ART Eemeren 2015
ART Eemeren 2015
ART Eemeren 2015
DOI 10.1007/s10503-015-9377-z
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
2 F. H. van Eemeren
1 Introduction
1
The meta-theoretical starting points of pragma-dialectics, which serve as its methodological premises,
can in fact be seen as constructive responses to what we considered to be shortcomings of other
approaches (van Eemeren & Grootendorst, 1984, pp. 4–18; van Eemeren et al. 2014, pp. 523–527).
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 3
2
A critical discussion reflects the Socratic dialectical ideal of testing any form of conviction rationally,
not only descriptive statements but also value judgments and practical standpoints about actions.
3
The instrumentality of the rules for critical discussion in distinguishing counterproductive moves
demonstrates their ‘‘problem-validity’’ as a code of conduct (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1994). In
order to serve in practice as tools for resolving differences of opinion on the merits, the rules also need to
be ‘‘conventionally valid’’. van Eemeren et al. (2009) have shown that these standards of reasonableness
are to a large extent intersubjectively accepted and can therefore lay claim to conventional validity.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
4 F. H. van Eemeren
discourse can be most appropriately analysed from this perspective. The model also
serves a critical function by providing, through the rules for critical discussion, a
coherent set of norms for determining in which respects an argumentative move
deviates from the course that is conducive to resolving a difference of opinion on
the merits. Due to its heuristic, analytic and critical functions, the pragma-dialectical
model of a critical discussion constitutes an adequate basis for developing practical
guidelines for the conduct, analysis and evaluation of argumentative discourse.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 5
policy also applies to the reconstruction of unexpressed premises (van Eemeren and
Grootendorst 1992, pp. 60–72).
In order to investigate the connections of pragma-dialectics with argumentative
reality, empirical research is required. The ‘‘qualitative’’ empirical research we have
carried out has focused primarily on the way in which argumentative moves relevant
to a critical discussion manifest themselves in argumentative reality (van Eemeren
et al. 1993). In the Indicator Project, we systematically examined the clues for
reconstructing argumentative moves by means of qualitative empirical research (van
Eemeren et al. 2007). Our central goals were to identify the words and expressions
that arguers use to indicate the functions of the various moves they make, to classify
these moves in accordance with the argumentative functions they can have in the
various stages of the resolution process, and to determine under which conditions
they fulfil these functions. In examining systematically the ways in which
argumentative moves are realized in argumentative reality we took as our point
of departure the notion of ‘‘dialectical profiles’’, introduced by van Eemeren and
Houtlosser (2007). Dialectical profiles specify the kinds of moves that can be
instrumental in realizing the specific tasks of the discussants at a particular point in
the discussion and the ‘‘dialectical routes’’ in which these moves are included. The
dialectical routes are specifications of the series of ‘‘analytically relevant’’ moves
that can be made in the argumentative exchange that is portrayed.
To establish the necessary connection between the pragma-dialectical theory and
argumentative reality, since the mid-1980s we have also been engaged in
quantitative empirical research of an experimental nature. Initially this research
concentrated on the extent to which in argumentative reality the recognition of
argumentative moves is facilitated or hampered by factors in the presentation (e.g.,
van Eemeren et al. 1984, 1989, 2000). Next, the clues for the recognition of indirect
argumentation provided by the context were taken into account.
In order to determine the ‘‘intersubjective validity’’ of the pragma-dialectical
standards for critical discussion, in a comprehensive research project, Conceptions
of Reasonableness, we concentrated for more than 10 years on ordinary arguers’
assessments of argumentative moves. This resulted in the monograph Fallacies and
Judgments of Reasonableness (van Eemeren et al. 2009). The general aim of the
project was to check to what extent ordinary arguers judge the reasonableness of
argumentative moves according to norms that match the norms expressed in the
rules for critical discussion. The general conclusions that can be deduced from the
research results are that the pragma-dialectical discussion rules are intersubjectively
valid to quite a high degree and that there are no spectacular differences in degree of
intersubjective validity between the rules (van Eemeren et al. 2009, pp. 222–224).
