Virtues For The Anthropocene
Virtues For The Anthropocene
Virtues For The Anthropocene
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
White Horse Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Environmental Values
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Virtues for the Anthropocene
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
ABSTRACT
KEYWORDS
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
184
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
185
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
186
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
2. I have discussed a larger number of garden virtues in Di Paola, 2012: chapter 4. On this top
see also Pollan, 1991 ; Brady, 2002; Cooper, 2006; Harrison, 2009, Brook, 2010. On environ
mental virtue more generally see the essays in Sandler and Cafaro, 2005; Jamieson, 20
Sandler, 2007; and the essays in Bendik-Keymer and Thompson, 2012.
3. For another contribution to this line of inquiry see Krakoff, 201 1 .
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
187
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
i) Geo-power
4. To my knowledge, the term 'geo-power' has to date only previously been used by Timothy
Luke in a paper called 'On environmental ity: Geo-power and eco-knowledge in the dis-
courses of contemporary environmental ism' (Luke, 1995). Luke's line of research was very
different from mine, and so are the two notions of geo-power involved. For one thing, Luke's
geo-power is explicitly intended to be an extension of Foucault's bio-power, while mine will
be defined in contrast to it.
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
188
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
189
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
190
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
191
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
6. This is not to say that rigor legis will be useless in the Anthropocene: just that, to be effecti
on individual lifestyles, its exercise will in many cases be quite costly in terms of resourc
expended and liberties sacrificed. Also note that I criticise policies that restrict individual
liberties while leaving largely unchallenged the often unsustainable, unfair and risky soci
economic systems in which such liberties have hitherto been exercised. With that, I am no
denying that it is a task for institutions to create and promote applicable alternatives to suc
systems. See Shove, 2010 for a relevant discussion specifically in connection to climat
change.
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
192
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
The second remark speaks to the past and the future of environment
ethics. Environmental ethicists have traditionally prized the property of
uralness, or even 'wildness', quite highly.7 Given clean-hands exploitatio
however, even the fate of that little 'wild' that is left (that scarce 10 per cen
the Earth's surface that has been declared a natural reserve or national p
now crucially depends on what happens in the remaining humanised 90
cent - and particularly in cities. Well over half the world's population liv
urban agglomerates, and this figure is only destined to increase. Most envi
mental degradation is nowadays produced or triggered by the demands
activities of city-dwellers. The salient loci of environmental protection in
Anthropocene are thus cities - thoroughly humanised rather than wild ar
Benign neglect obviously makes no sense in cities; and because the fate of
areas depends on the distant demands and activities of city-dwellers, it
makes less sense there, too (but see Sandler, 2013). The salient approach
environmental ethics in the Anthropocene seems thus to be one of steward
- self-starting engagement with the protection and promotion of ecolog
conditions that have so far been congenial to humanity (Di Paola, 2013).
In sum, rather than pre-committed, institutionalised, place-based ecosy
tem management whose backbone is benign neglect, an environmental e
for the Anthropocene must be based on individualised, self-starting, self-r
lating, metropolitan, networked ecosystem stewardship.
7. The axiological idealisation of 'the wild' has been a hugely influential theme in environ
tal ethics, particularly in North America. For a review of wilderness-based arguments,
Nelson, 2003; for an influential critique, see Callicott, 2003. For a general discussion of
topic see Jamieson, 2008: chapter 6. For some reflections on the sources of our fascinat
with naturalness and the wild see Di Paola, 2015.
8. What I am about to discuss are justificatory hurdles (and just two among many). Ther
also notable motivational hurdles in the Anthropocene. There is a significant amount of li
ture on both topics, often addressing specific sub-domains such as climate change and glo
poverty (see for instance Sunstein, 2007 and Jamieson, 2014 in relation to climate chan
and Singer, 2009 and Lichtenberg, 2013 in relation to global poverty). I will not disc
motivational hurdles here (but see Di Paola, 2013). Nonetheless, I will keep some of them
consideration when discussing the role of virtues in the next section.
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
193
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
these sources, and so is any other agent. Across the global systems that g
ern our planet, causation is non-linear. The actions of billions of other peo
as well as various natural and social feedback effects of various magnitud
perturb the causal chains that run from my own actions to any specific per
cious ecological or social outcome (climate change and global poverty,
instance).9 Moreover, given the sheer scale of the quandaries in question, m
contribution to (or against) them can seemingly make no difference over
Finally, when I drive or buy certain goods, I certainly have no intention
doing any evil to anyone or anything: whatever harms or burdens are impo
onto people or nature, I certainly did not set out to impose them. All of th
tends to justify moral disengagement on my (and everyone else's) part.
