Frederick Schauer - Formalism
Frederick Schauer - Formalism
Frederick Schauer - Formalism
Formalism
Author(s): Frederick Schauer
Source: The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 97, No. 4 (Mar., 1988), pp. 509-548
Published by: The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc.
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/796369 .
Accessed: 09/09/2014 02:21
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The Yale Law Journal.
http://www.jstor.org
Article
Formalism
Frederick Schauer*
Legal decisions and theories are frequently condemned as formalistic, yet little
* *
discussion has occurred regarding exactly what the term formalism* means.
In this Article, Professor Schauer examines divergent uses ofthe term to eluci-
date its descriptive content. Conceptions of formalism, he argues, involve the
notion that rules constrict the choice of the decisionmaker. Our aversion to
formalism stems from denial that the language of rules either can or should
constrict choice in this way. Yet Professor Schauer argues that this aversion to
formalism should be rethought: At times language both can and should re?
strict decisionmakers. Consequently, the term "formalistic" should not be used
as a blanket condemnation of a decisionmaking process; instead the debate
regarding decision according to rules should be confronted on its own terms.
* Professorof Law,
University of Michigan. I am grateful to audiences at Brooklyn Law School,
Cornell Law School, DePaul University College of Law, Duke University School of Law, Indiana
University at Bloomington School of Law, New York University School of Law, and the American
Political Science Association for helping me to clarify some of my good ideas and jettison some of my
bad ones. I am also indebtedto Alex Aleinikoff, Bruce Frier, Leo Katz, James Krier, William Miller,
and Richard Pildes for commenting on earlier versions of this article with just the right blend of
hostility and sympathy.
509
formalistic, except that whatever formalism is, it is not good.1 Few judges
or scholars would describe themselves as formalists, for a congratulatory
use of the word "formal" seems almost a linguistic error. Indeed, the pejo-
rative connotations of the word "formalism," in concert with the lack of
agreement on the word's descriptive content, make it tempting to conclude
that "formalist" is the adjective used to describe any judicial decision, style
of legal thinking, or legal theory with which the user of the term
disagrees.
Yet this temptation should be resisted. There does seem to be descrip?
tive content in the notion of formalism, even if there are widely divergent
uses of the term. At the heart of the word "formalism," in many of its
numerous uses, lies the concept of decisionmaking according to rule. For?
malism is the way in which rules achieve their "ruleness" precisely by
doing what is supposed to be the failing of formalism: screening off from a
decisionmaker factors that a sensitive decisionmaker would otherwise take
into account.
Moreover, it appears that this screening off takes place
largely through the force of the language in which rules are written. Thus
the tasks performed by rules are tasks for which the primary tool is the
specific linguistic formulation of a rule. As a result, insofar as formalism
is frequently condemned as excessive reliance on the language of a rule, it
is the very idea of decisionmaking by rule that is being condemned, either
as a description of how decisionmaking can take place or as a prescription
for how decisionmaking should take place.
Once we disentangle and examine the various strands of formalism and
recognize the way in which formalism, rules, and language are concep-
tually intertwined, it turns out that there is something, indeed much, to be
said for decision according to rule?and therefore for formalism. I do not
argue that formalism is always good or that legal systems ought often or
1. See, e.g., H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 124-30 (1961) (formalism as refusal to ac?
knowledgenecessityof choice in penumbralarea of rules); M. Horwitz, The Transformation of
American Law 254 (1977) (formalism as refusal to recognize instrumental functions of law); K.
Llewellyn, Jurisprudence: Realism in Theory and Practice 183-88 (1962) (formalism as
excessive reliance on canonicallywritten language of rules); R. Unger, The Critical Legal Stud?
ies Movement 1-2 (1986) (formalism as constrainedand comparativelyapolitical decisionmaking);
Kennedy,Legal Formality, 2 J. Legal Stud. 351, 355 (1973) (formalismas view that rule applica?
tion is mechanical and that mechanical rule application is just); Strauss, Formal and Functional
Approaches to Separation-of-Powers Questions?A Foolish Inconsistency?, 72 Cornell L. Rev.
488, 489 (1987) (formalism as refusal to acknowledge practical consequences of judicial decisions);
Tushnet, Anti-Formalismin Recent Constitutional Theory,83 Mich. L. Rev. 1502, 1506-07 (1985)
(formalism as artificial narrowing of range of interpretivechoices).
One can avoid the confusion of multiple usage by simply stipulating a meaning for the term "for?
malism." See, e.g., Posner, Legal Formalism, Legal Realism, and the Interpretation of Statutes and
the Constitution, 37 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 179, 181-82 (1986). This tack, however, evades most of
the interesting problems. Having stipulated that "formalism" means deductive logical reasoning,
Judge Posner proceeds easily to the conclusion that formalist reasoning has no application to the
interpretationof canonical texts. That conclusion, however, follows, if at all, only from the narrow-
ness of the stipulated definition. By not stipulating a meaning in advance of the analysis, I intend to
focus on a broaderrange of issues. In the process, I will explore the way in which deduction,even in
Posner's sense, may be related to the interpretationof canonical texts. See infra note 48.
2. 198 U.S. 45 (1905). For condemnationsof Lochner (and the era of which it is taken to be
archetypal) as formalistic, see Gordon, Critical Legal Histories, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 57, 99 (1984);
Peller, The Metaphysicsof American Law, 73 Calif. L. Rev. 1151, 1193, 1200-01 (1985); Seidman,
Public Principle and Private Choice: The Uneasy Case for a Boundary Maintenance Theory of
Constitutional Law, 96 Yale L.J. 1006, 1006-07 (1987); Developments in the Law?Immigration
Policy and the Rights of Aliens, 96 Harv. L. Rev. 1286, 1292 (1983); Note, The Constitutionalityof
Rent Control Restrictions on Property Owners*Dominion Interests, 100 Harv. L. Rev. 1067, 1077
(1987); Note, Formalism, Legal Realism, and Constitutionally Protected Privacy Under the Fourth
and Fifth Amendments,90 Harv. L. Rev. 945, 951 (1977); Powers, Book Review, 1985 Duke L.J.
221, 232; Rotenberg,Politics, Personality and Judging: The Lessons of Brandeis and Frankfurter
on Judicial Restraint (Book Review), 83 Colum. L. Rev. 1863, 1875 n.60 (1983).
3. 198 U.S. at 53.
4. Id.
5. Id. at 56.
know that such a choice is open, but treats the choice as no more available
than the choice to treat a pelican as other than a bird, is charged with
formalism for treating as definitionally inexorable that which involves
nondefinitional, substantive choices.9
Lochner is merely one example in which a false assertion of inexorabil-
ity is decried as formalistic. Much contemporary criticism of Blackstone,
Langdell, and others of their persuasion attacks their jurisprudence on
similar grounds.10 They stand accused of presenting contestable applica?
tions of general terms as definitionally incorporated within the meaning of
the general term. It is important, however, to understand the relationship
between the linguistic and the ontological questions for those of Black-
stone's vision. Blackstone's view that certain abstract definitionally terms
incorporate a wide range of specific results is tied intimately to his percep?
tion of a hard and suprahuman reality behind these general terms. If the
word "property," for example, actually describes some underlying and
noncontingent reality, then it follows easily specific embodi-
that certain
ments are necessarily part of that reality, just as pelicans are part of the
underlying reality that is the universe of birds. These instantiations might
still followeven if the general term is not a natural kind whose existence
and demarcation is beyond the control of human actors. There is nothing
natural or noncontingent about the term "basketball," but it is neverthe?
less an error in this culture at this time to apply that word to a group of
people hitting small hard balls with one of a collection of fourteen differ?
ent sticks. Still, linguistic clarity and rigidity are both facilitated insofar as
the words track the natural kinds of the world. To the extent that Black?
stone and others believed that
categories like liberty, property, and con?
tract were natural kinds ratherthan human artifacts, they were less likely
to perceive the choices we would now not think to deny. When one be?
lieves that a general term reflects a deep reality beyond the power of
human actors, the view that certain particulars are necessarily part of that
reality follows with special ease.
