2017 Illes - Neuroethics - Anticipating The Future
2017 Illes - Neuroethics - Anticipating The Future
2017 Illes - Neuroethics - Anticipating The Future
Neuroethics
ii
iii
Neuroethics
Anticipating the Future
Editor
Judy Illes
Associate Editor
Sharmin Hossain
1
iv
1
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP,
United Kingdom
Impression: 1
ISBN 978–0–19–878683–2
Foreword: Forays into neuroethics
It is early 2001, I had just been appointed as the inaugural Scientific Director of the Institute
of Neuroscience, Mental Health and Addiction (INMHA) of the Canadian Institutes of
Health Research (CIHR). The CIHR was created to usher in a new generation of thinking,
action, and innovation about basic and translational research, for junior and more senior
scientists and scholars alike.
One of the most exciting changes brought about by the creation of CIHR and its 13 insti-
tutes was the Institute Advisory Board structure and mandate enabling and encouraging
the exploration of novel research avenues and frontiers without the traditional bound-
aries. For those of us in brain research, mental health, and addiction, the work of my
inaugural Board and its vision were transformational. We nearly immediately departed
from conventional ideas about funding in neuroscience to support a New Emerging Team
(NET) program in 2002–2003, with topics such as the impacts of early life events on the
developmental course of brain disorders, regenerative medicine, and understanding the
placebo effect. This was merely our first call. The second followed directly from my own
experiences and leadership of over 20 years in my laboratories at the Douglas Mental
Health Institute affiliated with McGill University in Montreal. I was highly aware of ethi-
cal issues and challenges to optimal care for the mentally ill, their involvement in various
types of clinical trials, and the high incidence of co-morbidity between mental health
and addiction. Accordingly, I was keen to promote innovative research on ethical issues
related to the broad mandate of INMHA. But neuroethics?
I first heard about neuroethics in the early years of the CIHR. I asked some of my col-
leagues and few ethicists locally and internationally about it. Most basically said that “It
is a fad.” They saw no reason to create this specialty or subfield. In their minds, research
on ethics was complicated enough; neuroethics would only complicate the complicated
further. In retrospect, by most measures, they were wrong. Neuroethics may have added a
layer of complex inquiry to both neuroscience and biomedical ethics, but the sole fact that
Neuroethics: Anticipating the Future (2017) today follows Neuroethics: Defining the Issue
in Theory, Practice and Policy (2006), speaks for the need, force, and what was to come.
INMHA launched two calls to create NET teams on Neuroethics (awarded to research-
ers at Dalhousie University in Halifax, Nova Scotia) in addition to a partnered Chair in
Neuroethics to recruit an expert from outside Canada. The University of British Columbia
won the call, and book Editor Dr. Judy Illes was recruited back to Canada from the United
States as the chair holder. This was great coup for all in Canada and for the field as it would
ground neuroethics with the highest nationally named position and center yet.
Research in neuroethics by many scholars authoring chapters in this book and oth-
ers has moved the field forward significantly over the past decade on topics as varied as
vi
incidental findings in brain imaging, forensic psychiatry, improved design of clinical trials
in the fields of mental illnesses, addiction and incurable neurodegenerative diseases, neu-
rotechnology, cognitive enhancements, consciousness, and brain death, to name a few.
Of course, cutting-edge research in neuroethics is still urgently needed on these topics.
Novel areas have also emerged over the last few years to which neuroethics must lead
with evidence-based, best-way-forward guidelines for experts and the civil society. Take
for example, artificial intelligence and the interface between robots and the mind: How
can the discourse of neuroethics help society to take up related challenges in a sensi-
ble, balanced manner? Where will the novel concept of a cognitive footprint take us?
Will gene editing (CRISPR-Casp9-type) edit out incurable brain conditions or undesir-
able behavioral traits and states—and who will decide? How will the role and impact of
various cultures and the environment on values relevant to mental health and addiction
evolve? Will wearable technology, social media, digital e-health, and open access to large
public and private sets of data bring solutions to global attitudes and demands of societ-
ies toward brain diseases and various forms of addiction? And, link to these consider-
ations: cybersecurity and open access to large data sets.
Neuroethics has matured. It feels unstoppable not only because of the energy brought
to it by its current and future leaders, but by the pressing issues awaiting discovery, defi-
nition, awareness, and answers. Neuroethics: Anticipating the Future is a signature of this
momentum.
Rémi Quirion
Professor of Psychiatry, McGill University
Distinguished Researcher, Douglas Mental Health Institute
Quebec Chief Scientist
vi
Preface
Part 1: Looking to the future
—Judy Illes and Sharmin Hossain
This publication of Neuroethics: Anticipating the Future marks both an anniversary of one
of the first edited neuroethics volumes for the field (Illes 2006), as well as of the found-
ing of the International Neuroethics Society, the major professional organization for the
field. Like the publication of the first book volume that took the groundwork laid out at
the Mapping the Field neuroethics meeting in San Francisco, California—now 15 years
ago, and another anniversary—and gave it content anchor points in theory, practice, and
policy, this one also signals milestones. The authors contributing to the original volume
wrote to answer the question: Where should the field go? In this new volume, contributing
authors answer the question: Where must the field go next? With significant progress over
more than a decade, this is a critical undertaking with both legitimacy and gravitas.
In preparing this volume, the three sections on neurotechnology, healthcare, and policy
emerged naturally from the contributions we received. The prescient Joseph J. Fins pre-
dicted the neurotechnology focus in his epilogue to the Oxford Handbook of Neuroethics
(Illes & Sahakian 2011). Healthcare and public good are unwavering themes for the field,
involving ethical challenges around brain future of youth, aging and dementia, brain
injury and consciousness, stem cells and neurologic conditions, and global health and
cross-cultural justice, among others. With one foot within and one foot outside the walls
of the hospital and academy, neuroethics in the wild brings considerations of social and
regulatory challenges to a leading role in new discourse about the environment, brain,
and mental health, in part in a global rapprochement between neurology and psychiatry,
internationalization and intersections of brain and security, and criminal justice.
Among the mix of authors are neuroethicists in the pipeline for leadership who are
playing a pivotal role in charting the course of the field for decades to come. Like those
who are more senior, they hail from diverse disciplines, spanning the humanities, public
health and public policy, and science and medicine. Their diversity is reflected not only in
their disciplines, but also in their cultural backgrounds—different lenses that bring focus
and richness to any area of ethical inquiry.
Ten years ago, the International Neuroethics Society provided a platform for a small
neuroethics community to engage; today it offers hundreds of faculty, trainees, and col-
laborators from around the globe expanded opportunities for networking, showcasing
research, and career development, as well as a place to call a professional home. Over the
past year, Sharmin Hossain also participated in a further initiative focused on the next gen-
eration of ethics and policy leaders: the Trainee Policy and Advocacy Committee (T-PAC)
formed under the wing of Kids Brain Health Network (formerly NeuroDevNet, Inc.),
vi
viii Preface
Preface
Part 2: A brief look back
—Judy Illes
Learning from lessons of the past
In the firm belief that to move forward it is essential to learn lessons from the past, the
second part of this Preface is a brief look at the history of modern neuroethics. As I reflect
on this task, one of the most frequently asked questions comes to mind: Why do we,
citizens and beneficiaries of advances in the neuroscience, need neuroethics? And, formu-
lated slightly differently: How is neuroethics different than bioethics? My regular answer is:
neuroexceptionalism. Unlike the knee or the elbow, the liver or pancreas (but, with new
knowledge about the microbiome, perhaps like the gut (Mayer et al. 2014)), the brain
connects each of us to who we are. In health and in disease, it links us to our identity,
relations, autonomy, personality, capacity to make decisions, and much more. Each is
intricately intertwined with the other like the threads of a rope embedded in the context
in which we thrive, derive, and survive. It has allowed scholars in the field to frame and
reframe ethical concerns explicitly associated with the brain sciences, and to similarly
consider governance and advisory frameworks carefully attuned to relevant issues, help-
ing to define both good and ethically defensible neuroscience.
Reflections
I reflect on probably the most quoted phrase for the field, and I give it another nod here:
Adina Roskies’ “Ethics of neuroscience; neuroscience of ethics” (Roskies 2002). I have
never quite agreed with this dichotomy as the latter cannot exist except within the context
of the former, but no matter: even if the phrase is not perfectly dichotomous, its simplicity
gave us a welcome and forceful catch phrase to propel neuroethics forward.
I continue with other reflections. The topic that never dies: enhancement, whether for
the competitive boost or improved mental health (Illes 2016), and more recently for moral
fortitude (Persson & Savulescu 2008). If the use of drugs for the moral application could
give even a modicum of relief from its terror-riddled world, I would be all for it. Topics
that should never die: addiction and mental health, aging and dementia, consciousness,
justice and human rights, consent, dignity, pain, regenerative medicine, agency.
A topic that took on a life of its own: the management of unexpected (incidental, study
off-target) findings in brain imaging research. As much as the question about how to
handle incidental findings of possible health significance was not new to genetics, and
was introduced originally by the US National Bioethics Commission in 1999 (National
x
x Preface
Bioethics Advisory Commission 1999), the potency of the question took the neuroimag-
ing community by surprise. Lively debates since 2005 and ongoing today (Illes et al. 2006,
2008; Wolf et al. 2008) have yielded well-balanced policies and guidance for brain anato-
mies. And, while ample questions still remain (Gibson et al. Chapter 3, this volume), new
ones about the interpretation of the functional data in the context of functional outliers
that may be medically or societally significant (Scott et al. 2012) are arising. They require
urgent attention before solutions to inevitable challenges have to become reactive rather
than anticipatory and thoughtfully proactive (Foster et al. 2003).
Allow me to move to other enduring imperatives: I would place education and mentor-
ship of interested researchers and clinicians of all ranks and disciplines, and engagement
of the community outside the Academy at the top of the list of priorities. Neuroethics
teachers and mentors must support the move from didactic, unidirectional schooling
of foundational theories and axioms to modern case-and problem-based teaching. The
Internet has fueled a craving for autonomy in learning; classroom teaching should now
elevate do-it-yourself learning in this digital age, rather than the historical reverse where
book learning elevated lessons imparted from the more learned.
Similarly, there has not been a time in the history of biomedicine when the importance
of including the voice of research participants and patients in the design, execution, and
dissemination of research through methods such as participatory action and collaborative
research (Stevenson et al. 2016) has been as recognized if not mandated. These interactions
have brought a new level of meaningfulness to the specific translational goals of the biosci-
ences (Illes et al. 2011), human subjects protection (Eijkholt et al. 2012), rights (Human
Rights for Neuroethics: Reflection or Refraction, International Neuroethics Society
Meeting, Washington, DC, November 2014), and public engagement (Robillard et al. 2015).
This discussion brings me now to one of the most cited text in neuroethics, Mapping
the Field (Marcus 2002), the edited volume created from the transcripts of the landmark
neuroethics meeting in San Francisco in that same year. The field has many thanks to offer
to the Dana Foundation whose support is unfailing even 15 years later, and the vision for
neuroethics of the late William Safire (said to have been first articulated in a conversation
with Zack Hall in a taxi in New York City). Deep gratitude is also due to investment of
the late William Stubing of the Greenwall Foundation whose support was foundational
(e.g., Illes & Raffin 2002; Farah & Wolpe 2004), and also continues to date. Beyond these
neuroethics funding visionaries, I count more than two dozen other private and govern-
ment sponsors of research to whom the field owes thanks. Their financial contributions
to the advancement of critical thinking about ethics, society, policy, and law alongside
advances in the neurosciences, have enabled the field to gain traction, credibility, and
sustainability. As Professor of Medicine and Director of the Usher Institute of Population
Health Sciences and Informatics, Dr. Andrew Morris said at the International Association
of Bioethics meeting in Edinburgh, Scotland in June 2016 (a meeting at which neuroeth-
ics was only minimally represented), ethics must be (and I paraphrase) “a first thought;
not an after thought … in confluence to improve human and public health.”
xi
Preface xi
Perhaps it is both the alignment of neuroethics with neuro, and its practical pro-
positioning in science that best define the field as it is today more than any particular the-
oretical construct. Indeed, neuroethics seems well defined by what we, as scholars in the
field do with it and the interdisciplinary, often pragmatic approach we take (Racine 2010).
That is not to say that the theoreticians among us have not played a key role in integrat-
ing philosophy fundamentally into the field, but still, as University of British Columbia
Sociologist Professor D. Ralph Matthews and I concur about neuroethics at present: “We
are what we study” (loosely translated from “You are what you eat”). To this end, per-
haps we are raising more questions than answers, but that is not a failure, just a signal of
dimensionality.
Measurables
There is little doubt that this is the century of the brain. As University of Chicago bio-
ethicist Mark Siegler and I have discussed, technical advances in the last 75 years exceed
those of 2000–3000 years that precede it. With each advance in the brain sciences, ques-
tions about ethics arise. Think about end-of-life decision-making and today’s new laws;
predicting Alzheimer’s disease in the absence of cure, or predicting adult-onset diseases
in newborns and children; stem cells for autism or cerebral palsy; gene therapy; psychi-
atric neurosurgery for mental health disorders; technologically assisted communication
for the minimally conscious and other diagnostic and therapeutic advances for the spec-
trum of mild to severe central nervous system injuries; magnetic resonance imaging in
the courtroom; commercialization of health technology (some that preys on the most
vulnerable in our society); big data; environment and culture; and manipulating genes
to edit out disease and edit in desirable behavioral traits. The hype is phenomenal; pub-
lic interest growing and unprecedented (Beaulieu 2000; Whiteley 2012). Are we doing
enough? Are we progressing fast enough, meaningfully, transparently, interactively, and
effectively enough?
The answer is, on the most part, yes, judging from the numbers of books and edited vol-
umes, and international efforts in public engagement (Illes et al. 2005) ever since the early
days of neuroethics. For example, shortly after the 2002 meeting, the Dana Foundation’s
journal Cerebrum published a special issue on neuroethics in Fall 2004. A special issue
of the journal Brain and Cognition was published in 2005 devoted to ethical issues in
advanced neuroimaging. The American Journal of Bioethics published its own special
issue on neuroethics in 2005 and today, with a booming impact factor of more than 6, is
accepting target articles in the area. I created the AJoB–Neuroscience series and served as
its inaugural editor. It is now in Paul Wolpe’s capable hands as the official journal of the
International Neuroethics Society (INS). There are numerous relevant publications by the
US Presidential Commission on the Study of Bioethical Issues (PCSBI; from 2008 to 2016,
more than 50 neuroscientists and neuroethics scholars testified to the Commission).
Journal papers, trainees in a diverse range of disciplines and presenters at the annual
meeting of the INS and elsewhere, faculty in tenured, tenure-line, research stream, and
xi
xii Preface
private and government sector positions, programs of one type or another (41 worldwide
at last count), media coverage abound.
The first-ever formal strategic plan of the INS, the major professional society for neu-
roethics, speaks clearly to accomplishments of the past and aspirations for the future with
four priorities. With some editorial paraphrasing, the priorities are to:
1. position the INS, with its multidisciplinary membership and leadership, as an author-
itative body on matters pertaining to neuroethics
2. promote and support research, scholarship, and education in all aspects of
neuroethics
3. develop sustainable funding for the profession
4. grow in number and size.
The strategic achievement of the goals assigned to each of these priorities (http://www.
neuroethicssociety.org/strategic) will bring the membership closer to citable policy or
legal changes where it has yet to show its colors and truly define a legacy. The Neuroethics
Response Task Force (now Emerging Issues Task Force) of the INS that I struck in 2016,
initially chaired by Board of Directors member Mark Frankel, and engagement of the
broadest range of the profession’s diverse membership in rank, discipline, gender, and
geographic background, will further enable this goal and the positioning of the INS as the
authoritative go-to body in neuroethics.
Anniversaries
With this historical perspective, I also celebrate one of the concurrent past anniversaries
of neuroethics—the 10th—the meeting of a small group neuroscientists and bioethicists
in Asilomar, California in Spring 2006, to discuss a plan for the now established profes-
sional society. Early names were Neuroethics Interdisciplinary Association, competing
with Society for Interdisciplinary Neuroethics. It would draw upon knowledge gained in
prior meetings: besides the 2002 meeting (the 15th anniversary), in September 2003, the
American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) sponsored a meeting on
neuroscience and law and, in 2005, another on neuroethics and religion. In May 2005, the
Library of Congress sponsored a neuroethics meeting called Hard Science—Hard Choices.
These are just to name a few.
We were a small group (Figure 0.1) in a small conference room—the rest of the rustic
retreat center on the magnificent Pacific Ocean was occupied by a gathering of nearly
1000 church members seeking answers to questions of their own. In many ways, both
the content and interpersonal dynamics of that 2-day meeting foreshadowed the many
faces of neuroethics today: collaborations and entanglements; warmth and tensions;
rigor and fluidity; curiosity and resistance; friends, no fig leafs. In that setting, we cre-
ated a space for the liberal multiculturalism for the neuroethics that we live today.
Culture is a hybrid of internal and external principles. Principles, like ideas, travel.
I believe that we got it right then and that we continue to evolve productively. One
aspect of the evolution, in fact, was a name-change from the originally settled-upon
xi
Preface xiii
Figure 0.1 Participants at the Asilomar Neuroethics Society planning meeting 2006. Kneeling
from left to right: Martha Farah, Patricia Churchland. Standing from left to right: Anjan
Chaterjee, Turhan Canli, Allison Mackey, Elizabeth Phelps, Hank Greely, Judy Illes, Laurie Zoloth,
Mike Gazzaniga, Barbara Sahakian, Paul Wolpe. Not shown: Steve Hyman and Stephen Morse.
Reproduced courtesy of Judy Illes
xiv Preface
References
Beaulieu, A.E. (2000). The brain at the end of the rainbow: the promises of brain scans in the research
field and in the media. In: Marchessault, J. and Sawchuk K. (Eds.) Wild Science: Reading Feminism,
Medicine and the Media, pp.39–54. London: Routledge.
Clinton, H.R. (2006). It Takes a Village. New York: Simon and Schuster.
De Vries, R.D. (2005). Framing neuroethics: a sociological assessment of the neuroethical imagination.
American Journal of Bioethics, 5, 25–27.
De Vries, R.D. (2006, November). Firing the neuroethical imagination. In: 7th EMBL/EMBO Joint
Conference Programme, Genes/Brain, Mind and Behavior, Heidelberg, Germany.
Dickens, C. (2012). A Tale of Two Cities. New York: Vintage.
xv
Preface xv
Eijkholt, M., Anderson, J.A., and Illes, J. (2012). Picturing neuroscience research through a human
rights lens: imaging first-episode schizophrenic treatment-naïve individuals. International Journal of
Law and Psychiatry, 35, 146–152.
Farah, M.J. and Wolpe, P.R. (2004). Monitoring and manipulating the human brain: new neuroscience
technologies and their ethical implications. Hastings Center Report, 34, 35–45.
Fins, J.J. (2011). Epilogue. In: Illes, J. and Sahakian, B. (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Neuroethics,
pp.895–907. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Foster, K.R., Wolpe, P.R., and Caplan, A.L. (2003). Bioethics and the brain. IEEE Spectrum,
40, 34–39.
Illes, J. (Ed.) (2006). Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory, Practice, and Policy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Illes, J. (2006, November). From genetics to neuroethics: is imaging “visualizing” human thought?
In: 7th EMBL/EMBO Joint Conference Programme, Genes/Brain, Mind and Behavior, Heidelberg,
Germany.
Illes, J. (2016). A feast of thinking on the naturalization of enhancement neurotechnology. In: Jotterand,
F. and Dubljević, V. (Eds.) Cognitive Enhancement: Ethical and Policy Implications in International
Perspectives, pp.346–350. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Illes, J. and Raffin, T.A. (2002). Neuroethics: a new discipline is emerging in the study of brain and
cognition. Brain and Cognition, 50, 341–344.
Illes, J., Blakemore, C., Hansson, M.G., et al. (2005). International perspectives on engaging the public
in neuroethics. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6, 977–982.
Illes, J., Kirschen, M.P., Edwards, E., et al. (2006). Ethics: incidental findings in brain imaging research.
Science, 311, 783–784.
Illes, J., Kirschen, M.P., Edwards, E., et al. (2008). Practical approaches to incidental findings in brain
imaging research. Neurology, 70, 384–390.
Illes, J., Reimer, J.C., and Kwon, B.K. (2011). Stem cell clinical trials for spinal cord injury: readiness,
reluctance, redefinition. Stem Cell Reviews and Reports, 7, 997–1005.
Mayer, E.A., Knight, R., Mazmanian, S.K., Cryan, J.F., and Tillisch, K. (2014). Gut microbes and the
brain: paradigm shift in neuroscience. Journal of Neuroscience, 34, 15490–15496.
Marcus, S.J. (2002). Neuroethics: Mapping the Field, Conference Proceedings. New York: Dana Press.
National Bioethics Advisory Commission (1999). Research Involving Human Biological
Materials: Ethical Issues and Policy Guidance. Available from: https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.
edu/nbac/hbm.pdf [accessed August 4, 2016.
Parens, E. and Johnston, J. (2007). Does it make sense to speak of neuroethics? EMBO Reports, 8,
S61–64.
Persson, I. and Savulescu, J. (2008). The perils of cognitive enhancement and the urgent imperative to
enhance the moral character of humanity. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 25, 162–177.
Racine, E. (2010). Pragmatic Neuroethics: Improving Treatment and Understanding of the Mind-Brain.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Robillard, J.M., Cabral, E., Hennessey, C., Kwon, B.K., and Illes, J. (2015). Fueling hope: stem cells in
social media. Stem Cell Reviews and Reports, 11, 540–546.
Roskies, A. (2002). Neuroethics for the new millennium. Neuron, 35, 21–23.
Scott, N.A., Murphy, T.H., and Illes, J. (2012). Incidental findings in neuroimaging research: a
framework for anticipating the next frontier. Journal of Empirical Research on Human Research
Ethics, 7, 53–57.
xvi
xvi Preface
Stevenson, S., Beattie, B.L., Bruce, L., and Illes, J. (2016). When culture informs neuroscience:
considerations for community-based neurogenetics research and clinical care in a First Nation
Community with early onset familial Alzheimer disease. In: Chiao, J.Y. (Ed.) Cultural Neuroscience,
pp.171–181. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Whiteley, L. (2012). Resisting the revelatory scanner? Critical engagements with fMRI in popular
media. BioSocieties, 7, 245–272.
Wilfond, B.S. and Ravitsky, V. (2005). On the proliferation of bioethics sub-disciplines: do we really
need “genethics” and “neuroethics”? American Journal of Bioethics, 5, 20–21.
Wolf, S.M., Lawrenz, F.P., Nelson, C.A., et al. (2008). Managing incidental findings in human subjects
research: analysis and recommendations. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 36, 219–48.
xvi
Acknowledgments
We are deeply grateful for research funding and support over the past 15 years from
numerous organizations: the Canadian Institutes of Health Research, US National
Institutes of Health, Canada Research Chairs Program, Canada Foundation for
Innovation, British Columbia Knowledge Development Fund, Vancouver Coastal
Health Research Institute, Genome BC, Genome Canada, Stem Cell Network, Kids
Brain Health Network (formerly NeuroDevNet, Inc.), Canadian Dementia Knowledge
Translation Network, Vancouver Foundation, Djavad Mowafaghian Centre for Brain
Health at the University of British Columbia (UBC), W. Maurice Young Centre for
Applied Ethics at UBC, Peter Wall Institute of Advanced Studies, the Foundation for
Ethics and Technology, Institute of Mental Health, American Academy of Neurology,
Dana Foundation, Greenwall Foundation, North Growth Foundation, the Office for
Science and Technology of the Embassy of France to Canada, and the British Consulate
based in Vancouver, BC, and others. We extend our many thanks also to the team at the
National Core for Neuroethics at UBC, colleagues, collaborators, trainees within and
outside our university, province, and country, and family and friends who share and live
the vision for neuroethics with us.
The opinions expressed in the chapters are solely those of the contributing authors, and do
not necessarily reflect the views of the editors or research sponsors.
xvi
xi
Contents
xx Contents
Contents xxi
Part IV Epilogue
31. Neuroethics and neurotechnology: Instrumentality
and human rights 603
Joseph J. Fins
List of contributors
Shelly Benjaminy is a doctoral candidate at the National Core for Neuroethics, University
of British Columbia, and a Clinical Ethics Fellow at Providence Health Care in Vancouver,
BC. Her research interests lie at the intersection of ethics and novel biotechnologies that
present the potential for new knowledge, therapeutics, and improved clinical care.
James L. Bernat is the Louis and Ruth Frank Professor of Neuroscience and Professor
of Neurology and Medicine at the Geisel School of Medicine at Dartmouth. His research
interests are in brain death, the definition and criterion of death, and chronic disorders
of consciousness. He is the author of Ethical Issues in Neurology, 3rd edition (Lippincott
Williams & Wilkins, 2008).
Brian G. Booth is a postdoctoral researcher at the University of Antwerp. His research
interests are in medical image analysis with a focus on using machine learning techniques
to identify patterns of abnormality in medical images. He received his PhD in computing
science from Simon Fraser University where his thesis focused on diffusion magnetic
resonance imaging analysis techniques specialized for the preterm infant brain.
Laura Y. Cabrera is Associate Professor of Neuroethics at Michigan State University. Her
research focuses on the exploration of attitudes, perceptions, and values of the general
public toward neurotechnologies, the normative implications of using neurotechnologies
for medical and nonmedical purposes, and on the ethical and social implications of
environmental changes for brain and mental health. She received a BSc in Electrical and
Communication Engineering from the Instituto Tecnológico de Estudios Superiores de
Monterrey (ITESM) in Mexico City, a MA in Applied Ethics from Linköping University
in Sweden, and a PhD in Applied Ethics from Charles Sturt University in Australia.
Adrian Carter is Senior Research Fellow and Head of the Neuroethics and Policy Group,
Monash Institute of Cognitive and Clinical Neurosciences, Monash University. His
research interests are the impact of neuroscience on our understanding and treatment of
addictive behaviors, including agency, identity, and moral responsibility; coercion; and
the use of emerging technologies, such as deep brain stimulation and brain imaging, to
treat addiction. Dr. Carter has been an advisor to the World Health Organization, the
European Monitoring Centre for Drugs and Drug Addiction, the Australian Ministerial
Council on Drugs Strategy, and United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime.
Jennifer A. Chandler is a Professor of Law and holds the Bertram Loeb Research Chair
at the University of Ottawa. She researches and writes about the legal and ethical aspects
of advances in biomedical science and technology, with particular interest in neuroethics,
organ donation, and regenerative medicine. Recently she has written on the legal
xvi
Wayne Hall is Professor and Director of the Centre for Youth Substance Abuse Research,
University of Queensland, and Professor of the National Addiction Centre, Kings College
London. His research interests are in drug use and addiction, epidemiology, mental health,
ethics, and public health policy. He was formerly an NHMRC Australia Fellow at the
University of Queensland Centre for Clinical Research and the University of Queensland
Brain Institute (2009–2014), Professor of Public Health Policy, School of Population Health,
University of Queensland (2005–2009), and Director of the Office of Public Policy and
Ethics at the Institute for Molecular Bioscience (2001–2005), University of Queensland.
Sharmin Hossain is a Postdoctoral Research Fellow at the National Core for Neuroethics
at the University of British Columbia (UBC) and at Kids Brain Health Network (formerly
NeuroDevNet, Inc.), a Canadian Network of Centres of Excellence. She received a PhD in
Neuroscience from UBC with a thesis focused on revealing the dynamic growth patterns
of immature neurons in the brain. Her current research focuses on neurodevelopmental
disorders, ethics, and policy.
Steven E. Hyman is Harvard University Distinguished Service Professor of Stem Cell and
Regenerative Biology, a core faculty member of the Broad Institute of Harvard and MIT,
and Director of the Stanley Center for Psychiatric Research at the Broad Institute. From
2001 to 2011, he served as Provost of Harvard University and from 1996 to 2001, director
of the US National Institute of Mental Health. He is former Editor of the Annual Review
of Neuroscience and served formerly as President of the Society for Neuroscience and the
International Neuroethics Society.
Judy Illes is Professor of Neurology and Canada Research Chair in Neuroethics at the
University of British Columbia, in Vancouver, Canada. She is a pioneer of the field of
neuroethics, and has made ground-making contributions to a broad range of ethical,
social, and policy challenges at the intersection of biomedical ethics and neuroscience.
She is a Fellow of the Royal Society of Canada, Canadian Academy of Health Sciences,
and the American Association for the Advancement of Science. She is the editor of the
original neuroethics volume Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory, Practice, and Policy
(Oxford University Press, 2006).
Agnieszka Jaworska is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of California,
Riverside. Her research interests are at the intersection of ethical theory, medical ethics,
and moral psychology. Her current book in preparation concerns the ethics of treatment
of individuals whose status as moral agents and persons seems compromised or uncertain,
such as Alzheimer’s patients, addicts, psychopaths, and young children. It is part of a
larger project on the nature of the specifically human agency and the role of the capacity
to care in moral psychology. She has published in Ethics, Philosophy and Public Affairs,
and Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
Fabrice Jotterand is Associate Professor of Bioethics and Medical Humanities and Director
of the Graduate Program in Bioethics at the Center for Bioethics and Medical Humanities,
Medical College of Wisconsin, Milwaukee, and Senior Researcher in Bioethics/Neuroethics
at the University of Basel. His scholarship and research interests focus on issues including
moral enhancement, neurotechnologies and human identity, the use of neurotechnologies
in psychiatry, medical professionalism, and moral and political philosophy. He is the
co-editor of Cognitive Enhancement (Oxford University Press, 2016, with Veljko Dubljeviić)
and the co-editor of the book series Advances in Neuroethics (Springer).
Niranjan S. Karnik is the Cynthia Oudejans Harris, MD Professor of Psychiatry at the
Rush University Medical Center in Chicago. In the Department of Psychiatry, he serves
xxvi
as the Director of the Section of Population Behavioral Health and Medical Director of
the Road Home Program: Center for Veterans and their Families. He is also an Associate
Faculty Member of the Maclean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of
Chicago. His research interests are focused on homeless and underserved youth, mobile
technologies, and the mental health needs of veterans and their families.
Matthew P. Kirschen is an Assistant Professor of Anesthesiology and Critical Care
Medicine, Pediatrics and Neurology at the University of Pennsylvania Perelman School
of Medicine and The Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia. His research interests are
neuromonitoring of critically ill children with acute brain injury, early detection of brain
injury in critically ill children, neuroprognostication after acute brain injury in children,
and death by neurologic criteria determination in children.
Erika Kleiderman is an Academic Associate at the Centre of Genomics and Policy at
McGill University. Her research interests are the ethical, legal, and social implications
surrounding minors, access to data and genetic information, and the regulation of stem
cells, gene editing technologies, and regenerative medicine. She has also been involved in
the development of controlled data and biosamples access documentation for longitudinal
biobanks.
Eran Klein is a neurologist and philosopher at the Oregon Health and Science University,
Portland VA Medical Center, and Department of Philosophy and the Center for
Sensorimotor Neural Engineering at the University of Washington. His interests reside at
the intersection of neurology, neurotechnology, and philosophy.
Jonathan D. Moreno is the David and Lyn Silfen University Professor at the University of
Pennsylvania where he is a Penn Integrates Knowledge (PIK) professor. At Penn he is also
Professor of Medical Ethics and Health Policy, of History and Sociology of Science, and of
Philosophy. His books include The Body Politic, which was named a Best Book of 2011 by
Kirkus Reviews, Mind Wars (Bellevue Literary Press, 2012), and Undue Risk (Routledge,
2000). Moreno also frequently contributes to such publications as The New York Times,
The Wall Street Journal, The Huffington Post, Psychology Today, and Nature and appears
on broadcast and online media. In 2008–2009 he served as a member of President Barack
Obama’s transition team. The American Journal of Bioethics has called him “the most
interesting bioethicist of our time.”
Sabine Müller is an Assistant Professor of Neurophilosophy and Medical Ethics at the
Charité–Universitätsklinik Berlin. Her research interests are ethical issues of psychiatric
neurosurgery, particularly of deep brain stimulation, as well as ethical issues of psychiatry,
neurology, and neurology.
Saskia K. Nagel is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Ethics of Technology at
the University of Twente, Netherlands. Her research interests are at the intersection of
ethics, philosophy, life sciences, and technologies. Her background is in cognitive science
and philosophy. She works on approaches to individual and societal challenges in a
technological culture, with a focus on the ethical, anthropological, and social consequences
of neuroscientific progress. She is particularly interested in how technologies influence
our self-understanding, and how they impact our understanding of autonomy and
responsibility.
Brad Partridge is a Senior Research Fellow in the Research Development Unit at
Caboolture Hospital, Queensland. His research interests are ethical issues in sport, and
the use of human enhancement technologies.
Rémi Quirion is a Professor and Québec’s first chief scientist since 2011. Until his
appointment, Rémi Quirion was the vice-dean for science and strategic initiatives at
McGill University. He was the scientific director of the Douglas Mental Health Institute
and the executive director of the International Collaborative Research Strategy for
Alzheimer’s Disease of the CIHR. Professor Quirion was the first scientific director of
the Institute of Neurosciences, Mental Health and Addiction (INMHA). He has received
several awards and honours, including the Order of Canada (OC) and is a member of the
Royal Society of Canada.
Eric Racine is Director of the Neuroethics Research Unit and Full Research Professor
at the Institut de recherches cliniques de Montréal, Canada. Inspired by philosophical
pragmatism, his research aims to understand and bring to the forefront the experience
of ethically problematic situations by patients and stakeholders and then to resolve them
collaboratively through deliberative and evidenced-informed processes.
Vasiliki Rahimzadeh is a PhD Candidate with the Centre of Genomics and Policy at
McGill University and a 2016 Vanier Canada Graduate Scholar. Her doctoral thesis
x
systems that support complex social and cognitive functions. She investigates how
brain systems supporting how we respond to subtle social cues, understand actions, and
manage attention to pursue goals are compromised across a range of neurodevelopmental,
neuropsychiatric, and neurological conditions that are characterized by social and
cognitive symptoms.
Anthony Traboulsee is an Associate Professor and Research Chair of the MS Society of
Canada at the University of British Columbia in Vancouver. He is the Director of the MS/
NMO Clinic and Clinical Trials Research Group at UBC Hospital. His research focus is
on clinical trial design, the development of practice guidelines for the use of magnetic
resonance imaging (MRI) in the management of multiple sclerosis, establishing advanced
MRI imaging outcomes in multiple sclerosis, and the treatment of neuromyelitis optica.
Robert D. Truog is the Frances Glessner Lee Professor of Medical Ethics, Anesthesia
and Pediatrics at Harvard Medical School, where he serves as Director of the Center for
Bioethics. He is also a Senior Associate in Critical Care Medicine at Boston Children’s
Hospital, where he has practiced pediatric intensive care medicine for more than 30 years.
Lawrence M. Ward is a Full Professor of Psychology at the University of British
Columbia. He investigates brain regional interactions underlying a variety of visual,
auditory, and higher cognitive processes using EEG and MEG and advanced techniques
such as independent component analysis, phase synchronization, and transfer entropy.
He is currently focusing on the cognitive neuroscience of attention, memory, reading,
and consciousness, the effects of challenges such as drugs and dying on brain network
interactions, the effects of neural noise on cognition and perception, and mathematical
and computer modeling of neuronal oscillations and synchronization.
Joanna M. Wardlaw is a Professor and Chair of Applied Neuroimaging and Director of
Edinburgh Imaging, Neuroimaging Sciences and the Brain Research Imaging Centre at
the University of Edinburgh, and Honorary Consultant Neuroradiologist in the National
Health Service. Her research focuses on the pathophysiology, diagnosis, treatment, and
prevention of stroke, most recently focusing specifically on cerebral small vessel disease.
She led a UK-wide initiative to establish standards for management of incidental findings
during research imaging.
Sarah S. Welsh is a Fellow in Pediatric Critical Care Medicine at The Children’s Hospital
of Philadelphia. Her research interests include drug monitoring and pharmacokinetics in
pediatric status epilepticus, as well as the neuromonitoring and neuroprognostication of
children with acute brain injury.
