RH3403 02 Sgarbi
RH3403 02 Sgarbi
RH3403 02 Sgarbi
This research has been possible thanks to the ERC Starting Grant 2013, n. 335949
“Aristotle in the Italian Vernacular: Rethinking Renaissance and Early-Modern Intel-
lectual History (c. 1400–c. 1650)”.
1
On Robortello cf. G.G. Liruti, Notizie delle vite ed opere scritte da’ letterati del Friuli
(Venezia: Fenzo, 1762), vol. 2, 413–483; B. Weinberg, “Robortello on the Poetics,” in
Rhetorica, Vol. XXXIV, Issue 3, pp. 243–267. ISSN: 0734-8584, electronic ISSN:
1533-8541. © 2016 by The International Society for the History of Rhetoric. All rights
reserved. Please direct all requests for permission to photocopy or reproduce article
content through the University of California Press’s Reprints and Permissions web page,
http://www.ucpress.edu/journals.php?p=reprints. DOI: 10.1525/rh.2016.34.3.243.
244 RHETORICA
R.S. Crane et al., Critics and Criticism. Ancient and Modern (Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press, 1952), 319–48; C. Diano, “Francesco Robortello interprete della catarsi,”
in Aristotelismo padovano e filosofia aristotelica (Firenze: Sansoni, 1960), 71–9; C. Diano,
“Euripide auteur de la catharsis tragique,” Numen 2 (1961): 117–41; B. Weinberg, A
History of Literary Criticism in the Italian Renaissance (Chicago: Chicago University
Press, 1961), vol. 1, 66f and 388f; A. Carlini, “L’attività filologica di Francesco Robor-
tello,” Atti dell’Accademia di scienze lettere e arti di Udine 7 (1966–1969): 5–36; C. Diano,
“La catarsi tragica,” in Saggezze e poetiche degli antichi (Vicenza: Neri Pozza, 1968):
215–69; F. Donadi, “La catarsi storica secondo Robortello,” Atti e memorie dell’Accade-
mia patavina di Scienze Lettere ed Arti 82 (1969–1970): 63–9; F. Donadi, “Un inedito del
Robortello: La Praefatio in Tacitum,” Atti e memorie dell’Accademia patavina di Scienze
Lettere ed Arti 82 (1969–1970): 299–321; G. Cotroneo, I trattatisti dell’ars historica
(Napoli: Giannini, 1971), 121–68; E.E. Ryan, “Robortello and Maggi on Aristotle’s
Theory of Catharsis,” Rinascimento 22 (1982): 263–73; A. Carlini, “Robortello editore
di Eschilo,” Annali della Scuola Normale di Pisa. Classe di Lettere e Filosofia 19 (1989):
313–22; M.J. Vega Ramos , La formación de la teoría de la comedia: Francesco Robortello
(Cáceres: Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Extremadura, 1997); M. Venier,
“Belloni, Robortello ed Egnazio: Nuovi e vecchi documenti su una contesa umanistica,”
Metodi e Ricerche 17 (1998): 51–66; S. Cappello, “Francesco Robortello e la sua opera
nella cultura francese,” in I rapporti dei friulani con l’Italia e con l’Europa nell’epoca veneta
(Padova: Cleup, 2000), 117–46; F. Donadi, “Francesco Robortello da Udine,” Lexis.
Poetica, retorica e comunicazione nella tradizione classica 19 (2001): 79–91; D. Blocker,
“Élucider et équivoquer: Francesco Robortello (ré)invente la catharsis,” Le Cahiers
du Centre de Recherches Historiques 33 (2004), 2–24; B. Zlobec Del Vecchio, “Talia
divino dum fundit Sontius ore. Nota in margine a un carme di Francesco Robortello,”
Incontri triestini di filologia classica 6 (2006–2007): 121–39; K. Vanek, Ars corrigendi in
der frühen Neuzeit. Studien zur Geschichte der Textkritik (Berlin-New York: De Gruyter,
2007), 15–51; S. Cappello, “Robortello, Francesco,” in Nuovo Liruti. Dizionario biogra-
fico dei Friulani. II. L’età veneta, edited by C. Scalon, C. Griggio e U. Rozzo (Udine:
Forum Editrice, 2009), 2151–57; M.C. Angioni, “L’Orestea nell’edizione di Robortello
da Udine: alcuni casi di metafora e griphos,” Ìtaca. Quaderns Catalans de Cultura Clàs-
sica 27 (2011): 111–31; M.Venier, “Francesco Robortello: Discorso sull’arte ovvero sul
metodo di correggere gli autori antichi,” Ecdotica 9 (2012): 183–218; E. Garavelli, “Un
frammento di Francesco Robortello: Del traslare d’una lingua in l’altra,” in Studi di
Italianistica nordica (Roma: Aracne, 2014): 287–305; S. Cappello, “L’editio princeps
ritrovata del De artificio dicendi (1560) di Francesco Robortello,” in Dal Friuli alle
Americhe. Studi di amici e allievi udinesi per Silvana Serafin, edited by A. Ferraro (Udine:
Editrice Universitaria, 2015), 133–148; M. Sgarbi, “Francesco Robortello on Topics,”
Viator 47 (2016), 365–388.
