This document discusses different philosophical approaches to defining concepts and words, including their intension (essence or definition) and extension (set of things to which the concept applies). It describes the ancient Greek atomist and Platonic views, and more modern approaches focusing on similarities or extensions. The Platonic view that essences exist in non-physical Forms won out historically. Modern challenges to essences are noted, along with difficulties in the similarity view. The document also introduces a new approach adapted from the atomists that focuses on extensions rather than intensions.
This document discusses different philosophical approaches to defining concepts and words, including their intension (essence or definition) and extension (set of things to which the concept applies). It describes the ancient Greek atomist and Platonic views, and more modern approaches focusing on similarities or extensions. The Platonic view that essences exist in non-physical Forms won out historically. Modern challenges to essences are noted, along with difficulties in the similarity view. The document also introduces a new approach adapted from the atomists that focuses on extensions rather than intensions.
This document discusses different philosophical approaches to defining concepts and words, including their intension (essence or definition) and extension (set of things to which the concept applies). It describes the ancient Greek atomist and Platonic views, and more modern approaches focusing on similarities or extensions. The Platonic view that essences exist in non-physical Forms won out historically. Modern challenges to essences are noted, along with difficulties in the similarity view. The document also introduces a new approach adapted from the atomists that focuses on extensions rather than intensions.
This document discusses different philosophical approaches to defining concepts and words, including their intension (essence or definition) and extension (set of things to which the concept applies). It describes the ancient Greek atomist and Platonic views, and more modern approaches focusing on similarities or extensions. The Platonic view that essences exist in non-physical Forms won out historically. Modern challenges to essences are noted, along with difficulties in the similarity view. The document also introduces a new approach adapted from the atomists that focuses on extensions rather than intensions.
and Extension George Dickie 2. 1 Philosophical t heori zi ng arose, at least in t he West, in ancient Greek times. There and t hen, t he t wo main compet i t ors for explaining t he order t hat we experience were t he atomists and t he Platonists. The atomists explained this order as being t he result of t he mi cro-st ruct ure of individual things - gold has a different mi cro- st ruct ure from iron, tigers from lions, and so on. The atomists were t heori zi ng about t he essence of things, and they did so by talking about spatio-temporal, physical micro-structures. The Platonists also explained t he order that we experi- ence in t he world, but they said t hat individual things fall into t he types that they do because they participate in various Forms, these being non-spatial, non- t emporal abstractions. The essence of t hi ngs resides, for t he Platonists, in t he Forms. The atomists and t he Platonists differed about t he nat ure of t he essences of things. They also differed about how t he essences are responsible for t he order we experience: for t he atomists, causality 1 was responsible, whereas for t he Platon- ists, it was participation. 2 Thus, at t he very begi nni ng of t heori zi ng t here was a radical disagreement over what t he t heori zi ng was about - about what is real. Once t he atomists had enunciated their thesis t hat t he micro-structures of things differ from one another, they t hen had little else to say about t hose struc- tures. They spoke of invisible micro-structures but had no means of knowi ng any- t hi ng about these essences, al t hough they did speculate about t he movement and wei ght of atoms. They were so far ahead of their times t hat they were speechless; they were barred from inquiry into what they regarded as real by a lack of t echnol ogy and developed theory. The Platonists, however, were able to speak volumes, for in addition to t heori zi ng about t he order and essence of things, they also focused on words and their meanings, which were available in great supply. They had a philosophy of language, which t he atomists lacked. The atomists were as speechless about words as they were about invisible micro-structures. The 45 George Dickie Platonists spoke of non-visible things t oo, but they claimed we could know t hem because we underst and t he words whose meanings were constituted by t he non-visible Forms. The Forms were t hus alleged to be not only responsible for t he order of things but also t he meanings of words. The knowi ng of a Form is allegedly demonst rat ed when a word is underst ood. Compl et e knowi ng of a Form is supposedly demonst rat ed when an adequat e definition of a word - "figure," "justice," or t he like - is successfully achieved. The voluble Platonists, with a philosophy of language integrated with and underwri t t en by their metaphysics, won an easy victory over t he speechless atomists for control of subsequent philosophizing. Theori zi ng about t he essences of things and t he definitions of words - including art and "art" - t hus had its devel opment within t he Platonic vision of language and reality, with reality being underst ood to be a hierarchically ordered, rational st ruct ure of non-spatial, non- t emporal Forms that give order to t he world of experience and constitute t he intensions of words in a language. The metaphysical st ruct ure is rational in t he sense t hat it has t he form t hat woul d be given by a rational arranger, al t hough no arranger is envisaged within t he system. The st ruct ure of t he Forms is taken to be such t hat t here is a genus-species relation i nherent in every intension. Within this vision, t he essences of all sorts of different things - gold, water, tigers, justice, art, whatever - are taken to be of t he same sort and t he essences themselves are subject to dialectical analysis that can yield t he intensions - necessary and sufficient con- ditions - of t he words t hat apply to t he things with t he essences. For t he Platon- ists, inquiry about what is real was conceived of as a search i nt o t he intelligible realm of t he Forms for essences and meani ngs or intensions; empirical inquiry was regarded as a pursuit into t he illusion of sense. The intellectual agenda was t hus set by t he Platonists, and philosophical inquiry became an at t empt to produce t he essences of things and t he intensions of words. Philosophical inquiry continues to have somet hi ng of a Platonic flavor today. An apparent advantage t he Platonists' approach has over t he atomists' is t hat while in principle t he atomists have a way of explaining physical phenomena, t here is no obvious way for t hem to explain how non-physical characteristics (linguistic, moral, cultural, and t he like) arise from atomic configurations. On t he ot her hand, t he Platonists' metaphysics