Emily Wight is Communications Manager at the Djavad Mowafaghian Centre for Brain
Health at the University of British Columbia. Her focus is on plain-language science and
academic communication, and her background is in nonfiction writing and publishing.
xxixi
(c) Theta
Transfer
Entropy (vOT)
(d) Gamma
PLVs
(All ROIs)
(e) Gamma
PLVs (vOT)
(e) Gamma
Transfer
Entropy
(vOT)
gamma
Figure 2.1 Example of dynamic EEG synchronization and transfer entropy results from a word reading task. Synchronization was measured with
phase locking value (PLV), and narrow band transfer entropy was measured using an adaptation of the Kullback entropy (for vOT to/from other areas
only). Theta band is 3–7 Hz and gamma band is 35–45 Hz. Black lines (arrows) indicate significant interaction (directed information flow) between the
connected reading-related brain areas during the time period (ms after stimulus presentation) indicated at the top of the figure. vOT indicates ventral
occipital-temporal brain region, the putative word-form area.
Reproduced from Bedo N, Ribary U, and Ward LM. (2014) ‘Fast dynamics of cortical functional and effective connectivity during word reading’, PLoS ONE, Volume 9, Issue 2, e88940,
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0088940, Copyright © 2014 Bedo et al. Reproduced under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Version 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0), https://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
2
Source waveforms Fast-Fourier Transform
Anterior
25
LCMV
Source Amplitude
50 20 MCMV
Amplitude |y(f)|
16-Hz Mixing
(nAmp)
15
0
10
–50 5
0
0 50 100 150 200 0 10 20 30 40 50 60
Time (ms) Frequency (Hz)
25
LCMV
50 20
Amplitude |y(f)|
MCMV
Amplitude 36-Hz Mixing
15
(nAmp)
0
10
–50 5
LH RH 0
Posterior
0 50 100 150 200 0 10 20 30 40 50 60
Time (ms) Frequency (Hz)
Figure 2.2 EEG localization and connectivity accuracy. Left panel shows a simulated source location (blue square) that had only a 16-Hz oscillation and
a neighboring (within 15 mm) source location (red square) that had only a 36-Hz oscillation. Source mixing of 16-and 36-Hz oscillations were clearly
visible in the traditional beamformer (LCMV) reconstructed source waveforms (blue and red lines; middle panel). Amplitude spectra (right panels)
showed that both red and blue LCMV sources contained energies at 16 and 36 Hz (i.e., source mixing). Because of this source mixing, phase-coherence
between the sources existed and functional connectivity was falsely revealed (green line; left panel). Our MCMV beamformer (black lines), however,
prevented source mixing. MCMV sources only had 16-Hz (lower panels’ black lines) or 36-Hz oscillations (upper panels’ black lines). Obviously, false-
connections were not found for the MCMV beamformer.
3
Anterior
LH RH
Figure 2.4 Examples of visualizations associated with diffusion MRI (dMRI) data. Some
visualizations highlight the brain’s diffusion properties (a–e), while others highlight its geometric
properties (f–h), while still others highlight brain connectivity (i–l). See the text for a description
of each visualization technique: (a) mean diffusivity (MD); (b) fractional anisotropy (FA); (c) color-
coded FA; (d) ellipsoidal visualization of diffusion tensors; (e) perceptual color visualization of
diffusion tensors; (f) tubular structure detection in dMRI; (g) dMRI segmentation of corpus
callosum (above) and the cingulum (right), visualized in 2D and 3D respectively; (h) dMRI image
difference overlaid on MD image; (i) streamline tractography; (j) visualization of tract confidence
regions; (k) a connectome visualized as a circular graph; (l) a connectome overlaid on a brain
silhouette.
1
Part I
Neurotechnology: Today
and tomorrow
2
3
Chapter 1
Introduction
Neuroethics, like bioethics more broadly, has grown up alongside of and has, in many
ways, been propelled by emerging biomedical technologies. Over time, they have sorted
themselves into broad areas largely along the lines of clinical practice, public health, and
biomedical and research ethics. Each of these broad research areas can be further divided
into more specialized areas of research and scholarship. Within the ethics of biomedi-
cal research, subdisciplines have emerged around genetics and genomics, regenerative
medicine, synthetic biology, nanotechnology, and neuroscience. Neuroethics coalesced
in the early 2000s to focus on ethical issues raised by the neurosciences and their applica-
tion in medicine and society, as well as on issues related to the emerging neuroscience
of ethics (Marcus 2002; Illes & Bird 2006). Over the past 10 or 15 years, neuroethics
has founded an international professional society (http://www.neuroethicssociety.org/),
created specialist journals, and supported the development of an active community of
scholars. Neuroethics scholars have prompted and contributed to critical debates about
disorders of consciousness, research with brain-interfacing devices, criminal justice, and
moral decision-making, to name a few.
Neuroscience sometimes employs other emerging biomedical technologies, such as
genetics, regenerative medicine, and synthetic biology, which generate their own ethics
and policy conundrums. When emerging biomedical technologies converge or collide,
the challenges inherent to each can be compounded. These challenges are of at least two
types: First, emerging technologies are new by definition, fast moving, and have only
nascent and rapidly evolving theoretical and empirical scholarship on the associated ethi-
cal issues. When two or more such technologies are combined, existing ethics, governance,
and public engagement challenges are magnified. Second, communities of ethicists1 tend
to coalesce around specific technologies, and study the ethical, legal, and social implica-
tions (ELSI), and the governance landscape related to that particular technology or class
of technologies; however, these communities often have little overlap. Neuroethics schol-
ars are frequently, though certainly not always, different from ELSI scholars, who study
the ethical, legal, and social implications of genetics and genomics, who are often different
from ethicists who study regenerative medicine, synthetic biology, or nanotechnology.
4 5
The separation is particularly acute for the latter two, originating, as they have, largely
outside biomedicine. This siloing limits information exchange and the benefit that can
come from cross-pollination and collaboration not only between biomedical scientists
and ethicists, but also across scholars working on different emerging technologies.
As technologies mature and become tools for other areas of science, emerging biomedi-
cal technologies will increasingly converge in ways that bring these challenges into sharp
relief. In addition, the difficulty of staying up to date on bleeding-edge science, the silo-
ing of the science itself, and personal academic interest all suggest that the challenges of
siloing in the ethics community will persist. However, both sets of challenges might be
attenuated by a more systematic approach to ethical analysis across subdisciplines, and
at least some focus not on the details of the technologies but rather on the nature of the
technologies. The development of frameworks for ethical analysis based on shared char-
acteristics, including that the technologies are emerging, rapidly evolving, and ethically
contentious, provide a process for mutual learning and growth across a variety of emerg-
ing biomedical technologies, easing the challenges of bringing together not just two, but
many cultures (Snow 1998).
asked. Whole genome and whole exome (the part of the genome that codes for proteins)
sequencing, however, produces a huge amount of data, much of which has unclear or
unknown implications for the health of the individual. Some may have very serious, con-
crete, and medically actionable implications; the remainder of the data falls somewhere
in between these two ends of the spectrum. One particularly vexing type of data includes
genetic variants associated with serious adult-onset neurological conditions identified in
young people and in particular, in children (e.g., Anderson et al. 2015). The genetics and
ELSI communities have been working mightily to try to understand how best to manage
these data—whether, how, and in what format any or all of it should be returned (e.g.,
Haga & Zhao 2013; Kleiderman et al. 2014; Kullo et al. 2014; Lewis & Goldenberg 2015).
There remain many unsettled questions, and despite a strong and growing literature and
multiple frameworks and recommendations for managing these data (e.g., Fabsitz et al.
2010; Wolf et al. 2012; Sénécal et al. 2015), a review suggests that changes in practice
responding to these recommendations have been slow (Franca & Mathews, manuscript
in preparation).
Regenerative medicine
In the field of regenerative medicine, meanwhile, ethicists had been exploring the issues
raised by embryonic stem cell research, and developing relevant guidelines and gov-
ernance structures (Institute of Medicine and National Research Council 2005), when
Shinya Yamanaka announced at the annual meeting of the International Society for Stem
Cell Research that he had developed a way to turn adult cells into pluripotent stem cells
with properties similar to those of embryonic stem cells (Takahashi & Yamanaka 2006).
Unlike embryonic stem cells, to which so many scholars and members of the public voiced
moral objections due to their origins in the destruction of human embryos, these induced
pluripotent stem cells (iPSCs) required only somatic or body cells from a person, and
were therefore thought to be less problematic. In particular, somatic tissue such as that
from the skin is much easier to obtain and is readily available, unlike human embryos that
are usually obtained from couples who have completed in vitro fertilization treatment and
have leftover embryos stored in a clinic freezer. Due to this lower barrier to entry, many
investigators began studying and using iPSCs in their research, and the field accelerated
rapidly. Foreskin from infant circumcisions is a frequent source. Another source is left-
over pathology samples. Not only are there large institutional banks of such tissue, but if
the tissue was obtained in the course of clinical care and has had identifiers stripped from
the sample, its use in research does not require human subject research oversight in the
United States, under current regulations (US Department of Health & Human Services
2008). However, current regulations are under revision, recent events related to the family
of Henrietta Lacks (Skloot 2010; Callaway 2013), and existing data on patients’ views of
different uses of their archived tissue samples have led to new recommendations about the
use of archived tissue in iPSC research (Dasgupta et al. 2014; Lomax et al. 2015). As such,
institutions and stem cell research oversight committees are still trying to determine the
appropriate path forward.
6 7
Convergence
Now, imagine the convergence of these two rapidly evolving areas of biomedicine. Each
raises vexing ethics and policy issues in the absence of sufficient theoretical and empirical
research for norms or policy-making, or both, that come together under one umbrella
of research. Imagine, for example, a project that uses de-identified pathology samples to
derive iPSC lines and then uses those to derive neurons. As part of this research, whole
genome sequencing is completed for each cell line. Further, the data are posted to a pub-
licly available database to maximize the utility of the (possibly publicly funded) resource
that is this collection of lines. Sequence data reveal that several of the lines contain serious
mutations that would result in an immediate medical response, if known by the person
from whom the tissue was taken. Several contain mutations that guarantee that the per-
son from whom the tissue was taken will develop a serious neurological condition later in
life. How does the researcher respond?
Because the barrier to entry for iPSC research is so low and genome and exome
sequencing are now so affordable, this situation is likely to become increasingly common.
The genetics community may be well aware of the debate around the return of results and
incidental findings (e.g., Wolf et al. 2012; Sénécal et al. 2015), in particular those associ-
ated with neurological disease (e.g., Illes et al. 2004), but the stem cell scientists, who are
not technically working with human subjects, and perhaps never have, may not have any
familiarity with these debates. Neither of these communities may be well acquainted with
the debates within neuroethics about neurodegenerative disease, advance care planning,
and loss of cognitive capacities and self (e.g., Mathews et al. 2009; Pierce 2009; Robillard
et al. 2011).
This is but one example of how the convergence of emerging technologies can mag-
nify existing ethics, governance, and public engagement challenges. While the above-
mentioned example is hypothetical, real cases exist and are likely to become more
prevalent, both across biomedical technologies, such as deep brain stimulation, fetal
tissue research, novel treatments for psychiatric disease, genome editing, and including
other emerging technologies, as well (e.g., Chen et al. 2014; Hutmacher et al. 2015; Meshi
et al. 2015; Sproul 2015; Teoh et al. 2015).
issues, there is relatively little overlap in the researchers generating the related scholarship.
The separation is particularly acute for synthetic biology and nanotechnology for exam-
ple, originating as they have largely outside biomedicine and more closely associated with
engineering. This sorting of bioethics into increasingly specialized subdisciplines often
means that the scholars who read, write, and research ethics and policy issues related to
neuroscience do not necessarily—and often do not—overlap with the scholars who focus
on other emerging biomedical technologies.
It is not that there is no cross-talk or overlap across the subdisciplines—in the example
in the prior section, the work on return of results in the ELSI literature was helpfully
informed by parallel prior work in neuroimaging (e.g., Illes & Chin 2008; Illes et al. 2008).
Indeed, there are a number of prominent cross-pollinators between neuroethics and
ELSI, including several authors involved in the current volume (e.g., Cho and Knoppers).
Likewise, there are cross-pollinators between ELSI and regenerative medicine, but these
are emissaries, not robust conduits for data and knowledge exchange. For example, those
in regenerative medicine and the associated ethics community will not necessarily be
familiar with the theoretical and empirical research that has been done in neuroethics in
response to a search for ways to diagnose dementia and other cognitive disorders earlier
and earlier, in an effort to intervene before irreversible damage is done, and when a better
chance at delaying onset or otherwise mitigating the damage wrought by disease might
exist (e.g., Illes et al. 2007; Arias et al. 2015). Concerns have been raised and studied
regarding the psychological implications of presymptomatic diagnosis, discrimination,
stigma, and how preferences for individual care, life, and death might change as capacities
are lost and the self changed.
Another example of potentially problematic siloing may be found in synthetic biology,
for which many of the individuals working on the ethical implications of the science are
members of fields outside of ethics. This is not to disparage those scholars or their work
in synthetic biology in any way, only to note that synthetic biology, despite the explicit
intentions of the field to develop health-related biomedical applications, has not thus far
been a major focus of the biomedical ethics community. This disconnect exists despite
continuity with prior work in genetics, recombinant DNA and the Asilomar conference of
1975, and existing governance structures in biomedicine, most notably the Recombinant
DNA Advisory Committee. Instead, the ethics touchstones in synthetic biology are more
likely to be genetically modified organisms, such as golden rice (Enserink 2008), or dual-
use concerns, such as those raised by the introduction of new mutations that increased
the transmissibility of the H1N1 virus (Enserink 2012; Herfst et al. 2012). While these are
important and relevant cases, as synthetic biology moves more into biomedical science,
there is critical history and literature tied to their origins and future in genetics, about
which they must know. The story of Henrietta Lacks, her descendants, and the HeLa
cell line, and the human genetic modification debates that have been going on in genet-
ics for 30 years (President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine
Biomedical Behavioral Research 1982; Skloot 2010) are merely examples. Again, that is
not to say that there is not any cross-pollination—the Hastings Center had a large project
8 9
new morally contentious biomedical fields, the ethicists who study them, and the public
who funds and ultimately lives in the world that is shaped by the science, would all benefit
from a more systematic approach to information exchange and ethical analysis. One pos-
sible solution is a shared method or analytic framework, akin to technology assessment
but on a broader scale, to help emerging fields and the associated ethics community to
ask the right questions, learn from analogous prior cases in other fields, identify shared
challenges, and benefit from knowledge gained elsewhere, and to help both scientists and
ethicists to gain a broader understanding of the relationship of their research to other
areas of biomedical science. This analytic framework would focus not on the details of
the technology but rather on its nature, based on shared characteristics, including that the
technologies are emerging, rapidly evolving, and ethically contentious.
Late in its life in the US Congress, the Office of Technology Assessment (OTA)
produced a report assessing the content and quality of its policy analysis (Office of
Technology Assessment 1993). The OTA was a small shop that served the Congress
internally, and was a model for many similar entities internationally. The non-partisan
agency was charged with providing “thorough, objective information and analysis to
help Members of Congress understand and plan for the short-and long-term conse-
quences of the applications of technology, broadly defined.” One of the findings of the
1993 report was that there was little consistency in how different programs within the
OTA approached policy analysis. There were, however, commonalities. In developing
the context for their reports to Congress, the OTA often evaluated the historical con-
text and status quo, conducted a stakeholder analysis (including individuals, groups,
and institutions), identified key assumptions around the technology, determined the
international context and identified relevant international comparisons, and assessed
the legal and regulatory landscape. While some of these components would be more
easily addressed for a specific technology than for an entire field, these components are
a solid starting point. It should be noted, though, that there are other models of, and
exercises in, technology assessment and ethical analysis that can also serve as resources
for the development of a shared analytic framework (e.g., Tairyan & Illes 2009; Sclove
2010; Chameau et al. 2014).
Based on my own work across subdisciplines in bioethics, policy analysis, and tech-
nology assessment, I would add the following: First, stakeholder analysis, in particular
the role and views of the public, is critical. Scientists and ethicists need to know who
cares about this area of science, why, and what their views are. The public will be heard
at some point, so better earlier than later; besides, it is the right thing to do. Second, a
discussion about intellectual property and precompetitive public resources, their support,
and use should start early, though collective action may take time (Hinxton Group 2010).
This is particularly true in morally contentious areas of science that work with a scarce
or contested resource, or both, such as human embryos. Overall, from an ethics stand-
point, researchers engaged with contentious emerging technologies, in particular when
developing in pluralistic democracies, should be expected to identify key stakeholders, to
articulate what is morally at stake, and to ask and answer questions about the social goals
10 1
of the research, the anticipated benefits and harms and their distribution, the develop-
ment of shared resources, and governance.
In addition to facilitating ethics and policy analysis of converging technologies and
mitigating the negative effects of siloing, the broadest goal of this sort of systematic
effort at assessment or mapping of subdisciplines should be the same as the over-
arching goal of ethics in biomedicine, including neuroethics: to identify, frame, and
solve problems in medicine, public health, and the biosciences (Mathews et al. 2016).
Ideally, the process of working through the model would also facilitate stakeholder
engagement.
Table 1.1 combines the OTA components and the ethics-oriented components, and
provides an outline for a shared analytic framework. The approach is designed to produce
a series of reports on different emerging biotechnologies that would facilitate both infor-
mation flow across subdisciplines and comparison of different emerging biotechnologies
converging in a new project, application, or product, as well as the identification of novel
issues raised by that convergence.
The development of a shared analytic framework is, of course, only the first step. The
framework must also be put into practice, and there remain many practical questions;
in particular, how would these analyses be conducted and by whom? Two possibili-
ties are that this work could be centralized or distributed. The Human Fertilization and
Status quo What are the key questions, research areas, and prod-
ucts/applications in the field today?
Stakeholder analysis Which individuals, groups, and institutions have an inter-
est or role in the emerging biomedical technology?
Key assumptions around the technology What are the key assumptions of both the scientists and
the other stakeholders that may impede communication
and understanding or illuminate attitudes?
International context and relevant How is the technology and associated ethics and gover-
international comparisons nance landscape evolving internationally? Are there use-
ful international models?
Legal and regulatory landscape What are the laws and policies that currently apply and
what are the holes or challenges in current oversight?
Ethical and societal implications What is morally at stake? What are the sources of ethi-
cal controversy in the field? What are the other societal
concerns?
Social goals of the research What are the goals of the field that are oriented toward
improving the human condition? Are there other goals?
1
Conclusion 11
Embryology Authority in the United Kingdom currently does much of this analytic and
governance work across technologies related to reproductive medicine and research. In
addition, technology assessment of varying sorts occurs at national academies, national
bioethics commissions, and similar organizations internationally. But again, this work is
currently ad hoc, often in response to concerns about a particular application or product,
rather than a proactive, systematic effort to understand and help shape an emerging sub-
discipline. However, these centralized bodies do have significant authority and convening
power, which may allow them to both conduct the analysis and disseminate the products
effectively.
An alternative model would be to distribute the work to the subdisciplines themselves
through their relevant professional societies. These societies are likely to include many
of the relevant stakeholders, to encompass a broad understanding of the field, and to
hold the respect of their professional community. However, this model may perpetuate
the problem of siloing. To counteract this risk, a networked institution model might be
applied (Sclove 2010) wherein the professional societies ally with one another in a struc-
tured collaboration to exchange information and even partner in the work of analysis.
This virtual network of professional societies would also then be well positioned to dis-
seminate the products not only to the individual subdisciplines, but also across them, and
even to embody that work through, for example, the creation of cross-pollination ses-
sions at academic meetings or similar sections of specialist journals that explicitly solicit
cross-disciplinary views.
Regardless of the model for implementation of the shared analytic framework, given the
nature of emerging biomedical technologies, all analyses must be reviewed and refined
periodically with the natural ebb and flow of science and ethics.
Conclusion
When emerging biomedical technologies converge or collide, new challenges can arise.
These challenges are of at least two types: (1) Emerging technologies are new by definition,
fast moving, and have only nascent and rapidly evolving theoretical and empirical schol-
arship on the associated ethical issues. The combination of two or more technologies can
magnify existing ethics, governance, and public engagement challenges. (2) Communities
of ethicists tend to coalesce around specific technologies, to study the ethical, legal, and
social implications, and the governance landscape related to that particular technology or
class of technologies; however, these communities often have little overlap.
Just as the founders of a scientific field are responsible for laying the experimental
groundwork for that field, so too do they have a responsibility for laying the ethics and
governance groundwork. This responsibility applies to both scientists and ethicists. Each
new, morally contested field in biomedicine has the opportunity to try again to get it
right, in terms of evolution and shaping of the field, as well as in its governance. This
will only work, however, if we learn from the experience of other disciplines at different
developmental stages. Creation and implementation of a shared analytic framework will
12 1
accelerate this learning and improve the chances of getting it right—or some approxima-
tion thereof—more quickly and with fewer mistakes. Such a framework will also ease
the assessment of projects, applications, or products in which multiple emerging bio-
medical technologies converge or collide, and mitigate the effects of academic siloing.
Customization will always be required, and systematizing will never completely eliminate
siloing in academia. Neuroethics is a prime testing ground for a shared analytic frame-
work, and for the learning and collaboration that can benefit both biomedical research
and ethics overall.
Note
1. For the purposes of this chapter, I will use the term ethicist to mean the diverse array of scholars from
areas such as philosophy, theology, medicine, biology, public health, history, ethnography, economics,
sociology, political science, law, literature, and more, who focus on ethics and policy issues related to
biomedicine. I appreciate that this is an imperfect shorthand, but it has been adopted here for simplic-
ity and brevity.
References
Anderson, J.A., Hayeems, R.Z., Shuman, C., et al. (2015). Predictive genetic testing for adult-onset
disorders in minors: a critical analysis of the arguments for and against the 2013 ACMG guidelines.
Clinical Genetics, 87(4), 301–310.
Arias, J.J., Cummings, J., Grant, A.R., and Ford, P.J. (2015). Stakeholders’ perspectives on preclinical
testing for Alzheimer’s disease. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 26(4), 297–305.
Callaway, E. (2013). Deal done over HeLa cell line. Nature, 500(7461), 132–133.
Chameau, J.L., Ballhaus, W.F., and Lin, H.S. (Eds.) (2014). Emerging and Readily Available Technologies
and National Security: A Framework for Addressing Ethical, Legal, and Societal Issues. Washington,
DC: National Academies Press.
Chen, L., Qiu, R., and Li, L. (2014). The role of nanotechnology in induced pluripotent and embryonic
stem cells research. Journal of Biomedical Nanotechnology, 10(12), 3431–3461.
Dasgupta, I., Bollinger, J., Mathews, D.J.H., Neumann, N.M., Rattani, A., and Sugarman, J. (2014).
Patients’ attitudes toward the donation of biological materials for the derivation of induced
pluripotent stem cells. Cell Stem Cell, 14(1), 9–12.
Enserink, M. (2008). Tough lessons from golden rice. Science, 320(5875), 468–471.
Enserink, M. (2012, June 2). Free to speak, Kawaoka reveals flu details while Fouchier stays mum.
[News story.] Science. Available from: http://news.sciencemag.org/2012/04/free-speak-kawaoka-
reveals-flu-details-while-fouchier-stays-mum [accessed July 12, 2015].
Fabsitz, R.R., McGuire, A., Sharp, R.R., et al. (2010). Ethical and practical guidelines for reporting
genetic research results to study participants: updated guidelines from a National Heart, Lung, and
Blood Institute working group. Circulation: Cardiovascular Genetics, 3(6), 574–580.
Franca, A. and Mathews, D.J.H. Review of return of results policy, as reflected in clinical trial informed
consent documents. Manuscript in preparation.
Haga, S.B. and Zhao, J.Q. (2013). Stakeholder views on returning research results. Advances in Genetics,
84, 41–81.
Herfst, S., Schrauwen, E.J., Linster, M., et al. (2012). Airborne transmission of influenza A/H5N1 virus
between ferrets. Science, 336(6088), 1534–1541.
13
References 13
Hinxton Group (2010). Statement on Policies and Practices Governing Data and Materials Sharing and
Intellectual Property in Stem Cell Science. Available from: http://hinxtongroup.org/Consensus_
HG10_FINAL.pdf [accessed May 29, 2016].
Hutmacher, D.W., Holzapfel, B.M., De-Juan-Pardo, E.M., et al. (2015). Convergence of regenerative
medicine and synthetic biology to develop standardized and validated models of human diseases
with clinical relevance. Current Opinion in Biotechnology, 35, 127–132.
Illes, J. and Bird, S.J. (2006). Neuroethics: a modern context for ethics in neuroscience. Trends in
Neurosciences, 29(9), 511–517.
Illes, J. and Chin, V.N. (2008). Bridging philosophical and practical implications of incidental findings
in brain research. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 36(2), 298–304.
Illes, J., Rosen, A., Huang, L., et al. (2004). Ethical consideration of incidental findings on adult MRI in
research. Neurology, 62(6), 888–890.
Illes, J., Rosen, A., Greicius, M., and Racine, E. (2007). Ethics analysis of neuroimaging in Alzheimer’s
disease. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1097, 278–295.
Illes, J., Kirschen, M.P., Edwards, E., et al. (2008). Practical approaches to incidental findings on brain
imaging research. Neurology, 70(5), 384–390.
Institute of Medicine and National Research Council (2005). Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem
Cell Research. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
Kahn, J. (2011). The two (institutional) cultures: a consideration of structural barriers to
interdisciplinarity. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 54(3), 399–408.
Kleiderman, E., Knoppers, B.M., Fernandez, C.V., et al. (2014). Returning incidental findings from
genetic research to children: views of parents of children affected by rare diseases. Journal of Medical
Ethics, 40(10), 691–696.
Kullo, I.J., Haddad, R., Prows, C.A., et al. (2014). Return of results in the genomic medicine projects of
the eMERGE network. Frontiers in Genetics, 26(5), 50.
Lewis, M.H. and Goldenberg, A.J. (2015). Return of results from research using newborn screening
dried blood samples. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 43(3), 559–568.
Lomax, G.P., Hull, S.C., and Isasi, R. (2015). The DISCUSS Project: revised points to consider for the
derivation of induced pluripotent stem cell lines from previously collected research specimens. Stem
Cells Translational Medicine, 4(2), 123–129.
Marcus, S. (Ed.) (2002). Neuroethics: Mapping the Field, Conference Proceedings. New York: Dana Press.
Mathews, D.J.H., Bok, H., and Rabins, P.V. (Eds.) (2009). Personal Identity and Fractured Selves: Perspectives
from Philosophy, Ethics, and Neuroscience. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Mathews, D.J.H., Hester, M., Kahn, J., et al. (2016). A conceptual model for the translation of bioethics
research and scholarship. Hastings Center Report 46(5), 34–39.
Meshi, D., Tamir, D.I., and Heekeren, H.R. (2015). The emerging neuroscience of social media. Trends
in Cognitive Sciences, 19(12), 771–782.
Meslin, E.M., Thomson, E.J., and Boyer, J.T. (1997). The Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications
Research Program at the National Human Genome Research Institute. Kennedy Institute of Ethics
Journal, 7(3), 291–298.
Office of Technology Assessment (1993). Policy Analysis at OTA: A Staff Assessment. Available
from: http://ota.fas.org/reports/PAatOTA.pdf [accessed August 14, 2015].
Pierce, R. (2009). A changing landscape for advance directives in dementia research. Social Science &
Medicine, 70(4), 623–630.
President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine Biomedical Behavioral
Research (1982). Splicing Life: A Report on the Social and Ethical Issues of Genetic Engineering with
14
Human Beings. Washington, DC: President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in
Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research.
Robillard, J.M., Federico, C.A., Tairyan, K., Ivinson, A.J., and Illes, J. (2011). Untapped ethical
resources for neurodegeneration research. BMC Medical Ethics, 12. Available from: http://www.
biomedcentral.com/1472-6939/12/9 [accessed May 27, 2016].
Sclove, R. (2010). Reinventing Technology Assessment: A 21st Century Model. Washington, DC: Science
and Technology Innovation Program, Woodrow Wilson International Center for Scholars.
Sénécal, K., Rahimzadeh, V., Knoppers, B.M., Fernandez, C.V., Avard, D., and Sinnett, D. (2015).
Statement of principles on the return of research results and incidental findings in paediatric
research: a multi-site consultative process. Genome, 58(12), 541–548.
Skloot, R. (2010). The Immortal Life of Henrietta Lack. New York: Crown Publishing Group.
Snow, C.P. (1998). The Two Cultures. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sproul, A.A. (2015). Being human: the role of pluripotent stem cells in regenerative medicine and
humanizing Alzheimer’s disease models. Molecular Aspects of Medicine, 43–44, 54–65.
Tairyan, K. and Illes, J. (2009). Imaging genetics and the power of combined technologies: a perspective
from neuroethics. Neuroscience, 164(1), 7–15.
Takahashi, K. and Yamanaka, S. (2006). Induction of pluripotent stem cells from mouse embryonic and
adult fibroblast cultures by defined factors. Cell, 126(4), 663–676.
Teoh, G.Z., Klanrit, P., Kasimatis, M., and Seifalian, A.M. (2015). Role of nanotechnology in
development of artificial organs. Minerva Medica, 106(1), 17–33.
US Department of Health & Human Services (2008). Code of Federal Regulations Title 45, Section 46.
In: Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects. Washington, DC: US Government.
Wolf, S.M., Crock, B.N., Van Ness, B., et al. (2012). Managing incidental findings and research results
in genomic research involving biobanks and archived data sets. Genetics in Medicine, 14(4),
361–384.
15
Chapter 2
Introduction
In this chapter, we highlight a selection of advances, future challenges, and limitations of
emerging multimodal neuroimaging technologies, data signal processing, and visualiza-
tion strategies. We bring these examples to the forefront as experts in the field who are
also attentive to the ethical challenges they pose for personalized diagnostics, prognosis,
and targeted intervention into clinical practice.
practice. New MRI sequences have vastly expanded the types of information available by
MRI and the latest developments blur the boundaries between structural and functional
information. The new frontier in MRI is the quantification of changes in tissue due to
development, aging, disease, and therapy. In this very brief overview we highlight a few of
the most exciting developments.
A variety of imaging techniques measure brain perfusion (MacDonald & Frayne 2015);
for example, arterial spin labeling can yield estimates of cerebral blood flow rates without
requiring injection of a contrast agent. While most MR images arise from water, by using
magnetization transfer techniques, one can access protons resident on other molecules;
chemical exchange saturation transfer (CEST) (Ward K.M. 2000) promises to be able to
produce images of the distribution of several biologically important molecules like glucose
(Nasrallah et al. 2013) and amino acids residues in proteins. Inhomogeneous magnetization
transfer produces images that are specific for membrane lipids in brain (Varma et al. 2015).
There is a large literature on measurement of water diffusion in brain (Jones 2016).
Diffusion tensor imaging (DTI) enables tractography, which is the visualization of nerve
tracts in brain. DTI provides mean diffusivity and fractional anisotropy, which are highly
sensitive to subtle changes in microscopic brain structure. Despite limitations in terms of
specificity (Beaulieu 2002; Jones et al. 2013), DTI has been used widely in neuroimaging.
Advanced diffusion techniques, for example, diffusion-based size imaging (Wang Y. et al.
2011), enable more quantitative analyses including the proportion of axonal water and of
inflammatory cells.
A specific measurement of myelin can be accomplished by myelin water imaging
(MacKay et al. 1994; Prasloski et al. 2012). Assessment of myelin using this technique has
been performed in multiple sclerosis (Laule et al. 2008; Vavasour et al. 2009; Manogaran
et al. 2015), schizophrenia (Lang et al. 2014), stroke (Borich et al. 2013), and mild trau-
matic brain injury (Wright et al. 2016).
Probing the central nervous tissue using the phase information of MRI scans has
become an active field of research. Phase provides information on the magnetic properties
of tissue at high spatial resolution (Rauscher et al. 2005; Duyn et al. 2007). Considerable
research efforts have been going into turning the phase images into maps of underlying
magnetic tissue properties (quantitative susceptibility mapping (QSM) (Schweser et al.
2011, 2016; Bilgic et al. 2012; Liu C. et al. 2015)). Applications of phase-based contrast
and QSM range from the investigation of the developing (Lodygensky et al. 2011) and
aging brain (Li W. et al. 2014) to the assessment of changes in tissue structure and com-
position in neurodegenerative diseases (Wiggermann et al. 2013; Li X. et al. 2015; Guan
et al. 2016).
Using MR spectroscopy (Oz et al. 2014), researchers can create images of the concen-
trations of important brain metabolites, for example, N-acetylaspartate (measure of neu-
ronal integrity), the creatine/phosphocreatine pool (brain energetics), and glutamate (an
important excitatory neurotransmitter).
Surgical procedures can become much less invasive and more effective when the sur-
geon has access to real-time MR images of the subject. For example, abnormal brain tissue
17
may be ablated using high-intensity focused ultrasound while monitoring the health of
adjacent organs of risk using MR images sensitive to temperature (Coluccia et al. 2014).
Imaging of nuclei other than hydrogen introduces novel new imaging contrasts: hyper-
polarized MRI with carbon-13 nuclei enables detailed measurement of metabolic path-
ways (Ross et al. 2010) and sodium imaging (Shah et al. 2016) provides an indication of
cellular and metabolic integrity.
Fueled by the imagination of MRI scientists, advancements in MRI hardware have been
driving progress in MRI software (i.e., scans) and vice versa, transforming MRI from a
tool for the visualization of structure into a science of quantitative mapping of central
nervous system tissue properties.
of other people. Observing actions engages a distributed brain network of parietal, fron-
tal, and temporal sensorimotor brain regions known as the action observation network
(Buccino et al. 2001). An experimental design and analysis technique known as repeti-
tion suppression/fMRI adaptation (Grill-Spector et al. 2006) exploits the greater sensitiv-
ity of neural circuits to novel information than repeated information to reveal neural
populations that decode distinct dimensions of a stimulus. During an action observation
task, several dimensions of the action are processed concurrently (e.g., kinematics, goals,
outcomes, intentions, expressive meaning). Using repetition suppression, brain processes
that decode each of these dimensions have been localized to distinct, hierarchically orga-
nized functional modules nested within the larger action observation network (Grafton &
Hamilton 2007; Tipper et al. 2015). By identifying more precise functional granularity
within functional brain networks, the precision of the measuring sticks we use to assess
brain pathology across of broad range of clinical conditions is greatly increased.
Advances in fMRI study design are made possible in part by an increasing willing-
ness to utilize ecologically valid, complex, dynamic stimuli and tasks that employ video
displays, interactive tasks, physical manipulanda, virtual reality, and wide-field three-
dimensional (3D) immersion. As tasks and stimuli better match real-world conditions,
the richness of available behavioral measures is opening a window onto the significance
of individual variability. The result is a growing appreciation that clever new tools are
needed to quantify this meaningful social, cognitive, and behavioral information to define
nuanced sociocognitive phenotypes, and map them to distinct patterns of brain function.
This new perspective is critical to developing new tools for improving diagnostics and
individualized interventions for numerous neurodevelopmental, neurological, and neu-
ropsychiatric conditions.
occipitotemporal cortex, the anterior intraparietal sulcus, and the frontal eye fields, but
not V1, were implicated in the visual deficit (Secen et al. 2011). Other studies used the
subvoxel resolution provided by repetition suppression to confirm the involvement of V1
and extrastriate regions in amblyopia (Li X. et al. 2011a), and to demonstrate abnormal
binocular interactions in these regions (Jurcoane et al. 2009).
Functional MRI is now being used to assess new treatment approaches to amblyopia
aimed at augmenting visual cortex activity. A recent study reported an increase in BOLD
response in visual cortex with amblyopic eye viewing after 30 days of perceptual learning
treatment, but no structural change measurable with DTI (Zhai et al. 2013). In another
study, anodal direct current stimulation was found to improve vision in the amblyopic eye
in some adults with amblyopia; it also equalized the BOLD response of the visual cortex to
inputs from each eye (Spiegel et al. 2013). In a more controversial study, oral administra-
tion of levodopa produced a small improvement in visual acuity in the amblyopic eye and
a correspondingly small increase in V1 activation measured with fMRI (Yang et al. 2003).
relies upon parcellating a brain network into a set of nodes, computing the functional
relationships between each node-pair (e.g., activity correlations, coherence, mutual infor-
mation, transfer entropy; Wang H.E. et al. 2014), and then quantifying the overall organi-
zational structure, or architecture, of the network as a whole. A range of graph metrics is
available to quantify properties of brain network organization, such as strength, efficiency,
clustering, modularity, path length, centrality, and assortativity (Rubinov & Sporns 2010).
An important advantage of these metrics is their ability to reveal organizational features
that are unobservable with traditional fMRI analyses. As fMRI is used to characterize
brain pathology linked to heterogeneous symptom profiles that occur with neurodevel-
opmental and neurological disorders, topological network analysis provides a promising
analytical tool (Kaiser 2011).
