Dewey's Theory of Value
Dewey's Theory of Value
Dewey's Theory of Value
Author(s): T. V. Smith
Source: The Monist , JULY, 1922, Vol. 32, No. 3 (JULY, 1922), pp. 339-354
Published by: Oxford University Press
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The Monist
IN THE
not onlyBELIEF
the hub of that JohnbutDewey's
his philosophy, theory of value is
that it also con
stitutes the chief contribution of Pragmatism to current
philosophy, I wish, in this paper, to show what Dewey's
theory of value is, to indicate its relations and significance,
and to adduce corroborations of the theory from certain
unexpected quarters.
No one can hope to understand Dewey's theory of value
who does not grasp rather fully the meaning that he at
taches to the term "experience." Such an intellectualiste
penumbra hangs over the word that some readers never
understand that Dewey means other than what they would
mean if they used the word in a similar connection. That
he does mean something different, and something more,
he has emphasized most vigorously in the introduction to
his Essays in Experimental Logic. It seems that Profes
sor Dewey himself did not for a long while get fully clear
the significance of the distinction; and he gives Mr. S.
Klyce credit for pointing out to him this and "other indis
pensable considerations." Upon this point Dewey ex
plains: "Our words divide into terms and into names
which are not (strictly speaking) terms at all, but which
serve to remind us of the vast and vague continuum, select
portions of which only are designated by words as terms."1
1 Essays in Experimental Logic, p. 8n.
Now the word "experience" and such other words are not
terms at all; they are what Mr. Clyce calls "infinity and
zero" words. As opposed to such a word as "desk" (which is
a term referring to a definite object, on which conscious
ness is or may be focussed), the word "experience" refers
to the fringe or penumbra of the situation in which "desk"
or any other term is the focus. As Dewey says: "The
word 'experience' is ... a notation of an inexpressible
as that which decides the ultimate status of all which is
expressed; inexpressible not because it is so remote and
transcendent, but because it is so immediately engrossing
and matter of course."2 Such a word, then, connotes what
is before and after and around that which at any given
time is denoted. "I shall only point out," says Dewey,
"that when the word 'experience' is employed in the text,
it means just such an immense and operative world of
diverse and interacting elements."3
Experience, as this will indicate, is a much broader
term than knowledge. Instead, therefore, of putting the
auestion as some philosophers have, i. e., whether there
are different ways of knowing, we must cease begging the
auestion and ask whether there are not different ways of
experiencing, of which knowing is only one. We certainly
must be content to put the matter in this way, if we are to
understand Dewey ; for Dewey makes this point in wholly
unambiguous language. "Knowing," says he, "is one
mode of experiencing, and the primary philosophic de
mand . . . is to find out what sort of an experience know
ing is?or, concretely how things are experienced when
they are experience as known things. ... To assume that,
because from the standpoint of the knowledge experience
things are what they are known to be, therefore, meta
physically, absolutely, without qualification, everything in
2 Essays in Experimental Logic, . 10 .
3 Essays in Experimental Logic, p. 7.
II
. Experience, which furnishes the context of all val
ues, is largely non-cognitive? It is well to emphasize this
non-cognitive basis of cognition itself ; for upon this plane
of experiencing lie most of the contents of our living. Here
are included our loves and our hates, our eating and our
sleeping, our friendships and our animosities, our illness
and our health ; here too are the fine arts ;7 here the dumb
gladness that welcomes the dawn, the quiet contemplation
of the sun's trailing glory at eventide, and the silent watch
ing of the passing night. This is the primal and ever the
larger aspect of human life. It is the good-in-itself, from
which reflection rises and for whose sake reflection exists
as an instrument.
2. Experience becomes cognitive only when incom
patibilities demand more than mere appreciation for their
successful resolution? Dewey is primarily interested in
intrinsic values, in the appreciative life described above.
Indeed, no living being, thinks he, ever becomes interested
in "extrinsic" value until he must in order to save and
extend some of the "intrinsic" content of his appreciative
life. Then judgment comes into play as an instrument
that is justified by resolving the difficulty back into a situa
Democracy and Education, p. 279.
6 "Experience is primarily an active-passive affair ; it is not primarily cog
nitive." Essays in Experimental Logic.