and philosophy of language supposedly deal with all kinds of phenomena from physical to moral. As is well known, in recent times t he search for t he essences of art and ot her not i ons has been challenged by t he claim t hat t here are no such essences, and t hat "art" and ot her words apply to t he t hi ngs they do in virtue of intensions that take not e of t he overlapping similarities among those things. This is a challenge to whatever is left of t he Platonic tradition in philosophy. Ther e are t hree main dif- ficulties with this untraditional development. First, it is unclear how t he similar- ities are to be specified - how similar do t wo characteristics have to be to count as linking t wo works of art under t he word "art" (or any t wo objects under t he same word), and how many such similarities are required to make t wo objects fall under t he word "art" (or any word)? Second, t he reliance on similarities threatens Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension to draw i nt o and collect into t he class of art, or any ot her not i on specified in t erms of similarities, every object in t he universe because, in some way, everything resem- bles everything else. Thi rd, focusing now only on art, if one tries to contain t he collecting tendencies of similarities by specifying t hat t he similarities must be to prior-established works of art, t hen an infinite regress of prior-established works of art is generated so that t here could never have been a first work of art and hence no present works of art. Since t here are works of art, t he similarity conception as t he whole story is wrong, and t here woul d have to be some non-similarity ur-work or ur-works of art t hat have priority over "similarity" art. Thus, some kind of non- similarity foundation woul d be required by t he similarity view. The atomists, t he Platonists, and t he similarity theorists all begin by focusing on t he order t hat they not e in things: t he Platonists infer Forms to explain iden- tities in experience and to be t he intensions of all kinds of words, which they take to be manifested in genus-species relationships; t he atomists infer conclusions about micro-structures to explain identities of physical phenomena in experience but have not hi ng to say about intensions; and t he similarity theorists forego inference and focus solely on experienced similarities, out of which they try to construct intensions. I shall not discuss t he similarity theories further. 2. 2 Recently, some philosophers of language have tried to work out a way to adapt t he insight of t he t ongue-t i ed Greek atomists about t he essences of things to t he probl em of t he application of words to things. One of t he t hi ngs t hat has enabled these philosophers to try to do what t he atomists could not try to do is t hat t here are now well-worked-out and accepted theories of t he mi cro-st ruct ure of things t hat were not available to t he atomists. In general, this new t echni que, according to t hose who advance it, is said to approach t he question of t he application of words to things t hr ough their extensions rather t han t hr ough i nt ensi ons. 3 This new approach supposedly contrasts sharply with t he traditional, Platonic-tinged approach to meani ng. One begins, using t he new approach, with descriptions of features t hat function mor e or less like intensions which serve to focus on some gr oup of things (an extension), and t hen in t he cases of natural kinds one dis- covers or proceeds with t he assurances t hat an essential, underlying propert y of t he members of t he gr oup of things (the extension) can be discovered t hat uniquely picks out t he gr oup of things, or some significant subset of t he gr oup of things. This underlying property, if discovered or discoverable, is what identifies this kind of t hi ng in all possible worlds in which t hat kind of t hi ng exists. Some philosophers of art have subsequently tried to apply this new t echni que to t he philosophy of art. The approach of Platonists is a top-down approach; for t hem, t he Forms, which function as intensions, are given and complete, so that, for t hem, intensions come George Dickie first as ready made and det ermi ne extensions, t he members of which are mere appearances. The new philosophers of language, on t he ot her hand, use a bottom- up approach; for t hem, t he discovered or discoverable essential propert y of t he members of an extension constitutes its nat ure. These philosophers of language begin, not with a discussion of natural kinds, but with a discussion of proper names as rigid designators. According to this view, a proper name such as "Aristotle" is a rigid designator, a rigid designator being somet hi ng t hat picks out t he same object in all possible worlds where it exists. Also, according to this view, proper names are i nt roduced by a baptism or dubbi ng, and we track their referents t hr ough t he world by means of causal historical chains. Proper names, on this view, function by means of reference or extension rather t han by intension. We in later generations have come to believe various proposi- tions about Aristotle, and earlier philosophers of language tried to use these beliefs in one way or anot her as intensions to pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Almost all of our beliefs about Aristotle, however, could be false, and t he rigid- designator approach avoids using t hem in any way. These philosophers of language t hen go on to apply t he rigid-designator approach to words for natural kinds. In t he case of an element such as gold, various properties such as being yellow, very malleable, and so on served to focus on a gr oup of objects (an extension); it was later discovered t hat all or many (a significant subset) of t he objects have a particular atomic number which t hen henceforth serves as t he essential, underlying property t hat picks out t he gr oup of gold things. Gol d' s essential property is being t he element with t he atomic number 79, and this means t hat gold is identical with t he element with t he atomic number 79 and that gold is necessarily t he element with t he atomic number 79. In t he case of a compound such as water, t he essential, underlying propert y t urns out to be a particular molecular combi nat i on of elements, namely, H 2 0 ; thus, water is necessarily H 2 0 . In t he case of a species of plants or animals, t he essential, under- lying propert y woul d perhaps t urn out to be somet hi ng like a particular DNA profile or whatever t he correct underlying propert y is for species. These underly- ing properties serve to identify, for example, gold and water in all possible worlds in which t here are such substances. In t he cases of elements, compounds and species, t he essential properties are underlying because they are micro-structures. The discovery of t he essences of natural kinds - "gold, " "water," and so on - is approached t hr ough extensions. These philosophers of language have advanced t he insight of t he Greek atomists to a remarkable degree. 2. 