Gallagher 2018
Gallagher 2018
Gallagher 2018
Embodied Rationality
Shaun Gallagher
Introduction
S. Gallagher (&)
University of Memphis, Memphis, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
S. Gallagher
University of Wollongong, Wollongong, Australia
Marcel suggested that being in love is a good example of a mystery. But also,
one’s own existence, and one’s own body (not the body as a biological object, but
the body as it is lived or experienced by the embodied subject) are mysteries in this
sense.
Marcel is not the only philosopher to suggest such a distinction. Noam Chomsky
made a very similar one with respect to the study of language and the mind, indeed,
using the same terminology (1976, 281).
I would like to distinguish roughly between two kinds of issues that arise in the study of
language and mind: those that appear to be within the reach of approaches and concepts that
are moderately well understood — what I will call “problems”; and others that remain as
obscure to us today as when they were originally formulated — what I will call “mysteries.”
Although Gadamer (2004, 301) did not use the term ‘mystery’, his characteri-
zation of the ‘hermeneutical situation’ involved a similar structure to what Marcel
called a mystery—the inextricable involvement of the interpreter. Likewise, Dewey
(1938) defined the concept of ‘situation’, not as equivalent to the external envi-
ronment, but as inclusive of the agent (or the organism) as it is coupled to the
environment. The distinction between the ‘geographical environment’ and the
‘behavioral environment’ (Koffka 2013, 27–51) is similar in so far as the latter
concept includes the comporting agent. Along these lines, and I think in the same
spirit, Aristotle (350 BCEa, I, 3) famously noted that although in many subject
areas problems could be addressed by theoretical or scientific knowledge, in the
area of ethics, where human action is at stake, issues are not as well ordered, and
one would have to be satisfied with a precision ‘just so far as the nature of the
subject admits’.
Faced with these different suggestions and distinctions, there are at least two
possible stances. Either one takes the ‘mystery’ (to stay with Marcel’s term) to be
irrational; or one widens the definition of rationality to include mystery. Aristotle’s
notion of phronesis (practical wisdom), Dewey’s pragmatism, Gadamer’s
hermeneutics, and Marcel’s existentialism are attempts to expand the notion of
rationality beyond the instrumental or strict natural scientific conceptions. I’ll argue
in this paper that recent developments in embodied cognition in the field of cog-
nitive science also support this expanded notion of rationality. I’ll attempt to
explicate this expanded notion by introducing the concepts of embodied rationality
and enactive hermeneutics.
example, takes the role of the body to be fully accounted for in terms of neural
processes in which sensory-motor representations get reiterated for purposes other
than sensory-motor function. For example, B-formatted simulations may be
important for language and concept processing (e.g., Glenberg 2010; Meteyard
et al. 2012; Pezzulo et al. 2011; Pulvermüller 2005). Extended functionalist
approaches, like the extended mind hypothesis (Clark and Chalmers 1998; Menary
2010), also remain tied to computational rationality even as they minimize the role
of mental representations. On this model, some of the work of the mind is taken up
through an embodied engagement with tools, instruments and artifacts in the
environment.
A more radical break with computational models is made by enactivist
approaches, which call for a radical change in the way we think about the mind and
brain. These approaches emphasize dynamical, non-linear self-organizing systems
that constitute cognition from the bottom up, where cognition is defined in terms of
responses made by autopoietic biological organisms to environmental conditions
(Thompson 2007; Varela et al. 1991). Human cognition obviously involves the
brain, but the brain is considered part of the larger system of
brain-body-environment. In this dynamical intertwinement of brain and body with
the environment, the brain is not computing across representations. It’s not repre-
senting or creating an internal model of the world. It’s not taking the world as a
problem to be solved.1 It’s rather contributing to the ongoing responses made by the
embodied agent to physical, social and cultural environments, in ways that allow for
the enactment of meaning.
