Legal Heuristics and the Positivisa

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

A C TA U N I V E R S I TAT I S L O D Z I E N S I S

FOLIA IURIDICA 100, 2022

https://doi.org/10.18778/0208-6069.100.07

Jerzy Leszczyński*
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7588-7705

LEGAL HEURISTICS AND THE POSITIVISATION OF LAW


IN DOGMATIC DISCOURSE

Abstract. The general opinion that the text of the law does not imply its use leads to an
understanding of the role that legal dogmatics and legal practice can play in solving this problem.
Common thematic field of both those lawyers’ activities allows us to distinguish a dogmatic
discourse, by which and in which the law is positivised by consolidating applicable (operative)
patterns of solving legal problems. These patterns are created by referring to the aspects of text,
language, and system of law, but also to the history of the discourse. The positivisation of law is
the result of specific legal heuristics, consisting in combining meanings, expectations, values, and
existing practices in solving legal problems. Legal heuristics does not boil down to a method, but,
rather, is a framework, a context, and a set of conditions for cognition aimed at solving practical
problems.
Keywords: legal heuristics, legal dogmatics, positivisation of law, legal argumentation

HEURYSTYKI PRAWNICZE A POZYTWIZACJA PRAWA


W DYSKURSIE DOGMATYCZNYM

Streszczenie. Powszechna opinia, że tekst prawa nie wyznacza jego zastosowania


prowadzi do zrozumienia roli dogmatyki prawniczej i praktyki orzeczniczej w rozwiązaniu tego
problemu. Wspólne pole tematyczne obu obszarów działalności prawników pozwala wyodrębnić
dyskurs dogmatyczny, w którym prawo jest pozytywizowane poprzez utrwalanie stosowalnych
(operatywnych) wzorów rozwiązywania problemów prawnych. Wzory te powstają przez odwołania
do tekstowości, językowości prawa i systemowości prawa, ale również do historii samego dyskursu.
Pozytywizacja prawa jest wynikiem określonych heurystyk prawnych, polegających na łączeniu
znaczeń, oczekiwań, wartości i istniejących praktyk w rozwiązywaniu problemów prawnych.
Heurystyka prawnicza nie sprowadza się do metody, jest raczej ramą, kontekstem i zespołem
warunków poznania nakierowanego na rozwiązywanie praktycznych problemów.
Słowa kluczowe: heurystyka prawnicza, dogmatyka prawa, pozytywizacja prawa, argumen-
tacja prawnicza

*
University of Lodz, Faculty of Law and Administration, [email protected]

University of Lodz – Lodz University Press, Lodz, Poland.

(https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0)
Received: 7.02.2022. Verified: 21.09.2022. Revised: 3.10.2022. Accepted: 1.12.2022.

[83]
84 Jerzy Leszczyński

1. INTRODUCTION

In principle, the cognition of law has two dimensions – theoretical and


practical. It is difficult to differentiate between these two dimensions when only
the intentions of researchers are taken into account. Theoretical cognition takes
place at two levels. At the first level, one seeks to answer the question of what law
is; to what category of beings it belongs. Considerations of a philosophical nature
may develop into scientific theories which generally have a notional character,
or which seek to explain law as an empirically-studied phenomenon. A specific
characteristic of such research is that at the outset the researcher does not assume
that law is what it is understood to be in a given social practice.
At the second level, this very assumption is adopted at the outset. From this
it follows that legal doctrine (a term usually used in this context) is of a normative
nature, because it shapes legal practices while at the same time being a legal
practice itself. I understand the legal doctrine as the entirety of recognised
practical knowledge which is expected to provide an explanation of many things,
including what the law is in the practices of state organs, what its content is, and
which lawyers’ actions should be considered as acceptable in the light of their
institutional role. A very important component of the legal doctrine, apart from
the findings of the theory of law, involves the findings of legal dogmatics (legal
science, scientia iuris, Rechtswissenschaft) – a domain which is clearly identified
in European legal culture, though named in various ways (Peczenik 2005, 1–2).
The belief that legal doctrine – and especially legal dogmatics – is of
a normative nature is one that is held by many researchers. According to Kaarlo
Tuori, legal science possesses a particular normativity which separates it from
research on law conducted in the spheres of other social sciences, such as sociology
or political science. This particular normativity stems from its dual nature: legal
science is not only a scientific practice but also a legal one, and it participates in
the reproduction and modification of the legal order – its own object of research
(Tuori 2016, 285).
The aim of this article is to present some aspects of the normativity of legal
dogmatics. I suggest that utterances formulated within legal dogmatics, along
with court rulings, positivise the law, i.e. determine its content (3), by formulating
patterns of solving legal problems (4), justified in a specific way (5). I also indicate
the significance of the hermeneutic explanation of the relationship between
knowledge and practice (6). However, I start with some introductory remarks
concerning the self-consciousness of lawyers, highlighting the role of their work
in shaping the legal order (2)1.