Topological network metrics can be applied not only to functional brain organiza-
tion, but also to anatomical brain organization based on tractography analyses of diffu-
sion imaging data, which estimates probabilistic measures of white matter connectivity
between brain regions (Basser et al. 2000). Functional and anatomical network metrics
can then be compared to identify structure–function relationships related to task per-
formance (Hermundstad et al. 2013) and individual variability in how underlying brain
architecture is utilized to achieve particular cognitive states (Hermundstad et al. 2014).
This approach is also being applied to move beyond identifying static patterns of func-
tional organization to reveal dynamic brain changes that unfold over time (Bassett et al.
2011; Betzel et al. 2016). New techniques for characterizing interactions and transitions
between identifiable coherent brain states are providing promising avenues for enabling
distinctions between neurologically healthy and pathological brain function.
the cognitive operation differs between experiments. This case (viz., spatial but not tem-
poral replication) provides an important scientific opportunity to use differences between
experiments to help test the theorized timing of cognitive functions of brain networks.
That is to say, if a theorized cognitive function can be manipulated using (for example)
variation in task timing between experiments, it can be determined whether or not the
BOLD signal pattern supports the account of the cognitive operation performed by that
functional brain network, at least for the task in question. This is tested using the ANOVA
method already mentioned above with experiment as a within-or between-subject factor.
Finally, if a cognitive operation is elicited by only one version of the experiment but not
the other, the version not eliciting this cognitive operation would show a flat HDR shape
for that functional brain network, and therefore it could be concluded that neither spa-
tial nor temporal replication has been observed. This methodology has been used in past
work to test theoretical accounts of the function of brain networks across closely matched
experiments (Lavigne et al. 2015a).
Future directions
Moving forward, the combination of more nuanced experimental paradigms to assess
complex cognitive functions and characterize individual sociocognitive phenotypes and
more sophisticated analyses of functional and anatomical brain network organization
open up a new frontier for clinical neuroscience research. The potential to improve diag-
nostic and assessment capabilities and enhance individualized care across a range of neu-
rodevelopmental, neurological, and neuropsychiatric conditions is unprecedented.
promising novel tracers are currently used in human studies, 11C-PPB3, 18F-T807 or 18F-
AV-1451, and 18F-THK5351 (Villemagne et al. 2015). The tau tracers are not equivalent in
their ability to detect deposits of different tau isoforms that are selectively associated with
different aspects of neurodegeneration: the precise relevance of each tracer to specific
diseases is thus still under investigation. Development of PET tracers for other targets of
interest such as alpha-synuclein, whose aggregations are implicated in the pathogenesis of
Parkinson’s disease, is a very active research area, but no successful candidates have been
developed as yet (Eberling et al. 2013, Kikuchi et al. 2010).
The ability to identify abnormal protein aggregation or alterations in metabolic path-
ways observable with 18F-FDG, does not always by itself lead to accurate differential diag-
nosis or to improved understanding of pathogenic mechanisms. Informed combination
of data obtained from different imaging modalities has been shown to yield superior
information; for example, a recent study performed on a hybrid PET/MRI demonstrated
that the combination of regional metabolism, functional connectivity, and gray matter
volume, which were derived from disease characteristic networks, was able to achieve
high classification accuracies for separating patients with different neurodegenerative
syndromes of 77.5% for Alzheimer’s disease versus others, 82.5% for behavioral variant
frontotemporal dementia versus others, 97.5% for semantic dementia versus others, and
87.5% for progressive nonfluent aphasia versus others—this multimodal classification
was superior to unimodal approaches (Tahmasian et al. 2016). In addition to combing
data from different modalities, novel image analysis approaches for PET images are also
emerging and are proving complementary to the traditional ones based either on kinetic
modeling or radioactivity concentration values. Such approaches include information
about specific tracer distribution patterns within anatomically relevant regions of interest
(Klyuzhin et al. 2016; Liu S. et al. 2016). Combinations of such patterns or features applied
to the analysis of 18F-FDG data coupled with MRI-derived information, resulting in the
definition of multiparameter-based biomarkers, have been shown to be associated with
different aspects of Alzheimer’s disease progression (Liu et al. 2016). Such biomarkers will
be of great relevance when stratifying patients and evaluating mechanisms of action and
effectiveness of emerging treatments.
The hybrid PET/MRI provides access to novel measurements, such as direct investiga-
tion of the interactions between neurotransmitter activity and brain function either at rest
or as stimulated by a pharmacological or behavioral intervention. This is a very exciting
area of research relevant to many aspects of brain function that will see growth as the
availability of the hybrid PET/MR scanners increases. For example, it will be possible
to investigate correlations between responses to reward, pain, or treatment in terms of
dopamine release and activation of cognitive networks and how such correlations dif-
fer amongst different subject populations. Ideally, it will be possible to identify imaging-
based biomarkers that identify subjects at risk and thus promote development of disease
prevention strategies. Optimization of such approaches will drive development of joint
PET/MRI image processing methods, either in the image reconstruction step or image
analysis step (Sander et al. 2013; Kang et al. 2015). In summary, over the last decade PET
24 2
and adolescent development, particularly in beta and alpha frequency ranges (Schäfer
et al. 2014). EEG studies suggest that such increasing spontaneous electrophysiological
connectivity may be associated with the acceleration of the alpha peak (Miskovic et al.
2015), suggesting that acceleration of spontaneous oscillatory connectivity may lead
to the predominant expression of intrinsic connectivity networks in the beta band in
adulthood.
One important advantage MEG has over fMRI is temporal resolution. This allows map-
ping of the dynamics of intrinsic connectivity networks at faster time scales. For exam-
ple, this approach has been useful for exploring the expression of connectivity in these
networks in the time domain, and for elucidating sequential transitions between relative
dominance of specific intrinsic connectivity networks (Baker et al. 2014). For example,
it has been observed that it is much more likely for there to be a transition between a
default mode network (DMN) dominant state and the predominance of another intrin-
sic connectivity network than it is to transition directly between two non-DMN resting
state networks, and that these internetwork transitions primarily involve inter-regional
amplitude correlations in the beta frequency range (de Pasquale et al. 2012). This could be
interpreted as indicating that the DMN serves to shift the pattern of inter-regional com-
munication of the brain between different functional states. For example, beta-amplitude
correlations involving the DMN could mediate transitions between a motor-focused state
supported by the motor network and a spatial attention-focused state supported by the
dorsal attention network. Another advantage conferred by the millisecond timing accu-
racy of MEG network mapping is the ability to determine that certain networks, such as
the motor network, may actually be comprised of a larger number of subnetworks that
serially express periods of relative predominance (O’Neill et al. 2015). Notably, expres-
sion of local neuromagnetic spectral power has been shown to have clinical utility for
detecting and characterizing conditions such as mild traumatic brain injury (Huang et al.
2014). Recent observations that inter-regional amplitude correlations are altered in mild
traumatic brain injury and associated with cognitive and affective symptoms in this group
(Dunkley et al. 2015) buttresses the hope that this type of connectivity measure may also
hold future clinical applicability.
oscillations at lower frequencies (Fries 2009). Phase and amplitude should not be viewed
as independent in this context, however, as inter-regional correlations in cross-frequency
phase amplitude coupling in spontaneous MEG has also been shown to correspond to
resting-state networks first identified using fMRI (Florin and Baillet 2015).
Spontaneous neuromagnetic phase locking has been particularly successful for cap-
turing atypical connectivity in neurological and neuropsychiatric populations, adding
to the emerging network perspective on neurological disorders (Stam 2014), and add-
ing credence to the notion that brain oscillations and their coherence may constitute a
type of neural syntax for information processing and communication that is critical for
understanding the brain basis for psychiatric disorders (Buzsáki and Watson 2012). For
example, it has been shown that resting-state MEG synchrony is altered in post-traumatic
stress disorder (Dunkley et al. 2014). Source mapping of such atypical neural synchrony
has demonstrated that such altered neural synchrony prominently involves areas such
as amygdala and hippocampus, and is associated with symptom severity as well as asso-
ciated cognitive and affective sequelae (Dunkley et al. 2014). An exhaustive review of
atypical resting MEG phase synchrony is too long for the present chapter, but it appears to
be relevant for a broad array of conditions including neurodegenerative diseases such as
Alzheimer’s disease (de Haan et al. 2012), movement disorders such as Parkinson’s disease
(Berendse & Stam 2007), and epilepsy (Elshahabi et al. 2015), suggesting that such mea-
sures are tapping a fundamental aspect of neuronal communication and its disruptions
in brain disorders.
Electroencephalographic research using a large sample has demonstrated reorganiza-
tion of spontaneous network phase synchrony during child development (Boersma et al.
2011). Clinical child populations have been shown to express characteristic alterations in
spontaneous MEG synchrony. Children with dyslexia have been shown to exhibit atypi-
cal neural synchrony, which was also shown to be associated with language difficulties
(Dimitriadis et al. 2013). Frequency-and network-specific resting neuromagnetic phase
synchrony have been reported in adolescents with autism (Ye et al. 2014), and altered
MEG synchrony has also been reported autistic children (Kikuchi et al. 2015). Such alter-
ations of inter-regional MEG synchrony have been related to autistic symptomatology
(Kitzbichler et al. 2015). Spontaneous MEG synchrony has been shown to be reduced in
school-age children born very preterm across multiple physiologically relevant frequency
ranges (Ye et al. 2015), which may be related to well-characterized alterations in white
matter development in this group (Pannek et al. 2014).
repositories more explicitly focused on MEG such as “OMEGA” will also help to provide
large samples of MEG data collected across multiple centers (Niso et al. 2016). Hope is
increasing that big data in neuroimaging, combined with techniques such as machine
learning, will provide new translational opportunities for diagnosis and predicting treat-
ment response with sufficient sensitivity and specificity to enable translation (Deco and
Kringelbach 2014). Major future trends in resting MEG network mapping will likely
include mapping normative networks, their development and relation to function,
together with how such refined population data could be used for detection of neural
network abnormalities and to guide treatment and rehabilitation for those suffering from
disorders of the brain.
(electromyography (EMG)) (Fitzgibbon et al. 2016). Thus, EEG is becoming a cleaner
neuroimaging technique that can begin to approach the more expensive fMRI and MEG
results, but more flexibly and at much less expense.
Second, the fast time scale at which EEG can be recorded allows the analysis of
moment-to-moment dynamics in the neural networks that support cognition, emotion,
and behavior. Two currently available techniques are especially useful in this regard.
Various synchronization indices are available to measure phase synchronization of oscil-
latory neural activity. The first evidence of neural oscillations recorded by EEG was the
alpha wave (around 10 Hz; Berger 1929). Since then oscillatory activity in several fre-
quency bands has been closely associated with perceptual and cognitive processes (e.g.,
Varela, et al. 2001; Ward L.M. 2003). Phase synchronization between oscillations at the
same or different frequencies is an indication of functional coupling between the brain
areas generating the oscillations. Although the most direct evidence for such functional
coupling comes from studies with implanted electrodes (e.g., Lewis et al. 2016), EEG data
treated with advanced analysis techniques can also detect transient functional connectiv-
ity between neural sources at fast time scales of tens of milliseconds (e.g., Doesburg et al.
2009; Bedo et al. 2014) (Figure 2.1). In addition, new techniques of measuring directed
information flow between oscillatory sources, such as transfer entropy (Schreiber 2000;
Vicente et al. 2011; Wibral et al. 2011) and phase transfer entropy (Lobier et al. 2014), can
actually allow us to make (weak, or Granger-type) causal inferences about interactions
between brain areas, for example, in reading (Bedo et al. 2014). Finally, when there are
competing network topologies or interaction models based on previous data, dynamic
causal modeling can be applied to choose the most useful model (Friston et al. 2003).
There are still significant limitations to be overcome, however. One of the most impor-
tant is the inability of EEG to visualize subcortical areas—MEG also is not good at this,
but fMRI does it well. Thus, it will be important to develop linkages between fMRI and
EEG/MEG results to allow inferences of fast dynamics from fMRI when subcortical brain
regions are heavily involved. This is especially important for the thalamus, which is impli-
cated in nearly every brain operation and network (Ward L.M. 2013). Another limita-
tion is the relatively low signal to noise ratio enjoyed by EEG. Measures to increase this,
such as ICA, have been successful, but still more is needed. Synchronization and transfer
entropy analysis suffer particularly from this problem and new methods of filtering out
the noise are needed. But even given what is now available it should be possible to use
EEG both to characterize normal fast dynamics in neural networks, and to discover how
aberrations in these networks can lead to dysfunction. Of course, it will then be neces-
sary to decide what actions to take to ameliorate or rehabilitate these dysfunctions. The
neuroimaging techniques will help point to the necessary treatment foci, and they can
help assess whether the applied treatment has succeeded. But they will not answer the dif-
ficult ethical problems given rise to by the knowledge of the source or extent or cause of
a brain dysfunction, especially if treatment is expensive, risky, or impossible. This is par-
ticularly true for EEG-facilitated discoveries of residual functions, and even indications
29
0–100 100–200 200–300 300–400 400–500 500–600 600–700 700–800 800–900
theta
(c) Theta
Transfer
Entropy (vOT)
(d) Gamma
PLVs
(All ROIs)
(e) Gamma
PLVs (vOT)
(e) Gamma
Transfer
Entropy
(vOT)
gamma
Figure 2.1 (See also color plate section.) Example of dynamic EEG synchronization and transfer entropy results from a word reading task. Synchronization
was measured with phase locking value (PLV), and narrow band transfer entropy was measured using an adaptation of the Kullback entropy (for vOT
to/from other areas only). Theta band is 3–7 Hz and gamma band is 35–45 Hz. Black lines (arrows) indicate significant interaction (directed information
flow) between the connected reading-related brain areas during the time period (ms after stimulus presentation) indicated at the top of the figure. vOT
indicates ventral occipital-temporal brain region, the putative word-form area.
Reproduced from Bedo N, Ribary U, and Ward LM. (2014) ‘Fast dynamics of cortical functional and effective connectivity during word reading’, PLoS ONE, Volume 9, Issue 2, e88940,
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0088940, Copyright © 2014 Bedo et al. Reproduced under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Version 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0), https://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
30 3
ASSR testing had a noteworthy caveat; artifactual responses could be elicited at high
sound intensities. This would lead to falsely indicating that individuals with profound
sensorineural hearing loss had residual hearing. In other words, ASSRs would show
residual hearing in individuals who were known to have no residual hearing. Although
ASSR testing is not recommended currently for diagnostic hearing threshold testing
in infants, enough basic and clinical research was conducted to provide evidence for
its use as a tertiary-stage hearing screening tool. In addition, research is continuing
to identify other potential clinical uses of ASSR in evaluating hearing functions (see
Picton 2011, pp.320–325).
Neurological ABR testing is another auditory ERP method that is used clinically to
screen for vestibular schwannomas (aka acoustic neuromas; Selters & Brackmann 1977;
see also Picton 2011, pp.500–505). Although neurological ABR testing is not a spatial
neuroimaging method for detecting tumors, it is a useful neuroimaging method for
detecting delayed or disrupted neural communication along the auditory pathway (i.e.,
between the cochlear nerve and brainstem nuclei). There are clear guidelines and norma-
tive data collected in non-clinical and clinical populations (Stockard et al. 1978; Chiappa
et al. 1979; Campbell et al. 1981). This evidence has informed researchers and clinicians
about the validity of ABR to screen for tumors and brainstem lesions along the audi-
tory pathway. Importantly, clinical research has clearly identified that the sensitivity and
specificity for neurological ABR in detecting 1–2 cm tumors are 90–100% and 60–75%,
respectively (see Picton 2011, p.503). Notably, this performance is based on large samples
of patients. The tumor-detection performance of the ABR led early researchers to rec-
ommend that it was a good screening tool for discriminating between individuals with
and without retrocochlear pathologies (e.g., vestibular schwannomas). As MRI became a
more prevalent neuroimaging tool and its diagnostic performance was to be superior to
ABR, MRI became the recommended tool for screening and diagnostics. However, the
financial expense of MRI precluded much of its use as a screening tool (until recently)
and when MRI is contraindicated in certain populations (e.g., patients with cardiac pace-
makers). Thus, neurological ABR is still routinely used as a screening tool before using
more expensive MRI diagnostic methods or when MRI is contraindicated. When MRI
testing is available, MRI screening is recommended over ABR screening because of the
added benefits of better sensitivity and better ability to identify the etiology of auditory
pathology (Fortnum et al. 2009). However, a current challenge for using MRI as a screen-
ing tool is that MRI testing facilities typically reside only in major urban areas, which
add barriers and costs to providing healthcare in rural communities. Neurological ABR
testing, on the other hand, is easily performed in any clinical setting with significantly less
expensive equipment as compared to a MRI scanner. Thus, screening in rural communi-
ties using neurological ABR and then referring patients for MRI testing in urban areas
can be more cost-effective and easier for the patients and healthcare system. The history
of basic and clinical research for using ABR and MRI to diagnose retrocochlear patholo-
gies highlights the importance of initial and continued validation of using neuroimaging
tools for clinical purposes (see Fortnum et al. 2009). This evidence inevitably reduces the
32 3
uncertainty that clinicians often face when making decisions about diagnoses, prognoses,
and management.
These brief historical accounts of using auditory ERPs showcase some of the basic prin-
ciples that are needed for recommending clinical uses of specific neuroimaging tools.
Some of the basic challenges to the tests are to determine (1) specific validity and reli-
ability relating to technical algorithms used; (2) diagnostic performances relating to the
applications on pathological subpopulations (e.g., sensitivity, specificity, predictive value);
and (3) cost-effectiveness and cost-utility (Medina et al. 2013, pp.3–18). The histories
of using auditory ERPs to diagnose hearing loss and screen for tumors are interesting
with respect to how neuroimaging can be used as tools for screening and diagnosing sen-
sory and neurological impairments. These histories are also a reminder of the diligence
required to sufficiently evaluate and validate neuroimaging tools in order to recommend
their use in healthcare at single-patient and population-based levels.
Validating the neuroimaging tools from a methodological point of view is essential
before recommending their use for clinical purposes. One major goal of methodological
research in neuroimaging is to improve our ability to confidently identify local and global
brain function. For example, we are investigating the reliability of specific neuroimag-
ing analyses to localize the neural generators underlying EEG and MEG and to identify-
ing the neural communication within the human brain. However, some recent caveats
have come to light that we are currently investigating and attempting to overcome. Here
we highlight one of the major challenges in neural communication analyses of EEG and
MEG data (aka functional connectivity analyses). We briefly present this research here to
illustrate the point that basic methodological research is highly important before using
tools for clinical purposes. A major challenge in functional connectivity analyses is mak-
ing sure that the brain regions (aka, sources) under investigation do not contain activity
from other brain regions because of the inherent physics of the neuroimaging measure
or the mathematics underlying its analyses, or both. When using some neuroimaging
tools and analyses, nearby (<20 mm) brain regions can contain a mixture of signals that
are separately generated from different brain regions. This is known as source mixing
and can lead to false conclusions regarding how these regions are functionally connected
and how they communicate information among themselves (Sekihara & Nagarajan 2015).
Traditional beamforming and minimum-norm source modeling methods (Van Veen &
Buckley 1988; Hamalainen & Ilmoniemi 1994; Van Veen et al. 1997; see also Sekihara &
Nagarajan 2015, figure 2) cannot avoid source mixing where neighboring sources will be
modeled to contain contributions of each other’s activity. Unfortunately, this source mix-
ing can generate deceptively false oscillatory phase-coherence between sources; thereby
causing misleadingly strong inter-source connectivities (i.e., type I errors). To overcome
this source-mixing challenge, different connectivity measures of phase-coherence (e.g.,
phase-lag index or imaginary-phase coherence) (Stam et al. 2007; Ewald et al. 2012;
Sekihara and Nagarajan 2015) have been suggested and implemented with some success.
However, these compensatory algorithms become increasingly blinded to identifying true
connectivities as inter-source phase differences approach zero (type II errors). Another
3
method to overcome the possible type I errors of source mixing is to average across many
participants. However, this often leads to type II errors or spatial smearing of the con-
nectivity maps because individual participant’s inter-source connection pairs usually do
not exactly line up spatially across participants brains. Moreover, providing personalized
healthcare would require neuroimaging tools to provide reliable connectivity maps at the
individual patient level, not at the population level. Overall, source mixing leads to tra-
ditional beamformers being less sensitive and less specific to detecting true functional
connections in local networks. Thus, to be able to confidently evaluate functional connec-
tivity among locally connected brain regions in individual patients, we need better tools
that minimize or negate source mixing (Figure 2.2).
Multiple constrained minimum- variance (MCMV) beamforming (Moiseev et al.
2011) is one such neuroimaging method that overcomes source mixing. The MCMV
beamformer technology mathematically constrains the sources to be independent of each
other; thereby, preventing source mixing (see Figure 2.2; for mathematical proofs and
methods see Moiseev et al. 2011 and 2013). Figure 2.3 demonstrates the ability of MCMV-
connectivity analyses to accurately resolve network connectivity in real EEG data by over-
coming source mixing among nearby brain regions. Phase-locking connectivity maps
(Lachaux e al. 1999) using traditional LCMV beamformers revealed significantly strong
alpha-band (9–10 Hz) synchronization (red lines) among nearby sources in the posterior
left visual network (Figure 2.3, left brain map). However, when analyzed using a MCMV
beamformer, the connectivity map for these nearby sources had significantly larger alpha-
band desynchronizations (blue lines; Figure 2.3, right brain map). The MCVM results in
Figure 2.3, are likely the more valid result because the EEG data analyzed were from a
visual discrimination task and from a post-stimulus interval (380 ms) where event-related
desynchronization in the scalp recordings occurred. In addition, this interval is well
known to contain event-related desynchronizations over occipital scalp regions. Thus, it
is highly unlikely that the local visual network would be synchronized within this inter-
val as revealed by the traditional LCMV beamformer. Therefore, the LCMV connectivity
map on the left is likely showing false synchronizations among nearby posterior visual
sources due to source mixing. Given the advantage of MCMV beamforming not having
source mixing, we can now be more confident that our results of local functional connec-
tions represent the true underlying functional connectivity. By combining MCMV beam-
forming with functional connectivity measures (such as phase-locking values (Lachaux
et al. 1999)), we can significantly enhance our ability to image local and global network
connections. This will further improve the validity of our results obtained from network
graph-theory analysis (Sporns 2003). Overall, thoroughly investigating and validating our
methods will enhance our ability to accurately represent the local and global network
dynamics underlying the EEG and MEG recorded from individual patients.
This brief overview of ABR testing provided examples of how basic research has pro-
vided suitable evidence for using neuroimaging tools for clinical purposes. In addition,
continued research in validating neuroimaging analyses (such as source modeling meth-
ods) is essential so that we can obtain the most confident and accurate depiction of brain
34
Source waveforms Fast-Fourier Transform
Anterior 25
LCMV
Source Amplitude
50 20 MCMV
Amplitude |y(f)|
16-Hz Mixing
(nAmp)
15
0
10
–50 5
0
0 50 100 150 200 0 10 20 30 40 50 60
Time (ms) Frequency (Hz)
25
LCMV
50 20
Amplitude |y(f)|
MCMV
Amplitude
(nAmp) 15 36-Hz Mixing
0
10
–50 5
LH RH 0
Posterior
0 50 100 150 200 0 10 20 30 40 50 60
Time (ms) Frequency (Hz)
Figure 2.2 (See also color plate section.) EEG localization and connectivity accuracy. Left panel shows a simulated source location (blue square) that
had only a 16-Hz oscillation and a neighboring (within 15 mm) source location (red square) that had only a 36-Hz oscillation. Source mixing of 16-
and 36-Hz oscillations were clearly visible in the traditional beamformer (LCMV) reconstructed source waveforms (blue and red lines; middle panel).
Amplitude spectra (right panels) showed that both red and blue LCMV sources contained energies at 16 and 36 Hz (i.e., source mixing). Because of
this source mixing, phase-coherence between the sources existed and functional connectivity was falsely revealed (green line; left panel). Our MCMV
beamformer (black lines), however, prevented source mixing. MCMV sources only had 16-Hz (lower panels’ black lines) or 36-Hz oscillations (upper
panels’ black lines). Obviously, false-connections were not found for the MCMV beamformer.
3
35
Anterior
LH RH
Figure 2.3 (See also color plate section.) Challenge in EEG connectivity maps. Traditional LCMV-
beamformer connectivity map (left) for alpha-band (9–10 Hz) revealed highly synchronized (red
lines) local couplings in visual cortices at 380 ms after letter onset. However, MCMV-beamformer
connectivity map (right) revealed strongly desynchronized (blue lines) couplings. The MCMV-
connectivity maps fit better with known event-related desynchronizations that occur after a visual
stimulus onset for this band and latency. Thus, the MCMV map is likely the real map.
function. It is imperative that basic and clinical researchers work together to provide cli-
nicians with strong evidence that validates new neuroimaging tools in order to improve
patient care.
(Van Veen et al.1997; Robinson & Vrba 1999; Sekihara & Nagarajan 2008), but similar
considerations apply to other methods. Technically, the original beamformer solution was
developed assuming that electromagnetic field registered by the sensor array is produced
by a single brain source of interest, plus noise. This is called a single-source beamformer
approach. Of course in reality even performing very simple tasks engages many brain
areas, and consequently many sources are simultaneously activated. It turned out though
that single-source beamformer, applied to each source individually, is still quite success-
ful in locating and reconstructing multiple active sources, as long as they are not too
close to each other and their correlations are negligible. However, if sources are close or
they are strongly synchronized, or both, localization accuracy and spatial resolution of
the beamformer degrades. Besides, reconstructed signals become contaminated with arti-
factual contributions from other brain areas. This phenomenon is called source leakage.
To overcome these problems, more advanced multisource beamforming methods were
developed (Dalal et al. 2006; Hui et al. 2010; Moiseev et al. 2011; Moiseev and Herdman
2013). In particular, these methods allow for strong interactions (correlations) between
the sources, and they take care of signal leakage by rejecting any direct contributions from
one reconstructed signal to another.
The next step is estimating connectivity between the brain signals. No matter which
one of many known measures of synchronization between signals is applied (Lachaux
et al. 1999; Palva & Palva 2012; Vinck et al. 2011; Schoffelen & Gross 2009), it is impor-
tant to ensure that such synchronization is not artificial, occurring, for example, due to
the common noise components in the signals, or due to the signal leakage. One possible
way to achieve that is to use connectivity measures that are insensitive to correlations
between signals, which have no time delay. Linear mixing due to leakage involves no
time delay; therefore, measures in question are immune to those artifacts. The flip side of
this approach is that these measures are almost insensitive to connections with time lags
that are small compared to the time period of the signal frequency. Consider an alpha
frequency, for example. Its period is around 100 ms, therefore in the alpha range, connec-
tions with physiologically feasible propagation delays of several or even 10–20 ms may
not be detected. An alternative way to exclude spurious connectivity due to linear mixing
is to eliminate the leakage at the very beginning—that is, at source reconstruction step. In
this case, a broader set of connectivity measures, including those sensitive to zero-delay
connections, can be applied. This is where the multisource beamformers become handy,
because direct leakage from one source to another is rejected.
The third step in the analyses consists of recognizing distinct groups of interacting brain
regions, or brain networks, based on the connectivity data. The difficulty here is that the
number of possible pairwise connections between different regions is usually very large,
while existence of each connection can only be established with certain probability (say,
95%)—in other words, involves statistical error. It follows then that some of the found
connections will be not real, occurring simply because of random fluctuations. For exam-
ple, suppose we consider locations corresponding to approximately 50 known Brodmann
areas. The number of possible pairwise connections between those is around 1200. If our
37
statistical error per connection is 5%, then around 5% of all detected connections—say,
50 or 60 connections—will be false, and there is no way to distinguish between the real
and spurious connections. The situation we described is called a “multiple-comparisons
problem” in statistics (Shafer 1995). There is no general way to overcome the multiple
comparison problem. Depending on specific situation, different approaches can be used.
Here we will just mention a few popular ones.
The most straightforward approach is to try to reduce the number of statistical tests
(comparisons) using prior knowledge. For example, if one can limit the number of brain
areas to look at from 50 to 5 based on neurophysiological considerations, the number of
pairwise connections will go down from approximately 1200 to 10. Then by limiting sta-
tistical error for each pair to 0.5%, one can guarantee with 95% certainty that all detected
connections are the true ones. When such reduction of the number of connections is not
possible, another useful approach is to apply statistical tests pertaining to (sub)networks
as a whole rather than to individual connections. For example, one can look at subsets,
or “clusters” of locations with mutual connectivity values above a certain threshold. The
probability of such a cluster to occur by chance can be estimated (Zalesky et al. 2010), and
if it is small enough, one can argue that the locations involved constitute a brain network.
This way, interconnected brain areas can be identified in spite of the curse of multiple
comparisons, even though it might be not possible to make conclusions about individual
pairwise connections within the network. Another method is to consider a set of areas
strongly connected to a single location (a seed point) to form a separate network (Brookes
et al. 2012). Yet another set of approaches involves representing a signal from each loca-
tion as a linear combination of a certain number of uncorrelated or statistically indepen-
dent components (so-called principal or independent component analysis). When any
such component mostly consists of contributions from a well-defined, distinct subset of
locations, one can argue that corresponding areas operate synchronously and constitute a
single network (Luckhoo et al. 2012; Whitman et al. 2016).
In summary, we discussed how the focus on interactions and connectivity within the
human brain affected MEG/EEG analyses of brain signals. We showed that new, more
sophisticated signal processing techniques were developed to deal with the new chal-
lenges. However, this journey is far from over, and we need more novel, even more
advanced techniques to emerge in this field in coming years to further improve the qual-
ity of brain connectivity analysis.
structure in such a way that fibrous tissue (e.g., white matter) shows a maximal rate of dif-
fusion along the direction of the fibers (Stejskal & Tanner 1965; Le Bihan & Breton 1985).
Uncovering these directions of maximal diffusion—and therefore the fiber directions—
requires the use of diffusion-sensitizing gradient pulses to sample diffusion along tens, or
even hundreds, of directions (as in high angular resolution diffusion imaging, e.g., Q-ball
imaging) (Tuch 2004). The result is a high-dimensional 3D image with a (fiber) orienta-
tion distribution function (Tournier et al. 2007) at each voxel—an image that is difficult
to manually examine and interpret.
Initial attempts to visualize dMRI datasets revolved around reducing their dimension-
ality to a single scalar-valued image by computing statistics across the sampled diffusion
directions. By computing the mean and variance in diffusion across the sample direc-
tions, we obtain the commonly used mean diffusivity (MD) and fractional anisotropy
(FA) measures (Figure 2.4a, b). The MD is sensitive to the amount of cell structure present
while the FA is sensitive to how fibrous the tissue is. It is also common to see the FA image
color-coded to show the directions of maximal diffusion, which approximate the fiber
directions (Figure 2.4c). Other scalar measures include radial, axial, and relative diffusiv-
ity; linear, planar, and sphericity measures; mode; and volume ratio (Westin et al. 2002).
Finally, it has also become customary to reduce the dimensionality of a dMRI dataset by
fitting models, at each voxel, to the sampled diffusion measurements. Through the use of
tensors (i.e., DTI) and spherical harmonics (SPHARM) (Basser et al. 1994: Jian & Vemuri
2007), we can reduce the dimensionality of a dMRI dataset, from the number of diffusion
samples to the much lower number of parameters of the model, thus facilitating visualiza-
tion (Figure 2.4d).
More recent work has looked at producing dMRI visualizations that highlight dif-
ferent geometric properties. For example, recent work has led to color visualizations
of dMRI datasets that match the perceptual differences in color to the real differences
in measured diffusion (Figure 2.4e) (Hamarneh et al. 2011). Other works have looked
at extracting regions of interest—usually axon bundles—from a dMRI scan through
the use of specially-designed structure detectors (Figure 2.4f) (Nand et al. 2011) or
segmentation techniques (Figure 2.4g) (Hamarneh & Hradsky 2006; Weldeselassie &
Hamarneh 2007; Booth & Hamarneh 2013). Similarly, those regions of interest can
also be detected through the use of image registration. By aligning two dMRI scans
and examining the differences in the image data at the level of individual voxels, we
can flag regions of interest where the scans differ (Figure 2.4h) (Smith et al. 2006;
Booth et al. 2016). In all of these techniques, the high-dimensional dMRI scan under-
goes multiple processing steps in order to generate the visualization. As a result, vari-
ous mathematical models have had to be extended to account for the dMRI’s high
dimensionality and to ensure that its measured diffusion values remain positive (Booth
& Hamarneh 2011a). Further, these processing and analysis techniques benefit from
pre-processing algorithms that remove imaging noise (Hamarneh & Hradsky 2007;
Nand et al. 2012) and ones that capture relations between neighboring voxels (Booth
& Hamarneh 2011b).
39
Figure 2.4 (See also color plate section.) Examples of visualizations associated with diffusion
MRI (dMRI) data. Some visualizations highlight the brain’s diffusion properties (a–e), while
others highlight its geometric properties (f–h), while still others highlight brain connectivity
(i–l). See the text for a description of each visualization technique: (a) mean diffusivity (MD);
(b) fractional anisotropy (FA); (c) color-coded FA; (d) ellipsoidal visualization of diffusion tensors;
(e) perceptual color visualization of diffusion tensors; (f) tubular structure detection in dMRI;
(g) dMRI segmentation of corpus callosum (above) and the cingulum (right), visualized in 2D and
3D respectively; (h) dMRI image difference overlaid on MD image; (i) streamline tractography;
(j) visualization of tract confidence regions; (k) a connectome visualized as a circular graph; (l) a
connectome overlaid on a brain silhouette.
The most appealing aspect of dMRI may be its unique ability to examine structural
connectivity within the brain. As dMRI can identify the direction of tissue fibers, in a
process called tractography (Mori & van Zijl 2002; Booth & Hamarneh 2012), we can
trace out 3D curves called streamlines that estimate the location of white matter axonal
40 4
Conclusion 41
neocortex, as well as information transfer between them (FitzGerald et al. 2013).
Strong commonalities in rhythmic network properties have been observed across
recording techniques and task demands, but strong neuroscientific theories to situate
such observations within a unified framework that has direct relevance to the explana-
tion of neuropathologies remain scarce.
Our recent comprehensive review into the animal and human literature indicates
a further thinking beyond synchrony and connectivity and the readiness for more
hypothesis-driven research and modeling toward unified principles of thalamocorti-
cal processing (Doesburg et al. 2015). We further introduced such a possible emerg-
ing framework: “the alpha-theta-gamma (ATG) switch.” We probed and introduced
this neurophysiological framework to explain how coordinated cross-frequency and
interregional oscillatory cortical dynamics may underlie typical and atypical brain
activation, and the formation of distributed functional ensembles supporting cortical
networks underpinning sensation and cognition (Doesburg et al. 2015). We also dis-
cussed evidence that alpha-theta-gamma dynamics emerging from thalamocortical and
cortico-cortical interactions may be implicated in cognition across diverse contexts,
and that the disruption of such processes is implicated in numerous neurological and
neuropsychiatric conditions. Moreover, this emerging framework further challenges
the dominant view in current neuroscience on the classical activation of the brain per
se and rather suggests an inhibitory induced dis-inhibition of intrinsic cortical activity
during sensory and cognitive processing, a novel plausible mechanism to integrating
local and large-scale brain networks and its related alterations in clinical pathologies
(Doesburg et al. 2015).
Such neuroscientific advances, emerging neurophysiological frameworks, and more
future hypothesis-driven basic and clinical research and modeling will pose further future
ethical challenges for the implementation of quantitative diagnostic and prognostic strat-
egies into clinical practice according to best practice and the highest ethical standards.
Conclusion
This comprehensive chapter, highlighting advances in multimodal brain imaging,
signal processing, and visualization from related expert perspectives, points to the
next necessary step in cognitive and clinical neuroscience brain imaging, namely to
more basic and clinical research and the quantification of the five-dimensional human
brain (across 3D space, frequency, and time) in health and disease. In this chapter, we
urge quantification of the biochemical, structural, functional, and dynamic network
connectivity and causality of the brain underlying typical/atypical sensory and cogni-
tive processing, to establish objective diagnostic neuromarkers for the identification
and better characterization of subtypes of neurological disabilities and pathologies.
In addition, we believe that it is essential to indicate new innovative ways of how
such subtypes can be selectively and optimally targeted with existing or addition-
ally modified neuroscience-based interventional training programs that exploit brain
42 4
Acknowledgments
The co-authors are listed in chronological order of their contributions: MacKay and
Rauscher (MRI), Tipper, Giaschi and Woodward (fMRI), Sossi (PET), Doesburg
(MEG), Ward (EEG-1), Herdmann (EEG-2), Moiseev (Signal Processing), Hamarneh
and Booth (Processing and Visualization), Ribary, Doesburg and Ward (Emerging
Neurophysiological Frameworks).
