The Methodological Dimension of Antisth PDF
The Methodological Dimension of Antisth PDF
The Methodological Dimension of Antisth PDF
Claudia Mársico
The tradition that emerged in the context of the Homeric saga was
an important factor in the intergenerational transmission of knowl-
edge and it occupied a curious place in ancient philosophical dis-
course. Homer called Odysseus πολύτροπος at the beginning of his
work about the return of the hero to Ithaca. This line triggered a long
dispute whether this epithet was critical or laudatory. Alongside with
this, in Iliad (IX,313) Achilles condemned “polytropic” utterances
and advocated for a language without delusions. Later on, Antis-
thenes took part in the discussion on this issue and devoted great
efforts to homeric literary criticism. Plato also made an explicit judg-
ment on that point in the Hippias Minor and addressed this issue in
the Ion and Republic, if only his works of the first and second peri-
ods are taken into account. Intrasocratic discussions reveal persistent
concerns about this matter which suggest disagreements between
different lines which were close in their origin but remote because
of their dissimilar foundations and methods. First, I will consider the
central points of antisthenic position about the relationship between
methodology and the works of Homer. Afterwards, I will examine
the traces of dialogical tension between Antisthenes and Plato in
works such as Hippias Minor, Ion and Republic within the frame-
work of homeric literary criticism in order to examine its scope and
limits.
226
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
227
Claudia Mársico
228
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
horizon of οἰκεῖος λόγος implies that there is an ὄνομα for each thing
(or class of things), so that language not only shows reality but lies
on an unambiguous correlation with reality. Therefore in a case of
polysemy, while Prodicus tried to restore the pattern one name-one
thing, Antisthenes considered linguistic polysemy as a fact that does
not require any action. It was necessary just to determine the field
of application of the word, i.e. the χρῆσις ὀνομάτων, through lex-
ematic analysis, and this will show that language has a complete and
organized structure, so that a name actually belongs to each thing.
It is worth noting that this approach can be compared with that of
Trier, which holds that lexical meanings are a “mosaic” without gaps
or overlaps, where each unit can only belong to a field.4 Language
is a kind of “assemblage” of lexical units, so that each thing has its
own name. The modern concept of semantic field is a useful element
to think about the position of Antisthenes. Its origins date back to the
nineteenth century, although its central development corresponds to
the twentieth century, through the works on associative relations by
Saussure and Bally.5 The notion of Begriffsfeld postulated by G. Ip-
sen in his Der Alte Orient und Indogermanen6 prompted the studies
in this area. Among these studies the proposals of Trier, Pottier and
Coseriu are relevant. Coseriu defines “semantic field” as a lexical
paradigm which emerges from the division of a continuum of lexical
content in different words, among which an opposition is created by
means of distinctive features of content.7
The importance of this notion goes beyond linguistics, because
lexematic groups are linked to “semantic microuniverses” that play
a role in many areas of philosophy.8 So, it is not necessary to fall into
229
Claudia Mársico
230
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
231
Claudia Mársico
10 About this passage and the relationship with Antisthenes and Pythag-
oreanism, see C. Riedweg (Pythagoras: Leben, Lehre, Nachwirkung; eine
Einführung, p. 27), L. Zhmud (Pythagoras and the Early Pythagoreans,
p. 46ss.) and especially P. Horky (Plato and Pythagoreanism, pp. 88–89).
232
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
233
Claudia Mársico
234
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
235
Claudia Mársico
236
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
pp. 369–75). See also D. Tarrant (On the Hippias Major) and G. Grube (On
the Authenticity of the Hippias Maior) and the revitalization of the theme in
Ch. Kahn (The Beautiful and the Genuine, pp. 261–287).
17 See these traditional positions in Schleiermacher (Platons Werke, II,
pp. 296–296, and V, pp. 399–403; F. Ast (Platons Leben und Schriften, pp.
457–464); G. Stallbaum (Platonis Opera Omnia, IV, pp. 145–150, and 227–
235); J. Socher (Ueber Platons Schriften, p. 144 and 215) and G. Burges (The
Works of Plato).