Based on this indirect evidence, the rules may therefore lay claim to conventionally
validity, both individually and as a group.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
6 F. H. van Eemeren
After the standard theory had thus been consolidated, the pragma-dialectical
research has moved on from the ideal model of a critical discussion to the concrete
manifestations of the manifold practices of argumentative discourse. At the end of
the twentieth century, I set about, together with Houtlosser, to strengthen the
connection with argumentative reality in a fundamental way by including an
account of the ‘‘strategic design’’ of argumentative discourse in the theorizing (van
Eemeren 2010). The aim of including this vital but unexplored facet of
argumentative discourse in the theorizing was to extend the available analytic and
evaluative tools in such a way that more profound reconstructions and more realistic
assessments of argumentative discourse can be given, which can at the same time be
accounted for more thoroughly.4
Considering that for explaining the strategic design of argumentative discourse,
next to the dialectical dimension of reasonableness predominant in the standard
theory, the rhetorical dimension of effectiveness needed to be incorporated in the
theorizing, we started in the 1990s the Strategic Maneuvering Project (van Eemeren
and Houtlosser 2002). Our starting point was the ‘‘argumentative predicament’’ of
real-life argumentative discourse that, in every argumentative move that is made,
aiming for effectiveness and maintaining reasonableness always need to go together.
Because of the tension inherent in pursuing simultaneously these two objectives,
‘‘strategic maneuvering’’ is required to keep the balance. In case arguers in their
pursuit of effectiveness neglect their commitment to reasonableness and violate one
or more of the rules for critical discussion, their strategic maneuvering ‘‘derails’’
into fallaciousness (van Eemeren 2010, p. 198).
Adopting the theoretical notion of strategic maneuvering involves adding a
rhetorical dimension to the theoretical framework of pragma-dialectics. It is our
considered opinion that the dialectical and the rhetorical perspectives on argumen-
tative discourse are not incompatible, and can even be complementary (van
Eemeren 2013). In our view, studying the pursuit of rhetorical effectiveness in
argumentative discourse is in fact only worthwhile if it concerns effectiveness
reached within the boundaries of dialectical reasonableness, while setting dialectical
standards of reasonableness in argumentation theory is only of any practical
significance if it is combined with examining how rhetorical tools for achieving
effectiveness are brought to bear. This is why we think that the future of
argumentation theory lies in a constructive integration of the dialectical and the
rhetorical perspectives (van Eemeren 2010, pp. 87–92). In bringing about such an
integration in pragma-dialectics, the notion of strategic maneuvering is the primary
theoretical tool.5
4
Including an account of the strategic design in the theorizing is also helpful in developing more
sophisticated methods for improving the conduct of argumentative discourse, both orally and in writing.
5
Albeit in different ways, the rapprochement between dialectical and rhetorical approaches to
argumentation is also stimulated by communication scholars such as Wenzel (1990) and informal
logicians such as Tindale (2004).
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 7
6
The three hypotheses are closely connected with the theoretical views on the relationship between
reasonable argumentation and effectiveness in the sense of convincingness expounded in van Eemeren
and Grootendorst (1984).
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
8 F. H. van Eemeren
7
This type of effectiveness research constitutes the critically inspired pragma-dialectical complement to
the prevailing (non-dialectical) persuasion research. Our preference for the label ‘‘effectiveness research’’
rather than ‘‘persuasiveness research’’ is motivated by the fact that, unlike the term persuasiveness, the
term effectiveness is not exclusively connected with the argumentation stage but also pertains to
argumentative moves made in other discussion stages (e.g. proposing starting points, stating the outcome
of the discussion).
8
See the analysis of ‘‘interactional’’ (perlocutionary) effects in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984,
pp. 63–74) and van Eemeren (2010, pp. 36–39).
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 9
Because strategic maneuvering does not take part in an idealized critical discussion
but in the multi-varied communicative practices that have developed in argumen-
tative reality, in the extended pragma-dialectical theory due account needs to be
given of the macro-context of the institutional environment in which the
argumentative discourse takes place. We do so by relating our treatment of
strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse immediately to the ‘‘commu-
nicative activity types’’ that have established themselves in the various commu-
nicative domains in response to the institutional exigencies of the domain. These
communicative activity types have been conventionalized in accordance with the
needs of the institutional macro-context (van Eemeren 2010, pp. 129–162).10
It is through the use of the appropriate ‘‘genres’’ of communicative activity,11
varying from adjudication in the legal domain and deliberation in the political domain
to disputation in the academic domain, that communicative activity types are designed
to serve their rationale: the ‘‘institutional point’’ reflecting the exigency in response to
which the activity type has come into being. The institutional point of a parliamentary
debate, for instance, is reaching a well-considered decision on a policy proposal. To
complicate matters, in realizing the institutional point of ‘‘hybrid’’ communicative
activity types several genres of conventionalized communicative activity are activated
together. In a political interview, for instance, deliberation is intrinsically combined
with disseminating information to realize the institutional point of enlightening the
audience or readership (van Eemeren to be published).
