Stephan Muller 2006 Phrasal or Lexical Constructions
Stephan Muller 2006 Phrasal or Lexical Constructions
Stephan Muller 2006 Phrasal or Lexical Constructions
1. INTRODUCTION. Since the 1990s, more and more linguistic articles have been
published in the framework of CONSTRUCTION GRAMMAR. Some influential publications
are Goldberg 1995, Fillmore 1999, and Kay & Fillmore 1999. Although Kay and
Fillmore (1999:19) make it clear that Constructions are not necessarily phrasal, most
of the authors suggest phrasal Constructions.1 This is especially apparent in construction
grammar-inspired studies in the framework of head-driven phrase structure grammar
(HPSG; see for instance Sag 1997, Ginzburg & Sag 2001, Borsley 2004, Haugereid
2004).
In what follows I show that the difference between phrasal approaches and lexical
approaches is not as great as is sometimes claimed, although selecting one approach
over the other may nevertheless have serious consequences. This discussion focuses
on resultative constructions, a phenomenon for which both phrasal and lexical analyses
have been suggested. A considerable number of different Constructions must be postu-
lated to account for all of the patterns that may arise from the reordering of constituents
or the realization of the resultative construction in connection with valence-changing
processes. It is shown that adjuncts, predicate complexes, and derivational morphology
pose considerable problems for the phrasal approach, while they are unproblematic for
lexical rule-based approaches. An example of the resultative construction is given in 1.
The resultative construction consists of a verb that denotes some event and a secondary
predicate that provides information about the result of the event. In 1, the secondary
predicate predicates over an NP that is not an argument of the verb. There are other
patterns of resultative constructions, but they are not discussed here since they are
irrelevant to the issue under discussion (see for instance Simpson 1983 and Rothstein
1985).
(1) They drank the pub dry.
* I thank Brian D. Joseph, the editor of Language, associate editor James McCloskey, and an anonymous
referee for detailed comments on an earlier version of this discussion note.
I also thank Ann Copestake, Kerstin Fischer, Paul Kay, Laura Michaelis, Detmar Meurers, Frank Richter,
Ivan Sag, Anatol Stefanowitsch, and Arne Zeschel for discussion, and John Bateman, Dorothee Beermann,
Gisbert Fanselow, Hans-Ulrich Krieger, Andrew McIntyre, and Shravan Vasishth for discussion and com-
ments on earlier versions of this manuscript.
I gave presentations about phrasal and lexical analyses of the resultative construction at the Institute for
General and Applied Linguistics at the University of Bremen, at the Institute of Cognitive Science at the
University of Osnabrück, at the Deutsches Seminar of the University of Tübingen, at the Linguistics Institute
of the Ruhr University Bochum, at the workshop Foundations of Natural-Language Grammar at the ESSLLI
2005 in Edinburgh, and at HPSG 2005 in Lisbon. I thank the respective departments for the invitation, the
reviewers of the conference and the workshop for comments, and the audiences for comments and discussion.
The resultative construction was also one of the topics discussed during the Ph.D. school Languages and
Theories in Contrast in Bergen in 2005. I enjoyed the discussion very much and want to thank the organizers
Helge Dyvik and Torbjørn Nordgård, my coteachers Miriam Butt, Helge Dyvik, and Peter Svenonius, and
the audience again.
1
Throughout the discussion note I use the term ‘construction’ in a theory-neutral way. For constructions
in the sense of construction grammar, I use ‘Construction.’
850
DISCUSSION NOTE 851
Such constructions have been analyzed as SMALL CLAUSES (see for instance Hoekstra
1988, den Dikken 1995), as complex predicates where drank and dry form a constituent
at some level of representation (Dowty 1979:Ch. 4.7 for English; Neeleman & Weer-
mann 1993, Neeleman 1995 for English and Dutch; Müller 2002:Ch. 5 for German),
or as phrasal constructions (Goldberg 1995, Jackendoff 1997, Goldberg & Jackendoff
2004). In the following, I mainly discuss the question of how the combination of the
verb with the NP the pub and the predicate dry is licensed. Proponents of (phrasal)
construction grammar suggest either a phrasal Construction that licenses subject, verb,
object, and secondary predicate as in 2a or a phrasal Construction that licenses verb,
object, and secondary predicate as in 2b.
(2) a. [SUBJ [V OBJ OBL]] (Goldberg 1995:192)
b. VP N V NP AP/PP (Goldberg & Jackendoff 2004)
The lexicon-oriented approaches, by contrast, do not assume special phrase structure
rules for resultative constructions, but rather additional lexical items that license the
elements present in resultative constructions (see Simpson 1983, Wunderlich 1992:45,
Verspoor 1997, Wechsler 1997, Wechsler & Noh 2001, and Müller 2002 for analyses
of English, German, and Korean resultative constructions).
Approaches like Goldberg’s face certain problems when interaction with other phe-
nomena (e.g. passive, middle) is considered. In the following, I transfer Goldberg’s
analysis to German and show that further problems arise since German has a much freer
constituent order than English and allows interaction with derivational morphology. The
problems that already exist in the analysis of English are thus much more apparent. I
deal with interactions between resultative constructions and syntax (§2) and morphology
(§5). While there are several phenomena for which it is unclear what a phrasal analysis
might look like, it is clear that a large number of phrasal Constructions is needed to
account for the patterns that can be analyzed. Proponents of construction grammar
argue that this is not a problem since the regularities are captured in an inheritance
hierarchy and such inheritance hierarchies can be computed automatically from the set
of Constructions that are stated by the grammar writer. I show in §3 that the algorithm
that was suggested by Kay (2002:§7.1) does not work and that attempts to fix it lead
to unwanted consequences. I then discuss examples from Yucatec Maya that show that
passives cannot be analyzed with reference to classification in an inheritance hierarchy.
A discussion of the alternative lexical rule-based approaches follows, in which I com-
pare them with the phrasal approach. I next address the question of whether phrasal
approaches are needed at all, and show how phrasal approaches to other phenomena
such as idioms, for instance, can be converted into lexical approaches.
trees of a depth greater than one, and thus the constraints would be nonlocal, something
against which, for instance, Sag (2007) explicitly argues.
To give a full account of German resultatives, one has to explain the following
constituent-order phenomena.
1. Arguments can be reordered.
(6) a. weil niemand den Teich leer fischt
because nobody.NOM the pond.ACC empty fishes
‘because nobody fishes the pond empty’
b. weil den Teich niemand leer fischt
because the pond.ACC nobody.NOM empty fishes
2. The finite verb can appear in both initial (7) and final position (6).
(7) Fischt jemand den Teich leer?
fishes somebody the pond empty
‘Does somebody fish the pond empty?’
3. Adjuncts may appear anywhere between arguments.
(8) a. daß schnell jemand den Teich leer fischt
that quickly somebody the pond empty fishes
‘that somebody is fishing the pond empty quickly’
b. daß jemand schnell den Teich leer fischt
that somebody quickly the pond empty fishes
c. daß jemand den Teich schnell leer fischt
that somebody the pond quickly empty fishes
4. Arguments and adjuncts belonging to resultative constructions and predicates that
embed the resultative construction may be permuted and interleaved.
(9) a. weil niemand ihn den Teich leer fischen sah
because nobody.NOM him.ACC the pond.ACC empty fish saw
‘because nobody saw him fish the pond empty’
b. weil ihn den Teich niemand leer fischen sah
because him.ACC the pond.ACC nobody.NOM empty fish saw
In 9, niemand ‘nobody’ is dependent upon sah ‘saw’, but in 9b it is serialized between
the resultative predicate and its subject.
In transformation-based accounts, constituent reordering, fronting, and passive can
be explained by movement operations. Adjunct serialization can be explained by assum-
ing that adjuncts attach to VPs and the material from inside of the VP is scrambled to
positions preceding the adjuncts. Such analyses are usually rejected in nonderivational
constraint-based frameworks, and thus they are not an option for proponents of phrasal
construction grammar analyses. Instead, additional Constructions have to be stipulated
that account for patterns not covered by 4. In what follows, I show which Constructions
are needed to account for the patterns mentioned so far and for other interactions with
the grammar of German.
2.1. LOCAL REORDERING OF CONSTITUENTS. Since subject and object may be permuted
and since the verb can appear both in initial and in final positions, at least the following
Constructions are needed.2
2
Of course it is possible to distinguish between immediate dominance and linear precedence, as is done
in HPSG. The four Constructions in 10 could then be collapsed into one. But the reorderings come with
information-structure effects, and given that other reorderings such as Heavy NP Shift (Kay 2002) and
Subject-Auxiliary Inversion (Fillmore 1999) in English are modeled by Constructions, it thus seems safe to
assume that proponents of phrasal Constructions would posit Constructions for all of the patterns. See also
Goldberg 1995:7 for a statement regarding the representation of information about focused constituents and
DISCUSSION NOTE 853
2.2. FRONTING. German is a verb-second language. The position in front of the finite
verb is filled by a single constituent that is extracted from the remaining clause. The
fronted element may be deeply embedded and, thus, a nonlocal dependency is involved.