References
Baillet, S., Mosher, J.C., and Leahy, R.M. (2001). Electromagnetic brain mapping. IEEE Signal Process
Magazine, 18, 14–30.
Baker, A.P., Brookes, M.J., Rezek, I.A., et al. (2014). Fast transient networks in spontaneous human
brain activity. Elife, 3, e01867.
Bandettini, P.A., Wong, E.C., Hinks, R.S., Tikofsky, R.S., and Hyde, J.S. (1992). Time course EPI of
human brain function during task activation. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine, 25, 390–397.
Barth, M., Breuer, F., Koopmans, P.J., Norris, D.G., and Poser, B.A. (2016). Simultaneous multislice
(SMS) imaging techniques. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine, 75, 63–81.
Basser, P.J., Mattiello, J., and LeBihan, D. (1994). MR diffusion tensor spectroscopy and imaging.
Biophysical Journal, 66, 259–267.
Basser, P.J., Pajevic, S., Pierpaoli, C., Duda, J., and Aldroubi, A. (2000). In vivo fiber tractography using
DT-MRI data. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine, 44, 625–632.
Bassett, D.S., Wymbs, N.F., Porter, M.A., Mucha, P.J., Carlson, J.M., and Grafton, S.T. (2011).
Dynamic reconfiguration of human brain networks during learning. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 108, 7641–7646.
Beaty, R.E., Benedek, M., Silvia, P.J., and Schacter, D.L. (2015). Creative cognition and brain network
dynamics. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20, 87–95.
Beaulieu, C. (2002). The basis of anisotropic water diffusion in the nervous system—a technical review.
NMR in Biomedicine, 15, 435–455.
Bedo, N., Ribary, U., and Ward, L.M. (2014). Fast dynamics of cortical functional and effective
connectivity during word reading. PLoS One, 9(2), e88940.
Berendse, H.W. and Stam, C.J. (2007). Stage-dependent patterns of disturbed neural synchrony in
Parkinson’s disease. Parkinsonism & Related Disorders, 13(Suppl 3), S440–445.
Berger, H. (1929). Uber das elektrenkephalogramm des menschen. Archiv für Psychiatrie und
Nervenkrankheiten, 87, 527–570.
Betzel, R.F., Gu, S., Medaglia, J.D., Pasqualetti, F., and Bassett, D.S. (2016). Optimally controlling
the human connectome: the role of network topology. arXiv:1603.05261 [q-bio.NC]. Available
from: http://arxiv.org/abs/1603.05261 [accessed February 3, 2017].
43
References 43
Bilgic, B., Pfefferbaum, A., Rohlfing, T., Sullivan, E.V., and Adalsteinsson, E. (2011). MRI estimates
of brain iron concentration in normal aging using quantitative susceptibility mapping. NeuroImage,
59(3), 2625–2635.
Boersma, M., Smit, D.J., de Bie, H.M., et al. (2011). Network analysis of resting state EEG in the
developing young brain: structure comes with maturation. Human Brain Mapping, 32(3), 413–425.
Booth, B.G. and Hamarneh, G. (2011a, July). Consistent information content estimation for diffusion
tensor MR images. In Proceedings of IEEE International Conference on Healthcare Informatics,
Imaging and Systems Biology, HISB, 166–173.
Booth, B.G. and Hamarneh, G. (2011b, April). Exact integration of diffusion orientation distribution
functions for graph-based diffusion MRI analysis. In: Proceedings/IEEE International Symposium on
Biomedical Imaging: From Nano to Macro. IEEE International Symposium on Biomedical Imaging,
935–938.
Booth, B.G. and Hamarneh, G. (2012, January). Multi-region competitive tractography via graph-based
random walks. In: 2012 IEEE Workshop on Mathematical Methods in Biomedical Image Analysis
(MMBIA), 73–78.
Booth, B.G. and Hamarneh, G. (2013). A cross-sectional piecewise constant model for segmenting
highly curved fiber tracts in diffusion MR images. In: Mori, K., Sakuma, I., Sato, Y., Barillot, C., and
Navab, N. (Eds.) Medical Image Computing and Computer-Assisted Intervention –MICCAI 2013
(Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol. 8151), pp.469–476. New York: Springer.
Booth, B.G. and Hamarneh, G. (2015). Diffusion MRI for brain connectivity mapping and analysis.
In: Majumdar, A. and Ward, R.K. (Eds.) MRI: Physics, Image Reconstruction, and Analysis, pp.137–
171. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Booth, B.G., Miller, S.P., Brown, C.J., et al. (2016). STEAM—statistical template estimation for
abnormality mapping: a personalized DTI analysis technique with applications to the screening of
preterm infants. NeuroImage, 125, 705–723.
Borich, M.R., Mackay, A.L., Vavasour, I.M., Rauscher, A., and Boyd, L.A. (2013). Evaluation of white
matter myelin water fraction in chronic stroke. NeuroImage Clinical, 2, 569–580.
Brookes, M.J., Woolrich, M., Luckhoo, H., et al. (2011). Investigating the electrophysiological basis
of resting state networks using magnetoencephalography. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the United States of America, 108(40), 16783–16788.
Brookes, M.J., Liddle, E.B., Hale, J.R., et al. (2012a). Task induced modulation of neural oscillations in
electrophysiological brain networks. NeuroImage, 63(4), 1918–1930.
Brookes, M.J., Woolrich, M.W., and Barnes, G.R. (2012b). Measuring functional connectivity in
MEG: a multivariate approach insensitive to linear source leakage. NeuroImage, 63, 910–920.
Brown, C.J., Booth, B.G., and Hamarneh, G. (2013a, April). K-confidence: assessing uncertainty
in tractography using k optimal paths. In Proceedings of IEEE International Symposium on
Biomedical Imaging: From Nano to Macro. IEEE International Symposium on Biomedical Imaging,
250–253.
Brown, C.J., Booth, B.G., and Hamarneh, G. (2013b, January). Uncertainty in tractography via tract
confidence regions. In: Proceedings of Medical Image Computing and Computer-Assisted Intervention
Workshop on Computational Diffusion MRI (MICCAI CDMRI), 13–22.
Brown, C.J., Miller, S., Booth, B.G., et al. (2014). Structural network analysis of brain development in
young preterm neonates. NeuroImage, 101, 667–680.
Brown, C.J., Miller, S., Booth, B.G., et al. (2015, October). Prediction of motor function in very
preterm infants using connectome features and local synthetic instances. In: Proceedings of Medical
Image Computing and Computer Assisted Intervention (MICCAI) 2015, 9349, 69–76.
Buccino, G., Binkofski, F., Fink, G.R., et al. (2001). Action observation activates premotor and parietal
areas in a somatotopic manner: an fMRI study. European Journal of Neuroscience, 13, 400–404.
4 4
Bullmore, E.T. and Bassett, D.S. (2010). Brain graphs: graphical models of the human brain
connectome. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 7, 16–18.
Buzsáki, G. and Watson, B.O. (2012). Brain rhythms and neural syntax: implications for efficient coding
of cognitive content and neuropsychiatric disease. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, 14(4), 345–367.
Campbell, K.B., Picton, T.W., Wolfe, R.G., Maru, J., Baribeau-Braun, J., and Braun, C. (1981).
Auditory potentials. Sensus, 1, 21–31.
Chiappa, K.H., Gladstone, K.J., and Young, R.R. (1979). Brainstem auditory evoked responses: studies
of waveform variations in 50 normal human subjects. Archives of Neurology, 36, 81–87.
Coluccia, D., Fandino, J., Schwyzer, L., et al. (2014). First noninvasive thermal ablation of a brain tumor
with MR-guided focused ultrasound. Journal of Therapeutic Ultrasound, 2, 17.
Crawford, M.L. and Harwerth, R.S. (2004). Ocular dominance column width and contrast sensitivity in
monkeys reared with strabismus or anisometropia. Investigative Ophthalmology & Visual Science, 45,
3036–3042.
Cruse, D., Chennu, S., Chatelle, C., et al. (2011). Bedside detection of awareness in the vegetative
state: a cohort study. The Lancet, 378: 2088–2094.
Dalal, S., Sekihara, K., and Nagarajan, S. (2006). Modified beamformers for coherent source region
suppression. IEEE Transactions on Biomedical Engineering, 53, 1357–1363.
Decety, J. and Cacioppo, J. (2010). Frontiers in human neuroscience: the golden triangle and beyond.
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 767–771.
Deco, G. and Kringelbach, M.L. (2014). Great expectations: using whole-brain computational
connectomics for understanding neuropsychiatric disorders. Neuron, 84(5), 892–905.
DeHaan, W., van der Flier, W.M., Wang, H., Van Mieghem, P.F., Scheltens, P., and Stam, C.J. (2012).
Disruption of functional brain networks in Alzheimer’s disease: what can we learn from graph
spectral analysis of resting-state magnetoencephalography? Brain Connectivity, 2(2), 45–55.
Ding, K., Liu, Y., Yan, X., Lin, X., and Jiang, T. (2013). Altered functional connectivity of the primary
visual cortex in subjects with amblyopia. Neural Plasticity, 2013, 1–8.
Delorme, A., Palmer, J., Onton, J., Oostenveld, R., and Makeig, S. (2012). Independent EEG sources
are dipolar. PLoS One, 7, e30135.
DePasquale, F., Della Penna, S., Snyder, A.Z., et al. (2012). A cortical core for dynamic integration of
functional networks in the resting human brain. Neuron, 74(4), 753–64.
Dimitriadis, S.I., Laskaris, N.A., Simos, P.G., et al. (2013). Altered temporal correlations in resting-
state connectivity fluctuations in children with reading difficulties detected via MEG. NeuroImage,
83, 307–317.
Doesburg, S.M., Green, J.J., McDonald, J.J., and Ward, L.M. (2009). Rhythms of
consciousness: binocular rivalry reveals large-scale oscillatory network dynamics mediating visual
perception. PLoS One, 4(7), e6142.
Doesburg, S.M., Green, J.J., McDonald, J.J., and Ward, L.M. (2012). Theta modulation of inter-regional
gamma synchronization during auditory attention control. Brain Research, 1431, 77–85.
Doesburg, S.M., Ward, L.M., and Ribary, U. (2015). The alpha-theta-gamma (ATG) switch: toward
unified principles of cortical processing. Current Trends in Neurology, 9, 1–12.
Dunkley, B.T., Doesburg, S.M., Sedge, P.A., et al. (2014). Resting-state hippocampal connectivity
correlates with symptom severity in post-traumatic stress disorder. NeuroImage Clinical, 5, 377–384.
Dunkley, B.T., Da Costa, L., Bethune, A., et al. (2015). Low-frequency connectivity is associated with
mild traumatic brain injury. NeuroImage Clinical, 7, 611–621.
Duyn, J.H., Van Gelderen, B., Li, T.Q., de Zwart, J.A., Koretsky, A.P., and Fukunaga, M. (2007). High-
field MRI of Brain Cortical Substructure Based on Signal Phase. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences of the United States of America, 104, 11796–801.
45
References 45
Eberling, J.L., Dave, K.D., and Frasier, M.A. (2013). Alpha-synuclein imaging: a critical need for
Parkinson’s disease research. Journal of Parkinson’s Disease, 3, 565–567.
Elshahabi, A., Klamer, S., Sahib, A.K., Lerche, H., Braun, C., and Focke, N.K. (2015). Magneto-
encephalography reveals a widespread increase in network connectivity in idiopathic/genetic
generalized epilepsy. PLoS One, 10(9), e0138119.
Engel, A.K., Gerloff, C., Hilgetag, C.C., and Nolte, G. (2013). Intrinsic coupling modes: multiscale
interactions in ongoing brain activity. Neuron, 80(4), 867–886.
Ewald, A., Marzetti, L., Zappasodi, F., Meinecke, F.C., and Nolte, G. (2012). Estimating true brain
connectivity from EEG/MEG data invariant to linear and static transformations in sensor space.
NeuroImage, 60(1), 476–488.
Fitzgerald, T.H.B., Valentin, A., Selway, R., and Richardson, M.P. (2013). Cross-frequency coupling
within and between the human thalamus and neocortex. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 1–13.
Fitzgibbon, S.P., DeLosAngeles, D., Lewis, T.W., et al. (2016). Automatic determination of EMG-
contaminated components and validation of independent components analysis using EEG during
pharmacologic paralysis. Clinical Neurophysiology, 127, 1781–1793.
Florin, E. and Baillet, S. (2015). The brain’s resting-state activity is shaped by synchronized cross-
frequency coupling of neural oscillations. NeuroImage, 111, 26–35.
Fortnum, H., O’Nei, C., Taylor, R., et al. (2009). The role of magnetic resonance imaging in the
identification of suspected acoustic neuroma: a systematic review of clinical and cost effectiveness
and natural history. Health Technology Assessments, 13, 1–154.
Fox, M.D., Snyder, A.Z., Vincent, J.L., Corbetta, M., Van Essen, D.C., and Raichle, M.E. (2005). The
human brain is intrinsically organized into dynamic, anticorrelated functional networks. Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 102, 9673–9678.
Fries, P. (2009). Neuronal gamma-band synchronization as a fundamental process in cortical
computation. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 32, 209–224.
Fries, P. (2015). Rhythms for cognition: communication through coherence. Neuron, 88(1), 220–235.
Friston, K.J., Fletcher, P., Josephs, O., Holmes, A.P., Rugg, M.D., and Turner, R. (1998). Event-related
fMRI: characterizing differential responses. NeuroImage, 7, 30–40.
Friston, K.J., Harrison, L., and Penny, W. (2003). Dynamic causal modelling. NeuroImage, 19,
1273e1302.
Goodyear, B.G., Nicolle, D.A., and Menon, R.S. (2002). High resolution fMRI of ocular dominance
columns within the visual cortex of human amblyopes. Strabismus, 10, 129–136.
Grafton, S.T. and Hamilton, A.F. (2007). Evidence for a distributed hierarchy of action representation
in the brain. Human Movement Science, 26, 590–616.
Green, J.J., Doesburg, S.M., Ward, L.M., and McDonald, J.J. (2011). Electrical neuroimaging of
voluntary audio-spatial attention: evidence for a supramodal attention control network. Journal of
Neuroscience, 31(10), 3560–3564.
Grill-Spector, K., Henson, R., and Martin, A. (2006). Repetition and the brain: neural models of
stimulus-specific effects. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 14–23.
Guan, X., Xuan, M., Gu, Q., et al. (2016). Regionally progressive accumulation of iron in Parkinson’s
disease as measured by quantitative susceptibility mapping. NMR in Biomedicine. Advance online
publication. doi:10.1002/nbm.3489.
Hamalainen, M.S. and Ilmoniemi, R.J. (1994). Interpreting magnetic fields of the brain: Minimum
norm estimates. Medical & Biological Engineering & Computing, 32(1):35–42.
Hamarneh, G. and Hradsky, J. (2006, August). DTMRI segmentation using DT-snakes and DT-livewire.
In: Proceedings of IEEE International Symposium on Signal Processing and Information Technology
(IEEE ISSPIT), 513–518.
46 4
Hamarneh, G. and Hradsky, J. (2007). Bilateral filtering of diffusion tensor magnetic resonance images.
IEEE Transactions on Image Processing, 16, 2463–2475.
Hamarneh, G., McIntosh, C., and Drew, M. (2011). Perception-based visualization of manifold-valued
medical images using distance-preserving dimensionality reduction. IEEE Transactions on Image
Processing, 30, 1314–1327.
Hermundstad, A.M., Bassett, D.S., Brown, K.S., et al. (2013). Structural foundations of resting-state
and task-based functional connectivity in the human brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the United States of America, 110, 6169–6174.
Hermundstad, A.M., Brown, K.S., Bassett, D.S., et al. (2014). Structurally-constrained relationships
between cognitive states in the human brain. PLoS Computational Biology, 10, e1003591.
Hipp, J.F., Hawellek, D.J., Corbetta, M., Siegel, M., and Engel, A.K. (2012). Large-scale cortical
correlation structure of spontaneous oscillatory activity. Nature Neuroscience, 15(6), 884–890.
Ho, C.S. and Giaschi, D.E. (2009). Low-and high-level motion perception deficits in anisometropic and
strabismic amblyopia: evidence from fMRI. Vision Research, 49, 2891–2901.
Ho, C.S., Paul, P., Asirvatham, A., Cavanagh, P., Cline, R., and Giaschi, D. (2006). Abnormal spatial
selection and tracking in children with amblyopia. Vision Research, 46, 3274–3283.
Holz, E.M., Glennon, M., Prendergast, K., andSauseng, P. (2010). Theta-gamma phase synchronization
during memory matching in visual working memory. NeuroImage, 67:331–343.
Huang, M.X., Nichols, S., Baker, D.G., et al. (2014). Single-subject-based whole-brain MEG slow-
wave imaging approach for detecting abnormality in patients with mild traumatic brain injury.
NeuroImage Clinical, 5, 109–119.
Hubel, D.H., Wiesel, T.N., and LeVay, S. (1977). Plasticity of ocular dominance columns in monkey
striate cortex. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 278, 377–409.
Hui, H.B., Pantazis, D., Bressler, S.L. and Leahy, R.M. (2010). Identifying true cortical interactions in
MEG using the nulling beamformer. NeuroImage, 49, 3161–3174.
Immordino-Yang, M.H. and Singh, V. (2013). Hippocampal contributions to the processing of social
emotions. Human Brain Mapping, 34, 945–955.
Jerbi, K., Ossandón, T., Hamamé, C.M., et al. (2009). Task-related gamma-band dynamics from
an intracerebral perspective: review and implications for surface EEG and MEG. Human Brain
Mapping, 30(6), 1758–1771.
Jian, B. and Vemuri, B.C. (2007). A unified computational framework for deconvolution to reconstruct
multiple fibers from diffusion weighted MRI. IEEE Transactions on Medical Image Analysis, 26,
1464–1471.
Jones, D.K. (2016). Diffusion MRI: Theory, Methods, and Applications. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Jones, D.K., Knösche, T.R., and Turner, R. (2013). White matter integrity, fiber count, and other
fallacies: the do’s and don’ts of diffusion MRI. NeuroImage, 73, 239–254.
Jurcoane, A., Choubey, B., Mitsieva, D., Muckli, L., and Sireteanu, R. (2009). Interocular transfer of
orientation-specific fMRI adaptation reveals amblyopia-related deficits in humans. Vision Research,
49, 1681–1692.
Kaiser, M. (2011). A tutorial in connectome analysis: Topological and spatial features of brain networks.
NeuroImage, 57, 892–907.
Kang, J., Gao, Y., Shi, F., Lalush, D.S., Lin, W., and Shen, D. (2015). Prediction of standard-dose
brain PET image by using MRI and low-dose brain [18F]FDG PET images. Medical Physics, 42,
5301–5309.
Kaplan, J.T., Gimbel, S.I., Dehghani, M., et al. (2016). Processing narratives concerning protected
values: a cross-cultural investigation of neural correlates. Cerebral Cortex. Advance online
publication. doi:10.1093/cercor/bhv325
47
References 47
Kikuchi, A., Takeda, A., Okamura, N., et al. (2010). In vivo visualization of alpha-synuclein deposition
by carbon-11-labelled 2-[2-(2-dimethylaminothiazol-5-yl)ethenyl]-6-[2-(fluoro)ethoxy]benzoxazole
positron emission tomography in multiple system atrophy. Brain, 133, 1772–1778.
Kiorpes, L. and McKee, S.P. (1999). Neural mechanisms underlying amblyopia. Current Opinion in
Neurobiology, 9, 480–486.
Kitzbichler, M.G., Khan, S., Ganesan, S., et al. (2015). Altered development and multifaceted band-
specific abnormalities of resting state networks in autism. Biological Psychiatry, 77(9), 794–804.
Klyuzhin, I.S., Gonzalez, M., Shahinfard, E., Vafai, N., and Sossi, V. (2016). Exploring the use of shape
and texture descriptors of positron emission tomography tracer distribution in imaging studies of
neurodegenerative disease. Journal of Cerebral Blood Flow & Metabolism, 36(6), 1122–1134.
Kwong, K.K., Belliveau, J.W., Chesler, D.A., et al. (1992). Dynamic magnetic resonance imaging of
human brain activity during primary sensory stimulation. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the United States of America, 89, 5675–5679.
Lachaux, J.P., Rodriguez, E., Martinerie, J., and Varela, F.J. (1999). Measuring phase synchrony in brain
signals. Human Brain Mapping, 8, 194–208.
Lang, D.J.M., Yip, E., MacKay, A.L., et al. (2014). 48 echo T2 myelin imaging of white matter in first-
episode schizophrenia: evidence for aberrant myelination. NeuroImage Clinical, 6, 408–414.
Larson-Prior, L.J., Oostenveld, R., Della Penna, S., et al. (2013). Adding dynamics to the Human
Connectome Project with MEG. NeuroImage, 80, 190–201.
Laule, C., Kozlowski, P., Leung, E., Li, D.K.B., MacKay, A.L., and Moore, G.R.W. (2008). Myelin
water imaging of multiple sclerosis at 7 T: correlations with histopathology. NeuroImage, 40,
1575–1580.
Lavigne, K.M., Metzak, P.D., and Woodward, T.S. (2015a). Functional brain networks underlying
detection and integration of disconfirmatory evidence. NeuroImage, 112, 138–151.
Lavigne, K.M., Rapin, L.A., Metzak, P.M., et al. (2015b). Left-dominant temporal-frontal hypercoupling
in schizophrenia patients with hallucinations during speech perception. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 41,
259–267.
LeBihan, D. and Breton, E. (1985). Imagerie de diffusion in vivo par résonance magnétique nucléaire.
Compte Rendus de l’Académie de Sciences Paris, 301, 1109–1112.
Lerner, Y., Hendler, T., Malach, R., et al. (2006). Selective fovea-related deprived activation in
retinotopic and high-order visual cortex of human amblyopes. NeuroImage, 33, 169–179.
Lewis, C.M., Bosman, C.A., Womelsdorf, T., and Fries, P. (2016). Stimulus-induced visual cortical
networks are recapitulated by spontaneous local and interareal synchronization. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 113, E606–E615.
Li, W., Wu, B., Batrachenko, A., et al. (2014). Differential developmental trajectories of magnetic
susceptibility in human brain gray and white matter over the lifespan. Human Brain Mapping, 35,
2698–2713.
Li, X., Coyle, D., Maguire, L., McGinnity, T.M., and Hess, R.F. (2011a). Long timescale fMRI neuronal
adaptation effects in human amblyopic cortex. PLoS ONE, 6, e26562.
Li, X., Mullen, K.T., Thompson, B., and Hess, R.F. (2011b). Effective connectivity anomalies in human
amblyopia. NeuroImage, 54, 505–516.
Li, X., Harrison, D.M., Liu, H., et al. (2015). Magnetic susceptibility contrast variations in multiple
sclerosis lesions. Journal of Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 43(2), 463–473.
Lin, X., Ding, K., Liu, Y., Yan, X., Song, S., and Jiang, T. (2012). Altered spontaneous activity in
anisometropic amblyopia subjects: revealed by resting-state fMRI. PLoS ONE, 7, e43373.
Liu, C., Wei, H., Gong, N.J., Cronin, M., Dibb, R., and Decker, K. (2015). Quantitative susceptibility
mapping: contrast mechanisms and clinical applications. Tomography: A Journal for Imaging
Research, 1, 3–17.
48 4
Liu, S., Cai, W., Pujol, S., et al. (2016). Cross-view neuroimage pattern analysis in Alzheimer’s disease
staging. Frontiers in Aging Neuroscience, 8, 23.
Llinás, R. and Ribary, U. (1993). Coherent 40-Hz oscillation characterizes dream state in humans.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 90, 2078–2081.
Llinás, R., Ribary, U., Jeanmonod, D., Kronberg, E., and Mitra, P.P. (1999). Thalamocortical
dysrhythmia: a neurological and neuropsychiatric syndrome characterized by
magnetoencephalography. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of
America, 96, 15222–15227.
Lobier, M., Siebenhühner, F., Palva, S., and Palva, J.M. (2014). Phase transfer entropy: A novel
phase-based measure for directed connectivity in networks coupled by oscillatory interactions.
NeuroImage, 85, 853–872.
Lodygensky, G.A., Marques, J.P., Maddage, R., et al. (2011). In vivo assessment of myelination by phase
imaging at high magnetic field. NeuroImage, 59(3), 1979–1987.
Logothetis, N.K., Pauls, J., Augath, M., Trinath, T., and Oeltermann, A. (2001). Neurophysiological
investigation of the basis of the fMRI signal. Nature, 412, 150–157.
Luckhoo, H., Hale, J.R., Stokes, M.G., et al. (2012). Inferring task-related networks using independent
component analysis in magnetoencephalography. NeuroImage, 62, 530–541.
MacDonald, M.E. and Frayne, R. (2015). Cerebrovascular MRI: a review of state-of-the-art approaches,
methods and techniques. NMR in Biomedicine, 28, 767–791.
MacKay, A., Whittall, K., Adler, J., Li, D., Paty, D., and Graeb, D. (1994). In vivo visualization of myelin
water in brain by magnetic resonance. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine, 31, 673–677.
Manogaran, P., Vavasour, I., Borich, M., et al. (2015). Corticospinal Tract Integrity Measured Using
Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation and Magnetic Resonance Imaging in Neuromyelitis Optica and
Multiple Sclerosis. Multiple Sclerosis. Basingstoke, England: Houndmills.
McCall, C., Tipper, C.M., Blascovich, J., and Grafton, S.T. (2012). Attitudes trigger motor behavior
through conditioned associations: neural and behavioral evidence. Social Cognitive and Affective
Neuroscience, 7, 841–849.
Medina, L.S., Balckmore, C.C., and Applegate, K.E. (2013). Evidence-based imaging: principles.
In: Medina, L.S., Balckmore, C.C., and Applegate, K.E. (Eds.) Evidence-Based Imaging: Improving
Quality in Patient Care. New York: Springer.
Metzak, P.D., Riley, J.D., Wang, L., Whitman, J.C., Ngan, E.T.C., and Woodward, T.S. (2012).
Decreased efficiency of task-positive and task-negative networks during working memory in
schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 38, 803–813.
Miskovic, V., Ma, X., Chou, C.A., et al. (2015). Developmental changes in spontaneous electrocortical
activity and network organization from early to late childhood. NeuroImage, 118, 237–247.
Moiseev, A. and Herdman, A. (2013). Multi-core beamformers: derivation, limitations and
improvements. NeuroImage, 71, 135–146.
Moiseev, A., Gaspar, J., Schneider, J., and Herdman, A. (2011). Application of multi-source minimum
variance beamformers for reconstruction of correlated neural activity. NeuroImage, 58, 481–496.
Mori, S. and van Zijl, P.C.M. (2002). Fiber tracking: principles and strategies—a technical review. NMR
in Biomedicine, 15, 468–480.
Muckli, L., Kieb, S., Tonhausen, N., Singer, W., Goebel, R., and Sireteanu, R. (2006). Cerebral
correlates of impaired grating perception in individual, psychophysically assessed human
amblyopes. Vision Research, 46, 506–526.
Mullen, T., Kothe, C., Chi, Y.M., et al. (2013, July). Real-Time Modeling and 3D visualization of Source
Dynamics and Connectivity Using Wearable EEG. Presented at the 35th Annual International
Conference of the IEEE EMBS Osaka, Japan.
49
References 49
Nand, K.K., Abugharbieh, R., Booth, B.G., and Hamarneh, G. (2011). Detecting structure in diffusion
tensor MR images. International Conference on Medical Image Computing and Computer-Assisted
Intervention, 14(Pt 2), 90–97.
Nand, K., Hamarneh, G., and Abugharbieh, R. (2012). Diffusion tensor image processing using
biquaternions. In: Proceedings of 9th IEEE International Symposium on Biomedical Imaging (ISBI)
2012, 538–541.
Nasrallah, F.A., Pagès, G., Kuchel, P.W., Golay, X., and Chuang, K.H. (2013). Imaging brain
deoxyglucose uptake and Metabolism by glucoCEST MRI. Journal of Cerebral Blood Flow and
Metabolism, 33, 1270–78.
Niso, G., Rogers, C., Moreau, J.T., et al. (2016). OMEGA: The Open MEG Archive. NeuroImage, 124(Pt
B), 1182–1187.
Ogawa, S., Tank, D.W., Menon, R., et al. (1992). Intrinsic signal changes accompanying sensory
stimulation: Functional brain mapping with magnetic resonance imaging. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 89, 5951–5955.
O’Neill, G.C., Bauer, M., Woolrich, M.W., et al. (2015). Dynamic recruitment of resting state sub-
networks. NeuroImage, 115, 85–95.
Oz, G., Alger, J.R., Barker, P.B., et al. (2014). Clinical proton MR spectroscopy in central nervous
system disorders. Radiology, 270, 658–679.
Palop, J.J., Chin, J., and Mucke, L. (2006). A network dysfunction perspective on neurodegenerative
diseases. Nature, 443, 768–773.
Palva, J.M. and Palva, S. (2012). Discovering oscillatory interaction networks with M/EEG: challenges
and breakthroughs. Trends in Cognitive Science, 16(4), 219–230.
Palva, J.M., Monto, S., Kulashekhar, S., and Palva, S. (2010). Neuronal synchrony reveals working
memory networks and predicts individual memory capacity. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the United States of America, 107, 7580–7585.
Pannek, K., Scheck, S.M., Colditz, P.B., Boyd, R.N., and Rose, S.E. (2014). Magnetic resonance
diffusion tractography of the preterm infant brain: a systematic review. Developmental Medicine &
Child Neurology, 56(2), 113–124.
Picton, T.W. (2011). Human Auditory Evoked Potentials. San Diego, CA: Plural Publishing Incorporated.
Poldrack, R.A. (2010). Mapping mental function to brain structure: how can cognitive neuroimaging
succeed? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 753–761.
Prasloski, T., Rauscher, A., MacKay, A.L., et al. (2012). Rapid whole cerebrum myelin water imaging
using a 3D GRASE sequence. NeuroImage, 63, 533–539.
Pruessmann, K.P., Weiger, M., Scheidegger, M.B., and Boesiger, P. (1999). SENSE: sensitivity encoding
for fast MRI. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine, 42, 952–962.
Raichle, M.E. (2015). The restless brain: how intrinsic activity organizes brain function. Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 370(1668), 20140172.
Rauscher, A., Sedlacik, J., Barth, M., Mentzel, H.J., and Reichenbach, J.R. (2005). Magnetic
susceptibility-weighted MR phase imaging of the human brain. AJNR. American Journal of
Neuroradiology, 26, 736–742.
Ribary, U., Doesburg, S.M., and Ward, L.M. (2014). Thalamocortical network dynamics: a
framework for typical/atypical cortical oscillations and connectivity. In: Supek, S. and Aine,
C.J. (Eds.) Magnetoencephalography—From Signals to Dynamic Cortical Networks, pp.429–450.
Heidelberg: Springer Verlag.
Robinson, S. and Vrba, J. (1999). Functional neuroimaging by synthetic aperture magnetometry (SAM).
In: Yoshimoto, Y. (Ed.) Recent Advances in Biomagnetism, pp.302–305. Sendai, Japan: Tohoku
University Press.
50 5
Rogers, B.P., Morgan, V.L., Newton, A.T., and Gore, J.C. (2007). Assessing functional connectivity in
the human brain by fMRI. Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 25, 1347–1357.
Ross, B.D., Bhattacharya, P., Wagner, S., Tran, T., and Sailasuta, N. (2010). Hyperpolarized
MR imaging: neurologic applications of hyperpolarized metabolism. American Journal of
Neuroradiology, 31, 24–33.
Rubinov, M. and Sporns, O. (2010). Complex network measures of brain connectivity: uses and
interpretations. NeuroImage, 52, 1059–1069.
Saggar, M., Vrticka, P., and Reiss, A.L. (2016). Understanding the influence of personality on dynamic
social gesture processing: an fMRI study. Neuropsychologia, 80, 71–78.
Sander, C.Y., Hooker, J.M., Catana, C., et al. (2013). Neurovascular coupling to D2/D3 dopamine
receptor occupancy using simultaneous PET/functional MRI. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences of the United States of America, 110, 11169–11174.
Sauseng, P., Klimesch, W., Gruber, W.R., and Birbaumer, N. (2008). Cross-frequency phase
synchronization: a brain mechanism of memory matching and attention. NeuroImage, 40, 308–317.
Schäfer, C.B., Morgan, B.R., Ye, A.X., Taylor, M.J., and Doesburg, S.M. (2014). Oscillations, networks,
and their development: MEG connectivity changes with age. Human Brain Mapping, 35(10),
5249–5261.
Schoffelen, J.M. and Gross, J. (2009). Source connectivity analysis with MEG and EEG. Human Brain
Mapping, 30, 1857–1865.
Schreiber, T. (2000). Measuring information transfer. Physical Review Letters, 85, 461e464.
Schweser, F., Deistung, A., Lehr, B.W., and Reichenbach, J.R. (2011). Quantitative imaging of intrinsic
magnetic tissue properties using MRI signal phase: an approach to in vivo brain iron metabolism?
NeuroImage, 54, 2789–2807.
Schweser, F., Deistung, A., and Reichenbach, J.R. (2016). Foundations of MRI phase imaging and
processing for quantitative susceptibility mapping (QSM). Zeitschrift Für Medizinische Physik,
26, 6–34.
Secen, J., Culham, J., Ho, C., and Giaschi, D. (2011). Neural correlates of the multiple-object tracking
deficit in amblyopia. Vision Research, 51, 2517–2527.
Sekihara, K. and Nagarajan, S. (2008). Adaptive Spatial filters For Electromagnetic Brain Imaging.
Berlin: Springer.
Sekihara, K. and Nagarajan, S.S. (2015). Electromagnetic Brain Imaging: A Bayesian Perspective.
Switzerland: Springer International Publishing.
Selters, W.A. and Brackmann, D.E. (1977). Acoustic tumor detection with brainstem electric response
audiometry. Archives of Otolaryngology, 103, 181–187.
Shafer, J.P. (1995). Multiple hypothesis testing. Annual Review of Psychology, 46, 561–584.
Shah, N.J., Worthoff, W.A., and Langen, K.J. (2016). Imaging of sodium in the brain: a brief review.
NMR in Biomedicine, 29, 162–174.
Smith, S.M., Jenkinson, M., Johansen-Berg, H., et al. (2006). Tract-based spatial statistics: voxelwise
analysis of multi-subject diffusion data, NeuroImage, 31, 1487–1505.
Spearman, C. (1904). The proof and measurement of association between two things. American Journal
of Psychology, 15, 72–101.
Spiegel, D.P., Byblow, W.D., Hess, R.F., and Thompson, B. (2013). Anodal transcranial direct current
stimulation transiently improves contrast sensitivity and normalizes visual cortex activation in
individuals with amblyopia. Neurorehabilitation and Neural Repair, 27, 760–769.
Sporns, O. (2003). Graph theory methods for the analysis of neural connectivity patterns. In: Kötter, R.
(Ed.) Neuroscience Databases: A Practical Guide, pp.171–185. New York: Springer US.
51
References 51
Sporns, O., Tononi, G., and Kötter, R. (2005). The human connectome: a structural description of the
human brain. PLoS Computational Biology, 1, e42.
Stam, C.J. (2014). Modern network science of neurological disorders. Nature Reviews Neuroscience,
15(10), 683–695.
Stam, C.J., Nolte, G., and Daffertshofer, A. (2007). Phase lag index: assessment of functional
connectivity from multi-channel EEG and MEG with diminished bias from common sources.
Human Brain Mapping, 28(11), 1178–1193.
Stejskal, E.O. and Tanner, J.E. (1965). Spin diffusion measurements: spin echoes in the presence of a
time-dependent field gradient. Journal of Chemical Physics, 42, 288–292.
Stockard, J.J., Stockard, J.E., and Sharbrough, F.W. (1978). Nonpathologic factors influencing
brainstem auditory-evoked potentials. American Journal of EEG Technology, 18, 177–193.
Tahmasian, M., Shao, J., Meng, C., et al. (2016). Based on the network degeneration
hypothesis: separating individual patients with different neurodegenerative syndromes in a
preliminary hybrid PET/MR Study. Journal of Nuclear Medicine, 57, 410–415.
Thompson, B., Villeneuve, M.Y., Casanova, C., and Hess, R.F. (2012). Abnormal cortical processing of
pattern motion in amblyopia: evidence from fMRI. NeuroImage, 60, 1307–1315.
Tipper, C.M., Handy, T.C., Giesbrecht, B., and Kingstone, A. (2008). Brain responses to biological
relevance. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20, 879–891.
