect of sense-reality has the character of
the absolute (man-become-God dies and has his actuality in time in the
form of remembrance).
That Being itself becomes temporal does not signify only the noth¬
ingness of the temporal as such but also the authenticity of the temporal.
What passes away as finite sensibility in time is sublated in the time¬
lessness of Being where it originated.
As temporal and trivial Being the sensuous becomes an object-image;
but in disappearing, it is the manifestation of the eternal.
Comment
what the spirit is, this absolute substance which, in the complete freedom
and independence of its opposite, namely of various self-consciousnesses
that are for themselves, constitutes their unity; the I that is We, and the
We that is I” (ibid.).
3) Hegel anticipates the form of this movement before all his represen¬
tations of concrete movement:
a) There is for self-consciousness another self-consciousness; it has
come outside itself (2, 140; Phan., 123). This has a twofold meaning: it
has lost itself for it finds itself as another being; with this it has sublated
the other, for it does not see the other as a being, but sees itself in the
other.
b) “It must sublate its being other” (ibid.). This sublation of the first
double meaning is a second double meaning: First, self-consciousness
must aim at sublating the other independent being in order to become
certain of itself as that being; second, it thus aims at sublating itself, for
this other is itself.
c) The consequence of this ambiguous sublation is an ambiguous
return into itself. In the first place it receives its own self back through
the sublation; because, by sublating its otherness, it again becomes equal
to itself. But, in the second place, it gives the other self-consciousness
back again to itself, for it sublates its being in the other and in this way
lets the other again go free (2, 141; Phan., 124).
d) Thus all acts of self-consciousness are presented only as acts of
the One. But these acts of the One again have a double meaning: They
are just as much the acts of the one as those of the other. For the other
is equally independent, closed in himself. He has no power over the
other if he does not do to himself what he does to him. The movement
is that of the self-consciousness of both. Each does himself what he
demands of the other. Therefore self-consciousness does what it does
only insofar as the other does the same. One-sided action would be
useless because what is to happen can come to be only through both (2,
141; Phan., 124).
The same, expressed differently: What prevails for self-consciousness
is that it is and is not other consciousness immediately. Equally, the other
is only for itself by sublating itself as that-which-is-for-itself, and is for
itself the other only in being-for-itself. Each is the center for the other,
through which each mediates and joins with itself. Each is at the same
time for itself only through this mediation. “They acknowledge each
other as mutually acknowledging each other” (2, 142; Phan., 125).
That means self-consciousness is in and for itself through being for
another in and for itself; “it is only as something acknowledged.” The
234 Creative Orderers
that endures unchanged and represents the end. Instead, the master as
well as the servant now experiences a new movement—in fact, the very
reverse.
4) The master. Only the master has the unrestricted consciousness of
his beingrfor-himself. The servant acknowledges him, but he does not
acknowledge the servant. There has come about a one-sided and unequal
recognition. Lacking here is the recognition that what the master does
to the other he also does to himself, and that what the servant does to
himself he should also do to the other (cf. Mi, IJ191).
In achieving his mastery, the master has, in fact, gained something
quite different from an independent consciousness. Because he alone is
independent, is for himself, and only through recognition by his non-
independent servant, he finds himself the empty point whose indepen¬
dence has lost the movement that he sees only in the actions of the
servant. The master can fight, risk his life, and subjugate others but does
not come to himself by doing so, since, being alone and without concerted
movement with other independent individuals, he becomes empty him¬
self. He cannot make use of being master once the struggle and the risk
to life have ceased.
The master finds himself at a dead end.
Influenced by Hegel’s thought, Hebbel had Holofernes say: “Some¬
times, surrounded by all these imbeciles, I feel as though I were the only
one existing. . . . Oh, for an enemy, a single one, who would dare to
defy me! . . . Everything I respect I must destroy. . . . What a wretched
place the world appears to me. I think I was born to destroy it . . . let
him come, my challenger, he who will overthrow me. I long for him!
It is tedious to have nothing to honor save oneself.”5 Frederick the Great
is said to have exclaimed: “I am tired of ruling over slaves.”
5) The servant. The servant posits his own consciousness as unessen¬
tial, first, in working on things whose obstinacy confronts him, and by
fashioning them through his work to become something objective; sec¬
ond, in his dependence on another existence, the master, whom he obeys
as the free self-consciousness he recognizes. Unable to achieve mastery
over Being and to arrive at the absolute negation of his existence in
death, the servant now does to himself, in the existence preserved in
him, what the master does to him.
But this is indeed an analogue to trial by death. For he who became
a servant has experienced death. “For this consciousness has experienced
fear not for this or that, or at odd moments, but for his whole being;
5 Friedrich Hebbel (1813-1863), German dramatist; references are to Judith, Acts 1 and 5.
23 8 Creative Orderers
since it has felt the fear of death, the absolute master. In that experience
it has been quite unmanned, has trembled in every fiber of its being,
and everything solid and stable has been quaking” (2, 148; Phan., 129;
Mi, Hi94). \
Such an experience has transformed his essence; but only such an
experience is able to do that. “If it has not .experienced absolute fear but
only some lesser dread, the negative being has remained for it something
external, its substance has not been infected by it through and through.”
If it had not been that way and remained that way, then “the entire
contents of its natural consciousness had not been jeopardized,” then
“determinate being in principle still belongs to it,” then, having “a mind
of one’s own” is obstinacy,6 a freedom still enmeshed in servitude (2,
150; Phan., 131; Mi, H196).
As though he had died, the servant eradicates his existence in ser¬
vitude, obedience, labor. But herein freedom is accrued for him and not
for the master. For the nature of self-consciousness is absolute negativity.
It has actualized itself as creative, negatively in death and in the empty
self-consciousness of the master, and positively only in the servant. This
self-consciousness fulfills itself actually in service instead of dissolving
totally into nonactuality. “Through his service he sublates his attachment
to natural existence in every aspect; and gets rid of it by work.” By
serving he achieves what he wanted to avert by refusing death: he sublates
his dependence on natural existence. This occurs through labor and
servitude (2, 143; Phan., 130; Mi, H194).
Work: Through work the servant comes “to himself.” “The negative
relation to the object becomes its form and something permanent. Work
is arrested transitoriness, or: it educates” (2, 143; Phan., 130; Mi, H195).
The object gains independence and so does the worker (even if at first
merely “in itself,” not “for itself”). Working consciousness arrives “at
the intuition of independent being as itself” (2, 149; Phan., 130). Through
being made external to him the result of his work does not become
something other than the worker. “It is precisely in his work that he
acquires a mind of his own” which is no longer obstinacy (ibid.). He
brings forth a world ranging from agriculture to the creation of churches
and palaces, which are enjoyed by others. But this is a world in which
he recognizes himself, in which he is free with himself, and is in himself
free in the other, and in what has been produced, whereas the consumer
approaches the meaning—if he understands it at all—only at a distance
and passively. Whereas the master enjoys and, in his desire and its
6 Hegel s play on words: a mind of one’s own — eigener Sinn; obstinacy = Eigensinn.
HEGEL 239
recognition is already present there. In the state the individual obeys the
laws. “In the state the citizen receives his honor through the office he
holds, through the trade he practices and through his other work-related
activity. Through this his honor has a substantial, universal, objective
content no longer dependent on empty subjectivity; this is still lacking
in the state of nature.” “The struggle for recognition and the subordi¬
nation to a master is the phenomenon from which arose man’s communal
life, which is how states started to be” (7b, 278, 279-80; Enc., H432, Z,
433)-
Pedagogical import of servitude: The servant “works off, in serving
his master, his individual will and his self-will, sublates the inner im¬
mediacy of desire and, in this divestment and his fear of his master,
takes a first step toward wisdom—the transition to universal self-
consciousness” (7b, 281; Enc., H435).