2
The existence of the 1560 edition of the De artificio dicendi was unknown prior to
2014. Discovered by Cappello in the Biblioteca Civica di Udine (signature 7.B.8.25),
this is the only surviving evidence of this first printed edition, and remains to this
day uncatalogued in inventories both in Italy and internationally. I therefore take
Francesco Robortello’s Rhetoric 245
e di altre questioni letterarie nell’età della rinascenza (Torino: Loescher, 1885); J. Seigel,
Rhetoric and Philosophy in Renaissance Humanism (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1968); V. Cox, Ciceronian Rhetorical Theory in the Volgare: A Fourteenth-Century
Text and its Fifteenth-Century Readers in Rhetoric and Renewal in the Latin West 1100–
1544 (Turnhout: Brepols, 2003), 201–225; V. Cox, Ciceronian Rhetoric in Late Medieval
Italy: The Latin and Vernacular Tradition, in The Rhetoric of Cicero in its Medieval and
Early Renaissance Commentary Tradition, edited by V. Cox – J.O. Ward (Leiden-Boston.
Brill, 2006), 109–143; K.M. Fredborg, Ciceronian Rhetoric and Dialectic, in The Rhetoric of
Cicero in its Medieval and Early Renaissance Commentary Tradition, edited by V. Cox –
J.O. Ward (Leiden-Boston. Brill, 2006), 165–192; J. Monfasani, The Ciceronian Contro-
versy, in The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume III. The Renaissance, edited
by G. Norton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 395–401.
4
Cf. S.J. Milner, “Le sottili cose non si possono bene aprire in volgare: Vernacular
Oratory and the Transmission of Classical Rhetorical Theory in the Late Medieval
Italian Communes,” Italian Studies 2 (2009), 221–244.
5
Cf. P. Mack, A History of Renaissance Rhetoric, 1380–1620 (Oxford: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 2011), 282–283.
6
Cf. Ibid., 282.
7
Cf. I.F. McNeely, “The Renaissance Academies between Science and the
Humanities,” Configurations 3 (2009), 248, 257.
Francesco Robortello’s Rhetoric 247
8
Cf. M.L. McLaughlin, Literary Imitation in the Italian Renaissance: The Theory and
Practice of Literary Imitation in Italy from Dante to Bembo (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1995).
9
Cf. C. Dionisotti, Scritti sul Bembo (Turin: Einaudi, 2002), 211.
248 RHETORICA
2. S CHEMATIZING R HETORIC
10
Cf. V. Vianello, “Res e verba nel Dialogo della Retorica di Sperone Speroni,”
Atti dell’Istituto Veneto di Scienze, Lettere ed Arti 138 (1979–1980): 231–53; J.L. Fournel,
“La rhétorique vagabonde et le portrait de la vérité dans trois dialogues de Sperone
Speroni,” in Discours littéraires et pratiques politiques (Paris: Publications de la
Sorbonne, 1987), 11–59; R. Girardi, “Ercole e il Granchio, figure della retorica spero-
niana,” Giornale storico della Letteratura Italiana 167 (1990), 396–411; M. Sgarbi, The
Italian Mind. Vernacular Logic in Renaissance Italy (1540–1551) (Leiden: Brill, 2014).
Francesco Robortello’s Rhetoric 249
Robortello’s Scheme
11
Cf. Liruti, Notizie delle vite ed opere scritte da’ letterati del Friuli, 424–425, 436.
12
Cf. W.J. Ong, Ramus, Method, and the Decay of Dialogue: From the Art of Discourse to
the Art of Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983), 279; L.D. Green, Aristotle’s
Rhetoric Made Methodical, in Autour de Ramus: Texte, théorie, commentaire (Quebec: Nuits
Blanches, 1997), 135–173.
250 RHETORICA
13
For a brief discussion of the manuscript cf. L. Bolzoni, The Gallery of Memory.