Thus, one view of the vice of formalism takes that vice to be one of
deception, either of oneself or of others. To disguise a choice in the lan-
17. No. S197-86-WrC (Vt. July 28, 1986). The following account of the case is drawn from
Judge Cheever's brief opinion, the pleadings, news accounts in the Rutland Herald of July 22, 23,
24 and 26, 1986, and a conversationwith Marilyn Signe Skoglund,Assistant Attorney General in the
Office of the Attorney General, State of Vermont.
18. Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 17, ? 2356 (1982).
19. Id.
20. Rutland Herald, July 23, 1986, at 5, col. 4.
21. The petition is unclear as to whether Hunter was seeking the extraordinarylegal remedy of
mandamus or a mandatory injunction in equity.
the statute should prevail, mere citation of the statute as inexorably dictat-
ing the result would conceal from the litigants and from society the actual
determinative factors. Insofar as we expect the reasons for a decision to be
open (and that, after all, is usually the reason judges write
for inspection
opinions),24 failure
to acknowledge that a choice was made can be criti?
cized because knowing how the choice was made helps to make legitimate
the products of the system.
24. Although it is generally accepted that judges should write opinions explaining their actual
reasons for decision, see, e.g., Shapiro, In Defense of Judicial Candor, 100 Harv. L. Rev. 731
(1987), some scholars have suggested that there may be reasons to avoid a candid explanation of the
reasoning process.See sources cited id. at 731 n.4. Thus an opinion might be equated with a statute,
whose message legitimatelymay depart from a reflectionof the processthat generatedit. While recog?
nizing that reasons going to the symbolic, guiding, and persuasive function of opinions may urge
against candid explanation of the decision process, I address here only opinions in which honesty is
deemed appropriate.
25. See, e.g., California Fed. Sav. & Loan Ass'n v. Guerra, 107 S. Ct. 683, 691 (1987); United
Steelworkersv. Weber, 443 U.S. 193, 201 (1979).
26. See, e.g., Keystone Bituminous Coal Ass'n v. DeBenedictis, 107 S. Ct. 1232, 1251 (1987).
27. See, e.g., Monaco v. Mississippi, 292 U.S. 313, 329-30 (1934); Hans v. Louisiana, 134 U.S.
1, 10-11 (1890).
28. Heydon's Case, 76 Eng. Rep. 637 (Ex. 1584), phrases the rule as deriving from original
legislative intent. See infra note 68. However, limitation of the purpose of a rule to the intent of the
legislature that passed it unnecessarilyrestrictsthe meaning of the term "purpose." Purpose gleaned
from the words of a rule itself should not be confusedwith the psychologicalintentions of the drafters.
Consider a rule which specifically excludes from a park children, radios, musical instruments, dogs
but not eats, and cars and trucks but not bicycles. One might conclude from reading this rule that its
purpose is to prevent noise. Even if the drafters of the rule intended to promote safety rather than
prevent noise, their psychologicalintentions would not negate this reading of purpose from the rule's
words themselves,any more than a person, having said "stop," could deny the import of that phrase
because she in fact meant "go."
29. See Singer, supra note 13, at 17-18. The most "locally" applicable rule (or statute) is that
which most narrowly pertains to the situation at hand. "Dogs should be leashed" is, in a case involv?
ing a dog, more locally applicable than "animals should be restrained." Similarly, "beneficiaries
named by the testator are to inherit accordingto the will" is more locally applicable than "no person
should benefit by his own wrong." The idea of local applicability distinguishes the rules in each of
these pairs, for in each pair both rules might apply to the same situation. Local applicabilitycaptures
our intuition that a more specifically applicable rule is somehow more applicable than a less specifi?
cally applicable, but still applicable, rule.
30. See, e.g., Brenner v. Smullian, 84 So. 2d 44 (Fla. 1955) (unclean hands); Gorham v. Sayles,
23 R.I. 449, 50 A. 848 (1901) (laches).
31. See, e.g., Rozell v. Vansyckle, 11 Wash. 79, 39 Pac. 270 (1895). Riggs v. Palmer, 115 N.Y.
506, 22 N.E. 188 (1889), made famous in R. Dworkin, Law's Empire 15-20 (1986) [hereinafter
Law's Empire] and R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 23 (1977) [hereinafter Taking
Rights Seriously], presents a similar issue. Riggs is significant because the most locally applicable
legal rule, the relevantstatute of wills, would allow the murderingheir to inherit. Only the imposition
of the less locally applicable general principle that no person should profit from his own wrong al?
lowed the court to avoid the result indicated by the most directly applicable legal norm. From the
perspectiveof the result dictated by the most immediately applicable legal rule, Riggs is not a hard
case, but an easy one. UnderstandingDworkin's enterprise requires an understandingof his attempt
to explain the ways in which the result "easily" dictatedby the most locally applicable rule frequently
yields to less locally applicable legal and nonlegal norms. See Schauer, TheJurisprudence of Reasons
(Book Review), 85 Mich. L. Rev. 847 (1987).
32. See generally Gutteridge,Abuse of Rights, 5 Cambridge L.J. 22 (1935) (discussing possibil?
ity of incorporatingprinciple forbiddingexercise of legal rights for purposes of malevolence).
33. See Singer, supra note 13, at 17-18.
34. Use of precedentis not as simple as I make it out to be here, but these subtleties of preceden?
tial reasoning need not detain us here. For a discussion of precedent, see Schauer, Precedent, 39
Stan. L. Rev. 571 (1987).
35. See Law's Empire, supra note 31; Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 31. See also
discussion of Dworkin, supra note 31.
36. See especially Llewellyn, Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or
Canons About How Statutes Are To Be Construed, 3 Vand. L. Rev. 395 (1950).
37. Whether a system allows judges to create norms of rule avoidancewhere none exist, whether
judges in fact create such norms, and whether a sufficient stock of rule-avoidingnorms exists such that
judges need only apply them are all unavoidablyempirical questions. See Kennedy, Toward a Critical
PhenomenologyofJudging, 36 J. Legal Educ. 518, 547-48, 562 (1986); see also Trubek, Where the
Action Is: Critical Legal Studies and Empiricism, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 575 (1984). There is no reason,
of course, to presume that the answers to these empirical questions will remain consistent across all
decisional domains within a legal system. For example, no logical necessity dictates that the stock of
rule avoidancenorms applicable to administrativedeterminationof individual social security claims be
identical to that applicable to Supreme Court adjudicationof constitutionalquestions.
38. There need not be any conceptual inconsistencybetween the two models. The second can be
conceivedof as the end product of the first.
39. I need not consider here which factors the judge actually used to reach a conclusion, for I am
not trying to catalog the considerationscomprisingan ideal decisionmaker'stotally particularizeddeci?
sionmaking process. Instead, I seek merely to distinguish the concept of a complete array of factors
that any particularizingdecisionmakerwould take into account, regardlessof the source of the partic-
ularizing norms, from the more limited array of factors available to a decisionmakerinhibited by
rules.