3 James Carney (1975, 1982) at t empt ed to take t he insight of t he philosophers of language even further by applying t he rigid-designator approach to t he probl em of what has been characterized in t he past as t he defining of "art." For this appli- 48 Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension cation to be possible, according to Carney, it must be t he case t hat a paradigm set of objects had been dubbed "art" and t hat t he dubbers believed t hat t he objects share a universal property t hat is a nature, j ust as all pieces of gold share t he nature of having t he atomic number 79. And, for Carney, j ust as gold is necessarily t he element with t he atomic number 79, art woul d necessarily be whatever had t he universal property. Carney suggests t hat it is counterintuitive not to have t he belief t hat works of art have such an extension-determining nat ure. Carney t hen says: It is not unreasonable to suppose that what Danto, Dickie, and others have called the "artworld" is the subclass in a society that determines the universal property and that they rely on theories of art to do this. The artworld would be analogous to the metallurgists for "gold," and art theories would play a role similar to scientific theories and "gold" in that they would be taken as hypothesizing the extension- determining property of art. (1975: 200) A few lines later Carney writes, "Theories such as t he imitation t heory or expres- sion t heory woul d be adequate, since they hypothesize a universal property for paradigms" (1975: 201) . What Carney is saying is t hat any art t heory t hat claims t hat artworks share an essential property, which of course is every traditional art t heory except t he simi- larity view, is a candidate for being fitted to t he rigid-designator approach. Wi t h all t he historical theories of art t hat have been put forth, Carney' s final say on t he mat t er has to be hypothetical: "If t he paradigms [of art] have a universal property, t hen t here is a way to det ermi ne with certainty whet her x is art: x is art if x has t he universal propert y" (1975: 200) . This hypothetical resolution leaves open t he possibility t hat different universal properties mi ght be det ermi ned by different members of t he artworld, assuming for t he moment an underst andi ng of t he artworld as Carney is envisaging it. On Carney' s view, this apparent difficulty is resolved because of t he nat ure of t he only t wo possibilities. If a disagreement arises among t he members of t he artworld over t he common nature of artworks, t hen t he members may decide t hat all t he old paradigms of art do not share a single underlying nat ure and it will t urn out t hat t he old paradigms separate into t wo or mor e extensions, each with its underlying nature, and t here will be t wo or more kinds of art. Or, on t he ot her hand, if a disagreement arises within t he artworld over t he common nature of artworks, say, over whet her a new kind of t hi ng is art, with one side citing one nat ure and anot her side citing anot her nature as art -det ermi ni ng, t he t wo sides either accept t he t wo- or-more-kinds-of-art solution j ust discussed or can agree on one nature and t here will be only one kind of art. So, t he members of t he artworld will cither disagree and t here will be more t han one kind of art, or they will agree and t here will be one kind of art. Carney' s view raises t hree questions. First, can art theories play t he kind of role t hat scientific theories play in connect i on with t he rigid-designator approach to natural kinds? Carney' s answer is "Yes, if they assert a claim of a universal prop- George Dickie erty for t he paradigms. " This answer raises a second question: "Which art t heory is analogous to t he atomic t heory t hat yields t he atomic number 79 for gold, t he molecular t heory t hat describes t he molecular st ruct ure of water, or t he biologi- cal t heory t hat specifies DNA profiles?" Hi s answer is that it is t he art t heory (or theories) with t he universal propert y (or properties) det ermi ned by t he members of t he artworld. This answer raises a third question: "Does t he artworld function as Carney envisions?" He does not answer t he third question ot her than to say, "it is not unreasonable to suppose" t hat it does (1975: 200) . Peter Kivy was t he first to attack Carney' s suggested approach to t heori zi ng about art (1979). Kivy does not comment on Carney' s claim about actions of t he members of t he artworld, focusing solely on his claim of close analogy between art theories and scientific theories. Where Carney sees analogy, Kivy sees disanal- ogy We are not prepared, Kivy says, to accept an art t heory in t he way t hat we "are prepared to accept a scientific account of t he internal st ruct ure of a natural kind" (1979: 430). He agrees t hat in t he scientific domai n t here is a history of discovering t hat earlier theories are false and of their being replaced by new theories, and t hat this bears some resemblance to art theories being replaced by later art theories. But, he says, t he succession of scientific theories is different in t hat it reveals an increasing scope and ability to deal with t he data. Such success in t he scientific domai n inspires a confidence t hat is not found in t heori zi ng about art by philosophers. Thomas Leddy was t he next to attack Carney' s view (1987). He appears to accept Kivy's poi nt about t he disanalogy between art theories and scientific t heo- ries, but he focuses on a logically prior analogy alleged in Carney' s view - his con- t ent i on t hat t he artworld determines t he universal property of art analogously to t he way metallurgists det ermi ne t he nat ure of gold. Carney begins by talking about artworld members "hypothesizing" about t he universal property of art. Leddy notes, however, t hat it appears to t urn out t hat on Carney' s view t he members of t he artworld supposedly determine t he nature of art by deciding on a universal property. This contrasts sharply with how metallurgists determine t he nat ure of gold: they discoverthe universal propert y of gold (1987: 264) . Thus, Leddy uncov- ers anot her difference where Carney' s view requires similarity. What of Carney' s claim, which neither Kivy nor Leddy addresses, t hat t he members of t he artworld function to det ermi ne (even if it is only by deciding) t he nature of art? Carney says t hat t he members of what Dant o, I, and others have called t he artworld det ermi ne t he universal propert y of art. This makes t he art- world into somet hi ng like a legislative body t hat deliberates and issues directives t hat are bi ndi ng on t he ot her members of society. First, it is not indicated who t he "ot hers" are, but t he accounts t hat Dant o and I have given of t he artworld are very different, al t hough this was perhaps not so clear in t he mi d-1970s, when Carney published his view, as it is now. Carney writes t hat Dant o' s st at ement t hat "It is t he t heory that takes it [Brillo Box] up into t he artworld" means that we can take his st at ement to imply "that t he extension of t he t erm ' art' is det ermi ned by t he theories of art held by t he artworld" (1975: 201) . Perhaps Dant o' s account 50 Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension in "The Artworld" can be const rued to fit t he rigid-designator approach as Carney says, but I do not think this is Dant o' s view, and I, for one, do not think