Endogenous Credit Cycles
Endogenous Credit Cycles
Endogenous Credit Cycles
Author(s): Chao Gu, Fabrizio Mattesini, Cyril Monnet, and Randall Wright
Source: Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 121, No. 5 (October 2013), pp. 940-965
Published by: The University of Chicago Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/673472 .
Accessed: 16/09/2014 03:39
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal
of Political Economy.
http://www.jstor.org
Chao Gu
University of Missouri–Columbia
Fabrizio Mattesini
University of Rome Tor-Vergata
Cyril Monnet
University of Bern and Study Center Gerzensee
Randall Wright
University of Wisconsin–Madison, Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis, Federal Reserve Bank of
Chicago, and National Bureau of Economic Research
We thank two referees and the editor ðRobert ShimerÞ for very useful comments and sug-
gestions. We also thank Huberto Ennis, Karl Shell, Fernando Alvarez, Michael Woodfood, and
Christian Hellwig for their input. For research support, Wright thanks the National Science
Foundation and the Ray Zemon Chair in Liquid Assets at the Wisconsin School of Business.
The usual disclaimers apply.
940
I. Introduction
Are credit markets susceptible to animal spirits, self-fulfilling prophecies,
and endogenous fluctuations? This is different from asking if there are
channels in credit markets that amplify or propagate fluctuations driven
by fundamental factors, as emphasized in the literature surveyed by Gert-
ler and Kiyotaki ð2010Þ. In this paper, we show that even if fundamentals
are deterministic and time invariant, economies with credit market fric-
tions can display cyclic, chaotic, and stochastic dynamics driven purely by
beliefs. The key friction is limited commitment, which leads to endoge-
nous borrowing constraints.1 While most studies of these kinds of models
focus on stationary equilibria, we show that economies with commitment
frictions not only generate multiple steady states, with different credit con-
ditions and allocations, but also display equilibria in which credit condi-
tions and allocations vary over time, even when fundamentals do not.
This is true when the terms of trade are determined by Walrasian pric-
ing or by generalized Nash bargaining, although the economic forces gen-
erating dynamics in economies with the two pricing mechanisms are very
different.
With limited commitment, agents honor their debt obligations to
avoid punishment by exclusion from future credit. If one believes that
one’s debt limit in the future will be 0, one has nothing to lose by re-
neging on current obligations, which makes the equilibrium debt limit 0
today. Hence there is always a no-credit equilibrium. Generally, there is
also a steady-state equilibrium with a positive debt limit. To explain how
we get cycles, we find it useful to first build some intuition by considering
a competitive labor market. Let the unconstrained equilibrium hours
and wages be ð‘*; w * Þ. Suppose that we impose an exogenous restriction
‘ ≤ f, where f 5 ‘* 2 ε with ε > 0. There are two effects on workers: ,
goes down and w goes up. The first effect has a second-order impact on
their utility, by the envelope theorem, if ε is not too big. The increase in
1
By modeling debt limits endogenously using limited commitment, we follow Kehoe and
Levine ð1993, 2001Þ and Alvarez and Jermann ð2000Þ. See Azariadis and Kass ð2007, 2013Þ,
Lorenzoni ð2008Þ, Hellwig and Lorenzoni ð2009Þ, and Sanches and Williamson ð2010Þ for re-
lated work. As discussed in more detail below, our setup differs somewhat from the usual
limited-commitment model and is based on a framework we use elsewhere to study banking
ðGu et al. 2013Þ. While there are no banks here, the setup is used because it is tractable and
flexible. In particular, we have production and investment because we think that it may be
interesting to see how these vary over the credit cycle; but as we show, the model can be re-
interpreted as a Kehoe-Levine pure-endowment economy or as some other standard credit
models.
2
As suggested by a referee, one can also provide related examples using international
trade theory with tariffs; we think that the labor example should suffice.