As far as resultatives are concerned, the subject (13a), the object (13b), an adjunct
(13c), or the resultative predicate (13d) can be fronted.
(13) a. Er fischt den Teich schnell leer.
he fishes the pond quickly empty
‘He is fishing the pond empty quickly.’
b. Den Teich fischt er schnell leer.
the pond fishes he quickly empty
c. Schnell fischt er den Teich leer.
quickly fishes he the pond empty
d. Leer fischt er den Teich nicht.
empty fishes he the pond not
‘He is not fishing the pond empty.’
topicality in Constructions. Comments about Constructions and information structure can also be found in
Goldberg 2006:220.
The question of how verbs are ordered is independent of the order of SUBJ and OBJ, and Goldberg could
assume an empty verbal head in clause-final position that is related to an overt verb in clause-initial position.
Constructions 10a and 10b would then be sufficient and 10c and 10d would have the structures [Vi [SUBJ
OBJ OBL i ]] and [Vi [OBJ SUBJ OBL i ]], respectively. However, empty elements are usually avoided
in construction grammar. See Kathol 1997 for a proposal regarding German clause structure and n. 3 below
for remarks on traces.
In any case, for the passive and fronting cases discussed below, additional Constructions are needed since
the passive involves valence change and fronting involves a nonlocal dependency.
854 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
If one wants to avoid positing empty elements,3 additional Constructions for the intro-
duction of nonlocal dependencies are needed.4
(14) a. [V SUBJ OBL] (OBJ extracted)
b. [V OBJ OBL] (SUBJ extracted)
c. [V SUBJ OBJ] (OBL extracted)
d. [V OBJ SUBJ] (OBL extracted, OBJ and SUBJ permuted)
If one follows the phrasal approach, information about extracted elements cannot be
introduced lexically, since some parts of the Construction are contributed by the Con-
struction itself and hence cannot be accessed at the lexical level. An analysis of extrac-
tion such as the one suggested by Bouma and colleagues (2001) is thus incompatible
with the phrasal approach to resultatives.5
In addition to the Constructions in 14, one needs those in 16 to account for resultative
constructions in relative clauses and interrogative clauses like those in 15.
(15) a. der Mann, der den Teich leer fischt
the man who the pond empty fishes
‘the man who fishes the pond empty’
b. den Teich, den Richard leer fischt
the pond that Richard empty fishes
‘the pond that Richard fishes empty’
c. Er hat gefragt, wie platt Max das Metall gehämmert hat.
he has asked how flat Max the metal hammered has
‘He asked how flat Max hammered the metal.’
The relative phrase and the interrogative phrase, that is, the phrase containing the
relative pronoun or the interrogative pronoun, respectively, is usually analyzed as a
phrase that is extracted from the rest of the clause.
(16) a. [SUBJ OBL V] (OBJ extracted)
b. [OBJ OBL V] (SUBJ extracted)
c. [SUBJ OBJ V] (OBL extracted)
d. [OBJ SUBJ V] (OBL extracted)
The Constructions in 16 differ from those in 14 with respect to the serialization of the
verb: relative clauses and interrogative clauses are verb-final. Example 16 contains
patterns for the extraction of OBJ, SUBJ, and OBL (16a–c) and a fourth Construction
in which OBL is extracted and SUBJ and OBJ are permuted.
3
See for instance Kay & Fillmore 1999:7, 14 for a traceless analysis of extraction and Michaelis &
Ruppenhofer 2001:49–50 and Goldberg 2006:10 on the status of empty elements in construction grammar.
The analysis of English relative clauses suggested by Sag (1997) was developed in order to eliminate the
empty head that was necessary in the analysis of relative clauses in Pollard & Sag 1994:Ch. 5.
4
See also Müller 2002:Ch. 6.2.5.1, Ch. 7.3 and Müller 2007a for discussion. An approach that corresponds
to 14 is proposed by Haugereid (2004). Since Haugereid does not use a valence list that contains all the
arguments of a head, he cannot capture the commonalities of Constructions with an extracted subject and
those with an extracted object. The respective Constructions have to be stipulated in an inheritance network
separately.
5
Goldberg (2006:155) cites Sag and Fodor (1994) for a traceless account of long-distance dependencies
in a monostratal framework. This analysis is the predecessor of the Bouma, Malouf, and Sag paper (2001).
It is also lexical and incompatible with a phrasal analysis of resultative constructions.
DISCUSSION NOTE 855
Extraction patterns for the focus split Ⳮ resultative construction are also needed.
(17) a. [OBL OBJ V] (SUBJ extracted)
b. [OBL SUBJ V] (OBJ extracted)
c. [V OBL OBJ] (SUBJ extracted)
d. [V OBL SUBJ] (OBJ extracted)
The patterns in 17 are verb-final and verb-initial patterns with SUBJ or OBJ extracted
and OBL and the other remaining element permuted.
I have dealt here with local constituent reordering and extraction, but the surface
pattern of the resultative construction may also change due to changes in argument
realization. I next discuss passives, modal infinitives, and the middle construction.
2.3. PASSIVE, MODAL INFINITIVES, AND THE MIDDLE CONSTRUCTION. Resultatives can
appear in agentive passive sentences (18a), in stative passive sentences (18b), in the
middle construction (18c), and in modal infinitive constructions (18d).
(18) a. Der Teich wurde leer gefischt.
the pond.NOM was empty fished
b. Der Teich ist leer gefischt.
the pond.NOM is empty fished
c. Der Weinkeller trinkt sich schnell leer.6
the wine.cellar.NOM drinks self fast empty
‘What’s in the wine cellar is drunk quickly.’
d. Der Teich ist bis Montag leer zu fischen.
the pond.NOM is until Monday empty to fish
‘The pond has to be fished empty by Monday.’
The previous subsections show that one needs four Constructions for permutations of
subject and object, eight permutations for focus-split constructions in which the resulta-
tive predicate appears between or in front of the NPs, and twelve Constructions for
traceless extractions (if we abstract away from local reordering, four Constructions are
still needed). In addition, the following Constructions are needed to account for passive
together with reorderings, focus movement, and extractions.
(19) a. [SUBJ OBL V] (passive) e. [V SUBJ OBL] (passive)
b. [OBL SUBJ V] (passive, focus m.) f. [V OBL SUBJ] (passive,
focus m.)
c. [OBL V] (passive, SUBJ extracted) g. [V OBL] (passive, SUBJ
extracted)
d. [SUBJ V] (passive, OBL extracted) h. [V SUBJ] (passive, OBL
extracted)
On top of that, one needs Constructions for the middle construction and for modal
infinitives. The middle suppresses the logical subject of the verb and adds a dummy
reflexive, which allows for additional permutations.
Since some of the arguments in the Resultative Construction can be introduced by
the Construction, passive cannot be treated as a lexical process but must be treated on
the phrasal level. Therefore treatments in terms of lexical linking Constructions as
suggested by Kay and Fillmore (1999:12) and Michaelis and Ruppenhofer (2001:Ch.
4) or the more conventional analyses in terms of lexical rules (Bresnan 1982, Pollard &
Sag 1987:214–18, Müller 2002:Ch. 3) are excluded. Goldberg (1995:78–79) seems to
6
Wunderlich 1997:118. See also Koch & Rosengren 1995:17 for similar data.
856 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
We set aside here passive and middle resultatives, such as The metal was hammered flat and This metal
hammers flat easily. We take it that these expressions are formed by composing the passive and middle
constructions with resultative constructions.
2.4. ADJUNCTS. A further problem seems to be adjuncts like schnell ‘fast’ in 8. Since
the adjunct scopes over the semantic contribution of the Resultative Construction, one
needs a Construction like 20 to account for 8c, unless one is willing to assume a
discontinuous Resultative Construction that allows an adjunct to appear between parts
of the Resultative Construction.
(20) [SUBJ OBJ Adjunct OBL V]
In what follows, I discuss approaches to adjuncts suggested in the construction grammar
literature and show that these proposals cannot be used to analyze 8 and that therefore,
the stipulation of Constructions like 20 seems unavoidable. I start with the analysis
suggested by Kay and Fillmore (1999) and then turn to that of Kay (2005).