40. I assume here a distinctionbetween internal and external constraint.A host of factorsdefining
what I am and how I got that way constrain me from appearing unclothed in a football game at
Michigan Stadium. Some of these are internal constraints?the factors that shape my very existence.
These internal constraints may be psychological,ideological, or economic, but all shape what I am
internally up to the moment of decision to appear clothed rather than naked at the football game.
Even if I could overcomethese internal constraints,however, external ones, such as social disapproval
and a formal rule against such behavior, still might deter me from that action. Similarly, all sorts of
internal factors influence the decision a judge might reach about the optimal result in this case. But
these influences are distinguishablefrom external constraints, such as rules, that come from outside
the judge's personal determinationof what should be done.
Rules are only one possible example of external constraints. A decisionmakeralso may believe
herself to be externally constrainedby statutorypurpose. As I will demonstratebelow, however, see
infra text accompanyingnotes 77-79, statutory purpose is an external constraint when, and only
when, it operates as a rule in the sense central to my argument. That is, purpose is an external
constraintonly when someformulation of that purpose, on paper or in the mind, operates in substan?
tially the same way that a canonically formulated rule operates.
41. I explore this issue in depth below. See infra Section II-C.
42. For an example of this common use of the term "formalism,"see Levinson, What Do Lawyers
Know (and What Do TheyDo with Their Knowledge)?Commentson Schauer and Moore, 58 S. Cal.
L. Rev. 441, 445 (1985) (erroneouslyconcludingthat Schauer "is much too sophisticateda theorist to
endorse . . . linguistic formalism").This usage of the term "formalism"parallels that of other disci?
plines. See, e.g., Michaels, Against Formalism: The Autonomous Text in Legal and Literary Inter-
49. For an important defense of this variety of formalism, see Weinrib, Legal Formalism, 97
Yale L.J. (forthcoming 1988).
50. My point here parallels Dworkin's notion of "fit." As Dworkin illustrates the point, the de?
terminationwhether the existence of a homosexual relationshipbetween David and Steerforthbest fits
David Copperfieldis by no means mechanical,but its resolutiontakes place largely within the bound?
aries of the novel. Dworkin, No Right Answer?, in Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Hon?
our of H.L.A. Hart 58 (P. Hacker & J. Raz eds. 1977). A slightly different version of this article
appears under the same title in 53 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1 (1978) and as Is There Really No Right Answer
in Hard Cases?, in R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle 119 (1985). In a later work, Law's
Empire, supra note 31, Dworkin broadens the systemic boundaries with which he is concerned to
encompassthose norms commonly understoodas legal, political, and moral. The expansion of these
boundariesis a separateissue, however;one could agree with Dworkin that it is possible to look for fit
within a domain while disputing the size of the relevant domain.
51. The mechanical aspects of formalism are stressed in the important discussion in Kennedy,
supra note 1. The concept of formalismas not necessarilymechanicalbut involving significant limita?
tions on otherwise eligible results is the focus of Tushnet, supra note 1. See also, Grey, The Constitu?
tion as Scripture, 37 Stan. L. Rev. 1, 4 n.8 (1984) (distinguishing between "operative" textual
norms that guide decisions themselves and "non-operative"textual norms that tell decisionmakersto
use decisive norms outside text).
pacity of those who make decisions to abide by these constraints. But let
us turn first to the conceptual question.
Is it possible for written norms to limit the factors that a decisionmaker
considers? At first glance, the answer to this
question seems to be "no."
Language is both artificial and contingent and therefore appears insuffi-
ciently rigid to limit the choices of the human actors who have created it.
The word ucat," for example, could have been used to refer to canines,
and the English language could have followed the language of the Es?
kimos in having several different words to describe the varieties of snow.
Yet this answer confuses the
long-term mobility language of with its
short-term plasticity, and is a conclusion comparable to taking the ponder-
ous progress of a glacier as indicating that it will move if we put our
shoulders against it and push. Of course language is a human
creation,
and of course the rules
of language are contingent, in the sense that they
could have been different. It is also beyond controversy that the rules of
language reflect a range of political, social, and cultural factors that are
hardly a priori. But this artificiality and does not deny the
contingency
short-term, or even intermediate-term, noncontingency of meaning. If I go
to a hardware store and
request a hammer, the clerk who hands me a
screwdriver has made
a mistake, even though it is artificial, contingent,
and possibly temporary that the word "hammer" represents hammers and
not screwdrivers. Similarly, a rule requiring candidates to file nominating
petitions at a certain place by a certain time on a certain day is violated by
filing in the wrong place or after the specified time. Whatever the real
judge did say in Hunter v. Norman, and whatever some judge might have
said in any of my hypothetical variants, none of them would be that
Hunter, in filing at 5:03 p.m., had filed at or before
p.m. 5:00
The questions about
the possibility of linguistic constraint can be clari-
fied by considering again the rule prohibiting vehicles in the park. But
now let us turn from its peripheral applications to the central applica?
tions?whether cars and
trucks are excluded. Hart assumed that,
whatever else the rule did, it excluded cars and trucks. This was the rule's
ucore" of settled meaning and application.52 Against this, Fuller offered
the example of a statue of a truck erected as a war memorial by a group
of patriotic citizens. According to Fuller, the example challenges the idea
that a rule will have a settled core of meaning which can be applied with?
out looking at the rule's purpose. Fuller argues that it cannot be deter?
mined whether the truck, which is a perfectly functional vehicle, fails into
the rule's periphery or core unless one considers the purpose of the rule.53
Fuller's challenge is ambiguous, however; there are three variant interpre-
54. Fuller's example and other illustrations of seemingly absurd results generated by applying a
rule without attention to the circumstancesof its creationfigure prominentlyin criticismof formalism.
See, e.g., Moore, A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation, 58 S. Cal. L. Rev. 277, 386-88 (1985);
H. Hart & A. Sacks, The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of Law
1148-78 (tentative ed. 1958) (unpublished manuscript);see also Dworkin's use of Riggs v. Palmer,
supra note 31.
55. This use of the term "necessarily"to describe the essential features of anything properly
called a legal system would be consistent with the general tenor of Fuller's jurisprudence. See L.
Fuller, The Morality of Law (1964); R. Summers, Lon L. Fuller 27-31, 36-40 (1984).
56. See, e.g., Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theoryand Local Social Thought, 133
U. Pa. L. Rev. 685, 708-13 (1985) [hereinafterThe Politics of Reason] (arguing that words do not
mistaken view of the nature of language. Fuller and his followers fail to
distinguish the possibility and existence of meaning from the best or ful-
lest meaning that might be gleaned from a given communicative context.
In conversation, I am assisted in determining what a speaker intends for
me to understand by a number of contextual cues, including inflection,
pitch, modulation, and body language, as well as by the circumstances
surrounding the conversation. That such contextual cues assist my under?
standing, however, does not imply that the words, sentences, and
paragraphs used by the speaker have no meaning without those cues. The
uno vehicles in the park" rule clearly points to the exclusion of the statue
from the park even if we believe that the exclusion is unnecessary from
the point of view of the statute's purpose.