1
I was encouraged to write this text by Tomasz Bekrycht, who was working on a collection of
articles on legal heuristics, which was not completed. Legal heuristics was then the subject of his
keen interest. This article is based partly on my previous work: Leszczyński (2010).
Legal Heuristics and the Positivisation of Law in Dogmatic Discourse 85

2. THE SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS OF LAWYERS AND THE NORMATIVITY


OF LEGAL KNOWLEDGE

Legal doctrine is based upon a certain “image” of what a legal order is,
resulting from many sophisticated assumptions, but above all from what is
expected by the participants of the discourse. This “image” of law is confronted
both with an ideal of law brought into the discourse through theoretical and
philosophical reflection and, on the other hand, with everyday facts concerning
the practices of state offices and courts. Thus, it can be said that the “image” of the
legal order is a product of negotiation. However, this assertion is not encountered
in the discourse of legal practices; neither is the notion that law is just an “image”.
If a given social practice perceives the image of law as inadequate in some of its
parts or aspects, then the removal of this inconsistency must take place through
a correction of the practice or theory of law. The significant and permanent
inadequacy of the doctrinal image of law would be a source of its dysfunctionality
due to various social implications, such as those associated with the educational
function of the theory of law.
The practical aspect of the theory of law is twofold. In an obvious way, the
theory is practical, normatively concentrating the actions of lawyers who arrange
the limits of law and its contents, using heuristic criteria deemed consistent with
the theory. Such a theory legitimises specific legal practices. In a less obvious
way, the theory is also practical, because it constructs lawyers’ self-consciousness,
drawing on those aspects that create given practices. Somewhat paradoxically,
for the same reasons that justify describing this aspect of the theory of law as
practical, we can also identify cognitive values in the theory, since they condition
one another.
Legal scholars, of course, differ in their self-understanding, and legal theorists and legal
philosophers in particular may deny the normative implications of their statements and the
corresponding normative validity claims. Nevertheless, it appears that the legal scholar is not
free to choose between a purely cognitive and a performative attitude. She is, to a certain
extent, a prisoner of her social position; the implications and validity claims of her statements
are affected by her dual citizenship. (Tuori 2016, 292)

The shaping of the self-consciousness of lawyers by the theory of law


is a subject often discussed in the literature of modern legal theory and legal
philosophy. I treat this paper as a contribution to the debate and propose treating
legal dogmatics as playing a key role in the positivisation of law. The positivisation
of law is understood here as a function of some legal practices consisting in
limiting a multitude of possible solutions to legal problems that arise during the
application of law.
86 Jerzy Leszczyński

3. THE POSITIVISATION OF LAW AND LEGAL DOGMATICS

The concept of the positivisation of law indicates a certain way of solving


social problems, namely the fact that legal provisions do not determine, in
principle, the way they are applied in court decisions. It is not an issue of the
sheer “technical” possibility of applying law, but a question of how this can be
accomplished in a way that is acceptable from the point of view of the adopted
values and purposes of law. It can be said that the positivisation of law is the
result of specific legal heuristics, consisting in combining meanings, expectations,
values, and existing practices in solving legal problems and consolidating patterns
of these solutions. Thus understood, heuristics does not boil down to a method,
but, rather, is a framework, a context, and a set of conditions for cognition aimed
at solving practical problems (Hartman 2011, 25). The concept of the positivisation
of law is not a concept developed in legal doctrine; it belongs to the legal theory
that constructs the self-consciousness of lawyers, explaining and justifying their
actions at the same time.
There are at least two meanings of the “positivisation” and the “positiveness”
of law. The more traditional one concerns turning a law that already exists in some
way (i.e. natural law) into a form of positive law. As an effect of the enactment
of law (law-making), the positiveness of law can be described as the positiveness
of a legal text. However, this paper concerns the positiveness of law which is
achieved in practice, especially in court decisions. Therefore, the issue concerns
the positiveness of law in terms of its determinacy with regard to content.
Jan M. Broekman demonstrates that the adoption of linguistic measures alone
will not impart stability to a certain way of understanding the contents of law. The
action of some institutional mechanisms is essential. According to Broekman, the
positivisation of law (the author introduces this concept in the second meaning
described above), takes place in legal dogmatics (Broekman 1985). Broekman
notices that the auto-referential structure of legal dogmatics, constituting the
central core of a legal paradigm, must remain intact to compensate the open and
informal character of a legal text. The auto-referentiality of dogmatics remains in
a functional relationship to the argument of the open textuality of law. Not only is
this relationship a result of philosophical reflection, but it is also a structure – and
thus an element of the argumentation structure. This means that when one arrives
at some dogmatic conclusions, the argumentation attains the objectivity which
cannot be achieved through reference to a legal text alone.
The connection between the positivisation of law and legal dogmatics is clear
when one appreciates that legal dogmatics has a practical function. The theory of
law often accepts that the cognitive functions of legal dogmatics are secondary
to the practical functions connected with the practice of applying and creating law.
In reflection on legal dogmatics, there was a distinct idea that, because of its close
Legal Heuristics and the Positivisation of Law in Dogmatic Discourse 87