7
Goldberg (1995:7, 2006:205) states that construction grammar is not transformational.
8
Since Goldberg (1995:192) assumes the complex structure in (i), GPSG metarules cannot be used to
map active Constructions to passive Constructions. GPSG metarules apply to simple phrase structure rules
only, not to trees with a depth greater than one.
(i) [SUBJ [V OBJ OBL]]
A metarule approach could be assumed if the Resultative Construction were a specialization of the rule in
2b.
9
See Goldberg 2006:22, n. 3 for the stipulation of the Passive ditransitive Construction, that is, a specific
passive Construction that is relevant for ditransitive verbs only.
10
Setting adjuncts are, for instance, those of time, place, and condition. Such adjuncts are licensed by the
Setting Construction.
DISCUSSION NOTE 857
cat v
I FRAME ARRIVE
sem
ARGS {A}
val {[sem{A}]}
b. Setting Construction11
cat v
I FRAME [] , II FRAME []
sem
ARGS {} ARGS {I}
val {[sem{[II ]}]}
The items in 21 provide information about the part of speech of the respective object
(represented as value of CAT) and information about the meaning of the linguistic object
(represented as the value of SEM), and also refer to the valence of a linguistic object
(represented under VAL). In 21a the semantics of a dependent element—that is, an
element that is contained in VAL —is identified with an argument slot in a semantic
frame. This is indicated by the ‘A’. The Setting Construction is a Construction that
has to be unified with a verbal constituent already containing the scene indexed as I. The
Setting Construction adds a scene, typically a locational or temporal setting, indexed as
II.
Kay and Fillmore want to extend the valence set of the lexical entry by unification with
the Setting Construction. The intended result is a structure that contains both the element
the verb originally selects in 21a and an additional element, namely the adjunct contrib-
uted by the Setting Construction. According to Kay and Fillmore, the unification of
21a and 21b plus additional information provided by the lexical item before is as in 22.
(22) Unification of 21a and 21b and the information in the lexical entry of before,
according to Kay and Fillmore
cat v
I FRAME ARRIVE , II FRAME BEFORE
sem
ARGS {A} ARGS {I, E}
CAT p
[sem{A}], LEXICAL-HEAD before
val
GF obj
VAL
SEM E
But this presupposes a special definition of set unification that allows the extension of
the number of elements in a set. Since an element of a set may also be unified with
one element of the other set (the first element in SEM in 21b with the element in SEM
in 21a), Kay and Fillmore’s version of unification cannot be understood as a (multi)
11
The ‘兵 其’ stands for an unspecified set, not for the empty set.
858 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
set union as in Krieger et al. 2004.12 If set unification can result in set union and in
element unification, the result of the unification of the elements in SEM should be a
disjunction of the value given in 22 and a set that contains the set union of the two
SEM sets. Thus the notion of set unification that Kay and Fillmore assume seems not
to be sound.
The unification of two structures FS1 and FS2 is defined to be the structure FS3 that
is subsumed by both FS1 and FS2 and that is not subsumed by any other structure that
is subsumed by both FS1 and FS2 . Intuitively, this states that the information represented
in FS1 and the information represented in FS2 is also represented in FS3 , but FS3
includes no additional information. FS1 and FS2 are less specific than or equally as
specific as FS3 . If set unification is assumed to be set union, the definition of unification
would require the following understanding of valence representations: a valence value
兵NP其 says something like the following: this lexical item needs at least one NP argument.
A valence value 兵NP, NP其 says: this lexical item needs at least two NP arguments. This
means that the last valence list is more specific than the first one. The set of objects
described by the first valence list includes the set of objects described by the last one.
In particular, transitive verbs are a special case of intransitive verbs, which is not what
is usually assumed when linguistic objects are classified with respect to their valence.13
It is interesting to note that if set unification is (multi) set union, the result of unifying
a structure with itself differs from the structure.
(23) [F 兵a其] [F 兵a其] ⱨ [F 兵a, a其]
This is not consistent with the definition of unification given above since the unification
of X with X should be X and not a more specific structure. In some knowledge-
representation systems that are used in artificial intelligence, the unification of two sets
S1 and S2 is defined in a way that elements in S2 that are compatible with elements
from S1 are unified while elements that are not compatible with any elements of S1 are
added to the result set. The examples given in Clark & Porter 2004:36 are shown in
24.
(24) a. 兵cat, dog其 兵dog, elephant其 ⳱ 兵cat, dog, elephant其
b. 兵cat其 兵cat其 ⳱ 兵cat其
But since adjunction is recursive (see below), one needs multi sets: it has to be
possible that one predicate appears more than once in a set. With the above definition
of set unification, the unification of arrive with two adjunct constructions would be
25a and not the intended 25b.
(25) a. 兵[sem 兵A其]其 兵[sem 兵[ II ]其]其 兵[sem 兵[ II ]其]其 ⳱
兵[sem 兵A其], [sem 兵[ II ]其]其
b. 兵[sem 兵A其]其 兵[sem 兵[ II ]其]其 兵[sem 兵[ II ]其]其 ⬆
兵[sem 兵A其], [sem 兵[ II ]其], [sem 兵[ II ]其]其
The following example by Frey and Gärtner (2002:47–48) shows that recursion is
needed for handling adjuncts.
(26) dass Hans den Tisch ungeschickt geschickt ungeschickt abräumte
that Hans the table clumsily skillfully clumsily cleared
12
A multi set may contain an element several times. Thus 兵a, a, b其 is a multi set but no set.
13
In HPSG, it is assumed that two sets of different arity do not unify unless some elements in the set
that has more elements describe the same object. See for instance Pollard & Sag 1987:47–49, Pollard &
Moshier 1990, and Carpenter 1992:34 for discussions of set unification. With the HPSG definition, transitive
verbs are no more special than intransitive verbs and vice versa.
DISCUSSION NOTE 859
This results in a total of 218 Constructions. These Constructions account for most of
the phenomena discussed so far. Adjuncts and complex predicates, as discussed in §2.5,
are not included, and there are probably other phenomena that interact with the resulta-
tive construction in a way that would make the stipulation of even further Constructions
necessary.
If local reordering of constituents is accounted for by separating dominance from
precedence information, as was done in GPSG (Gazdar et al. 1985), the Constructions
given in Table 2 are needed (see n. 2 on reordering).
CONSTITUENTS PHENOMENON 噛 OF CONSTRUCTIONS
SUBJ OBJ OBL V Active RC 1
Extraction 3
SUBJ OBL V V-Aux Passive RC 1
Extraction 3
SUBJ OBL V V-Aux Modal Infinitive RC 1
Extraction 3
SUBJ Refl Adj OBL V Middle RC 1
Extraction 3
Various readers ask whether it is sufficient for arguing against an analysis to show that
one has to pose 218 rules to describe certain phenomena.15 After all, there are certainly
cases in the literature (e.g. Janda 1998) where the formulation of large numbers of
rules is justified.
I agree that sometimes the stipulation of special rules or phrasal Constructions is
justified. For example, computational grammars are often required to analyze phenom-
ena that are (for diverse reasons) seldom if ever mentioned in the literature on grammati-
cal theory. One example of this is date expressions, where it is probably sensible to
assume special rules that cover just these expressions. The difference between such
cases and the Constructions discussed so far is that the syntax of date expressions
cannot be made to follow from anything, while it is sufficient to state one resultative
lexical rule (Müller 2002:241 and §6 below), one participle-formation lexical rule
(Müller 2002:151), one infinitive-formation lexical rule (Müller 2002:153), one lexical
rule for free datives, and syntactic rules for verb positioning (a lexical rule that licenses
fronted verbs (Kiss & Wesche 1991, Müller 2005b)), scrambling (as part of the general
schema for head-argument combination (Müller 2005b)), and extraction (Pollard & Sag
1994, Müller 2005b) to get the effect of the 218 Constructions above. The participle-
formation lexical rule and the infinitive lexical rule are responsible for appropriate
inflection of the infinitives, something that has to be accounted for in a phrasal model
as well (in addition to the 218 Constructions). Thus these lexical rules do not count in
terms of a comparison. An adjunction rule (Pollard & Sag 1994:Ch. 1.9) together with
15
I would like to thank editors Brian Joseph and James McCloskey for raising this question.
DISCUSSION NOTE 863
binary branching structures accounts for the placement of adjuncts in 8, and the predicate
complex schema (Hinrichs & Nakazawa 1989, Müller 2005b:21) together with appro-
priate lexical entries for sehen ‘see’ licenses 29. For the phrasal approach, no analysis
exists for 29. A further difference between the lexical and the phrasal model is that
the lexical approach states one resultative rule and the interaction with the rest of the
grammar follows from constraints on syntactic structures and from input conditions of
other lexical rules. By comparison, the phrasal approach has to stipulate a Construction
for every single case, since Kay’s algorithm, which was suggested to compute interac-
tions of Constructions, is not sound, as is shown in the next section.