If I come across an Australian newspaper from 1827, I can read it
because I understand, acontextually, the meaning of most of the words
and sentences in that newspaper, even though with better historical un?
derstanding I might understand more of what was written by a colony of
transported English convicts. This example does not demonstrate that lan?
guage is unchanging, nor that language can be perfectly understood with?
out attention to context, but rather that some number of linguistic conven?
tions, or rules of language, are known and shared by all people having
competence in the English language. Linguistic competence in a given lan?
guage involves understanding some number of rules also understood by
others who are linguistically competent in the same
language. When indi?
viduals understand the same rules, they convey meaning by language con-
forming to those rules.57 Members of the community of English speakers,
have essences or core meanings); Boyle, Thomas Hobbes and the Invented Tradition of Positivism:
Reflections on Language, Power, and Essentialism, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 383, 408-19 (1987) (dis?
cussing Hobbes' rejectionof notion of linguistic essences). In passing, I note my disagreementwith
those who describe as "post-Wittgensteinian"the view that meaning cannot be separated from the
particular context of a particular utterance. E.g., Boyle, The Politics of Reason, supra, at 708. A
footnotein a law review article is hardly the place to debate interpretationsof Wittgenstein, including
whether Wittgensteincan even plausibly be interpretedto support a pragmatist/particularisttheory of
meaning. Yet I would briefly note that a fair reading of Wittgenstein reveals that he argued that the
meaning of a word is a function of how that word is contingently used in an existing linguistic
community, but emphatically not a function of how the word is used on a particular occasion by a
particular member of that community.
It is crucial to recognizethe seductivequality of phrases like "post-Wittgensteinian,"which suggest
that if the reader acknowledgesWittgenstein'sgenius, then she must agree with the point describedin
those terms. It is better to discuss the point at issue without attempting to lean on the argumentative
props of associationswith philosopherswhose names are currentlyfashionablein legal circles. In light
of the still-raging disputes about the most foundational questions in the philosophy of language, to
substitute Wittgenstein'sname for an argument is unwarrantedeven if the use of his name is accu?
rate. When that use is mistaken or at the very least contested, the dangers of facile borrowing from
other disciplines are compounded.
This criticism of the presentationof Boyle's argument has no bearing on its underlying validity,
however. Although I disagree with much of what he and Fuller argue, those arguments raise central
questions about the nature of law which I believe should be confronteddirectly. Boyle's useful per?
spectives are ill-served by clothing them in what appears to me to be an idiosyncraticmisreading of
Wittgenstein.
57. For a particularlyinsightful and influential articulationof the view that meaning exists inde-
for example, possess shared understandings that enable them to talk to all
other members of the community.
Among the most remarkable features of language is its compositional
nature, i.e., the way in which we comprehend sentences we have never
heard before. We can do this because rules, unspecified and perhaps un-
specifiable, allow us to give meaning to certain marks and certain noises
without having to inspect the thought processes of the speaker or the full
context in which words appear. Words communicate meaning at least
partially independently of the speaker's intention. When the shells wash
up on the beach in the shape of C-A-T, I think of small house pets and
pendent of speaker's purpose or other related aspects of context, see J. Searle, Speech Acts: An
Essay in the Philosophy of Language 42-50 (1969). This view also seems to be the import of
paragraphs 489-512 of L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (G.E.M. Anscombe
trans. 3d ed. 1953). A similar interpretationof Wittgenstein, relying on different passages, is G.
Baker & P. Hacker, Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity 329-38 (1985). Indeed,
even those who are rightly concerned with the foundational rule-following questions posed by
Wittgenstein would not dispute that "communal language constitutes a network of determinate pat?
terns." Wright, Rule-Following, Objectivityand the Theory of Meaning, in Wittgenstein: To
Follow a Rule 99, 105 (S. Holtzman & C. Leich eds. 1981).
Interpretationsof Wittgenstein apart, acceptance of the possibility of literal meaning has passed
into the commonplaceof contemporaryanalytical philosophy of language, even while philosophers
hotly dispute the source or explanation of that phenomenon.See, e.g., W. Alston, Philosophy of
Language 74-75 (1964); M. Black, Meaning and Intention, in Caveats and Critiques: Philo?
sophical Essays in Language, Logic, and Art 109 (1975); S. Cavell, Aesthetic Problems of
Modern Philosophy, in Must We Mean What We Say? 73, 80-82 (1969); S. Cavell, Knowing
and Acknowledging,id. at 238, 248-49; D. Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpreta?
tion xix, 243-64 (1984); D. Holdcroft, Words and Deeds: Problems in the Theory of
Speech Acts 122-23 (1978); R. Martin, The Meaning of Language 217 (1987); M. Platts,
Ways of Meaning: An Introduction to a Philosophy of Language 130-32 (1979); I.
scheffler, beyond the letter: a philosophical inquiry into ambiguity, vagueness and
Metaphor in Language 81 (1979).
In one philosopher'swords:
It is a platitude?something only a philosopherwould dream of denying?that there are con?
ventions of language, although we do not find it easy to say what those conventionsare. If we
look for the fundamentaldifferencein verbal behaviorbetween membersof two linguistic com?
munities, we can be sure of finding something which is arbitrarybut perpetuatesitself because
of a common interest in coordination. In the case of conventions of language, that common
interest derives from our commoninterest in taking advantageof, and in preserving,our ability
to control others' beliefs and actions to some extent by means of sounds and marks. That
interest in turn derives from many miscellaneous desires we have; to list them, list the ways
you would be worse off in Babel.
D. Lewis, Languages and Language, in 1 Philosophical Papers 163, 166 (1983).
Obviously some tension exists between the way that language is discussed in analytic philosophy of
language and the way that it is discussedin other circles, including literary theory. Part of the differ?
ence between the terms of the debate in these two circles can be explained by the different extent to
which the two disciplines focus on "difficult" interpretations.This may also explain the extent to
which some branchesof legal theory, with their focus on difficult interpretationsin linguistically hard
cases, have been drawn to literary theory. Moreover, insofar as literature exists primarily to illumi-
nate, inspire, and transform, its very existence encourages attempts to pierce literal meaning. The
relationship between the enterprise at issue and the view of literal meaning adopted suggests an im?
portant question: Might the purposes of the legal enterprise be so different from those of interpreting
literature that literal meaning is no longer an obstacle but instead a tool? I have no answer to this
question, nor do I intend to offer a few easy citations to suggest a familiarity I do not possess. Never?
theless, the very differencesin focus between analytic philosophy of language and literary theory may
suggest that it is a bit too easy, for me or for those who draw on literary theory or other perspectives
on language, to assume that the applications of these perspectivesto law cannot take place without
some theoretical slippage.
speakers of English.
Given that the meaning of words may be acontextually derived from
our understandings of language, the central question becomes whether
guage. In other words, we must ask whether words have sufficient acon?
textual import so that communication can take
place among speakers of
English a
in suchway that at least a certain limited range of meaning, if
not one and only one meaning, will be shared by all or almost all speakers
of English. The answer to this question is clearly "yes." As with the shells
that washed up on the beach in the shape of C-A-T, words strung to?
although that meaning might depart from the purposes behind the rule or
from the richer understanding to be harvested from considering a wider
range of factors than the rule's words. That we might learn more from
considering additional factors or from more fully understanding a
speaker's intentions does not mean that we learn nothing by consulting the
language of rules themselves.
Of course, certain obvious, accessible, and by and large undisputable
features of rules distinguish the meaning we cull from them from our
interpretation of other types of communications. For example, when we
interpret a rule of law, we understand that it is a law and that it is to be
interpreted in light of surrounding language in the same law. In addition,
ordinary "lawspeak" (habeas corpus, certiorari, party, appeal) can be
viewed as a language for a subcommunity in the community of English
speakers, capable of doing within the subcommunity what ordinary lan?
guage does within the larger community of English speakers. Thus, al?
though all those reading a statute come to that task with certain shared
58. See J. Searle, Literal Meaning, in Expression and Meaning 117 (1979) (literal meaning
exists albeit only against a set of backgroundassumptions about contexts in which sentence could
appropriatelybe uttered);Moore, supra note 54, at 304-07 (arguing that minimal context allows and
is required for fixing referencesto singular terms).
