Formalism
Formalism
Formalism
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Yale Law Journal
Article
Formalism
Frederick Schauer*
Legal decisions and theories are frequently condemned as formalistic, yet little
discussion has occurred regarding exactly what the term * formalism* * means.
In this Article, Professor Schauer examines divergent uses ofthe term to eluci-
date its descriptive content. Conceptions of formalism, he argues, involve the
notion that rules constrict the choice of the decisionmaker. Our aversion to
formalism stems from denial that the language of rules either can or should
constrict choice in this way. Yet Professor Schauer argues that this aversion to
formalism should be rethought: At times language both can and should re?
strict decisionmakers. Consequently, the term "formalistic" should not be used
as a blanket condemnation of a decisionmaking process; instead the debate
regarding decision according to rules should be confronted on its own terms.
509
1. See, e.g., H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 124-30 (1961) (formalism as refusal to ac?
knowledge necessity of choice in penumbral area of rules); M. Horwitz, The Transformation of
American Law 254 (1977) (formalism as refusal to recognize instrumental functions of law); K.
Llewellyn, Jurisprudence: Realism in Theory and Practice 183-88 (1962) (formalism as
excessive reliance on canonically written language of rules); R. Unger, The Critical Legal Stud?
ies Movement 1-2 (1986) (formalism as constrained and comparatively apolitical decisionmaking);
Kennedy, Legal Formality, 2 J. Legal Stud. 351, 355 (1973) (formalism as view that rule applica?
tion is mechanical and that mechanical rule application is just); Strauss, Formal and Functional
Approaches to Separation-of-Powers Questions?A Foolish Inconsistency?, 72 Cornell L. Rev.
488, 489 (1987) (formalism as refusal to acknowledge practical consequences of judicial decisions);
Tushnet, Anti-Formalism in Recent Constitutional Theory, 83 Mich. L. Rev. 1502, 1506-07 (1985)
(formalism as artificial narrowing of range of interpretive choices).
One can avoid the confusion of multiple usage by simply stipulating a meaning for the term "for?
malism." See, e.g., Posner, Legal Formalism, Legal Realism, and the Interpretation of Statutes and
the Constitution, 37 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 179, 181-82 (1986). This tack, however, evades most of
the interesting problems. Having stipulated that "formalism" means deductive logical reasoning,
Judge Posner proceeds easily to the conclusion that formalist reasoning has no application to the
interpretation of canonical texts. That conclusion, however, follows, if at all, only from the narrow-
ness of the stipulated definition. By not stipulating a meaning in advance of the analysis, I intend to
focus on a broader range of issues. In the process, I will explore the way in which deduction, even in
Posner's sense, may be related to the interpretation of canonical texts. See infra note 48.
2. 198 U.S. 45 (1905). For condemnations of Lochner (and the era of which it is taken to be
archetypal) as formalistic, see Gordon, Critical Legal Histories, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 57, 99 (1984);
Peller, The Metaphysics of American Law, 73 Calif. L. Rev. 1151, 1193, 1200-01 (1985); Seidman,
Public Principle and Private Choice: The Uneasy Case for a Boundary Maintenance Theory of
Constitutional Law, 96 Yale L.J. 1006, 1006-07 (1987); Developments in the Law?Immigration
Policy and the Rights of Aliens, 96 Harv. L. Rev. 1286, 1292 (1983); Note, The Constitutionality of
Rent Control Restrictions on Property Owners* Dominion Interests, 100 Harv. L. Rev. 1067, 1077
(1987); Note, Formalism, Legal Realism, and Constitutionally Protected Privacy Under the Fourth
and Fifth Amendments, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 945, 951 (1977); Powers, Book Review, 1985 Duke L.J.
221, 232; Rotenberg, Politics, Personality and Judging: The Lessons of Brandeis and Frankfurter
on Judicial Restraint (Book Review), 83 Colum. L. Rev. 1863, 1875 n.60 (1983).
3. 198 U.S. at 53.