7 "For Dewev's feeling estimate of the place of art in life, see Reconstrue
tion in Philosophv, P. 212. Cf. Human Nature and Conduct, p. 159ff.
8 "Difficulties occasion thinking only when thinking is the imperative or
urgent way out. ..." Reconstruction in Philosophy, p. 139. Cf. Democracy
and Education, p. 280.
Ill
It is this ringing call for man to live in his own world
and this justification for his so doing, that constitutes the
essence of Dewey's philosophy. While others have cried
"lo, here; lo, there!" Dewey has continually insisted that
the kingdom of good is within human experience. It is dif
ficult to see why this course should need to be emphasized.
For other-wordliness is supposed to have passed with many
other anemic beauties of the mediaeval world. And this
is all that Dewey is really saying in his" theory of value :
values are immanent in human experience. Take them for
what they are: if they are many, so much the better; if
20 Darwin, p. 70.
21 Ibid., p. 75.
22 /?id., p. 71.
23 /Hdp. 69.
IV
If one must have in every philosophy a metaphysics, I
wonder if we might not call Dewey's theory of value, his
metaphysics? This is suggested to me by the discovery
that Dewey is treating in his theory of immediate values
what those who have monopolized the term "metaphysics"
treat under that head. The Absolute is the metaphysical
object, par excellence; and Dewey also has his doctrine of
the absolute or of absolutes. Every act of thinking finds
its specific absolute in the restored immediate experience
to which the act is instrumental. Immediate experience is
absolute in the sense that it is the end of the problematic
situation, and as such is consequently "invaluable."81 Im
mediate experience enjoys the same surcease from the
exigencies of thinking as does Bradley's Absolute. It
seems to me that all the really distinctive and valuable at
tributes of the historical Absolute is preserved in Dewey's
absolute(s), for the doctrine of the Absolute (absolutists
to the contrary notwithstanding) has ever been an effort
to guarantee emotional satisfaction through the procedure
of rationalization. Dewey guarantees it, not by rationaliz
ing, but by recognizing it for what it is and setting about
with scientific foresight to make it permanent. In short,
Dewey has succeeded in showing how within human expe
rience itself, thought, instead of breeding vast contradic
tions through its relational nature, is, in the ascent of man,
the instrument evolved for the resolution of the difficulties
V
I wish now to return briefly to Dewey's own th
order to consider what seems to me the most sig
objection made to it, an objection raised curiously
not more by critics than by Dewey himself. Dew
ory of value, as we have seen, calls for a dichotom
experience; i. e., appreciation and reflection. But
actually exist, separated from each other, as t
sion seems to imply? However appreciative it
is not all experience judgmental, implicitly at lea
too easy to beg the question with the use of the t
plicit." That all experience, however purely appre
may (and does) become judgmental on occasion
both admits and affirms. Moreover, he explain
"the occasion." But if the critics should affirm
experience is actually judgmental, they would be
more than Dewey himself seems more than once to
With this admission one might still maintain t
two aspects?judgmental and appreciative?pred
in different situations, as Dewey himself affirms.
admit that all experiences are all the time actually
with more or less of the judgmental aspect, it see
that the distinction loses much of its significanc
still be justified as an explanatory device, but
longer be sharply descriptive of actual experie
lieving that the division is not only explanatory
rately descriptive of human experience as well,
feel that Dewey need make the admission (if the
quoted below and other similar ones constitute
sion.)38
32 "No experience having a meaning is possible without some element of
thought. But we may contrast two types of experience, according to the pro
portion of reflection found in them." {Democracy and Education, p. 169.)
38 "That something of the cognitive . . . enters in as a catalyzer ... in
even the most aesthetic experiences, seems to be altogether probable." (Loaic,
p. 394.)
84 It is, I think, because he does not clearly recognize this that Mr. Delton
Thomas Howard in Dewey's Logical Theory (Cornell Studies in Philosophy,
No. 11), is betrayed first into admitting that "it is doubtless true that men think
only occasionally and with some reluctance" (p. 124), later into the declaration
that "there is nothing in evidence to show that thinking is a special kind of
activity, which operates now and then" (p. 127), and finally into the distinc
tion that "the moment of real, earnest thinking is at the high tide of life, when
all the powers are awake and operating" (p. 132).