59. Note that I am talking about language and about two different embellishmentson the main
theme of literal meaning. First, ordinary people within a given linguistic culture might share, as
linguistic conventions,knowledge about how to interpret the language of rules, including conventions
relating to the differencebetween normativeand descriptivelanguage and conventionstelling them to
interpretwords in light of surroundinglanguage in the same rule or statute. This suggests only that
all competent speakersof the language in which the text is written have access to a certain minimal
amount of noncontroversialinformation about what kind of text it is.
Second, literal meaning is not necessarily ordinary meaning, because linguistic conventions may
exist within a technicalor professionalsubcommunityof a larger community.For example, photogra-
phers may have a literal sense of the meaning of the term "burningin," physicians may have a literal
sense of the meaning of the term "Cushing's Syndrome,"and lawyers may have a literal sense of the
meaning of the term "assumpsit,"even though none of these are terms used at all or in the same way
by ordinary English speakers. This second embellishment, however, must be sharply distinguished
from other notions of "conventionalism"that build in much more than linguistic meaning. See, e.g., S.
Burton, An Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning (1985); Fiss, Conventionalism, 58 S.
Cal. L. Rev. 177 (1985); Fiss, Objectivityand Interpretation, 34 Stan. L. Rev. 739 (1982). The
conventionalistlegal literature talks merely about the conventionsof permissible legal argument and
does not confront the question of the relationship between the conventionsof permissible legal argu?
ment and the conventionsof literal meaning, whether ordinaryor technical. Thus, legal conventional?
ists such as Fiss avoid questions regardingwhether and why certain literal readings of legal rules are
or are not permissible arguments within the legal interpretive community. It is these questions, in
some sense more foundational,that concern me here, because my aim is to locate the particular per?
missible arguments in the legal interpretivecommunity, rather than merely to assert the existence of
permissible arguments.
60. Salomons v. Miller, 8 Ex. 778, 155 Eng. Rep. 1567 (1853); Miller v. Salomons, 7 Ex. 475,
155 Eng. Rep. 1036 (1852).
61. 46 U.S.C. ? 201 (1958), repealed by Pub. L. No. 98-89, 97 Stat. 600 (1983).
62. "When you come tomorrow, bring my football boots. Also, if humanly possible, Irish water
spaniel. Urgent. Regards. Tuppy."
"What do you make of that, Jeeves?"
"As I interpret the document,sir, Mr. Glossop wishes you, when you come tomorrow,to bring his
football boots. Also, if humanly possible, an Irish water spaniel. He hints that the matter is urgent,
and sends his regards."
"Yes, that's how I read it, too . . . ."
P.G. Woodehouse, The Ordeal of Young Tuppy, quoted in S. Blackburn, Spreading the Word:
Groundings in the Philosophy of Language 3 (1984).
63. See Aleinikoff, Constitutional Law in the Age of Balancing, 96 Yale L.J. 943, 985, 1004
(1987).
64. Noteworthy exceptions are J. Frank, Law and the Modern Mind (1930), and Kennedy,
supra note 37. However, legal scholarship still must systematically investigate the important issues
that Frank, Kennedy, and others have raised in an impressionisticway.
65. See D. Black, The Behavior of Law (1976); L. Friedman, The Legal System: A
Social Science Perspective (1975); Hogan & Henley, Nomotics: The Science of Human Rule
Systems,5 Law & Soc'y Rev. 135 (1970); Johnson, Law, Politics, and Judicial Decision Making:
Lower Federal Court Uses of Supreme Court Decisions, 21 Law & Soc'y Rev. 325 (1987);
Scandura,New Directionsfor Theoryand Research on Rule Learning, 28 Acta Psychologica 301
(1968).
66. There is somethingunrealistic about all of this, because it erroneouslyassumes that my para?
digm "easy" cases are representativeof the kinds of decisions that come before decisionmakers.They
are not, at least when we take "decisionmaker"in a somewhat narrow sense to refer to formal deci?
sionmakerssuch as judges sitting in courts of law. In most legal systems, various screening devices
ensure that cases at the center of decisionaldeterminacywill not enter the formal adjudicativeprocess.
The time and expense of litigation and the widespreadinclination to avoid futile battles are such that
decisionsat the core of settled meaning seldom confrontany formal decisionmakingprocess.See Priest,
Reexamining the Selection Hypothesis:Learning from Wittman's Mistakes, 14 J. Legal Stud. 215
(1985) (develops selection hypothesis to determine which cases are settled and which are litigated);
Priest and Klein, The Selection of Disputes for Litigation, 13 J. Legal Stud. 1 (1984) (presents
model to predict whether litigation will be resolved by suit or settlement).
This, however, is but a contingentfeature of modern legal systems. It is possible to imagine a legal
system closer to a sporting event, where umpires call "safe" or "out" on every play, or where officials
with red penalty flags in their back pockets patrol the social landscape, ready to throw the flag and
call "tort,"or "crime,"or "breachof etiquette" whenever there is a transgressionof the rules. Obvi?
ous logistical problemsprevent such a system from being a reality, but it is a useful Gedankenexperi-
ment for thinking about the innumerable instances in which rules are followed or clearly broken
without coming to the attention of the judicial system.
Many legal systems, unlike those with "roving umpires," operate largely in the area of linguistic
indeterminacy,generated either by vagueness of the governing norm or by open texture when previ?
ously clear norms confrontthe unexpected.And in some systems, such as that of the United States, the
likelihood of success is sufficient to make it worth litigating cases in which linguistic determinacy
produces a politically or morally uncomfortableresult. But that is exactly our question, because the
weight the system gives to literal meaning will determine the extent to which it is worth litigating
against literal meaning.
70. Note that the "No vehicles in the park" example may be a flawed illustration of the problem
Hart, Fuller, and I explore, because locomotive capacity may now be definitional of a "vehicle."
Insofar as this is true, the statue is not a vehicle, and no conflict arises between literal meaning and
purpose. This is a defect only in the example, however, rather than in the general formulationof the
issue. I will therefore stipulate, for the purposes of this argument, that a statue of a vehicle is a
vehicle, just as a lion in a cage is still a lion. Consider a rule prohibiting "live animals on the bus"
and whether it would prohibit carrying on the bus three live goldfish in a sealed plastic bag.
71. My point about the plasticity of purpose should not be confused with claims, often correct,
about the indeterminacyof purpose. See, e.g., Easterbrook,Foreword: The Court and the Economic
System, 98 Harv. L. Rev. 4, 15-18 (1984); Easterbrook,Statutes' Domains, 50 U. Chi. L. Rev.
533, 537-38 (1983); Kennedy, supra note 1; Posner, Statutory Interpretation?In the Classroom
and in the Courtroom, 50 U. Chi. L. Rev. 800, 819-820 (1983). Insofar as purpose becomes both
concreteand determinate,as when everyone agrees what the purpose is, the argumentthat "ruleness"
resides in purpose becomes more plausible. But when some conception of purpose is determinate,
noncanonicalpurpose itself can operate formalistically.Conversely, if purpose is comparativelyinde?
terminate, then it looks especially odd to say that the rule exists not in the specific rule-formulation,
but in the quite different and nonspecific purpose. Thus, those who argue for the indeterminacyof
purpose make claims consistent with mine.