4. Id.
5. Id. at 56.
6. This was noted by Holmes in his now-famous observation, "General propositions do not decide
concrete cases." Id. at 76 (Holmes, J., dissenting).
7. Of course when I use the term "inexorable," I do not mean that the world and our language
could not have been otherwise; the word "bird" could have referred to frogs instead of pelicans, or to
only puffins, robins, and sparrows, but not pelicans, ostriches, and condors. Definitions are contingent
and subject to change, and therefore the word "bird" might yet come to be the word that speakers of
English use to refer to frogs, or only to small and not to large birds. Yet although there remains a
possibility that the word "bird" will come to mean these things, this is only a possible world?it is not
our world. In our world, the exclusion of frogs and the inclusion of large birds is definitionally part of
the meaning of the word "bird." As I argue below, see infra notes 56-57 and accompanying text, the
contingency of definition hardly entails the view that it is within the province of any one actor, legal
or otherwise, to change it. Neither you nor I have the power to make it proper to use the word "bird"
to refer to a frog, even though the word "bird" could in another world be used to refer to frogs.
8. The extent to which this is true for morally and politically loaded words such as "liberty" is
likely to vary with time, place, and culture. Take, for example, the transformation of the "honor
codes" at various venerable universities. These codes were phrased in quite general terms at their
inception in the 18th and 19th centuries because these schools contained homogeneous student bodies
who shared a common conception of the type of conduct definitionally incorporated within the word
"honor." If a person thought that purchasing a term paper from a professional term paper service was
consistent with being honorable, then that person simply did not know what "honor" meant. As
values have changed and as student bodies have become less homogeneous, however, shared definitions
of terms such as "honor" have broken down. Some people now do think that buying a term paper can
be honorable, and this breakdown in shared meaning has caused general references to "honor" to be
displaced in such codes by more detailed rules. There may now be little shared agreement about what
the precept "be honorable" requires, but there is considerable agreement about what the rule "do not
purchase a term paper" requires.
Thus, the criticism of Lochner and its ilk as "formalistic" in the sense discussed in the text is
ambiguous. The critic could mean that the term we now take to be susceptible to debate was not as
debatable at the time of the relevant decision. But this would hardly explain the pejorative, unless we
want to condemn an entire era and the conceptual and linguistic apparatus that reflected its under?
standings. The alternative is that the term "formalism" charges that there was at the time room for
debate about the application of the general term to the particular case, but the relevant decisionmakers
either did not recognize that fact (perhaps because they refused to look outside their own socioeco-
17. No. S197-86-WrC (Vt. July 28, 1986). The following account of the case is drawn from
Judge Cheever's brief opinion, the pleadings, news accounts in the Rutland Herald of July 22, 23,
24 and 26, 1986, and a conversation with Marilyn Signe Skoglund, Assistant Attorney General in the
Office of the Attorney General, State of Vermont.
18. Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 17, ? 2356 (1982).
19. Id.
20. Rutland Herald, July 23, 1986, at 5, col. 4.
21. The petition is unclear as to whether Hunter was seeking the extraordinary legal
mandamus or a mandatory injunction in equity.
C. Is There Always a Ch
Ryshpan v. Cashman is a
sider the number of Rysh
avoid the specific mandates
termine that the literal lan
nal intent, as the Supreme
1964,25 the contracts cla
Amendment.27 Or a decisio
variants to determine that
the rule's purpose.2* Or a
that denies relief to a claim
applicable rule;29 for examp
34. Use of precedent is not as simple as I make it out to be here, but these subtleties of preceden?
tial reasoning need not detain us here. For a discussion of precedent, see Schauer, Precedent, 39
Stan. L. Rev. 571 (1987).
35. See Law's Empire, supra note 31; Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 31. See also
discussion of Dworkin, supra note 31.
36. See especially Llewellyn, Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or
Canons About How Statutes Are To Be Construed, 3 Vand. L. Rev. 395 (1950).