Tipper, C.M., Signorini, G., and Grafton, S.T. (2015). Body language in the brain : constructing
meaning from expressive movement. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 9, 450.
Tournier, J.D., Calamante, F., and Connelly, A. (2007). Robust determination of the fibre orientation
distribution in diffusion MRI: non-negativity constrained super-resolved spherical deconvolution.
NeuroImage, 35, 1459–1472.
Tuch, D.S. (2004). Q-ball imaging. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine, 52, 1358–1372.
Uhlhaas, P.J., Pipa, G., Lima, B., et al. (2009). Neural synchrony in cortical networks: history, concept
and current status. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 3(17), 1–19.
Van Veen, B.D. and Buckley, K.M. (1988). Beamforming: a versatile approach to spatial filtering. IEEE
Transactions on Signal Processing, 5, 4–24.
Van Veen, B.D., van Drongelen, W., Yuchtman, M., and Suzuki, A. (1997). Localization of brain
electrical activity via linearly constrained minimum variance spatial filtering. IEEE Transactions on
Biomedical Engineering, 44, 867–880.
Varela, F., Lachaux, J.P., Rodriguez, E., and Martinerie, J. (2001). The brainweb: phase synchronization
and large-scale integration. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2(4), 229–239.
Varma, G., Duhamel, G., de Bazelaire, C., and Alsop, D.C. (2015). Magnetization transfer from
inhomogeneously broadened lines: a potential marker for myelin. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine,
73, 614–622.
Vavasour, I.M., Laule, C., Li, D.K.B., et al. (2009). Longitudinal changes in myelin water fraction in two
MS patients with active disease. Journal of the Neurological Sciences, 276, 49–53.
Vicente, R., Wibral, M., Lindner, M., and Pipa, G. (2011). Transfer entropy-a model-free measure of
effective connectivity for the neurosciences. Journal of Computational Neuroscience, 30, 45–67.
Villemagne, V.L. (2016). Amyloid imaging: past, present and future perspectives. Ageing Research
Reviews, 30, 95–106.
Villemagne, V.L., Fodero-Tavoletti, M.T., Masters, C.L., and Rowe, C.C. (2015). Tau imaging: early
progress and future directions. The Lancet Neurology, 14, 114–124.
Vinck, M., Oostenveld, R., van Wingerden, M., Battaglia, F., and Pennartz, C. (2011). An improved
index of phase-synchronization for electrophysiological data in the presence of volume-conduction,
noise and sample-size bias. NeuroImage, 55, 1548–1565.
52 5
Wang, H.E., Bénar, C.G., Quilichini, P.P., Friston, K.J., Jirsa, V.K., and Bernard, C. (2014). A
systematic framework for functional connectivity measures. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 8, 1–22.
Wang, T., Li, Q., Guo, M., et al. (2014). Abnormal functional connectivity density in children with
anisometropic amblyopia at resting-state. Brain Research, 1563, 41–51.
Wang, X.J. (2010). Neurophysiological and computational principles of cortical rhythms in cognition.
Physiological Reviews, 90, 1195–1268.
Wang, Y., Wang, Q., Haldar, J.P., et al. (2011). Quantification of increased cellularity during
inflammatory demyelination. Brain, 134, 3590–3601.
Ward, K.M., Aletras, A.H., and Balaban, R.S. (2000). A new class of contrast agents for MRI based on
proton chemical exchange dependent saturation transfer (CEST). Journal of Magnetic Resonance,
143, 79–87.
Ward, L.M. (2003). Synchronous neural oscillations and cognitive processes. Trends in Cognitive
Science, 7, 553–559.
Ward, L.M. (2013). The thalamus: gateway to the mind. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews Cognitive
Science, 4(6), 609–622
Weldeselassie, Y. and Hamarneh, G. (2007). DT-MRI segmentation using graph cuts. SPIE Medical
Imaging, 6512–1K, 1–9.
Westin, C.F., Maier, S.E., Mamata, H., Nabavi, A., Jolesz, F.A., and Kikinis, R. (2002). Processing and
visualization for diffusion tensor MRI. Medical Image Analysis, 6, 93–108.
Whitman, J.C., Takane, Y., Cheung, T.P.L., et al. (2016). Acceptance of evidence-supported hypotheses
generates a stronger signal from an underlying functionally-connected network. NeuroImage, 127,
215–226.
Wibral, M., Rahm, B., Rieder, M., Lindner, M., Vicente, R., and Kaiser, J. (2011). Transfer entropy in
magnetoencephalographic data: quantifying information flow in cortical and cerebellar networks.
Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 105, 80–97.
Wiggermann, V., Torres, E.H., Vavasour, I.M., et al. (2013). Magnetic resonance frequency shifts
during acute MS lesion formation. Neurology, 81, 211–218.
Wong, A.M. (2012). New concepts concerning the neural mechanisms of amblyopia and their clinical
implications. Canadian Journal of Ophthalmology, 47, 399–409.
Woodward, T.S., Cairo, T.A., Ruff, C.C., Takane, Y., Hunter, M.A., and Ngan, E.T.C. (2006). Functional
connectivity reveals load dependent neural systems underlying encoding and maintenance in verbal
working memory. Neuroscience, 139, 317–325.
Woodward, T.S., Tipper, C., Leung, A., Lavigne, K.M., Sanford, N., and Metzak, P.D. (2015). Reduced
functional connectivity during controlled semantic integration in schizophrenia: a multivariate
approach. Human Brain Mapping, 36, 2949–2964.
Woodward, T.S., Leong, K., Sanford, N., Tipper, C.M., and Lavigne, K. M. (2016). Altered balance of
functional brain networks in schizophrenia. Psychiatry Research, 248, 94–104.
Wright, A.D., Jarrett, M., Vavasour, I., et al. (2016). Myelin water fraction is transiently reduced after
a single mild traumatic brain injury—a prospective cohort study in collegiate hockey players. PloS
One 11(2), e0150215.
Yang, C.I., Uang, M.L., Huang, J.C., Wan, Y.L., Tsai, R.J.F., Wai, Y.Y., and Liu, H.L. (2003). Functional
MRI of amblyopia before and after levodopa. Neuroscience Letters, 339, 49–52.
Ye, A.X., Leung, R.C., Schäfer, C.B., Taylor, M.J., and Doesburg, S.M. (2014). Atypical resting
synchrony in autism spectrum disorder. Human Brain Mapping, 35(12), 6049–6066.
Ye, A.X., AuCoin-Power, M., Taylor, M.J., and Doesburg, S.M. (2015). Disconnected neuromagnetic
networks in children born very preterm. NeuroImage Clinical, 9, 376–384.
53
References 53
Yoshinaga-Itano, C., Sedey, A.L., Coulter, D.K., and Mehl, A.L. (1998). Language of early-and later-
identified children with hearing loss. Pediatrics, 102, 1161–1171.
Yoshinaga-Itano, C., Coulter, D.K., and Thomson, V. (2000). The Colorado newborn hearing screening
project: effects on speech and language development for children with hearing loss. Journal of
Perinatology, 20(8 Pt 2), S132–137.
Zalesky, A., Fornitoa, A., and Bullmorec, E.T. (2010). Network-based statistic: Identifying differences
in brain networks. NeuroImage, 53, 1197–1207.
Zalesky, A., Fornito, A., Cocchi, L., Gollo, L.L., and Breakspear, M. (2014). Time-resolved resting-state
brain networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America,
111(28), 10341–10346.
Zhai, J., Chen, M., Liu, L., Zhao, X., Zhang, H., Luo, X., and Gao, J. (2013). Perceptual learning
treatment in patients with anisometropic amblyopia: a neuroimaging study. British Journal of
Ophthalmology, 97, 1420–1424.
54 5
Chapter 3
Introduction
Incidental findings (IFs) on neuroimaging are the subject of widespread debates, and with
the increase in use of imaging across research, clinical, and commercial sectors, there is
a pressing need to address knowledge gaps to inform the development of appropriate
strategies for their management.
Incidental findings may be defined as “observations of potential clinical significance
unexpectedly discovered in healthy subjects or in patients recruited to any imaging
research study, and unrelated to the purpose or variables of the study” (Illes et al.
2006). However, with the recent surge of interest in and experience of managing par-
ticipants with IFs, IFs can no longer be deemed unexpected, and should be antici-
pated (Medical Research Council & Wellcome Trust 2014; Bunnik & Vernooij 2016).
Instead, an IF may be defined as “a finding concerning an individual research par-
ticipant that has potential health or reproductive importance and is discovered in the
course of conducting research but is beyond the aims of the study” (Wolf et al. 2008).
The increasing use of imaging as a research tool, a clinical diagnostic tool, and within
the commercial sector increases the likelihood of detecting IFs, and necessitates the
development of a robust evidence base to inform policies for detecting, classifying,
and feeding back information on IFs to individuals, and evaluation of the feasibility
and impact of those policies.
In this chapter, we will describe the scale of the problem of IFs; summarize current
knowledge on the prevalence and determinants of prevalence of IFs, the impact of IFs on
key stakeholders, and the expectations of the public; and highlight gaps in the evidence
that will inform debates on the management of IFs. While we focus on IFs detected dur-
ing research imaging, we also highlight issues related to the management of IFs detected
during clinical and commercial imaging.
5
56 Incidental findings
1453 (48.4%) men) was 7.2% (217/3000), which rose almost by a factor of ten (68.7%,
2060/3000) on dedicated review of images to identify IFs. The lower prevalence in clinical
reports may partly be explained by a lack of reporting of nonserious IFs in clinical prac-
tice, such as diverticulosis (330/351 unreported), renal cysts (702/732 unreported), or
postsurgical appearances (13/16 unreported), but also lack of reporting of a smaller num-
ber of potentially clinically significant IFs that could be reasonably expected to be well
characterized, including abdominal aortic aneurysms (10/11 unreported), and enlarged
lymph nodes (36/38 unreported) (Quattrocchi et al. 2013).
58 Incidental findings
The difficulty of handling IFs of potential clinical significance is that lack of a firm
diagnosis is likely to prompt further investigations. There is limited reporting of system-
atic follow-up of participants with indeterminate IFs. At the very least, potential imaging
research participants should be made aware of the possibility of demonstrating an IF and
that further tests and referrals may be required to accurately characterize it (Illes et al.
2006, 2008). In the event that an IF is finally diagnosed as not clinically significant, in
retrospect, any follow-up that occurred may be deemed unnecessary. Such unnecessary
follow-up may have exposed the individual to harm, for example, through the use of ion-
izing radiation for further imaging, or an invasive procedure, without clinical benefit to
the individual. Unnecessary follow-up may also impact resources of individuals and soci-
ety, in terms of incurring costs of unnecessary healthcare, unnecessary use of healthcare
services, and time away from employment.
The clinical significance of some IFs is currently uncertain due to lack of data on their
natural history. A systematic review of the clinical significance of white matter hyper-
intensities found associations with risk of incident stroke in six studies of the general
population (hazard ratio 3.1, 95% CI 2.3–4.1) and with risk of incident dementia in three
studies of the general population (hazard ratio 2.9, 95% CI 1.3–6.3), leading the authors
to conclude that the identification of white matter hyperintensities should prompt assess-
ment for other risk factors for stroke and dementia in such individuals (Debette & Markus
2010). However, the methods of measuring white matter hyperintensities varied between
studies and risk of incident stroke and dementia with varying volumes was not presented.
Whether it is the presence versus absence, or a particular proportion of white matter
affected by hyperintensities that is associated with increased risk of incident disease
remains unclear. In addition, there is limited evidence of effective preventive therapies for
stroke and dementia in people with white matter hyperintensities. With further research,
judgment of the clinical significance of these and many other IFs is likely to evolve.
In contrast to lesions that can be detected by visual assessment of images, abnormali-
ties of brain tissue volumes, which require segmentation and computation, tend not to
be considered as IFs. Recent studies suggest an association between small hippocampal
volumes with a first episode of major depressive disorder (Cole et al. 2011), and with
genetic risk for Alzheimer disease (Lupton et al. 2016), but there is not enough evidence
yet to support advising assessment for depressive symptoms or cognitive impairment in
participants identified to have hippocampal volumes below a particular level. A small
hippocampal volume may not be readily apparent on visual assessment of images, and
measuring hippocampal volume seems to have a more “active” nature of seeking IFs com-
pared to visual assessment alone. However, it is not clear how performing measurements
on imaging to identify IFs differs from the act of, for example, calculating a cognitive test
score, on which a low score on a clinically validated instrument may also be deemed an
IF. Researchers should consider how to handle abnormal results generated by any data
collection activity or measure that may have clinical implications.
Further studies of the natural history of different IFs and robust evidence for benefits
of treatment are needed. In the meantime, for IFs in which the clinical significance and
59
Determinants of prevalence 59
Determinants of prevalence
With better understanding of the subject, imaging, and image reader characteristics that
affect prevalence of potentially serious IFs, better predictions will be possible about the
likely prevalence of IFs generated by newly planned studies. Such estimates could then
inform the design of appropriate consent materials and policies for detecting, classifying,
and feeding back IFs in imaging studies, which are now mandated by major funding bod-
ies including the Medical Research Council and the Wellcome Trust (Farrar & Savill 2014;
Medical Research Council & Wellcome Trust 2014).
Subject characteristics, such as age and sex, may affect the prevalence of IFs. Such char-
acteristics are selection criteria likely to be considered at study planning stage, therefore
data on the prevalence of IFs in different groups will inform future studies’ estimates
of the likely prevalence of IFs they will generate, and help them to design appropri-
ate consent materials and policies to handle IFs. Data from the Rotterdam Scan Study
participants show that the prevalence of asymptomatic brain infarcts increases with age,
from 30/750 (4.0%) in those aged 45–59, to 47/257 (18.3%) in those aged 75–97. Median
volume of white matter lesions also increased, from 1.8 mL in those aged 45–59 years,
3.1 mL in those aged 60–74 years, to 7.7 mL in those aged 75–97 years (Vernooij et al.
2007). In contrast, the prevalence of intracranial aneurysms did not differ significantly
between participants within these age groups (Vernooij et al. 2007).
The prevalence of IFs may vary between men and women. In the Lothian Birth Cohort,
brain imaging of 700 adults aged 73 years (SD 1.5 years) found that the prevalence of IFs
was higher in men (134/368, 36.4% of men versus 89/332, 26.8% of women, p = 0.007)
(Sandeman et al. 2013). However, these prevalence estimates include IFs that may not
be clinically significant, such as arachnoid cysts. Of 1113 consecutively imaged healthy
adults aged 22–84 years, no significant difference in distribution of men and women was
observed between groups with and those without IFs (Hoggard et al. 2009).
Less is known about the influence of imaging and imaging reader characteristics
on the prevalence of IFs. Sequences and combinations of sequences may influence
the perceptibility and characterization, and therefore the frequency and diagnostic
certainty, of IFs. T2-weighted sequences are helpful in distinguishing between solid
and liquid lesions, and the use of a contrast agent can make some lesions more con-
spicuous, or demonstrate the extent of a lesion more completely. The volume of tissue
coverage and the resolution of images will also likely increase the prevalence of IFs
60 6
60 Incidental findings
(Maxwell et al. 2015). In one study, there was no difference in the prevalence of IFs in
healthy volunteers imaged on a 1.5 T (31/374) compared to a 3.0 T (15/151, p = 0.6)
MRI scanner (Hoggard et al. 2009).
The effect of reader experience on the prevalence of IFs is not known. Reader expe-
rience is likely to affect prevalence for two reasons: first, perception of a demonstrable
lesion may increase with experience; second, interpretation of the clinical significance of
a demonstrated lesion may be more accurate by people with medical, or more specifically,
radiological training. For these reasons, it is natural to assume that consultant radiologists
would be the most appropriate readers of imaging for IFs, being doctors who are highly
trained in perception and interpretation of images. However, there is a lack of evidence
to inform this view. While radiologists may detect many IFs, the proportion of these that
turn out to be serious is not known, and the sensitivity and specificity of radiologists
for detecting potentially clinically serious IFs on nonoptimized, nondiagnostic-grade
research imaging is not known. Logistically, given the shortage of staff in clinical prac-
tice (The Royal College of Radiologists 2011), it is not feasible for radiologists to report
all research imaging, particularly now that much larger imaging studies are being con-
ducted. One solution may be a network of local reporting radiologists although, where
reported, there appears to have been limited uptake of such services by local researchers
(Cramer et al. 2011). While inexperienced readers may be expected to fail to perceive or
misinterpret some IFs, this is not always the case. For example, correct classification of
a set of 14 CT brain scans, performed in patients with suspected stroke documented in
the European Co-operative Acute Stroke Study trial book that details imaging findings as
normal or abnormal did not differ significantly between observers classed as experienced
(consultant neuroradiologists, consultant neurologists with an interest in stroke, consul-
tant stroke physicians), and those classed as inexperienced (consultant neurologists, gen-
eral practitioners, trainee physicians) (68% correctly classified compared to 63%, p = 0.3)
(Wardlaw et al. 1999). To date, there have been no published head-to-head comparisons
of detection of IFs, or those which are finally diagnosed as serious, between readers of
differing experience, such as trainee radiologists, radiographers, or nonmedically trained
scientists, to inform study policies on the detection of IFs.
Research is needed on participant, imaging, and reader- related determinants of
prevalence, to inform estimates of the likely prevalence of potentially serious IFs when
planning new neuroimaging studies. Such data could be generated from prespecified sub-
group analyses of participants, head-to-head comparisons between different neuroimag-
ing studies, or between different types of readers within the same study.
62 Incidental findings
with patient sex and family history, and experience of reporter (Sadatsafavi et al. 2010).
For example, imaging review by a nonspecialist, such as a nonmedical postdoctoral fel-
low, with confirmation or refutation of detected abnormalities by a radiologist, was not
deemed cost-effective (Sadatsafavi et al. 2010). However, decision analytical modeling
is limited by the availability of data to inform the model, and in this case the sensitivity
and specificity of detection of incidental aneurysms of a variety of sizes by a nonspecialist
reader was informed by expert opinion rather than empirical data.
It is extremely difficult to estimate the cost of follow-up and any cost-benefit of detect-
ing IFs given the variety of possible detected IFs, variation in clinical practice between
centers, necessity to tailor management to the patient, and differences in costs incurred
between countries and even between different institutions within those countries. The
magnitude of increase of service use and cost by people who receive feedback of an IF,
compared to people of similar age, sex, and comorbidities, might usefully inform our
understanding of the cost and service use impact on healthcare systems, but to our knowl-
edge, such comparisons have not been published.
The impact of IFs on a particular research study and on the wider scientific commu-
nity, in terms of cost of administering an IFs handling policy, and the impact on public
trust and involvement in research, is also unknown. Procedures for handling IFs vary
widely among research imaging centers (The Royal College of Radiologists 2011). Recent
guidance and funding bodies have forced researchers to develop policies to handle IFs
that must be submitted during the application for funding (Medical Research Council
& Wellcome Trust 2014). It is emphasized that such plans be appropriate, in terms of
time and cost (Medical Research Council & Wellcome Trust 2014), but there is currently
little guidance or training to assist researchers with the development and administration
of IFs policies (Wardlaw et al. 2015). Methods and descriptions of the results of current
policies for handling IFs have been published (Hegenscheid et al. 2013; Sandeman et al.
2013; Boutet et al. 2016), but head-to-head comparisons of different methods of handling
IFs, the time and cost they take to administer, and their impacts, have not. Appropriate
handling of IFs and clear communication with participants is particularly important for
longitudinal cohort studies, where attrition of the cohort could seriously bias the results
of research arising from the study. In the burgeoning era of big data and biobanking,
research data, including biobanked images, are generated for and are being used by sec-
ondary researchers, that is, those not involved in the process of the data collection. Such
“secondary research” on biobanked images may yield IFs, potentially some years after
the initial data collection. Researchers must consider how to handle IFs detected during
secondary research (Richardson & Cho 2012), and the implications for consent processes.
Biobank participants may give broad consent at the time of data collection for their bio-
banked data to be used for as-yet-unspecified future projects, or alternatively, participants
may be contacted to give repeat consent to use their biobanked data at the start of each
new project, so-called dynamic consent (Steinsbekk et al. 2013). Either way, the implica-
tions for participants and the financial and reputational costs to studies of detecting an IF
months or even years after imaging should be considered.
63
Public expectations 63
Future financial and reputational costs relating to IFs should be considered by any
research imaging study, not just biobanks. Months or years after imaging, participants
may be diagnosed with conditions and may return to study investigators wanting to
know whether those conditions were in fact visible on their research scan. While there
are no documented cases of this within the literature, the scenario is not unrealistic,
and in such a case a participant may seek legal action or financial compensation, or
both, for a clinically significant finding if it was deemed to have been missed on a
research scan.
To inform the design of future neuroimaging studies, further data are needed on the
impact of IFs, and how these may vary between different policies to handle IFs. Studies of
neuroimaging could build in robust data collection on the impact of IFs on a participant’s
emotional well-being, employment and finances, clinical follow-up, and final diagnoses
in order to generate evidence that will help inform future potential research participants’
consent. Data on the impact on health service use and cost of different policies of han-
dling IFs would inform future policymaking. It is in the interests of science that processes
for handling IFs are sensible, appropriate, and clearly communicated to potential and
actual research participants, and to their healthcare providers, in order to maintain trust
in and cooperation with researchers and the wider scientific community.
Public expectations
Maintaining trust in research is paramount as the progress of clinical science depends on
the participation of human volunteers. However, several studies show that participants’
expectations of research may be unrealistic, with research imaging being associated with
clinical diagnosis, and consequently raising expectations that such images will be assessed
by a competent, clinical professional (The Royal College of Radiologists 2011).
The National Child Development Study is a longitudinal cohort study of approximately
17,000 people born during 1 week of 1958 in England, Scotland, and Wales. In 2010,
133 of the participants living in and around Cambridge were invited to complete further
cognitive assessments, of whom assessments were conducted in 45 people, and of these,
7 had previously undergone MRI for clinical diagnosis, and none for research. A qualita-
tive interviewer explained the idea that taking part in a fMRI study “could reveal some-
thing that suggests that there could be a more serious problem […] in about one in 40
scans.” The researcher explained people may have different views on the feedback that
they would like or expect, and offered the 45 respondents five options: not to take part in
a fMRI research study; take part regardless of the provision or not of feedback; take part
only if all potential problems were fed back; take part only if serious, treatable problems
were fed back; or take part only if the study provided no feedback. Of 45 potential imag-
ing research participants, 40.9% reported that they would only participate in a study that
provided feedback on all IFs, with a minority (11.4%) responding that they would only
participate in a study that fed back only IFs that were considered serious and treatable
(Brown & Knight 2010).
64 6
64 Incidental findings
Findings were similar in participants who had already undergone neuroimaging for
research. Participants were invited to complete a web-based questionnaire about IFs
on neuroimaging if they had acted as healthy controls for fMRI research studies at one
of two imaging facilities in the United States. Over 90% of 104 respondents (mean age
25 years, 76/104 (73.1%) were undergraduate or postgraduate students) who had under-
gone research brain imaging wished to be informed of any IFs, regardless of its clinical
significance, and 94% wished to be informed by a member of the research team, and 54%
expected any abnormality present to be detected although 84% did not expect images to
be reviewed by a doctor (Kirschen et al. 2006). These expectations would be extremely
costly to meet, particularly in large studies, both in terms of researchers’ time and study
costs. Furthermore, given the range of the definition of IFs by some investigators to
include postsurgical appearances (Sandeman et al. 2013), and normal variants such as
cavum septum pellucidum (Lubman et al. 2002), this approach is likely to be of limited
benefit to participants. While many potential research participants might anticipate that
their research imaging would be reviewed by a competent professional, the provision
for review of images varies considerably throughout centers, ranging from full review of
images by radiologists, to no review of images by radiologists at all (The Royal College of
Radiologists 2011).
Members of the public perceive the benefits of receiving feedback on IFs to outweigh
potential disadvantages. Detecting a condition before symptoms arise is seen as advanta-
geous by potential research participants as it may allow early intervention, decision-making
around family planning, or prompt screening for conditions in relatives (Wellcome Trust
et al. 2012). This may be founded on the belief that to detect a disease before it becomes
symptomatic must confer a survival benefit, a concept introduced to the public domain by
widespread public health messages related to screening programs (McCaffery et al. 2016).
As discussed previously, research imaging is not a substitute for clinical assessment and
diagnostic imaging, therefore IFs demonstrated on research imaging may be incompletely
characterized, and may require clinical follow-up and generate anxiety. However, despite
considering that feedback of IFs may generate shock and worry, and that this may be
unnecessary if an IF turned out to be a false positive (i.e., a nonserious condition, artifact,
condition which turns out already to be known, or a finding which is not confirmed on
follow-up investigations), there remains overwhelming support from the UK public to
receive feedback on IFs (Wellcome Trust et al. 2012).
People who have health problems but are unable to afford healthcare within a private
healthcare system might view research as an opportunity to have a free scan (Wardlaw
et al. 2015). Not only would such participants be at risk of failing to understand consent,
researchers may find themselves handling more potentially serious IFs than expected.
A variation of “research tourism” may also exist within publicly funded healthcare sys-
tems, whereby participants may view research imaging either as a faster means to access
health services in order to investigate specific health concerns, or as an opportunity to gain
peace of mind, which would not warrant investigation within such publicly funded health
services (Townsend & Cox 2013). Within developing countries, participation in research
65
References 65
may be driven by either therapeutic misconception, defined as the mistaken belief by par-
ticipants that they are receiving clinical care, or in order to access treatments and health
services as ancillary care, whereby being a research participant enables them to access
free treatments or diagnostic services for problems unrelated to the purposes of the study
(Mfutso-Bengo et al. 2008). However, participants may also recognize the potential detri-
mental effects of receiving health-related information from research studies. For example,
research participants in private healthcare settings in the United States have raised con-
cerns that disclosure of results of genetic research may impact health insurance cover-
age (Murphy & Thompson 2009). To our knowledge, there are no data on the association
of participants’ motivation to take part in neuroimaging and prevalence of IFs, or direct
comparisons of the prevalence of IFs in studies performed within different healthcare sys-
tems. Researchers should consider participants’ existing access to healthcare and potential
motivations for participating in research when preparing information materials and when
obtaining consent and managing participants’ expectations about handling of IFs.
When developing policies for handling IFs, researchers should consider balancing fea-
sibility, in terms of cost and time of administration, with the potential impacts of IFs, and
with participants’ expectations. Such expectations may need to be managed during the
consent process, and evaluation of understanding consent is needed to ensure this process
is adequate.
Looking to the future
Despite the progress to date, difficult issues around handling IFs remain, due to the com-
plex and variable nature of IFs and the lack of robust, empirical data to inform practice.
The usefulness of current estimates of the prevalence of IFs on neuroimaging is limited
by variability in case definitions, methods of determining clinical significance, and lack
of information on natural history. Research on participant, imaging, and reader-related
determinants of prevalence are also needed to inform our understanding of the likely
prevalence of potentially serious IFs in any new neuroimaging study. Data are needed on
the extent of the impact of IFs on individuals, health services, and the scientific commu-
nity, and how impact may vary between different methods of handling IFs. Together, such
data would build an evidence base to inform the design of feasible policies for handling
and feeding back IFs that do not unduly encumber individual research studies or health
services and that are acceptable to the multiple stakeholders. Such an evidence base would
also facilitate informed consent of participants prior to participating in neuroimaging
research studies while managing their expectations and preserving public trust in medi-
cal research.
References
Agarwal, N., Gala, N.B., Choudhry, O.J., et al. (2014). Prevalence of asymptomatic incidental
aneurysms: a review of 2685 computed tomographic angiograms. World Neurosurgery, 82(6),
1086–1090.
6 6
66 Incidental findings
Alphs, H.H., Schwartz, B.S., Stewart, W.F., and Yousem, D.M. (2006). Findings on brain MRI
from research studies of occupational exposure to known neurotoxicants. American Journal of
Roentgenology, 187(4), 1043–1047.
Apold, V.S. and Downie, J. (2011). Bad news about bad news: the disclosure of risks to insurability in
research consent processes. Accountability in Research, 18(1), 31–44.
Booth, T.C., Jackson, A., Wardlaw, J.M., Taylor, S.A., and Waldman, A.D. (2010). Incidental findings
found in “healthy” volunteers during imaging performed for research: current legal and ethical
implications. British Journal of Radiology, 83(990), 456–465.
Boutet, C., Vassal, F., Celle, S., et al. (2016). Incidental findings on brain magnetic resonance imaging in
the elderly: the PROOF study. Brain Imaging and Behavior. Advance online publication. doi:10.1007/
s11682-016-9519-4
Brown, M.A. and Knight, H.M. (2010). Attitudes Towards Participating in fMRI Studies Amongst
Participants in a Birth Cohort Study. CLS Working Paper 2010/8. Available from: http://www.cls.ioe.
ac.uk/library-media/documents/CLS_WP_2010_8_.pdf [accessed January 30, 2017].
Bunnik, E.M. and Vernooij, M.W. (2016). Incidental findings in population imaging revisited. European
Journal of Epidemiology, 31(1), 1–4.
Cheung, K., Chan, D., Song, Y., et al. (2009). Prevalence and pattern of lumbar magnetic resonance
imaging changes in a population study of one thousand forty-three individuals. Spine, 34(9), 934–940.
Cieszanowski, A., Maj, E., Kulisiewicz, P., et al. (2014). Non-contrast-enhanced whole-body magnetic
resonance imaging in the general population: the incidence of abnormal findings in patients
50 years old and younger compared to older subjects. PLoS One, 9(9), e107840.
Cole, J., Costafreda, S.G., McGuffin, P., and Fu, C.H.Y. (2011). Hippocampal atrophy in first episode
depression: a meta-analysis of magnetic resonance imaging studies. Journal of Affective Disorders,
134(1–3), 483–487.
Cramer, S.C., Wu, J., Hanson, J.A., et al. (2011). A system for addressing incidental findings in
neuroimaging research. NeuroImage, 55(3), 1020–1023.
Deary, I.J., Gow, A.J., Taylor, M.D., et al. (2007). The Lothian Birth Cohort 1936: a study to examine
influences on cognitive ageing from age 11 to age 70 and beyond. BMC Geriatrics, 7, 28.
Debette, S. and Markus, H.S. (2010). The clinical importance of white matter hyperintensities on brain
magnetic resonance imaging: systematic review and meta-analysis. BMJ, 341, p. c3666.
Eskandary, H., Sabba, M., Khajehpour, F., and Eskandari, M. (2005). Incidental findings in brain
computed tomography scans of 3000 head trauma patients. Surgical Neurology, 63(6), 550–553.
Farrar, J. and Savill, J. (2014). UK funders’ framework for health-related findings in research. The
Lancet, 383(9933), 1954–1955.
German National Cohort (GNC) Consortium (2014). The German National Cohort: aims, study
design and organization. European Journal of Epidemiology, 29(5), 371–382.
Hegenscheid, K., Seipel, R., Schmidt, C.O., et al. (2013). Potentially relevant incidental findings on
research whole-body MRI in the general adult population: frequencies and management. European
Radiology, 23(3), 816–826.
Hoggard, N., Darwent, G., Capener, D., Wilkinson, I.D., and Griffiths, P.D. (2009). The high
incidence and bioethics of findings on magnetic resonance brain imaging of normal volunteers for
neuroscience research. Journal of Medical Ethics, 35(3), 194–199.
Ikram, M.A., van der Lugt, A., Niessen, W.J., et al. (2011). The Rotterdam Scan Study: design and
update up to 2012. European Journal of Epidemiology, 26(10), 811–824.
Illes, J., Kirschen, M.P., Edwards, E., et al. (2006). Incidental findings in brain imaging research.
Science, 311(5762), 783–784.
Illes, J., Kirschen, M.P., Edwards, E., et al. (2008). Practical approaches to incidental findings in brain
imaging research. Neurology, 70(5), 384–390.
67
References 67
Jaremko, J.L., MacMahon, P.J., Torriani, M., et al. (2012). Whole-body MRI in neurofibromatosis:
incidental findings and prevalence of scoliosis. Skeletal Radiology, 41(8), 917–923.
Kamath, S., Jain, N., Goyal, N., Mansour, R., and Mukherjee, K. (2009). Incidental findings on MRI of
the spine. Clinical Radiology, 64(4), 353–361.
Katzman, G.L., Dagher, A.P., and Patronas, N.J. (1999). Incidental findings on brain magnetic
resonance imaging from 1000 asymptomatic volunteers. JAMA, 282(1), 36–39.
Khandanpour, N., Hoggard, N., and Connolly, D.J. (2013). The role of MRI and CT of the brain in first
episodes of psychosis. Clinical Radiology, 68(3), 245–250.
Kirschen, M.P., Jaworska, A., and Illes, J. (2006). Subjects’ expectations in neuroimaging research.
Journal of Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 23(2), 205–209.
Koppelmans, V., Schagen, S.B., Poels, M.M., et al. (2011). Incidental findings on brain magnetic
resonance imaging in long-term survivors of breast cancer treated with adjuvant chemotherapy.
European Journal of Cancer, 47(17), 2531–2536.
Lubman, D.I., Velakoulis, D., McGorry, P.D., et al. (2002). Incidental radiological findings on brain
magnetic resonance imaging in first-episode psychosis and chronic schizophrenia. Acta Psychiatrica
Scandinavica, 106(5), 331–336.
Lupton, M.K., Strike, L., Hansell, N.K., et al. (2016). The effect of increased genetic risk for Alzheimer’s
disease on hippocampal and amygdala volume. Neurobiology of Aging, 40), 68–77.
Matthews, P.M. and Sudlow, C. (2015). The UK Biobank. Brain, 138(12), 3463–3465.
Maxwell, A.W.P., Keating, D.P., and Nickerson, J.P. (2015). Incidental abdominopelvic findings on
expanded field-of-view lumbar spinal MRI: frequency, clinical importance, and concordance
in interpretation by neuroimaging and body imaging radiologists. Clinical Radiology, 70(2),
161–167.
McCaffery, K.J., Jansen, J., Scherer, L.D., et al. (2016). Walking the tightrope: communicating
overdiagnosis in modern healthcare. BMJ, 352, p. i348.
Medical Research Council and Wellcome Trust (2014). Framework on the Feedback of Health-
Related Findings in Research. Available from: https://www.mrc.ac.uk/documents/pdf/mrc-
wellcome-trust-framework-on-the-feedback-of-health-related-findings-in-researchpdf/
[accessed January 30, 2017].
Mfutso-Bengo, J., Ndebele, P., Jumbe, V., et al. (2008). Why do individuals agree to enrol in clinical
trials? A qualitative study of health research participation in Blantyre, Malawi. Malawi Medical
Journal, 20(2), 37–41.
Milstein, A.C. (2008). Research malpractice and the issue of incidental findings. Journal of Law,
Medicine and Ethics, 36(2), 356–360.
Morris, Z., Whiteley, W.N., Longstreth, W.T., et al. (2009). Incidental findings on brain magnetic
resonance imaging: systematic review and meta-analysis. BMJ, 339, b3016.
Murphy, E. and Thompson, A. (2009). An exploration of attitudes among black Americans towards
psychiatric genetic research. Psychiatry, 72(2), 177–194.
Papanikolaou, V., Khan, M.H., and Keogh, I.J. (2010). Incidental findings on MRI scans of patients
presenting with audiovestibular symptoms. BMC Ear, Nose and Throat Disorders, 10, 6.
Park, H.-J., Jeon, Y.-H., Rho, M.-H., et al. (2011). Incidental findings of the lumbar spine at MRI
during herniated intervertebral disk disease evaluation. American Journal of Roentgenology, 196(5),
1151–1155.
Parker, J., Wolansky, L.J., Khatry, D., Geba, G.P., and Molfino, N.A. (2011). Brain magnetic resonance
imaging in adults with asthma. Contemporary Clinical Trials, 32(1), 86–89.
Powell, H.F. and Choa, D. (2010). Should all patients referred for magnetic resonance imaging scans
of their internal auditory meatus be followed up in ENT clinics? European Archives of Oto-Rhino-
Laryngology, 267(9), 1361–1366.
68 6
68 Incidental findings
Prince, M.R., Zhang, H., Zou, Z., Staron, R.B., and Brill, P.W. (2011). Incidence of immediate
gadolinium contrast media reactions. American Journal of Roentgenology, 196(2), W138–W143.
Proctor, R.D., Gawne-Cain, M.L., Eyles, J., Mitchell, T.E., and Batty, V.B. (2013). MRI during cochlear
implant assessment: should we image the whole brain? Cochlear Implants International, 14(1), 2–6.
