Overington (1977) Kenneth Burke and The Method of Dramatism
Overington (1977) Kenneth Burke and The Method of Dramatism
Overington (1977) Kenneth Burke and The Method of Dramatism
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theory and
Society
MICHAEL A. OVERINGTON
It is possible that sociologists have read the work of Kenneth Burke and
found it neither important nor interesting.1 One searches in vain for any
expository treatment of his work in those journals read by sociologists, or
indeed, for any expository treatment of the sociological importance of Burke
in other journals. Yet Burke has been lurking in sociologists' footnotes since
the 1930s, and recently his system, "Dramatism," has been promoted to
equal rank with "Symbolic Interaction" and "Social Exchange" in the cover-
age given to these aspects of "Interaction" in the International Encyclopedia
of the Social Sciences.2 What are we to make of this?
Clearly, Louis Wirth did not think so in 1938 when he said of Burke's
Permanence and Change (1965) that "It contains more sound substance than
any text on social psychology with which the reviewer is familiar." But in his
caution that "There is much in this treatise that will appear unsystematic and
irrelevant to those accustomed to a less personal and poetic mode of dis-
course,"3 one may find a plausible answer. The full corpus of Burke's work is
broader than the social psychological thrust of this volume, but an idiosyn-
cratic style does characterize all his work and has surely proven to be a major
stumbling block for sociologically trained readers. Although Wayne Booth is a
little strong when he says, "Among anthropologists, sociologists, psycholo-
gists, and rhetoricians his 'dramatism' is increasingly recognized as something
that must at least appear in one's index, whether one has troubled to
understand him or not,"4 it is long since time for a sociologically interested
exposition of Burke's work to be presented to a broad sociological audience,
so as to hasten an informed recognition. The challenge here is to respect
Burke's stylistic metier, which is an integral part of his work, while offering a
translation of his systematic writings that makes sense to sociologists.
work of Parsons, and perhaps the writings of Weber, Simmel, Schutz, Mead
and other theorists of social action, Abraham Kaplan has clarified the ambi-
guity in these two definitions:
Much of Burke's work shuttles between these two positions, and the reader is
not always clear whether a given analysis is addressed to terms about action
or to action itself: In practice, this unclarity beclouds the use of dramatism as
a meta-method for talking about the explanatory (in his language, motivation-
a/) terms of theories of social action, with its employment as a method (with
its own terms) for explaining social action.
Whether or not there is a relation between things, Burke argues that if there is
a connotational relation between the terms which symbolize these things,
then the embedment of such a connotational relation in the linguistic struc-
tures of human mental processes is sufficient to influence people to translate
this symbolic relation into action (by providing a sufficient justification, by
making sense for them of the projected action). For example, to call some
occurrence of a death "murder" is to justify (explain, motivate) the search
for an individual who intended to kill; to call some property loss "theft" is to
sanction a police dragnet for a thief. Murder and theft are criminal acts
because of the statutory decision of some political body; they are not
inherently criminal. No matter what took place at the scene of the crime,
calling the situation "murder" or "theft" brings into play the terminological
relations which inhere in the meaning of these words. Thus, if there was a
"murder," then there was a "murderer"- a person who, having constructed
the "intention," put it into action by killing an individual. Whatever took
place to bring about this death, the attachment of meaning to it as a
"murder" requires, because of the connotational relations which inhere in
this term, that we look for an individual who planned and executed the act,
whether or not such an individual exists. It is not the fact of the act as
murder, but the fact of calling it "murder" which leads to the search for an
intentional killer. Language is itself the motive for the search.1'
This may be a rather startling idea, and it might help to clarify it if we look at
some consequences of Burke's view as it could apply to something as familiar
as the sociologist's language of explanation. We are fond of talking, for
example, about "explained variance," a concept defined in statistical theory
It is not unreasonable to ask why Burke argues for a dialectical rather than
positive method for understanding the social world. I suspect that the answer
to that question reveals how similar his basic ontological assumptions about
the world are to those of Wilhelm Dilthey, although Burke does not evidence