37. Whether a system allows judges to create norms of rule avoidance where none exist, whether
judges in fact create such norms, and whether a sufficient stock of rule-avoiding norm
judges need only apply them are all unavoidably empirical questions. See Kennedy,
Phenomenology of Judging, 36 J. Legal Educ. 518, 547-48, 562 (1986); see also Tru
Action Is: Critical Legal Studies and Empiricism, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 575 (1984). Th
of course, to presume that the answers to these empirical questions will remain con
decisional domains within a legal system. For example, no logical necessity dictates
rule avoidance norms applicable to administrative determination of individual social se
identical to that applicable to Supreme Court adjudication of constitutional question
38. There need not be any conceptual inconsistency between the two models. Th
conceived of as the end product of the first.
39. I need not consider here which factors the judge actually used to reach a conclusion, for I am
not trying to catalog the considerations comprising an ideal decisionmaker's totally particularized deci?
sionmaking process. Instead, I seek merely to distinguish the concept of a complete array of factors
that any particularizing decisionmaker would take into account, regardless of the source of the partic-
ularizing norms, from the more limited array of factors available to a decisionmaker inhibited by
rules.
40. I assume here a distinction between internal and external constraint. A host of factors defining
what I am and how I got that way constrain me from appearing unclothed in a football game at
Michigan Stadium. Some of these are internal constraints?the factors that shape my very existence.
These internal constraints may be psychological, ideological, or economic, but all shape what I am
internally up to the moment of decision to appear clothed rather than naked at the football game.
Even if I could overcome these internal constraints, however, external ones, such as social disapproval
and a formal rule against such behavior, still might deter me from that action. Similarly, all sorts of
internal factors influence the decision a judge might reach about the optimal result in this case. But
these influences are distinguishable from external constraints, such as rules, that come from outside
the judge's personal determination of what should be done.
Rules are only one possible example of external constraints. A decisionmaker also may believe
herself to be externally constrained by statutory purpose. As I will demonstrate below, however, see
infra text accompanying notes 77-79, statutory purpose is an external constraint when, and only
when, it operates as a rule in the sense central to my argument. That is, purpose is an external
constraint only when some formulation of that purpose, on paper or in the mind, operates in substan?
tially the same way that a canonically formulated rule operates.
41. I explore this issue in depth below. See infra Section II-C.
42. For an example of this common use of the term "formalism," see Levinson, What Do Lawyers
Know (and What Do They Do with Their Knowledge)? Comments on Schauer and Moore, 58 S. Cal.
L. Rev. 441, 445 (1985) (erroneously concluding that Schauer "is much too sophisticated a theorist to
endorse . . . linguistic formalism"). This usage of the term "formalism" parallels that of other disci?
plines. See, e.g., Michaels, Against Formalism: The Autonomous Text in Legal and Literary Inter-
49. For an important defense of this variety of formalism, see Weinrib, Legal Formalism, 97
Yale L.J. (forthcoming 1988).
50. My point here parallels Dworkin's notion of "fit." As Dworkin illustrates the point, the de?
termination whether the existence of a homosexual relationship between David and Steerforth best fits
David Copperfield is by no means mechanical, but its resolution takes place largely within the bound?
aries of the novel. Dworkin, No Right Answer?, in Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Hon?
our of H.L.A. Hart 58 (P. Hacker & J. Raz eds. 1977). A slightly different version of this article
appears under the same title in 53 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1 (1978) and as Is There Really No Right Answer
in Hard Cases?, in R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle 119 (1985). In a later work, Law's
Empire, supra note 31, Dworkin broadens the systemic boundaries with which he is concerned to
encompass those norms commonly understood as legal, political, and moral. The expansion of these
boundaries is a separate issue, however; one could agree with Dworkin that it is possible to look for fit
within a domain while disputing the size of the relevant domain.
51. The mechanical aspects of formalism are stressed in the important discussion in Kennedy,
supra note 1. The concept of formalism as not necessarily mechanical but involving significant limita?
tions on otherwise eligible results is the focus of Tushnet, supra note 1. See also, Grey, The Constitu?
tion as Scripture, 37 Stan. L. Rev. 1, 4 n.8 (1984) (distinguishing between "operative" textual
norms that guide decisions themselves and "non-operative" textual norms that tell decisionmakers to
use decisive norms outside text).