The enactivist approach can be summarized by the following background
assumptions.2
(1) Cognition is not simply a brain event. It emerges from processes distributed
across brain-body-environment;
(2) The world (meaning, intentionality) is not pre-given or predefined, but is
structured by cognition and action;
(3) Cognitive processes acquire meaning in part by their role in the context of
action, rather than through a representational mapping or replicated internal
model of the world;
(4) The enactivist approach has strong links to dynamical systems theory,
emphasizing the relevance of dynamical coupling and coordination across
brain-body-environment;
(5) In contrast to classic cognitive science, which is often characterized by
methodological individualism with a focus on internal mechanisms, the
1
Enactivism, however, may be viewed as consistent with predictive models of brain function as
long as the relation between brain, body and environment is properly conceived (see Gallagher and
Allen 2016).
2
See Gallagher (2017). These assumptions are drawn from the following sources: Clark (1999), Di
Paolo et al. (2010), Dominey et al. (2016), Engel (2010), Engel et al. (2013), Thompson and
Varela (2001), Varela et al. (1991).
86 S. Gallagher
I agree with McDowell that we have a freedom to step back and reflect that nonhuman
animals lack, but I don’t think this is our most pervasive and important kind of freedom.
Such stepping back is intermittent in our lives and, in so far as we take up such a ‘free,
distanced orientation’, we are no longer able to act in the world. I grant that, when we are
absorbed in everyday skillful coping, we have the capacity to step back and reflect but I
think it should be obvious that we cannot exercise that capacity without disrupting our
coping. (Dreyfus 2007, 354).
Here the notion of affordance (Gibson 1977) offers some explanatory help. The
concept of affordance is defined as having the same relational structure as Dewey’s
notion of ‘situation’. That is, it does not signify something about an objective
structure in the environment; it’s defined in terms of the relation between a certain
type of organism or agent, which has a certain skill level, and the particularities of
the environment. Dreyfus distinguishes affordances as facts (or as Rietveld and
Kiverstein 2014 put it, affordances relative to a way of life) from affordances as
specific solicitations, here and now. ‘Although when we step back and contemplate
them affordances can be experienced as features of the world, when we respond to
their solicitations they aren’t figuring for a subject as features of the world [in
McDowell’s sense]’ (2007, 358). McDowell, according to Dreyfus, assumes that
the world is already a set of facts that are determinate and that can then be named,
and thought, and fit into rational concepts. In contrast, for Dreyfus, the world is
indeterminate, ‘not implicitly conceptual and simply waiting to be named. Our
relation to the world is more basic than our mind’s being open to apperceiving
categorially unified facts’ (2007, 359). This fits well with the enactivist idea that,
rather than finding meaning pre-formed, we enact meaning in our ongoing actions.
Embodied Rationality
The notion of embodied rationality splits the difference between Dreyfus and
McDowell. On the enactivist view, the world is laid out in perception, not in terms of
a conceptual, or proto-conceptual meaning, but first of all, in terms of differentiations
that concern my action possibilities or affordances—the object is something I can
reach, or not; something I can lift, or not; something I can move or not. One’s ability
to make sense out of the world comes, in part, from an active and pragmatic
engagement with the world. If we can then turn around or step back to discover that
our world or our experience has an inherent rational or proto-conceptual structure,
that’s because that structure has already been put there by our pre-predicative
embodied engagements. Dreyfus may reject this as a form of rationality because he is
thinking of rationality in the standard way. As Zahavi (2013) points out, both
Dreyfus and McDowell continue to retain and share an overly intellectualized
(conceptualized, “languaged”) conception of the mind. In contrast to this traditional
conception (which is the concept of mind that Dreyfus rejects and McDowell
accepts), the alternative is to think of mental skills such as reflection, problem
solving, decision making, and so on, as enactive, non-representational forms of
88 S. Gallagher
Still, in the Aristotelian tradition the hand is raised to the level of the rational by
considering it the organum organorum.3 For the enactivist, hands (as part of a
complete system that includes the brain and the rest of the body) are action oriented.
As an agent reaches to grasp something, the hand automatically (and without the
agent’s conscious awareness) shapes itself into just the right posture to form the
most appropriate grip for that object and for the agent’s purpose. If I reach to grab a
banana in order to take a bite, the shape of my grasp is different from when I reach
to grab a banana in order to pretend it’s a phone. Differences in my grasp reflect my
intention so that if I grasp the fruit to eat it, the kinematics of my movement are
different from when I grasp it to offer it to you, and different again from when I
grasp it to throw at you (Ansuini et al. 2006, 2008; Jeannerod 1997; Marteniuk et al.
