Aristotle and Linguistics
Aristotle and Linguistics
Aristotle and Linguistics
The combination of a predicate with a term denot- likewise for the predicate. Steinthal, for example,
ing the hypokeı́menon Aristotle calls prótasis (Latin observed (1860: 101–102):
propositio). A proposition is true just in case the
One should not be misled by the similarity of the terms.
property assigned to the hypokeı́menon actually
Both logic and grammar speak of subject and predicate,
adheres to it; otherwise it is false. Moreover, a true but only rarely do the logician and the grammarian
proposition is made false, and vice versa, by the pre- speak of the same word as either the subject or the
fixing of not (‘‘it is not the case that’’). The term predicate.. . .Consider the sentence Coffee grows in
prótasis occurs for the first time on the first page Africa. There can be no doubt where the grammarian
of Prior Analytics, which contains his doctrine of will locate subject and predicate. But the logician? I do
syllogisms (Prior Analytics 24a16): not think the logician could say anything but that
‘Africa’ contains the concept that should be connected
A proposition (prótasis) is an affirmative or negative with ‘coffee grows’. Logically one should say, therefore,
expression that says something of something. ‘the growth of coffee is in Africa’.
A proposition is divided into terms (Prior Analytics Observations like this gave rise to a long debate,
24b16): which lasted more than 80 years. At the end, it was
decided to keep the terms subject and predicate for
A term (hóron) I call that into which a proposition is
analyzed, such as the predicate (katêgoroúmenon) and the syntactic analysis and speak of topic and com-
that to which the predicate is applied. ment for the semantic analysis in the Aristotelian
sense (see Seuren, 1998: 120–133 for a detailed
One notes that Aristotle lacked a word for what we discussion).
call the subject term of a sentence. During the late Syntax, in the modern sense, is largely absent from
Middle Ages, the Latin subiectum began to be used in Aristotle’s writings. He does, however, distinguish
that sense—an innovation that has persisted until the between different sentence types (On Interpretation
present time (Seuren, 1998: 121–124). 17a1–12):
This was the first semantic analysis of sentence
structure in history, presaged by, and probably Every sentence is meaningful, not in virtue of some
unthinkable without, Plato’s incipient analysis of sen- natural force but by convention. But not all sentences
are assertions, only those in which there is question of
tence meaning in his dialogue The Sophist. It is
truth or falsity. In some sentences that is not so. Wishes,
important to note that Aristotle’s analysis of the prop-
for example, are sentences but they are not true or false.
osition does not correspond to the modern syntactic We will leave all other sentence types out of consider-
analysis in terms of subject and predicate, but rather ation, as they are more properly studied in rhetoric or
to what is known as topic-comment analysis. The poetics. But assertions are the topic of the present study
identification of Aristotle’s sentence constituent for [i.e., logic]. The primary assertive sentence type is the
the denoting of a hypokeı́menon with ‘‘grammatical simple affirmation, the secondary is the simple negation.
subject,’’ characterized by nominative case, and of All other, complex, assertions are made one by conjunc-
Aristotle’s predicate with ‘‘grammatical predicate,’’ tion. Every assertion must contain a verb or a conjugated
may have been suggested by Aristotle, as when he form of a verb. For a phrase like ‘‘man’’ is not yet an
says that a morphological verb ‘‘always is a sign of assertion, as long as no verb in the present, past, or
future tense is added.
something said of something else’’ (On Interpretation
16b7). But it was carried through systematically a few Some word classes are already there. Thus, at the
decades after Aristotle’s death by the linguists of Alex- outset of On Interpretation, he defines ónoma (noun)
andria, whose task it was to develop teaching material as ‘‘a stretch of sound, meaningful by convention,
for the Egyptian schools where local children had to without any reference to time and not containing
learn Greek in the shortest possible time (Seuren, any internal element that is meaningful in itself’’
1998: 21–22). Unfortunately, this identification was, (On Interpretation 16a19–21). Rhêma (verb) is de-
though convenient, rash and ill-considered. It per- fined as ‘‘that which, in addition to its proper mean-
sisted more or less unchallenged until the middle of ing, carries with it the notion of time, without
the 19th century, when some, mostly German, scho- containing any internal element that is meaningful
lars discovered that the Aristotelian subject–predicate in itself; it always is a sign of something said of
distinction does not coincide with the syntactic sub- something else’’ (On Interpretation 16b6–8). In his
ject–predicate analysis universally applied in linguis- Rhetoric, at 1406a19, Aristotle uses the term epı́the-
tics. For in actual discourse, very often what should ton for adjective. All other terms for word classes
be the subject according to Aristotle’s definition is not are of a later date, with many of them having been
the subject recognized in grammatical analysis, and created by the Alexandrian linguists.
Aristotle and the Stoics on Language 471
The term ptôsis is found relatively frequently, in the person you call). These terms smell of the classroom,
sense of nominal or verbal morphological modifica- not of philosophy.
tion, as in Categories 1a13–15: ‘‘Things are said to be
named ‘derivatively’ when they derive their name
from some other word that differs in morphological See also: Aristotle and the Stoics on Language.
form (ptôsei), such as the grammarian from the word
grammar or the courageous from the word courage.’’
The literal meaning of ptôsis is ‘fall’ (Latin: casus). Its Bibliography
use in the sense of morphological modification is
based on the metaphor that the word ‘as such’ stands Allan K (2004). ‘Aristotle’s footprints in the linguist’s gar-
upright (in the ‘upright case’ or orthê ptôsis; Latin: den.’ Language Sciences 26(4), 317–342.
casus rectus). Its other falls are represented by forms Ogden C K & Richards I A (1923). The meaning of mean-
ing. A study of the influence of language upon thought
that are modified morphologically according to some
and of the science of symbolism. London: Routledge &
paradigm. The Alexandrians began to reserve the Kegan Paul.
term ptôsis for the nominal cases of nominative (the Seuren P A M (1998). Western linguistics: An historical
form of your own name), genitive (the form of your introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.
father’s name), dative (the name of the person you Steinthal H (1860). Charakteristik der hauptsächlichsten
give something to), accusative (the name of the per- Typen des Sprachbaues (Neubearbeitung von Dr. Franz
son you take to court), and vocative (the name of the Misteli). Berlin: Dümmler.