The way in which communicative activity types are conventionalized to make
their institutional point can be explicit and highly formalised in constitutive and
regulative rules, as is usual in adjudication in the legal domain. The convention-
alization may also be partly implicit and formalised to a lesser degree in looser
regulations of some kind, as is often the case in deliberation in the political domain.
The conventionalization might even be only informal and simply reflect established
practices, as is customary in communion-seeking in the interpersonal domain.
The next step we had to take in our research program was to explore the
consequences engaging in a particular communicative type has for the conduct of
9
Both in the original test and in the replication straightforward abusive attacks are consistently rejected
as unreasonable discussion moves and legitimate personal attacks are invariably considered reasonable.
The ‘‘disguised’’ abusive attacks presented as responses to a wrong use of authority however are judged as
substantially less unreasonable than the overtly fallacious direct attacks.
10
Communicative activity types are in pragma-dialectics defined as communicative practices whose
conventionalization serves the specific communicative needs instigated by the institutional exigencies of
a certain domain (van Eemeren 2010, pp. 139–145).
11
Fairclough characterizes a ‘‘genre’’ of communicative activity broadly as ‘‘a socially ratified way of
using language in connection with a particular type of social activity’’ (1995, p. 14).
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
10 F. H. van Eemeren
argumentative discourse (van Eemeren 2010, pp. 144–159). The ideal model of a
critical discussion can be instrumental in characterizing the particular ways in
which, depending on the specific institutional requirements that must be fulfilled,
the argumentative dimension is substantiated in the various communicative activity
types. Using the model of a critical discussion in all cases as the analytical point of
reference not only ensures a coherent and consistent appreciation of the
argumentative dimension, but it also creates unity in the comparison between
different communicative activity types.12
Taking the four stages of a critical discussion as the point of departure, four focal
points can be identified that need to be taken into account in an argumentative
characterization of a specific communicative activity type (van Eemeren 2010,
p. 146).13 These four focal points are the empirical counterparts of the four stages of
the process of resolving a difference of opinion in contextualized argumentative
discourse: the initial situation (confrontation stage), the starting points (opening
stage), the argumentative means and criticisms (argumentation stage), and the
outcome of the exchange (concluding stage). Starting from this division helps us to
determine in the argumentative characterization in what way exactly the constitutive
stages of the process of resolving a difference of opinion on the merits are
represented in a certain communicative activity type.
Because communicative activity types impose certain extrinsic constraints on the
possibilities for strategic maneuvering, it is necessary to take the conventionaliza-
tion of the communicative activity type in which the argumentative discourse takes
place into account when analyzing and evaluating strategic maneuvering. Together,
the institutional point and the conventionalization determine the ‘‘institutional
preconditions’’ for strategic maneuvering in a particular communicative activity
type. In pragma-dialectics we distinguish between ‘‘primary’’ institutional precon-
ditions, which are as a rule official, usually formal, and often procedural, and
‘‘secondary’’ institutional preconditions, which are as a rule unofficial, usually
informal, and often substantial (van Eemeren and Garssen 2010, 2011).
As is indicated by the conventionalization determining the institutional
preconditions, in a particular communicative activity type certain modes of
strategic maneuvering will be suitable—or not suitable, as the case may be—to
realizing the institutional point of the activity type. Since an argumentative
characterization of the communicative activity type makes clear in what way
exactly the argumentative discourse is conventionalized to serve the institutional
point of the activity type, this characterization provides an appropriate point of
departure for tracing methodically the ways in which the possibilities for strategic
maneuvering are in practice affected by the communicative activity type.
From communicative activity type to communicative activity type the scope of
the possibilities available for strategic maneuvering in each of the empirical
counterparts of the critical discussion stages may vary. In some communicative
12
Diversity is then not the relativistic point of departure, but a reality-based outcome of a systematic
comparison of the various manifestations of argumentative reality.
13
An argumentative characterization of a communicative activity type is only worthwhile when it is
inherently, essentially or predominantly argumentative or argumentation incidentally plays an important
part.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 11
activity types, for instance, the participants will be allowed more room for defining
the initial situation in accordance with their own preferences than in others. A
similar variety may exist with regard to the choice of procedural and material
starting points, the choice of argumentative means and kinds of criticism, and the
outcomes of the argumentative exchange. In each particular case, all three aspects of
strategic maneuvering can be affected by the need to comply with the institutional
preconditions (van Eemeren 2010, pp. 93–127). There may be constraints on the
topical choices that are allowed, on the adaptation to audience demand that is
regarded appropriate, and on the presentational devices that are permitted. Although
these constraints are in principle a limitation of the possibilities for strategic
maneuvering, they may also create special opportunities for strategic maneuvering
to some of the participants.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
12 F. H. van Eemeren
The initial situation in the communicative activity types that have come into being
in the various communicative domains revolves around different kinds of
differences of opinion. The types of standpoints at issue vary from evaluative and
14
Still other pragma-dialectical research projects focus on argumentative discourse in Dutch Parliament
(Plug 2010, 2011) and the use of pragmatic argumentation in lawmaking debates in British Parliament
(Ihnen Jory 2010, 2012).