And in its general application: “Without having experienced the
discipline that breaks self-will, nobody becomes free, rational, and capable
of commanding. Hence, in order to become free—to become capable of
ruling oneself—all peoples have had to pass first through the strict
discipline of subjugation to a master” (7b, 282; Enc., H435, Z).
Appraisal of the servant: “Those who remain servants do not suffer
any absolute injustice; for whoever lacks the courage to risk his life for
the sake of gaining his freedom—he deserves to be a servant.” But to
the extent that the servant does in fact raise himself above the selfish
individuality of his natural will, he stands, “as far as his value is con¬
cerned, on a higher plane than the master who is caught in his own
egotism . . . and who is recognized by an unfree consciousness in a
formal manner. The subjugation of the egotism of the servant constitutes
the beginning of the true freedom of man” (7b, 281-82; Enc., H435, Z).
Universal self-consciousness: Out of the struggle evolved the division
into the extremes of master and servant; out of the development of the
servant universal self-consciousness will evolve, which is the knowledge
of myself in the other self.
This universal self-consciousness “is the form of the knowledge of
the substance of all essential spirituality—of family, fatherland, state, as
well as of all virtues, of love, friendship, valor, honor, renown” (7b, 283-
84; Enc., H436).
7) If, in assuring ourselves of the truth 'of this dialectic—through vi¬
sualization based on inner actions and vivid events—we ask about the
origin of the evidence, the question becomes more specific: Is it a matter
of movements in the self-consciousness of the individual? of the meaning
of work for liberation in the creation of a world? of the fear of death
HEGEL 241
absorb each moment, avoiding being drawn into any particular moment
as though it were the absolute one.
Sense-certainty is the beginning to which the circle returns in the
end, having, on the way, already experienced in increasing fulfillment a
return to phis certainty. In the same way self-consciousness is for self-
consciousness in mutuality the point of departure whose immediacy is
the mutual struggle, then in the relation of mastery and servitude, then
in the new dialectics of being-master and being-servant only to enter
farther into the movement at the end of which stands the reconciliation
in the spiritual daylight of the eternal present.
2) The completion of recognizing each other as mutually recognizing
each other.
a) On the way to the complete unity of self-being in the multiplicity
of selves lies the “life of a people.” This is the “universal substance.”
“Reason is present here as the fluid universal substance . . . which in
the same way bursts apart into many wholly independent beings just as
light bursts apart into stars as countless self-luminous points” (2, 265;
Phan., 232; Mi, U350). The individuals are conscious of being these single
independent beings through the sacrifice of their singularity and because
this universal substance is their soul and essence.
b) Between two singular individuals the movement completes itself
in forgiveness and reconciliation.
First of all Hegel describes the moral consciousness of the other. The
one who judges, who sets himself up in this inactuality and conceit of
knowing-better, places himself above the deeds he discredits and wants
the “words without deeds to be taken for a superior actuality.” Hegel
calls this “insidious” and hypocritical because it “passes off such judging
not as another way of being wicked but as the right consciousness of
the action” (2, 502; Phan., 430; cf. Mi, H666).
Thus the one who acts recognizes him who passes judgment as his
equal. “Perceiving this identity and giving expression to it, he confesses
this to the other, and expects likewise that the other—having in fact
put himself on the same level—will also respond in words in which he
will express his identity with him, and expects that this mutual recog¬
nition will now exist in fact” (2, 503; Phan., 430; Mi, H666).
“But the confession of the wicked: This is the way I am, is not
followed by a reciprocal similar confession.” Quite the contrary; the
judgment “rejects this community of nature and is the hard heart. . . .”
It remains for itself and rejects any community with the other. It refuses
“the emergence of its own inner being into the outer existence of speech”
244 Creative Orderers
and contraposes the “wicked with the beauty of his own soul”; it counters
“the confession of the penitent with his own stiff-necked . . . character,
mutely keeping himself to himself and refusing to throw himself away
for someone else.” This is the “extreme form of revolt of the Spirit
certain of itself.” It refuses to initiate communication with the one who
made the confession, who, in his admission, renounced separate con¬
sciousness. It reveals itself as a consciousness forsaken by the spirit, for
it does not recognize “that spirit, in the absolute certainty of itself, is
master over every deed and actuality and can cast them off and make
them as if they had never happened” (2, 503-04; Phan., 430-31; Mi, H667).
The scene has been reversed. The judgmental and separated “beau¬
tiful soul” has become Being devoid of spirit as well as devoid of actuality
in the immediacy of this firmly held antithesis. It ends “unhinged to the
point of madness in its unreconciled immediacy and wastes itself in
yearning consumption” (2, 505; Phan., 432; Mi, 1I668).7
The path leads in another direction: The “breaking of the hard heart”
is the same movement that was expressed by the one who “made confes¬
sion.” The consciousness confesses: “The wounds of the spirit heal with¬
out leaving scars; the deed is not imperishable but is taken back by the
Spirit into itself.” The one who confesses “exhibits the power of the
Spirit over his actual existence,” as the breaking of the hard heart shows
“the power of Spirit over the specific concept of itself” (2, 505; Phan.,
432; Mi, U668-69).
The result is forgiveness. The one who judges renounces his unactual
nature by equating it with that other which was a real action: “The
word of conciliation is the objectively existing Spirit which beholds the
pure knowledge of itself qua universal essence in its opposite” (2, 506;
Phan., 433; Mi, %yo).
Here Hegel’s language rises to the comprehension of intuition. “It
is the actual I, the universal knowledge of itself in its absolute opposite,
in the knowledge that remains in-itself, and which, on account of the
purity of its separated being-in-itself, is itself completely universal. The
reconciling Yea, in which the two I’s let go of their antithetical existence,
is the existence of the I which has expanded into a duality wherein it
remains identical with itself, and in its complete externalization and
opposite, possesses the certainty of itself; it is God manifested among
those who know themselves in the form of pure knowledge” (2, 507-
08; Phan., 434; Mi, H671).
c) Religion and, finally, absolute knowing, complete, as actual con-
7 Hegel’s play on words is lost in translation: Schwindsucht, the German word for the disease
“consumption,” can mean the strong desire to waste away.
HEGEL 245
8 Jaspers probably noted this reference from memory. He is most likely referring to Hegel’s
Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, 12, 434: “Logic is God in the ether of pure thought” —Hans
Saner.
g In Logic, Introduction, 3, 36, Hegel characterizes logic as “representation of God ... as He
is in His eternal essence prior to the creation of nature and of a finite spirit” —Hans Saner.
HEGEL 247
1.
2.
i-
The statement “Being and Nothing are the same” expresses the identity
of these two determinations—which are not yet supposed to be
determinations—both of which it also contains as differentiated. Hence
“in itself it contradicts itself and dissolves.” It is a statement that “contains
the movement of disappearing through itself”; there happens to it that
“which is supposed to constitute its true content, namely, Becoming' (3,
88-89).