Quattrocchi, C., Giona, A., Di Martino, A., et al. (2013). Extra-spinal incidental findings at lumbar
spine MRI in the general population: a large cohort study. Insights into Imaging, 4(3), 301–308.
Raeburn, S. (2002). Implications of genetic testing for the insurance industry: the UK example.
Community Genetics, 5(2), 102–109.
Randall, B., Kraus, K., Simard, M., and Couldwell, W. (2010). Cost of evaluation of patients with
pituitary incidentaloma. Pituitary, 13(4), 383–384.
Richardson, H.S. and Cho, M.K. (2012). Secondary researchers’ duties to return incidental findings and
individual research results: a partial-entrustment account. Genetics in Medicine, 14(4), 467–472.
Sadatsafavi, M., Marra, C., Li, D., and Illes, J. (2010). An ounce of prevention is worth a pound of
cure: a cost-effectiveness analysis of incidentally detected aneurysms in functional MRI research.
Value in Health, 13(6), 761–769.
Sandeman, E.M., Hernandez, M.D.C.V., Morris, Z., et al. (2013). Incidental findings on brain MR
imaging in older community-dwelling subjects are common but serious medical consequences are
rare: a cohort study. PLoS One, 8(8), e71467.
Schmidt, C.O., Hegenscheid, K., Erdmann, P., et al. (2013). Psychosocial consequences and severity
of disclosed incidental findings from whole-body MRI in a general population study. European
Radiology, 23(5), 1343–1351.
Smith, E.E., O’ Donnell, M., Dagenais, G., et al. (2015). Early cerebral small vessel disease and brain
volume, cognition, and gait. Annals of Neurology, 77(2), 251–261.
Steinsbekk, K.S., Kare Myskja, B., and Solberg, B. (2013). Broad consent versus dynamic consent in
biobank research: is passive participation an ethical problem? European Journal of Human Genetics,
21(9), 897–902.
Stephan, B.C.M., Tzourio, C., Auriacombe, S., et al. (2015). Usefulness of data from magnetic
resonance imaging to improve prediction of dementia: population based cohort study. BMJ, 350,
p. h2863.
Sudlow, C., Gallacher, J., Allen, N., et al. (2015). UK Biobank: an open access resource for identifying
the causes of a wide range of complex diseases of middle and old age. PLoS Medicine, 12(3),
e1001779.
The Royal College of Radiologists (2011). Management of Incidental Findings Detected During Research
Imaging. London: The Royal College of Radiologists.
Thomson, B. (1998). Time for reassessment of use of all medical information by UK insurers. The
Lancet, 352(9135), 1216–1218.
Townsend, A. and Cox, S.M. (2013). Accessing health services through the back door: a qualitative
interview study investigating reasons why people participate in health research in Canada. BMC
Medical Ethics, 14, 40.
Trufyn, J., Hill, M.D., Scott, J.N., et al. (2014). The prevalence of incidental findings in multiple
sclerosis patients. Canadian Journal of Neurological Sciences, 41(1), 49–52.
Vernooij, M.W., Ikram, M.A., Tanghe, H.L., et al. (2007). Incidental findings on brain MRI in the
general population. New England Journal of Medicine, 357(18), 1821–1828.
Wahlund, L.O., Agartz, I., Saaf, J., Wetterberg, L., and Marions, O. (1989). Magnetic resonance
tomography in psychiatry-clear benefits for health care services. Lakartidningen, 86(46),
3991–3994.
69
References 69
Wardlaw, J.M., Dorman, P.J., Lewis, S.C., and Sandercock, P.A. (1999). Can stroke physicians
and neuroradiologists identify signs of early cerebral infarction on CT? Journal of Neurology,
Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 67(5), 651–653.
Wardlaw, J.M., Bastin, M.E., Valdes Hernandez, M.C., et al. (2011). Brain aging, cognition in youth and
old age and vascular disease in the Lothian Birth Cohort 1936: rationale, design and methodology of
the imaging protocol. International Journal of Stroke, 6(6), 547–559.
Wardlaw, J.M., Davies, H., Booth, T.C., et al. (2015). Acting on incidental findings in research imaging.
BMJ, 351, h5190.
Wellcome Trust, Medical Research Council, and Opinion Leader (2012). Assessing Public Attitudes to
Health Related Findings in Research. London: Opinion Leader.
Winston, G.P., Micallef, C., Kendell, B.E., et al. (2013). The value of repeat neuroimaging for epilepsy at
a tertiary referral centre: 16 years of experience. Epilepsy Research, 105(3), 349–355.
Wolf, S.M., Lawrenz, F.P., Nelson, C.A., et al. (2008). Managing incidental findings in human
subjects research: analysis and recommendations. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 36(2),
219–248.
Zealley, I.A. (2015). Re: Incidental abdominopelvic findings on expanded field-of-view lumbar spinal
MRI: frequency, clinical importance, and concordance in interpretation by neuroimaging and body
imaging radiologists. Clinical Radiology, 70(6), 679.
70 7
Chapter 4
There is understandable anxiety about the nature of technology and its impacts on the lives
of young people. Over 90% of adolescents now use social media with a significant num-
ber using it on a regular basis and a marked subset reporting nearly constant connection
(Lenhart 2015). Prior to the development of social media and mobile technologies, television
and radio were triggers for similar waves of anxiety. It may be true that every new societal
technology change prompts concern for the impact on adolescents and young people. Much
of this might be traced to a developmental truism—that young people seek to differenti-
ate themselves from the prior generation. All children go through a phase of development
wherein they seek to establish themselves as autonomous individuals. One requisite to estab-
lish an individual’s identity is to differentiate and separate from other adults to whom an
individual has been connected up to this point in life. For most children, this process of
individuation involves creating separation from parents or guardians. Technology is often an
easy way to achieve this goal. Young people often claim a cultural space in new technology,
and this space can be difficult for parents and other adults to enter. Adults have less incentive
to use these spaces for their everyday needs as they have already established patterns of work,
communication, cultural meaning, and social interaction with their peers. Youth are not only
early adopters of technology for the desire to be in novel spaces, but also precisely due to the
fact that their parents and other adults are less likely to be on these media.
71
When I present talks on social media and adolescence, I often take an informal poll
of the providers in the room to see which platforms they prefer. Facebook, Twitter, and
Instagram often lead the current line-up. I then assure the audience that if they are on
these platforms their cool factor is likely diminishing and their youngsters are likely now
moving to Snapchat and other newer and more advanced media.
Nevertheless, there are certain heuristics that are useful in considering how adolescents
use new social media. One notion that is important to dispel is the traditional distinction
between “real” and “virtual.” For people who grew up prior to the advent of social media,
the separation between the real world—that space where they live, work, and have social
interactions—feels very different from the virtual world built within social media plat-
forms. For adolescents who have grown up in the period of an omnipresent social media
landscape, these worlds are not necessarily separate: they are continuous—the physical
world connecting with new social media in a rather seamless way. The communications
that they have in the presence of other people feel very much parallel to those online.
Hence, why it is easy to observe young people sending text messages and links to one
another while physically being in the same space.
One of the issues that youth, generally, are apt to not consider is that in the virtual space
people may not be who or what they seem. They see this space as a means to connect with
their peers and friends. As youth emerge from childhood which is traditionally in contact
with friends and family that are relatively narrowly circumscribed by their schools and
families’ social lives, they are then in a developmentally sensitive period of time where
they trust others around them to be like their prior contacts. The virtual space of social
media introduces the potential for people to represent themselves in an alternative way.
Briefly, they may not be who they say they are, and can instead create a character.
This fluidity of expression and projection of self presents a risk for adolescents in that
other adolescents or adults might pose as peers or age-appropriate friends online when
in fact they may be different. The stories of these types of behaviors have been told many
times in news stories across multiple platforms and need not be repeated here. The coun-
ter to this nefarious behavior is to give adolescents an opportunity to explore themselves.
Adolescents can alter and change their hobbies, interests, gender identity, and even claim
a different sexual orientation within the space of social media. Such exploration can hap-
pen under their own name or handle, or could be created with another pseudonym. While
individuals interacting with a somewhat fictionalized character might justifiably claim
that they are being misled, the youth projecting the character could be learning what their
choices might engender in terms of relationships, people, and connections. They may be
learning the types of people that share their interests and may be using the experience as
a chance for personal growth.
Clinically, I often liken virtual spaces for adolescents and young people to extensions of
their rooms. The computer or smartphone is a portal into their lives and their communi-
cation with others is often taking place in the privacy of their rooms or other unobserved
venues. This leads to a situation where young people often believe they have privacy and
in fact can interact in ways that expose them very publically. Social media creates a new
72 7
form of public space or commons. Many people believe that when they post text, video,
or photos that only their friends can see this. The degree to which these communiques
are limited to a small group is directly related to the degree to which privacy settings
have been enabled. For many adolescents, privacy is not a key concern, especially when
weighed against peer acceptance and social popularity. Hence, young people are more
likely to unknowingly take risks in the space and be unaware of the ways in which their
private information might be used or misused.
Digital literacy—the education and teaching about the ways that digital media work and
impact our lives—is an absent part of present educational practices. Society desperately
needs a pedagogical approach to digital culture that starts at an early age because we can
easily witness children as young as 2 or 3 years of age interacting with iPads and iPhones.
The data on the use of online social media and development of mental health problems
is a vexed area. While many popular commentators like the actor Wentworth Miller have
argued for a link between depression, suicide, and other behavioral problems, and the
online environment (Grant 2016), the academic research in this area is more subtle and
less clear. One of the few reviews of this literature concluded that the methods and time
lags for this field lead to an inability to draw conclusions on the direct impact of social
media on mental health (Pantic 2014). While the majority of studies reviewed did find
correlations between amount of time spent on social media and symptoms of depression,
low self-esteem, and online addiction, the directionality of these relationships is unclear.
A recent study by Lin and colleagues examined 1787 young adults and determined that
there appeared to be a relationship between the amount of social media use and degree of
depressive symptoms (Lin et al. 2016). Nevertheless, the authors were unable, using their
methodology, to assess the directionality of this effect. They speculate that there is a dose
relationship to this effect but a number of questions remain. For example, does use of
social media lead to mental health and behavioral issues or is the mental health problem
driving the youth toward social media use? Correlational studies are unable to assess the
directionality due to their cross-sectional nature. A set of longitudinal studies is needed
to better understand the nature of these relationships.
One issue that has emerged is cyberbullying. This form of bullying has become an issue
of deep concern for child mental health professionals (Sivashanker 2013) because of the
73
multiple impacts that it has on youth in terms of depression and suicidal ideation (Pham &
Adesman 2015; Mitchell et al. 2016; Ranney et al. 2016). In contrast to the broad impacts
of social media on mental health, the specific impact of cyberbullying has been well docu-
mented as being at least as potent as in-person bullying or even more toxic because of the
extent and remoteness of the attacks. In other words, while social media mitigates the
physical component of bullying, the psychological component may become more toxic
because of the frequency of attacks and the often relative isolation of the victim.
Cyberbullying of teens and adolescents emerges largely from the social context of edu-
cation and peer relationships. The study of social relationships in schools and the sociol-
ogy of education have been significant parts of the social science canon. The introduction
of social media has likely changed this milieu but it also offers a new opportunity to study
and understand adolescent social relationships. These connections or social networks
may be adaptive and promote self-esteem or resiliency, and they might also be maladap-
tive as in the case of cyberbullying.
Ethically, studying adolescent social relationships is hard. Traditionally, these youth can-
not provide consent because they lack adult decision-making capabilities. Most scholars
in this area are required to obtain informed consent from the parents or guardians of ado-
lescents, and then the adolescent may be allowed to opt out by virtue of an assent process.
The challenge arises in that the youth who are most at risk of, or being, victimized may
be the least likely to share their true experiences. As in the case outlined at the beginning
of this section, Debbie has yet to inform adults. Is there a scenario where she is going to
be willing to work with researchers who, depending on jurisdiction, may be required to
report the bullying to authorities? Such disclosure would require that her parents learn
about the ongoing issues. While this disclosure may be necessary and even therapeutic, the
researcher is caught in a dilemma of facing likely refusal from the teen and also failing to
capture the realities of what is happening in this context. Based on these structural issues,
studies of adolescence and social media likely overestimate positive outcomes and under-
estimate negative effects. This observation bias cannot be easily overcome under current
research ethics standards. Even anonymous online surveys that are used may suffer from
a degree of observation bias and they are likely at risk for other types of bias due to their
low response rates.
Youth with autism often face a variety of challenges. The core illness is character-
ized by difficulties in social communication, stereotypic or repetitive behaviors, lack
74 7
from her father who continues to refuse to acknowledge her new gender identity. She has been meet-
ing young men to date via a social networking profile. She practices safer sex inconsistently and is
often pressured by her partners to have unprotected sex. As her primary care physician, you are now
giving some consideration to prescribing pre-exposure prophylaxis to better protect her against HIV
transmission.
Lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender (LGBT) youth are a subgroup of adolescents
and young adults who deserve special attention. LGBT youth face multiple challenges
including rejection or violence in the coming out process, increased risk of mental health
and substance use disorders, and, depending on the LGBT subgroup, increased risk of
sexually transmitted infections (STIs).
Mustanski and colleagues have published a series of papers on the ethics of research
with LGBT youth (Mustanski 2011; Fisher & Mustanski 2014; Ybarra et al. 2016). They
generally argue that the health disparities facing these populations merit a change of
approach to ethical standards for considering studies in this area. They note multiple
challenges for investigators in this field including heightened perceptions of risk, cum-
bersome requirements for parental consent, and a lack of expertise concerning this pop-
ulation on IRBs.
Elements of Mustanski’s critique are accurate especially in regard to the lack of experi-
enced investigators in this subfield who are willing to serve on institutional review boards
(IRBs). The lack of knowledgeable researchers who are willing to expend time and effort
to serve on an IRB is likely a result of the small size of this field. In addition, Mustanski
accurately outlines why adolescents under the age of 18 would potentially be at greater
risk in the event of inadvertent disclosure to parents and others who may not be aware of
the youth’s sexual orientation or gender identity.
Mustanski’s analysis of risk estimation for LGBT youth is more problematic. He and
his colleagues argue in the absence of evidence that subjective estimates of suicide, sub-
stance use, and HIV/STI risks are overestimated and that most research should be con-
sidered minimal risk because of the techniques used by social and behavioral scientists.
The difficulty with this risk analysis is that it ignores several lines of research that indicate
higher risks of mental health issues, substance use, suicidality, and HIV/STI transmission.
In order to mitigate these risks, researchers need to develop clear assessment plans for
addressing mental health and substance use disorders. In regards to LGBT youth, it would
be prudent to involve clinicians who routinely work with patients. Many researchers have
clinical credentials but do not have active clinics or lead clinical teams. In the conduct of
research with LGBT youth, attention needs to be paid to providing care to patients when
the need is clear or the risks are high. This approach is more likely to create a safer pro-
tocol for LGBT youth, and also maximize the potential for advancement of the research
without having adverse events. Such an approach will likely also better address concerns
that IRBs may raise and serve to convince reviewers who only see risk, that the research
teams have protocols for working with these youth that acknowledge risks and address
them directly.
76 7
Homeless youth
Case scenario: Gene is a 15-year-old male who was kicked out of his home when he was age 13 and
announced to his family that he was gay. He ran away from his rural environment in a southern US
state and hitchhiked his way to Chicago. He lived on the streets for several months, and survived by
engaging in the sex trade and sex work. He would often sleep with people in exchange for a night in a
bed, and a shower. Some of these people would sometimes give him money, and he often found himself
using drugs with them, especially alcohol, marijuana, and methamphetamines. He comes to the home-
less drop-in shelter at times to meet with a case manager as he is hoping to get clean and go to college.
Homeless youth are a major social problem with estimates varying in the range of 1.6 to
2 million youth annually experiencing homelessness (Edidin et al. 2011). The social forces
that drive youth on to the streets include domestic violence, perceived LGBT identity, and
economic instability or poverty. All of the groups described earlier in this chapter includ-
ing youth with mental health issues, autistic youth, and LGBT youth are at disproportion-
ately higher risk of becoming homeless. Most homeless youth in the US come out of the
fractured foster care system where young people who turn age 18 “age-out” and are ineli-
gible to remain in their foster homes or receive ongoing state support. This transition has
been identified repeatedly as an ongoing source of homeless youth and small programs
have been established to stem this trend but none of these have achieved the growth and
coverage that are needed to reduce youth homelessness.
In this section I will review some of the homelessness research I have pursued with
an interdisciplinary team across three institutions. In this manner, I hope to highlight
practices we have developed or used to underpin our research from a strong ethically
informed perspective. Our research team has been working with homeless youth for
the past 7 years in Chicago and 2 years before that in San Francisco. We initially started
by chronicling the mental health and substance use challenges faced by this popula-
tion (Quimby et al. 2012; Castro et al. 2014). These studies demonstrated that this was
a population in high need. Our research also began to show that many homeless youth
use the Internet and social media at high rates (Goldberg et al. 2013). This finding was in
line with our colleague Eric Rice and his team’s findings in Los Angeles-based homeless
youth (Rice et al. 2011).
We sought to develop an intervention based on cell phones that would enable us to
better reach these youth and to intervene at an earlier time point. We discussed our proj-
ect with staff members at several of the community-based organizations with which we
have partnered with in the past, and also undertook some qualitative research to guide
our work (Goldberg et al. 2013). As we assembled our research protocol we initially
thought we would deliver a trauma-informed sleep intervention using cell phones that we
would give homeless youth. We then launched a series of five focus groups with shelter-
based youth (Kaiser et al. in press). The youth in the focus groups urged us to change the
approach to our study. They agreed that sleep and trauma are major issues but they felt
that their more pressing issues related to anxiety and depression. They advised us to direct
our treatment toward these symptoms.
7
Homeless youth 77
In the course of our protocol creation we heard questions from various individuals
about three issues including (1) distribution of high-quality smartphones, (2) appropri-
ate amount of compensation, and (3) monitoring youth using tracking software. First, we
opted to give these youth the best smartphones we could afford to buy or have donated.
This logic was challenged because many observers assume that homeless youth will use
any technology that is given or donated to them. Our experience was different in that
we discovered that homeless youth value the best and most current technology, and will
go to great lengths to direct funds that they get toward their phone or obtaining cell/
data time. The rationale is simple—when you lack a permanent physical address, a virtual
one is even more essential and important. Homeless youth live through their phones and
use them as means to search for resources, keep connected to friends and family, and to
entertain themselves. Thus, from our perspective, giving a high-quality smartphone was
an important part of our study.
Compensation for underserved or impoverished populations is always a point of con-
cern for review committees. The balance point is to give compensation that is not coer-
cive and yet acknowledges the time and effort that the youth put into working with our
research team. While our distribution of a smartphone and 6 months of data plan are a
major part of the compensation, we also knew that the measures we were asking youth to
complete for follow-up require time and effort on their part. We opted to give gift cards to
a local store where they could obtain food or clothing.
When considering compensation, there is also a justice issue that arises. It would be
ethically inappropriate to give an impoverished youth less compensation than a wealthier
youth who was participating in the same study or the same type of study. This issue arises
even though the power to coerce may be greater for the impoverished youth. One of the
issues that my team has debated repeatedly is how to value time in a research study that
is spent completing measures or other questionnaires. There is no easy answer and hence
why I have avoided specifying amounts—the answers to these questions will vary by the
study, the topics under investigation, the time required, and locality. We work closely with
our community-based partners to define appropriate compensation levels. We believe
that it is important to repeatedly visit these issues, and consider them at regular intervals
and in tandem with local human subject protection committees.
Our study makes use of novel software from Northwestern University’s Center for
Behavior Intervention Technologies (CBITs) called Purple Robot. This software is able to
send comprehensive user data from the phone and tell us locations, contacts, texts, emails,
and which apps are used. There are also algorithms that the CBITs teams have developed
using smartphone sensor data to estimate factors like sleep and mobility. All of these
capabilities give the appearance of a very invasive study. In the course of our focus groups,
we reviewed the use of this software with the homeless youth. They asked good questions
about what the data would be used for, and also requested that the software be removed
at the end of the study period. The focus groups supported the use of this approach if the
findings would help other homeless youth. We included specifics about the monitoring
element of the study in our consent forms that all study participants sign.
78 7
Our study is presently in progress and to this point our team has not faced any major
problems with the consent process. We are providing telephone-based brief psycho-
therapy to homeless youth and also enabling them to contact their study therapist via a
custom-designed text messaging interface. We hope that these interventions will increase
the likelihood of homeless youth engaging in mental health services.
Conclusion
Vulnerable youth and social media is a new area of research. In our experience work-
ing with homeless youth, there has been an exploration of appropriate research practices
and approaches which we tried to define within existing standards and in tandem with
community-based stakeholders. Further research is needed in developing appropriate
ethics standards for research in this population. In particular, it is clear that adolescents
and youth have a different view of privacy than prior generations. They are more apt to
share deeply personal elements of themselves on social media and do so in a way that
they see as empowering. Further research should examine the intersection of privacy and
social media for young people in order to understand this space better and to develop
appropriate standards for researchers to follow.
Finally, IRBs are advised to undertake to educate their members about the needs of
these youth populations so as to be better positioned to judge protocols in this subfield.
Knowledge about adolescents, LGBT youth, the impact of homelessness and trauma on
brain development, and technology are all presently lacking on most IRBs. These com-
mittees should also seek external consultation when protocols fall outside of their areas of
expertise and draw from individuals who have worked in these subfields.
Note
1. All clinical examples in this chapter are created for educational purposes only and do not reflect any
patients directly.
References
Castro, A.L., Gustafson, E.L., Ford, A.E., et al. (2014). Psychiatric disorders, high-risk behaviors, and
chronicity of episodes among predominantly African American homeless Chicago youth. Journal of
Health Care for the Poor and Underserved, 25(3), 1201–1216.
Edidin, J.P., Ganim, Z., Hunter, S.J., and Karnik, N.S. (2011). The mental and physical health of
homeless youth: a literature review. Child Psychiatry and Human Development, 43(3), 354–375.
Fisher, C.B. and Mustanski, B. (2014). Reducing health disparities and enhancing the responsible
conduct of research involving LGBT youth. The Hastings Center Report, 44(Suppl 4), S28–31.
Goldberg, S., Karnik, N.S., and Hunter, S.J. (2013, October). Technology Usage and Social Support in
a Population of Inner-City Homeless Youth. Presented at the 60th Annual Meeting of the American
Academy of Child & Adolescent Psychiatry, Orlando, Florida.
Grant, S. (2016, March 29). Wentworth Miller opens up about depression and suicidal thoughts
in candid Facebook post. MTV News. Available from: http://www.mtv.com/news/2858392/
wentworth-miller-facebook-weight-gain-memes-depression-suicide-the-lad-bible/
79
References 79
Kaiser, E., Zalta, A.K., Boley, R.A., Glover, A., Karnik, N.S., and Schueller, S.M. (in press). Exploring
the potential of technology-based mental health services for homeless youth: a qualitative study.
Psychological Services.
Kuehn, B.M. (2007). CDC: autism spectrum disorders common. JAMA, 297(9), 940.
Kuo, M.H., Orsmond, G.I., Coster, W.J., and Cohn, E.S. (2014). Media use among adolescents with
autism spectrum disorder. Autism, 18(8), 914–923.
Lenhart, A. (2015). Teens, Social Media & Technology Overview 2015. Washington, DC: Pew Research
Center.
Lin, L.Y., Sidani, J.E., Shensa, A., et al. (2016). Association between social media use and depression
among U.S. young adults. Depression and Anxiety, 33(4), 323–331.
Mazurek, M.O., Shattuck, P.T., Wagner, M., and Cooper, B.P. (2012). Prevalence and correlates of
screen-based media use among youths with autism spectrum disorders. Journal of Autism and
Developmental Disorders, 42(8), 1757–1767.
Mitchell, S.M., Seegan, P.L., Roush, J.F., Brown, S.L., Sustaíta, M.A., and Cukrowicz, K.C. (2016).
Retrospective cyberbullying and suicide ideation: the mediating roles of depressive symptoms,
perceived burdensomeness, and thwarted belongingness. Journal of Interpersonal Violence. Advance
online publication. doi:10.1177/0886260516628291
Mustanski, B. (2011). Ethical and regulatory issues with conducting sexuality research with LGBT
adolescents: a call to action for a scientifically informed approach. Archives of Sexual Behavior,
40(4), 673–686.
Pantic, I. (2014). Online social networking and mental health. Cyberpsychology, Behavior and Social
Networking, 17(10), 652–657.
Pham, T. and Adesman, A. (2015). Teen victimization: prevalence and consequences of traditional and
cyberbullying. Current Opinion in Pediatrics, 27(6), 748–756.
Quimby, E.G., Edidin, J.P., Ganim, Z., Gustafson, E., Hunter, S.J., and Karnik, N.S. (2012). Psychiatric
disorders and substance use in homeless youth: a preliminary comparison of San Francisco and
Chicago. Behavioral Sciences, 2(3), 186–194.
Ranney, M.L., Patena, J.V., Nugent, N., et al. (2016). PTSD, cyberbullying and peer violence: prevalence
and correlates among adolescent emergency department patients. General Hospital Psychiatry,
39, 32–38.
Rice, E., Lee, A., and Taitt, S. (2011). Cell phone use among homeless youth: potential for new health
interventions and research. Journal of Urban Health, 88(6), 1175–1182.
Sivashanker, K. (2013). Cyberbullying and the digital self. Journal of the American Academy of Child
and Adolescent Psychiatry, 52(2), 113–115.
Ybarra, M.L., Prescott, T.L., Phillips, G.L. 2nd, Parsons, J.T., Bull, S.S., and Mustanski B. (2016).
Ethical considerations in recruiting online and implementing a text messaging-based HIV
prevention program with gay, bisexual, and queer adolescent males. Journal of Adolescent Health,
59(1), 44–49.
80 8
Chapter 5
Introduction
Imagine you come home to your apartment after a long day at work. It is a comfort-
able 72ºF (22ºC), just as you like it, because your smart phone has alerted your smart
thermostat to your impending arrival and activated the heating in time for you to walk
through the door. Your wrist-worn heart rate monitor, the size of a wrist watch, which
also functions as an activity tracker, GPS device, and pulse monitor, detects a slightly
elevated heart rate, and the sweat-sensing fabric of your smart shirt measures cortisol in
your sweat. These data are sent wirelessly to your sound system, which chimes in with
a soothing Chopin Nocturne. You just now remember that you had run out of almond
milk this morning, but fortunately your smart fridge has ordered some online and it is
now sitting in a little box in front of your door. Also waiting for you is your salmon din-
ner, delivered from the local Italian restaurant. Your blood nutrient wearable device, a
noninvasive Band-Aid-like patch that continuously measures your glucose, iron, elec-
trolytes, and proteins in your blood, has deduced that your high-density lipoprotein is
low, but that your glucose is high. The computer in your smart phone matched this infor-
mation with all nearby delivery-enabled restaurants, cross-referenced it with your taste
preferences—which it learned via machine learning from accumulated data from your
smart plates—then deprioritized recently consumed meals to ensure an element of nov-
elty and made the optimal choice. After you finish your dinner the cortisol levels in your
sweat decline and the smart music serenades you with a more vigorous Bach as you use
your smart tooth brush to apply precisely the right amount of pressure during your 2-
minute teeth cleaning. Tooth brushing movements, times, and patterns are also relayed to
your designated smart phone app, where they are displayed in graphic format. Finally, you
sink into your bed, which is fully enabled via your smart mattress pad to track your heart
rate and sleep cycles, and offset disturbing light levels or detected noise pollution with
soothing orange melatonin-activating light and lullabies of circadian rhythm-mimicking
frequencies.
Of course, you need not imagine it, since (almost) all of this technology already exists.1
Wearable and mobile technology, along with the Internet of Things (IoT), has firmly estab-
lished its foothold in virtually every arena of twenty-first century Western life. In addition to
81
Introduction 81
the near ubiquitous activity trackers (such as Fitbit®, Jawbone®, and Misfit®) that are esti-
mated to constitute an over $5 billion USD industry by the year 2019 (Lamkin 2015), there
is a huge array of other wearable technology on both the consumer and industrial markets,
with new modalities seemingly appearing on a weekly basis. This technology includes smart
clothing, headphones, shoes, wristbands, ski goggles, and jewelry, as well as smart mouth
guards, ovulation trackers, personal trainers, and asthma monitors (Wearable Technologies
2016). Devices may be unobtrusive patches worn on the skin, sensors woven into clothing,
or even ingestible sensors swallowed inside pills (Belknap et al. 2013; Banerjee et al. 2015;
Lehmkuhle et al. 2015). Technologies can mine location, activity, breathing rate and volume,
sleep patterns, heart rate, sweat, blood chemistry, and even brain waves for biometric data
(Lupton 2013).
Furthermore, these wearable devices are inextricably connected with mobile technol-
ogy, smartphones, smart watches, tablets, and personal computers in intelligent ways.
Through mobile apps and mobile platforms that allow the integration of data from mul-
tiple apps, biometric data is stored, processed, and represented in colorful visual formats.
The data can be shared online and on social platforms; one’s performance can even be
used to compete in games or as part of an employer wellness incentive.
Healthcare emerges as a natural target for wearable and mobile technology. Indeed
thousands of wearable devices and mobile apps have been developed and are in use
for healthcare purposes (Zheng et al. 2014). Health-related platforms, such as Apple’s
Health Kit (Apple Inc. 2016), allow for the integration of health and fitness data from
different mobile apps as well as wearable technologies. Furthermore, Apple’s Research
Kit permits the creation and roll out of medical research apps, for example, Stanford’s
My Heart Counts (Apple Inc. 2015; Stanford Medicine 2016). Proponents for the use of
this technology in healthcare see a future in which medically relevant data are wirelessly
relayed to one’s physician or electronic health record on a continuous basis, obviating
the need for cumbersome in-office visits and patients’ subjective logging (Lupton 2013).
Many of the same ethical issues that arise with wearable and mobile technology in gen-
eral are exacerbated when the technology enters the domain of neuroscience, neurology,
and mental health. Technology here runs the gamut from transcranial magnetic stimula-
tion (TMS) systems designed for the casual user, such as the neuro-stimulating wearable
Thync® (Zinko 2015), to seizure monitoring devices for epileptics, such as the EEG Patch™
(Lehmkuhle 2015), to mobile apps intended to provide nontraditional modes of mental
healthcare (see “A case study: Mental health apps”).
In this chapter, we conduct an exploration into some of the neuroethical issues associ-
ated with wearable and mobile technology. In “Classifications,” we classify neuro-and
mental health wearable and mobile technology according to a number of ethically rel-
evant criteria, including the purpose, functionalities, and user profiles of the technology.
In “Ethical considerations,” we consider the accuracy and reliability of these technologies,
and address the issue of privacy and confidentiality. We also provide a discussion of new
opportunities and issues with informed consent. We then broaden the angle to see how
this technology factors into the deprofessionalization trend in healthcare in general and
82 8
Classifications
The concept of wearable devices eludes simple definition, so in this section we provide the
parameters of what falls within this category. As already stated, any discussion of wearables
must recognize that such technology is inextricably linked with the mobile technology,
usually smartphones, that support it. Consequently, we cannot in any principled way sepa-
rate wearable from mobile technology. In the arena of healthcare in particular, the mobile
health aspects relevant to our discussion cut across mobile platforms and wearable devices.
Indeed, in many ways the smartphone is itself a wearable device. It accompanies individu-
als almost everywhere, including during exercise and sleep, and can be used as an activity
tracker, as well as a means to measure an array of other biometric and behavioral dimen-
sions (Bonnington 2014). It is not feasible, therefore, to distinguish sharply between tech-
nology that is worn on the body, such as a wristband or a patch, and a smartphone. In this
chapter we are thus looking at an inclusive class of technologies that covers mobile tech-
nology and devices traditionally thought of as wearables. In fact, some forms of wearables
are not worn at all, but are ingested or inserted. For the purposes of brevity, we will refer to
all members of this class as technology*. Roughly, we can think of the class of technology*
as encompassing technology that is worn, adhered to, ingested, or inserted in the body, or
that is contained on mobile computing platforms, that provides and/or manipulates data
generated by the physiological, behavioral, and environmental features of an individual’s
quotidian activities. We delineate the parameters of this technology* in what follows.
It is useful to make categorizations along three dimensions: purpose, functionality, and
usage profile. Purpose refers to the goal or aim of the particular technology in a given con-
text. Functionality refers to the method by which that technology operates. Usage profile
describes the kind of user using the technology.
Purposes
We have identified five general purposes of this technology*.2 These are:
◆ education
◆ diagnosis
◆ treatment
◆ crisis management
◆ research.
83
Classifications 83
Functionalities
Having outlined the five purposes of this technology, let us now turn to the functionalities
with which these purposes are to be achieved. Some of the most common functionalities
of this technology are:
Tracking: First and foremost, this technology allows individuals to track a variety of
bodily, mental, and environmental dimensions. Some of the most important ones are
as follows:
Sleep—One of the most obvious ways in which technology* interacts with neurologi-
cal and mental health issues is through the tracking of sleep. There is a wide array of
sleep trackers available. Many are wrist-worn, such as Fitbit®, Jawbone®, and Misfit®
(Stables 2016). These mainly use motion sensors to monitor sleep and sleep cycles,
displaying a large array of data to one’s smartphone or other mobile device. But
there are also sensors that are placed in the bed and connect to a smartphone via
Bluetooth®, for example, Sense® and Beddit®, or body-sized sensors that are placed
under the bed sheets, track sleep patterns and are connected to lamps that acti-
vate to wake the sleeper during the lightest part of her sleep, for example, Withings
Aura™ (Haslam 2015). Of course, smartphones also have sleep tracking apps, though
purpose-built technologies appear to be more accurate (Winter 2014).
Activity and location—Besides their use for measuring fitness, which also has effects
on mental health (Folkins & Sime 1981), activity trackers are used for detecting
specific neurological or mental health conditions (Banerjee et al. 2015). There are
apps that track activity for the purpose of monitoring an individual’s bipolar disor-
der as reduced activity indicates a depressive phase, such as Mood Rhythm™ (Voida
et al. 2013). There are sensors (worn on the wrist or elsewhere on the body) that are
used to monitor the activity and whereabouts of individuals with dementia, such as
9Solutions products (9Solutions n.d.). Wearable clothing (e.g., LifeShirt™) is used to
research behavior and activity in people with schizophrenia (Miniassian et al. 2010).
Many such devices and technologies are also equipped with alarm systems that alert
the user or a designated care giver when either the user’s location or her activity is
outside of pre-set values (Samson 2015).
Electroencephalogram (EEG)—Continuous EEG monitoring, such as EEG Patch™
(Lehmkuhle 2015), uses small, waterproof wearable patches that are placed on the
scalp of a person suffering from epilepsy and enables continuous seizure tracking.
Electromyography (EMG)—Convulsive seizure detection and warning systems, such
as Brain Sentinel® (Cavazos et al. 2015), are being developed. They are worn on the
biceps and measure skeletal muscle electrical activity.
Electrocardiogram (ECG)—ECG tracking, for instance in wearable vests and shirts
such as those produced by Hexoskin™ (Banerjee et al. 2015), allows for monitoring
ECG which can be used in the diagnosis of dementia.
85
Classifications 85
Quizzes and questionnaires: Apps such as What’s my M3™ (iTunes App Store 2016c) are
designed both to diagnose and to provide ongoing progress reports on conditions such
as mood disorders.
Activity tasks: Some mobile apps provide tasks that users have to complete for diagnostic
purposes. These include tapping and breathing tasks, for example, ReachOut Breathe™
(iTunes App Store 2016b).
Games: Gamification is one way in which this technology* has made an impact on men-
tal healthcare. Users can use values “achieved” on their technologies* to compete
against others or themselves. SuperBetter™ (Roepke et al. 2015) is one example of this
technology.
Medication delivery: Some technologies*, for example, Chrono Therapeutics (Alba
2015b), deliver treatment such as nicotine replacement therapy, and then tailor
the coaching recommendations on the app to the amount of nicotine replacement
consumed.
Augmented reality: While virtual reality headsets are not typically thought of as “wear-
able” technology*, developers are beginning to use this functionality as part of addic-
tion treatment, by recreating trigger situations for the addict, and then providing
cognitive skills for the patient to avoid succumbing to her addiction (e.g., University
of Houston Virtual Reality Lab, Loria 2016). Moreover, augmented reality, such as
Google Glass™, that overlays information onto reality and thereby reminds or nudges a
user about relevant information, may be useful in addressing neurological and mental
health issues.