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 13
15
In the subtypes of the argument schemes used in the various subtypes of a certain type of
argumentation the critical questions pertaining to that scheme will be specified in somewhat different
ways.
16
The relevant critical questions need to be envisaged in the implementation pertinent to the use of the
argument scheme concerned in the specific macro-context of the communicative activity type.
17
It depends on the micro-, meso-, macro- and intertextual context, the logical and pragmatic inferences
that can be drawn and the available general and specific background information (van Eemeren 2010,
pp. 17–19), which particular critical questions are by institutional convention required to be answered in a
certain communicative activity type.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
14 F. H. van Eemeren
legal verdict.18 This means that in such a case the specific types of critical questions
are pertinent that are associated with symptomatic argumentation and analogy
argumentation. In the political domain, in an argumentative exchange taking place
in the communicative activity type of a parliamentary debate, the use of
‘‘pragmatic’’ argumentation is a characteristic way to defend a policy standpoint,
and the pertinent critical questions can be specified accordingly.19 In the academic
domain, in an argumentative exchange taking place in the communicative activity
type of a scientific discussion, using certain subtypes of ‘‘causal’’ argumentation is a
characteristic way to establish the truth of a scientific claim, and the pertinent
critical questions are those associated with the particular (sub)type of causal
argumentation that is used.20
In conducting an argumentative exchange, the arguers are supposed to take the
institutional preconditions of the communicative type and the critical reactions into
account that are pertinent in the communicative activity type concerned when a
certain argument scheme is being used. Doing so will result in the creation of what I
have named a specific argumentative pattern in the discourse (van Eemeren to be
published).21 Such an argumentative pattern is characterized by a constellation of
argumentative moves in which, in order to deal with a particular kind of difference
of opinion, in defence of a particular type of standpoint a particular argument
scheme or combination of argument schemes is used in a particular kind of
argumentation structure.22 Next to relatively simple, ‘‘basic’’ argumentative
patterns, covering only the first level of defence of a standpoint by the main
argument or main arguments, in analysing argumentative practices more elaborated
argumentative patterns can be distinguished, covering also further levels of defence
and having varying degrees of complexity.23
18
Then it is first argued by means of symptomatic argumentation that dealing with a case in a certain
way is justified because it is covered by a certain rule, and next by analogy argumentation that the case is
similar to other cases to which the rule applies. Whether the symptomatic argumentation is supported by
analogy argumentation or by some other type of argumentation depends on the kind of problem that needs
to be solved. If a decision is to be made that requires a judge to make an exception to a general rule,
pragmatic argumentation can be instrumental.
19
Then it is argued by means of the pragmatic subtype of causal argumentation that a measure should be
taken because it will lead to a result the acceptability of which is beyond any doubt. If the acceptability
needs to be motivated all the same, this can most simply be done by means of ‘‘symptomatic’’
argumentation. However, when such support is necessary, the argumentation loses its pragmatic force of
straightforward effectiveness.
20
Then it is argued by means of a certain subtype of causal argumentation that a thesis should be
accepted because it is based on an established causal relationship.
21
The occurrence an argumentative pattern can be explained by taking account of the institutional point
and the institutional preconditions for strategic maneuvering in the (cluster of) communicative activity
type(s) concerned in combination with the critical questions pertaining to the argument schemes that are
used and the way in which the responses to these critical questions are supposed to hang together.
22
The argumentative patterns that can be observed in argumentative discourse can be viewed as
empirical analogues of the patterns of analytically relevant moves in a critical discussion that are on
theoretical grounds distinguished in dialectical profiles. For the notion of a dialectical profile see van
Eemeren (2010, pp. 98–100).
23
The term level of defense refers to the distinction between the defense of a main standpoint (first level),
the defense of (a reason serving as) a substandpoint (second level), the defense of (a reason for a reason
serving as) a subsubstandpoint (third level), etc. (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992, Chapter 7).