The statement “Being and Nothing are the same” appears to be such
a paradoxical statement to the imagination or to the intellect that it might
not be recognized as seriously meant. But in Hegel it possesses an all-
dominating seriousness. ^
To be sure, the statement is indeed “one of the most difficult that
thinking demands of itself” (6, 171; Enc., H88). Being and Nothing are
opposition in its full immediacy; as yet no determination containing the
relation of the one to the other is being thought in it. Yet in it I think,
HEGEL 249
4-
The proposition Being and Nothing are “to all intents and purposes different”
is just as correct as its opposite (6, 172; Enc., U88; cf. 3, 89-90). Becoming
would not be Becoming, but static identity, if only the being-the-same
of Being and Nothing were valid. Only the fact that the unity of Being
and Nothing maintains absolute differentiation in itself constitutes its
concrete concept.
The differentiation of Being and Nothing is, as such, devoid of
relation. Hence to express the difference as Being and not-Being would
be inappropriate: the relation to Being would be introduced through the
word “not-Being.” The Nothing is “the negation devoid of relation—
something one . . . could express also through the mere: Not” (3, 79).
5-
Since Being and Nothing lack all determination, that is, remain within
immediacy, difference is also not as yet determined. It is the inexpressible,
the merely meant. Both Being and Nothing are “the same ground¬
lessness.” Being is “not a particular, definite thought, but, rather, the
still wholly indeterminate thought that precisely for this reason cannot
be differentiated” (6, 171; Enc., H87, Z).
It is impossible to indicate a difference between Being and Nothing,
for in order to do so we would need a determinateness. Both, however,
are the sheerly indeterminate. “If Being and Nothing had any deter¬
minateness at all by means of which they would differ, they would be
. . . determinate Being and determinate Nothing, and not pure Being
and pure Nothing. . . . Hence the difference between them is completely
empty; each of the two is the indeterminate in the same way”; they are
“empty thought-things” (3, 91, 82).
The first thought is that of Becoming, in which Being and Nothing
are thought, whereas they cannot really be thought each for itself. In
Becoming, Being and Nothing have “their consistence.” They are dif¬
ferentiated in their Becoming. They consist only in an other, in a third,
in Becoming. Their consistency is only their being in one (3, 82).
250 Creative Orderers
6.
The question is asked: How does the static unity of being-the-same of
Being and Nothing turn into the moving unity of Becoming?
Hegel answers: Within the sequential presentation of the text, Being
and Nothing are discussed first, followed by Becoming. But in truth
Becoming is first (3, 93; 6, 175-76; Enc., f 88, Z). Comprehension proceeds
from Becoming. Becoming does not become, but is the beginning from
which we think back to that which-—in an act of meaning-reference to
the unthinkable—is isolated, devoid of relation, as Being and Nothing,
only to be sublated at once. Becoming is the first concrete concept (all
true concepts are concrete concepts) following what is merely meant.
It is always this way in Hegel’s dialectics of becoming-manifest: The
result is in fact the beginning. Bringing-itself-forth is not a result that
follows cogently from beginnings merely expressed. Hence the circle is
the correct picture for this thought-process, which does not know a real
beginning aside from itself as a whole, but which is the movement that
illuminates itself.
7-
5.
9-
10.
which it is for its own self, and thus gives itself an object of its own
production” (6, 25; Enc., If 17; W, § 17).10
But that means that the “I” as such has vanished in Being itself. The
process of production is the rule of the matter itself in pure thought,
whichvas thought, simply has the form of the “I think.”
The road of this experience leads to the limits where no special
thought is carried out any longer and no object is thought, and where
Being and the thinking of Being in the self-being of the “I” are the
same; where I, having stood at the edge of the abyss, am indeterminately
certain of Being in all its possibility; where, out of the stillness of coming
to a standstill, I am, after all abstraction, again I, thinking I, and hear
myself, as it were, by experiencing the dialectic of the movement of
thought through carrying it out.
b) The beginning is the “decision to want to thin\ purely, achieved
through the freedom that abstracts from everything and takes hold of
its pure abstraction, that is, the simplicity of thought.” Reaching the
beginning demands “total absence of presupposition,” total skepticism
must precede everything so that now pure thought can be accomplished
and develop its certitude (6, 146; Enc., U78; W, §78).
Hence the beginning of philosophy is “a beginning only in relation
to the person who proposes to philosophize.” The beginning has no
relation “to the science (of philosophy) as such” (6, 26; Enc., Hi7). Being
has no beginning, nor does the thinking which is this Being itself. The
thoughtful action of the individual human being has a beginning, as
does its presentation in a work.
c) What is achieved for us through the mediation of abstraction is
the immediate, that which is not mediated by anything.
“The indeterminate, as we have it here, is the immediate, not the
mediated indeterminate, not the sublation of all determinateness, but the
immediacy of indeterminateness preceding all determinateness, indeter¬
minateness at the very first” (6, 166; Enc., f86, Z, 1). It cannot be felt
or perceived by sense or pictured in imagination: it is pure thought.
d) We free ourselves from all that is determinate, submerge ourselves
in the abyss of the indeterminate of Being, which is Nothing.
If I want to grasp it determinately as Being, it is already in existence;
it comes to be and passes away. Then Being and Nothing cease “to be
abstractions by receiving a determinate content... only existence contains
the real difference between Being and Nothing, namely a Something
and Other” (3, 85).
10 References preceded by W are to Hegel's Logic, trans. by William Wallace, emended as needed.
254 Creative Orderers
12 Cf. Alfons Lehmen’s Lehrbuch der Philosophic auf aristotelisch-scholasticher Grundlage; I: Logif(,
358; 4th ed. Freiburg-im-Breisgau, Herder, 1917.
HEGEL 257
the beginning of Logic in Being, Nothing, and Becoming. His thesis is:
Being exists in actuality, but Nothing, not-Being, exists only in the
imagination and in reflection. “Nothing is that which is . . . devoid of
thought and reason. Nothing cannot be thought at all, for thinking is
determining . . . and therefore would cease to be Nothing” (II, 223).13
All of Hegel’s propositions about Nothing are, according to Feuer¬
bach, in fact already determinations (simple self-identity, and so on).
“Thinking cannot go beyond beings since it cannot go beyond itself,
because reason only means positing Being, because only this or that being
but not Being . . . can be thought as having become” (II, 224).
“The thinking of Nothing is self-contradictory thinking. He who
thinks Nothing just does not think . . . hence it can be thought only by
being made into Something. Thus at the same moment when it is
thought, it is not thought, for I always think the opposite of Nothing”
(ibid.).
“Nothing is the limit of reason . . . which reason posits for itself”
(II, 226).
“Nothing is just Nothing, — hence also Nothing for thinking; Noth¬
ing further can be said about it; for Nothing refutes itself. Only imag¬
ination turns Nothing into a substantive.” “Admitting that it occurs . . .
in our thought, does it therefore belong in our logic? Even ghosts occur
in our thought” (II, 229, 227). Feuerbach’s critique lives in and by He¬
gelian thought. There is hardly anything in it that has not been said by
Hegel himself. But all Hegel’s statements are changed in their meaning;
they cease to be links in a dialectical movement that advances into the
ground of Being and allows whatever may issue from it; rather, they
become a game under Hegel’s direction but as such denatured, merely
a clever game of constant self-sublation, its stake not speculative under¬
standing but the banality of finite existence and being-there, of an intellect
which grasps only finitudes. Nothing remains of Hegelian speculative
experience except that its dicta are used for defiant banality. It is from
this remaining trace, reflected in the emptying and twisting show, that
the superficial vitality and the illusion of spirit in this childish game
arise.
Such objections make us see more clearly what Hegel means and
what he does, but also about what perhaps he remains in the dark,
carried away by the conviction that in universal dialectic he is bringing
to mind absolute knowledge. We shall now try to explain what this
dialectic is.