Joseph 1997 argues that there are no complete generalizations and that one has to
be prepared to find counterexamples and subregularities, which may originate from
language contact, for instance. He discusses the claim that Adj N is the normal order
in NPs like the fat cat and that the cat fat is ungrammatical. He states the corresponding
generalization in 32.
(32) [NP ADJ N]/*[NP N ADJ]
He notes that sequences like attorney general, however, contradict the negative pat-
tern.16 This problem can be fixed easily in theories that allow for a more fine-grained
categorization of linguistic objects: if it is possible to distinguish adjectives that have
to appear in prenominal position from those that appear postnominally, grammatical
theory has no problem. If a linguistic grammar contains a statement like 32 and it is
pointed out that examples like attorney general contradict this statement, the statement
that describes ADJ has to be made more specific. The same applies for the case at
hand: resultative constructions interact with the normal syntax as expected, but if there
were a particular resultative construction that did not allow for the placement of the
finite verb in initial position (no such thing exists), one would have to specify subclasses
and rule out the positioning of the finite verb in initial position for one of the subclasses.
So, I believe it to be valid to assume one lexical rule in addition to a general syntactic
system containing the six parts mentioned above to account for the data discussed so
far, and this solution has to be preferred over the phrasal alternative.
3. AUTOMATIC COMPUTATION OF CONSTRUCTION-LIKE OBJECTS. It might appear that
an analysis based on 218 distinct constructions is unobjectionable, given that Kay (2002:
§7.1) has suggested an algorithm that computes so-called CONSTRUCTION-LIKE OBJECTS
from a small set of specified Constructions. Construction-like objects are descriptions
of phrasal configurations or lexical items that result from the interaction of Construc-
tions. For the analysis of resultative constructions one would specify the Construction
hierarchy in Figure 1, and the algorithm would compute construction-like objects for
all compatible Constructions. The result of this computation would be equivalent to a
Construction hierarchy with explicitly specified Constructions for the respective combi-
nations (Figure 2).
construction
16
See also Dürscheid 2002 for a discussion of the German Forelle blau ‘trout blue’ and Deutsche Syntax
deklarativ ‘German syntax declarative.’
864 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
construction
Kay suggests the following in his ‘Informal sketch of a formal architecture for con-
struction grammar’ (2002:§7.1).
Unlike LFG phrase structure rules and lexical items and unlike HPSG maximal types, distinct maximal
constructions can span the same (piece of) FT [feature structure tree—SM]. For example, the English
VP construction, which provides for a lexical verb followed by an arbitrary number of constituents
(subject to valence restrictions), can unify with a construction specifically licensing a VP displaying
the ‘heavy NP shift’ property. In order to specify an explicit recursive licensing procedure for sentences,
we need some way to deal with this overlap of constructions. We wish to reduce the set of constructions
of a grammar to a set of construction-like objects (let’s call them CLOs) with the property that in
licensing a given sentence, exactly one CLO licenses each node. To obtain the set of CLOs from the
set of constructions C: (1) form the power set of the set of constructions ℘(C); (2) for each set of
constructions in ℘(C), attempt to unify all the members, matching the root nodes; (3) throw away all
the sets that don’t unify; (4) the remainder is the set of CLOs.
17
At first glance, one might get the impression that the algorithm could be fixed by replacing ‘power set’
by ‘restricted powerset’. RESTRICTED POWERSETS are defined as follows and were used, for instance, for the
computation of greatest lower bounds in type hierarchies (Aı̈t-Kaci et al. 1989):
The restricted powerset of a poset S, ⱕ is the set 2(S) of nonempty finite subsets of pairwise incomparable
elements of S.
But in the case discussed here, only maximally specific Constructions (leaves in the inheritance hierarchy)
are considered. Therefore the restricted powerset of the set of Constructions under consideration is identical
to the power set of this set without the empty set.
DISCUSSION NOTE 865
is, the result of the unifications of elements in sets is added to the set of CLOs only
if it does not subsume any other unification result.18
However, the modified algorithm would fail in one particular case that is otherwise
considered a highlight of construction grammar, namely idiomatic expressions: since
idiomatic Constructions are subconstructions of regular Constructions, having idiomatic
Constructions in the power set would cause the nonidiomatic Constructions to be elimi-
nated from the set of CLOs since nonidiomatic Constructions are more general and
subsume the idiomatic Constructions.
For the purpose of illustration let us assume that we have Constructions for the VP, for
Transitive, and an idiomatic Construction for kick the bucket. The set of Constructions is
thus 34a. The power set of this set is 34b. If the set of CLOs is allowed to contain the
most specific construction-like objects only, the result would be 34c, but this is a set
that contains a construction-like object that describes kick the bucket and no other
VP with a transitive verb. The intended outcome is 34d, which also admits normal,
nonidiomatic VPs with transitive verbs.
(34) a. C ⳱ 兵VP, Transitive, kick the bucket其
b. ℘(C) ⳱ 兵兵 其,
兵VP Construction其,
兵Transitive其,
兵kick the bucket其,
兵VP Construction, Transitive其,
兵VP Construction, kick the bucket其,
兵Transitive, kick the bucket其,
兵VP Construction, Transitive, kick the bucket其其
c. Result with a subsumption test in the algorithm:
CLOs ⳱ 兵VP Construction Transitive kick the bucket其
d. Desired result:
CLOs ⳱ 兵VP Construction Transitive,
VP Construction Transitive kick the bucket其
It could be argued that idiomatic Constructions have to be specified in a way that does
not include the information contributed by more general Constructions (this is what
Kay and Fillmore (1999) do in the case of the What is X doing Y? Construction19 ).
For our artificial example in 34 this means that the kick the bucket Construction does
not contain information about the VP Construction and the Transitive Construction.
The information that was left out on purpose could then be obtained by the CLO
computation. However, idioms vary in syntactic flexibility (Fleischer 1982, Nunberg
et al. 1994). For instance, some idiomatic expressions resist passivization, and others
do not allow fronting of idiom parts or relativization. So, for instance, the kick the
bucket Construction would not have a passive subconstruction, since the idiom cannot
be passivized without losing the idiomatic reading. One way to capture such syntactic
18
There is a problem with the understanding of valence and semantics sets assumed in Kay & Fillmore
1999. Since 兵a其 subsumes 兵a, b其, a Construction C1 that differs from another Construction C2 by containing
more information in semantics sets or valence sets will be subsumed by C1 . This would result in the elimination
of C1 from the set of Constructs. An example for such a situation might be adjuncts or free datives if they
are introduced at a phrasal Construction.
19
Examples of this Construction are given in (i).
(i) a. What is this scratch doing on the table?
b. What is it doing raining?
866 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
to the passive and show that inheritance-based analyses of passive are not appropriate for
all languages. The conclusion is that—if one wants to analyze passive crosslinguisti-
cally in a uniform way—neither English nor German passives should be analyzed with
reference to inheritance hierarchies. As mentioned in §2.3, Goldberg assumes a cross-
classification of the Resultative Construction with regard to the active and passive
dimension, that is, she assumes a hierarchy of the kind shown in Fig. 2. This cross-
classification of Constructions with respect to active and passive is also suggested by
Kay and Fillmore (1999:12) and Michaelis and Ruppenhofer (2001:Ch. 4).20 Kay and
Fillmore’s and Michaelis and Ruppenhofer’s analyses differ from Goldberg’s in that
they assume that linking patterns are verb-level Constructions, which unify with the
lexical entries of verbs (Michaelis & Ruppenhofer 2001:39). With respect to the data
that I discuss below, however, it does not matter whether a phrasal or a lexical approach
is chosen: the data show that inheritance-based analyses are inappropriate to handle
passive.
The examples in 35, which are Yucatec Maya, show that multiple passivization of
a word is possible, if a causative morpheme intervenes: 35a shows an active sentence
with the verb learn and 35b its passive variant.21 Example 35c demonstrates that the verb
learn can be causativized. The result is equivalent to the English teach. Interestingly, it
is possible to embed a passivized verb under the causative morpheme, as is shown in
35d. The causative morpheme adds an argument for the causer, which can be affected
by passivization, as is shown in 35e.
(35) a. K⳱u kan-ik le teòria-o’.
INCOMPL⳱3.ERG learn-IMPF DET theory-D1
‘He is learning the theory.’
b. K⳱u ká’an-al le teòria-o’.