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 15
24
In speaking of a prototypical argumentative pattern I refer to a pattern that is characteristic of the
communicative activity type in which it occurs because it is pre-eminently instrumental in realizing the
institutional point of the communicative activity type. It stands to reason that it may be expected that in
practice such an instrumental argumentative pattern will indeed be found in specimens of the
communicative activity type. However, being prototypical does not necessarily mean that the pattern
occurs frequently in this communicative activity type, let alone that it will always be present. If one thinks
that the term prototypical is too strongly connected with absolute or relative frequency, it can be replaced
by the term characteristic or some other term that does not carry this quantitative connotation.
25
The underlying assumption is that in principle protagonists may be supposed to aim for making the
strongest case in the macro-context concerned by trying to advance a combination of reasons that will
satisfy the antagonist through leaving no critical doubts unanswered, using the argument schemes they
consider most effective in the situation at hand and advancing all multiple, coordinative and subordinative
argumentation necessary to respond to the critical reactions the antagonist may be expected to come up
with.
26
Identifying prototypical argumentative patterns makes clear what kind of evaluation is required in
assessing the argumentative discourse concerned and what exactly this evaluation involves. In addition,
prototypical argumentative patterns can be helpful in teaching arguers how to conduct certain
argumentative practices.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
16 F. H. van Eemeren
Let us now turn to the specific theme of this special issue: argumentative patterns
with pragmatic argumentation as a main argument. According to the pragma-
dialectical approach, argument (sub)schemes are to be distinguished from each
27
Thus I have made a terminological distinction between prototypical argumentative patterns
characteristically used in realizing the institutional point of a certain communicative activity type and
stereotypical argumentative patterns, which are not only prototypical but also occur frequently in the
communicative activity type concerned. Generally, prototypical argumentative patterns can be brought to
light by means of qualitative empirical research; stereotypical argumentative patterns can only be
detected by means of quantitative research.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 17
other when, due to the critical questions pertinent to the argument (sub)scheme, they
initiate a dialectical route in argumentative discourse that is different from the
dialectical routes initiated by other (sub)schemes. Pragmatic argumentation is a
subtype of causal argumentation because the pertinent critical questions are in some
sense specifications of the critical questions pertinent to the general argument
scheme of causal argumentation.
In pragmatic argumentation the standpoint that an action should be carried out (or
should not be carried out) is defended by pointing out that the result of carrying out
this action is desirable (or that the result of carrying out this action is undesirable).
The ‘‘positive’’ variant of pragmatic argumentation defends a positive standpoint
(‘‘Action X should be carried out’’), the ‘‘negative’’ variant defends a negative
standpoint (‘‘Action X should not be carried out’’). The pragma-dialectical
definition of the argument scheme of pragmatic argumentation in its positive
version is as follows:
1 Standpoint Action X should be carried out
1.1 Because Action X will lead to positive result Y
(1.1’) And (Actions of type X [such as X] that lead to positive results of type
Y [such as Y] must be carried out)
Argumentation that is pragmatic is to be evaluated in accordance with the critical
questions pertinent to the specification of the argument scheme of causal
argumentation in this subscheme. This results in the following critical questions:
As in other cases, the way in which these critical questions are implemented
depends on the context of the communicative activity type in which the pragmatic
argumentation concerned is used. If, when pragmatic argumentation has been
advanced, certain critical questions are anticipated or responded to in the discourse,
more complex argumentation will come into being, with a more complicated
argumentation structure.
If in a certain argumentative practice the circumstances in which pragmatic
argumentation occurs call for it, the list of critical questions must sometimes be
expanded. As a sequel to question (a), for instance, the question can then be asked
whether result Y could not be achieved more easily or more economically by other
actions. As a sequel to question (b), the question can be asked whether another result
(of type Z) would not be even more positive (i.e., more desirable) than results of
type Y, such as Y. As a sequel to question (c), the question can be asked whether the
negative (i.e., undesirable) side-effects can be prevented or suppressed, etc.
Depending on the exigencies of the macro-context, in the various kinds of
argumentative practices the critical questions (a), (b) and (c) may be asked and
responded to—or anticipated and responded to. This does not mean, however, that
all these critical questions will always be dealt with. In some cases it will be
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
18 F. H. van Eemeren
unnecessary to deal with a certain critical question because it is already clear that
there is mutual agreement about the answer. It may also be the case that a particular
critical question is not explicitly dealt with—or is explicitly dealt with—for
rhetorical reasons of effectiveness. The same might apply to the critical questions
added to the list because of the need for expansions motivated by the circumstances
in which the argumentation occurs. In all cases, when they are implemented in a
particular activity type the general critical questions need to be specified, amended
and supplemented in accordance with the institutional requirements of the macro-
context.