t hat t he artworld functions as a legislative body. Richard Wollheim has attributed to me t he view of t he artworld as legislative body and t hen has gone on to ridicule t he view (1987: 14- 15) . This underst andi ng of t he institutional t heory of art deserves to be ridiculed because t here is no reason at all to think t hat t he artworld or any aspect of it acts like a legislative body - with meetings and decisions, and with declarations and proclamations. Fort u- nately, t he view of t he artworld t hat Wollheim attributes to me is not one t hat I have ever held (Dickie 1993: 69- 71) , al t hough he and a number of ot her people seem to have t hought I did. I have always underst ood t he artworld to be a back- gr ound for t he practice of creating and experiencing art - a background t hat is an essential part of t he practice. So, t here seem to be t wo strikes against Carney' s view - Kivy's and Leddy' s - and perhaps a third against his underst andi ng of t he nat ure of t he artworld. I do think t he rigid-designator approach can be fitted to t he imitation t heory of art and to some versions of t he expression t heory of art, but not because these theories mi ght be held by members of t he artworld. The t wo theories can be fitted to t he approach because they are what I have elsewhere called "natural-kind t he- ories" (1997a: 25- 8) . The philosophers who were t he proponent s of these t wo theories were at t empt i ng to identify art with one, single, particular kind of human activity - imitating or t he expression of emot i on - t hat can quite reasonably be regarded as natural or what today woul d be t hought of as hard-wired. Not e t he parallel here with gold, water, and species. In t he case of gold and t he ot her ele- ment s, it t urned out that t here is a fairly small number (something over a hundred) elements, and physicists discovered t hat each one has one distinct atomic number t hat uniquely picks it out . (Apparently, isotopes can be ignored. ) In t he case of water and t he ot her compounds, it t urned out t hat t here is a very large number of compounds, but even so physicists and chemists discovered t hat each one has one distinct molecular configuration t hat uniquely picks it out . The case is perhaps similar for species. It is quite reasonable to suppose that some day t he now-hi dden, underlying nat ure of t he behavior of imitating or expressing of emot i on will be discovered by a scientist - some breed of psychologist/biologist. These t wo ways of acting woul d be natural-kind behaviors of natural-kind beings. I am speaking here of imitating and expressing as such; how such imitating and expressing are st ruct ured and directed and t oward what may vary from culture to culture. By t he way, these behaviors are not limited to human beings. Unfort unat el y for t he imitation and expression theories, t here is no good reason to think t hat either of these behaviors is identical with art - some works of art are not imitations or expressions of emot i on and some imitations and expressions of emot i on are not art - which is why t he theories have been almost universally rejected. So, al t hough t he imitation t heory and t he expression t heory are t he sort of theories t hat could be fitted to t he rigid-designator approach, because t here is reason to think t hat imitation and t he expression of emot i on have underlying 51 George Dickie essences, it woul d be a mistake to try to do so because t hose behaviors j ust do not match up with all our artworks. They are t he wr ong theories to use. 2. 4 There is perhaps a way to fit certain aspects of t he rigid-designator approach to art, namely, to approach t hr ough an extension, looking for an underlying prop- erty, al t hough not one t hat functions in all t he ways t hat a property such as being H 2 0 does. Consider Carney' s procedure. His account of t he application of t he rigid-designator approach to natural kinds can be summarized by picturing t he following pairs: gold./physicists, water/physicists and chemists, and species/molecular biologists. Carney t hen tries to use t he rigid-designator approach with t he specifi- cation of t he essence of art, pairing art and members of the artworld. In effect, Kivy and Leddy in different ways poi nt out t hat Carney' s pairing is not analogous to t he earlier pairs which all involve scientists. In order to extend t hose aspects of t he rigid-designator approach t hat I wish to use, t he second place in t he art/ pair should be filled with t he name of some kind of scientist. In t he above discussion of t he fitting of t he imitation and expression theories to t he rigid-designator approach, t he second place in t he pair was filled by psychologists/biologists, who presumably woul d focus on t he behavior specified by t he t wo old theories of art. But what I am envisaging here is scientists who woul d focus directly on t he art of our culture or ot her cultures. Before trying to apply t he aspects of t he rigid-designator approach I wish to use to t he complicated not i on of art, consider how it mi ght go with a simpler cul- tural concept. Assume an ant hropol ogi st goes to work, say, in t he 1920s on a par- ticular sout h Pacific island culture. In landing on t he island, t he ant hropol ogi st ' s native translator is drowned, so she must carry out her studies wi t hout t he benefit of access to t he islanders' language. One of her observations is t hat many people are referred to as pukas but not all. She t hen observes t hat only males are pukas, al t hough some of t hem are fat and some skinny, some are short and some tall, and so on. So what is a puka? In her further observing of t he social st ruct ure of t he islanders, our ant hropol ogi st discovers t hat t he teenage boys and girls regularly engage in promiscuous sexual behavior wi t hout anyone disapproving, but t hat about age 16 on t he day of t he summer solstice they are compelled to st op this behavior by everyone in t he society. The 16-year-olds t hen have t he opt i on of par- ticipating in an elaborate ceremony in which a male and a female are paired and thereafter must maintain a monogamous relation. Those who choose not to par- ticipate in t he ceremony are thereafter not permi t t ed to engage in sexual activity with a partner wi t hout social disapproval. It is t he males who do not participate in t he ceremony t hat are thereafter pukas. So, al t hough it was not at first evident to our anthropologist, t he "underlying" feature in t he case of pukas is t he prac- tice of t he members of t he culture, treating a male 16 years old or older who has 52 Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension refused to participate in t he ceremony t hat regularizes sexual activity among persons over 16 in a certain fashion. The practice t hat our ant hropol ogi st takes not e of is not underlying or hi dden in t he way t hat t he universal properties of gold, water, and species are, but it is not as obvious as t he colors of t he islanders' clothes either. It takes some observing, inferring, and t heori zi ng to arrive at an underst andi ng of t he cultural practice, but t he practice in a way is transparent. The cultural practice is underlying but t here to be taken not e of. When writing