18 See A. Winckelmann et al. (Platonis Opera Omnia, VI, p. 1).
19 On this last issue, see G. Romeyer-Dherbey (Les deux discours de
la guerre d’Antisthène) and V. Suvak, in this volume.
237
Claudia Mársico
238
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
239
Claudia Mársico
two people and hiding himself behind that split, or surrounding his
partner with the same thesis presented in multiple ways in order to
force him to accept all the corrollaries.
This comparison, which could even be deepened, indicates that
Plato and Antisthenes are facing and issue that divided the Socratic
circle. Hippias Minor is not, certainly, a direct answer to Antisthenes,
although this hypothesis has been raised. Antisthenes said that Hom-
er did not consider Odysseus a liar, but Platonic Hippias states the
opposite. Instead of choosing either hermeneutic approach, it can be
said that both works are part of a larger group of texts which have
these issues as a central topic but were not well preserved. From
the Platonic perspective, the whole antisthenic approach is worthy
of suspicion. Indeed, in the Hippias Minor Plato examines the issue
of πολυτροπία as a starting point to challenge the use of traditional
poetic elements as in the guise of a material suitable to apply his
philosophical methodologies. In this framework, the character Hip-
pias could have taken any other basis, even ordinary conversation, to
apply his approach. He should have done so, since his fragmentary
appeal to tradition obscures the real mechanism that governs philo-
sophical reflection.
The criticism of this kind of approach is that intellectual posi-
tions, such as Antisthenes’ view, which are based on these devel-
opments, would be condemned insofar as they look at phaenomena
through the deforming crystals of the texts of Homer. Hippias Minor
shows the advantage of abandoning those limits. This can be inter-
preted as the main point in 365c–d, where Socrates states that he is
talking to Hippias and not to Homer, because it is impossible to know
what he was strictly thinking when he composed a given verse. So,
Homeric criticism is not a reliable method. The “theoretical wander-
ing” advocated in this platonic dialogue is a legitimate way of seek-
ing knowledge in unknown lands, unlike the mechanical repetition
of traditional topics manipulated like puzzle pieces to make them say
what an author chooses.
240
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
241
Claudia Mársico
242
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
the criterion to infer Forms and in the choice of the bed as example.
The passage X,596a is the only one which reduces Forms to univer-
sals: “we establish a Form for each multiplicity of things to which
we give the same name”. Only this passage argues that Forms were
made by a divinity and suggests there is no difficulty in grasping
the eidetic level, since it is available in language. At the same time,
the bed is an artifact, which according to the testimony of Aristotle
has a problematic status among platonic philosophers.29 This scheme
even seems at times to suggest most extravagant shapes, like the
Form of shoemaker that has been inferred from X,598b. Let us note
briefly that the strangeness on this passage and its problematic choice
of the bed as example can hide an intertextual link with Antisthenes.
Antisthenes’ methodology involved homeric criticism and therefore
a positive epistemic evaluation of poetry. Poetry is plainly the origin
of knowledge. Furthermore, ἐπίσκεψις ὀνομάτων involves the thesis
of οἰκεῖος λόγος or οἰκεῖον ὄνομα, a name for each type of thing,
which clearly reminds this allusion to universals.
The characterization of the theory of Forms through the exam-
ple of the bed, a man-made object that it is far from having the
traits of typical instances of Plato’s middle dialogues, creates the
feeling that in these passages there is something strange. The solu-
tion which claims that we are facing a formidable lapsus of Plato
coexists with varied ways of making sense of the passage, some of
them with high degree of plausibility. The proposal Stählin stated in
1901, in order to fill out Dummler suggestions can be added to the
many puzzles which the text itself combines.30 In this perspective,
Antisthenes would have argued that poetic knowledge is the copy
of individuals, which is the only reality according to his corporeist
model. On this basis, Plato would have taken this view and inserted
it into a scheme where individuals are themselves copies of an in-
stance of greater reality. With this, he would be saying that the whole
243
Claudia Mársico
244
VI. The methodological dimension of antisthenic philosophy
245