It is a distinctive feature of pragmatic argumentation that it can only be
instrumental in offering conclusive support of a prescriptive standpoint if, in the
case of a positive standpoint, the positive character (i.e., desirability) of the result
that is aimed for is clearly beyond doubt (or, in the case of a negative standpoint, the
negative character, i.e., undesirability). In a political macro-context, for instance,
the positive character of the result that is, according to the standpoint, to be achieved
is often evident. Who would, for instance, object to the proposal of a policy measure
leading to higher employment rates? If, for some reason or other, to some or all of
the addressees the desirability of the result is not so obvious, this desirability needs
to be motivated. However, when the desirability of the action that is proposed is no
longer beyond doubt, the argument loses its pragmatic force.
In the macro-contexts of the legal domain it is generally a necessary requirement
that the desirability of the action that is proposed will be explicitly motivated. In the
political domain it may happen that it is not the positive value of the result to be
achieved by the action (i.e., its desirability) as such that is at issue, but the relative
value of this result compared with another result, which could be achieved by taking
another action. This can, for example, be the case when the actions concerned have
different positions in the existing value hierarchy or when the parties involved in the
discussion favour different value hierarchies. The latter occurs, for instance, when
for the protagonist fighting unemployment is the main problem while the audience
(or a relevant part of the audience) considers putting an end to the budget deficit
more important.28
Because of their relevance to the acceptance of the argumentation, the critical
questions pertaining to pragmatic argumentation are likely to be anticipated in the
discourse. This applies, of course, in the first place to the critical questions (in their
specific contextual implementation) that are most pertinent in the institutional
context in which the discourse takes place. In argumentative discourse taking place
in communicative activity types in domains in which pragmatic argumentation is
pre-eminently called for, such as the political domain and the legal domain, such
anticipation of pertinent critical questions is likely to be expected. Due to the need
to satisfy the institutional preconditions and to respond to the critical questions that
are to be anticipated, the prototypical argumentative patterns coming into being in
these domains may involve a combination of pragmatic argumentation with other
28
This may in the cases concerned lead to an amendment of the first critical question going with
pragmatic argumentation so that is made relative to achieving some other result: ‘‘Is the result Y’ really
more positive, i.e., more desirable, than positive result Z’, so that actions are preferable that lead to
achieving the latter?’’.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 19
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
20 F. H. van Eemeren
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 21
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0
International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, dis-
tribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original
author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were
made.
References
Andone, C. 2013. Argumentation in political interviews. Analyzing and evaluating responses to
accusations of inconsistency. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Fairclough, N. 1995. Critical discourse analysis. The critical study of language. London: Longman Group
Limited.
Feteris, E.T. 2009. Strategic maneuvering in the justification of judicial decisions. In Examining
argumentation in context: Fifteen studies on strategic maneuvering, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, 93–114.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Ihnen Jory, C. 2010. The analysis of pragmatic argumentation in law-making debates: Second reading of
the terrorism bill in the British House of Commons. Controversia 7(1): 91–107.
Ihnen Jory, C. 2012. Analysing and evaluating pragmatic argumentation in lawmaking debates:
Institutional constraints on pragmatic argumentation in the British parliament. Unpublished
doctoral dissertation University of Amsterdam.
Labrie, N. 2012. Strategic maneuvering in treatment decision-making discussions. Two cases in point.
Argumentation 26(2): 171–199.
Lewinski, M. 2010. Internet political discussion forums as an argumentative activity type. A pragma-
dialectical analysis of online forms of strategic manoeuvring with critical reactions. Unpublished
doctoral dissertation University of Amsterdam.
Mohammed, D. 2009. ‘‘The honourable gentleman should make up his mind’’. Strategic manoeuvring
with accusations of inconsistency in Prime Minister’s Question Time. Unpublished doctoral
dissertation University of Amsterdam.
Pilgram, R. 2015. A doctor’s argument by authority. An analytical and empirical study of strategic
manoeuvring in medical consultation. Unpublished doctoral dissertation University of Amsterdam.
Plug, H.J. 2010. Ad-hominem arguments in Dutch and European parliamentary debates: Strategic
manoeuvring in an institutional context. In Discourse and metadiscourse in parliamentary debates,
ed. C. Ilie, 305–328. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Plug, H.J. 2011. Parrying ad-hominem arguments in parliamentary debates. In Proceedings of the 7th
conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, B.J.