down her notes on t he island culture, our ant hropol ogi st trans- lates "puka" as "bachelor." When at t he end of her first year on t he island anot her native translator arrives, he says t hat t he translation is close but incorrect and t hat t here is no exact equivalent for "puka" in English. Our ant hropol ogi st woul d have discovered t he underlying nat ure of pukas, but she woul d t hen have gone on to translate t he word "puka" wrongly. American and European societies do not have pukas because we do not compel t he ceremony and behavior described above. Any society t hat did compel t he ceremony and behavior described woul d have pukas, even if only this island in fact had this practice. Pukas are individuals compelled and regulated as described, and they woul d be such in all possible worlds in which they exist. Our ant hropol ogi st woul d have const ruct ed an essentially correct t heory of one aspect of t he island culture wi t hout t he help of t he intensional cont ent of t he island language, al t hough her use of "bachelor" in her account is not quite right. Pukas and bachelors are similar in a certain central respect, but they also differ in some i mport ant central aspects, so we cannot say that they have t he same underlying nat ure. The underlying nat ure t hat bachelors have and t he underlying nat ure t hat pukas could have, unlike t he physical reality t hat gold, water, and species have, are cul- tural realities (cf. Searle 1997). Such cultural natures are or woul d be a small part of a larger reality t hat is constituted by webs of relations t hat are or could be instituted by a society of persons. 2. 5 Theori zi ng about art began in and has been carried out t hr oughout almost all of its history in t he Platonic mode, which focuses on discovering t he intensions of our words. Even when philosophers have given up on Forms, they have contin- ued t he top-down approach of seeking intensions - in t he analysis of concepts, in ordinary language, or in j ust seeking definitions wi t hout saying how they are doi ng so. The "intensional" approach, which focuses on language, will not work for such t erms as "gold, " "water," and their like, but it appears to work for t erms like "bachelor." Carney himself ment i ons that, unlike "gold, " "bachelor" has a specifiable intension. He writes, "A term like ' bachelor' in its accurate adult use is i nt roduced as a synonym for ' adult male not previously mar r i ed' " (1975: 199). Carney' s saying t hat "bachelor" is "i nt roduced as a synonym" makes it sound as 53 George Dickie if t he t erm was put i nt o t he language in t he way a technical t erm is i nt roduced by a philosopher or a logician, but of course he does not mean t hat it was. "Bache- lor" came i nt o t he language as a co-relative t erm to "marriage, " and bot h t erms (and many others) ride on practices t hat we have instituted as a cultural gr oup. So, "bachelor," unlike "gold, " has an intension, but on t he ot her hand, "bache- lor," like "gol d, " can be approached t hr ough its extension; al t hough in t he case of an English word like "bachelor," we never bot her to do this because, as native speakers of English, we have intensional access to its meani ng. In t he imagined case of pukas, t he language-deprived ant hropol ogi st is forced to approach t hr ough an extension because she lacks intensional access to t he islander' s language. The concepts bachelor and puka, unlike t he concepts gold, water and tiger, are transparent, t hat is, a person who knows t he culture in which t he concept func- tions, knows t he concept. The natures of bachelors and pukas are underlying in t he sense that one cannot j ust look at an individual and see t hat he is a bachelor or a puka; one must know whet her an individual is enmeshed in t he relevant cultural relations. The nature of bachelors and t he nature of gold are similar in t hat they are dis- coverable by empirical inquiry. The natures differ in t hat t he nature of bachelors depends on cultural developments - decisions and t he like - whereas t hat of gold does not . So, one is t empt ed to say t hat t he nat ure of gold cannot change, which is t rue, but t hat t he nat ure of bachelors can, which is misleading. The use of t he word "bachelor" can change in several different ways. Assume that at a given time t he word has one meani ng. The word could change its meani ng entirely while still having only one meani ng. It could change entirely and have t wo completely new meanings. The word could acquire a second meani ng with t he original meani ng remaining unchanged, and so on. But even if t he word "bachelor" changed in one of these ways or even if t he word ceased to exist as a word in t he language, t he condi t i on of being an unmarri ed adult male and t he cultural practice of categorizing such an individual need not change. The condi t i on and practice remain a logical possibility even if "bachelor" ceases to exist in t he language and every person is in fact married or previously married. I believe t he concept art is like t he concept bachelor (and t he concept puka), and t he word "art" is like t he word "bachelor" (and t he word "puka"). Of course, no one has ever felt t he need to put forth a t heory of bachelorness. Plato seems never to have felt t he need to write a dialogue about it as he did about piety, friendship, and justice, or even to attack it in passing as metaphysically inferior and psychologically dangerous as he did art. Why has no one ever felt t he need for a t heory of bachelorness? Perhaps because "bachelor" does not serve as an evalua- tive weapon-word in t he way t hat "art" does, and, no doubt , for a variety of ot her reasons; but probably no one has ever felt t he need for a t heory of bachelorness because intensional access to its meani ng is so easy and uncontroversial. In any event, Plato did theorize about art and did attack art on metaphysical and psychological grounds, and philosophers have been trying to theorize about art ever since. Intensional access to "art" is obviously much mor e difficult t han to Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension "bachelor," and it is clearly much more controversial. We do not seem to need to apply what may be called "t he extensional approach" to "bachelor," but perhaps t he difficulty and controversy involved with "art" can be avoided by using t he extensional approach with it. Earlier I not ed t hat in order to use t he extensional approach to "art" t he second place in t he art/ pair should be filled with t he name of some kind of scien- tist. Following t he pattern established with t he case of bachelors and pukas, I think t he pair should be art/cultural anthropologists. Art is, I have l ong believed, a cul- tural not i on, and cultural anthropologists are t he scientists that deal with cultural phenomena. My own belief in art as a cultural phenomenon is demonst rat ed by t he fact that t he institutional t heory of art, which I have been defending in one form or anot her for a l ong time, is clearly a cultural theory. Perhaps it is wor t h not i ng that Leddy twice alludes to art as a cultural concept by contrasting it with what he calls natural science concepts in his 1987 article t hat I discussed above, but t hat is