awareness of the likeness. Like Dilthey he assumes that physical and social
objects are different kinds of realities. The physical world is whatever it is,
independent of human action, thought, belief or values. The social world,
however, is an interpreted reality erected through action, belief and thought
on the raw physical material. The consequence of this for both Burke and
Dilthey is a presupposition that the methodology of the social sciences will be
different from that of the physical sciences. For Burke, who takes the social
world to be constituted through a dialectical (contradictory) process of
interest-oriented action, this means electing a methodology which traces the
multiplicity of interests and orientations possible in any situation. A dialec-
tical ontology requires a dialectical epistemology. His dialectic thus involves
an epistemological perspectivism16 as the methodology to grasp the "essen-
tial" reality of the human world of action. His irony of contradiction,
however, does not at all lead him to a "debunking" critique of the social
realm. Rather it operates as a protection from the powerful influence of
modal vocabularies of motives which have their roots in the property rela-
tions of society. If, as Marx says, "The ideas of the ruling class are, in every
age, the ruling ideas: i.e. the class which is the dominant material force in
society is at the same time its dominant intellectual force,"17 then only
through a deliberate and seemingly perverse entertainment of contradictory
explanations can the social analyst construct an understanding of social
relations (or, taking dramatism as meta-method, erect a vocabulary of terms)
broader than that legitimated by the ruling class and its intellectual servants.
While this latter point may well be a little stronger than Burke's view, it is a
consistent conclusion drawn from two Burkean premises. First, vocabularies
of motive are rooted in the property structure and the influence of men of
property; and second, multiplying such vocabularies will lead, through a
dialectic of contradiction, to an "essentially" true explanation.
dialogue as a whole, the voices in harmony and discord, which is the end of
the dialectic. There is here no question of a synthesis as the culmination of
the dialectic; there is no single authoritative perspective; it is only the
multiplicity of elements in the dialectic which offers an accurate account.19
The reader should not yield to the temptation to dismiss lightly Burke's use
of this particular method (logic of inquiry); it is not a literary critic's whim
but an essential philosophical and political principle which underlies its usage.
Burke finds in the institutionalizing of the dialectical process (as he conceived
it) the only chance for a society to continue to function in its contacts with
the obdurate character of the natural world. The natural world is whatever it
is inherently; to define the world incorrectly, to act in the world on a false
hypothesis has, as the limit, destructive consequences. A perspectival ap-
proach to the world offers, at least for Burke, more probability of an accurate
interpretation of, and, thus, adaptive action on the natural and social world.
This point is most clearly made where Burke says:
Clearly, this dialectic did not appear fully developed in his work in the
nineteen twenties and thirties. Yet, even in Counterstatement, his earliest
critical volume, the operation of his logic is clear, and Burke's own comment
on the seminal nature of this volume is essentially accurate, both with respect
to its system and its method.21 Indeed, his later work may be seen as a
development of the method and substance of this first volume, although it
would be misleading to claim that there is anything in this work but the
conceptual possibility of the final system.
When one connects this oppositional concept of dialectic with the interest-
based theory of ideational association that Burke takes explicitly from De
Gourmont, then the adumbration of his method of inquiry stands forth in
this first volume. From it, one can conclude that inquiry into human action is
to be conducted by examining the interest bases for people's ideas and
ideational relations through a deliberate introduction of a contradictory
perspective into the interaction of this action. Understanding is to be
achieved by ironic illumination. Yet it is not at all clear in this book why it is
that a contradictory perspective will lead one to a more accurate view, save
that it can bring into analytic focus other aspects of human life which are
obscured by the modal motivational framework legitimated by the "industri-
al" division of property and labor. Nor is it obvious what a contradictory
perspective would be, or how one might construct it. However, in his next
two volumes Permanence and Change (1965) and Attitudes Toward History
(1959), Burke offers a more helpful account of the process of his dialectic.