72. L. Fuller, supra note 55, at 81-91; Fuller, supra note 53; Fuller, The Speluncean Explor-
ers, 62 Harv. L. Rev. 616, 620-26 (1949) ("opinion" of Foster, J.).
73. H. Hart & A. Sacks, supra note 54.
74. Law's Empire, supra note 31.
75. K. Llewellyn, supra note 1.
76. See Wellman, Dworkin and the Legal Process Tradition: The Legacy of Hart & Sacks, 29
Ariz. L. Rev. 413 (1987); Note, Intent, Clear Statements, and the Common Law: Statutory Con?
struction in the Supreme Court, 95 Harv. L. Rev. 892 (1982). Recent manifestationsof this para?
digm include G. Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of Statutes (1982); Eskridge, Dy?
namic StatutoryInterpretation, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1479 (1987); Langevoort,Statutory Obsolescence
and the Judicial Process: The Revisionist Role of the Courts in Federal Banking Regulation, 85
Mich. L. Rev. 672 (1987). But see, e.g., United States v. Locke, 471 U.S. 84 (1985) (failure to file
timely claim deprives petitioner of right, irrespectiveof statutory purpose).
won six gold medals in the Olympic Games is returning to this park, the
scene of her youth, along with a widely popular President of the United
States. Suppose as well that the park with the "no vehicles in the park"
is the only suitable place for the motorcade, which must be a
regulation
motorcade because the President is disabled and cannot walk. Under these
circumstances, the purpose behind the "no vehicles in the park" rule
would be served by excluding the motorcade, but the purpose behind that
Thus the same logic that requires the for?
purpose would be frustrated.
mulation of a rule to be defeasible in the service of its purpose would also
that purpose to be defeasible in the service of the purpose behind
require
it.
As the example reveals, the potential tension between the general goal
and its concretized instantiation exists at every level. At one level, the ten?
sion is between language and purpose; at the next, it is between that pur?
behind at the between the deep
pose and the deep purpose lying it; next,
and an even deeper purpose; and so on. When we decide that
purpose
must not be frustrated by its instantiation, we embark upon a
purpose
infinite in which all forms of concretization are
potentially regress
defeasible.
The view that rules should be interpreted to allow their purposes to
in fact collapses the distinction between a rule and a
trump their language
reason, and thus loses the very concept of a rule.77 Rules are by definition
known and unknown under
general. They gather numerous particulars
headings such as "vehicles," "punishment," "dogs," and "every person
who is directly or indirectly the beneficial owner of more than 10 per
centum of any class of any [registered] equity security (other than an ex-
empted security)." After identifying a category of items or events to which
the rule applies, in the protasis, rules then prescribe what shall be done
with these particulars in the apodosis7* Occasionally, however, not all of
the particulars comprising the rule's category of coverage are suitable for
the prescribed treatment; the generalizations that are a necessary part of
in a manner that be
any rule treat all members of the class may appropri?
ate only for most members of the class. What, then, is to happen when a
case arises in which the generalization does not apply to this particular?
When a rule's prescribed treatment is unsuitable, if the decisionmaker
77. Note, however, that this claim is not inconsistent with the view that rules should be inter?
preted to further their purposes when several interpretationsof the rule are possible and all are
supported by the language ofthe rule. In such cases, it is not only possible but positively desirableto
choose the interpretationthat will serve the rule's purpose. See H.L.A. Hart, Introduction, in Es?
says in Jurisprudence and Philosophy 1, 8 (1983).
78. On this terminologyfor the structureof rules, which distinguishesthe part of the rule specify-
ing its operative facts from the part describing the consequencesflowing from the existence of those
facts, see W. Twining & D. Miers, How To Do Things With Rules 136-40 (2d ed. 1982). See
also Friedman,Legal Rules and the Process of Social Change, 19 Stan. L. Rev. 786, 786-87 (1967)
(same distinction with different labels); Schlag, Rules and Standards, 33 UCLA L. Rev. 379,
381-83 (1985) (same).
79. This is not to say that rules are always or even ever good things to have. My aim now is to
distinguish a form of decisionmakingin which generalizations have independent normative power
from a form of decisionmakingin which the full richness of the particular event always is open to
consideration.The questions of whether rules should be employed, in which domains, and to what
extent, are addressedbelow. See infra Section III.
80. See Schauer, Authority and Indeterminacy, in Authority Revisited: NOMOS XXIX 28
(1987).
81. The closed system/open system dispute merely recasts the debate about legal positivism in
differentterminology.Any version of legal positivism is premised on what Ronald Dworkin, no posi?
tivist, has felicitously referred to as "pedigree."Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 31, at 17.
Positivism posits that legal norms are identified by reference to some other norm, rule, or standard
that distinguishes legal from non-legal norms. Hart's "rule of recognition" serves this purpose,
H.L.A. Hart, supra note 1, as does the "next higher norm" for Kelsen. H. Kelsen, The Pure
Theory of Law 193-278 (M. Knight trans. 1967). The positivist conceives of the set of norms so
pedigreedas constitutingsome sort of a closed system, although that system will not necessarilydecide
all or even most cases that come before the courts. Kelsen, for example, sees every law-applying act as
only partially determined by law. Id. at 233-36, 244-45. By contrast, the opponents of positivism,
most notably Dworkin, attack the pedigreeabilitythesis by arguing that in no case is the distinction
between pedigreed and nonpedigreednorms dispositive and consequently the characterizationof law
in terms of pedigreed norms is descriptivelyinaccurate.
account. Understanding the way in which rules truncate the range of rea?
sons available to a decisionmaker helps us to appreciate the distinction
between formalism and functionalism, or instrumentalism.82 Functional-
ism focuses on outcomes and particularly on the outcome the deci?
sionmaker deems optimal. Rules get in the way of this process, and thus
functionalism can be perceived as a view of decisionmaking that seeks to
minimize the space between what
a particular decisionmaker concludes,
all things considered, should be done and what some rule says should be
done. Rules block consideration of the full array of reasons that bear upon
a particular decision in two different ways. First, they exclude from con?
sideration reasons that might have been available had the decisionmaker
not been constrained by a rule. Second, the rule itself becomes a reason for
action, or a reason for decision.
The notion of a rule as a reason for decision requires further explora?
tion. What makes formalism formal is this very feature: the fact that tak?
ing rules seriously involves taking their mandates as reasons for decision
independent of the reasons for decision lying behind the rule.88 If it were
otherwise, the set of reasons considered by a decisionmaker would be con-
gruent with the set of reasons behind the rule, and the rule would add
nothing to the calculus. Rules therefore supply reasons for action qua
rules. When the reason supplied by a rule tracks the reasons behind the
rule, then the rule is in a different way superfluous in the particular case.
Rules become interesting when they point toward a different result than
do the reasons behind the rule?when they indicate, for example, that
statues of vehicles ought to be excluded eventhough the reasons behind
the rule indicate that the statues ought not to be excluded. To take these
occasionally perverse reasons as always relevant and therefore sometimes
dispositive is condemned as "formalistic" because it abstracts the mandates
of a rule from the reasons behind it. Yet that is what rules do. Refusal to
abstract the rule from its reasons is not to have rules. This refusal reduces
rules to rules
of thumb, useful but intrinsically unweighty indicators of
the results likely to be reached by direct application of reasons.