all he says on t he topic. When I say t hat art is a cultural not i on, I mean t hat it is a phenomenon t hat has been invented by a cultural gr oup and t hat it is not a genetically det ermi ned behavior like mating, eating, and t he like. 4 In saying this, I do not mean to suggest t hat only we or some small gr oup of societies have art or our concept of art. I think that Denni s Dut t on is probably right that all human societies have art (2000). Of course, t here could be and mi ght be a human society t hat does not yet in fact have art. I only wish to say of each society t hat has art t hat it was invented at some poi nt in t he past. It is, of course, possible t hat in t he case of a given society art was i mport ed from anot her culture before it could be invented indigenously, so in this case t he poi nt in t he past referred to woul d be in t he past of anot her society. What woul d be t he general features of t he application of t he extensional approach to t he not i on of art using t he art/cultural anthropologist pairing? We woul d be looking for a cultural phenomenon t hat is shared by all cultures or at least many cultures, since, as not ed, a given culture mi ght not yet have art. The phenomenon woul d have to be of a cultural nat ure t hat is t he same in all cultures t hat have it. That nat ure woul d have to be of a rather abstract kind, given t he widely differing kinds of art t hat t here are. And it mi ght be t hat t here are things t hat very closely resemble a kind of art t hat are not art; t hat is, t here could be an arbitrariness about one t hi ng' s being art and a very closely resembling t hi ng not being art. Such arbitrariness is perhaps inevitable where cultural matters are con- cerned, because cultural matters are how they are as t he result of how a culture has "set things up" at some time or duri ng some period in t he past. It woul d perhaps be best to begin our looking within our own culture. We woul d approach our own culture as t he imagined ant hropol ogi st did t he island culture, except t hat we have t he advantage t hat we are native speakers of our own language. Of course, various aspects of language could be handicaps that lead native speakers astray. Words in their dictionary senses typically have a number of different meanings, which could be confusing. Further, we (and any native speaker 55 George Dickie of any natural language) can make a word mean almost anything by t he use of inflection, irony, gestures, juxtaposition, and t he like, and this t oo may confuse us in t he cases of t he meanings of some words. All of this linguistic flexibility may obscure our view of t he practices t hat underlie t he specific meani ngs of some words. We mi ght be better able to isolate these specific meani ngs of these practice-dependent words if we were language-deprived observers, like t he imagined anthropologist. Of course, language-deprived observers can make t he kind of mistranslation imagined. The first lesson to be derived from t he imagined case of t he language-deprived ant hropol ogi st ' s mistranslation is t hat in t he case of t he meani ng of culturally det ermi ned words, access to t he intensional cont ent of t he language of t he members of t he culture involved can be useful. The second lesson to be derived from t he case of t he language-deprived ant hropol ogi st (one i gnored by t he purely intensional approaches of historical philosophers of art) is t hat in t he cases of certain concepts and t he words t hat go with t hem, knowl edge of t he practices t hat underlie t he concepts and their words is crucial to their meani ng. Applying these t wo lessons, it may be possible to make some progress in t heori zi ng about art. To apply t he extensional approach to t he not i on of art using t he art/cultural anthropologist pairing, one needs to look for linguistic usage that is integrated with cultural practice analogous to t he islanders' use of "puka" and their practice involved in organizing t he cultural activities of pukas, and our use of "bachelor" and t he practice involved in our organizing t he cultural practice of bachelors. If we start, as cultural anthropologists, with our own linguistic usage, t he usages of "art" woul d have to relate to a provisional description in t he way t hat t he usages of "gold" relate to t he properties of being yellow and malleable as a pro- visional description. In t he way t hat physicists t hen focus on yellow and malleable objects on their way to discovering t he atomic number of gold, cultural ant hro- pologists will have to start by focusing on objects t hat satisfy t he provisional description. The usages we will find with "art," however, because of our wide linguistic flexibility, will be all over t he place. But not e t hat t he usages of "gold" will be t oo; consider, "You struck gold!" said to someone who bought Xerox stock early on or to t he discoverer of an i mport ant scientific t rut h. Despite all of its many and varied usages, with "gold" we somehow wi nnowed our way down to a preliminary extension of yellow and malleable objects and t hen proceeded to atomic theorizing. Wi t h "art," we will have to wi nnow our way down to a reasonable preliminary extension and t hen look for a cultural practice t hat underlies this preliminary extension or some significant subset of it. We can think of t he history of t he philosophy of art - from Plato to Dant o - as a kind of wi nnowi ng of t he preliminary description of "work of art," al t hough, as we shall see, t he process does not always eliminate items from t he extension of works of art - sometimes it adds t hem. Not even t he earliest imitation theorist woul d have been moved to think of driftwood as art if some ot her ancient Greek, foreshadowing Morris Weitz and some ot her t went i et h-cent ury philosophers, had ut t ered t he Greek equivalent of Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension "That driftwood is a lovely piece of sculpture. " He woul d not have considered t he driftwood to be within t he extension of art, not only because it is not an imita- tion but also because it is not an artifact, t hat is, a human artifact. Someone has to be in t he grip of a philosophical movement to think that a piece of driftwood all by itself is an artwork because it has been referred to as a lovely piece of sculp- t ure. Thus, non-artifactuality was wi nnowed out of (or perhaps it should be said never got into) t he preliminary description of "work of art" by virtue of some- t hi ng like common sense. Imitation theorists were, however, moved - eventually anyway - by anot her kind of case: things t hat were obviously not imitations but which seemed like art- works nevertheless. Being bot hered by this kind of case forced an expansion in their concept i on of t he intension of artworks and caused t hem to cease being imi- tation theorists. The expansion of t he intension of artworks by counterexamples advanced by others or j ust noticed has been a standard feature of t heori zi ng about art. Not i ce t hat to work as a counterexample to someone' s theory, t he alleged counterexample must plausibly fit into an extension despite t he fact t hat it lacks all or some part of t he theorist' s underst andi ng of t he intension of a t erm under