13 Ludwig Feuerbach, “Zur Kritik der Hegel’schen Philosophic” (1839), in Samtliche Wer\e, ed.
by W. Bolin and F. Jodi, II, 185-232. Stuttgart, Frommann, 1903-
258 Creative Orderers
Introduction
If I ask, What is Being? I want to know what it is. Hegel supplies the
answer. Being has opened itself to him completely in thinking the truth,
but has done so in a manner alien to everyday thinking. The true can
be grasped almost nowhere, or everywhere. Nowhere, because it is in
no thing, in no object, in nothing determinately known; everywhere,
because it is in motion. The true does not lie in a statement, in which
it would be firmly embedded. The true is the whole, in which the
movement completes itself.
1) Wherever I take hold, that which I know as Being turns out to
be something it is not. It is—not authentically, not absolutely—but in
a vanishing configuration.
That which authentically is, is not in the sense of a thing. It is not
a fixed, self-enclosed object. These objects are merely in transition. They
come on the scene and melt away, they art here and are sublated in the
movement of truth, which preserves in itself everything it traverses, thus
steadily becoming richer.
2) Being is knowing and being-known. What would that be which
is known by no one and cannot be known? It would be as nothing. If
HEGEL 261
(5> 342)-
e) In Hegel’s dialectic negativity has not only a negating meaning
but also one that propels the new Yes. The negative sublates what has
been grasped by it, but in a threefold sense: It destroys it; it preserves
it; it raises it to a higher plane. That which preserves and drives upward
is “what is most important in rational cognition”; “to preserve in the
result the positive in its negative, the content of the presupposition” (5,
340).
The negative is false as the merely negative, “which does not catch
sight of the positive in itself’ (2, 47; Phan., 40). Thus the absolute freedom
of the French Revolution is the point of departure for the terror in which
the negation becomes “the meaningless death, the pure terror of the
negative which harbors nothing positive, nothing fulfilling” (2, 449;
Phan., 386).
3) Immediacy and mediation: Being is Immediate; I am immediate in
my murky torpor, am not actuality but possibility. Only negation awak¬
ens, by creating movement.
Examples: According to Hegel’s dialectic of master and servant I am
actual for myself as self-being only when I have risked my life and have
HEGEL 265
of the negative . . . the energy of thought” (2, 25, 26; Phan., 22). “Death
... is of all things the most dreadful and to hold fast to what is dead
requires the greatest strength. Lacking strength, beauty hates the un¬
derstanding for asking from her what she cannot do. But the life of the
Spirit is not the life that shrinks from death and keeps itself untouched
by devastation but rather the life that endures it and maintains itself in
it” (2, 26; Phan., 22; Mi, H32).
The activity of the understanding is compared here to the devastation
of death. The inner action of Existenz influences the spiritual activity
of observing dialectically, lends it weight but also allows it to become
ambiguous. In any case, what is decisive for Hegel’s philosophy is the
following: It is not mysticism, not edifying talk, not whispering, sug¬
gesting, limiting, but, rather, what he calls “the exertion of the concept”
(2, 46; Phan., 39). The understanding serves dialectical speculation as a
means in every one of its movements. No dialectic without understand¬
ing! Yet the dialectic cannot be comprehended by means of the under¬
standing that serves it. It is “mysticism for the understanding” (6, 59;
Enc., H82, Z).
5) What the understanding contrasts (negative dialectically) is linked
together by reason (positive dialectically). The static concept of the un¬
derstanding, which is used in every proposition, is taken up into the
concept of reason only in the sequence of propositions, where it manifests
itself in its wholeness.
Being is torn apart just as much by negativity as bound into oneness
and wholeness. The struggle of separation is followed by reconciliation in
wholeness. Negativity drives forward the movement, which in the end
is completed in the reconciliation of all opposites.
At bottom and as a whole, Being is separation and return to itself.
Negativity is the suffering of existence, and this suffering is the foun¬
tainhead of actualized Being.
Hegel knows no limit in the development of sufferings through all
their configurations up to the “speculative Good Friday.” “God ... is
dead” (1, 157). This proposition denotes the most extreme negativity,
which immediately turns around dialectically into “God is risen.” Each
suffering seemingly fated to end in despair soon finds its way to return:
it was merely the dialectical negative movement. Reconciliation is the
encircling bond of the whole. Thus, in studying Hegel’s philosophy,
which penetrates into all abysses and seems to risk the ultimate, the
reader remains unperturbed; in the end everything is in order, secure
and positive.
In other words, the dialectic is not carried into infinity. Just as each
HEGEL 267
14 Karl Rosenkranz (1805-1879) was a German Hegelian philosopher who interpreted Hegel in
a somewhat liberal, semi-Kantian manner.
268 Creative Orderers
Through all great philosophy there runs the question regarding the
thinking that unlocks the truth, allows it to show itself and to become
manifest. Such thinking is not the everyday thinking of the understand¬
ing, which grasps, ad infinitum, things as static and which, in practical
life, has specific goals in the world. For this reason a doctrine of a ladder
of levels in our way of thinking runs, in variations, through the history
of philosophy.
In Hegel the highest level of thinking—which preserves, at the same
time, all the lower ones in itself but out of which it cannot be compre¬
hended itself—is the dialectic as the absolute method or absolute
knowing.
truth of knowledge rests in the circle that is formed by all the steps of
appearing knowledge.
Self-consummation and self-dissolution of knowledge take place at
every level; the philosopher who ha? reached a clear overview of the
whole brings to mind the event of emerging knowledge. To be sure,
each and every configuration regards itself as true, yet has to experience
that its thinking is turned around; it then either abides within itself or
is driven beyond. But only the philosopher knows the meaning through
which, and the goal toward which, and the road on which this takes
place.
e) Everywhere consciousness intends the truth, but reality does not
coincide with it. So it keeps on going, destroying and reappearing anew.
Only in completion do consciousness, truth, and actuality coincide. But
on the road to this completion the following applies: “Actuality is in
league with truth against consciousness.”
Consciousness believes itself to grasp truth in the phenomenality of
thought and so to encounter actuality. But what it experiences is
discrepancy.
There it can erupt, as it were, into skepticism and nihilism. But these,
together with their lapse into hopelessness, ultimately are only moments
of the one whole, true, and actual, and are the critical turning points of
radical negativity, which bring about what is new in consciousness, a
newness of which actuality itself makes sure.
When Hegel, in a lecture at Jena, demonstrated the course of knowl¬
edge in its appearance and dwelt repeatedly upon the reversals, thus
arriving at nihilistic turnings, a student jumped up, after an hour of this,
and exclaimed: “Now everything is destroyed.” Not at all: To be sure,
Hegel presented the negative with devastating consistency; but he did
so with the tranquillity that had been present from the start, based on
the knowledge of the whole truth, a knowledge that had never ceased.
f) Each instance of coming-to-be of the new object in a consciousness
transformed by it happens by means of a leap. All the conditions are
present under which the birth of the new can take place. The leap itself
brings about a new manifestness, or a resolve; in a crisis this leads to an
act out of the depth of our ground. The negative does not necessarily
bring about the new position for our understanding by violence; instead,
by understanding the conditions and possibilities, the new is like a gift
(as, by willing suicide, you may come to yourself with a new will to live;
or, in the despair brought about by the loss of faith and the collapse of
all objects of faith, a new faith may come into being).