Usage profiles
Technologies* can also be categorized based on the type of user. We have identified four
relevant usage profiles:
Direct-to-consumer use: This category comprises the technology* that is commercially
available, that consumers can purchase directly, and that is not mediated by a health-
care provider or other professional.
Provider-mediated clinical use: Technology* in this category may be either commer-
cially available or not. However, it differs from the previous category in that it is
administered and monitored by a healthcare professional, such as a neurologist or a
mental healthcare provider.
Provider-mediated research use: Research may be conducted with this technology*, in
which case it is monitored by a researcher. Research uses differ from the previous two
use profiles in that they have no clinical (diagnostic or therapeutic) intent.
Third-party use: Although this practice is not yet common with neuro-and mental health
wearable and mobile health technology, technology* may be used by employers as part
of a wellness incentive, by universities and schools to encourage healthy behavior, by
87
Ethical considerations 87
the military and hospitals to track the practices of soldiers/physicians, and by insur-
ance companies to learn more about their subscribers.
We have thus identified the various purposes, functionalities, and usage profiles that
are implicated in the generation of ethical issues of this technology*. As we will see, the
ethical issues that arise, arise out of a combination of these three dimensions. In “A case
study: Mental health apps,” for example, we find that the purpose of treatment as pursued
by the direct-to-the-consumer user emerges as particularly precarious. Having laid the
groundwork we now move on to delineate the various ethical issues.
Ethical considerations
Accuracy and reliability
A primary consideration with this technology*, indeed all technologies involved in a
person’s well-being and healthcare, is accuracy and reliability. Here, the extent to which
accuracy and reliability matters depends both on the usage profile as well as the pur-
pose. Technology* that is used for clinical purposes and is provider mediated demands a
high level of accuracy and reliability. In treating epilepsy, a clinician may base her treat-
ment plan on the readings from an EEG patch—a small patch worn on the scalp that
continually tracks seizures over the course of multiple days (Lehmkuhle 2015)—and in
dealing with bipolar disorder, schizophrenia, or dementia, on the data of a wearable sleep
and activity tracking sensors (Alba 2015a; Banerjee 2015). Any medical device that is
used in clinical decision-making in the United States must conform with Food and Drug
Administration (FDA) regulations for medical devices (FDA 2014). This ensures a certain
degree of sensitivity and specificity of the device, which is obviously necessary to prevent
harmful medical advice.
In general, the FDA’s approach to regulation is risk-based, that is, dependent on a con-
sideration of the potential risks of the technology not working as intended, as well as based
on the specific health-related claims the developer makes about the product (FDA 2013).
However, technology* may not always be used as specified or intended. Commercially
available devices that are not regulated by the FDA can also be used by healthcare provid-
ers for clinical purposes (Sutner 2016). Here, accuracy and reliability are not regulated
and devices have been found to be inaccurate (Geddes 2015; Cipriani 2016). This presents
a problem when clinicians rely on such devices for the purposes of diagnosis or treatment.
Naturally, accuracy and reliability is also critical for the purpose of research. Often
researchers have to rely on participants correctly employing the technology*, since it is
used remotely and researcher have little to no oversight. A subject that is being tracked
for dementia might forget to put on or activate her device and consequently is recorded
as having been stationary all day. Moreover, the identity of the person who is wearing the
device could also be at issue. This, however, becomes less of a concern when the technol-
ogy* includes devices that are implanted, inserted, or even ingested.
An issue for research applications of this technology* may arise when it is intended for
dual use. For example, some vocal analysis platforms are intended both for researching
8 8
speech patterns associated with conditions such as depression or bipolar disorder and
are simultaneously being used by insurance companies to evaluate their policy hold-
ers (Walker 2015).4 Given this dual purpose of both research and diagnosis, incentives
may not be aligned for the user, and data may be inaccurate as a result. For example,
when an individual uses technology* to participate in a corporate wellness program, the
researcher’s goal of obtaining accurate data, may not be those of the user, who is trying to
do well in a competitive, and possibly remunerated, setting. Moreover, given the remote
nature of this technology*, which is of course touted as one of its benefits (e.g., perform-
ing EEG readings on-the-go rather than in-office), correct use is not always easy to ensure
in research contexts.
Prima facie, technology* that is used directly by the consumer and is commercially
available may seem to have the least stringent requirements for accuracy and reliability.
Casual usage of an activity tracker, for example, even if the measurements are inaccurate,
seems unlikely to have a major detrimental impact on a person’s health and behavior.
After all, if the idea is to motivate an individual to participate in healthier behavior, being
off by a few percentage points should not matter too much. However, individuals are
increasingly using this technology* in ways that amount to treatment, in the sense speci-
fied earlier of mental health problems, enabling individuals to address conditions such
depression, anxiety, obsessive–compulsive disorder, eating disorders, and PTSD (Luxton
et al. 2011). Technology* used in this arena (mainly mobile or online services) are largely
unregulated, and are therefore not legally required to meet minimum accuracy, reliability,
safety, or efficacy standards.
With the presence of the internet in every facet of modern life and the spread of technol-
ogy* advancing at a staggering pace, individuals are increasingly empowered with respect
to their psychological health, taking treatment into their own hands. Traditional mental
healthcare is often inaccessible particularly for young people (Melnyk 2007). Moreover,
a do-it-yourself attitude toward healthcare, along with patient advocacy and citizen sci-
ence groups, is gaining prominence (Sarasohn-Kahn 2008; Greene 2016). In the time of
Uber and Airbnb, individuals are moving away from professional providers of services
and toward the soliciting of services from technology* enthusiasts or financially moti-
vated lay people. Individuals are replacing psychotherapy with online services in which
anonymous “listeners” provide support. Accuracy and reliability matter to the extent
that users are employing this technology* for diagnostic and treatment purposes, which
indeed seems to be the case (Jacobson 2014). While some individuals may be helped in
their mental healthcare by technology* that is accessible and cheap, or free, and provided
by altruistic or well-meaning outlets, the lack of oversight of technology* used in this cat-
egory, either through government regulation, legislation, or professional self-regulation,
means that inaccurate and unreliable information is a serious risk.5
Ethical considerations 89
of the data involved in mental health is sensitive and it is not clear that this technol-
ogy* has the requisite precautions in place to deal with data of this sort. In the direct-to-
consumer category, for instance, the mobile, wearable nature of this technology* makes
it easy for users to share sensitive information about themselves in a non-private, non-
confidential way. Of course, voluntary sharing of identified sensitive medical information
on social media, on platforms like PatientsLikeMe, or in games is always problematic.
However, neurological and mental health information from wearable devices is arguably
more sensitive to the extent that it can be coupled with GPS-tracked location and other
information that gives unprecedented insight into an individual’s behavior. This can make
her vulnerable to criminal activity, social discrimination, and employer retaliation.
Users of this technology*, especially children, may not be aware just how accessible
their data are, or what the potential effects of a loss of privacy may be. However, providers
of the technology* arguably have a duty to apprise users of the non-confidentiality of their
data. Given the lack of comprehension that is present when users click through usage
agreements, it is not clear that this duty is being satisfied (Felt et al. 2012). In the United
States, in the direct-to-consumer category, devices and apps that are not considered to
be medical devices by the FDA are under no obligation to comply with Health Insurance
Portability and Accountability Act (HIPAA). Individuals are likely to underestimate the
accessibility of this information, which suggests greater efforts must be made to empha-
size the non-private status of this information, as well as possible negative consequences.
A further concern is simply the security of data. Medically sensitive data is stored
on personal devices, such as smart phones, that are not HIPAA compliant and security
breaches both there and on the servers of the technology* developers who are receiv-
ing the data are unavoidable (McNeal 2015). Moreover, hackers may actually hijack the
device itself and track the user or issue malicious guidance (Leavitt 2011), which would
not only endanger the data, but could have dangerous consequences for the user’s health
and safety.
Users’ privacy may also be at risk in the provider-mediated clinical category. When a
user receives an alert or a signal from her technology*, this may be more intrusive than
receiving an email or phone call. The likelihood of a bystander noticing a buzzing or flash-
ing wearable device is high and might result in socially uncomfortable situations. This
indicates both the promise of this technology*, since messages can be relayed to patients
in a more time-sensitive manner than ever before, and the peril, since these messages may
be less private than is desirable.
Third parties may also be employing this technology* in ways that are worrisome from
a privacy standpoint. Insurance companies (e.g., Aetna and Humana) are using voice
analysis during phone calls to detect whether a person may be exhibiting speech patterns
that are indicative of depression (Hodson 2014; Walker 2015). The purpose is to monitor
whether that person is engaged with “activities like physical therapy or taking the right
kinds of medications” in an effort to ensure that individuals on short-term disability ben-
efits return to work sooner (Sanicola 2015). Often, individuals are not even informed that
their voices are being analyzed, because of the risk that that might cause the individual to
90 9
modify his speech patterns.6 Technology* that conducts this kind of voice analysis may
be administered remotely or be installed directly on the user’s smartphone. When voice
data is being recorded for the purpose of monitoring smartphone users, privacy and con-
fidentiality may not be regulated by HIPAA or other regulation, and there is a risk that the
individual’s privacy is not being adequately respected.
Finally, data security and privacy laws vary internationally, but technology* and smart
phones move across borders. Europe, for instance, has strict, centrally mandated privacy
laws that allows users to remove personal information about them from online searches
as well as prevent the transfer of data between companies or across borders (European
Union 1995), while such laws are nonexistent in the United States. Since European laws
apply not only to hardware physically located in Europe, but similarly to all data accessed
through search engines in Europe (European Commission 2014), this might mean that
while an individual located in the United States has no recourse to prevent her employer
from recording data pertaining to her practices, the same individual when travelling in
Europe does, raising issues of justice and fairness.
Consent
Medical consent forms are notorious for being difficult to understand, and indeed mis-
understood (Akkad et al. 2006). Given that consent with this technology*, in particular
in the direct-to-consumer category, is usually indicated by a tap on a mobile screen, it
is likely that users’ comprehension of data usage, sharing, privacy, security, and other
important issues may be similarly low (Felt et al. 2012). Users may believe they own or
have control over the sharing of their data, while the app developer collecting the data is
bound, in fact, only by the voluntary terms set forth in the poorly understood consent
agreement (Rosner 2014). Users may be unaware that the data they generate may be sold
for commercial gain (Kaye 2014). In addition, the context of a smart phone app may elicit
less than rigorous consideration, due to an app being viewed not as a serious medical
intervention. Moreover, should the development company go out of business—a com-
monplace occurrence in the fast-paced start-up world—the data may be bought by a dif-
ferent company with no obligation to honor the terms of the original consent.
Consent is a particular concern for technologies* that offer unregulated online or
mobile mental health services. Users and participants as young as 15 or 13 years old are
permitted to use these services and even here very little effort is made to verify the age or
identity of the user (7 Cups of Tea 2016e). In fact, many technologies* stress the anony-
mous nature of their services and actively discourage users from revealing any identifying
information, which raises concerns of a lack of accountability on the part of the provider.
It is unlikely that such young individuals understand the complexities of consenting to
releasing sensitive information about themselves and more protections probably ought
to be in place.7
At the same time, the potential for two-way interaction between technology* users and
researchers or clinicians presents an opportunity for novel approaches that may be more
effective than existing, traditional means of obtaining consent. Early developers of some
91
Ethical considerations 91
medical research apps, including ResearchKit, utilize multimedia and animation, and
require research participants to go through a set of screens that explain the research prior
to consent being obtained (Stanford Medicine 2016).
In the provider-mediated clinical use category, users also may not understand that
while the primary goal of data generated will be clinical, physicians are permitted to
share data for research purposes (US Department of Health and Human Services 2003).
Electronic health records that have been de-identified, but linked to identifiable informa-
tion have been consistently used in research settings without explicit informed consent,
even though there is evidence that patients expect and prefer to be asked for such consent
(Cho et al. 2015). Despite such research not being considered human subject research in
the United States, it may nonetheless be a violation of patient autonomy and the principle
of respect. This issue may be exacerbated when the correlated data include locations fre-
quented, phone calls made, items purchased, or websites visited (Rothstein 2010).
In the instances where there is a lack of explicit informed consent with research con-
ducted on technology*-generated data, the issue of incidental findings is also complicated
(Illes et al. 2008). For instance, data gleaned from this technology*, intended to study
something unrelated, might reveal that a particular user exhibits a pattern highly corre-
lated with dementia—maybe going back in and out of the same room, or dialing a number
wrong multiple times. Should the user be alerted to this? In the absence of an explicit
directive, as may be the case with de-identified research data, the researcher cannot know
whether the user wants to be informed of a finding that suggests she may have a poten-
tially serious medical condition. Moreover, the participant will likely not have appropriate
expectations for such findings, as her intentions may have been more casual; she may have
worn the technology* or downloaded the app as light-hearted entertainment.
Democratization of healthcare
Technology* in this area lends itself to individuals taking both clinical decision-making
and mental health research into their own hands. We look more closely at how this tech-
nology* is influencing traditional mental healthcare in the next section; here we con-
sider some general features of how this technology* contributes to the democratization
of healthcare.
Within the category of research, wearable and mobile technology in neurological and
mental health area allows users to track large amounts of data about themselves. This
copious amount of data has the potential to be mined either individually, or in conjunc-
tion with other users, outside of the umbrella of professional research teams or academic
institutions. While there may not yet be a publicly accessible repository of wearable and
mobile technology* data for neurological or mental conditions, models for such data-
bases exist in Harvard’s Personal Genome Project (Church 2005) and the American Gut
Microbiome Project (Garbarino & Mason 2016). Moreover, individuals who are invested
in the medical research for particular conditions are finding a voice on patient advocacy
and data collection sites such as PatientsLikeMe, where they share data with each other, as
well as with commercial entities (PatientsLikeMe n.d.).
92 9
Increasingly, the roles of patient, provider, subject, and researcher are becoming blurred.
Big data projects where self-trackers contribute clinical data, which nonprofessional
data scientists analyze, are becoming more widespread (Sarasohn-Kahn 2008; Kelty &
Panofsky 2014). This raises issues regarding the roles and responsibilities of the actors
engaged in this “citizen science.” Since this research is typically not publicly funded and
since individuals engaged in this research are generally not associated with academic or
research institutions, the regulations and norms that usually apply to healthcare research
may not apply. So far we have not seen massive citizen science endeavors in neurology
or mental health arenas, as we have seen with genomic data, but it seems only a matter
of time that data consolidated from this technology* become subject to big data analysis
projects. It is thus important to determine whether in addition to general duties of non-
maleficence to others, lay researchers possess any special duties, for example, duties of
veracity, confidentiality, and data sharing, associated with scientific research.
Similarly, in the clinical category, nonprofessional individuals are taking on roles hith-
erto reserved for trained professionals (see “A case study: Mental health apps”). While this
offers the promise of fillings gaps in clinical care, little is known so far about the kinds of
responsibilities implicated in this kind of democratization of healthcare. Do nonprofes-
sional treatment providers have the same duties of care as professionals? If not, is this a
function of a difference in role, or a difference in training? Or is this difference in respon-
sibilities due to a different set of intentions or aims inherent in the definition of a lay per-
son healthcare provider? Does it matter what the expectations of the individuals seeking
treatment are? And if the responsibilities of a professional and a lay person healthcare
provider are similar, are these responsibilities being effectively discharged by such “citizen
clinicians”? We address some of these questions in the case study we consider in the next
section.
Ethical considerations 93
per month with a 2-year subscription to a lifetime subscription for $419.95 USD (7 Cups
of Tea 2016f).
Given the recent advisory by the US Preventive Services Task Force (USPSTF) to screen
the general adult population, including pregnant and postpartum women, for depression
(Siu et al. 2016), and the fact that the USPSTF is poised to recommend similar screen-
ing in 12-to 18-year-old adolescents (Siu & US Preventive Services Task Force 2016) it
stands to reason that a greater incidence of diagnosis and treatment will be in demand,
which traditional mental health services, already overextended, will struggle to fulfill
(Melnyk 2007). Moreover, it is likely that adolescents in particular will increasingly seek
out cheap or free, nontraditional, readily-available treatment options, such as mobile apps
and online services.
Let us thus take a closer look at such technologies*. There are indeed online therapy
services that operate with licensed therapists and adhere to professional guidelines and
regulations, utilizing the communication and information functionalities listed discussed
previously. These services show considerable promise for patients dealing with affective
disorders (Wagner et al. 2014) and include examples such as the US Veterans Affairs
telemedicine service, but also private providers such as Talkspace™ and Breakthrough™.
Additionally, other mobile and online technologies function as self-help guides and refer-
ence sources for mental wellness concerns. These technologies* utilize the information,
quizzes, and questionnaires, and sometimes activity task functionalities. Such resources
can provide useful information to individuals who may wish to enhance their well-being
through approaches such as mindfulness or meditation, or learn about cognitive behav-
ioral or dialectic behavioral therapy.
A third category of services, comprising technologies* such as 7 Cups of Tea, can rea-
sonably be taken to offer something akin to therapy; they offer the advice or commentary
of concerned but nonprofessional lay people, fellow sufferers, or both. This may look like
a form of peer counseling, but it is problematic, as it intimates the guise of traditional
therapy. For example, 7 Cups of Tea advertises that these listeners are specialized in issues
“ranging from panic attacks and bullying to eating disorders, surviving a breakup, and
more” (Google Play 2016a; iTunes App store 2016a).
Employing the categories of purposes, functionalities, and usage profiles we introduced
earlier, we find that the purposes involved here are primarily education and treatment.
Users seek out this technology* to learn more about the particular mental health issue
they perceive themselves to be experiencing, and they aim to treat these issues by talk-
ing them through with and receiving guidance from nonprofessional listeners, as well as
progressing along the games, quizzes, and activity tasks that constitute their progression
paths. At the same time, research is occurring in the background with this technology*
(Baumel 2015). Finally, while crisis management is explicitly a purpose 7 Cups of Tea
rejects as being one of its applications, there are likely instances where this technology*
is employed for the purpose of seeking out psychological help in times of critical mental
health need.
94 9
Ethical considerations 95
may be, the combination of minimal training of the nonprofessional listeners combined
with the gravity of some of the conditions for which this service is advertised, increases
the risk of harmful or misguided medical advice. We also worry that this technology*
may be conveying a false sense of therapeutic efficacy. The problem here is not merely
that these mobile or online services are not providing effective treatment, but that users
are eschewing actual effective treatment for the sake of these services under the mistaken
belief that these services provide effective interventions. Since users on a site like 7 Cups
of Tea can be as young as 13 years—with parental consent, though this consent is not
confirmed it is likely that users may believe that they are effectively treating their mental
health issues, when in reality they are not.
In a recent study, Baumel (2015) finds that individuals who engaged both in sessions on
7 Cups of Tea and with a real-life psychotherapist, rated the support provided by online
nonprofessional listeners as equally or more helpful than that of the professionals. This,
Baumel argues, is because individuals find online listeners to be more genuine. But of
course, whether an individual finds the therapist to be genuine is not the true measure of
the efficacy of the intervention. The efficacy of nonprofessional listener services must be
assessed according to actual medical outcomes rather than user satisfaction. Moreover,
the perceived genuineness of listeners may actually exacerbate the false sense of therapeu-
tic efficacy this technology* is providing.
While the efficacy of technology* in this third category is an important question that
must be studied empirically, it is worth noting that nonprofessional listeners are not
trained to handle individuals in situations of crisis with serious and potentially life-
threatening conditions. As already noted, 7 Cups of Tea does state that its service is not
intended for crisis situations (7 Cups of Tea 2016e). However, while such a disclaimer
may be legally exculpating, we argue that 7 Cups of Tea nonetheless has an ethical obliga-
tion toward individuals in states of great mental distress. Particularly if users have strong
expectations that listeners can provide assistance in critical situations, this technology*
has some duty to offer precisely such assistance. It is a real concern to us that listeners
may provide inaccurate and inadequate medical advice in such critical situations. Further
exacerbating this concern is that there seems to be a large turnover amongst listeners, sug-
gesting not only that there is little consistency or opportunity to build up expertise, but
that accountability is also limited.
these are not legally mandated. As a private company, it is within its rights to pass on user
data to third parties for the purposes of marketing or consumer research, which 7 Cups of
Tea explicitly states it does (7 Cups of Tea 2016e). Listeners of course face similar privacy
concerns as any information they reveal about themselves, either toward 7 Cups of Tea or
a particular user, is also not legally protected. For both listener and user, this highlights
precisely the concern we stressed above. Moreover, communications between listeners
and users on 7 Cups of Tea are not encrypted and are thus under considerable threat of
unauthorized interception and monitoring (7 Cups of Tea 2016b).
Democratization of healthcare
Having looked at issues with this technology* including accuracy and reliability, privacy
and confidentiality, we now consider how this technology* illustrates the concerns dis-
cussed in “Democratization of healthcare.” As we have already argued, technology* such
as 7 Cups of Tea seeks to augment and possibly replace traditional mental healthcare with
accessible, democratized, and nonprofessional avenues of counseling and therapy. We can
now consider what sorts of responsibilities this might generate for the nonprofessional
treatment providers—where treatment is intended in the sense discussed in “Purposes”
in the “Classifications” section—who populate such sites.
Individuals who operate as listeners complete a multiple choice training guide (7
Cups of Tea 2016a). This training consists of clicking through a small number of
screens featuring scenarios that the listener might encounter. Still, this does not equip
them to respond to serious mental health issues that users might be experiencing;
and, 7 Cups of Tea explicitly states that dealing with critical mental health situations
is not the responsibility of the listener (7 Cups of Tea 2016g). For example, listeners
are instructed that if a user appears to be in a state of crisis, they are immediately to
interrupt the session, direct the user to an emergency resource, and terminate the
interaction.
However, given that as we have already argued, a user can have a justifiable expectation
of receiving mental healthcare, the question arises whether a given listener truly has no
ethical responsibilities toward the struggling user with whom she is communicating. If we
believe that responsibilities are generated by the kind of role that an individual occupies,
and if this role shares some of the features of that of a professional mental healthcare
provider, then the listener may well have at least some of the ethical responsibilities that
a professional therapist or counselor has. For instance, it is worth considering whether
listeners, as is the case with counselors and therapists, have a duty to report evidence of
child, partner, or elder abuse (US Department of Health and Human Services 2009). Even
though listeners may not have legal responsibilities in this arena, the role they assume
may engender such ethical duties.
While professional mental healthcare providers are well-positioned to discharge such
duties of care thanks to their training, it is not clear that nonprofessional listeners are
similarly well-apportioned. Consider the instruction to cut off communication with
a user who exhibits signs of severe mental anguish. As a listener, one may have been
97
Ethical considerations 97
conversing with this user for many hours and have gotten a sense that one is providing
vital support to a troubled person. In abruptly terminating the conversation with such
an individual in what may be a moment of dire need, the user may feel abandoned.
Moreover, due to the anonymous nature of the technology*, unless that user reaches out
to the same listener again, the listener will have no way of knowing whether the user
did seek professional services or, troublingly, acted on emotionally distressed impulses.
In contrast, professional mental healthcare providers are both trained to deal with and
support patients through crises, and in general are privy to a patient’s mental health
developments.
Similarly, many listeners are themselves individuals who are currently or have in the
past struggled with mental health issues. Unlike their professional counterparts, who have
been trained in coping with problematic countertransference, listeners may have nega-
tive emotions triggered and experience a worsening of their own condition as a result of
their relationship with the user. 7 Cups of Tea does suggest that listeners steer away from
subjects with which they themselves are struggling, but listeners cannot know in advance
if or when such a triggering issue may arise in a given session.
A further worrisome feature of the anonymous nature of technologies* such as 7 Cups
of Tea is that listeners have no way of ensuring that users are honest. Listeners may be
trolled, that is to say, a seemingly legitimate user may guide conversations into inappro-
priate or hurtful areas. This can be emotionally taxing for a listener who may be torn
between wanting to support the user and creating some self-protection against abuse
by inappropriate questions or comments. We believe that this negotiation may be dif-
ficult and harmful particularly for younger listeners.10 7 Cups of Tea listener training
does instruct listeners-in-training to terminate a chat when one suspects that a user is a
troll, but there is a risk of cutting off a discussion with a person in actual need of help.11
7 Cups of Tea also releases itself of any legal responsibility for listeners’ actions by stating
that a listener is “solely and fully liable for all conduct, services, advice” and “solely [ …
] responsible and liable for any damages to any member to whom listener provides serv-
ices and where that member suffers damages arising from or connected to such services”
issued within the framework of the service (7 Cups of Tea 2016b). All this suggests that
listeners, who are generally no more than concerned, nonprofessional volunteers and,
with parental consent, can be as young as 15 years old (7 Cups 2016d) are expected to
operate in the context of professional duties and responsibilities for which they are likely
not equipped.
In conclusion, mobile and online mental health technology* has the potential to
make care more accessible. For young people for whom mobile technology is already
integrated into life, it may be particularly beneficial in enabling access to mental health-
care otherwise unavailable. The adoption of a nonprofessional technology* variants
of mental healthcare, however, represents a troubling erosion of professional norms.
Ethical duties and responsibilities are generated by technologies* such as 7 Cups of
Tea. Regulations and oversight in this new area of democratized mental healthcare are
urgently needed.
98 9
Authentic living
Wearable and mobile technology not only constitutes a new means for consumers and
healthcare providers to acquire unprecedented continuous and detailed information
about bodily and environmental goings-on, it also affects the very way an individual
relates to herself. Thus, any neuroethical overview here would not be complete without
a consideration of the psychological and existential effects this technology* precipitates.
Use of this technology* is touted, particularly in the direct-to-consumer category, as
enabling individuals to take control of their quotidian habits and thus improve their over-
all health and well-being. Increasingly, individuals use this technology* to continuously
track their heart rates, glucose levels, stress levels, activity patterns, food intake, sleep
activity, as well as numerous features of their environments (Boudway 2014). Adherents of
the so-called quantified self movement, whose slogan may be taken to be “self-knowledge
through numbers,” aim to employ this wealth of self-centered data pertaining to their
bodies, minds, and environments to subtly alter everyday behaviors and decisions in pur-
suit of a more efficient, more productive, healthier, and happier life (Wolf 2009). In the
final section of this chapter, we explore a number of concerns that arise as a result of this
pursuit.
Approaching one’s being-in-the-world, to use a Heideggerian notion, through quanti-
fication and self-tracking presupposes a fundamentally reductionist model of the mind
and mental well-being (Heidegger 1953).12 Here we do not mean to imply that the mind
is not identical to or supervenient on a physical entity. As do most philosophers these
days, we embrace physicalism about the mind. This does not entail, however, that psycho-
logical, behavioral, and social phenomena are reducible to quantities a wearable device
or smart phone app can track. The difficulty is threefold. Firstly, it is not at all clear that
aspects of daily living that matter to us correspond neatly to quantifiable dimensions.
A feeling of elation after a love interest’s text message may be accompanied by an increase
in heart rate, but it is not therefore given that an increase in heart rate is indicative of a
feeling of elation. Secondly, by quantifying aspects of mental or physiological processes,
we necessarily strip away the complexity and entanglement inherent in the experienced
present. In reality, the phenomenology of a particular instant is composed of a multitude
of mental, environmental, physiological, and antecedent phenomenological experiences
of the world. It is likely that by capturing a measurable data point, we are simply grasp-
ing a partial and conceivably accidental feature of that experience. This means we may
be missing the intended goal—assuming this goal is something like greater well-being or
happiness and not merely the attainment of certain quantitative values—when we seek
to adjust our behavior to attain particular numerical results. Lastly, it may not be the
case that what amounts to a useful quantification of a facet of one individual’s experience
translates across individuals.
In general, the trend toward self-tracking and the quantified self demonstrates our
changing relationship with health and sickness. As Schüll (2016, p.2) aptly notes, “once
understood as a baseline state temporarily interrupted by anomalous moments of illness,
health has been recast as a perpetually insecure state that depends on constant vigilance,
9
Ethical considerations 99
assessment and intervention.” This twenty-first century attitude toward our health and
well-being brings with it the burden of constantly being in charge and aware of our bodily
functioning. Traditionally harmless behaviors, for example, sleeping too long, eating
irregularly, or skipping visits to the gym, become medicalized, and normal variation in
everyday life is pathologized. In light of all the technology at our fingertips, it is really a
shortcoming on the individual’s part, we might think, if she fails to keep her physiologi-
cal data points within levels that are hailed as desirable or at least condoned as normal.
Motivational features of these technologies range from gentle reminders to, say, take the
stairs instead of the elevator, to shaming-inducing social media posts of a person’s unde-
sirable behavior, to physical pain upon the measurement of an unacceptable tracked value,
or the performance of an unsanctioned action (Leonard 2014). This trend may set up
unrealistic, overly onerous expectations of the user, and engender obsession and anxiety.
There is an analogy to be drawn here with calorie counting. Counting calories was long
thought to be a reliable way to reduce body weight. However, evidence is mounting that
by tracking and logging calories as a long-term strategy, individuals become depressed,
lonely, preoccupied with food, lose their intuitive abilities to listen to their inner signals,
and are more prone to binge-eating and over-eating than if they were not counting calo-
ries (Smith et al. 1999). Similar adverse and counterproductive effects are likely when
individuals attempt to control behavior by quantifying dimensions that previously resided
in the realm of intuitive functioning.
In fact, it has been shown that externally rewarding, inherently pleasurable activities
may negatively affect their enjoyableness. With respect to self-tracking specifically, Etkin
(2016) provides preliminary experimental evidence that suggests that while measuring
output can increase the amount of activity an individual achieves, it can simultaneously
decrease how much the activity is enjoyed, to the point that it may reduce how happy and
satisfied the individual feels overall. In one study, participants who knew they were track-
ing their progress on walks through nature experienced less joy than those who did not.
It seems it is precisely the drawing of the attention toward output, rather than allowing
the individual to enjoy the pleasurable activity in itself, that undermines motivation and
overall happiness (Etkin 2016).
In a certain sense, we may think of this as an issue concerning the kind of epistemic
access we have to our inner states. While in the past a person may have relied primarily
on immediate access to inner states to know whether she was hungry or sated, tired or
energized, nervous or calm, with the increasing quantification of the self, we are turning
to external technology and thus, mediated access, to inform us of whether we are hungry
or tired, how warm we would like our apartment to be, or the kind of music to which
we would like to listen. This can be seen as an offloading of first-person capacities to
third-person means.
Similarly, some philosophers have argued that this technological external cognitive
scaffolding represents a development of the mind into something they call the extended
mind, which consists not only within the biological confines of the skull, but extends
into the world to the extent that information is readily available to the cognizer (Clark
10 1
& Chalmers 1998). As such, the mind, properly conceived, may encompass an indi-
vidual’s computing devices, smart phone, and arguably self-tracker. Rather than being
merely a theoretical metaphysical stance, the extended mind hypothesis has moral and
existential implications. First, a reliance on non-biological, external components of our
minds makes us dependent on this technology. Thus, should we temporarily or perma-
nently lose access to this technology, we may be rendered helpless in the face of cognitive
challenges that were hitherto within our capacities. Second, it may erode evolutionarily
established methods of determining bodily needs. Relying on GPS technologies for such
tasks as navigation has been shown to have adverse effects on memory and hippocampal
health (Edwards 2010). It is plausible that relying on technologies for other cognitive
tasks may also have detrimental effects for our brain health. Finally, offloading the moni-
toring of our mental and physiological processes, and relying on third person means
of acquiring self-knowledge, we risk becoming removed from our bodily selves, rather
than experiencing the world in a present, in-the-moment fashion, characteristic of such
phenomena as flow.
We may even think of the integration of self-tracking into everyday life as altering the
very way individuals relate to and conceive of themselves. Swan (2013, p.95) calls this a
“fourth-person perspective” on the self. An individual’s being-in-the-world is no longer
immediate, but is mediated by data, to constitute what Schüll (2016, p.8) calls the “self as
database.” This is a self not accessible via ordinary senses and thus is not phenomenologi-
cally parameterized. Rather the self is reconstituted as information, beyond the sensory
domain. The body, rather than functioning as a sensing entity through which the world
is experienced and “gains self-knowledge [is instead] [ … ] a data-generating device that
must be coupled to sensor technology and analytic algorithms in order to be known”
(Schüll 2016, p.10). Swan (2013, p.96) believes that the quantified self will be transformed
in to an “extended exoself ” as quantification and self-tracking make the body “a more
knowable, calculable, and administrable object [ … ]. and individuals have an increas-
ingly intimate relationship with data as it mediates the experience of reality.” While this
future vision constitutes an exciting scenario for some, the mediation of one’s experience
of reality through data risks alienating the individual from her biological, instinctual self.
Much of the intelligence that drives our behavior is evolutionarily entrenched and below
the threshold of conscious decision-making (Wilson 2004; Gigerenzer 2007). It is not
clear that by inserting a quantified layer between behavior and processing, we will truly
achieve greater mental and physical well-being.
Conclusion
Neurological and mental health applications of wearable and mobile health technol-
ogy show great promise to benefit humans in their pursuit of health and knowledge.
In particular, in the hands of healthcare providers and medical researchers, this tech-
nology* can aid in the diagnosis, treatment, and research of illness. However, for this
10
Conclusion 101
Notes
1. Smart thermostats are available from Ecobee (2016), sweat sensing technology from UC Berkeley
(Geddes 2016), and smart fridges from Samsung (Bohn 2016). Smart Plate makes smart plates (Pugh
2015). Smart toothbrushes are available from Kolibree (Kolibree 2016). The sleep system is the
Withings Aura™ (iClarified 2014).
2. In general, the purpose of a technology* is determined by the developer. However, the developer-
intended purpose may be subverted by the user and a new or extended purpose may be generated.
The notion of “purpose” is meant to encompass all these meanings.
3. Examples here include activity and sleep tracking, in addition to mood-logging and games to test
mental acuity, in an attempt to diagnose conditions such as bipolar disorder and schizophrenia.
4. This also raises privacy and consent issues, which we will look at in “Privacy and confidentiality” and
“Consent.”
5. We explore this issue further in “A case study: Mental health apps.”
6. This also seems to be a violation of consent, even though individuals are usually informed that their
conversations are being recorded for quality purposes.
7. We will take an in-depth look at these kinds of technologies in “A case study: Mental health apps.”
8. A list of conditions addressed by this service is only accessible after signing on as a member, but
anyone can join at https://www.7cups.com/member/.
9. It is possible that Europe, with its stronger privacy laws (European Union 1995), may actually pro-
hibit the sharing of identifiable information of users. This illustrates the complexity of privacy con-
siderations with a technology* that is not in any way geographically contained.
10. One of the authors experienced several presumed trolling experiences while acting as a listener.
11. Instructions on how to deal with trolling events are only accessible after one has signed into one’s
listener account. We therefore cannot provide a URL citation here. However, anyone can sign up as a
listener (7 Cups of Tea 2016d).
12. Heidegger himself was concerned that technology may convert people into things that are measur-
able and can be manipulated, thus ultimately reducing beings to not-beings.
102 1
References
7 Cups of Teas (2016a). FAQ. Available from: http://www.7cups.com/about/faq.php [accessed April
4, 2016].
7 Cups of Tea (2016b). Listener Agreement. Available from: https://www.7cups.com/inc/listenerTOS.
html [accessed April 12, 2016].
7 Cups of Tea (2016c). Listener Reputation. Available from: https://www.7cups.com/about/
faqBadgesCheers.php [accessed April 5, 2016].
7 Cups of Tea (2016d). Listener Signup. Available from: https://www.7cups.com/listener/CreateAccount.
php [accessed April 13, 2016].
7 Cups of Tea (2016e). Privacy Policy. Available from: http://www.7cups.com/memberAgreement.php
[accessed April 5, 2016].
7 Cups of Tea (2016f). Start Feeling Better Today! Enroll in the 7 Cups Self-Harm: Safer Solutions Path.
Available from: https://www.7cups.com/backus/upgrade7cups_19.php [accessed April 14, 2016].
7 Cups of Tea (2016g). Support Desk. Available from: http://www.7cups.com/supportDesk.php [accessed
April 4, 2016].
9Solutions (n. d.). Products. Available from: http://www.9solutions.com/home [accessed February
24, 2016].
Akkad, A., Jackson, C., Kenyon, S., Dixon-Woods, M., Taub, N., and Habiba, M. (2006). Patients’
perceptions of written consent: questionnaire study. BMJ, 333(7567), 528.
Alba, D. (2015a, November 20). How smartphone apps can treat bipolar disorder and schizophrenia.
Wired Magazine. Available from: http://www.wired.com/2014/11/mental-health-apps/ [accessed
April 3, 2015].
Alba, D. (2015b, January 15). This wearable helps you quit smoking by dosing you with nicotine. Wired
Magazine. Available from: http://www.wired.com/2015/01/chrono-therapeutics/ [accessed April
14, 2016].