consideration. This kind of philosophical move has been responsible, not for a wi nnowi ng out of characteristics from t he preliminary description of "work of art," but for an addi ng of characteristics. This kind of move eliminates theories - t he imitation t heory of art, for example, and, I think, t he expression t heory as well. I think t hat virtually all philosophers of art - present and past - are and always have been agreed t hat it is poems, painting, plays, sonatas, sonnets, sculptures, and such familiar items t hat are works of art and t hat this is t he extension that they are and always have been t heori zi ng about - trying to state t he intension t hat fits it. There has of course been some disagreement as to whet her to count Dada objects and similar things as works of art, but this is a skirmish of little signifi- cance. I have maintained t hat Dada objects are theoretically useful because they have helped us gain insight i nt o t he art-making cont ext in which works of art are embedded, either because Dada objects are works of art or because they are not works of art but have been mistaken for works of art by some people. In any event, let us set aside this dispute and focus at t ent i on on t he huge gr oup of works of art about which t here is compl et e agreement. The philosophical probl em with t he large gr oup of items that constitutes t he extension of works of art has always been t he great diversity of its members. This het erogeneousness has been t he great barrier to t he traditional at t empt s to extract t he intension from t he exhibited features of these works. 5 By "exhibited features" I mean characteristics t hat can be noticed by directly experiencing works of art - for example, t hat they are representations, are expressive, are delicate, and t he like. What exhibited features could be found to be exemplified in all these many and diverse works of art? And what a ready source of counterexamples t hat same diver- sity has been against all t hose imitationists, expressionists, and t he like who have tried to specify partial or complete conditions from among exhibited features. 57 George Dickie Focus now on present-day theories of art. I think Dant o' s at t empt to charac- terize art in t erms of aboutness is an example of t he traditional search for t he inten- sional meani ng of "work of art" among exhibited characteristics, and I believe t hat his t heory is vulnerable to t he traditional kind of counterexample attack (cf. Dickie 1993: 76- 7; Carroll 1993). Beardsley' s at t empt to characterize art in t erms of aes- thetic character is also an example of t he same traditional search among exhibited characteristics and is subject to t he same kind of attack (1979: 729, 1983: 299) . On t he ot her hand, I think Jerrold Levinson' s historical t heory and my institu- tional t heory are different from t he traditional theories and can be underst ood as attempts to discover t he underlying nature of t he extension of works of art - t he underlying nat ure being t he non-exhibited, feature of works of art t hat ties t hem together. I will not discuss Levinson' s t heory here because I have discussed its difficulties elsewhere (1997a: 22- 4) . What woul d a search by a cultural ant hropol ogi st uncover in a study of "how we deal wi t h" works of art? I believe such a search woul d reveal an underlying cultural st ruct ure like t hat envisaged by t he institutional t heory of art. The insti- tutional t heory is an account of t he cultural st ruct ure within which works of art are produced and function, and t he st ruct ure itself is specified in t erms of a variety of cultural roles. In any event, even if cultural anthropologists could not find a cultural struc- t ure identical with t hat described by t he institutional theory, I believe they woul d find a st ruct ure very much like it. That is, they woul d find a st ruct ure of t he general sort t hat t he five declarations I gave as definitions in The Art Circle can serve as a summary account of. These five are as follows: 1 An artist is a person who participates with underst andi ng in t he making of a work of art. 2 A work of art is an artifact of a kind created to be presented to an artworld public. 3 A public is a set of persons t he members of which are prepared in some degree to underst and an object which is presented to t hem. 4 The artworld is t he totality of all artworld systems. 5 An artworld system is a framework for t he presentation of a work of art by an artist to an artworld public. (1997b: 80- 2) The st ruct ure presented by these five woul d be t he sort of t hi ng t hat constitutes t he cultural essence of t he institution within which art has its being. And t he second declaration (definition) is t he sort of t hi ng t hat can be taken as a state- ment of t he cultural essence of a work of art, namely, a st at ement that identifies art with t he complicated property of being an artifact of a kind created to be pre- sented to an artworld public. 58 Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension 2. 6 Assume for argument ' s sake that "A work of art is an artifact of a kind created to be presented to an artworld public" captures t he cultural essence of art because t he st at ement has been arrived at by means of a search by anthropologists into cultural structure. Would t hat mean t hat it states t he intension of "work of art"? When Carney applies t he rigid-designator approach to "work of art," he concludes t hat "work of art" has no intension. Remember, however, what Carney says about "bachelor," namely, t hat it has an intension. So, Carney treats words like "bachelor" differently from t he way in which he treats words like "gold. " He does not explain why "bachelor" is different from "gold, " and t here is not hi ng in his article t hat requires him to do so. I, however, have claimed that what I am calling "t he extensional approach" can be applied to "work of art" and have also tried to apply it to "bachelor." So, I need at least to show how "bachelor" has an intension if t he extensional approach can be applied to it. In effect, I have agreed with Carney t hat "bachelor" means "an adult male not previously married" and added that being an adult male not previously married is t he underlying cultural nature of bachelors. How does t he case of t he nature of bachelors, which is derived by means of t he extensional approach, differ from t hat of t he nature of gold, which is derived by means of t he rigid-designator approach? And how does t he case of "bachelor" differ from "gold" so t hat "bachelor" can have an intension and "gol d" does not? Consider t he question of how t he nat ure of bachelors differs from t he nat ure of gold. First, t he nat ure of bachelors is a cultural nature; it is a cultural status. Being a bachelor is of course not a legal status, but it is related to and derived from marriage, which is a mat t er of law - law being an officially enacted cultural phenomenon. Marriage is a cultural (legal) way of organizing various central aspects of t he lives of human beings. Being a bachelor is a cultural (non-legal) way of organizing aspects of t he lives of some human males - how and under what cir- cumstances, for example, certain human males are invited to