It is said about this leap (a term Hegel avoids, since it would deny
HEGEL 273
The “concept that knows itself subjectively” is, at the same time, the
objective “substantiality of things.” For representation and reflection
the concepts appear as the other; in truth they are, in their movement,
the matter itself. For reflection, the method is universal and applicable
to everything. In its idea and actuality it is the particular method of each
matter itself.” The concept corresponds to its reality “as an existence
which it, the concept, itself is” (ibid.)
The method of the movement of the concept can be called the form
in which all content lies. This form is “the soul of all objectivity”; “all
otherwise determined content” has its actuality “only in the form” (5,
329).
Third: The infinite power of the method.
The movement of the concept, the method, is “the unrestrictedly
universal, inner and outer mode” of “absolute activity,” which has the
“simple infinite power against which no object could put up any resis¬
tance.” The method is “therefore the highest power, or, rather, the only
and absolute power of reason—not only, but also—its highest and only
impulse to find and to recognize itself through itself in everything” (5,
330-31)-
4. Resistance to mathematics
opposes this view with something approaching hate and bitterness in his
remarks:
"The essential point of view is that it is altogether a matter of a new
concept of scientific treatment. Philosophy, insofar as it is purported to
be a science, cannot ... for this purpose borrow its method from a
subordinate science such as mathematics; neither can it leave it at cat¬
egorical assurances of inner intuition” (3, 6-7).
It cannot be said that Hegel was ignorant of mathematics. As is
shown by his detailed exposition of mathematical problems, his knowl¬
edge is by no means negligible. But number as such “is the pure thought
of one’s own renunciation of thought,” “the abstract thought of super¬
ficiality itself”; thinking finds itself here “in the violent activity of moving
within thoughtlessness” (3, 246).
The numerical unit is “the totally inactive, lifeless and indifferent
determinateness in which all movement and relation is extinguished,
and which has broken off the bridge leading to living existence” (2, 215;
Phan., 189).
193)-
276 Creative Orderers
“The true is the whole. But the whole is the essence consummating
itself through nothing other than its development. Of the absolute it
must be said that it is essentially a result, that only in the end is it what
it truly is; that precisely in this consists its nature of being actual, or
subject, or becoming itself’ (2, 16; Phan., 14; cf. Mi, H20).
c) The proof lies in coherence, in necessary coherence. In philosophy
this coherence is, first of all, not an external but an internal one, and,
second, one that is completed and proved only in the absolute whole.
Speculative thinking is not scientific inquiry; it is not experimental
getting-to-the-bottom-of-things, not methodical approach to dealing with
worldly things. Rather, it means surrendering to the matter into whose
innermost depth we enter.
Whatever is discovered, whatever is intuited in light of the matter,
whatever becomes clear as meaning, in terse formulation-—none of these,
nothing is valid for Hegel in isolation, out of its separate self, as a clever
aphorism; only in its coherence is it valid for him, and the latter only
in the completion of the whole. What Hegel calls “science” is thinking
the coherence systematically.
On this point two things need to be said:
First: The claim that something is true only at its place within a
totality and can be understood solely in this context reveals insight. It
expresses that which, counter to the dissipation of current opinions and
sudden inspirations, points to the ground without which everything turns
into mere prattle.
Second: This coherence is not open-ended and to be sought unto
infinity, as it is in the Kantian idea, while effectively providing guidance
to movement and exercising control over random meanings. Rather, the
coherence is completely present in the system. Hence everything that
happens in it is “proved” through the preceding dialectical movement,
and for the purpose of conclusive proof requires the presentness of the
whole system, which, self-encircled, has neither beginning nor end.
Thus it says at the end of Logic: “It is too late to ask for proof that
the idea is the truth; the proof of that is contained in the whole exposition
and development of thought up to this point. The idea is the result of
this course of dialectic. ... It is ... its own result and, being so, is no
less immediate than mediated” (6, 387; Enc., I213, Z; W, §213).
d) The proofs for the existence of Gqd are a special example of
philosophical demonstration. In the way Hegel shows them to be true,
they have the significance “that they should contain the ascent of man’s
spirit to God, and express, for thought, how the ascent is an ascent of
thinking, moreover to the realm of thought.” This ascent is “essentially
HEGEL 277
6. Resistance to reflections
In the true dialectic, what goes on is the progression of the matter itself.
This progression should not be interfered with. Hence the demand “to
let go of specific opinions and presuppositions and to let the matter
prevail in itself.”
But when it proceeds in this manner, Hegel himself often inserted
reflections about it. Such reflections can serve “to facilitate the overview
and thereby the understanding.” The disadvantage is “to look like un¬
justified assertions, reasons and bases for what follows. Hence one should
not take them to be more than what they are meant to be, and should
differentiate them from that which is a moment in the progression of
the matter itself” (3, 114).
But we are to resist reflections arising out of finite understanding
devoid of any intuition of the whole that dialectical movement comprises
in regard to the theses it incorporates. These are inexhaustible. Their
endlessness would have to be countered by an endless refutation, which,
however, by means of the repeated attempts to raise reflection, would
have no other result than progressing from mere understanding to di¬
alectical reason.
Totally to be rejected is the demand—inherent in the understanding’s
reflection—for conformity to its conceptual mode. This conceptuality
“belongs ... to the bad manners of reflection, which looks for concep¬
tualization but simultaneously presupposes its static categories, thus
knowing itself forearmed against the answer to what it looks for.” In
this way, for example, reflection provides the “presupposition of the
absolute separation of Being from Nothing.” Becoming, then, turns into
something incomprehensible for reflection, since it has been superseded
by this presupposition. But then again this Becoming, and “this contra-
278 Creative Orderers
diction which one posits oneself and whose solution one makes impos¬
sible, is called the incomprehensible” (3, 96, 107).
The understanding, which is always the indispensable means for the
dialectic movement, cannot itself comprehend the dialectic. Hence Hegel
calls it “mysticism for the understanding.”
Logic examines the forms of thinkability as empty forms that are the
conditions for the correctness of all cognition but are not the basis of
the content of cognition.
Another logic sees, in the forms of thinking, the content itself and
the truth of Being.
Lask called the first logic the analytic logic, because it allows concepts
to emerge, according to their content, out of their abstraction from
experience; the second logic he called emanatistic, because it lets the
content of cognition flow forth, as it were, from the concept.15
For analytic logic the concept having the widest perimeter is the
emptiest; it is the concept of a universal. For emanatistic logic the concept
with the widest perimeter is, to be sure, at first devoid of content, but
it shelters the entire fullness of content that emerges from the concept
through its self-movement; the concept is not the concept of a universal
but the concept of totality present at the beginning as a germ and at the
end in its complete development.
At first glance this differentiation seems apt. Hegel states it time and
again: By abstracting, “the finite cognition according to the understand¬
ing” produces that universal which leaves out the concrete, which it later
again takes up just as externally. “The absolute method, on the other
hand, does not behave in the manner of external reflection but extricates
the determinate from its object, since it is itself the object’s immanent
principle and soul.” For Hegel, the universal is “not merely something
abstract but . . . the concrete totality” (5, 335, 334).
Because of this alternative, the matter seems clear for a moment. It
appears that we can choose which logic to consider the true one, and
accordingly we have to reject the other. We can show this difference
historically in the permutations of the medieval opposition of nominalism
(concepts are mere names, produced by our thinking, an order of valid
relations all its own) and realism (concepts are themselves actualities).