connection to practice, dogmatics does not fit the model of humanistic science,
or even that it is a form of a practical activity. It has been noted that solving
dogmatic problems consists not only in providing an exhaustive description of
a legal norm, but also in ensuring that the implementation of such a norm is
an appropriate means for achieving the desired objectives. Irrespective of the
ideology determining the attitude of lawyers to the interpretation of the law, legal
dogmatics subordinates itself – deliberately or unconsciously – to a certain socio-
technical task of building trust in the certainty of legal transactions, legal security,
and the stability of interpretation (Ziembiński 1980, 26).
Legal dogmatics also has a normative function. It does not restrict itself to the
description of binding legal norms: it proposes or suggests criteria for solving legal
problems. Systematisation is an important activity of legal dogmatics, and not only
for the sake of systematisation itself. Dogmatics plays a more significant social
role in providing models for the application, interpretation, and modification of
law (Atienza, Manero 1998, 20–21). As Jan M. Smits notes:
Legal systematisation differs in one important respect from description in other disciplines: it
influences the actual application of the law. Because legal academics work on a system that is
also used in practice, important normative consequences can follow from their work. Anyone
making use of a coherent system will propagate a change of the law if this fits in with the
system itself. (Smits 2015, 11)

When viewed in the light of the above-mentioned qualities, legal dogmatics is


brought closer to the discourse of applying the law, which leads to the conclusion
that the positivisation of law is a result of legal discourse being understood more
broadly than it is within the field legal dogmatics. The activities of judges or
officials produce real effects which are not brought about by the scientific theses of
legal dogmatists. However, this difference results from the power to produce such
effects, which are institutionally-attributed to state organs, and to which the roles
played by lawyers correspond. Legal scholars do not have such power because the
institution within which they act is not thus equipped. However, one should not
draw conclusions about the principal differences between these two discourses
and the knowledge that constitutes their thematic field on the basis of whether or
not such a power exists.
To combine these two discourses and refer to them as a “dogmatic
discourse” would constitute a step beyond the traditional distinction between
the doctrine (legal dogmatics) and the judicature. The discourse thus understood
comprises legal dogmatics and the discourse of applying the law. The leading
role of legal dogmatics expressed this way is in line with the belief that the
function of articulating the legal worldview is mainly vested in legal dogmatics
(Zirk-Sadowski 1998, 70–71).
88 Jerzy Leszczyński

4. PATTERNS OF SOLVING LEGAL PROBLEMS

The knowledge which positivises the law consists of conclusions concerning


various issues: understanding a legal rule, situations to which it applies, the
relation of a given rule to another rule, etc. The applicability of a legal rule, as
reached through these arrangements, does not mean only that the scope of its
application is determined, but also that it is acceptable in the light of the purposes
and the values connected with the legal rule. An applicable legal rule becomes
a pattern of solving legal problems.
Such a pattern meets the requirements of utility and validity. To achieve utility
means satisfying the expectation that the actual situations to which such models
apply should be clearly determined. This allows for repeatability in the way legal
problems are solved. The requirement of validity is fulfilled when the patterns of
solving legal problems are models for the application of law that is relevant in every
respect. Validity is related to interpretative directives, to whether the understanding
of the provisions is compatible with the content of other legal texts (especially those
of a constitutional nature), and, finally – and this is quite problematic – to moral and
economic arguments or a legal policy. The validity of the pattern for resolving a legal
problem requires that it should be characterised by universality and objectivity. The
requirement of universality means that the essence of the problem characterising
a given case should be recognised, and an appropriate model for resolving each
case containing this essential problem should be formulated. Objectivity (non-
subjectivity) can be understood in a two-fold way. On the one hand, the model
should not be an individual expression of the lawyer’s views, while on the other
hand, it is expected to be justified by reference to something that is beyond the
lawyers’ consideration of the problem. The latter requirement sometimes raises
pitfalls when the reference is to discussions in the legislative process.
It is necessary to indicate some objections to the inclusion of this issue in
the discourse of the positivisation of law. One could say that to show the validity
of a norm impartially is one thing, and to apply it impartially is entirely another
thing. The norm recognised as valid prima facie will be the basis of a valid
resolution when it is appropriately and impartially applied without any relation
to the problematisation of the validity of this norm or the other norms competing
with it (Günther 1989, 156 ff). However, the legal rule understood in some way,
applied and functioning as the pattern of solving a legal problem, at least in some
cases, is not the same legal norm as the one prima facie belonging to the legal
system (viewed in the abstract).
The application of competing legal principles, based on their balancing,
also demands a justification which will function as a precedent for other cases.
Robert Alexy argues that claims to validity cannot be repealed through reference
to assertions formulated in the discourse of applying the law, and suggests that
Legal Heuristics and the Positivisation of Law in Dogmatic Discourse 89