54. Fuller's example and other illustrations of seemingly absurd results generated by applying a
rule without attention to the circumstances of its creation figure prominently in criticism of formalism.
See, e.g., Moore, A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation, 58 S. Cal. L. Rev. 277, 386-88 (1985);
H. Hart & A. Sacks, The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of Law
1148-78 (tentative ed. 1958) (unpublished manuscript); see also Dworkin's use of Riggs v. Palmer,
supra note 31.
55. This use of the term "necessarily" to describe the essential features of anything properly
called a legal system would be consistent with the general tenor of Fuller's jurisprudence. See L.
Fuller, The Morality of Law (1964); R. Summers, Lon L. Fuller 27-31, 36-40 (1984).
56. See, e.g., Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social Thought, 133
U. Pa. L. Rev. 685, 708-13 (1985) [hereinafter The Politics of Reason] (arguing that words do not
have essences or core meanings); Boyle, Thomas Hobbes and the Invente
Reflections on Language, Power, and Essentialism, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev.
cussing Hobbes' rejection of notion of linguistic essences). In passing, I n
those who describe as "post-Wittgensteinian" the view that meaning can
particular context of a particular utterance. E.g., Boyle, The Politics
footnote in a law review article is hardly the place to debate interpretation
whether Wittgenstein can even plausibly be interpreted to support a pragm
meaning. Yet I would briefly note that a fair reading of Wittgenstein revea
meaning of a word is a function of how that word is contingently used
community, but emphatically not a function of how the word is used on
particular member of that community.
It is crucial to recognize the seductive quality of phrases like "post-Wittge
that if the reader acknowledges Wittgenstein's genius, then she must agree
those terms. It is better to discuss the point at issue without attempting to
props of associations with philosophers whose names are currently fashiona
of the still-raging disputes about the most foundational questions in the
substitute Wittgenstein's name for an argument is unwarranted even if
rate. When that use is mistaken or at the very least contested, the dangers
other disciplines are compounded.
This criticism of the presentation of Boyle's argument has no bearing
however. Although I disagree with much of what he and Fuller argue, th
questions about the nature of law which I believe should be confronted d
spectives are ill-served by clothing them in what appears to me to be an
Wittgenstein.
57. For a particularly insightful and influential articulation of the view that meaning exists inde-
assumptions, it is probabl
tional
set of assumptions w
Both those within the lega
guistic community are capa
though the literal lawyer
literal lay meaning of the
Parliament to those who take an oath "on the true faith of a Christian"
59. Note that I am talking about language and about two different embellishments on the main
theme of literal meaning. First, ordinary people within a given linguistic culture might share, as
linguistic conventions, knowledge about how to interpret the language of rules, including conventions
relating to the difference between normative and descriptive language and conventions telling them to
interpret words in light of surrounding language in the same rule or statute. This suggests only that
all competent speakers of the language in which the text is written have access to a certain minimal
amount of noncontroversial information about what kind of text it is.
Second, literal meaning is not necessarily ordinary meaning, because linguistic conventions may
exist within a technical or professional subcommunity of a larger community. For example, photogra-
phers may have a literal sense of the meaning of the term "burning in," physicians may have a literal
sense of the meaning of the term "Cushing's Syndrome," and lawyers may have a literal sense of the
meaning of the term "assumpsit," even though none of these are terms used at all or in the same way
by ordinary English speakers. This second embellishment, however, must be sharply distinguished
from other notions of "conventionalism" that build in much more than linguistic meaning. See, e.g., S.
Burton, An Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning (1985); Fiss, Conventionalism, 58 S.
Cal. L. Rev. 177 (1985); Fiss, Objectivity and Interpretation, 34 Stan. L. Rev. 739 (1982). The
conventionalist legal literature talks merely about the conventions of permissible legal argument and
does not confront the question of the relationship between the conventions of permissible legal argu?
ment and the conventions of literal meaning, whether ordinary or technical. Thus, legal conventional?
ists such as Fiss avoid questions regarding whether and why certain literal readings of legal rules are
or are not permissible arguments within the legal interpretive community. It is these questions, in
some sense more foundational, that concern me here, because my aim is to locate the particular per?
missible arguments in the legal interpretive community, rather than merely to assert the existence of
permissible arguments.
