Does The Legal Concepts Travel
Does The Legal Concepts Travel
Does The Legal Concepts Travel
1
Compare the detailed analysis of the issue of the national aspects of arbitration in Joanna
Jemielniak, Legal Interpretation in International Commercial Arbitration (2014), 2–8.
2
We will not analyse ‘formal legal concepts’, such as ‘right’, ‘power’, and ‘immunity’. For the distinc-
tion between substantive and formal concepts, see Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki and Mateusz Klinowski,
‘Are Legal Concepts Embedded in Legal Norms?’ International Journal for the Semiotics of Law, 25/4
(2012), 556.
Adam Dyrda and Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki, Do legal concepts travel? In: Language and Legal Interpretation in
International Law. Edited by: Anne Lise Kjær and Joanna Lam, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2022.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780190855208.003.0003
Do l egal conce pt s t ravel ? 51
that such a term expresses the same concept.3 The meaning of such concepts
should initially be derived from the applicable law of a particular jurisdiction.
The rules of specific legal systems (taken together with the conceptions devel-
oped in jurisprudence and the case laws of a particular country) define ‘owner-
ship’, ‘tort’, or ‘contract’, particularly in terms of what the truth conditions are
for statements of the type ‘X is the owner of Y’ and ‘X and Y are bound by a
contract’. Such truth conditions are, at least to a certain extent, specific to a given
3
We will not discuss the problems of double intermediacy, particularly linguistic intermediacy,
in the application of national law. See Jemielniak, Legal Interpretation in International Commercial
Arbitration, 64–7.
4
This is a paraphrase of a question formulated by William Twining, ‘Have Concepts, Will
Travel: Analytical Jurisprudence in a Global Context’, International Journal of Law in Context (2005), 7.
52 Adam Dyrda and Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
5
Marvin Harris, ‘History and Significance of the Emic/Etic Distinction’, Annual Review of
Anthropology, 5 (1976), 329–50.
6
Michael Morris, Kwok Leung, Daniel Amies, and Brian Lickel, ‘Views from Inside and
Outside: Integrating Emic and Epic Insights about Culture and Justice Judgments’, The Academy of
Management Review, 24/4 (October 1999), 781.
Do l egal conce pt s t ravel ? 53
how they perceive their rules of behaviour, and what holds meaning for them. The
etic approach focuses on what a researcher considers important from the perspec-
tive of comparative research on other cultures. The etic approach analyses culture
in terms that can be applied across cultures and attempts to be ‘culturally neutral’ in
that it excludes ethnocentric and cultural limitations or biases.
In the attempt to apply the emic/etic distinction to our problem of interpreting
SMCs, the following questions arise: (1) should an ideal arbitrator adopt the etic
7
Compare Jemielniak, Legal Interpretation in International Commercial Arbitration, 63, for the dis-
tinction of three possible approaches to interpretation from this perspective.
54 Adam Dyrda and Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
Morris, Leung, Amies, and Lickel, ‘Views from Inside and Outside’, 794.
8
Joseph Raz, ‘On the Nature of Law’, Archiv für Rechts-und Sozialphilosophie, 82 (1996), 4.
9
10
We take here the position of a moderate legal relativism. See Twining, ‘Have Concepts, Will
Travel’, 8.
11
Gizbert-Studnicki and Klinowski, ‘Are Legal Concepts Embedded in Legal Norms?’, 553–62.
12
Alf Ross, ‘TŭTŭ’, Scandinavian Studies in Law (1957), 139–53.
Do l egal conce pt s t ravel ? 55
The main argument developed against ET is based on the observation that cer-
tain (but not all) SMCs appear not only at the level of national legislation, but also
at the level of supranational laws (European law, international law, and human rights
law). Such supranational laws serve as benchmarks for assessing national legisla-
tion. This benchmarking gives rise to two issues. First, SMCs are not equivalent to
the sets of inferential links determined by a national law because a supranational law
also contributes to the content of SMCs. Second, the interpretation of SMCs must
13
See Jemielniak, Legal Interpretation in International Commercial Arbitration, 149–74.
14
Brian Tamanaha, A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society (2001), 126.
15
Tamanaha, A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society, 126.
56 Adam Dyrda and Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
16
Joanna Jemielniak and Przemysław Miklaszewicz, ‘Introduction’, in Joanna Jemielniak and
Przemysław Miklaszewicz, ed., Interpretation of Law in the Global World: From Particularism to a
Universal Approach (2010), 62. Compare also Jemielniak and Miklaszewicz, ‘Introduction’, 17, who
write ‘[t]he continuing quest for determining a possible common core of diverse legal systems has been
the driving force of the lex mercatoria through arbitral case law, as well as via private codification efforts’.
Do l egal conce pt s t ravel ? 57
law systems. These meanings are only very roughly equivalent (e.g. the concepts
of ‘trust’, ‘tort’, and, probably, ‘negligence’). As far as LM is concerned, its rules,
standards, and principles contain only a limited number of concepts, in the first
place linked to the trade of goods and services (e.g. delivery, payment, and delay).