Indeed, he makes an effective presentation of a particular dialectical tech-
nique that he calls "perspective by incongruity." This is a method that operates
by bringing together terms and concepts which are normally never found
together and which, in their ironic juxtaposition, undermine the "taken for
granted" character of the motivational force of the terms in their convention-
al relations. In his words: "Perspective by incongruity [is] a method for
gauging situations by verbal atom cracking. That is, a word belongs by custom
to a certain category-and by rational planning you wrench it loose and
metaphorically apply it to a different category."22 Burke notes that this
technique is closely connected to De Gourmont's notion of the "dissociation
of ideas," which "was concerned with the methodic blasting apart of verbal
particles that had been considered inseparable; [whereas on the other hand]
'perspective by incongruity' refers to the methodic merger of particles that
had been considered mutually exclusive."23
Nonetheless, these two techniques are hardly independent. They are a kind of
early version of the "merger and division" technique, a device for exploring
connotational transformations which flowers in his later work,24 and which
Burke traces back to the Phaedrus and Plato's distinction between the twin
processes of the dialectic-organization into unity and division into parts-
which work together to produce truthful discourse. But there must surely be
many incongruous meldings of terms that one could use. Why one incon-
gruity rather than another? Is Burke arguing for a "verbal cubism," or does
the atomic imagery he uses to define this technique expose a desire to be
taken scientifically?
The best answer one can extract from this context suggests that " 'perspective
by incongruity' makes for a dramatic vocabulary, with weighting and coun-
ter-weighting, in contrast with the liberal ideal of neutral naming in the
characterization of processes."25Yet, we can only guess at the basis for the
"weighting." While it is moral and aesthetic, and it seems to be informed by
"a Marxism so tolerant, so tentative that he must find it a bit uncomfor-
table ....,"26 we have no explicit rules for it. However, it would not be
inaccurate to read Burke as offering us a three-step guide to motivational
analysis. First, identify the modal motivational framework, both its terms and
the weighting of these terms on behalf of the ruling elites. Second, construct
an ironic motivational terminology weighted in opposition to the interests of
property by constructing incongruous motivational phrases from the modal
vocabulary of motives and from whatever terms one's own inventive genius
will supply. Finally, offer this analysis in public discourse, in order to give a
truer explanation for human action and to provide people with a liberating
alternative justification for their action. This logic of inquiry, therefore, is not
simply an instrument for interpreting the social world; it also gives the
possibility of changing that world!
However, Burke did not produce this ironic perspectivism de novo; indeed, he
relates it to the basic orientation of Nietzsche and to the system of Bergson.
Burke traces to Nietzsche the sense of perspectives as interpretations from a
particular position, which become "true" insofar as they encourage a creative
The pentad retains both the "inner symposium" and the etymological ap-
proach at the same time as it offers the final reconstruction of the dialectic.
However, in this reconstruction, the "tolerant Marxism" of the earlier dialec-
tic is incorporated into a procedure wherein incongruity is almost entirely
teased out of motivational frameworks themselves, without explicit attention
to their social or cultural roots in property relations. Yet, the pentad does
codify the dramatistic logic of inquiry; it does provide rules, albeit of a
general kind, for the explanation of human action. As Burke summarizes it:
In any rounded statement about motives, you must have some word that
names the act (names what took place, in thought or deed), and another
that names the scene (the background of the act, the situation in which it
occurred); also, you must indicate what person or kind of person (agent)
performed the act, what means or instruments he used (agency), and the
purpose.35
The five terms of the pentad are therefore Act, Scene, Agent, Agency,
Purpose, to which he later added Attitude (as incipient act) to make a hexad.