60. Salomons v. Miller, 8 Ex. 778, 155 Eng. Rep. 1567 (1853); Miller v. Salomons, 7 Ex. 475,
155 Eng. Rep. 1036 (1852).
61. 46 U.S.C. ? 201 (1958), repealed by Pub. L. No. 98-89, 97 Stat. 600 (1983).
62. "When you come tomorrow, bring my football boots. Also, if humanly possible, Irish water
spaniel. Urgent. Regards. Tuppy."
"What do you make of that, Jeeves?"
"As I interpret the document, sir, Mr. Glossop wishes you, when you come tomorrow, to bring his
football boots. Also, if humanly possible, an Irish water spaniel. He hints that the matter is urgent,
and sends his regards."
"Yes, that's how I read it, too . . . ."
P.G. Woodehouse, The Ordeal of Young Tuppy, quoted in S. Blackburn, Spreading the Word:
Groundings in the Philosophy of Language 3 (1984).
63. See Aleinikoff, Constitutional Law in the Age of Balancing, 96 Yale L.J. 943, 985, 1004
(1987).
64. Noteworthy exceptions are J. Frank, Law and the Modern Mind (1930), and Kennedy,
supra note 37. However, legal scholarship still must systematically investigate the important issues
that Frank, Kennedy, and others have raised in an impressionistic way.
65. See D. Black, The Behavior of Law (1976); L. Friedman, The Legal System: A
Social Science Perspective (1975); Hogan & Henley, Nomotics: The Science of Human Rule
Systems, 5 Law & Soc'y Rev. 135 (1970); Johnson, Law, Politics, and Judicial Decision Making:
Lower Federal Court Uses of Supreme Court Decisions, 21 Law & Soc'y Rev. 325 (1987);
Scandura, New Directions for Theory and Research on Rule Learning, 28 Acta Psychologica 301
(1968).
66. There is something unrealistic about all of this, because it erroneously assumes that my para?
digm "easy" cases are representative of the kinds of decisions that come before decisionmakers. They
are not, at least when we take "decisionmaker" in a somewhat narrow sense to refer to formal deci?
sionmakers such as judges sitting in courts of law. In most legal systems, various screening devices
ensure that cases at the center of decisional determinacy will not enter the formal adjudicative process.
The time and expense of litigation and the widespread inclination to avoid futile battles are such that
decisions at the core of settled meaning seldom confront any formal decisionmaking process. See Priest,
Reexamining the Selection Hypothesis: Learning from Wittman's Mistakes, 14 J. Legal Stud. 215
(1985) (develops selection hypothesis to determine which cases are settled and which are litigated);
Priest and Klein, The Selection of Disputes for Litigation, 13 J. Legal Stud. 1 (1984) (presents
model to predict whether litigation will be resolved by suit or settlement).
This, however, is but a contingent feature of modern legal systems. It is possible to imagine a legal
system closer to a sporting event, where umpires call "safe" or "out" on every play, or where officials
with red penalty flags in their back pockets patrol the social landscape, ready to throw the flag and
call "tort," or "crime," or "breach of etiquette" whenever there is a transgression of the rules. Obvi?
ous logistical problems prevent such a system from being a reality, but it is a useful Gedankenexperi-
ment for thinking about the innumerable instances in which rules are followed or clearly broken
without coming to the attention of the judicial system.
Many legal systems, unlike those with "roving umpires," operate largely in the area of linguistic
indeterminacy, generated either by vagueness of the governing norm or by open texture when previ?
ously clear norms confront the unexpected. And in some systems, such as that of the United States, the
likelihood of success is sufficient to make it worth litigating cases in which linguistic determinacy
produces a politically or morally uncomfortable result. But that is exactly our question, because the
weight the system gives to literal meaning will determine the extent to which it is worth litigating
against literal meaning.
70. Note that the "No vehicles in the park" example may be a flawed illustration of the problem
Hart, Fuller, and I explore, because locomotive capacity may now be definitional of a "vehicle."
Insofar as this is true, the statue is not a vehicle, and no conflict arises between literal meaning and
purpose. This is a defect only in the example, however, rather than in the general formulation of the
issue. I will therefore stipulate, for the purposes of this argument, that a statue of a vehicle is a
vehicle, just as a lion in a cage is still a lion. Consider a rule prohibiting "live animals on the bus"
and whether it would prohibit carrying on the bus three live goldfish in a sealed plastic bag.
71. My point about the plasticity of purpose should not be confused with claims, often correct,
about the indeterminacy of purpose. See, e.g., Easterbrook, Foreword: The Court and the Economic
System, 98 Harv. L. Rev. 4, 15-18 (1984); Easterbrook, Statutes' Domains, 50 U. Chi. L. Rev.
533, 537-38 (1983); Kennedy, supra note 1; Posner, Statutory Interpretation?In the Classroom
and in the Courtroom, 50 U. Chi. L. Rev. 800, 819-820 (1983). Insofar as purpose becomes both
concrete and determinate, as when everyone agrees what the purpose is, the argument that "ruleness"
resides in purpose becomes more plausible. But when some conception of purpose is determinate,
noncanonical purpose itself can operate formalistically. Conversely, if purpose is comparatively inde?
terminate, then it looks especially odd to say that the rule exists not in the specific rule-formulation,
but in the quite different and nonspecific purpose. Thus, those who argue for the indeterminacy of
purpose make claims consistent with mine.
72. L. Fuller, supra note 55, at 81-91; Fuller, supra note 53; Fuller, The Speluncean Explor-
ers, 62 Harv. L. Rev. 616, 620-26 (1949) ("opinion" of Foster, J.).
73. H. Hart & A. Sacks, supra note 54.
74. Law's Empire, supra note 31.
75. K. Llewellyn, supra note 1.
76. See Wellman, Dworkin and the Legal Process Tradition: The Legacy of Hart & Sacks, 29
Ariz. L. Rev. 413 (1987); Note, Intent, Clear Statements, and the Common Law: Statutory Con?
struction in the Supreme Court, 95 Harv. L. Rev. 892 (1982). Recent manifestations of this para?
digm include G. Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of Statutes (1982); Eskridge, Dy?
namic Statutory Interpretation, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1479 (1987); Langevoort, Statutory Obsolescence
and the Judicial Process: The Revisionist Role of the Courts in Federal Banking Regulation, 85
Mich. L. Rev. 672 (1987). But see, e.g., United States v. Locke, 471 U.S. 84 (1985) (failure to file
timely claim deprives petitioner of right, irrespective of statutory purpose).
As the example reveals, the potential tension between the general goal
and its concretized instantiation exists at every level. At one level, the ten?
sion is between language and purpose; at the next, it is between that pur?
pose and the deep purpose lying behind it; at the next, between the deep
purpose and an even deeper purpose; and so on. When we decide that
purpose must not be frustrated by its instantiation, we embark upon a
potentially infinite regress in which all forms of concretization are
defeasible.
The view that rules should be interpreted to allow their purposes to
trump their language in fact collapses the distinction between a rule and a
reason, and thus loses the very concept of a rule.77 Rules are by definition
general. They gather numerous known and unknown particulars under
headings such as "vehicles," "punishment," "dogs," and "every person
who is directly or indirectly the beneficial owner of more than 10 per
centum of any class of any [registered] equity security (other than an ex-
empted security)." After identifying a category of items or events to which
the rule applies, in the protasis, rules then prescribe what shall be done
with these particulars in the apodosis7* Occasionally, however, not all of
the particulars comprising the rule's category of coverage are suitable for
the prescribed treatment; the generalizations that are a necessary part of
any rule treat all members of the class in a manner that may be appropri?
ate only for most members of the class. What, then, is to happen when a
case arises in which the generalization does not apply to this particular?
When a rule's prescribed treatment is unsuitable, if the decisionmaker
77. Note, however, that this claim is not inconsistent with the view that rules should be inter?
preted to further their purposes when several interpretations of the rule are possible and all are
supported by the language ofthe rule. In such cases, it is not only possible but positively desirable to
choose the interpretation that will serve the rule's purpose. See H.L.A. Hart, Introduction, in Es?
says in Jurisprudence and Philosophy 1, 8 (1983).
78. On this terminology for the structure of rules, which distinguishes the part of the rule specify-
ing its operative facts from the part describing the consequences flowing from the existence of those
facts, see W. Twining & D. Miers, How To Do Things With Rules 136-40 (2d ed. 1982). See
also Friedman, Legal Rules and the Process of Social Change, 19 Stan. L. Rev. 786, 786-87 (1967)
(same distinction with different labels); Schlag, Rules and Standards, 33 UCLA L. Rev. 379,
381-83 (1985) (same).
79. This is not to say that rules are always or even ever good things to have. My aim now is to
distinguish a form of decisionmaking in which generalizations have independent normative power
from a form of decisionmaking in which the full richness of the particular event always is open to
consideration. The questions of whether rules should be employed, in which domains, and to what
extent, are addressed below. See infra Section III.
80. See Schauer, Authority and Indeterminacy, in Authority Revisited: NOMOS XXIX 28
(1987).
81. The closed system/open system dispute merely recasts the debate about legal positivism in
different terminology. Any version of legal positivism is premised on what Ronald Dworkin, no posi?
tivist, has felicitously referred to as "pedigree." Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 31, at 17.
Positivism posits that legal norms are identified by reference to some other norm, rule, or standard
that distinguishes legal from non-legal norms. Hart's "rule of recognition" serves this purpose,
H.L.A. Hart, supra note 1, as does the "next higher norm" for Kelsen. H. Kelsen, The Pure
Theory of Law 193-278 (M. Knight trans. 1967). The positivist conceives of the set of norms so
pedigreed as constituting some sort of a closed system, although that system will not necessarily decide
all or even most cases that come before the courts. Kelsen, for example, sees every law-applying act as
only partially determined by law. Id. at 233-36, 244-45. By contrast, the opponents of positivism,
most notably Dworkin, attack the pedigreeability thesis by arguing that in no case is the distinction
between pedigreed and nonpedigreed norms dispositive and consequently the characterization of law
in terms of pedigreed norms is descriptively inaccurate.
82. See, e.g., R. Summers, Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory 136-75 (1982);
Aleinikoff, supra note 63, at 985; Summers, Professor Fuller's Jurisprudence and America's Domi?
nant Philosophy ofLaw, 92 Harv. L. Rev. 433 (1978).
83. Insofar as a system permits recourse to the purpose behind a rule's formulation but does not
permit departure from that purpose when adhering to it will produce unfortunate results or will
frustrate the even deeper purpose behind it, that system will still be formal in the sense I am now
using that term. It will also be rule-bound, because the less than totally plastic purpose (although
more plastic than the rule-formulation) will operate as a rule vis-a-vis the higher order reasons that
generated that particular purpose.
84. In a trivial sense, rules differ from their formulations. See, e.g., G. Baker & P. Hacker,
supra note 57, at 41-52; M. Black, The Analysis of Rules, in Models and Metaphors: Studies
in Language and Philosophy 95 (1962); D. Shwayder, The Stratification of Behaviour
241 (1965); G. von Wright, Practical Reason 68 (1983). "Do not walk on the grass," "Walking
on the grass is prohibited," and "No walking on the grass" constitute one and not three rules. Refer?
ring to these three formulations as formulations of only one rule, however, presupposes that all have
the same meaning, that the differences are syntactical and not semantic. Thus, the distinction between
a rule and its formulation is like the distinction between a proposition and a sentence. When I discuss
a rule and equate it with its formulation, I therefore mean that a rule is that set of semantically
equivalent rule formulations.
85. My references to "literalism" are slightly metaphorical. As noted above, see supra note 59,
literalism includes those aspects of context, such as the appearance of words in a statute rather than in
a poem, that are accessible to all or most readers. Moreover, although I often use single words as
examples, statutes are not read word by word, but instead by sentences, paragraphs, and larger units
of text. This is not to deny, however, that the ability to assign meanings to individual words is what
enables us to understand a sentence we have never seen before. See D. Davidson, Truth and Mean?
ing, in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation 17 (1984). This assertion, however, superfi-
cially in conflict with Frege's assertion that only in the context of a sentence does a word have any
meaning, see G. Frege, The Foundations of Arithmetic (J.L. Austin trans. 1959), is not with?
out its detractors and complexities. See, e.g., Wallace, Only in the Context of a Sentence Do Words
Have Any Meaning, in Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language 305 (P.
French, T. Uehling, Jr., & H. Wettstein eds. 1979).
Still, pace Fuller, supra note 53, at 662-63, sentences and paragraphs can have literal and even
acontextual meaning insofar as an entire sentence or paragraph may supply enough context to make
its meaning comparatively clear. As texts become lengthier and richer it is often more possible to
understand those texts without departing from them and thus more possible for them to have acontex?
tual meaning.
Moreover, literal meaning need not always be ordinary meaning. Where some aspect of the mini?
mal and uncontested context makes it plain that a settled specialized or technical meaning of a term or
phrase applies, that technical meaning, rather than the ordinary usage of the man on the Clapham
omnibus, is controlling.
86. See generally A. Kocourek, An Introduction to the Science of Law 165-85 (1930);
R. Wasserstrom, The Judicial Decision: Toward a Theory of Legal Justification 60-66
(1961); Marsh, Principle and Discretion in the Judicial Process, 68 Law Q. Rev. 226 (1952). Along
with Wasserstrom, supra, at 61, I object to the use of the word "certainty" in this context because,
unlike the term "predictability," it suggests that no doubt is involved. I can predict that it will snow in
Vermont this winter and rely on that prediction in making winter plans, yet still not be certain that it
will snow. Although one usage of "certain" does recognize variability, I prefer the term "predictabil?
ity" because its common usage implies such variability.
89. See Horwitz, The Rule ofLaw: An Unqualified Human Good? (Book Review), 86 Yale L.J.
561 (1977). I use the term "conservatism" to refer to the desire to hold onto the past or present in the
face of pressures to change. This usage bears only a contingent connection to the range of political
views now labeled "conservative." Left-wing conservatism is not oxymoronic, because one can imagine
left-wing systems adopting preservational (conservative) strategies or systems to prevent movement
away to the right.
90. This is not a logical truth. Grants of jurisdiction can incorporate substantive requirements.
Dworkin, Non-Neutral Principles, in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies of A Theory of Jus?
tice 124 (N. Daniels ed. 1975). Insofar as some grants of jurisdiction aim to increase the ability of
decisionmakers to adapt to an unknown future, however, they will be comparatively open-ended. It is
this open-endedness, whether couched in substantive (do good) or less substantive (determine the pur?
pose) terms, that creates the possibility of unintended and uncontrollable variance.
91. I therefore disagree with Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89
Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976), insofar as he argues that ruleness is acontextually individualistic and
particularization is acontextually altruistic. Even if there is truth in Kennedy's acontextuality, it still
is not clear that his analysis of the acontextual tendencies promoted by ruleness is correct. It is quite
plausible that the inherently stabilizing tendencies of rule-bound adjudication will dampen individual
differences, stifle claims to special treatment as an individual, and encourage decisional modesty rather
than decisional arrogance. It could be argued quite sensibly that all these tendencies foster rather than
impede altruism.
92. The last example, from 1 S. Pufendorf, De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo
(1672), comes to us through United States v. Kirby, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 482, 487 (1868).
93. For a recent articulation of this view, see Michelman, Foreword: Traces of Self-Government,
100 Harv L. Rev. 4 (1986). A useful contrast is Christie, An Essay on Discretion, 1986 Duke L.J.
747.
V. Conclusion