These points create difficulties for both deontological and consequentiali
moral theories. The former are particularly troubled by lack of intentiona
and non-linear causal chains. To assign responsibility, deontologists typica
want to know whether the harms or burdens imposed were intended by age
(as opposed to merely foreseen, risked, allowed or enabled), and/or they wa
to know whether these harms or burdens were in fact brought about by agent
along a readable causal chain unequivocally connecting outcomes to actors.
Neither of these conditions apply when it comes to the global quandaries th
characterise the Anthropocene.
Consequentialist moral theories would struggle with the idea of assignin
responsibilities to individual agents whose actions cannot make any differe
overall (Glover, 1975; Parfit, 1984; Sinnott-Armstrong, 2005; Kagan, 2011
The global quandaries of the Anthropocene are just so vast that it does no
matter what I personally do: I do not personally cause them, nor can I pe
sonally fix them.10 In regards to causing them, in particular, the point is
that I am not part of the cause of, say, climate change: of course I am, inso
as I exercise geo-power by driving cars, eating steaks, taking long shower
etc. The point is rather that to be part of a cause is not to be the cause of
specific part of its effect, or any one of its many effects.11 The emissions p
duced by my car will cumulate with those of other billions of cars, travel acro
space-time, disperse into the workings and feedbacks of various physical an
chemical systems at different scales, and at no point ever cause any speci
flood, drought, species extinction or impose specific harms and burdens on
specific humans. The impacts of my geo-power do not harm or burden anyo
or anything in particular: at most, they lightly impinge on nature's future an
derivatively, on the fate of humanity. In this respect, individual responsibi
9. In connection with this see Sinnott- Armstrong, 2005; Gardiner, 2011; and Jamieson, 2
on climate change; Pogge, 2008 and Wenar, 201 1 on global poverty.
10. For an alternative view in relation to climate change see Di Paola, 2014.
1 1 . Sinnott- Armstrong makes this point in an online dialogue with A. Hiller, available at htt
www.philostv.com/avram-hiller-and-walter-sinnott-armstrong/
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
194
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
12. It still does exist, of course, in all red-handed cases. The latter continues to be very possible
and widely practised in the Anthropocene.
13. One way to do this would be by configuring a non-maximising (but rather systematically or
overall improving), non-act based (but rather practice-based) consequentialist theory. The
responsibility of those able to pay would then be not to maximise through each and all of
their actions the benefits accruing to the spatiotemporally distant, but rather to individuate
and engage in practices that benefit the spatiotemporally distant systematically or overall. I
have given a first presentation of these ideas in Di Paola, 2014, and I am further developing
them in an article entitled 'Practice consequentialism'. For a discussion of improving (or as
the authors dub it 'progressive') consequentialism, see Elliot and Jamieson, 2009.
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
195
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
Obligation - Agents can be held responsible for the fate of patients on other
grounds than what they did to (or can do for) them. They can also simply owe
it to patients that they do (or not do) certain things to (or for) them, just on the
grounds of the sorts of patients that these are - i.e., if and when they have some
intrinsic moral worth, and thus moral standing. Now, the relevant patients in
the Anthropocene are spatiotemporally distant humans (the global poor and
future generations) and non-human nature. Whether or not these peculiar pa-
tients can be rightful addressees of moral obligations is highly controversial.
In the case of the global poor, there is no doubt that they have moral standing
but determining what obligations the relatively affluent have towards them de-
pends on first resolving the issues of responsibility raised above. In the case of
non-human nature, the question is whether or not natural entities and systems
have moral standing at all, and thus whether or not they even qualify as right-
ful addressees of moral obligations. Future generations, for their part, may be
granted moral standing on grounds of their very humanity, or because future
well-being is not intrinsically less valuable than present well-being. But if that
means granting moral standing to specific future individuals (as granting mora
standing to the global poor means granting it to specific poor individuals across
the globe), then it is unclear whether, or at least how, consideration for their
fate should guide our present actions.