1987; Sartori et al. 2011). Hands are integrated with visual perception (via the
dorsal visual pathway), so that I see the fruit as graspable for specific purposes. The
brain evolved to do what it does in this regard only because it had hands to work
with—hands that evolved with the brain in a holistic relation with other bodily
aspects.
It is sometimes the case that very smart hand-brain dynamics take the lead over a
more conceptual, ideational intelligence. For example, a patient with visual agnosia
who is unable to recognize objects, when shown a picture of a clarinet, calls it a
‘pencil’. At the same time, however, his fingers began to play an imaginary clarinet
(Robertson and Treisman 2010, 308). The hands, and more generally, the body and
its movement in this regard are rational and perform a kind of ‘manual thinking’
(Bredekamp 2007) that integrates its action across all perceptual modalities. Thus
3
Beyond the Aristotelian view, Newton suggested that the thumb is good evidence of God’s
existence (see Dickens 1908, 346), and Kant (1992) used his hands (the fact that hands are
incongruent counterparts, e.g. a left hand doesn’t fit properly into a right-hand glove) to prove that
Newton was right about space being absolute.
7 Embodied Rationality 89
4
An anonymous reviewer suggested that “we have still to give a place in this very framework to
abstraction, generalization, theory and formalization as useful tools—for planning coordinated
actions, for extending previous methods to new situations and new domains, for making revisions
in order to restore coherence in a belief base, etc.” I agree. We can argue for a kind of continuity
between embodied practices and reflective practices even if the former are considered more
concrete than the latter. We do not have to conceive of the continuity as hierarchically organized.
Consider the suggestion made by Goldstein and Scheerer: “Although the normal person’s beha-
viour is prevailingly concrete, this concreteness can be considered normal only as long as it is
embedded in and codetermined by the abstract attitude. For instance, in the normal person both
attitudes are always present in a definite figure-ground relation” (Goldstein and Scheerer 1964, 8;
see Gallagher (2017), for more on this gestalt view of the relations between embodied and
reflective practices.
90 S. Gallagher
Enactivist Hermeneutics
5
Rietveld and Kiverstein (2014) use the term ‘landscape of affordances’ and define it relative to a
form of life.
7 Embodied Rationality 91
situation’ (Dewey 1938, 67). For Dewey, it is not the organism that is placed in a
situation. Rather the situation is constituted by organism-environment, which
means that the situation already includes the agent or experiencing subject. In this
regard, for example, I cannot strictly point to the situation because my pointing is
part of the situation. I cannot speak of it as some kind of distanced objective set of
facts because my speaking is part of it. My movement is a movement of the
situation. My reflection, and even my stepping back, is likewise part of the situa-
tion. Situated coping does not mean simply to rearrange objects in the environment,
but to rearrange oneself as well. Indeed, any adjustment one makes to objects,
artifacts, tools, practices, social relations or institutions, is equally an adjustment
one makes to oneself.
An enactivist hermeneutics is, accordingly, a hermeneutics of affordances and
ambiguities. An agent interprets the world in terms of what Husserl (1989) called
the ‘I can’. The ‘I can’ expresses the idea that agents perceive their world in
pragmatic terms of what they can do with things, or how they can interact with
others. Another way to say this is that an enactivist hermeneutics involves the
acknowledgement that interpretation is always in and of a hermeneutical situation
where ‘situation’ (as both Dewey and Gadamer suggested) includes not only the
historical and horizonal limits of interpretation, but the interpreter him- or herself,
understood as an agent, and the affordances (physical, pragmatic, social and cul-
tural) that are relative to that agent.