INCOMPL⳱3.ERG learn.PASS-IMPF DET theory-D1
‘The theory is being learned.’
c. K⳱u kan-s-k-en le teòria-o’.
INCOMPL⳱3.ERG learn-CAUS-IMPF-me DET theory-D1
‘He teaches me the theory.’ (‘He causes that I learn the theory.’)
d. K⳱u ká’an-s-ik le teòria-o’.
INCOMPL⳱3.ERG learn.PASS-CAUS-IMPF DET theory-D1
‘He is teaching the theory.’ (‘He causes that the theory is being
learned.’)
e. K⳱u ká’an-s-á’al le teòria-o’.
INCOMPL⳱3.ERG learn.PASS-CAUS-PASS.IMPF DET theory-D1
‘The theory is being taught.’ (‘Somebody causes that the theory is
being learned.’)
Thus the following situation is found in 35e: the agent of a bivalent verb is suppressed
by passivization, another agent is added by the causative morpheme, and this agent is
suppressed by the second passive morpheme. This situation cannot be modeled in an
inheritance hierarchy that classifies objects according to an active/passive and a
causative/noncausative dimension, since one can say only once about an object that it
has a certain property. Consider the hierarchy in Figure 3: if the lexeme kan ‘learn’ is
cross-classified according to active/passive and causative/noncausative, we get among
20
See also Davis & Koenig 2000 for such a proposal in the framework of HPSG.
21
The data is inspired by Wunderlich (1999:508–9). I thank Thomas Stolz for a modification of the
examples that made the arguments overt.
868 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
others a description for passive causative kan. But for 35e a double application
of passive is needed, and this is impossible to model in the inheritance hierarchy.
lexeme
passive ∧ n-c ∧ kan active ∧ n-c ∧ kan passive ∧ c ∧ kan active ∧ c ∧ kan
Construction that licenses 37a onto one that licenses the corresponding phrase in 37b
or onto the noun in this phrase with an appropriate valence specification.
(37) a. jemand die Nordsee leer fischt
somebody.NOM the North.Sea.ACC empty fishes
b. wegen der Leerfischung der Nordsee (taz, 6/20/1996, p. 6)
because.of the empty.fishing of.the North.Sea.GEN
To make this work, one has to assume a Construction that licenses jemand die Nordsee
leer fisch-, that is, a sentence with a verb that is not inflected. Without this assumption,
one has to reverse the inflection of fischt to be able to append the suffix -ung contained
in Leerfischung. The alternative to the assumption that phrases or phrasal rules serve
as input to morphology or morphological rules is to assume a very general Resultative
Construction that does not contain information about the phrasal realization of the
elements involved in resultative constructions. A phrasal SUBJ-OBJ-OBL-V Construc-
tion and the -ung Construction inherit from this general Construction.
Since the automatic computation of possible Constructions in a hierarchy is problem-
atic (see §3), one has to specify explicitly that there is a Construction that inherits from
the general Resultative Construction and the -ung Construction. The same applies to
-er and Ge- -e nominalizations, which are also compatible with resultative constructions.
Therefore, the phrasal approach has to make explicit statements about the interaction
of phenomena that are unnecessary in a lexicon-based system since the interaction
between phenomena is governed by rules designed to cover a single phenomenon:
either the output of a lexical rule satisfies the input description of another lexical rule
or it does not. If it does not, the second lexical rule cannot apply. For instance, 38b is
ruled out, since the passive lexical rule cannot apply to the unaccusative verb schmilzt
that is the output of the resultative lexical rule.
(38) a. Die Butter schmilzt zu einer Pfütze. (Kaufmann 1995:146)
the butter melts to a puddle
b. *weil zu einer Pfütze geschmolzen wurde
because to a puddle melt was
Miriam Butt (p.c. 2005) argues that the nominalizations can be seen as compounds and
that therefore the interpretation of the compound is not taken care of by the grammar,
but is left underspecified. It is clear that an analysis that derives the readings of the
nominalizations in 36 without reference to grammar-external principles should be pre-
ferred. Apart from this, it should be noted that the noun Fischung does not exist in
German in the relevant sense. The noun exists, but it refers to a plank on a boat. So
Leerfischung is not a compound of leer and Fischung, but a nominalization of leer
fisch-. A similar situation is found with derivations of particle verbs: there is a word
Ausraubung ‘robbing’, which is derived from ausraub- ‘to rob’, but there is no word
Raubung (Fleischer & Barz 1995:173), so Ausraubung cannot be the combination of
a nominalization of rauben ‘to steal’ with aus, but should be treated as the nominaliza-
tion of ausrauben. See Müller 2003a for an analysis of the morphology of particle verbs.
Since particle verbs and resultative constructions behave similarly in many respects, the
problem of nonexisting bases for particle-verb derivation is additional support for the
analysis of Leerfischung as true nominalization rather then compounding.
5.2. RESULTATIVE CONSTRUCTIONS AND ADJECTIVE DERIVATION. But even if one ac-
cepts a compound analysis, not all problems are solved, since the problem with deriva-
tion is not restricted to nominalizations, as the examples in 39 show.
870 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
overridden by subconstructions, or one can throw away the conflicting information and
possibly state new values within the inheriting Construction. It is important to note
that one can refer only to features inside of a Construction. It is impossible to refer to
features in a super Construction if the values of the respective features are overridden.
Thus, if we have a general Resultative Construction, as for example in 41a, a nominali-
zation Construction that would be needed to account for Leerfischung in 37b cannot
be related to 41a by inheritance.25
(41) a. general Resultative Construction
The reason for this is that the semantic properties of the Constructions are different:
the general Resultative Construction has a verbal semantics, and the nominalization
construction has a nominal semantics in which the resultative semantics is embedded.
By overriding the SEM value of the super Construction, the semantic information of the
super Construction is lost. Therefore, linkings to arguments (#1, #2, #3, #4) are also
lost, and these have to be respecified by hand in the subconstruction.26 If such respecifi-
cations are necessary in an analysis, this indicates that generalizations are lost. If values
at subconstructions cannot be inherited but have to be specified, this also means that
there is no way to derive the respective subconstruction by some general mechanism
like the one discussed in §3.
Apart from such problems, inheritance-based proposals have other problems: first,
recursion, as for example in Vorvorvorversion ‘preprepreversion’, cannot be covered
25
The ‘#’ followed by a number is used to mark identity of values. See Kay 2002. The subscript ‘#1’ in
NP#1 is used to refer to the discourse referent of a referring NP.
26
One way of solving this problem is to use auxiliary features to represent a prototypical semantic represen-
tation and specify a mapping from this auxiliary feature to the SEM feature of the subtype. See Kathol 1994:
263 and Koenig 1999 for similar suggestions. Koenig (1999:§4.1.1) also argues against an inheritance-based
analysis of derivational morphology. For the inheritance approach to work for the cases at hand, one needs
auxiliary features for all features that differ in various instances of the resultative construction, that is, for
part of speech, valence, and semantic contribution. If more than one value-changing Construction interacts
(as for instance in the complex derivation Leerfischbarkeit ‘empty fishability’ or in the interaction of resulta-
tive, free dative, and Accusative with Infinitive Construction), one has to stipulate complex systems of
interacting mappings from auxiliary features, which makes this proposal very unattractive. See Müller 2007b
for a discussion of inheritance.
Another solution is to use lists to represent semantic information. If relations embed other relations, the
embedded relations are stored in the lists and pointers are used to refer to the respective list element. A
special pointer is used to mark the main semantic contribution of a sign. In such a setting, one could inherit
the resultative semantics from the super Construction and add the nominal semantics at the end of the list
(see Müller 2005a for a partial implementation of this idea). The nominal semantics points to the resultative
semantics, and the pointer that points to the main semantic contribution is overridden such that it points to
the nominal semantics. MINIMAL RECURSION SEMANTICS (Copestake et al. 2005) is a formalism that uses such
pointered lists. This framework is also assumed by Kay (2005).
872 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
in inheritance networks (Krieger & Nerbonne 1993). If one assumes that Vorversion
is an object that inherits information from vor- and from Version, one has problems
with the analysis of Vorvorversion, since information about the prefix vor- is contained
in Vorversion already and inheriting this information a second time from vor- would
not add anything. Second, in an inheritance-based approach to derivation, it cannot be
explained why undoable has the two readings that correspond to the two bracketings
in 42 (Krieger & Nerbonne 1993).
(42) a. [un- [do-able]]
b. [[un-do] -able]
If we inherit information about un-, do, and -able, the order of the combination of this
information does not matter, and hence only one representation for undoable will result
in an inheritance-based analysis, which is not adequate.