dinner. The nat ure of gold, on t he ot her hand, is not cultural, but physical. There woul d be gold if t here were no cultures anywhere. Ther e could not be bachelors wi t hout a culture and in fact not wi t hout a culture t hat has marriage. We have no control over t he nat ure of gold, but we do have control over t he nature of cultural things, al t hough it is a complicated matter. There is anot her i mport ant difference between t he nat ure of gold and t he nat ure of bachelors. An individual sample of gold in t he actual world (the element with t he atomic number 79) woul d be gold in all possible worlds, t hat is, t he indi- vidual sample of gold is necessarily t he element with t he atomic number 79. In contrast, an individual bachelor Adam in t he actual world mi ght be a married man in some possible worlds and t hus not a bachelor in all possible worlds, t hat is, t he individual bachelor Adam is not necessarily a bachelor. Being gold is a nat ure t hat mi ght be called an intrinsic nature, while being a bachelor is a nat ure t hat an indi- 59 George Dickie vidual acquires by fitting into a cultural context. It is wor t h not i ng in passing t hat particular works of art are like bachelors in this respect. For example, a particular physical object t hat is a work of representational art in t he actual world mi ght not be a work of art in some possible world, because that possible world lacks t he cul- tural institution of art and t hat particular physical object woul d t hen merely be a representation; t hus, a particular work of art in t he actual world is not necessarily a work of art. Second, in t he case of discovering (or j ust knowing) t he nature of bachelors, t here is no intellectual division of labor t hat requires experts to discover t hat nat ure as is required in t he case of gold. Gold has a hi dden nature t hat requires highly specialized individuals - physicists, chemists, and t he like - to discover its nat ure. The nat ure of bachelors, al t hough it is underlying in being a culturally founded phenomenon, is known to virtually everyone; its nature is transparent rather than hidden. Consider now how "bachelor" differs from "gold. " First, "bachelor" is a cul- tural t erm in t hat it derives in part from t he cultural t erm "married, " al t hough of course it also involves t he biological t erms "adult" (which may be given some cul- tural cont ent by way of a roughly specified age designation) and "male. " "Gol d" is not a cultural t erm but a physical t erm, t hat is, it refers to objects with a physical nat ure. Second, "bachelor" has some similarity to technical words t hat are stipulated to have a certain meani ng. In t he case of technical terms, it is typically individual persons who do t he stipulating, but in t he case of words like "bachelor," it is t he culture t hat does t he "stipulating" or somet hi ng like stipulating t hat may be called cultural det ermi nat i on. The exact nature of this det ermi nat i on is vague, and fur- t her mor e t he courses of t he various det ermi nat i ons probably differ in t he cases of different cultural t erms. The cultural det ermi nat i on of t he meani ng of cultural words is of course closely related to t he fact that we have some control over t he natures of cultural matters. There is an intimate connect i on between "bachelor" and t he nat ure of bachelors - a sort of congruency in which t he intension of "bachelor" and t he nature of t he members of t he extension of "bachelor" are det ermi ned by our culture in a logically concomi t ant way. The word "bachelor" (and its definition) and t he nature of bachelors are bot h t he same kind of thing, namely, they are bot h cultural product s. Bot h are co-ordinated and mi rrori ng product s of how we organize t he intertwined pathways of our linguistic and behavioral lives. "Gol d" and t he nat ure of gold lack this intimate, mi rrori ng relationship. We are partici- pants in t he initiating and maintaining of t he cultural natures of t he kinds of things of which being a bachelor is a prime example; these are cultural kinds. In contrast, we have no such "insider" relation to t he natures of natural kinds. The inarticulate Greek atomists were on t he right track about gold. In a way, t he Platonists woul d have been on t he right track if they had t urned their atten- tion to transparent t erms like "bachelor"; they woul d have had, however, to focus attention, not on rational intuition of Forms in which supposedly every sort of Defining Art: Int ensi on and Extension Notes I wish to thank Suzanne Cunningham and Ruth Marcus for reading and commenting on earlier versions of this chapter. 1 In ancient Greek times perhaps this would have been called efficient causality. 2 In ancient Greek times this might have been called formal causality. 3 This approach is derived from the well-known work of Saul Kripke and Hilary Putnam. 4 For a discussion of cultural-kind and natural-kind theories of art, see Dickie (1997a: 25-8). 5 The distinction between the exhibited and non-exhibited features of works of art was first made and used by Maurice Mandelbaum (1965). References Beardsley, M. (1979). "In Defense of Aesthetic Value." In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association. Newark, DE: American Philosophical Association. (1983). "Redefining Art." In M. J. Wreen and D. M. Callen (eds), The Aesthetic Point of View: Selected Essays. Cornell University Press. Carney, J. (1975). "Defining Art." British Journal of Aesthetics, 15: 191-206. (1982). "A Kripkean Approach to Aesthetic Theories." British Journal ofAesthetics 22: 150-7. Carroll, N. (1993). "Essence, Expression, and History." In Rollins (1993): 79-106. (ed.) (2000). Theories of Art Today. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Dickie, G. (1993). "An Artistic Misunderstanding." Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 51: 69-71. (1993). "Tale of Two Artworlds." In Rollins (1993): 76-7. (1997a). "Art: Function or Procedure - Nature or Culture?" Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 55: 25-8. (1997b). The Art Circle. Evanston: Chicago Spectrum Press. Originally pub. 1984. Dutton, D. (2000). "But They Don' t Have Our Concept of Art." In Carroll (2000): 217-38. Kivy, P. (1979). "Aesthetic Concepts: Some Fresh Considerations." Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 37: 423-32. Leddy, T. (1987). "Rigid Designation in Defining Art." Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 45: 263-72. 61 t hi ng participates, but on t he underst andi ng of our participation in cultural prac- tices that are involved with transparent t erms. The cultural t erm "work of art" is, I believe, like t he cultural t erm "bachelor" and not like t he physical t erm "gold. " There is an intimate cultural connect i on between "work of art" and t he nat ure of a work of art t hat our cultural ant hro- pologists can discover such t hat that nat ure can be converted into a definition of "work of art." I hope it will be discovered that t he definition is my institutional one.
[Cultural and Historical Perspectives On Science education] Susan A. Kirch, Michele Amoroso (auth.) - Being and Becoming Scientists Today_ Reconstructing Assumptions about Science and Science Education to Reclaim a .pdf