The very idea of a situation means that we are not standing outside of it; hence we are
unable to have any [purely] objective knowledge concerning it. We always find ourselves
within a situation, and throwing light on it is a task that is never entirely finished. This is
also true of the hermeneutic situation (Gadamer 2004, 301)
What then is rationality for an enactivist hermeneutics in which body and envi-
ronment are co-relational; and in which this co-relationality shapes our interpreta-
tions of what things mean and what value they may have? It’s not an observational or
spectatorial stepping back that detaches from the situation to frame the world in
abstract concepts. This latter form of rationality, traditionally characterized as the
primary or highest form of knowledge—theoretical knowledge (as in Aristotle), or
scientific knowledge (as in the positivists)—may in fact be derived or secondary, and
limited. Limited insofar as, even if it does aspire to encompass, epistemologically or
formally, everything there is (as in Leibniz’s conception of divine rationality6), and
to do so from an objective (view-from-nowhere) perspective, it fails to capture the
6
‘God is that which perceives perfectly whatever can be perceived’ (Leibniz, cited in Nachtomy
2008, 74). Nachtomy (2008, 80) summarizes Leibniz’s ‘hard’ conception of rationality as a ‘divine
combinatorics’: ‘The combinatorial nature of concepts serves as the formal and universal structure
of all concepts by stipulating a calculus of all the consistent combinations among all simple forms
in God’s mind. The combinatorial nature of concepts applies to human thought as well. However,
humans must substitute the variables – and the simple elements and the combinatorial rules – with
notations, including the “alphabet” and the syntax of actual sciences, practices, and applications,
such as written languages, geometry, music, chemistry….’ See the related notion of a mathesis
universalis.
92 S. Gallagher
ambiguity intrinsic to the relational dynamics of the agentive situation; and sec-
ondary because it may be the product or outcome of abstracting from and inter-
nalizing the more basic (pragmatic, and in Marcel’s sense, ‘mysterious’) rationality
that characterizes the worldly engagements of participants in embodied situations,
and operates as its shaky and imperfect ground.
Acknowledgements Research on this paper was supported by the Australian Research Council
Discovery Project “Minds in Skilled Performance” (DP170102987), and by the Humboldt
Foundation’s Anneliese Maier Research Award.
References
Alsmith, A. J. T., & de Vignemont, F. (2012). Embodying the mind and representing the body.
Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1), 1–13.
Ansuini, C., Giosa, L., Turella, L., Altoè, G. M., & Castiello, U. (2008). An object for an action,
the same object for other actions: Effects on hand shaping. Experimental Brain Research, 185,
111–119.
Ansuini, C., Santello, M., Massaccesi, S., & Castiello, U. (2006). Effects of end-goal on hand
shaping. Journal of Neurophysiology, 95, 2456–2465.
Aristotle. (350 BCEa). Nicomachean ethics. Trans. W. D. Ross. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/
nicomachaen.html.
Aristotle. (350 BCEb). On the parts of animals. Trans. W. Ogle. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/
parts_animals.html.
Bredekamp, H. (2007). Galilei der Künstler. Die Zeichnung, der Mond, die Sonne.
Akademie-Verlag.
Brincker, M. (2014). Navigating beyond ‘here & now’ affordances—On sensorimotor maturation
and ‘false belief’ performance. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1433. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.
2014.01433.
Chomsky, N. (1976). Problems and mysteries in the study of human language. In Language in
focus: Foundations, methods and systems (pp. 281–357). Netherlands: Springer.
Clark, A. (1999). An embodied cognitive science? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3(9), 345–351.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.
Cole, J., Gallagher, S., & McNeill, D. (2002). Gesture following deafferentation: A phenomeno-
logically informed experimental study. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(1),
49–67.
Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Dickens, C. (1908). Miscellaneous Papers: From the Morning Chronicle, the Daily News, the
Examiner, All the Year Round, and Other Sources. London: Chapman & Hall.
Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values,
social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction:
Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 33–87). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dominey, P. F., Prescott, T., Bohg, J., Engel, A.K., Gallagher, S., & Heed, T., et al. (2016).
Implications of action-oriented paradigm shifts in cognitive science. In Where’s the action?
The pragmatic turn in cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dreyfus, H. L. (2005). Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the
phenomenology of everyday expertise. In Proceedings and Addresses of the American
Philosophical Association (pp. 47–65). American Philosophical Association.
Dreyfus, H. L. (2007). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it
more Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology, 20(2), 247–268.
7 Embodied Rationality 93
Engel, A. K. (2010). Directive minds: How dynamics shapes cognition. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne,
& E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 219–243).
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Engel, A. K., Maye, A., Kurthen, M., & König, P. (2013). Where’s the action? The pragmatic turn
in cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(5), 202–209.