Consider first the idea that we have obligations towards nature, or elements
thereof. After a few decades of reflection, environmental ethics (at least in its
analytic incarnation) has produced strong arguments for the moral standing of
individual sentient animals (Singer, 1975), but only considerably more fragile
ones when it comes to plants (Taylor, 1986), species (Sarkar, 2005) and eco-
systems (Rolston III, 1994). These debates are still open and rich, of course,
but that only signals their complexity, and there is currently no promise of
breakthroughs.14 As things stand, our moral systems seem to tell us that we
have no decisive reason to believe that those elements of nature have moral
standing. If they do not, then they cannot count as legitimate addressees of any
moral obligations at all.
Eco-centric views may suggest that Earth, as such, has moral standing
- over and beyond, and perhaps independent of whether specific natural ele-
ments within its systems do. But even granting that, the notion that we may
have moral obligations towards the planet , as such, is implausible. One reason
for that is that personal responsibility of the agent (for harms and burdens
inflicted) and moral standing of the patient, while being logically distinct
grounds for ascribing obligations, are in fact intimately related. Even if the
planet has moral standing (a thought that needs much unpacking anyway), we
still cannot harm or burden the planet. Climate change, biodiversity loss and
whatever we may call the toughest ecological quandaries of our time are such
only for us humans (and many other species), but of no matter whatsoever to
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
196
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
197
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
whose very existence and identity depends on our choices being such as they
are. The existence and identity of particular future people is so dependent (
Parfit, 1984).
From all this, however, it need not follow that we have no obligations to
future people. It only follows that such obligations should not be to particular
future people. To that extent, my moral obligation in the Anthropocene sounds
quite peculiar: to steward humanity rather than particular humans. By human-
ity one may mean the species Homo sapiens (rather than particular specimens
of it); or those human features that enable and require us to relate morally as
fellows to whoever may happen to possess them (cf. L. Meyer, 2008); or again
the ongoing adventure of Homo sapiens on Earth (cf. Scheffler, 2013) - the
human practice of living in response to our needs and in pursuit of our aspira-
tions, as these have evolved up until today and may further evolve in the future
and as they are exemplified, often in widely different ways and combinations,
in and by each and every human specimen.17
Any way one chooses to go, it is clear that such peculiar obligation would
need much conceptual unpacking. At the same time, it is quite unclear what
practical directives it would deliver in real life. Moreover, the obligation to
steward humanity looks more like an aesthetic and/or perfectionist endeavour
than a moral one. Perhaps these distinctions are to some extent blurred by the
circumstances of the Anthropocene: but whether this is so, and the desirabil-
ity (both theoretical and practical) of such possible conclusion, remain open
questions.18
The last circumstance of the Anthropocene that I want to signal is quite obvi-
ous. The alleviation of the global ecological quandaries that characterise the
Anthropocene depends on us; at the same time, these quandaries are largely
brought about by us. The alleviation must thus perforce be homeopathic: hu-
mans must steward the congenial ecosystem ic conditions their very form of
life tends to disrupt.
What makes stewardship in the Anthropocene something of a curse is its
inherently self-contradictory and desperate nature. In order to defend congenial
ecosystemic conditions, thus defending ourselves from the threats connected
to a loss of their congeniality, we must in a sense defend ourselves from our-
selves, as such loss is anthropogenic. In fact, each individual would just do
best to self-regulate her geo-power to the point of minimising or even erasing
its impacts altogether (through offsetting perhaps - see Di Paola, 2014), thus
1 7. Not all human interests and cares are deserving of our stewardship: those that run contrary to
the Harm Principle, for instance, are not.
18. All those general statements obviously call for further and dedicated treatment. This is the
subject of an article I am currently working on entitled 'Stewarding humanity'.
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
198
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
199
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
distinctive of resolves is not the sorts of reasons for adopting them, but the fa
that their adoption entrenches such reasons, whatever they may be. Resolve
are intentions especially designed to stand firm in the face of contrary incli
tions, and their pursuit is non-contingent on the behaviour of others. In mod
cases, having resolved in favour of a certain course of action, I simply avo
reconsidering my stance (see Holton, 2009 for an extended discussion). This
a matter of character and strength of will, not obligation.