He notes that, as terms, they are neither positive nor dialectical, defined
neither lexically nor oppositionally; rather they are collapsed questions, e.g.,
Act is equivalent to "U hat was done?";Scene is the same as "In what sort of
a situation was it done?" and so on.36
In the relationships among these five terms there is a whole series of word
pairs, correlations, or "ratios," which may be used to explain action or to
explicate explanations of action. The Scene-Act ratio, for example, is an
assertion that particular acts correlate with particular scenes, and "sensible"
explanations will exhibit a consistency between acts and their scenes. Like-
wise, the Scene-Agent ratio explains action as a result of a correlation
between agents and scenes: "It is a principle of drama that the nature of acts
and agents should be consistent with the nature of the scene."39 However,
the original "consistency" of the ratios has, in the latest formulation, become
"correspondence," such that with respect to a Scene-Act ratio he is talking
about "a proposition such as: Though agent and act are necessarily different
in many of their attributes, some notable element of one is implicitly or
analogously present in the other."40
The context in which we can best make sense of these explanatory correspon-
dences between various terms of the pentad is to be found in Burke's early
work, The Philosophy of Literary Form. There he notes that dramatism is an
heuristic for the analysis of human action; it is
The basic, corrective principles of dramatism and the ratios are taken from
drama because human action is "essentially" dramatic, for Burke. The drama
presumes human action; the playwright's task is to offer a plausible account
of the acts of agents in terms of scenes, purposes, and agencies. As Burke puts
it in "Dramatism," "drama is employed, not as a metaphor but as a fixed
form that helps us discover what the implications of the terms 'act' and
'person' really are."45 In other words, the drama is Burke's choice for an
analytic model of the social world. What makes drama work is the ability of
playwrights to call upon cultural expectations of consistency between scenes
and both acts and agents. Burke is saying that drama provides a form for the
analysis of human action; drama "works" only when it draws on these
cultural expectations so as to build plot and characters around these ratios.
Thus, the drama is a major research site to which Burke has turned for his
insight into motives. When he understands how a play operates, he knows
about the expectations of both audience and playwright with respect to a
convincing explanatory framework. It was precisely from his study of the
drama that he was able to abstract the terms of the pentad as the major
dimensions of the explanation of human action.
The most common ratios used by Burke are Scene-Act and Scene-Agent.
When engaged in a dramatistic study, he notes, "the basic unit of action
would be defined as 'the human body in conscious or purposive motion',"46
in other words, an agent acting in a situation. For example, in a mental
hospital (scene) one would expect to find insane acts performed by insane
agents; and conversely, one would also expect that agents who are insane and
so act are properly found in mental hospitals. The correspondence between
the pentadic terms is transitive. In this example, we can see that these ratios
(linguistically based expectancies) provide guidance for people unsure of how
to act in a situation (like a mental hospital), a framework with which to
understand and explain the interaction around them, and justification for
bringing some consistency into a situation which may lack it. Thus, in
addition to their analytic contribution here, dramatistic ratios make explica-
ble placing people into mental hospitals whom we find to be insane. Whether
or not such action makes any therapeutic sense, it does bring the situation
into line with the cultural expectancies that are encoded in the linguistic
structure of mind.
The first of these four, contextual definition, locates the essence of objects
Indeed, one of these clusters, "order" (the cluster of terms which are
connotatively implicit in this concept), contains, for Burke, the whole drama
of human relations - contains, therefore, the essence of the human condi-
tion. Through his analysis of the connotations of the term "order," Burke
tries to show that the substance of the human social realm is that of an
hierarchial order held together by norms, where both hierarchy and norms are
Burke also outlines some principles for the selection of words into the
"concordance," which are of interest in that they give an idea as to why he
focuses on one word rather than another; but they do not help to explicate
the relation between words, which is crucial to understanding word clusters.
Indeed, when he summarizes the essay and its methodological advice, he says
to "look for moments at which in your opinion, the work comes to fruitiorL
Imbue yourself with the terminology of these moments. And spin from
them."53 But it is precisely this "spinning" for which we are trying to
discover a logic; it is "spinning" which is his technique for constructing
dialectical clusters.