Literary and Iconographic Models in the Age of the Printing Press (Toronto: Toronto Uni-
versity Press, 2001), 24–27. For a discussion of its content and a diplomatic transcrip-
tion of the manuscript cf. M. Sgarbi, “Francesco Robortello on Topics,” 365–388.
14
Cf. N.W. Gilbert, Renaissance Concepts of Method (New York-London: Columbia
University Press, 1960).
Francesco Robortello’s Rhetoric 251
15
Emphasis are mine. Translated by Lina Bolzoni in Bolzoni, The Gallery of
Memory, 25–26.
16
Cf. Bolzoni, The Gallery of Memory. Literary and Iconographic Models in the Age of
the Printing Press, 23–34.
252 RHETORICA
3. L ATIN R HETORIC
17
Cf. Liruti, Noizie delle vite ed opere scritte da’ letterati del Friuli, vol. 2, p. 421.
Cf. N. Aksamija, “Architecture and Poetry in the Making of a Christian Cicero:
18
Giovanni Battista Campeggi’s Tuscolano and the Literary Culture of the Villa in
Counter-Reformation Bologna”, I Tatti Studies 13 (2011), 133–43. Robortello has a
long-lasting relationship with Campeggi, and already in 1559 dedicated to him the
De vita, et victu populi romani (Benacci: Bologna, 1559).
19
Mack, A History of Renaissance Rhetoric, 1380–1620, 164.
Francesco Robortello’s Rhetoric 253
20
F. Robortello, De artificio dicendi (Bologna: Benati, 1567), 9r-v.
21
For a description of the manuscript cf. P.O. Kristeller, Iter Italicum. A Finding
List of Uncatalogued or Incompletely Catalogued Humanistic Manuscripts of the Renais-
sance in Italian and other Libraries Volume 1. Italy. Agrigento to Novara (Leiden: Brill,
1963), 416.
22
BNN, V D 45, f. 70r.
23
BNN, V D 45, f. 70v.
254 RHETORICA
4. T HE O RATOR
24
The work was catalogued for the first time in Catalogo dei codici che componevano
l’archivio dei nobili conti Donà dalle Rose, ora presso il Museo Civico e Raccolta Correr,
BMCVe, ms. Donà dalle Rose 7, f. 433.
25
Cf. infra, p. 261.
Francesco Robortello’s Rhetoric 255
26
Cf. infra, p. 261.
256 RHETORICA
of science or can be written in the future. This idea leads to two very
important conclusions.
The activity of an orator is mainly oral in the sense that it concerns
the possibility of transmitting knowledge orally and not necessarily by
the written word, which on the contrary seems necessary for all the
other sciences. The subject-matter of the orator seems to be concerned
only with what can be treated in moral philosophy and politics, that
is human actions, not with all the other speculative sciences. Conse-
quently, an orator can only popularise philosophical discourses that
deal with moral philosophy, politics, law, etc., which explains why
Robortello, in the chapter “Quomodo sermo philosophicus ad popula-
rem et oratorium redigi possit,” gives examples of how to popularise
philosophy only in respect of ethics and civil philosophy, not other
sciences. But this also means that common people can be taught only
in practical disciplines dealing with particulars, not in sciences that
inquire into universals. There is thus a sharp distinction for Robortello
between moral philosophy for all and speculative philosophy, or sci-
ence properly speaking, which is for the elite alone. As a matter of fact,
Robortello restricts his conception of the popularisation of knowledge
by identifying the domain of rhetoric strictly with civil philosophy. In
so doing, he is following a characteristic conception of various Aristote-
lians such as Sperone Speroni, who maintained the idea that rhetoric
was useful only for civil philosophy and literary purposes. He does
point out, however, that one can argue that scientists employ enthyme-
mes too, because they do not usually reason following complete syllo-
gisms with all the premises. This is possible, Robortello states, because
it is customary also for scientists to understand universal things even
when one of the premises is lacking. Not even in his physical or astro-
nomical works, notes Robortello, does Aristotle employ a complete syl-
logism. This amounts to a reduction of the language of science proper to
a common or more popular scientific language, but without inhibiting
the demonstrative force of the reasoning, since if in science some prem-
ise is lacking, this is because the scientist already implies it as being true.
Moreover, Robortello explains that the oratorical enthymeme is in
“darii” form, not “barbara,” because it is grounded in the rhetorical
inference of the example, which is always particular. Syllogism, on
the contrary, is based not on example, but induction.
5. R HETORICAL A RGUMENTS
27
On Robortello’s use of example cf. C. Vasoli, Francesco Patrizi da Cherso (Roma:
Bulzoni, 1989), 25–90; C. Vasoli, “Il modello teorico”, in La storiografia umanistica (Messina:
Sicania, 1992), 24–31.
258 RHETORICA
28
Cf. J.M. Atwill, Rhetoric Reclaimed. Aristotle and the Liberal Arts Tradition (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1998), 196–201.
29
The scheme is reproduced in the appendix. Cf. P.O. Kristeller, Iter Italicum. Iter
Italicum. A Finding List of Uncatalogued or Incompletely Catalogued Humanistic Manu-
scripts of the Renaissance in Italian and other Libraries Volume 6. Italy III and alia Itinera
IV (Leiden: Brill, 1991), 275.
260 RHETORICA
6. C ONCLUSION
[1 R ] D ELL ’ ORATORE 30
Quesito primo
mo
E Sig risponderò al quesito primo che fu se ben mi ricordo,
perché l’oratore usa lo entimema cosi imperfetto et non intiero come
il sillogismo usato dal Dialectico, in questo modo. Omnes proditores
sunt puniendi, ergo Aeschynes est puniendus. Ne vedo che alcuno Rhetore
antico habbi fatto tal quesito, ovvero assegnato la ragione, onde più
necessaria causa apparirà et V.S.E. havere mossa a farsi il quesito, et
me al rispondere. Sarò pero breve riserbandomi a vestire in Latino
questa disputazione più copiosamente.
Fundamento della mia risposta sarà questo. L’ORATORE ha da
farsi con auditori rozzi, et ignoranti di scienze. Et questo disse anchora
Ariste nel pmo della sua Rhet.ca non una volta ma più togliendo la simi-
litudine dall’huomo che ha vista curta, ne vede molto da lungo, perché
l’ignorante vede poco al pari del sciente, il quale specula da lungo ogni
cosa con il suo intelletto per mezzo delli universali. Et l’ignorante a
pena vede il particolare, perché non è usato ad abstragere speculando
l’universale dalli particolari, come il sciente, perché tutte le scienze sono
fatte di termini universali. Onde s’imparano anticamente prima da i
putti le mathematice per assuefare l’intelletto a tal specule, la quale
causa dalli particolari sensati l’universale. Et invero è più difficile da
prendere l’universale, che il particolare, onde ben habbiamo detto che
l’universale è apreso solamente dal sciente, et il particolare dal’igno-
rante, et rozzo, ovvero popolar huomo. Il secondo fondamento adunca
sarà che l’auditore dell’oratore per essere rozzo, et populare apprende
solamente il particolare, ma non l’universale. Più l’oratore versa circa
le attioni particolari di questo o quello, ne tratta questione alcuna uni-
versale. Di qui nasce che l’oratore mette la sua materia nella forma
del sillogismo detto volgarmente nelle scuole DARIJ, ma non mai nella
forma del sillogismo detto nelle scuola Barbara, et la ragione è, perché il
sillogismo DARIJ ha una universale proposizione, l’altra particolare, et
similmente la conclusione particolare, ma il sillogismo Barbara è tutto
30
BMCVe, Donà dalle Rose 447, folder 28 (1566–1567 ca.). Folder 28 contains: 1)
Dell’oratore, ff. 1r-3v (with one additional unbounded leaf); 2) Del translatare d’una lin-
gua in l’altra, ff. 4r-5v; 3) Quae potissimum in oratore requirantur, ff. 6r-v; 4) Della figura
delle parole, ff. 7r-v. The transcript of BMCVe, Donà dalle Rose 447, folder 28, ff. 1r-3v
is an exact copy of the text. The present edition – strictly diplomatic – preserves origi-
nal spelling as well as capitalization, italicization, lineation, and punctuation, even
when erroneous, reproducing all the orthographic information provided by the
manuscript.
262 RHETORICA
31
A me pare, che non per questo, che il sillogismo in barbara è tutto di universali,
l’oratore non l’usa, ma ben per questo, perché non gli è necessario usarlo, et a cio è
astretto, peroche trattando per il più cose particolari l’oratore, conviene ancho che le
proposi: tiene del suo sillogismo andino a particolari, ne pero anchora mai non l’usa
il sillogismo in barbara l’oratore, ma ben alcune volte come, quando diggreditur in
locum commune che è come questione universale.
Francesco Robortello’s Rhetoric 263
Q UESTIO 2°
Rerurum gestarum
materies
ab hominibus
Exemplorum
unius ad unum
forma
plurium
singularium ad
unum generale
verum naturalium
materies
verum artificialium
Inductionum
plurium
forma singularium ad
unum generale
electione
constructione
gestu
vultu