To develop relevant environmental virtues, one must resolve to practice
that are conductive to such development. One such practice is gardening - a
this is fortunate, because gardens are available to us even in cities. In fact
food-producing urban gardens/gardening seem distinctly apt contexts/pr
tices for the actualisation of that self-starting, self-regulating, individualise
metropolitan, networked ecosystem stewardship that, as I argued in sectio
1, point ii, is the form that environmental protection shall have to take in t
Anthropocene.19
My suggestion, then, is that the process of developing and exercisin
relevant environmental virtues by gardening will disclose, and enable the ex
ploration of, important sources and dimensions of meaning and value in a
for our lives in the Anthropocene. In particular, garden-based virtue-develo
ment will enable a deeper understanding and acceptance of our new station
within the wider workings of things (see Cooper, 2006; Harrison, 2009; Di
Paola, 2012) and the reaffirmation of the dignity of our humanity right in t
face of possible anthropogenic disaster. In what follows, I describe two gard
virtues that I believe will be of special relevance for the Anthropocene.
i) Mindfulness
A mindful agent takes account of and responsibility for the causal premis
and implications, however remote, of her behaviours. Most of our environ
mentally pernicious behaviours are commonplace, habitual and unthinking
These behaviours are nested in, and reinforce, ecologically unsustainab
economic, political, social and cultural infrastructures whose costs are pass
onto the spatiotemporally distant and the rest of nature. The mindful age
will consistently strive to locate her behaviours within said infrastructures
reconstructing the causal premises and anticipating the causal implications
of her taking a drive for pleasure, or of her fruit having been delivered fro
overseas. She will also take responsibility for the contribution of such cau
19. On urban gardening as a form of stewardship see Di Paola, 2012, particularly chapter
On the positive ecological impacts of urban gardening see Viljoen, 2005; Hester, 2006;
Cumberlidge and Musgrave, 2007; the WorldWatch Institute's State of the World 2011
chapter 10; and The Climate-Friendly Gardener report, produced by the Union of Concerne
Scientists and available at http://www.ucsusa.org/assets/documents/food_and_agriculture
climate-friendly-gardener.pdf. Other useful sources and case studies are available at http:/
www.iclei.org and http://www.urbanagricultureeurope.la.rwth-aachen.de
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
200
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
201
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
ii) Cheerfulness
The other virtue that I want to discuss is a behavioural and attitudinal response
to the homeopathic curse. It is learnt in gardens by pursuing the most mundan
of garden tasks: digging weeds. That is the very core of gardening, and es-
sential to it. There is no garden without weeds, as weeds spread thanks to the
gardener herself, who disseminates and nurtures them as she works the soil and
waters her plants. Weeds are the result and the signal of human presence and
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
202
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
activity: unless humans brought them there, there are no weeds in the 'w
They are rather found in gardens, cultivated fields, cities. If climate chang
the grand herald of the Anthropocene, weeds are its viral ground-troops
Meyer, 2006). For every weed that is pulled, others grow because the first
been pulled: seeds fly through the air, or chunks of roots remain in the soil a
harbour new sprouts. The gardener produces weeds by gardening; and bein
gardener, she must eliminate them. This is a self-contradictory and despe
task.
The battle against weeds is a defence of what is important to the gardener
in the face of a threat. Though the latter is disguised as an external threat, the
gardener is in fact defending her spaces and plants from herself - after all,
she is the demiurge of weeds. In defending her spaces and plants, she fully
acknowledges the threat posed by weeds. However, because that threat is not
brought by an external intrusion, but originates in her own practice, she is
wholly free to defend her spaces through that very same practice. In so doing,
and in doing so well, she masters her world, as it were: but only momentarily,
and then only seemingly, as weeds resume their growth the instant they are
pulled out and because they are pulled out. The battle against weeds is relent-
less and without end: there will not come a day when weeds will have been
permanently defeated, and the gardener's work will be done. To the contrary, a
day will inevitably come that the gardener will no longer be around, and weeds
will take over what once was hers.
If her practice is self-contradictory and desperate - then why, and in the
name of what, does a gardener act? Solely in her own name: she defends her
spaces and plants simply because they make her world better for her - no more,
but no less. To protect and promote such world, she must first accept the way
it works. Weeds are brought in by her; they will not go away by themselves;
and by getting them out of the way more will come. In the very act of weed-
ing, therefore, a gardener renounces the dream of an end-point to her toils,
and simply adheres to the way things work, accepting her station within them.