3
See Azariadis ð1993Þ for an overview and references to primary sources on money and
dynamics in the overlapping-generations tradition, see Woodford ð1986, 1988Þ for models
with exogenous cash-in-advance or borrowing constraints, and see Matsuyama ð1990Þ for
money in the utility function. Boldrin and Woodford ð1990Þ provide a survey of related
work. Matsuyama ð2013Þ provides an alternative approach, as does Myerson ð2012, 2013Þ.
There is also work on dynamics in growth models with externalities ðsee, e.g., some of the
papers in the Benhabib ½1992 volumeÞ; there are no such externalities in our model.
Sanches and Williamson ð2010Þ also comment on a similarity between money and credit
models and particularly on the no-credit equilibrium. Although we learned a lot from their
analysis about credit markets, generally, Sanches and Williamson do not study dynamics,
which is the main point of this paper.
Vt 1 5 U 1 ðxt ; yt Þ 1 bVt11
1
; ð1Þ
Vt 2 5 U 2 ðyt ; xt Þ 1 bVt11
2
: ð2Þ
The critical condition is the repayment constraint for type 1 in the second
subperiod,
lyt 1 ð1 2 pÞbVt11
1
≤ bVt11
1
: ð4Þ
The left-hand side of ð4Þ is type 1’s instantaneous deviation payoff lyt
plus the continuation value: with probability p, he is caught and ex-
cluded from future markets; with probability 1 2 p, he is not caught and
continues in good standing. It is convenient to rewrite ð4Þ as
4
As mentioned, this environment is taken from Gu et al. ð2013Þ, where we discuss im-
perfect monitoring in more detail. But there we study only the incentive-feasible set in the
spirit of mechanism design, while here we study price-taking and bargaining equilibria. To
be clear, we do not need p < 1 for any general results, but it can be useful in applications
and examples.
5
These equations are sometimes referred to as “promise-keeping constraints” in the
related literature.
where ft ; ðbp=lÞVt111
is the debt limit. Using ð1Þ, we can express this re-
cursively to make it clear that the debt limit in one period depends on
the debt limit in the next period:
bp 1
ft21 5 U ðxt ; yt Þ 1 bft : ð6Þ
l
Uy2
U 1y U 2 2U
2 2 2
yx y
Uxyy xy
5 h 0 ðfÞ 5 2 ð12Þ
yf U2
Ux2 1 x Uxx2 2 x2 Uxy2
Uy
yU 1 ½hðfÞ; f
yf
Uy2 U2
Uy1 Ux2 2 Ux1 Uy2 2 yUx1 Uyy2 2 2 Uxy2 1 xUy1 Uxx2 2 x2 Uxy2 ð13Þ
U Uy
5 x
U2
Ux2 1 x Uxx2 2 x2 Uxy2
Uy
is ambiguous. As we show below, yU 1 =yf < 0 is not only possible but in-
evitable for some f. Hence, a borrower’s payoff can decrease with his
credit limit.
Following Alvarez and Jermann ð2000Þ, for all t, the equilibrium debt
limit ft is defined as follows: type 1 is indifferent between repaying ft
and defaulting. In any feasible allocation, payoffs, and hence ft , must be
bounded ðso, as in many other models, we rule out explosive bubblesÞ.
We can also bound xt and yt without loss in generality. Hence we have
the following definition.
Definition 1. An equilibrium is given by nonnegative and bounded
` `
sequences of credit limits fft gt51 and credit contracts fxt ; yt gt51 such that
ðiÞ for all t, ðxt ; yt Þ solves ð11Þ given ft and ðiiÞ ft solves the difference
`
equation ð6Þ given fxt ; yt gt51 .