Thus, the essential equivalency of formalism and "ruleness" is before
us. Viewing formalism as merely rule-governed decisionmaking does not
make it desirable. Yet recognizing the way in which formalism is merely a
way of describing the process of taking rules seriously allows us to escape
82. See, e.g., R. Summers, Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory 136-75 (1982);
Aleinikoff, supra note 63, at 985; Summers, Professor Fuller's Jurisprudence and America's Domi?
nant Philosophy ofLaw, 92 Harv. L. Rev. 433 (1978).
83. Insofar as a system permits recourse to the purpose behind a rule's formulation but does not
permit departure from that purpose when adhering to it will produce unfortunate results or will
frustrate the even deeper purpose behind it, that system will still be formal in the sense I am now
using that term. It will also be rule-bound, because the less than totally plastic purpose (although
more plastic than the rule-formulation)will operate as a rule vis-a-vis the higher order reasons that
generated that particular purpose.
84. In a trivial sense, rules differ from their formulations.See, e.g., G. Baker & P. Hacker,
supra note 57, at 41-52; M. Black, The Analysis of Rules, in Models and Metaphors: Studies
in Language and Philosophy 95 (1962); D. Shwayder, The Stratification of Behaviour
241 (1965); G. von Wright, Practical Reason 68 (1983). "Do not walk on the grass," "Walking
on the grass is prohibited,"and "No walking on the grass" constituteone and not three rules. Refer?
ring to these three formulationsas formulationsof only one rule, however, presupposesthat all have
the same meaning, that the differencesare syntacticaland not semantic. Thus, the distinctionbetween
a rule and its formulationis like the distinctionbetween a propositionand a sentence. When I discuss
a rule and equate it with its formulation, I therefore mean that a rule is that set of semantically
equivalent rule formulations.
85. My referencesto "literalism"are slightly metaphorical.As noted above, see supra note 59,
literalismincludesthose aspects of context, such as the appearanceof words in a statute rather than in
a poem, that are accessible to all or most readers. Moreover, although I often use single words as
examples, statutes are not read word by word, but instead by sentences, paragraphs,and larger units
of text. This is not to deny, however, that the ability to assign meanings to individual words is what
enables us to understanda sentence we have never seen before. See D. Davidson, Truth and Mean?
ing, in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation 17 (1984). This assertion, however, superfi-
cially in conflict with Frege's assertion that only in the context of a sentence does a word have any
meaning, see G. Frege, The Foundations of Arithmetic (J.L. Austin trans. 1959), is not with?
out its detractorsand complexities. See, e.g., Wallace, Only in the Context of a Sentence Do Words
Have Any Meaning, in Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language 305 (P.
French, T. Uehling, Jr., & H. Wettstein eds. 1979).
Still, pace Fuller, supra note 53, at 662-63, sentences and paragraphs can have literal and even
acontextualmeaning insofar as an entire sentence or paragraphmay supply enough context to make
its meaning comparativelyclear. As texts become lengthier and richer it is often more possible to
understandthose texts without departingfrom them and thus more possible for them to have acontex?
tual meaning.
Moreover, literal meaning need not always be ordinary meaning. Where some aspect of the mini?
mal and uncontestedcontext makes it plain that a settled specializedor technical meaning of a term or
phrase applies, that technical meaning, rather than the ordinary usage of the man on the Clapham
omnibus, is controlling.
86. See generally A. Kocourek, An Introduction to the Science of Law 165-85 (1930);
R. Wasserstrom, The Judicial Decision: Toward a Theory of Legal Justification 60-66
(1961); Marsh, Principle and Discretion in theJudicial Process, 68 Law Q. Rev. 226 (1952). Along
with Wasserstrom,supra, at 61, I object to the use of the word "certainty"in this context because,
unlike the term "predictability,"it suggests that no doubt is involved.I can predictthat it will snow in
Vermont this winter and rely on that predictionin making winter plans, yet still not be certain that it
will snow. Although one usage of "certain"does recognize variability, I prefer the term "predictabil?
ity" because its common usage implies such variability.
that some item is a member of some category, little in the way of poten?
tially variable judgment clouds the prediction of whether the rule will ap?
ply to this particular item. This relates to the second factor: that the deci?
sionmakers in the system will perceive those particulars as being members
of the same category perceived by the addressees and will be seen as so
perceiving by those affected. That is, people perceive pelicans as birds;
decisionmakers perceive pelicans as birds; and people know that deci?
sionmakers will perceive pelicans as birds. Third, the rule must speak in
terms of an accessible category. Predictability requires that a rule cover a
category whose
denotation is substantially noncontroversial among the
class of addressees of the rule and common to the addressees of the rule
and thosewho apply it. Finally, the rule must treat all members of a
category in the same way. Only if the consequences specified in the apod-
osis of the rule are as accessible and noncontroversial as the coverage spec?
ified in the protasis can a rule produce significant predictability of appli?
cation. Thus, predictability comesfrom the knowledge that if this is a bird
a certain result will follow, and from the confidence that what I now per?
ceive to be a bird will be considered a bird by the ultimate decisionmaker.
This predictability comes at a price.87 Situations
only may arise in
which putting this particular that into
category seems just too
crude?something about this particular makes us desire to treat it spe-
cially. This vehicle is merely a statue, emits no fumes, makes no noise,
and endangers no lives; it ought to be treated differently from those vehi?
cles whose characteristics mesh with the purpose behind the rule. Serving
the goal of predictability, however, requires that we ignore this difference,
because to acknowledge this difference is also to create thepower?the
jurisdiction?to determine whether this vehicle or that vehicle actually
serves the purpose of the "no vehicles in the park" rule. It is the jurisdic?
tion to determine that only some vehicles fit the purpose of the rule that
undermines the confidence that all vehicles will be prohibited. No longer
is it the case that anything that is a vehicle, a moderately accessible cate?
gory, is excluded. Instead, the category is now that of vehicles whose pro?
hibition will serve the purposes of the "no vehicles in the park" rule, a
potentially far more controversial category.
Thus, the key to understanding the relationship of ruleness to predict?
ability is the idea of decisional jurisdiction.88 The issue is not whether the
statue serves the purpose of the "no vehicles in the park" rule. It is
whether giving some decisionmaker jurisdiction to determine what the
89. See Horwitz, The Rule ofLaw: An Unqualified Human Good? (Book Review), 86 Yale L.J.
561 (1977). I use the term "conservatism"to refer to the desire to hold onto the past or present in the
face of pressures to change. This usage bears only a contingent connection to the range of political
views now labeled "conservative."Left-wing conservatismis not oxymoronic,becauseone can imagine
left-wing systems adopting preservational(conservative)strategies or systems to prevent movement
away to the right.
90. This is not a logical truth. Grants of jurisdiction can incorporatesubstantive requirements.
Dworkin, Non-Neutral Principles, in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies of A Theory of Jus?
tice 124 (N. Daniels ed. 1975). Insofar as some grants of jurisdiction aim to increase the ability of
decisionmakersto adapt to an unknown future, however, they will be comparativelyopen-ended. It is
this open-endedness,whether couched in substantive(do good) or less substantive(determinethe pur?
pose) terms, that creates the possibility of unintended and uncontrollablevariance.