We are not completely without guidance. There is one important clue to the
criteria for the relations between words, which may be found in Burke's
comment:
as language is the unique human capacity, and the mind is formed out of the
social process (which is one of communication), so the principles of mental
functioning (and the symbolic and social action in which it results) are built
on the syntactic and semantic qualities of particular languages.61 Thus,
grammars of motivational terms can also be treated as grammars of human
action.
Of course, one could see this argument as nothing more than an attempt to
fill out the linkages concealed by the "frustration-aggression" hypothesis,
and, given Burke's familiarity with Freud, it may well be that this particular
explanation of aggressive behavior was a stimulating influence in Burke's
development of his own more elaborate theory. Nonetheless, we will not get
far in understanding this example of Burke's analytic technique if we treat
him as a plagiarizer of Freud. Nor would it greatly assist this illustration of
the figurative logic of dramatism if we were to use the merger and division
technique, as does Burke himself in a later volume.63 On the other hand, if
we reconstruct this argument and try to amplify the links in the argument by
appeal to the pentadic ratios, it may help to bring out the mixture of
metaphorical, "logical," relata in the theory.
This illustrative reconstruction from Burke's work, selected for its sociologi-
cal topic, does pose the two questions that remain to be asked about
dramatism. First, how are we to separate the methodic use of this system
from its employment as a meta-method (as an analytic device for examining
explanatory terms)? The illustration, of course, is methodic in character; it
implies that this account of anti-Semitism is a description of the process
through which individual Germans came to hold their position. Nonetheless,
it would take little effort to suggest that, whether or not this description was
This moves us to the second, and perhaps more important question, one that
relates directly to the sociological efficacy of dramatism. Is there a practical
limit, a limit that would make analytic sense, to the kinds of descriptive
accounts that could be spun out of the terms of this illustration, or, more
generally, out of any set of analytic terms? Certainly there is no reason to
scorn the pentad as a guiding rule for the critique of analyses of human
action. Indeed, Zollschan and Overington (1975) have exhibited the pentad's
utility as a rule for assessing the theoretic generality of theories of motiva-
tion. Yet, the actual operation of such dramatistic critiques of explanations,
as well as dramatistic explanations themselves through the development of
dialectical clusters of terms, raises problems.
And so to repeat the question: "Is the dramatistic analyst worse off than any
sociologist engaged in the reconstruction, the representation, of another's
theory?" If we restrict the answer to those theories (explanations of action)
addressed to a sociological audience, then I believe the answer to be "No." In
the first place, we do not know what the rules are for presenting plausible
reconstructions (unless stylistic familiarity or sociological fashionability be
crucial!); a dramatistic reconstruction has as much a priori plausibility as any
other interpretation that could be generated with the text. In the second
place, to match the claimed reconstructive adequacy of well-formed and
testable propositions (either in interrelated nets or wrenched out of any
context), the dramatistic logic of inquiry proposes its own criteria. These are
twofold. First, identify the key analytic terms in the explanation; and second,
explore the connotational links in dialectical clusters formed by these key
analytic terms under the pentadic rubric (Remember that "In any rounded
statement about motives, you must have some word that names . . . [the act,
scene, agent, agency, and purpose]."65 Performing both of these tasks leads
to a rounded dramatistic analysis, and, insofar as the original explanation of
action (theory) is inadequately developed with respect to the pentad, makes a
dramatistic critique possible.