Garssen, D. Godden and G. Mitchell, ch. 138, 1570–1578. Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat. CD-rom.
Snoeck Henkemans, A.F. 2011. Shared medical decision-making: Strategic maneuvering by doctors in
the presentation of their treatment preferences to patients. In Proceedings of the 7th conference of
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
22 F. H. van Eemeren
the International Society for the Study of Argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, B.J. Garssen, D.
Godden and G. Mitchell, ch. 162, 1811–1818. Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat. CD-rom.
Tindale, C.W. 2004. Rhetorical argumentation. Principles of theory and practice. Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Tonnard, Y.M. 2011. Getting an issue on the table. A pragma-dialectical study of presentational choices
in confrontational strategic maneuvering in Dutch parliamentary debate. Unpublished doctoral
dissertation University of Amsterdam.
Toulmin, S.E. 2003. The uses of argument. Updated ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1st ed.
1958).
van Eemeren, F.H. 1986. Dialectical analysis as a normative reconstruction of argumentative discourse.
Text 6(1): 1–16.
van Eemeren, F.H. 1987. Argumentation studies’ five estates. In Argument and critical practices.
Proceedings of the fifth SCA/AFA conference on argumentation, ed. J.W. Wenzel, 9–24. Annandale,
VA: Speech Communication Association.
van Eemeren, F.H. 2002. Democracy and argumentation. Controversia 1(1): 69–84.
van Eemeren, F.H. 2010. Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Extending the pragma-
dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
van Eemeren, F.H. 2013. In what sense do modern argumentation theories relate to Aristotle? The case of
pragma-dialectics. Argumentation 27(1): 49–70.
van Eemeren, F.H. to be published. Pragmatic argumentation in stereotypical argumentative patterns. In
Practical argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, E. Rigotti, A. Rocci, and D. Walton. Amsterdam-
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
van Eemeren, F.H., and B. Garssen. 2010. In varietate concordia—United in diversity: European
parliamentary debate as an argumentative activity type. Controversia 7(1): 19–37.
van Eemeren, F.H., and B. Garssen. 2011. Exploiting the room for strategic maneuvering in
argumentative discourse. Dealing with audience demand in the European Parliament. In Exploring
argumentative contexts, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and B. Garssen. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John
Benjamins.
van Eemeren, F.H., and B. Garssen. 2014. Argumentation by analogy in stereotypical argumentative
patterns. In Systematic approaches to argument by analogy, ed. H. Jales Ribeiro, 41–56. Dordrecht:
Springer.
van Eemeren, F.H., B. Garssen, E.C.W. Krabbe, A.F. Snoeck Henkemans, B. Verheij, and J.H.M.
Wagemans. 2014. Handbook of argumentation theory. Dordrecht etc.: Springer.
van Eemeren, F.H., B. Garssen, and H.L.M. Meuffels. 2009. Fallacies and judgments of reasonableness.
Empirical research concerning the pragma-dialectical discussion rules. Dordrecht: Springer.
van Eemeren, F.H., B. Garssen, and B. Meuffels. 2012a. Effectiveness through reasonableness.
Preliminary steps to pragma-dialectical effectiveness research. Argumentation 26(1): 33–53.
van Eemeren, F.H., B. Garssen, and B. Meuffels. 2012b. The disguised abusive ad hominem empirically
investigated. Strategic maneuvering with direct personal attacks. Thinking & Reasoning 18(3):
344–364.
van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1984. Speech acts in argumentative discussions. A theoretical
model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Berlin: de
Gruyter.
van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1992. Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-
dialectical perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1994. Rationale for a pragma-dialectical perspective. In Studies
in pragma-dialectics, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and R. Grootendorst, 11–28. Amsterdam: Sic Sat.
van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-
dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, S. Jackson, and S. Jacobs. 1993. Reconstructing argumentative
discourse. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.
van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, and B. Meuffels. 1984. Het identificeren van enkelvoudige
argumentatie [Identifying single argumentation]. Tijdschrift voor Taalbeheersing 6(4): 297–310.
van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, and B. Meuffels. 1989. The skill of identifying argumentation.
Journal of the American Forensic Association 25(4): 239–245.
van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2002. Strategic maneuvering: Maintaining a delicate balance. In
Dialectic and rhetoric: The warp and woof of argumentation analysis, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and P.
Houtlosser, 131–159. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Identifying Argumentative Patterns: A Vital Step in the… 23
van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2007. Seizing the occasion. Parameters for analysing ways of
strategic manoeuvring. In Proceedings of the sixth conference of the International Society for the
Study of Argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, J.A. Blair, C.A. Willard and B. Garssen, 375–380.