15 Emil Lask, Fichtes Idealismus und die Geschichte. Tubingen, Leipzig, J. C. B. Mohr, 1902, 28ft.
HEGEL 279
Prior to our critical remarks let us look once more at the viewpoint of
this astounding philosophy:
The center and surrounding circle of Hegelian philosophy is the
dialectic as concretely carried out by him and comprehended in its
entirety. To achieve understanding of it, we attempt time and again to
leap into it, as it were, to share Hegel’s experience via the figures of
thought that are in motion, to vibrate along with him in and toward
the One itself, to attain the plenitude of the absolute that Hegel believed
he had grasped and recognized anew in all things, in logic, in the world,
in nature, in man and his history, and in the actuality of the philosophy
that, by understanding everything and the whole, understands itself.
We go on accompanying him in the circular movements, whose
operations nowhere permit us to come to a halt; for only in the completion
of the movement, not at its end but, rather, through it as such, when it
returns within itself in its infinite circle of circles, is the tranquillity
achieved in which the answer to all questions is given.
Hence there is no answer if we demand that it be in the form of an
intelligible unequivocal statement.
Hence in following Hegel we find ourselves in ever new circular
movements, whose whirling may confuse us, until we grasp, by way of
trial, the configuration of thought that keeps recurring within them and
in this way the great order pervading the whole.
If we understand him on his terms, we arrive at a whole that, in the
magnitude of its rich development and the inexhaustible, constantly
expanding plenitude, as well as in the detail of the individual content
of thought, always speaks the same language, out of the absolute of the
ground of all Being. All things reflect in each other the same plenitude,
which, however, becomes manifest only as individual being through the
completion of the mirroring in the infinite movement.
being “with the matter itself,” indeed claiming to be “the matter itself,”
knows this matter in its wholeness as the absolute, as God, and itself
thinks God’s thoughts, God’s thoughts before creation (in logic), after
creation as operative in the process (in the philosophical “real sciences”
of philosophy of nature and philosophy of spirit)?
The grandeur of the actual achievement, the attractiveness of so many
intuitions of actualities, the acuity of Hegel’s powers of thought, in all
of which a most serious contemplation of the deity can be felt, do not
readily allow us to reject this philosophy because of its disconcerting
inferences and postulates. But for the same reason they must not demand
that we surrender to them. The power of Hegel’s achievement demands
our effort to immerse ourselves in it. Only then can we experience that
which becomes apparent to us in such an effort. The study of this
philosophy, which, as a configuration of thought, belongs to the few in
the history of philosophy which are most comprehensive, remains im¬
perative. It reveals itself surprisingly rewarding by insights as well as by
eliciting opposing powers of which without Hegel we would hardly be
fully aware.
Hegel’s dialectic may repel as grandiloquent nonsense, but only if it
is regarded one-sidedly in its fallacious inferences and applications. It
keeps its attractiveness as profound insight only if its significance is
critically considered, analyzed, and resolved. To undertake this success¬
fully requires a position that is not overpowered by the dialectic itself,
but still can make use of all its true elements. Where do we find such
a position?
It cannot be a matter of a determinate “standpoint” or of the ra¬
tionality of finite intelligence. Rather, thinking has to be guided by
Existenz at one with reason.
The critique of the dialectic can be directed radically only against the
“absolute method.”
a) The comparison between the reality of what is understood through
dialectic and the dialectical meaning-structure shows what in reality does
not fit the understood meaning. The same reality can also be grasped
through a different dialectical meaning-structure. This means that each
dialectical meaning-structure is a construct arrived at by an understand¬
ing that arises from the nature of intelligibility. The type of construct
can be applied to reality. Insofar as reality conforms to construct, it has
been comprehended in a specific aspect but not as a whole.
The wholenesses of the absolute dialectical method are intended as
real substances. The wholenesses of the dialectical meaning-structures
are sketches of constructive evidence which are useful as tools for grasp¬
ing reality and recognizable as reality in the sense of an individually
limited line of effectiveness.
b) Each dialectic is to be questioned as to the evidence specific to it.
If this is lacking, we recognize it to be a formal and superficial toying
with concepts.
c) The meaning of dialectic resides in its specificity in each case.
Universal or absolute dialectic is an abstraction from formal analogies.
The critical appropriation of the dialectic takes place in concrete spec¬
ificity and not in the totality.
The first reply to the foregoing is: In principle Hegel’s dialectic is all-
encompassing. The dialectic must overwhelm each particular dialectic
but it has no power over the completed total dialectic. Any dialectic op¬
posing Hegel’s would be absorbed in his totality and restricted from
letting this totality become again a moment of something more compre¬
hensive. From this angle we are justified in saying that Hegel anticipated
the Marxist dialectic of the labor process, located in a few paragraphs
of his Philosophy of Right—in the dialectic of bourgeois society. In the
same way we are justified in saying that Kierkegaard’s concept of Ex-
istenz is anticipated in a few passages of Hegel’s Aesthetics—in the
Romantic Spirit. Admittedly, in neither instance has the meaning of
Marx or Kierkegaard been captured, much less developed. But seen from
the Hegelian perspective, its anticipated incorporation might be claimed
by means of seemingly identical concepts. Hegel’s breadth is extraor¬
dinary and is of a sort that, if one remains within it, can be broadened
even further.
But if the dialectic as a whole cannot be overcome by dialectic, it
can still be penetrated by something that itself is undialectical (or is
something that forces itself upon us in a dialectic that leaves things open
and does not arrive at synthesis, at reconciliation): first, by true scientific
knowledge and research, going forward into infinity; second, by exis¬
tential decision in historicity; third, by the “place” of being-human as
an indeterminable place within the indeterminable whole. Man has no
overview of the whole; rather, by going forward into incalculable dis¬
tances, he penetrates it. He does not know what he himself truly is but
goes forward in his decision to his unforeseeable, incalculable actuali¬
zation.
Hegel sees his dialectic in its historical derivation and summarizes it.
Heraclitus is the most ancient philosopher of dialectical insight; Plato is
the originator of dialectic as method. Dialectic has always been misun¬
derstood by popular philosophy and common sense. The Eleatics used
it to deny the truth of the world and of motion, since that which contains
contradiction must be illusion. Educated skepticism has always made
use of dialectic. Thus dialectic has had a negative result throughout
history, and is even called the “logic of illusion” by Kant. The coincidentia
oppositorum of Nicholas of Cusa, and the mystical speculation and the
broad current of genuine philosophy are all for Hegel a single testimony
to the eternal truth. Hegel is conscious of being the first to develop
dialectics to its full extent, in its comprehensive and positive import,
making use of all preceding achievements, especially those of Kant,
Fichte, and Schelling. In Hegel the all-penetrating method becomes not
only the one actively effective everywhere, but also the one that orders
everything in a system, in which respect Proclus is the precursor.
Hegel praises Kant as the one who revived dialectics because of this
infinite achievement and at the same time opposes him in regard to the
way in which he took it up. It is important for us to contrast the two.
For Kant’s dialectical synthesis, the idea is the regulative principle
of progressing into the infinite, into the open world. For Hegel’s dialectic,
the process of the concept is itself the substance of Being, the eternal,
internally moving permanence. For Kant there exists the wholly other,
in the form of the turmoil of the emotions and in the forms of diversity
and chance. For Hegel the other is merely the other of the concept,
which he posits as a moment of itself released by itself. Kant knows
cognition through experience and comprehends its possibility. Hegel
knows and understands the cognition of the absolute. For Kant there
are limit-concepts, the encounter with mystery, the incomprehensibility
of freedom. For Hegel there is no limit to cognition, no darkness, no
mystery; everything is comprehensible and comprehended.