However, although these same three factors provide practical limits in the
dramatistic analysis of motivational (explanatory) frameworks that are not
addressed to sociologists, they do not offer guidance in the sampling of
motivational discourse that is to become the "text" for the inquiry. Of
course, such a sampling problem does not arise with motivational frameworks
(explanations of action) that are offered to a sociological audience. But when
it comes to an attempt to analyze the frameworks of motives that members
of some group, organization, institution, or even a whole culture66 employ in
explaining their completed or proposed actions, we are very much in need of
some rules for sampling. These the dramatistic logic of inquiry fails to offer,
and Burke's own practice suggests little more than the rhetorical techniques
of example and illustration as procedures for sampling. These are certainly
not adequate as systematic rules for selecting items of motivational discourse
from socially bounded universes of motivational talk. Yet, surely we have
enough theories of sampling in use among sociologists engaged in observation-
al, experimental, and survey research to provide some basis for sampling
items of motivational discourse from motivational frameworks. This defect of
dramatism is hardly crippling!
Clearly, the present brief exposition has not provided an inventory of the
techniques to be used in a dramatistic analysis; that was not its purpose.
Indeed, from the dearth of sociological commentary on dramatism, it would
appear that no sociological audience is yet available for the monographic
length that such completeness would entail. Here, rather, we have examined
the sociological pertinence of Burke's work through a concentration on the
intersubjectivity of his methodology. This intersubjectivity is a necessary
condition for the sociological import of dramatism. It is reasonable to
conclude from the present reconstruction that dramatism does provide such
an intersubjective method for the analysis and critique of explanations of
action. Dramatism meets the necessary condition for its sociological impor-
tance. Only time will tell if that necessary condition is also "sufficient."
REFERENCES
Burke, Kenneth, The Philosophy of Literary Form, New York: Vintage, 1957.
Burke, Kenneth, Attitudes Toward History, Boston: Beacon Press, 1959.
Burke, Kenneth, "Fact, Inference and Proof in the Analysis of Literary Symbolism,"
Stanley Hyman, ed., Terms for Order, Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana Universi
Press, 1964, pp. 145-172.
Burke, Kenneth, Permanence and Change, Indianapolis, Indiana: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965.
Burke, Kenneth, Language as Symbolic Action, Berkeley: University of California Press,
1966.
Burke, Kenneth, Counterstatement, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1968a.
Burke, Kenneth, "Dramatism," International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, New
York: Macmillan, 1968b, pp. 445-452.
Burke, Kenneth, A Grammar of Motives, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1969a.
Burke, Kenneth, A Rhetoric of Motives, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1969b.
Burke, Kenneth, The Rhetoric of Religion, Berkeley: University of California Press,
1970.
Lipset, Seymour Martin, "The Sources of the Radical Right," in Daniel Bell, ed., The
Radical Right, Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 1963.
NOTES
13. I agree with Burke that "things" and the symbols for things are not the same; but
what one can know about "things" without symbols, apart from their resistance, is
quite mysterious. Thus, what the actual relations between phenomena might be is
always an hypothesis; the only way to address this is in the selection of a set of
terms by means of which to conduct an analysis. If human knowledge is acquired
through symbols, then the "actual" state of affairs of the world is not open to
human knowledge, only that "actuality" which enters in its symbolic "transforma-
tion."
14. See further, Overington, "Kenneth Burke as Social Theorist: He's Got Some
Explaining to Do," op. cit.
15. Louis Schneider, "Dialectic in Sociology," American Sociological Review 36
(August 1971), pp. 667-678.
16. "Epistemological perspectivism" is a locution chosen to express a philosophical
view of knowledge of the social world as fundamentally available only within
personal, social, and ideological perspectives; to claim that there is no knowledge of
social objects, no knowledge of persons, no social knowledge, therefore, which is
complete, absolute, unconditioned by intellectual frameworks and language. One
should not be tempted to see Burke as idiosyncratic in his perspectivism. Others
who have advocated similar positions are Karl Mannheim, George Mead, Alfred
Schutz, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, a distinguished collection of people who have
had some influence on the development of sociological thinking.
17. Karl Marx, Selected Writings in Sociology and Social Philosophy, T. B. Bottomore
and Maximilien Rubel, eds. (New York, 1956), p. 78.