The conclusion is that embedding Constructions are needed for derivation. The -ung
Construction could be stated as in 43.
(43) embedding -ung Nominalization Construction
syn N
sem nominal-semantics(#1)
phon #2 ⊕ 〈ung〉
syn V
sem #1
phon #2
In this Construction, a verbal stem is embedded. The embedding is marked by the box
in 43. The embedded stem has the syntactic category V (syn V), while the whole
Construction has the syntactic category N. The PHON value of this verbal stem (#2) is
used for the computation of the PHON value of the whole construction, which is the
result of appending -ung. The semantic contribution of the construction consists of the
nominal semantics, into which the contribution of the embedded verb (#1) is integrated.
This embedding Construction is equivalent to an HPSG analysis that uses lexical
rules.27 The analysis requires the existence of a verbal stem that can function as an
embedded construction or as input to the respective lexical rule. No such stems exist
in the phrasal analysis. This analysis is therefore incompatible with an embedding
analysis of derivation.
Concluding this section, it can be said that interactions between resultative construc-
tions and derivational morphology can be represented in inheritance hierarchies that
allow for default specifications and overriding. Such representations would, however,
be stipulations that do not capture the general properties of derivational morphology.
6. LEXICAL RULE-BASED APPROACHES. I now give an outline of the lexical rule-based
analysis, compare it with the phrasal approach, and discuss crosslinguistic aspects of
the respective analyses.
27
See Meurers 2001 for a formalization of lexical rules in HPSG and Pollard & Sag 1987:Ch. 8.2, Orgun
1996, Ackerman & Webelhuth 1998, Riehemann 1998, Kathol 1999, Koenig 1999, and Müller 2002 for
analyses of inflection and/or derivation that use lexical rules.
DISCUSSION NOTE 873
6.1. OUTLINE OF THE BASIC ANALYSIS. Lexical rule-based approaches assume a lexical
rule that takes an intransitive (version of a) verb as input and licenses a special lexical
item that selects for an additional object and a secondary predicate. One formalization
of such a lexical rule in the framework of HPSG (Pollard & Sag 1994) is shown in
44.28
(44) Lexical rule for resultatives
HEAD verb
CAT
SUBCAT 1 〈NP[str]〉
CONT 2
stem
HEAD adj-or-prep
〈 〉
CAT
CAT SUBCAT 1 ⊕ 3 ⊕ SUBCAT 3 〈 NPref 〉
CONT 4
ARG1 2
ARG1 4
CONT ARG2
become
cause
stem
This lexical rule takes a verb stem as input (an object of type stem with a HEAD value
verb). The input verb has to have a subject and no object. This is represented by the
valence specification in the SUBCAT list. The rule licenses an item that selects a predicate
that has a referential subject. This subject is raised to the object of the output of the
lexical rule, which is indicated by the tag 䡺3 which appears simultaneously before the
value of the SUBCAT list of the selected predicate and in the SUBCAT list of the output
of the lexical rule. The output item thus selects for a subject (the element in 䡺), 1 an
object that is raised from the secondary predicate, and the secondary predicate. As was
suggested by Dowty (1979:221), the semantic content of the input verb (䡺) 2 is embedded
under the cause relation, and the semantics of the secondary predicate (䡺) 4 is embedded
under become.
The output of the lexical rule is a stem. This stem may be inflected and then used
to analyze sentences like 5, repeated here as 45, or it may be the input to derivational
lexical rules.
(45) (weil) sie die Nordsee leer fischen
because they the North.Sea empty fish
‘because they fish the North Sea empty’
One such derivational lexical rule licenses -ung nominalizations, so from fisch- ‘to
fish’ one can derive fischung-. This fischung- is special in that it selects for a secondary
predicate and can be used in words such as Leerfischung. The stem that is the output
of 45 can also be used to derive the passive form or other forms with respective valence
28
I omit feature paths like SYNSEM or SYNSEM|LOC since they are not relevant in the current context. I also
omitt feature value pairs that are important for distinguishing unaccusative verbs from unergative ones. See
Müller 2002:241 for the full analysis.
874 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
patterns. The case of subjects and direct objects is underspecified in the lexicon. The
arguments are marked for structural case. Whether the case value is nominative, accusa-
tive, or genitive depends on the syntactic context in the actual utterance and is deter-
mined by a case principle. See Meurers 1999 for details.
Several readers suggested that Embick 2004 is relevant here. He claims that lexical
approaches to resultatives cannot explain why adjectival passive formation interacts
with the resultative constructions. To quote from this article:
(73) a. The door remained opened.
b. The metal remained flattened.
c. the recently hammered metal
...
(75) The metal is [hammered [aP flatter than a pancake that has been run over by a steamroller
and stomped on by elephants]].
Clearly, one would not want to derive the predicate (75) in the lexicon; it is a syntactic structure. Within
standard Lexicalist assumptions, a lexical process cannot form an adjective out of hammer and the
resultative secondary predicate in (75) because lexical processes cannot follow syntactic processes.
Thus, the formation of resultative participles that have resultative secondary predicates must be syntactic,
according to Lexicalist assumptions. If the Lexicalist view is to be maintained, this means that there
must be two ways of forming resultative participles: one lexical rule for forming adjectival passive
predicates like those in (73); and a second, syntactic process that creates an adjective out of hammer
flat and the like. (Embick 2004:389)
CONTENT values in Fig. 4.). The additional lexical item is used in the syntax in the way
predicted by the syntactic system of a language. No special mention of resultatives
must be present in the syntax. All constraints that can be attached to headed phrasal
Constructions can also be attached to lexical rules. Instead of specifying what is domi-
nated by a Construction, one specifies what is selected by the lexical item that is the
output of a lexical rule. Since lexical rules can be organized in type hierarchies in the
same way phrasal Constructions can, there is no advantage offered by the Construction-
based approach. Goldberg considers the need to stipulate new verb senses to be a crucial
disadvantage of lexical rule-based approaches, but note that one does not say that the
intransitive verb fischen gets a new meaning. Rather, it is said that when the verb
fischen is used together with a secondary predicate and the subject of this predicate,
the whole complex has a resultative meaning.
Thus, as far as the encoding of constraints is concerned, the approaches are equivalent.
Yet the phrasal approach interacts in various undesirable ways with the rest of the
grammar.
6.3. CROSSLINGUISTIC CONSIDERATIONS. It is obvious that the syntax of English and
German resultative constructions differ, and Korean can be added in as well, to name
just a few languages for which lexical rule-based approaches have been suggested (see
Wunderlich 1992:45, Verspoor 1997, Wechsler 1997, Wechsler & Noh 2001, Müller
2002). But this is not due to peculiarities of the construction in the respective languages.
Rather, the constructions behave as expected, given the overall syntactic systems of
the languages; that is, there is no need to say anything special about extraction, about
passivization, or verb position that is relevant in the context of resultative constructions
only. Lexical rule-based approaches to resultatives capture this, while the phrasal ap-
proach has to mention the particular language-specific phrasal realization.
Having shown that lexical rule-based analyses are better suited for the analysis of
resultative constructions, I now turn to the question of whether phrasal Constructions
are needed at all.
7. DO WE NEED PHRASAL CONSTRUCTIONS AT ALL? In their classic paper, Fillmore
and colleagues (1988) show that one has to assign special meaning to certain phrasal
configurations, since the meaning of the utterance cannot be determined solely on the
basis of the meaning of its parts.
DISCUSSION NOTE 877
However, the question is what the meanings of the parts are. As it is possible to
shift syntactic information around between lexicon and syntactic rules (Constructions),
it is also possible to represent semantic information at noncanonical places and, by doing
so, to obtain a grammar that can derive the meaning of all utterances compositionally. I
demonstrate this by explaining idiom analyses developed in the framework of HPSG.
Instead of representing the meaning of a certain expression at the phrasal level, one
can represent it in the lexical entry of the head.29 The specification of the meaning
goes hand in hand with lexical restrictions regarding the syntactic context in which the
head may be used, meaning that the lexical entry contains a statement of the following
kind: if the head X is used with certain arguments or modifiers, it means Y. The meaning
provided with such special entries for idioms may be different from the canonical
reading of the respective head. For example, Krenn and Erbach (1994) suggest a lexical
entry for the analysis of jemandem den Garaus machen ‘somebody the GARAUS make’
⳱ ‘to kill somebody’ that has the SUBCAT list in 49.
(49) machen: SUBCAT 具NP[nom], NP[dat], NP[acc]典
In addition, they specify that the NP[acc] has to contain the bound word Garaus and
that the article has to be definite. The meaning of this machen is specified to be ‘kill’.