91. I therefore disagree with Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89
Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976), insofar as he argues that ruleness is acontextually individualistic and
particularizationis acontextuallyaltruistic. Even if there is truth in Kennedy's acontextuality,it still
is not clear that his analysis of the acontextual tendencies promotedby ruleness is correct. It is quite
plausible that the inherently stabilizing tendenciesof rule-bound adjudicationwill dampen individual
differences,stifle claims to special treatmentas an individual, and encouragedecisionalmodesty rather
than decisionalarrogance.It could be argued quite sensibly that all these tendenciesfoster rather than
impede altruism.
In sum, it is clearly true that rules get in the way, but this need not
always be considered a bad thing. It may be a liability to get in the way of
wise decisionmakers who sensitively consider all of the relevant factors as
they accurately pursue the good.
However, it may be an asset to restrict
misguided, incompetent, wicked, power-hungry, or simply mistaken deci?
sionmakers whose own sense of the good might diverge from that of the
system they serve. The problem, of course, is the difficulty in determining
which characterization will fit decisionmakers; we must therefore decide
the extent to which we are willing to disable good decisionmakers in order
simultaneously to disable bad ones.
With these considerations in mind, let us approach formalism in a new
light. Consider some of the famous marchers in formalism's parade of
horribles,examples such as R. v. Ojibway, Fuller's statue of the truck in
the park, and the poor Bolognese surgeon who, having opened the vein of
a patient in the course of performing an emergency operation outdoors,
was prosecuted for violating the law prohibiting "drawing blood in the
streets."92 Each of these
examples reminds us that cases may arise in
which application of the literal meaning of words produces an absurd re?
sult. But now we can recast the question, for we must consider not only
whether the result was absurd
in these cases but also whether a particular
decisionmaker should
be empowered to determine absurdity. Even in cases
as extreme as these, formalism is only superficially about rigidity and ab?
surdity. More fundamentally, it is about power and its allocation.
Formalism is about
power, but is also about its converse?modesty. To
be formalistic as a decisionmaker is to say that something is not my con?
cern, no matter how compelling it may seem. When this attitude is ap?
plied to the budget crisis or to eviction of the starving, it seems objectiona?
ble. But when the same attitude of formalism requires judges to ignore the
moral squalor of the Nazis or the Ku Klux Klan in First Amendment
cases, or the guilt of the defendant in Fourth Amendment cases, or the
wealth of the plaintiff who seeks to recover for medical expenses occa?
sioned by the defendant's negligence, it is no longer clear that refusal to
take all factors into account is condemnable.
92. The last example, from 1 S. Pufendorf, De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo
(1672), comes to us through United States v. Kirby, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 482, 487 (1868).
93. For a recent articulationof this view, see Michelman, Foreword: Traces of Self-Government,
100 Harv L. Rev. 4 (1986). A useful contrastis Christie, An Essay on Discretion, 1986 Duke L.J.
747.
good. "Fm in charge here" has a long but not always distinguished his?
tory. Part of what formalism is about is its inculcation of the view that
sometimes it is appropriate for decisionmakers to recognize their lack of
jurisdiction and to defer even when they are convinced that their own
judgment is best. The opposite of modesty is arrogance, not just responsi?
bility. True, modesty itself carries responsibility, because an actor behav-
ing modestly is participating and thus assisting
in the legitimacy of the
grant of authority to someone else. But this is a responsibility of a differ?
ent and limited kind. That one accepts partial responsibility for the deci?
sions of others does not entail the obligation to substitute one's judgment
for that of others.
The distinctive feature of rules, therefore, lies in their ability to be for?
mal, to exclude from consideration in the particular case factors whose
exclusion was determined without reference to the particular case at hand.
This formalism of rules is not only conceptually sound and psychologi-
cally possible, but it also, as I have tried to show, is on occasion norma-
tively desirable. Insofar as formalism disables some decisionmakers from
considering some factors that may appear important to them, it allocates
power to some decisionmakers and away from others. Formalism therefore
achieves its value when it is thought desirable to narrow the decisional
opportunities and the decisional
range of a certain class of decisionmakers.
I stress that all of this is compatible with agnosticism about how rule-
bound decisionmaking applies to legal systems in general, to particular
legal systems, or to particular parts of legal systems. It is far from a neces?
sary truth that legal systems must be exclusively or even largely operated
as rule-governed institutions. Judgments about when to employ formalism
are contextual and not inexorable, political and not logical, psychological
and economic rather than conceptual. It would blunt my point about the
simultaneously plausible and contingent nature of decision according to
rule to offer in this acontextual
setting my recommendations about what if
any parts of the orAmerican
any other legal system should operate in
such a fashion. My goal is only to rescue formalism from conceptual ban-
ishment. But having been readmitted to the community of respectable
ideas, formalism, or decisionmaking according to rule in any strong sense,
still has the burden of showing that it is appropriately used in a particular
decisional domain.
have its decisionmakers ignore the novelty of the situations that come
before them. Accommodation between these two forms of decisionmaking
might be possible, however.
Let us contrast two cases, both arising out of the "No vehicles in the
park" rule. The first involves the statue of the truck erected by the veter?
ans' organization. The second golf cart, as quiet as a
involves an electric
bicycle, incapable of proceeding at greater than ten miles an hour, and
emitting no noxious fumes. Can these cases be distinguished? In both
cases, exclusion of the object under consideration would not seem to serve
upheld despite its divergence from the result that would be reached by
direct application of the reasons. In the third, however, a de novo applica?
tion of the reasons indicates that the result generated by the rule is so far
out of bounds, so absurd, so preposterous that it is analogous to an abuse
of discretion and would therefore be reversed?the rule would not be ap?
plied in this case.
Under a theory of presumptive
such formalism there would be a pre?
sumption in favor
of the result generated by the literal and largely acon-
textual interpretation of the most locally applicable rule. Yet that result
would be presumptive only, subject to defeasibility when less locally appli?
cable norms, including the purpose behind the particular norm, and in?
cluding norms both within and without the decisional domain at issue,
offered especially exigent reasons for avoiding the result generated by the
presumptively applicable norm.
Such a system would bring the advantages of predictability, stability,
and constraint
of decisionmakers commonly associated with decision ac?
cording to rule, but would temper the occasional unpleasant consequences
of such a system with an escape route that allowed some results to be
avoided when their consequences would be especially outrageous. Such a
system would not be without cost. First of all, the escape route would
necessarily decrease the amount of predictability, stability, and deci?
sionmaker restraint. In short, it would diminish the amount of ruleness by
placing more final authority in the decisionmaker than in the rule. Sec?
ond, the presumptive force attached to the formalist reading of the appli?
cable norms would still result in some odd or suboptimal results. In this
sense, such a system would fail to honor all of the goals either of unre?
strained particularism or unrestrained formalism. Finally, such a system
would risk collapse into one in which the presumptions were for all prac?
tical purposes either absolute or nonexistent.
Even on the assumption that such a system might be desirable in some
decisional domains, this does not mean that all or part of what we com?
monly call the legal system might be one of those domains. It might be
that formalism, even only presumptively, is a good idea, but that the goals
of the legal system, in light of the decisions we ask it to make, are such
that it ought not to be designed along such a model. More likely, formal?
ism ought to be seen as a tool to be used in some parts of the legal system
and not in others. Determining which parts, if any, would be susceptible
to such treatment is not my agenda here, for what I have attempted to
offer is only an argument that formal systems are not necessarily to be
condemned. That is not to say they are universally or even largely to be
applauded, nor that they are to be pervasive or even frequent within that
segment of society we call the legal system. To answer this last question
we must ask what the legal system, in whole or in part, is supposed to do,
for only when we answer that question can we determine what kinds of
tools it needs to accomplish that task.
V. Conclusion