Gadamer, H. G. (2004). Truth and method. Trans. J. Weinsheimer & D. G. Marshall. New York:
Bloomsbury Publishing.
Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Gallagher, S. (2015). Doing the math: Calculating the role of evolution and enculturation in the
origins of mathematical reasoning. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 119,
341–346.
Gallagher, S., & Allen, M. (2016). Active inference, enactivism and the hermeneutics of social
cognition. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1269-8.
Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving,
acting, and knowing (pp. 67–82). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Glenberg, A. M. (2010). Embodiment as a unifying perspective for psychology. Wiley
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1(4), 586–596.
Goldman, A. I. (2014). The bodily formats approach to embodied cognition. In U. Kriegel (Ed.),
Current controversies in philosophy of mind (pp. 91–108). New York and London: Routledge.
Goldstein, K., & Scheerer, M. (1964). Abstract and concrete behavior. An experimental study with
special tests. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University. Reprint of Psychological Monographs 53
(2), 1941.
Høffding, S. (2015). A phenomenology of expert musicianship. PhD Dissertation, Department of
Philosophy, University of Copenhagen.
Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological
philosophy, second book. Trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers.
Jeannerod, M. (1997). The cognitive neuroscience of action. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Kant, I. (1992). Concerning the ultimate ground of the differentiation of directions in space. In D.
Walford & R. Meerbote (Eds.), The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant.
Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770 (pp. 365–372). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Koffka, K. (2013). Principles of Gestalt psychology. London: Routledge.
Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Marcel, G. (1949). Being and having. Trans. K. Farrer. Westminster, UK: Dacre Press.
Marteniuk, R. G., MacKenzie, C. L., Jeannerod, M., Athenes, S., & Dugas, C. (1987). Constraints
on human arm movement trajectories. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 41, 365–378.
McDowell, J. (2007). What myth? Inquiry, 50(4), 338–351.
McNeill, D., Duncan, S., Cole, J., Gallagher, S., & Bertenthal, B. (2008). Neither or both: Growth
points from the very beginning. Interaction Studies, 9(1), 117–132.
Menary, R. (Ed.). (2010). The extended mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception. Trans. D. A. Landes. London:
Routledge.
Meteyard, L., Cuadrado, S. R., Bahrami, B., & Vigliocco, G. (2012). Coming of age: A review of
embodiment and the neuroscience of semantics. Cortex, 48(7), 788–804.
Nachtomy, O. (2008). Leibniz’s rationality: Divine intelligibility and human intelligibility. In M.
Dascal (Ed.), Leibniz: What kind of rationalist? (pp. 73–82). Dordrecht: Springer.
Pezzulo, G., Barsalou, L. W., Cangelosi, A., Fischer, M. H., McRae, K., & Spivey, M. J. (2011).
The mechanics of embodiment: a dialog on embodiment and computational modeling. In A.
Borghi & D. Pecher (Eds.), Embodied and grounded cognition (p. 196). Frontiers E-books.
Pulvermüller, F. (2005). Brain mechanisms linking language and action. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 6, 576–582.
94 S. Gallagher
Quaeghebeur, L., Duncan, S., Gallagher, S., Cole, J., & McNeill, D. (2014). Aproprioception and
gesture. In C. Müller, E. Fricke, A. Cienki, S. H. Ladewig & D. McNeill (Eds.), Handbook on
body—language—communication (2048–2061). De Gruyter-Mouton Publisher.
Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26
(4), 325–352.
Robertson, L. C., & Treisman, A. (2010). Consciousness: Disorders. In E. B. Goldstein (Ed.),
Encyclopedia of perception. New York: Sage.
Salice, A., Høffding, S., & Gallagher, S. (2017). Putting plural self-awareness into practice. Topoi.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9451-2.
Sartori, L., Becchio, C., & Castiello, U. (2011). Cues to intention: The role of movement
information. Cognition, 119, 242–252.
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology and the sciences of mind. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Thompson, E., & Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(10), 418–425.
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and
human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Zahavi, D. (2013). Mindedness, mindlessness and first-person authority. In J. K. Schear (Ed.),
Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell-Dreyfus debate (pp. 320–340). London:
Routledge.