The origin of the content of Hegel’s dialectic is religious in nature.
The notion of “reconciliation,” to which he held fast with unwavering
certainty and which in the end brings a comforting conclusion to the
most extreme ruptures, is of Christian origin.
288 Creative Orderers
FRAGMENTS
judge and measure the other against an ideal, whereas this is permissible
only in respect to yourself.
2) This will to communication—particularly where the opposites are
extreme—repudiates, in the end, the all-embracing objective reconcili¬
ation in the circle of circles.
/ *t
attitudes actually termed skepticism and nihilism, to attain via this pro¬
cedure the despairing of everything and thus the total tranquillity of the
Nothing.
Second, it is possible to attain in this universal movement—which
dissolves everything determinate—precisely the reverse, that is, Being,
whole and fulfilled, the truth and actuality itself.- This is what Hegel
means and wants. The true is at no place, no standpoint, on neither side
of alternatives, in nothing enduring; instead, it rests in the entirety of
movement itself. For the latter not only eradicates, but also, in sublating,
it preserves what it has eradicated. What is untrue by itself becomes true
as moment. According to Hegel, to sublate has the following threefold
meaning: to negate, to preserve, to raise to a higher level. The ground
of the movement is the plenitude of Being that unfolds in this movement.
It does not trickle away into endlessness, does not come to Nothing, but
completes itself in wholeness. The means of the movement is negation,
is contradiction, is pain and death, is untruth and evil. But within the
wholeness there is constant reconciliation. The movement is not an
arbitrary one, but is necessary and must be understood as such. All that
is terrible, destructive, divisive turns out to be the road to the tranquillity
of truth and actuality. The experience of soaring is itself a moment of
bringing this tranquillity into the present.
Third, it is, however, possible that the movement is the medium in
which historic Existenz finds its unknowable tranquillity. In the liber¬
ation from the cogent and coercive capacities of objective positions and
statements and established truths, Existenz—-not through casting them
off, but through mastering them—attains self-certainty based in its
unique historicity and its results: its irrevocable decisions and actuali¬
zations. For Existenz, objective visions of reconciliation such as Hegel’s
are seen as possible ciphers among other ciphers which may unpredictably
bring their language to bear in existential situations.
1) Among the three great creators of systems in the West, Hegel is still
so close to us in time that we cannot know whether we can place him
legitimately alongside the two others. His historical impact, which, to
be sure, has grown up to our day, must yet prove itself in the long term.
Above all, he is close to us in his world and his humanity. We know
more about his life, and his development is much better documented,
than are those of the other two.
2) Also, the principle of his system is an entirely new one, much
more difficult to comprehend than that of the other two. Whereas Ar¬
istotle and Aquinas address our intellect and are comparatively more
accessible to our understanding, there is something in Hegel’s thinking
that may strike us as odd, as nonsense. To penetrate to his meaning, a
different kind of effort is required. We are never sure of having truly
understood him. He himself called his thinking “mysticism for the
understanding.”
And yet this difficulty can suddenly vanish. Then it is as though we
had learned a trick and now everything for the understanding falls into
place in a grandiose unanimity of method.
3) On the other hand, he is richest in tangible substance. It is possible
(even if, in Hegel’s sense, it is a misunderstanding) to keep to the wealth
of interesting contents and concrete intuitions, to forget about dialectic
method, and to appropriate his genuine insights into history.
4) Hegel can be seen as a figure at the conclusion of an era, but one
who conceals dynamite within the method, a figure of the Western spirit
as it comes to a “conclusion” in “Verstehen” [comprehension]. In that
respect Hegel is a “hermeneutic philosopher.”
This Bibliography lists the main primary sources used by Jaspers in his exposition of the
individual thinkers. In some cases several editions in different languages were drawn upon to
explicate the same thinker. Also included under primary sources are standard English editions
used in translating the text; they are identified in the text. Included under Secondary Works
are some consulted or referred to by Jaspers.
Xenophanes
SOURCES
SECONDARY WORKS:
Bowra, C. M.: Early Greeks Elegists. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1938.
Freeman, Kathleen: The Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A Companion to Diels, Fragmente
der Vorsohratiker. 3rd ed., Oxford, Blackwell, 1953.
Griinwald, Michael: Die Anfange der abendlandischen Philosophie, Fragmente und Lehr-
berichte. Zurich, Artemis, 1949.
Jaeger, Werner: The Theology of the Early Greek, Philosophers. Trans, by E. S. Robinson.
New York, Oxford University Press, 1947.
Democritus
SOURCES
Diels, Hermann: see under Xenophanes.
Freeman, Kathleen: see under Xenophanes.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Barnes, Jonathan: The Pre-Socratic Philosophers. London and Boston, Routledge &
Kegan Paul, 1979.
Guthrie, William: A History of Greek, Philosophy. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1962.
Snell, Bruno: The Discovery of the Mind: The Greek, Origins of European Thought. Trans,
by T. G. Rosenmayer. Oxford, Blackwell, 1953.
299
300 Bibliography
Empedocles
SOURCES
Diels, Hermann: see under Xenophanes.
O’Brien, Denis. Empedocles’ Cosmic Cycle: A Reconstruction from the Fragments and
Secondary Sources. London and New York, Cambridge University Press, 1969.
Wright, M. R., ed.: Empedocles: The Extant Fragment's. New Haven, Yale University
Press, 1981.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Barnes, Jonathan: see under Democritus.
Kranz, Walther: Empedocles. Antfie Gestalt und romantische Neuschopfung. Zurich,
Artemis, 1949.
Bruno
SOURCES
Giordano Bruno: Gesammeltephilosophische Wer\e. Ed. by L. Kuhlenbeck. 6 vols. Jena,
E. Diederichs, 1904-.
The Ashwednesday Supper. Trans, with an Introduction by S. Jaki. The Hague, Mouton,
r975-
The Expulsion of the Triumphant Beast. Trans, and ed. by A. Imerti. Brunswick, NJ,
Rutgers University Press, 1964.
The Heroic Frenzies. Trans, and introduction by P. M. Memmo. Chapel Hill, University
of North Carolina Press, 1964.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Cassirer, Ernst: Individual and Cosmos in Renaissance Philosophy. New York, Barnes
& Noble, 1963.
Michel, Paul-Henri: The Cosmology of Giordano Bruno. Paris, Hermann, 1973.
Singer, Dorothea: Giordano Bruno: His Life and Thought. New York, Schumm, 1950.
Yates, Frances: Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition. Chicago, University of
Chicago Press, 1969; repr., 1979.
Epicurus
SOURCES
Bailey, Cyril, ed.: Epicurus: The Extant Remains. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1926; New
York, Limited Editions Club, 1947.
Diogenes Laertius: De vitis . . . , Book 10.
Gigon, Olaf Alfred: Epfiur. Von der Uberwindung der Furcht. Zurich, 1949.
Miihll, P. von der: Epicuri epistolae tres et ratae sententiae. Leipzig, Teubner, 1922.
Nestle, Wilhelm: Die NachsofiatiCer. Jena, E. Diederichs, 1923.
Strodach, George, ed.: The Philosophy of Epicurus. Lvanston, IL, Northwestern Uni¬
versity Press, 1963.
Usener, Hermann, ed.: Epicurea. Leipzig, B. G. Teubner, 1887.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Asmis, Elizabeth: Epicurus’ Scientific Method. Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press,
1984.
Bibliography 301
Bailey, C.: The Greeks Atomists and Epicurus. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1928.
Jones, Howard: The Epicurean Tradition. London and New York, Routledge, 1989.