Since this lexical entry is similar to other ditransitive verbs, it is explained why the
NPs can be reordered or fronted and why the idiom can be passivized: the normal rules
of German syntax apply.30 In connection with this example, it should be noted that, in
a grammar employing a lexical entry like the one suggested by Krenn and Erbach
(1994), it is orthogonal to the issue discussed here whether binary branching or flat
structures are assumed. In his radical-construction-grammar FAQ, Croft (2001:Ch.
1.6.2) says that his proposals can be formalized in feature-based theories like categorial
grammar, but that it is a disadvantage of such frameworks that they assume binary
branching structures since there are constructions with more than two parts. Croft notes
that a representation like that in 50a can be converted into a categorial grammar notation
like 50b.31
(50) a. [ VP V NP]
b. VP/NP
The representation in 50b stands for an entity that will be a VP if an NP is added.
Contrary to Croft’s claim, however, such a conversion is also possible for Constructions
with three or more parts. The result of converting 51a is 51b.
(51) a. [ VP V NP NP]
b. (VP/NP)/NP
The representation in 51b says: if we combine (VP/NP)/NP with NP we get VP/NP
29
If there is no constituent that can be regarded as the head, an empty head can be stipulated. Of course,
this comes with a cost and should be motivated by other theoretical considerations.
30
The examples in (i) are the respective examples for reordering ((i)a) and fronting ((i)b–c) of arguments
and passive ((i)d).
(i) a. weil ihm jemand den Garaus gemacht hat
because him.DAT somebody.NOM the GARAUS.ACC made has
b. Jemand hat ihm den Garaus gemacht.
somebody.NOM has him.DAT the GARAUS.ACC made
c. Ihm hat jemand den Garaus gemacht.
him.DAT has somebody.NOM the GARAUS.ACC made
d. weil ihm der Garaus gemacht wurde
because him.DAT the GARAUS.NOM made was
31
See for instance Steedman 2002 on the categorial grammar notation.
878 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
and if we combine this with NP we get VP. The representation given in 49 corresponds
to ((S/NP)/NP)/NP, that is, to a statement saying: if we combine a verb with three NPs,
we get a sentence.32 What the meaning of the sentence will be is specified to a large
extent in the lexical representation of the head.
In fact, Kay and Fillmore (1999:20) give a representation of the What is X doing Y?
Construction that could be a lexical entry. The only argument they put forward for a
phrasal Construction is that they avoid stipulating additional senses for the copula BE
as it appears in this construction. However, the lexical introduction of adjuncts sug-
gested by Kay (2005) amounts to saying that each head has infinitely many meanings.
A drawback of the Krenn & Erbach approach is that it involves nonlocal selection
since the verb machen states constraints on the determiner of the NP den Garaus.
However, locality is not recognized as an issue by those working within construction
grammar. For instance, Goldberg’s Resultative Construction is specified as [Subj
[V OBJ OBL]], and thus the constraints regarding resultatives involve trees of a depth
greater than one. In the analysis outlined in Kay & Fillmore 1999, all information about
adjuncts and arguments of a head is available at the top-most node in a tree. Since the
representation of arguments and adjuncts in turn contains their internal structure, basi-
cally the whole internal structure of a linguistic object is represented at the top-most
node and it is also possible to select internal parts of it. Selecting internal parts is what
Kay and Fillmore do in their analysis of the What is X doing Y? Construction.
In HPSG, nonlocal selection is usually made much harder by assuming a feature
geometry that does not allow for the selection of daughters of selected elements (Pol-
lard & Sag 1994; see also Sag 2007 on locality). Yet even with this restrictive feature
geometry it is possible to specify restrictions on the syntactic context in which a lexical
item is uttered. For instance, Sailer (2000) has developed a collocation module that
allows a lexical item to look at the whole surrounding sentence. This is possible if one
uses relational constraints. This approach was recognized to be too powerful, however,
since it did not place enough constraints on what kind of information may be selected.
The approach developed in Söhn & Sailer 2003 is more restrictive in this respect.
This discussion shows that it is possible to control everything from the lexicon.
Whether this is motivated and whether a particular analysis is too expensive or too
powerful because of heavy usage of relational constraints or other devices has to be
decided on a case-by-case basis.
32
Steedman (2002:159) gives a parallel lexical entry for the Dutch verb gaf ‘gave.’
DISCUSSION NOTE 879
The discussion of Fig. 4 above shows that information that can be attached to phrasal
Constructions can be attached to lexical items as well. The representation of such
information can be done at a phonologically filled head (as in the case of the resultative
construction) or it can be attached to a phonologically empty head. An example of the
latter is the analysis of relative clauses in Pollard & Sag 1994:Ch. 5. As the discussion
of the idiom analysis shows, even the tiniest bit of a sentence may be controlled from
within a lexical entry. If one does not follow the lexical approach and specifies phrasal
Constructions instead, one encounters problems in explaining the interactions between
syntax and morphology. This suggests that a lexical treatment of resultative construc-
tions is more appropriate. Such a lexicon-based analysis was suggested by Boas 2003
in the framework of construction grammar. The lexical rules that Boas refused to
formulate can be formulated as suggested by authors working in the HPSG framework
or as lexical Argument Structure Constructions similar to the ones proposed by Kay
(2005). So, I do not argue here against construction grammar as a framework, but rather
against a specific type of analysis within this framework and other nontransformational
frameworks. Goldberg and Jackendoff (2004) are right in claiming that one needs a
tight connection between form and meaning and that some approaches will have diffi-
culties in capturing their findings, but the question is how the resultative Construction
is stated. I maintain that stating it in the lexicon is the better solution.
REFERENCES
ACKERMAN, FARRELL, and GERT WEBELHUTH. 1998. A theory of predicates. (CSLI lecture
notes 76.) Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
AÏT-KACI, HASSAN; ROBERT BOYER; PATRICK LINCOLN; and ROGER NASR. 1989. Efficient
implementation of lattice operations. ACM Transactions on Programming Languages
and Systems 11.1.115–46.
BOAS, HANS CHRISTIAN. 2003. A constructional approach to resultatives. (Stanford mono-
graphs in linguistics.) Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
BORSLEY, ROBERT D. 2004. An approach to English comparative correlatives. In Müller
2004, 70–92.
BOUMA, GOSSE; ROB MALOUF; and IVAN A. SAG. 2001. Satisfying constraints on extraction
and adjunction. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19.1.1–65.
BRESNAN, JOAN. 1982. The passive in lexical theory. The mental representation of grammati-
cal relations (Cognitive theory and mental representation), ed. by Joan Bresnan, 3–86.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
BRESNAN, JOAN, and SAM A. MCHOMBO. 1995. The lexical integrity principle: Evidence
from Bantu. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 13.181–254.
BUTT, MIRIAM. 1997. Complex predicates in Urdu. Complex predicates (CSLI lecture notes
64), ed. by Alex Alsina, Joan Bresnan, and Peter Sells, 107–49. Stanford, CA: CSLI
Publications.
CARPENTER, BOB. 1992. The logic of typed feature structures. (Cambridge tracts in theoretical
computer science 32.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
CLARK, PETER, and BRUCE PORTER. 2004. KM—The knowledge machine 2.0: Users manual.
Online: http://www.cs.utexas.edu/users/mfkb/km/userman.pdf.
COPESTAKE, ANN; DAN FLICKINGER; CARL POLLARD; and IVAN A. SAG. 2005. Minimal recur-
sion semantics: An introduction. Research on Language and Computation 4.3.281–332.
CROFT, WILLIAM. 2001. Radical construction grammar: Syntactic theory in typological
perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
DAVIS, ANTHONY R., and JEAN-PIERRE KOENIG. 2000. Linking as constraints on word classes
in a hierarchical lexicon. Language 76.1.56–91.
DEN DIKKEN, MARCEL. 1995. Particles. On the syntax of verb-particle, triadic, and causative
constructions. (Oxford studies in comparative syntax.) Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
DOWTY, DAVID R. 1978. Governed transformations as lexical rules in a Montague grammar.
Linguistic Inquiry 9.3.393–426.
880 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)
DOWTY, DAVID R. 1979. Word meaning and Montague grammar. (Synthese language library
7.) Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
DÜRSCHEID, CHRISTA. 2002. „Polemik satt und Wahlkampf pur“—Das postnominale Adjek-
tiv im Deutschen. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 21.1.57–81.
EMBICK, DAVID. 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in English. Linguistic In-
quiry 35.3.355–92.
FANSELOW, GISBERT. 2001. Features, -roles, and free constituent order. Linguistic Inquiry
32.3.405–37.
FANSELOW, GISBERT. 2002. Against remnant VP-movement. Dimensions of movement: From
features to remnants (Linguistik aktuell/Linguistics today 48), ed. by Artemis Alexia-
dou, Elena Anagnostopoulou, Sjef Barbiers, and Hans-Martin Gärtner, 91–127. Amster-
dam: John Benjamins.
FILLMORE, CHARLES J. 1999. Inversion and constructional inheritance. Lexical and construc-
tional aspects of linguistic explanation (Studies in constraint-based lexicalism 1), ed.
by Gert Webelhuth, Jean-Pierre Koenig, and Andreas Kathol, 113–28. Stanford, CA:
CSLI Publications.
FILLMORE, CHARLES J.; PAUL KAY; and MARY CATHERINE O’CONNOR. 1988. Regularity
and idiomaticity in grammatical constructions: The case of let alone. Language
64.3.501–38.
FLEISCHER, WOLFGANG. 1982. Phraseologie der deutschen Gegenwartssprache. Leipzig:
VEB Bibliographisches Institut Leipzig.
FLEISCHER, WOLFGANG, and IRMHILD BARZ. 1995. Wortbildung der deutschen Gegenwarts-
sprache. 2nd edn. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
FREY, WERNER, and HANS-MARTIN GÄRTNER. 2002. On the treatment of scrambling and
adjunction in minimalist grammars. Proceedings of Formal Grammar 2002, ed. by
Gerhard Jäger, Paola Monachesi, Gerald Penn, and Shuly Wintner, 41–52.
GAZDAR, GERALD; EWAN KLEIN; GEOFFREY K. PULLUM; and IVAN A. SAG. 1985. Generalized
phrase structure grammar. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
GEACH, PETER THOMAS. 1970. A program for syntax. Synthese 22.3–17.
GINZBURG, JONATHAN, and IVAN A. SAG. 2001. Interrogative investigations: The form, mean-
ing, and use of English interrogatives. (CSLI lecture notes 123.) Stanford, CA: CSLI
Publications.
GOLDBERG, ADELE E. 1995. Constructions: A construction grammar approach to argument
structure. (Cognitive theory of language and culture.) Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
GOLDBERG, ADELE E. 1996. Optimizing constraints and the Persian complex predicate.
Berkeley Linguistics Society 22.132–46.
GOLDBERG, ADELE E. 2003. Words by default: The Persian complex predicate construction.
Mismatch: Form-function incongruity and the architecture of grammar (CSLI lecture
notes 163), ed. by Elaine J. Francis and Laura A. Michaelis, 117–46. Stanford, CA:
CSLI Publications.
GOLDBERG, ADELE E. 2006. Constructions at work: The nature of generalization in language.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
GOLDBERG, ADELE E., and RAY S. JACKENDOFF. 2004. The English resultative as a family
of constructions. Language 80.3.532–68.
HAIDER, HUBERT. 1986. Fehlende Argumente: Vom Passiv zu kohärenten Infinitiven. Lin-
guistische Berichte 101.3–33.
HAUGEREID, PETTER. 2004. Linking in constructions. In Müller 2004, 414–22.
HINRICHS, ERHARD W., and TSUNEKO NAKAZAWA. 1989. Subcategorization and VP structure
in German. Aspects of German VP structure. (SfS report 1-93.) Tübingen: Eberhard-
Karls-Universität.
HINRICHS, ERHARD W., and TSUNEKO NAKAZAWA. 1994. Linearizing AUXs in German verbal
complexes. In Nerbonne et al., 11–38.
HOEKSTRA, TEUN. 1988. Small clause results. Lingua 74.101–39.
JACKENDOFF, RAY S. 1997. The architecture of the language faculty. (Linguistic Inquiry
monographs 28.) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
JANDA, RICHARD. 1998. German umlaut: Morpholexical all the way down from OHG through
NHG (Two Stützpunkte for Romance metaphony). Rivista di linguistica 10.1.163–232.
DISCUSSION NOTE 881
JOSEPH, BRIAN D. 1997. How general are our generalizations? What speakers actually know
and what they actually do. Proceedings of the Thirteenth Eastern States Conference
on Linguistics (ESCOL ’96), ed. by Anthony D. Green and V. Motopanyane, 148–60.
Ithaca: Cascadilla Press.
KASPER, ROBERT T. 1994. Adjuncts in the Mittelfeld. In Nerbonne et al., 39–70.
KATHOL, ANDREAS. 1994. Passives without lexical rules. In Nerbonne et al., 237–72.
KATHOL, ANDREAS. 1997. Concrete minimalism of German. Zur Satzstruktur im Deutschen
(Arbeitspapiere des SFB 340, 90), ed. by Franz-Josef d’Avis and Uli Lutz, 81–106.
Tübingen: Eberhard-Karls-Universität.
KATHOL, ANDREAS. 1998. Constituency and linearization of verbal complexes. Complex
predicates in nonderivational syntax (Syntax and semantics 30), ed. by Erhard W.
Hinrichs, Andreas Kathol, and Tsuneko Nakazawa, 221–70. San Diego: Academic
Press.
KATHOL, ANDREAS. 1999. Agreement and the syntax-morphology interface in HPSG. Studies
in contemporary phrase structure grammar, ed. by Robert D. Levine and Georgia M.
Green, 223–74. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
KATHOL, ANDREAS. 2000. Linear syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
KAUFMANN, INGRID. 1995. Konzeptuelle Grundlagen semantischer Dekompositionsstrukt-
uren. (Die Kombinatorik lokaler Verben und prädikativer Linguistische Arbeiten 335.)
Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
KAY, PAUL. 2002. An informal sketch of a formal architecture for construction grammar.
Grammars 5.1.1–19.
KAY, PAUL. 2005. Argument structure constructions and the argument-adjunct distinction.
Grammatical constructions: Back to the roots. (Constructional approaches to language
4), ed. by Mirjam Fried and Hans C. Boas, 71–98. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
KAY, PAUL, and CHARLES J. FILLMORE. 1999. Grammatical constructions and linguistic
generalizations: The What’s X doing Y? construction. Language 75.1.1–33.
KISS, TIBOR, and BIRGIT WESCHE. 1991. Verb order and head movement. Text understanding
in LILOG (Lecture notes in artificial intelligence 546), ed. by Otthein Herzog and
Claus-Rainer Rollinger, 216–42. Berlin: Springer.
KOCH, WOLFGANG, and INGER ROSENGREN. 1995. Secondary predications: Their grammati-
cal and conceptual structure. (Forschungsprogramm Sprache und Pragmatik 35.) Lund:
Germanistisches Institut der Universität Lund.
KOENIG, JEAN-PIERRE. 1999. Lexical relations. (Stanford monographs in linguistics.) Stan-
ford, CA: CSLI Publications.
KRENN, BRIGITTE, and GREGOR ERBACH. 1994. Idioms and support verb constructions. In
Nerbonne et al., 365–96.
KRIEGER, HANS-ULRICH; WITOLD DROŻYŻDŃSKI; JAKUB PISKORSKI; ULRICH SCHÄFER; and
FEIYU XU. 2004. A bag of useful techniques for unification-based finite-state trans-
ducers. Proceedings of 7th KONVENS, ed. by Ernst Buchberger, 105–12.
KRIEGER, HANS-ULRICH, and JOHN NERBONNE. 1993. Feature-based inheritance networks for
computational lexicons. Inheritance, defaults, and the lexicon, ed. by Ted Briscoe, Ann
Copestake, and Valeria de Paiva, 90–136. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[A version of this paper is available as DFKI Research Report RR-91-31 at http://
www.dfki.de/lt/publications_show.php?id⳱342. Also published in: Proceedings of the
ACQUILEX Workshop on Default Inheritance in the Lexicon (Technical report 238),
Cambridge: University of Cambridge Computer Laboratory, 1991.]
LÜDELING, ANKE. 2001. On particle verbs and similar constructions in German. (Disserta-
tions in linguistics.) Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
MEURERS, WALT DETMAR. 1999. Raising spirits (and assigning them case). Groninger Ar-
beiten zur Germanistischen Linguistik (GAGL) 43.173–226.
MEURERS, WALT DETMAR. 2001. On expressing lexical generalizations in HPSG. Nordic
Journal of Linguistics 24.2.161–217.
MICHAELIS, LAURA A., and JOSEF RUPPENHOFER. 2001. Beyond alternations: A constructional
model of the German applicative pattern. (Stanford monographs in linguistics.) Stan-
ford, CA: CSLI Publications.
MÜLLER, STEFAN. 1999. Deutsche Syntax deklarativ: Head-Driven Phrase Structure Gram-
mar für das Deutsche. (Linguistische Arbeiten 394.) Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
882 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 82, NUMBER 4 (2006)