Amsterdam: Sic Sat.
van Eemeren, F.H., P. Houtlosser, and A.F. Snoeck Henkemans. 2007. Argumentative indicators in
discourse. A pragma-dialectical study. Dordrecht: Springer.
van Eemeren, F.H., B. Meuffels, and M. Verburg. 2000. The (un)reasonableness of the argumentum ad
hominem. Language and Social Psychology 19(4): 416–435.
van Poppel, L. 2013. Getting the vaccine now will protect you in the future! A pragma-dialectical analysis
of strategic maneuvering with pragmatic argumentation in health brochures. Unpublished doctoral
dissertation University of Amsterdam.
Wagemans, J.H.M. 2011. The assessment of argumentation from expert opinion. Argumentation 25(3):
329–339.
Wenzel, J.W. 1990. Three perspectives on argument: Rhetoric, dialectic, logic. In Perspectives on
argumentation: Essays in the honor of Wayne Brockriede, ed. R. Trapp, and J. Schuetz, 9–26.
Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland.
Wierda, R. 2015. Strategic maneuvering with authority argumentation in direct-to-consumer medical
advertisements. An analytical and experimental study into authority argumentation relying on
experience expertise. Unpublished doctoral dissertation University of Amsterdam.
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Terms and Conditions
Springer Nature journal content, brought to you courtesy of Springer Nature Customer Service Center
GmbH (“Springer Nature”).
Springer Nature supports a reasonable amount of sharing of research papers by authors, subscribers
and authorised users (“Users”), for small-scale personal, non-commercial use provided that all
copyright, trade and service marks and other proprietary notices are maintained. By accessing,
sharing, receiving or otherwise using the Springer Nature journal content you agree to these terms of
use (“Terms”). For these purposes, Springer Nature considers academic use (by researchers and
students) to be non-commercial.
These Terms are supplementary and will apply in addition to any applicable website terms and
conditions, a relevant site licence or a personal subscription. These Terms will prevail over any
conflict or ambiguity with regards to the relevant terms, a site licence or a personal subscription (to
the extent of the conflict or ambiguity only). For Creative Commons-licensed articles, the terms of
the Creative Commons license used will apply.
We collect and use personal data to provide access to the Springer Nature journal content. We may
also use these personal data internally within ResearchGate and Springer Nature and as agreed share
it, in an anonymised way, for purposes of tracking, analysis and reporting. We will not otherwise
disclose your personal data outside the ResearchGate or the Springer Nature group of companies
unless we have your permission as detailed in the Privacy Policy.
While Users may use the Springer Nature journal content for small scale, personal non-commercial
use, it is important to note that Users may not:
1. use such content for the purpose of providing other users with access on a regular or large scale
basis or as a means to circumvent access control;
2. use such content where to do so would be considered a criminal or statutory offence in any
jurisdiction, or gives rise to civil liability, or is otherwise unlawful;
3. falsely or misleadingly imply or suggest endorsement, approval , sponsorship, or association
unless explicitly agreed to by Springer Nature in writing;
4. use bots or other automated methods to access the content or redirect messages
5. override any security feature or exclusionary protocol; or
6. share the content in order to create substitute for Springer Nature products or services or a
systematic database of Springer Nature journal content.
In line with the restriction against commercial use, Springer Nature does not permit the creation of a
product or service that creates revenue, royalties, rent or income from our content or its inclusion as
part of a paid for service or for other commercial gain. Springer Nature journal content cannot be
used for inter-library loans and librarians may not upload Springer Nature journal content on a large
scale into their, or any other, institutional repository.
These terms of use are reviewed regularly and may be amended at any time. Springer Nature is not
obligated to publish any information or content on this website and may remove it or features or
functionality at our sole discretion, at any time with or without notice. Springer Nature may revoke
this licence to you at any time and remove access to any copies of the Springer Nature journal content
which have been saved.
To the fullest extent permitted by law, Springer Nature makes no warranties, representations or
guarantees to Users, either express or implied with respect to the Springer nature journal content and
all parties disclaim and waive any implied warranties or warranties imposed by law, including
merchantability or fitness for any particular purpose.
Please note that these rights do not automatically extend to content, data or other material published
by Springer Nature that may be licensed from third parties.
If you would like to use or distribute our Springer Nature journal content to a wider audience or on a
regular basis or in any other manner not expressly permitted by these Terms, please contact Springer
Nature at