Her practice, self-contradictory and desperate as it is, once accepted as such
becomes cheerful in Democritus' sense: a force aiming at no set and final tar-
get - which is, for that very reason, self-propelling and thus ultimately free. A
resolute force, whose freedom and dignity resides precisely in its resoluteness
- in its being consistently and thoroughly applied, no matter what. In short,
a gardener knows the game cannot be won, but denies that this is enough to
disqualify her from playing it. By contesting what cannot be contested, she
reaffirms her freedom to do so, her ways of doing so, and the dignity of doing
so well. Such reaffirmation can be replicated at will, and the transient but mo-
mentarily pervasive satisfaction of a job well done is never foreclosed. This is
reason for cheerfulness.
Cheerfulness in the Anthropocene is thus not a negation but an embrace-
ment of the homeopathic curse. Much like a gardener pulling weeds, in order
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
203
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
CONCLUDING REMARKS
20. Note that this neither means that outcomes do not matter, nor that good outcomes
materialise even if their production is not the agent's primary focus (on the good outcom
urban gardening see note 21). See O'Neill, 2008 and Jamieson, 2014 for analogous foc
practice over outcome. On the notion of benefits internal to practices see Maclntyre, 1
and also Elster, 1985. On the notion of practice see Thompson, 2008.
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
204
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
REFERENCES
Cumberlidge, C., and L. Musgrave. 2007. Design and Landscape for People. London:
Thames and Hudson.
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
205
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
Jamieson, D. 2014. Reason in a Dark Time: Why the Struggle Against Climate Change
Failed, and What It Means for Our Future. New York: Oxford University Press.
CrossRef
Jamieson, D., and M. Di Paola. 2014. 'Climate change and global justice: New prob-
lem, old paradigm?'. Global Policy 5(1): 105-111. CrossRef
Kagan, S. 201 1 . 'Do I make a difference?'. Philosophy and Public Affairs 39: 105-141 .
CrossRef
Krakoff, S. 2011. 'Parenting the planet'. In D. Arnold (ed.), The Ethics of Global
Climate Change , pp. 145-169. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRef
Lichtenberg, J. 2013. Distant Strangers: Ethics, Psychology, and Global Poverty.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRef
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
206
MARCELLO DI PAOLA
O'Neill, J. 2008. 'Happiness and the good life'. Environmental Values 17 (2): 125-144.
CrossRef
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
207
VIRTUES FOR THE ANTHROPOCENE
Singer, P. 2009. The Life You Can Save. New York: Random House.
Sinnott- Armstrong, W. 2005. Tťs not my fault'. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong an
Howarth (eds), Perspectives on Climate Change , pp. 221-253. Amsterd
Elsevier.
Smith, B., and M. Zeder. 2013. The onset of the Anthropocene'. Anthropocene 4: 8-13.
Cross Ref
Southerton, D., H. Chappells and B. Van Vliet. 2004. Sustainable Consumption: The
Implications of Changing Infrastructures of Provision. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.
Steffen, W., J. Grinewald, P. Crutzen, and J. McNeill. 2011. The Anthropocene:
Conceptual and historical perspectives'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society A 369: 842-867. CrossRef
Stiglitz, J., A. Sen and J.-P. Fitoussi. 2009. Report by the Commission on the
Measurement of Economic Performance and Social Progress. Paris: CMEPSP.
Available at http://www.stiglitz-sen-fitoussi.fr/documents/rapport anglais.pdf
Sunstein, C. 2007. Worst Case Scenarios . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Taylor, P. 1986. Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Thompson, M. 2008. Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical
Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Van Vliet, B., H. Chappells, and E. Shove. 2005. Infrastructures of Consumption:
Environmental Innovation in the Utility Industries. London: Earthscan.
Viljoen, A. 2005. Continuous Productive Urban Landscapes. Oxford: Architectural
Press.
Zalasiewicz, J., C. Waters and M. Williams. 2014. 'Human bioturbation and the subter-
reanean landscape of the Anthropocene'. Anthropocene 6: 3-9. CrossRef
Zalasiewicz, J., M. Williams, W. Steffen and P. Crutzen. 2010. The new world of the
Anthropocene'. Environment Science & Technology 44 (7): 2228-2231. CrossRef
This content downloaded from 218.107.132.113 on Mon, 25 Jul 2022 17:03:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms