Smith Conceptlegitimacy 1970
Smith Conceptlegitimacy 1970
Smith Conceptlegitimacy 1970
Author(s): R. W. SMITH
Source: Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory , October 1970, No. 35 (October
1970), pp. 17-29
Published by: Berghahn Books
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theoria: A Journal of
Social and Political Theory
by R. W. SMITH
The validity of
1. Rational g
patterns of n
authority und
2. Traditional
sanctity of im
status of tho
authority); or
3. Charismatic
exceptional s
individual pe
revealed or or
Rational - Lega
Rational-legal
in which obed
order. To a lar
There is, in p
status : the per
his delineated s
with no more
separate from
regarded as a
the individual
requires long p
bureaucratic ca
is a normal ca
Remuneration
treasury. In W
other type of o
and reliability.
Some of the c
dency toward
promotion of
Weber's view, t
communicatio
Traditional Auth
In a tradition
person of the c
of authority.
personal order,
accustomed obl
either of two
Charismatic Authority 10
In the beginning charismatic authority is highly unstructured,
being identified not with a society, but with an individual. The
charismatic leader is set apart from ordinary men by what is re-
garded as exceptional, if not supernatural, qualities. His charisma is
dependent on its recognition by members of society, but he always
regards those who ignore or deny his powers as delinquent in moral
duty. But if proof of his qualifications fails, if he is for long un-
successful, it is likely that his charismatic authority will disappear.
The charismatic leader is a revolutionary, setting his personal legiti-
macy against that of the institutionalized order. He preaches, creates,
or demands personal trust in him and his revelation. If he is success-
ful, there will result a radical alteration of attitudes, a new orientation
towards the world.
The administrative staff is chosen in terms of their own charis-
matic qualities; they are not officials, but disciples. 'There is no such
thing as "appointment" or "dismissal", no career, no promotion.
There is only a "call" at the instance of the leader on the basis of
charismatic qualifications of those he summons.' There is no hier-
archy - the leader may intervene at any moment. There are no rules
of a formal kind; rather there is the pattern of 'It is written . . . , but
I say unto you . . . '. There is no definite sphere of authority and
competence; no salary or benefice. The disciples tend to live in a
communistic r
order, living f
tional or ration
income by con
Charismatic a
the routine and
both rational
bound to analy
precedents tho
however, is for
personal char
and trust.
Charismatic au
exists only as
prophetic reli
in their early
established, or
gives way to t
that then driv
charismatic au
the part of th
existence and
blems are solv
traditional or r
trate how this is so : If the new leader is chosen on the basis of lots or
oracles, his legitimacy is dependent on the technique of selection,
which involves a form of legalization. If the leader is chosen, like
the Dalai Lama, on the basis of certain qualities which mean he is the
reincarnation of the original leader, then there is a bias in favor of
traditionalism. Similar examples could be given for the administra-
tive staff. But for the most part, a combination of the two types of
authority is likely to result.
contribute to t
leaders appear
nothing but a f
lem of how ch
What is neede
problem of le
authorities, th
will 'significa
ready to give
he thinks, help
Such an analy
of authority
analysis. By c
members of t
image of the a
Up to a certa
pectations may
point, then a
actually take p
plish the task.
tance between
dissemination
The 'discrepan
does provide a
dex brings tog
social structur
system. By con
'we have a met
of these multi
Easton is corr
in his belief
analysis. Easto
mars his own
this were a ch
legitimacy. In
procedural mat
tional system
necessarily me
to measure the
Weber's analys
The Parsons C
By far the mo
each type of le
seems necessar
the legal : the
cannot be red
the man of kn
to base the wo
case, unfortun
of the Stoics,
structuring of
who believed
over what is la
bility between
to reject the
the charisma
unlike the dem
not personal,
rational term
course, does no
'crimes of pas
'crimes of logi
Weber is at le
if not of its ef
Rousseau thou
imposed the l
here, of cours
ideas which t
procity, self-r
subject under
charismatic lea
presents us wi
from the mass
consent to tha
seems not to
university and
rule, but rathe
rejected in fa
new form of l
is involved, in
pation can ta
content of m
few) begin to
occurs: since
it were, from
society, the la
macy along no
attempt to imp
and that is w
theory might
Weber remark
ten, twenty, f
it is the very m
Yet Weber's th
conception of
and utility tha
who are sharp
end up, wheth
rather than o v
Binder, have
limited in imp
results with th
what we now
Weber; buildi
College of Wil
Virginia , U.S.
REFERENCES
18 Ibid., p. 213.
19 Ibid., p. 211.
20 Cf. Robert A. Dahl, Modern Political A
Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1963), p. 30.
21 Tocqueville s remark in Democracy in Am
York: Vintage, 1954), Vol. 1, p. 258, is inte
passing from a free country into one which is
the change; in the former all is bustle and a
seems calm and motionless. In the one, am
topics of inquiry; in the other, it seems as i
repose in the enjoyment of advantages alread
22 Cf. Jean Piaget, The Moral Judgement of t
(New York: Free Press, 1965).
23 Op. cit., p. 30.
24 The Theory of Social and Economic Organization . dd. 124-27. 324-27.
25 Ibid., pp. 130-31.
26 Ibid., pp. 115-18.
27 Albert Camus, The Rebel: An Essay on Man in Revolt, trans. Anthony Bower
(New York: Vintage, 1956).
28 See Piaget, op. cit.
29 Weber, 'Religious Rejections of the World and Their Directions', in H. H.
Gerth and C. Wright Mills, ed., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology
(New York: Oxford University Press. 1958). o. 334.
30 Weber, The Sociology of Religion, p. 117.
31 Weber, 'Science As A Vocation', in Gerth and Mills, op. cit., d. 138.
32 See, for example, Dolf Sternberger, op. cit. ; Guglielmo Ferrero, The Principles
of Power (New York: Putnam, 1942); Carl Schmitt, Legalitat und Legitimität
(Munich: Duncker & Humblot, 1932).
33 Carl Joachim Friedrich, Man and His Government: An Empirical Theory of
Politics (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1963), Ch. 13.
34 Leonard Binder, Iran: Political Development in a Changing Society (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1962), Ch. 2.