We can collapse the two conditions in definition 1 into one:
ðbp=lÞU 1 ½hðft Þ; ft 1 bft if ft < y *
ft21 5 f ðft Þ ; ð14Þ
ðbp=lÞU 1 ðx *; y * Þ 1 bft otherwise:
III. Results
A stationary equilibrium, or steady state, is a fixed point f ðfÞ 5 f. Ob-
viously f 5 0 is one such point, associated with ðx; yÞ 5 ð0; 0Þ. Intuitively,
if there is to be no credit in the future, you have nothing to lose by re-
neging, so no one will extend you credit today. A nondegenerate steady
state is a solution to f ðfs Þ 5 fs > 0. The mild assumption Ux1 ð0; 0Þh 0 ð0Þ
1 Uy1 ð0; 0Þ > lð1 2 bÞ=bp guarantees the following.
Proposition 1. There exists at least one positive steady state, fs 5
f ðfs Þ > 0. If f ðy * Þ < y *, the repayment constraint is binding at any steady
state.
All proofs are in Appendix A, but the existence result is easy to un-
derstand from figures 1A and B. In figure 1A, the debt constraint in
steady state is slack, fs ≥ y *, and in figure 1B, it is binding, fs < y*. Note
that f ðfÞ is not necessarily monotone for f ∈ ð0; y * Þ, so we cannot guar-
antee uniqueness of a positive steady state fs, in general, although it
was unique in all the examples we tried. Some statements of results be-
low proceed as if fs were unique, but this is only to ease the presenta-
tion, and the results hold more generally if one replaces the clause “the
unique positive” with “the smallest positive” steady state.7
It is clear that there exist equilibria in which ft → 0, as shown in fig-
ures 2A and B. Note that with ft21 on the horizontal and ft on the ver-
tical axis, in these diagrams the curve is f 21. We draw it this way even
though the dynamics are forward looking, with causality running from
future to previous periods. In figure 2A, f is monotone, so f 21 is a
function; in figure 2B, it is not monotone, so f 21 is a correspondence.
When f is monotone, once we pick an initial f0 ∈ ð0; fs Þ, the sequence
fft g is pinned down. When f is not monotone, over some range for f0
there are multiple equilibrium paths for fft g. There are even perfect-
foresight equilibria in which we start at fs and stay there for any number
of periods, until dropping to the lower branch of f 21, and then ft → 0.
This is a serious and escalating credit crunch caused by nothing more
than beliefs—a self-fulfilling prophecy.
7
One can make a few observations about the case with multiple positive steady states;
e.g., they alternate between stable and unstable. We omit this in the interest of space.
F IG . 2.—Nonstationary equilibria
Now consider two-period cycles, with f1 and f2 > f1 denoting the pe-
riodic points. Following standard methods ðsee Azariadis ½1993 for a
textbook treatmentÞ, we have the following proposition.
Proposition 3. Suppose that there is a unique positive steady state
0
fs . If f ðfs Þ < 21, there is a two-period cycle with f1 < fs < f2 .
x 12a x 11g
U 1 ðx; yÞ 5 2y and U 2 ðy; xÞ 5 y 2 : ð15Þ
12a 11g
For simplicity, for now we set a 5 0.8 Thus, U 1 is linear, but since U 2 is
nonlinear, interesting dynamics still obtain via x 5 hðfÞ. The parameters
are not calibrated to be empirically reasonable, only to illustrate some
mathematical possibilities ðthis is not to say that the model could not be
calibrated more realistically in future workÞ. Examples 1 and 2 show
cycles in which f1 < f2 < y* and f1 < y * < f2, respectively.
Example 1. Let g 5 2:1, b 5 0:4, and p=l 5 6. Then fs 5 0:7194
and there is a two-cycle with f1 5 0:4777 < y * and f2 5 0:9357 < y *. See
figure 3A.
Example 2. Let g 5 0:5, b 5 0:9, and p=l 5 10. Now fs 5 0:9674
and there is a two-cycle with f1 5 0:9328 < y* and f2 5 1:0365 > y *. See
figure 3B.
The next example has a three-period cycle, shown in figure 4A. The
existence of a three-period cycle implies the existence of cycles of all
orders by the Sarkovskii theorem, as well as chaotic dynamics by the Li-
Yorke theorem ðagain see Azariadis 1993Þ. Chaos is observationally equiv-
alent to a stochastic process for ft. Hence, debt limits, investment, and
consumption can appear random when they are not ðsee fig. 4BÞ. Note
that credit limits are marked by x’s in the figure. As one can see, there
are recurrent episodes with three or four periods of unconstrained credit
followed by a crunch, as well as episodes with three periods of tight credit
followed by easy credit. Hence, compared to equilibria with two-period
cycles, these chaotic equilibria can have much more intricate dynamics.
Example 3. Let g 5 0:8, b 5 0:9, and p=l 5 15. Now fs 5 0:9835,
and there is a three-cycle with f1 5 0:9464 < y*, f2 5 1:0516 > y *, and f3
5 1:1684 > y *.
The next result says that in any cycle we must have ft < y * at some
point over the cycle, but not necessarily at all points. In other words, the
debt limit binds infinitely often.
8
It is not merely a normalization to set a 5 0, although that would be the case in the
model with bargaining. In the bargaining version, it is equivalent to bargain over either x
and y, on the one hand, or x 12a =ð1 2 aÞ and y, on the other. In the Walrasian model, how-
ever, we have already bought into linear pricing. If this is not obvious, consider a competitive
profit-maximizing firm with cost function cðyÞ, for which it obviously matters, for profit,
if cðyÞ is linear or strictly convex. We return to a > 0 below. For now, a 5 0 provides a stark
illustration of the economic mechanism at work: in this case, type 1 agents realize no gains
from trade, like a competitive profit-maximizing firm with linear cost, if the constraint is
slack.
f1;t21 j f ðf1;t Þ 1 ð1 2 j1 Þf ðf2;t Þ
5 1 : ð20Þ
f2;t21 j2 f ðf2;t Þ 1 ð1 2 j2 Þf ðf1;t Þ
IV. Discussion
The existence of equilibria with deterministic or stochastic cycles relies
on the nonmonotonicity of f ðft Þ. To understand this, recall that
bp 1
ft 5 f ðft11 Þ 5 U ðxt11 ; yt11 Þ 1 bft11 : ð21Þ
l
9
Looking at ð21Þ, it appears that cycles are more likely when b is small, since this reduces
the impact of the linear term, as long as we keep the coefficient on the nonlinear term big
by increasing p=l. It is not quite that simple, however, since the allocation ðxt11 ; yt11 Þ de-
pends on these parameters.
f yU 1 ½hðfÞ; f
hðfÞ 5 :
U ½hðfÞ; f
1
yf
Corollary 1. If hðy * Þ < 21, then we can always pick b and p=l to
generate cycles.
It is not hard to satisfy this elasticity condition.10 If U 1 5 log ð1 1 xÞ
2 A logð1 2 yÞ and U 2 5 log ð1 1 yÞ 2 A logð1 2 xÞ, for A ∈ ð0; 1Þ, hðy * Þ <
^ where A
21 iff A > A, ^ ≃ 0:132. Basically, hðy * Þ < 21 allows us to choose
bp=ð1 2 bÞl close to y* =U 1 ðx *; y* Þ so that fs is near y * and then pick b
and p=l to guarantee f 0 ðfs Þ < 21. Although this is not a quantitative
paper, we mention that having p=l and b makes it easier to construct in-
teresting examples. This is not surprising but is relevant because in fu-
ture quantitative work it may be useful to allow the monitoring proba-
bility p, which is absent in most related models, to play a role.
To say more about conditions to guarantee cycles, reconsider the func-
tional forms in ð15Þ, where now a ∈ ½0; 1Þ. Also assume ð1 2 aÞg > ð1 1 gÞa.
Then we have the following corollary.
Corollary 2. Given the parameter restrictions listed above, there is
a unique positive steady state fs > 0, and there are cycles around fs if
gð1 2 aÞ 2 að1 1 gÞ
b< and
a1g
ð22Þ
21g2a p 12a 12b
11 < < :
bða 1 gÞ l a b
10
At the suggestion of a referee and the editor, an alternative elasticity condition is pro-
vided in App. C.
ft21 5 f ðft Þ
bpu½h ○ g ðft Þ 1 bpv½1 2 g ðft Þ 1 bft if g ðft Þ < y * ð23Þ
;
bpuðx * Þ 1 bpvð1 2 y * Þ 1 bft otherwise:
11
While we can imagine a variety of other applications, contracting with contractors is
one that many people have experienced firsthand. In fact, the editor’s suggestion was ac-
tually more along the lines of MacLeod and Malcomson ð1993Þ: A firm needs to hire work-
ers before profits are realized, with only the promise of future wages. The firm may renege
but faces punishment, like any other defaulter. Hence, there is a maximum credible wage
promise. The main difference in these applications concerns who has a first-mover disad-
vantage: the household paying a contractor x up front and hoping to receive y or an indi-
vidual working in advance and hoping to get paid. Again, it is easy to imagine other appli-
cations along these lines.
F ðxt Þ 2 yt 1 bVt11
1
≥ F ðxt Þ 2 ð1 2 lÞyt 2 C 1 ð1 2 pÞbVt11
1
;
yt ≤ C =l 1 ðbp=lÞVt11
1
; ft : ð24Þ
ft21 5 f ðft Þ
ðbp=lÞF ½hðft Þ 2 ðbp=lÞft 1 bft 1 ð1 2 bÞC =l if ft < y*
;
ðbp=lÞF ðx * Þ 2 ðbp=lÞy * 1 bft 1 ð1 2 bÞC =l otherwise:
ð25Þ
V. Conclusion
This paper has developed a framework to study dynamics in lending,
production, and investment. There always exist multiple steady states and
multiple dynamic equilibria in the baseline model. There can exist deter-
ministic, chaotic, and stochastic cycles, where credit conditions fluctuate
even though fundamentals are deterministic and time invariant. Even if
we add features, such as collateral, that rule out the no-credit equilib-
rium and paths that converge to the no-credit equilibrium, cycles still exist.
The key friction in the theory is limited commitment, although there are
other ingredients, including imperfect monitoring. Still, the model is
simple to use. One reason is that equilibrium allocations reduce to a se-
quence of two-period ðor two-subperiodÞ credit arrangements, although
the economy goes on forever. The setup is also quite flexible and can eas-
ily accommodate both price taking and bargaining. We provided sev-
eral interpretations, including pure-credit economies, as well as those with
production and investment.
Of course, we made some strong assumptions, including our assump-
tion of perfect-foresight or rational expectations. Obviously, if one re-
laxes these assumptions, even more exotic equilibria could arise; the goal
here was to show that even with the discipline of rational expectations,
one can get complicated dynamics. It would be interesting to see if com-
binations of fundamental shocks and the endogenous dynamics empha-
sized here might generate empirically plausible cycles. This and other
Appendix A
Proofs
Proof of Proposition 1
0 0
Define T ðfÞ 5 f ðfÞ 2 f. Our assumptions imply T ð0Þ > 0. Also, T ðfÞ 5 b 2 1
< 0 for f > y *. By the continuity and monotonicity of T ðfÞ for f > y *, it is easy to
see the following: if T ðy * Þ ≥ 0, there exists fs > y* such that T ðfs Þ 5 0; and if
T ðy* Þ < 0, there exists fs in ð0; y * Þ such that T ðfs Þ 5 0. In the latter case, there are
no stationary equilibria in which fs > y* because T ðfÞ is strictly decreasing for
f > y * . QED
Proof of Proposition 2
Because f ðft Þ is continuous, ft21 covers the interval ½0; f ~ for ft ∈ ½0; fs . Since
there is a unique positive steady state, f ðft Þ ft for ft ∈ ð0; fs Þ and f ðft Þ < ft for
>
ft ∈ ðfs ; `Þ. That is, ft21 > ft for ft ∈ ð0; fs Þ and ft21 < ft for ft ∈ ðfs ; `Þ. Given
~ there is a f1 such that f1 ∈ ð0; fs Þ and f1 < f0 , which implies a f2 ∈ ð0; fs Þ
f0 < f,
with f2 < f1 , and so on. This sequence fft g0` converges to zero. QED
Proof of Proposition 3
Let f 2 ðfÞ 5 f ○ f ðfÞ. Because fs is the unique positive steady state, f ðfÞ > f for
f < fs and f ðfÞ < f for f > fs. Because f ðfÞ is linearly increasing for f > y *, there
exists a f~ > y* such that f ðfÞ
~ > y*. By the uniqueness of the positive stationary
~ < f ðfÞ
equilibrium, f 2 ðfÞ ~ < f.
~ Note that 0 and fs are two fixed points of f 2 . The
slope of f ðf Þ is
2 s
df 2 ðfs Þ
5 f 0 ½ f ðfs Þ f 0 ðfs Þ 5 f 0 ðfs Þf 0 ðfs Þ 5 ½ f 0 ðfs Þ2 > 1:
dfs
The last inequality uses f 0 ðfs Þ < 21. Similarly, df 2 ð0Þ=df > 1. By continuity, f 2
~ it
must cross the 45-degree line in ð0; fs Þ. Because f 2 lies below the diagonal at f,
~ So there are fixed points f1 and f2 such that
crosses it at least once in ðfs ; fÞ.
0 < f1 < fs < f2 for f 2 ðfÞ. QED
Proof of Proposition 5
0
Since f ðfs Þ < 0, there is an interval ½fs 2 ε1 ; fs 1 ε2 , with ε1 , ε2 > 0, such that
f ðf1 Þ > f ðf2 Þ for f1 ∈ ½fs 2 ε1 ; fs Þ and f2 ∈ ðfs ; fs 1 ε2 . By definition, ðf1 ; f2 Þ is a
proper sunspot equilibrium if there exists ðj1 ; j2 Þ, with j1 , j2 < 1 such that
Because f1 and f2 are weighted averages of f ðf1 Þ and f ðf2 Þ, where f ðf1 Þ > f1 and
f ðf2 Þ < f2 , by the uniqueness of the positive steady state, necessary and sufficient
conditions for ðA1Þ and ðA2Þ are
f ðf2 Þ < f1 < f ðf1 Þ and f ðf2 Þ < f2 < f ðf1 Þ: ðA3Þ
When we expand f ðf1 Þ and f ðf2 Þ around fs and use f ðfs Þ 5 fs, the above in-
equalities are equivalent to
f 2 2 fs fs 2 f1
< 2f 0 ðfs Þ < :
f 2 f1
s
f2 2 fs
0
Because 2f ðfs Þ > 1, ðf2 2 fs Þ=ðfs 2 f1 Þ < 2f 0 ðfs Þ is redundant if 2f 0 ðfs Þ < ðfs
2 f1 Þ=ðf2 2 fs Þ. Now we have two unknowns ðf1 ; f2 Þ and only one inequality,
2f 0 ðfs Þ < ðfs 2 f1 Þ=ðf2 2 fs Þ, to solve. It is straightforward that multiple solu-
tions exist on ½fs 2 ε1 ; fs 1 ε2 . To show j1 1 j2 < 1, rewrite ðA1Þ and ðA2Þ as
f1 2 f ðf2 Þ 2 f2 1 f ðf1 Þ f 1 2 f2
j1 1 j2 5 5 1 1 < 1;
f ðf1 Þ 2 f ðf2 Þ f ðf1 Þ 2 f ðf2 Þ
If f 5 y*, equilibrium is on the contract curve and 2Ux1 =Uy1 5 2Ux2 =Uy2 5 y=x. A
calculation implies
" #
yU 1 ½hðfÞ; fx Uy1 x 2 Uxx2 1 2xyUxy2 1 y2 Uyy2
5 :
yf x U2
Ux2 1 x Uxx2 2 x2 Uxy2
*
f→y2
Uy
The term outside the brackets is negative. The term in brackets is positive as long
as y is normal for type 2. QED
Proof of Corollary 1
To construct cycles, it suffices to show that we can choose b and p=l such
that fs is close to y* and f 0 ðfs Þ < 21. A steady state exists at f 5 y2* if y2* 5
ðbp=lÞU 1 ðx2* ; y2* Þ 1 by2* , or
p 12b f
5 : ðA5Þ
l b U ½hðfÞ; f f→y2*
1
bp yU 1 ½hðfÞ; f
l yf * 1 b < 21: ðA6Þ
f→y2
If the elasticity condition holds, we can pick b and p=l to satisfy ðA7Þ. QED
Proof of Corollary 2
Appendix B
Bargaining
Here we show that a model with bargaining can generate the same type of dy-
namics. For ease of presentation, assume that each type 1 meets a random type 2
at each date, and they negotiate a contract ðxt ; yt Þ, taking as given what happens
in all other meetings. Generalized Nash bargaining determines ðxt ; yt Þ. Note that
the strategic foundations of Nash bargaining are not straightforward in non-
stationary situations ðsee, e.g., Coles and Wright 1998; Ennis 2001, 2004; Coles and
Muthoo 2003Þ. Thus, we are taking the Nash solution as a primitive, and there is
no claim here that it is derived from a strategic bargaining game as in standard
stationary models. That said, there is no presumption that one could not gener-
ate interesting dynamics with some strategic bargaining model, such as the ones
used in the above-mentioned papers, but that is not the goal here.
Let type 1’s bargaining power be v, and let threat points be given by contin-
uation values. Since the continuation values and threat points cancel, the bar-
gaining outcome solves the simple problem
yU 1 ½hðfÞ; f vU 2 ðUxx1 Uy1 2 Uxy1 Ux1 Þ 1 ð1 2 vÞU 1 ðUy1 Uxx2 2 Ux1 Uxy2 Þ
5 ; ðB5Þ
yf vðUxx1 U 2 1 Ux1 Ux2 Þ 1 ð1 2 vÞðUx1 Ux2 1 U 1 Uxx2 Þ
Appendix C
Alternative Elasticity Conditions
Here, at the request of the editor and referee, we present an alternative condi-
tion to guarantee the existence of cycles, in terms of the elasticity of credit sup-
ply. From ð13Þ, we have
Uy2 2 Ux2 2
U 1
U 2
2 U 1
U 2
2 yU 1
U 2
2 U 1 xU 1
U 2
2 U
yU 1 ½hðfÞ; f
y x x y x yy
U 2 xy y xx
Uy2 xy
5 x :
yf U 2
Ux2 1 x Uxx2 2 x2 Uxy2
Uy
The left-hand side is yU 1 ½hðfÞ; f=yf 5 Ux1 dh=yf 1 Uy1 . Around ðy*; x * Þ, we have
yU 1 ½hðfÞ; f 1 dh
* 5 Ux df 1 Uy
1
yf f→y2
" #
Uy1 x 2 Uxx2 1 2xyUxy2 1 y 2 Uyy2
5 :
x U2
Ux2 1 x Uxx2 2 x2 Uxy2
Uy
As the last term is negative, Ux1 dh=yf 1 Uy1 < 0. Around ðy *; x * Þ, Ux1 =Uy1 5 2f=h,
and the inequality implies
dh f
< 1:
df h f→y2*
That is, around the unconstrained steady state, the elasticity of credit supply is
less than one.
The ðutilityÞ elasticity hðfÞ defined just before corollary 1 can be rewritten
f yU 1 ðhðfÞ; fÞ f 1 dh
5 U 1 U 1
U 1 ðhðfÞ; fÞ yf U 1 ðhðfÞ; fÞ x df y
dh f Ux h1 Uy f
1
5 1 :
df h U 1 U1
dh f U 1 ðx *; y* Þ
<12 :
df h Ux1 ðx *; y* Þx *
We conclude that if the elasticity of credit supply is small, cycles exist. QED
References