for this reason the distinction between the discourse concerning the validity of
legal norms and the discourse concerning their application is not firmly grounded
(Alexy 1993, 163–164).

5. THE PROPERTIES OF ARGUMENTATION IN DOGMATIC DISCOURSE

The positivisation of law is conducted through reference to a rather


generically closed set of arguments which can be divided into two groups. The
first one includes references to the legal text, the language of law, and the system
of legal norms, while the second one – references to the history of the dogmatic
discourse. The properties of the text, language, or the system of norms can be
called their attributes; they are decisive for the formulated arguments attaining
objectivity. For example: (1) the attributes of facticity, legibility (regardless of its
clarity or non-clarity), internal context, and semantics appertain to the text of law;
(2) the attribute of intersubjectivity appertains to the language of law, because it
is a fragment of a natural language determined by semantic and syntactic rules;
and (3) the attributes of the law as a legal system are the relations between norms:
hierarchical relations, interim ones, and the ones connected with the content of
norms, especially those that concern the consistency of the legal system.
The attributes of the text of law, language of law, system of law and the
relations between them, i.e. recognised ways of joining them in argumentation,
make up the structure of law in dogmatic discourse. What we are concerned with
here is not a system of law in which a structure is a collection of relations between
legal norms; rather, a structure is something that is accepted as an objective
determinant which grounds an utterance on law in real dogmatic discourse.
A structure of law appears at the level of argumentation concerning legal norms
and not at the level of the system of legal norms.
Structural arguments are of a fundamental character, because dogmatic
discourse treats a structure of law as external to dogmatic argumentation, and
due to this arguments which lean towards an adopted method of solving a problem
are objectified. This serves to foster and maintain convictions that the structure
of law is stable, irrespective of those arguing, and, hence, it does not allow any
discretion in argumentation.
As the interpretative directives are derivative in relation to a legal structure,
they do not constitute an object of reference in dogmatic discourse. They are
“tools” for solving problems. In the practice of dogmatic discourse, these rules
come to the foreground; through them, and especially by means of interpretative
directives, lawyers refer to the text of the law, the language of the law, and the
legal system. Due to the prescriptive nature of these directives, making references
to the structures of law is one of the obligations of lawyers. Not all interpretative
directives use the objectivity of the object of reference in the same way; the
90 Jerzy Leszczyński

differences between references to language rules and references to the purposes


and intentions of the legislator, or to the function of the law, are evident. These
differences are a reason for problematising the values of various methods of
interpretation and are associated with general disputes about the values pursued
by law or by the application of law. The fact of whether one accepts or rejects
the factuality or the objectivity of references to legislative intentions, purposes,
functions, etc. has the ideological dimension. Hence, the preference for the priority
of linguistic interpretation, which is often justified by methodological reasons,
often conceals axiological choices, connected either to types of interpretative
directives or directly to the effects of their application.
Referring to the attributes of the text, the language, and the system of law is
often not sufficient for justifying the application of a legal provision in a certain
way. The reason for this is especially, though not exclusively, the openness of
functional interpretative directives (including purposeful ones). The acceptance
of the resolution to some legal problems, weakly justified in a legal text or not
justified at all, is supported by reference to the history of the dogmatic discourse.
In this way, doctrinal utterances, not least those of the judicature, are ascribed
the same attributes which primarily belong to legal texts (factuality, legibility,
etc.) However, controversies arise due to support for proposals which seek
to solve certain problems posed in the dogmatic discourse through assigning such
attributes to the utterances of participants of the legislative process.

6. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THEORY AND PRACTICE

The concept of the positivisation of law is associated with the philosophical


issue of the relationship between theory and practice, or between knowledge and
practice. The philosophical hermeneutics of Hans-Georg Gadamer draws attention
to the bidirectional relation of acquiring general knowledge and its practical
exploitation. It follows that the application of a general norm is not a consequence
of its understanding, but, rather, is its integral part. Gadamer believes that the
cognition of the meaning of a legal text and applying it to a specific legal case are
not two separate acts but one and the same process (Gadamer 2004, 308–309).
Practicality in the legal sphere means, on the one hand, the possibility of applying
the law according to the general knowledge one has acquired, and, on the other
hand, the necessity of finding oneself in an unpredictable, specific case of practical
reality which reciprocally influences the understanding of what constitutes general
knowledge. As models for action, rules are concretised through application. The
problem is what makes one application of a rule correct, and not another. One
response given to this question (i.e. by Ludwig Wittgenstein) emphasises the role
of practice, including customs and institutions, because – as Aristotle held – a rule
in itself does not unambiguously determine the way it is applied.
Legal Heuristics and the Positivisation of Law in Dogmatic Discourse 91

7. CONCLUDING REMARKS

One can notice that the forms of discourse in which law is positivised
are stable, and this is certainly the case with legal dogmatics. The failure of
attempts to present the development of the dogmatics of law in accordance with
the conception of a historically-changing paradigm (in the sense given to this
concept by Thomas S. Kuhn) is explained by the fact that legal dogmatics is not
only – or perhaps not even primarily – a field of cognition, but is at least equally
a sphere of practical action. In this case, assumptions as to the nature of objects
distinguished from the point of view of practice, the relations between them, their
influence on practice, etc. do not have a theoretical character sensu stricto. The
assumptions do not form part of an empirical theory in which the objects may have
a theoretical explanation as natural objects. What influences the shift of paradigms
in the empirical sciences cannot be found here.
While fulfilling the important social function of maintaining the values of
justice and legality, legal dogmatics is guided by the necessity of prudence and
theoretical self-restraint to avoid the pluralism of ideas and incessant change.
The factors limiting potential change are assumptions concerning the object of
research, heuristic methods, and the internal values of law. On the other hand,
legal dogmatics is a “science of meaning.” It follows that the use of conceptual
tools for regulating social conduct is justified not only by science, but also by
a free and morally-responsible discourse (Aarnio 1984, 31).

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Aarnio, Aulis. 1984. “Paradigms in Legal Dogmatics.” In Theory of Legal Science. Edited by
Aleksander Peczenik et al. 25–38. Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-
6481-5_4
Alexy, Robert. 1993. “Justification and Application of Norms.” Ratio Juris 6(2): 157–170. https://
doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1993.tb00144.x
Atienza, Manuel. Juan Ruiz Manero. 1998. A Theory of Legal Sentences. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publisher. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0848-8
Broekman, Jan M. 1985. “The Minimum Content of Positivism. Positivism in the Law and in Legal
Theory.” Rechtstheorie 16(4): 349–366.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 2004. Truth and Method. London: Continuum.
Günther, Klaus. 1989. “A Normative Conception of Coherence for a Discursive Theory of Legal
Justification.” Ratio Juris 2(2): 155–166. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1989.tb00034.x
Hartman, Jan. 2011. Heurystyka filozoficzna. [Philosophical Heuristics]. Toruń: Wydawnictwo
Naukowe Uniwersytetu Mikołaja Kopernika.
Leszczyński, Jerzy. 2010. Pozytywizacja prawa w dyskursie dogmatycznym. [Positivisation of Law
in Legal Dogmatic Discourse]. Kraków: Towarzystwo Autorów i Wydawców Prac Naukowych
Universitas.
Peczenik, Aleksander. 2005. Scientia Iuris. Legal Doctrine as Knowledge of Law and as a Source
of Law. Dordrecht: Springer.
92 Jerzy Leszczyński

Smits, Jan M. 2015. “What is Legal Doctrine? On the Aims nad Methods of Legal-Dogmatic
Research.” Maastricht European Private Law Institute Working Papers 06: 207–228. https://
doi.org/10.1017/9781316442906.006
Tuori, Kaarlo. 2016. Critical Legal Positivism. New York: Routledge. https://doi.
org/10.4324/9781315258867
Ziembiński, Zygmunt. 1980. Podstawowe problemy prawoznawstwa. [Basic Problems of
Jurisprudence]. Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Zirk-Sadowski, Marek. 1998. Prawo a uczestniczenie w kulturze. [Law and Participation in Culture].
Łódź: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Łódzkiego.

You might also like