Mitsis, Phillip: Epicurus’ Ethical Theoiy. Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press, 1989.
Rist, John M.: Epicurus: An Introduction. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1972.
/ '
Boehme
SOURCES
SECONDARY WORKS:
Benz, Ernst: Der Volljommene Mensch nach Jakob Bbhme. Stuttgart, W. Kohlhammer,
T937-
Elert, Werner: Die voluntaristische MystiJ Jakob Bohmes. Eine psychologische Studie.
Berlin, Trowitzsch & Sohn, 1913.
Hegel: Samtliche Weife: see under Hegel.
Koyre, Alexandre: La philosophie de Jacob Boehme. Paris, J. Vrin, 1929.
Martensen, Hans Lassen: Jakob Bohme, Theosophische Studien. Leipzig, J. Lehmann,
1882.
Richter, Liselotte: Jakob Bohme. Mystische Schau. Hamburg, Hofmann und Campe,
I943-
Stoudt, John: Jakob Boehme: His Life and Thought. New York, Seabury Press, 1957;
repr., 1968.
Walsh, David: The Mysticism of Innerworldly Fulfillment: A Study of Jakob Boehme.
Gainesville, University Presses of Florida, 1983.
Sc helling
SOURCES
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von: Samtliche Werke. Ed. by K. F. A. Schelling.
Stuttgart and Augsburg, Cotta, 1856-61.
Werke. Ed. by M. Schroter. Munich, Beck & Oldenbourg, 1927-56.
The Ages of the World. Trans, and introduction by F. Bolman. New York, Columbia
University Press, 1942.
Bruno, or, On the Natural and Divine Principles of Things. Ed., trans., and introduction
by Michael Vater. Albany, State University of New York Press, 1984.
Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature. Trans, by E. Harris and P. Smith. New York,
Cambridge University Press, 1988.
The Philosophy of Art. Ed., trans., and introduction by D. W. Stott. Minneapolis,
University of Minnesota Press, 1989.
Schelling: Of Human Freedom. Trans, by James Gutman. Chicago, Open Court, 1936.
System of Transcendental Idealism. Trans, by Peter Heath. Charlottesville, University
Press of Virginia, 1978.
302 Bibliography
Leibniz
SOURCES
Opera philosophica. Ed. by J. E. Erdmann. Berlin, G. Eichler, 1839-40.
Die philosophische Schriften von G. W. Leibniz. Ed. by C. J. Gerhardt. 7 vols. Berlin,
Weidmann, 1875-90.
Sdmtliche Schriften und Briefe. Ed. by P. Ritter and E. Hochstetter. Darmstadt, Reisel,
I923-
Discourse on Metaphysics. Ed. by R. Martin and S. Brown. New York, St. Martin’s,
1988.
Logical Papers. Ed. by G. Parkinson. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1966.
New Essays on Human Understanding. Ed. by P. Remnant and J. Bennett. New York,
Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Philosophical Papers and Letters. Ed. by L. Loemker. Chicago, University of Chicago
Press, 1956.
Philosophical Writings. Ed. and trans. by Mary Norris. New York, Dutton, 1951.
The Political Writings of Leibniz. Ed. by P. Riley. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1972.
Theodicy: Essays. LaSalle, IL, Open Court, 1985.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Aristotle
SOURCES
SECONDARY WORKS:
Ackrill, J. L.: Aristotle the Philosopher. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1981.
Allen, Donald James: The Philosophy of Aristotle. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1952.
Barnes, Jonathan: Aristotle. Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press, 1982.
Edel, A.: Aristotle and His Philosophy. Chapel Hill, University of North Carolina Press,
1982.
Grene, Marjorie: A Portrait of Aristotle. London, Faber & Faber, 1963.
Hardie, W. F.: Aristotle's Ethical Theory. 2nd ed., Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1980.
Jaeger, Werner: Aristotle. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1934; repr., 1948.
-—: Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development. New York, Oxford
University Press, 1962.
-: Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture. Trans, by Gilbert Highet. 3 vols. New
York, Oxford University Press, 1944.
Rose, Valentin: Aristoteles Pseudepigraphus. Leipzig, 1863. Trans, quoted from The
Complete Works of Aristotle.
Veatch, H. B.: Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation. Bloomington, Indiana University
Press, 1974.
Hegel
SOURCES
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegels Werke, vollstandige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von
Freunden des Verewigten. Ed. by P. Marnheinecke et al. 19 vols. in 23 vols. Berlin,
Duncker and Humblot, 1832-87.
Samtliche Werke. Ed. by H. Glockner. 26 vols. Stuttgart, F. Fromann, 1927-40.
Samtliche Werke: Neue Kritische Ausgabe. Ed. by J. Hoffmeister. 52 vols. Leipzig,
Meiner, 1930-.
Encyclopadie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse. Ed. by G. Lasson. 3rd
ed. Leipzig, F. Meiner, 1923.
Phanomenologie des Geistes. Ed. by J. Hoffmeister. In Samtliche Werke. Ed. by
G. Lasson. 6th ed., Philosophische Bibliothek, 1952.
Early Theological Writings. Trans, by T. M. Knox. Chicago, University of Chicago
Press, 1948.
304 Bibliography
SECONDARY WORKS:
Avineri, Shlomo: Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1972.
Findlay, J. N.: Hegel: A Re-Examination. New York, Humanities Press, 1958; repr.,
1976.
Harris, H. S.: Hegel’s Development: Toward the Sunlight, 1770-1801. London, Oxford
University Press, 1972.
Kaufmann, Walter: Hegel: A Reinterpretation. New York, Doubleday, 1965; repr.,
r978-
Lowith, Karl: From Hegel to Nietzsche. New York, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1965;
repr., 1984.
O’Brien, George: Hegel on Reason and History: A Contemporary Interpretation. Chicago,
University of Chicago Press, 1975.
Rosen, Stanley: G. W. F. Hegel: An Introduction to the Science of Wisdom. New Haven,
Yale University Press, 1974.
Taylor, Charles: Hegel. London, Cambridge University Press, 1975.
I
/
INDEX OF NAMES
3°5
306 Index
Terence, 105
Paracelsus, Philippus Aureolus, 118
Thales, 11, 16
Parmenides, 9, 14-16, 18, 21, 25, 35,
Themistocles, 105
52-54. 56
Tieck, Ludwig, 141, 143
Pascal, Blaise, 178
Trendelenburg, Friedrich Adolf, 255-56
Pausanias, 35, 48
Peter the Great, 171 Valla, Lorenzo, 106
Philodemos, 76, 77 Virgil, 39, 89
Pico della Mirandola, 89
Pindar, 15 Walter, 141
Plato, 14, 17, 20, 21, 24, 40, 43, 56, 59, Weber, Max, 297
62, 68, 70, 145, 166, 176, 182, 193, 195, Weigel, Valentine, 118
200, 203, 210, 218-20, 226, 274, 287, Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 178
297
Plotinus, 47, 59, 64, 156, 176 Xenophanes, 9-19, 51, 53, 54
\
'
■ *
■V
PHILLIPS ACADEMY
DEMCO
(Continued from front flap)
Mankind, The Question of German Guilt, and The Origin and Goal
The Great
Philosophers
Volume I
■ • \ i
. f
Done with such exemplary clarity that one need not be a student of the subject in
learned and generous-spirited man taking stock of his heritage and thus taking
—MD
“ Full of profound and original insights . . . Jaspers has opened a significant and
ISBN 0-15-136942-9
90000>
9 780151 369423