Even if shared by arbitrators, LM concepts, therefore, do not allow for a solution to
all jurisdiction-specific interpretation problems that may arise in connection with
dispute resolution.
17
Jemielniak, Legal Interpretation in International Commercial Arbitration, 134, draws attention to
‘false friends’, namely, legal concepts that seem to have direct counterparts in other legal systems but
are not freely exchangeable. Examples are the concept of ‘contract law’ and addressing the issue of un-
foreseeable circumstances.
18
Twining, ‘Have Concepts, Will Travel’, 8ff.
58 Adam Dyrda and Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
19
Twining, ‘Have Concepts, Will Travel’, 8ff.
Do l egal conce pt s t ravel ? 59
in a different legal culture. The only condition is that in both cultures—the emigrant
(the culture from which the concept travels) and the immigrant (the culture to which
the concept travels)—a concept should be relatively isolated; that is, it should be
simple and connected to its easily translatable ordinary language counterpart.20 The
distinction between concepts that travel well and those that travel badly is not a log-
ical dichotomy. Whether a concept travels well or travels badly is a matter of degree.
Therefore, our third explanatory point related to our basic question is that reaching
20
To use Ludwig Wittgenstein’s metaphor, good travellers are those concepts that are not exclu-
sively determined by complicated and specific forms of life and are, therefore, able only to play a role
in language games performed with this form. Rather, given their simplicity, being a relatively stable
element of one form of life, they can be found in other, even very distinct, forms of life. Thus, they
can be applied in different language games performed in the context of even very distant forms of life.
21
Basil Markesinis, ‘Unity or Division: The Search for Similarities in Contemporary European
Law’, Current Legal Problems, 54 (2001), 591–617.
60 Adam Dyrda and Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
this approach is to look into cases and not concepts. As Markesinis indicates, ‘the
observer is comparing familiar situations and is not confused by structures, termi-
nology, or concepts that are either untranslatable or, if apparently easy to translate,
they are misleading’.22 Markesinis presents a brief comparison of the German con-
cept of ‘tort’ with respective common-law concepts. ‘Tort’ in German law is closely
linked to the concept of ‘Rechtswidrigkeit’ (‘illegality’), which is historically derived
from the Roman concept of iniuria. Rechtswidrigkeit is determined by reference to
24
Cass S. Sunstein, ‘Practical Reason and Incompletely Theorized Agreements’, in E. Ullmann-
Margalit, ed., Reasoning Practically (2000), 106–22.
25
Such a procedure is developed by J. Rawls, for example, in Political Liberalism (1993), 7, passim.
Do l egal conce pt s t ravel ? 61
26
It may be claimed that if each arbitrator (assuming three arbitrators, A1, A2, and A3) reaches the
same outcome O by using different tools and considerations [P(A1), P(A2) and P(A3), respectively],
the justification of a decision can be presented either in a ‘weak’ disjunctive form, { P(A1) ∨ P(A2) ∨
P(A3) } → O, or in a ‘strong’ conjunctive form, { P(A1) ∧ P(A2) ∧ P(A3) } → O. The weak form would
exactly resemble the process of heuristics but would also allow the risk that the particular, conflicting
reasons that arbitrators had whilst reaching the outcome would be unsatisfactorily appreciated; con-
versely, the strong form may be counter-intuitive for someone who cannot accept that contradictory
premises can generate one outcome (another plausible argument is that in such case, each outcome
would be the right outcome, according to the logical rule that {X, −X} → Y, where Y is ‘whatever’).
This argument is the last point that eventually (at least in the case of justification of the decision), some
common elements of A1, A2, and A3 have to be found and underlined; these elements are roughly re-
ferred to as ‘policy considerations’.
62 Adam Dyrda and Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
References
Gizbert-Studnicki, Tomasz and Mateusz Klinowski, ‘Are Legal Concepts Embedded in Legal
Norms?’ International Journal for the Semiotics of Law, 25/4 (2012), 553–62.
Harris, Marvin, ‘History and Significance of the Emic/ Etic Distinction’, Annual Review of
Anthropology, 5 (1976), 329–50.
Jemielniak, Joanna, Legal Interpretation in International Commercial Arbitration (2014).
Jemielniak, Joanna and Przemysław Miklaszewicz, ‘Introduction’, in Joanna Jemielniak and
Przemysław Miklaszewicz, ed., Interpretation of Law in the Global World: From Particularism to
a Universal Approach (Berlin, Heidelberg 2010).
Do l egal conce pt s t ravel ? 63
Markesinis, Basil, ‘Unity or Division: The Search for Similarities in Contemporary European Law’,
Current Legal Problems, 54 (2001), 591–617.
Morris, Michael, Kwok Leung, Daniel Amies, and Brian Lickel, ‘Views from Inside and
Outside: Integrating Emic and Epic Insights about Culture and Justice Judgments’, The
Academy of Management Review, 24/4 (October 1999), 781–96.
Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York, 1993).
Raz, Joseph, ‘On the Nature of Law’, Archiv für Rechts-und Sozialphilosophie, 82 (1996), 1–25.
Ross, Alf, ‘TŭTŭ’, Scandinavian Studies in Law (1957), 139–53.