18 Charles Morris, "The Strategy of Kenneth Burke," in William Rueckert, ed., op.
cit., p. 164.
19. Here Burke differs from both Plato and Hegel, for, of any one voice in the dialogue
(or dialectic, the terms are equivalent for him), "[It is] necessarily a restricted
perspective, since it represents but one voice in the dialogue, and not the perspec-
tive-of-perspectives that arises from the cooperative competition of all the voices as
they modify one another's assertions, so that the whole transcends the partiality of
its parts." [Kenneth Burke, A Grammar of Motives (Berkeley, California, 1969),
p. 89.]
20. Kenneth Burke, The Philosophy of Literary Form (New York, 1957), p. 328.
21. Kenneth Burke, Counterstatement (Berkeley, California, 1968), p. xi. 22.
22. Kenneth Burke, Attitudes Toward History (Boston, Mass., 1959), p. 308.
23. Kenneth Burke, Permanence and Change (Indianapolis, Indiana, 1965), pp. liv-lv.
When not applied too narrowly, this conception of "perspective by incongruity" is
not strange to sociology. Most familiar to American sociologists, perhaps, will be its
application by the Chicago School. Although the University of Chicago Sociological
Series, which is the best collection of the work of the researchers at Chicago,
contains around thirty-five volumes, it is the studies of deviance which are best
known and are seen as best representative of the School. It is in these volumes that
irony can be seen in the use of terms like "profession," "career," "morality," etc.,
to analyze the activity of deviants and criminals. This linking of "respectable"
terms with deviant activity quite clearly captures the sense of verbal incongruity to
which Burke is referring.
24. Burke, A Grammar of Motives, op. cit., pp. 402-418.
25. Burke, Attitudes Toward History, op. cit., p. 311.
26. Crane Brinton, "What is History?, " Saturday Review of Literature 15 (August,
1937), pp. 3-4, 11.
27. Burke, Permanence and Change, op. cit., p. 125.
28. For similar accounts of the procedures of psychoanalysis, cf. O. Hobart Mowrer,
The Crisis in Psychiatry and Religion (Princeton, New Jersey, 1961) and Jerome
Frank, Persuasion and Healing (New York, 1961). A parallel description of con-
50. Burke, The Philosophy of Literary Form, op. cit., pp. 56-75, and Kenneth Burke,
"Fact, Inference and Proof in the Analysis of Literary Symbolism," in Stanley
Hyman, ed., Terms for Order (Bloomington, Indiana, 1964), pp. 145-172.
51. Burke, The Philosophy of Literary Form, op. cit., pp. 6-7, 241-243.
52. Burke, Attitudes Toward History, op. cit., p. 200.
53. Burke, "Fact, Inference and Proof in the Analysis of Literary Symbolism," op. cit.,
p. 167.
54. Burke, The Philosophy of Literary Form, op. cit., p. 65.
55. Burke, "Dramatism," op. cit., p. 450.
56. Sigmund Freud, The Interpretation of Dreams (New York, 1965).
57. Burke, The Philosophy of Literary Form, op. cit., p. 229.
58. Freud, op. cit., p. 353.
59. Burke, The Philosophy of Literary Form, op. cit., p. 239.
60. Burke, A Grammar ofMotives, op. cit., pp. 503-517.
61. The parallels here with G. H. Mead, Sapir-Whorf, and the symbolic interactionist
tradition, are obvious.
62. Burke, Attitudes Toward History, op. cit., pp. 168-169.
63. Burke, A Grammar of Motives, op. cit., pp. 406-408.
64. See further, Zollschan and Overington, op. cit.
65. Burke, A Grammar of Motives, op. cit., p. xv.
66. For example, see Burke, Attitudes Toward ttistory, op. cit., pp. 111-165.
67. See Edmund Leach, Claude Levi-Strauss (New York, 1970).