American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (5th
ed.). Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Publishing.
Apple Inc. (2015). Apple Introduces ResearchKit, Giving Medical Researchers the Tools to Revolutionize
Medical Studies. Available from: https://www.apple.com/pr/library/2015/03/09Apple-Introduces-
ResearchKit-Giving-Medical-Researchers-the-Tools-to-Revolutionize-Medical-Studies.html
[accessed January 22, 2016].
Apple Inc. (2016). Health; An innovative way to use your health and fitness information. Available
from: http://www.apple.com/ios/health/ [accessed January 22, 2016].
Banerjee, T., Anantharam, P., Romine, W.L., and Lawhorne, L.W. (2015). Evaluating a Potential
Commercial Tool for Healthcare Application for People with Dementia. Available from: https://drive.
google.com/file/d/0By39GGXx-P9NR29MeUx3b19abDQ/view?pref=2&pli=1 [accessed April 13, 2016].
Baumel, A. (2015). Online emotional support delivered by trained volunteers: users’ satisfaction and
their perception of the service compared to psychotherapy. Journal of Mental Health, 24(5), 313–320.
Belknap, R., Weis, S., Brookens, A., et al. (2013). Feasibility of an ingestible sensor-based system for
monitoring adherence to tuberculosis therapy” PloS One, 8(1), e53373.
Bohn, D. (2016, January 5). Samsung’s new fridge can order Fresh Direct groceries from its humongous
touchscreen. The Verge. Available from: http://www.theverge.com/2016/1/5/10708380/samsung-
family-hub-fridge-mastercard-app-groceries-ces-2016 [accessed April 12, 2016].
Bonnington, C. (2014, January 28). Turn your smartphone into the ultimate fitness tracker. Wired.
Available from: http://www.wired.com/2014/01/smartphone-fitness-tracker/ [accessed April 12, 2016].
103
References 103
Boudway, I. (2014, June 6). Is Chris Dancy the most quantified self in America? Bloomberg News.
Available from: http://www.bloomberg.com/bw/articles/2014-06-05/is-chris-dancy-the-most-
quantified-self-in-america [accessed April 11, 2016].
Breakthrough (2016). We Cover Most Insurance Plans. Available from: https://www.breakthrough.com/
how-it-works/insurance [accessed April 22, 2016].
Cavazos, J., Girouard, M., and Whitmire, L. (2015). Novel ambulatory EMG-based GTC seizure
detection device for home & hospital use (I6-4B). Neurology, 84, 14 Supplement.
Cho, M.K., Magnus, D., Constantine, M., et al. (2015). Attitudes toward risk and informed consent
for research on medical practices: a cross-sectional survey. Annals of Internal Medicine, 162(10),
690–696.
Church, G.M. (2005). The personal genome project. Molecular Systems Biology, 1(1).
Cipriani, J. (2016, January 6). Lawsuit says Fitbit fitness trackers are inaccurate. Fortune. Available
from: http://fortune.com/2016/01/06/fitbit-heart-rate-accuracy-lawsuit/ [accessed March
15, 2016].
Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.
Ecobee (2016). The Smarter Wifi Thermostat with Remote Sensors. Available from: www.ecobee.com
[accessed March 10. 2016].
Edwards, L. (2010). Study Suggests Reliance on GPS May Reduce Hippocampus Function as We Age.
Available from: http://phys.org/news/2010-11-reliance-gps-hippocampus-function-age.html
[accessed April 11, 2016].
Etkin, J. (2016). The hidden cost of personal quantification. Journal of Consumer Research, 42(6),
967–984. Available from: https://jcr.oxfordjournals.org/content/early/2016/03/04/jcr.ucv095.full
[accessed April 11, 2016].
European Commission (2014). Factsheet EU-US Negotiations on Data Protection. Available from: http://
ec.europa.eu/justice/data-protection/files/factsheets/umbrella_factsheet_en.pdf [accessed April
11, 2016].
European Union (1995). Directive 95/46/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council on the
Protection of Individuals with Regard to the Processing of Personal Data and on the Free Movement of
Such Data, 24 October. Available from: http://www.refworld.org/docid/3ddcc1c74.html [accessed
April 18, 2016].
FDA (2013). Guidance for Industry Oversight of Clinical Investigations—A Risk-Based Approach to
Monitoring. Available from: http://www.fda.gov/downloads/Drugs/.../Guidances/UCM269919.pdf
[accessed January 12, 2016].
FDA (2014). Is the Product a Medical Device? Available from: http://www.fda.gov/MedicalDevices/
DeviceRegulationandGuidance/Overview/ClassifyYourDevice/ucm051512.htm [accessed March
22, 2016].
Felt, A.P., Ha, E., Egelman, S., Haney, A., Chin, E., and Wagner, D. (2012). Android permissions: user
attention, comprehension, and behavior. In: Proceedings of the Eighth Symposium on Usable Privacy
and Security, p.3, ACM. Washington, DC, July 11–13.
Folkins, C.H. and Sime, W.E. (1981). Physical fitness training and mental health. American Psychologist,
36(4), 373–389.
Garbarino, J. and Mason, C.E. (2016). The power of engaging citizen scientists for scientific progress.
Journal of Microbiology & Biology Education, 17(1), 7–12.
Geddes, J. (2015, January 18). Fitness trackers up to 40% inaccurate: Fitbit, Jawbone, Nike, others
tested in new study, which performed best? Tech Times. Available from: http://www.techtimes.com/
articles/27248/20150118/fitness-trackers-up-to-40-inaccurate-fitbit-jawbone-nike-others-tested-in-
new-study-which-performed-best.htm [accessed February 12, 2016].
104 1
Geddes, L. (2016, January 27). Wearable sweat sensor paves way for real-time analysis of body
chemistry. Nature News. Available from: http://www.nature.com/news/wearable-sweat-sensor-
paves-way-for-real-time-analysis-of-body-chemistry-1.19254 [accessed April 13, 2016].
Gigerenzer, G. (2007). Gut Feelings: The Intelligence of the Unconscious. New York: Penguin.
Google Play (2016). 7 Cups of Tea. Available from: https://play.google.com/store/apps/details?id=com.
sevencupsoftea.app&hl=en [accessed April 12, 2016].
Greene, J.A. (2016). Do-it-yourself medical devices—technology and empowerment in american health
care. New England Journal of Medicine, 374(4), 305–308.
Haslam, C. (2015). Counting Sheep: The Best Sleep Trackers and Monitors. Available from: http://www.
wareable.com/withings/best-sleep-trackers-and-monitors [accessed April 14, 2016].
Heidegger, M. (1953). An Introduction to Metaphysics. [Manheim, R., trans, in 1959.] New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
Hodson, H. (2014, May 7). Speech analyser monitors emotion for call centres. New Scientist. Available
from: https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg22229683-800-speech-analyser-monitors-emotion-
for-call-centres/ [accessed March 31, 2016].
iClarified (2014, January 6). Withing Unveils the First Active Sleep System “Aura. Available from: http://
www.iclarified.com/37345/withings-unveils-the-first-active-smart-sleep-system-aura [accessed
February 22, 2016].
Illes, J., Kirschen, M.P., Edwards, E., et al. (2008). Practical approaches to incidental findings in brain
imaging research. Neurology, 70(5), 384–390.
iTunes App Store (2016a). 7Cups of Tea. Available from: https://itunes.apple.com/us/app/7-cups-
anxiety-stress-depression/id921814681?mt=8 [accessed April 11, 2016].
iTunes App Store (2016b). ReachOut Breathe. Available from: https://itunes.apple.com/us/app/reachout-
breathe/id985891649?mt=8 [accessed April 14, 2016].
iTunes App Store (2016c). What’s My M3. Available from: https://itunes.apple.com/us/app/whatsmym3/
id515945611?mt=8 [accessed April 13, 2016].
Jacobson, R. (2014, November 1). 10 mobile apps that deliver advice and therapy. Scientific American.
Available from: http://www.scientificamerican.com/article/10-mobile-apps-that-deliver-advice-and-
therapy/[accessed December 10, 2015].
Jeffrey, C. (2014, July 18). Vive aims to help avoid alcohol fueled social dangers” gizmag. Available
from: http://www.gizmag.com/vive-bracelet-concept/32993 [accessed April 13, 2106].
Kaye, K. (2014). FTC: Fitness Apps Can Help You Shred Calories—and Privacy. Available from: http://
adage.com/article/privacy-and-regulation/ftc-signals-focus-health-fitness-data-privacy/293080/
[accessed April 3, 2016].
Kelty, C. and Panofsky, A. (2014). Disentangling public participation in science and biomedicine.
Genome Medicine, 6(1), 8.
Kolibree (2016). Meet Kolibree: The Fun, Intelligent & Beautiful Tootbrush. Available from: https://www.
kolibree.com/en/ [accessed April 2, 2016].
Lamas, D. (2014, August 4). Virtual therapy expanding mental health care. Boston Globe, Available
from: http://www.bostonglobe.com/lifestyle/health-wellness/2014/08/03/virtual-therapy-sessions-
make-mental-health-care-more-widely-available/t5kWYFmQP609BohewW3HuK/story.html
[accessed April 13, 2016].
Lamkin, P. (2015). Fitness Tracker Market to Top $5bn by 2019. Available from: http://www.wareable.
com/fitness-trackers/fitness-tracker-market-to-top-dollar-5-billion-by-2019-995 [accessed January
12, 2016].
Leavitt, N. (2011). Mobile security: finally a serious problem? Computer, 44(6), 11–14.
105
References 105
Lehmkuhle, M., Elwood, M., Wheeler, J., Fisher, J., and Dudek, F.E. (2015). Development of Discrete,
Wearable EEG Device for Counting Seizures. Available from: https://www.aesnet.org/meetings_
events/annual_meeting_abstracts/view/2327785 [accessed April 3, 2016].
Leonard, A. (2014). Wearable technology that hurts you on purpose. Available from: http://www.salon.
com/2014/07/23/wearable_technology_that_hurts_you_on_purpose/ [accessed April 11, 2016].
Loria, K. (2016, March 2). Therapists have created a virtual reality ‘heroin cave’ in an attempt to help
addicts. Tech Insider. Available from: http://www.techinsider.io/university-of-houston-heroin-cave-
virtual-reality-2016-3 [accessed April 20, 2016].
Lufkin, B. (2014). A psychologist in Y combinator, and his controversial mission to revolutionize
therapy. Fast Company. Available from: http://www.fastcompany.com/3026967/a-psychologist-in-y-
combinator-and-his-controversial-mission-to-revolutionize-therapy [accessed February 6, 2016].
Lupton, D. (2013). Quantifying the body: monitoring and measuring health in the age of mHealth
technologies. Critical Public Health, 23(4), 393–403.
Luxton, D.D., McCann, R.A., Bush, N.E., Mishkind, M.C., and Reger, G.M. (2011). mHealth
for mental health: Integrating smartphone technology in behavioral healthcare. Professional
Psychology: Research and Practice, 42(6), 505–512.
McNeal, G.S. (2015, February 4). Health insurer Anthem struck by massive data breach. Forbes Online.
Available from: http://www.forbes.com/sites/gregorymcneal/2015/02/04/massive-data-breach-at-
health-insurer-anthem-reveals-social-security-numbers-and-more/ [accessed April 3, 2016].
Melnyk, B.M. (2007, April/May). The child & adolescent mental health crisis: closing the service gap.
Imprint. Available from: http://www.nsna.org/Portals/0/Skins/NSNA/pdf/Imprint_AprMay07_Feat_
Child.pdf [accessed April 2, 2016].
Minassian, A., Henry, B.L., Geyer, M.A., Paulus, M.P., Young, J.W., and Perry, W. (2010). The
quantitative assessment of motor activity in mania and schizophrenia. Journal of Affective Disorders,
120(1–3), 200–206.
PatientsLikeMe (n.d.). Help Center. Available from: https://support.patientslikeme.com/hc/en-us/
articles/201245750-How-does-PatientsLikeMe-make-money [accessed March 5, 2016].
Pugh, C. (2015, June 16). A plate that can count your calories and more. Huffington Post Blog [Blog
post]. Available from: http://www.huffingtonpost.com/caroline-pugh/a-plate-that-can-count-yo_b_
7548948.html [accessed April 18, 2016].
Roepke, A.M., Jaffee, S.R., Riffle, O.M., McGonigal, J., Broome, R., and Maxwell, B. (2015).
Randomized controlled trial of SuperBetter, a smartphone-based/Internet-based self-help tool to
reduce depressive symptoms. Games for Health Journal, 4(3), 235–246.
Rosner, G. (2014). Who owns your data? In: Proceedings of the 2014 ACM International Joint Conference
on Pervasive and Ubiquitous Computing: Adjunct Publication, pp. 623–628. ACM. New York, USA.
Rothstein, M.A. (2010). Is deidentification sufficient to protect health privacy in research? American
Journal of Bioethics, 10(9), 3–11.
Samson, K. (2015). Wearing the detectives: wristbands, smartwatches, and other wearable devices allow
for more real-time monitoring of seizures and other neurologic symptoms—and, possibly, more
precise treatment. Neurology Now, 11(4), 34–36.
Sanicola, L. (2015). The Fitbit for the Mind. Available from: https://www.linkedin.com/pulse/fitbit-
mind-lenny-sanicola?trk=prof-post&trkSplashRedir=true&forceNoSplash=true [accessed April
4, 2016].
Sarasohn-Kahn, J. (2008). The Wisdom of Patients: Health are Meets Online Social Media. Available
from: http://www.chcf.org/publications/2008/04/the-wisdom-of-patients-health-care-meets-online-
social-media [accessed January 5, 2016].
106 1
Schüll, N.D. (2016). Data for life: wearable technology and the design of self-care. BioSocieties. Available
from: http://www.palgrave-journals.com/biosoc/journal/vaop/ncurrent/abs/biosoc201547a.html
[accessed March 30, 2016].
Siu, A.L., Bibbins-Domingo, K., Grossman, D.C., et al. (2016). Screening for depression in adults: US
Preventive Services Task Force recommendation statement. JAMA, 315(4), 380–387.
Siu, A.L. and US Preventive Services Task Force (2016). Screening for depression in children
and adolescents: US Preventive Services Task Force recommendation statement. Pediatrics,
137(3), 1–8.
Smith, C.F., Williamson, D.A., Bray, G.A., and Ryan, D.H. (1999). Flexible vs. rigid dieting
strategies: relationship with adverse behavioral outcomes. Appetite, 32(3), 295–305.
Stables, J. (2016). Best Fitness Trackers 2016: Jawbone, Misfit, Fitbit, Garmin and More. Available
from: http://www.wareable.com/fitness-trackers/the-best-fitness-tracker [accessed April 12, 2016].
Stanford Medicine (2016). My Heart Counts iPhone Application. Available from: https://med.stanford.
edu/myheartcounts.html [accessed December 19, 2015].
Sutner, S. (2016). Physicians, Patients Benefit From Wearable Activity Trackers. Available from: http://
searchhealthit.techtarget.com/feature/Physicians-patients-benefit-from-wearable-activity-trackers
[accessed April 2, 2016].
Swan, M. (2013). The quantified self: fundamental disruption in big data science and biological
discovery. Big Data, 1(2), 85–99.
US Department of Health and Human Services (2003). Protecting Personal Health Information in
Research: Understanding the HIPAA Privacy Rule. Available from: http://privacyruleandresearch.nih.
gov/pdf/HIPAA_Booklet_4-14-2003.pdf [accessed December 6, 2015].
US Department of Health and Human Services (2009). Mandatory Reporters of Child Abuse and
Neglect. Available from: http://www.childwelfare.gov/systemwide/laws_policies/statutes/manda.cfm
[accessed April 7, 2016].
Voida, S., Matthews, M., Abdullah, S., et al. (2013, September). MoodRhythm: tracking and supporting
daily rhythms. In: Proceedings of the 2013 ACM Conference on Pervasive and Ubiquitous Computing
Adjunct Publication, pp.67–70. ACM, Zurich, Switzerland.
Wagner, B., Horn, A.B., and Maercker, A. (2014). Internet-based versus face-to-face cognitive-
behavioral intervention for depression: a randomized controlled non-inferiority trial. Journal of
affective disorders, 152, 113–121.
Walker, J. (2015, January 5). Can a smartphone tell if you’re depressed? The Wall Street Journal.
Available from: http://www.wsj.com/articles/can-a-smartphone-tell-if-youre-depressed-
1420499238?cb=logged0.14367316628029903 [accessed February 23, 2016].
Wearable Technologies (2016). Innovation World Cup Series. Available from: http://www.
innovationworldcup.com/2016/01/the-wt-wearable-technologies-innovation-world-cup-crowned-
the-six-most-innovative-wearable-companies/ [accessed March 24, 2016].
Wilson, T.D. (2004). Strangers to Ourselves. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Winter, C. (2014, February 26). Personal sleep monitors: do they work? Huffington Post Blog [Blog
post]. Available from: http://www.huffingtonpost.com/dr-christopher-winter/sleep-tips_b_4792760.
html [accessed April 18, 2016].
Wolf, G. (2009, June 22). Know thyself: tracking every facet of life, from sleep to mood to pain, 24/7/
365. Wired Magazine. Available from: http://www.wired.com/2009/06/lbnp-knowthyself/ [accessed
December 1, 2015].
World Health Organization (1992). The ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioural
Disorders: Clinical Descriptions and Diagnostic Guidelines. Geneva: World Health Organization.
107
References 107
Zheng, Y.L., Ding, X.R., Poon, C.C.Y., et al. (2014). Unobtrusive sensing and wearable devices for
health informatics. IEEE Transactions on Biomedical Engineering, 61(5), 1538–1554.
Zinko, C. (2015, July 3). Seen: partygoers in Thync to alter moods. SFGate. Available from: http://www.
sfgate.com/entertainment/article/Seen-Partygoers-in-Thync-to-alter-moods-6363869.php#photo-
8248816 [accessed April 5, 2016].
108 1
Chapter 6
Introduction
One of the primary concerns of the field of neuroethics has been the sanctity of the mind.
Whether the worry is over others gaining access to a person’s most private thoughts or
manipulating memories, increasing cognitive abilities beyond species-typical functioning
or the authenticity of modern life, the recurring ethical issues center around the question
of whether people are masters of their own destinies. The progress that has been made in
exploring this fascinating terrain has been substantial, as evidenced by the growing matu-
rity of the field. Yet even while making great strides in defending the boundaries of what is
neuroethically acceptable, many people seem to be yielding the sanctity of their minds to
the convenience of modern devices. People do not rely only upon their 3-pound brains to
navigate the world that surrounds them. Increasingly, a substantial portion of the popula-
tion is blending their cognitive space with the algorithmic devices that are nearly always
at hand. It is time that we recognize these devices as technologies of the extended mind
(TEMs) (Fitz & Reiner 2016; Nagel et al. 2016).
he carries with him in his breast pocket. When he hears about the exhibition, he consults
his notebook, finds that the museum is on 53rd Street, and, just like Inga, sets off for the
same destination. The similarity between the two situations should now be obvious: the
cognitive function of storing information is mediated by neurons in one case and pen and
paper in the other.
From this example, Clark and Chalmers develop the parity principle, asserting that if a
process that unfolds in the external world would readily be classified as part of the cogni-
tive toolkit when it goes on in the head, then it is, at least for that point in time, part of
the cognitive process. Using the parity principle as a guide, Clark and Chalmers assert the
equivalence of neuronal memory and paper memory as information storage strategies in
the case of Otto and Inga.
The claims of the EMH are radical, and it remains a highly contentious theory in philos-
ophy of mind (Adams & Aizawa 2001, 2010; Rupert 2004, 2013; Menary 2010). However,
one need not fully accept the philosophical premise to appreciate that the concept reso-
nates with a key feature of modern life: the growing sense that computers and smart-
phones (and soon “the Internet of Things”) function as sophisticated extensions of the
modern cognitive toolkit, even more so than Otto’s dog-eared notebook. Moreover, rather
than relying upon the parity principle to guide thinking in this regard, we will provide
further specification on the features and uses of these algorithmic devices that serve to
qualify them as TEMs.
other than the brain contributing to mind. Such formulations represent direct chal-
lenges to the hard neuroessentialist perspective which, one of us has argued, suggests
that there is no need to include anything other than the brain (Reiner 2011). Yet, as
we shall see below, once one begins to give due consideration to things outside of the
brain—in particular TEMs—it becomes difficult to conclude that they are not being
deployed in the service of thinking. In this view, mental processes and mind cannot
be fully reduced to cognitive processes, as they also refer to the plethora of affective,
motivational, and social resources that can influence thinking and go beyond it in vari-
ous ways. While many current TEMs aim at the extension of cognitive processes, this is
by no means a principal constraint; to the contrary, design might explicitly focus on an
extension of affective processes as well.
Having provided some conceptual clarity over what constitutes mind, we now address
the question of what sorts of devices are TEMs. It is not the case that every algorithmic
function carried out by devices external to the brain qualifies them as a TEM, but rather
that there is a relatively seamless interaction between brain and algorithm such that a per-
son perceives of the algorithm as being a bona fide extension of a person’s mind. This raises
the bar for inclusion into the category of algorithms that might be considered TEMs. It is
also the case that algorithmic functions that do not qualify as TEMs today may do so at
some future point in time and vice versa.
By way of illustration, consider the use of GPS in a smartphone, an example we have
previously described in Nagel et al. (2016). Imagine a 35-year-old man John who has
lived in Manhattan for the past decade. John has rarely driven a car since he moved to
New York, as he now relies heavily on the subway or taxis to get about town. But John
recently had a baby and needs a bit of extra income, so he asks his brother whether he
thinks he could become a driver for Uber, a company that enables non-professionals to
act as taxi drivers using their own vehicles. His brother, who has been making a fair bit
of money doing just that over the past year, is quite encouraging and even offers John the
use of his car in the evenings when it is idle. John signs up and within a week finds himself
behind the wheel of his brother’s car, answering calls for Uber drivers to come and ferry
people all over New York City.
In the normal course of events, Uber drivers are highly reliant on GPS. On his very first
day, John, an avid user of computer technology, is fascinated by how easy it is to enter
addresses into his smartphone and have it show him the best route to his passengers’
destinations. It is particularly helpful because otherwise John would often find himself
lost, as many of his fares lead him to visit neighborhoods with which he is unfamiliar. Of
course, John has heard stories that sometimes GPS can lead you to the wrong place, so he
remains alert to his environment in order to be certain that he delivers his passengers to
their destination without a hitch.
Is John’s GPS functioning as a TEM? It is certainly carrying out computational work
that is external to John’s brain. But it is probably most appropriate to consider the GPS
in John’s smartphone as cognitive support, for neither the algorithmic calculations nor
John’s reliance upon them are seamlessly integrated with John’s mind.
1
Now imagine that a week or two has passed. John has taken dozens of passengers to
their destinations. Even though he now knows the city a bit better than before, he always
uses the GPS in his smartphone, and it has not let him down even once. At this point,
when he enters an address and the route flashes up on the screen, he doesn’t give it a
moment’s notice before following it to the destination suggested by his smartphone. The
GPS now functions very much as a TEM, for John has integrated its algorithmic output
into the working of his mind.
Much as neuroessentialism challenges traditional views of how people view themselves
(Reiner 2011), conceiving of the mind as a blend between brain and algorithm poses a
challenge to a range of existing worldviews. At one end of the spectrum, if one is troubled
attempting to reconcile concepts of ensoulment with mechanistic explanations of how the
brain works (Bering 2006; Farah & Murphy 2009; Preston et al. 2013), the realization that
an algorithm is now an extension of one’s mind makes the issue even more problematic.
At the other end of the spectrum, the very same mechanistic explanations of brain func-
tion that lead to the position that “we are our brains” (Greene & Cohen 2004; Roskies
2007; Reiner 2011) are somewhat destabilized by the emerging reality of TEMs. For these
reasons, people may very well resist the disruptive concept of TEMs. However, the intru-
sion of algorithms upon daily life seems relentless, and in much the same way as John’s
GPS transitioned from external computational algorithm to bona fide TEM, we envision
this concept becoming an emergent meme, with an ever-growing share of the population
perceiving of their devices as TEMs, even if they do not explicitly conceptualize them
as such.
The neuroethical issues
The neuroethical issues engendered by the EMH were first brought to light by Neil Levy
in a prescient paper published in 2007 (Levy 2007). At the time, he allowed that the EMH
was an obscure debate, but nonetheless suggested that it had substantial implications for
the field. He points out that part of what makes neuroethics a discipline is the claim,
sometimes explicit but nearly always implicit, that there is something different about
intervening in the brain, that such interventions are different than traditional means of
altering mental states. Levy suggests that if one accepts the EMH, the exceptionalism that
is normally offered to worries about intrusions, manipulations, and surveillance of mental
states in the brain naturally flow to the extended mind as well. He sums the situation up
nicely in his concluding paragraph:
These reflections on the prima facie parity between environmental manipulations and new tech-
nologies may seem to reduce the importance of neuroethics. On the contrary, I think that it dra-
matically increases it. It might seem that the extended mind thesis entails that neuroethics is less
important inasmuch as, in its light, it becomes apparent that neurological interventions into the
mind—that is, interventions that target neurons, neurotransmitters or brain structures—are not
after all so special: they represent merely the latest means of doing something that is quite ubiq-
uitous in human cultures. Although it is true that the extended mind thesis may dampen some of
the hype surrounding these technologies, it should be seen as dramatically expanding the scope of
12 1
neuroethics, not detracting from its importance. Neuroethics focuses ethical thought on the physi-
cal substrate subserving cognition, but if we accept that this substrate includes not only brains, but
also material culture, and even social structures, we see that neuroethical concern should extend
far more widely than has previously been recognized. In light of the extended mind thesis, a great
many questions that are not usually seen as falling within its purview—questions about social pol-
icy, about technology, about food and even about entertainment—can be seen to be neuroethical
issues. (Levy 2007)
We agree with Levy that the EMH has profound implications for our thinking about neu-
roethics. Three issues are particularly worthy of further elaboration: the threat to auton-
omy posed by manipulation of our TEMs, the threat to privacy of thought by peering
into TEMs, and the relevance of TEMs to questions regarding cognitive enhancement.
Each has changed substantially in the decade since Levy’s paper, a decade in which adop-
tion of smartphones as ubiquitous computing has moved from concept to reality. This
development is worth highlighting, as it seems to be more than just another technology,
but rather has been a major influence that shapes our technological surroundings. Other
influences are and will be relevant, but the prevalence of smartphones—nearly half the
adult population on the planet has one (Pew Research Center 2016)—and our readiness
to rely on them is certainly remarkable. These features make it a useful example with
which to explore some of the neuroethical issues associated with TEMs.
Autonomy
The concept of autonomy is foundational to modern thinking about who we are as sen-
tient beings. Particularly since the Enlightenment, Western societies have largely accepted
the position that we—and only we—have the right to determine the course of our lives.
Autonomy underpins many of the most celebrated political and social movements of
modernity. In human rights, it is autonomy that beckons us to consider the needs and
desires of the individual as having primacy. In politics, autonomy is the firmament upon
which democratic governance rests. Autonomy shows no signs of losing its appeal, con-
tinually forcing us to modify our practices. This is best exemplified in the medical realm
in which modern bioethical principles have invoked the concept of autonomy to pro-
duce a sea change in the way that physicians and their patients interact (Beauchamp &
Childress 2012).
A fundamental feature of the concept of autonomy is that the autonomous individ-
ual should not be unduly influenced when making decisions (Frankfurt 1971; Dworkin
1981). One need look no further than the ideal of the rugged individualist who navigates
their environment relying on nothing more than his or her wits to see how this works.
In this common trope, the autonomy of decision-making by the individual is held as sac-
rosanct, and any infringement is considered a violation. It turns out that this picture of
humans as self-sufficient rational actors who live their lives independently of others is
at substantial variance with how people actually live in the real world. Rather, decisions
are regularly influenced by the input of others, whether it is in the form of the books and
newspapers that we read, the opinions of people that we listen to, or other features of the
13
social and physical environment around us. Recognizing this, feminist and communitar-
ian scholars have updated the concept, developing variants on what is commonly known
as relational autonomy (Nedelsky 1989; Friedman 2003; Christman 2004; Meyers 2005;
Mackenzie 2010). The relational account of autonomy suggests that when people make
decisions, they often admit input from friends, family, colleagues, or professionals. That
this occurs without demurral complicates the calculus for evaluating when an external
influence might be considered due and undue. Indeed, “representing these two sorts of
effects with roughly accurate proportionality is, however, a formidable project [since]
matters of degree are notoriously difficult to specify philosophically” (Friedman 2003).
If it is a struggle to determine what influences are due and undue in the context of input
from other people, the task is even more complicated when we consider the influence of
TEMs upon these very same decisions. Before we do so, it is worth considering the general
features of algorithms that might modify the degree to which an influence is perceived as
violating autonomy. We have suggested that three factors are key: (1) the persuasiveness
of the algorithm in the decision-making process, (2) the seriousness of the decision, and
(3) the ability for the algorithm to learn about user preferences (Nagel et al. 2016).
Persuasiveness seems to be a central feature of technological autonomy violations.
Decision-making can be influenced across a spectrum ranging from minimally to highly
persuasive, and can even turn into being coercive (Fogg 2002; Verbeek 2006, 2009). If the
ability to thoughtfully engage in the decision-making process and to reflect on the situ-
ation is ensured, the influence of the technology will not be perceived as a particularly
problematic autonomy violation, as self-control does not seem to be harmed.
The seriousness of the decision also varies across a spectrum that differs depending
upon the level of potential harm or benefit an individual may experience as a result of a
particular choice. The lower the assumed potential harms or benefits, the lower the per-
ceived seriousness of the decision. Imagine for a moment the grave real-world situation of
an individual grappling with the decision of whether to undergo a course of chemother-
apy that will briefly extend his or her life by some weeks but will compromise the quality
of those weeks substantially. Many such patients consult—and trust—online resources to
help them evaluate the relative risks and benefits. Under such circumstances, even a small
misstep in influence can result in a substantial autonomy violation.
The ability to learn about user preferences is important, as it makes a great difference
as to whether a system only follows a set of preprogrammed instructions or is able to
monitor individual behaviors and preferences and learns from them. If we return to the
situation of the individual confronting the decision of whether to embark upon a course
of chemotherapy, we can easily imagine two versions of the online resource. In the static
version where the information that is found online is offered by an unknown designer,
the opportunity for the designers’ preferences to be unwittingly smuggled into the algo-
rithmic calculation is high, and the possibility that an autonomy infraction may occur
not insubstantial. A more dynamic version would have the underlying algorithm learn
something about the preferences of the user and then provide advice accordingly. Since
the algorithm has learned at least something about the user’s worldview, the advice that
14 1
it offers might better be tailored to their second-order desires, and the likelihood of an
autonomy violation diminished.
Having laid the groundwork for our thinking about the issue, we turn our attention to
an example in which the external technology is a TEM. We will use a simple and rela-
tively trivial example to illustrate the relevant issues, but the reader can readily imagine
how modifying persuasiveness, seriousness, and learning user preferences can affect the
degree of perceived autonomy violation.
To begin, consider an algorithm that is not a TEM, for example, the GPS app on John’s
smartphone in the example described in the previous section. Imagine that on the first
evening that John used the GPS function (i.e., before it has transitioned into being a TEM),
John passes a billboard advertising a bakery. Pushing the bounds of current practice (but
only slightly), let’s also imagine the smartphone calls attention to the billboard and alerts
John to the fact that the bakery is just up ahead; sealing the deal, the smartphone “asks” if
John wishes to drop in to get something sweet. John is tempted, and although he likes to
manage his intake of sugar, he decides that there would be little harm. A moment later he
stops at the bakery, purchases a donut, and soon is smiling as he tastes the sugary treat. In
this scenario, the GPS program has clearly influenced John, sufficiently so that he altered
his second-order desires about his food intake. Many people would call such an influ-
ence undue and, despite the relative triviality of the infraction, the situation represents an
autonomy violation of sorts.
Now let us imagine that 2 weeks have passed, and the relationship between John and
the GPS app has grown more intimate—John now integrates its algorithmic output into
the working of his mind while driving his Uber cab. For all intents and purposes, the GPS
algorithm is now functioning as a TEM. Of course, because John carries his smartphone
everywhere, the device gathers a fair bit of information about his daily activities, and the
abilities that this confers on the smartphone only serve to reinforce the feeling that the
suite of apps on the phone are functioning as a more-or-less unified TEM. It requires little
in the way of stretching credulity to imagine that the GPS might not only call attention
to a billboard alongside the road, but having “consulted” a database that indicates that
John frequently shops at an organic grocery store, instead of suggesting that John get
something sweet, the smartphone now suggests that he may wish to get a piece of organic
blueberry pie. Adding to the persuasiveness of the suggestion, the GPS program on his
smartphone—which also monitors his activity levels during the day—reminds John that
he went for a 5K run this morning and can probably afford the calories. A few minutes
later, John is smiling as he enjoys a forkful of delicious pie. Once again, the GPS program
has influenced John, sufficiently that he altered his second-order desires about his food
intake. But given that the suggestions are aligned with John’s overall desire to eat organic
food, and that they include at least a rough calculation on calories burned earlier in the
day, does the persuasive influence of the GPS app represent an autonomy violation?
The difference between the two scenarios described above depends to a substantial
degree on how John perceives the algorithmic device that accompanies him everywhere.
As his relationship to the smartphone becomes closer, as both he and device provide
15
information that the other uses to help them navigate the world around them and John
perceives more and more that he relies on the program’s advice, the device increasingly
becomes an integral part of his extended mind. Given the considerations from relational
autonomy, the influence of the smartphone on John’s behavior in the second scenario
appears to be less “undue” than it was in the first instance. In this view, the more that
devices become TEMs, the likelihood that their advice results in perceived autonomy
violations diminishes.
However, there is something missing from this description, and that is that the very
same algorithm that is an extension of John’s mind is also an extension of the mind of an
other—in this case the corporate entity that has designed the GPS app. It is not at all out
of the bounds of modern economic activity that the corporate entity would be paid for
directing John to the bakery. Thus, while one objective of that app is to align John’s behav-
ior with his second-order desires, a second objective of another entity is also smuggled
into the relationship. In view of such potential conflicts of interest, it becomes harder to
accept the premise that as our devices become TEMs, autonomy violations become less
likely; if anything, they become more insidious. Serving two masters is certainly part of
the issue, but it is also the case that the privacy implications are impossible to ignore.
Privacy of thought
One of the most controversial topics in neuroethics is the worry over mind reading (Wolpe
et al. 2005; Illes 2006, 2007; Greely & Illes 2007; Parens & Johnston 2014). Frances Shen
has summarized the sentiments of many by suggesting that using advances in neurosci-
ence to access the most private of spaces—our minds—would have tremendous privacy
implications (Shen 2013). Yet despite intriguing insights obtained with functional mag-
netic resonance imaging (Haynes & Rees 2006; Mitchell et al. 2008; Naselaris et al. 2009;
Rissman et al. 2010), it remains difficult to obtain more than a rudimentary profile of
the thoughts of individuals by measuring brain activity (Farah et al. 2009). In contrast, it
seems that a great deal of what might be termed the inner life of the mind may be acces-
sible via the technologies on our desktops, and even more so, in our pockets. Cognizant
that this is a discourse that has encountered more than its fair share of hype, it seems
prudent to consider whether access to our TEMs may represent intrusions upon privacy
of thought.
Such considerations come in the context of the well-known fact that online privacy
is generally under threat. Illegal breaches and over-sharing of digital information have
grown from the occasional to everyday events. While any intrusion on privacy may be
unwelcome, some transgressions are more problematic than others. When others gain
access to information that reflects one’s innermost thoughts, the incursion may go beyond
privacy to intrude upon privacy of thought. Such intrusions have particular normative
significance in neuroethics, and thus our analysis focuses upon this subset of privacy
concerns.
The manifesto establishing the right to privacy was drafted in 1890 by Samuel Warren
and Louis Brandeis (Warren & Brandeis 1890). As influential as it has been in legal circles,
16 1
it is the historical sweep of the article that draws one’s awe. As Warren and Brandeis inci-
sively explain, at one time liberty meant freedom from physical restraint, but as society
increasingly recognized the inner life of individuals, the right to life came to mean the
right to enjoy life, and protection of corporeal property expanded to include protection of
the products of the mind such as literature and art, trademarks, and copyrights. Warren
and Brandeis noted that “recent inventions and business methods call attention to the
next step which must be taken for the protection of the person.” In 1890, their worry was
the intrusiveness of photographers, but more generally their article suggested that as tech-
nology changes, societal norms might require updating. In the modern world, in which
information all-too-readily moves online, we appear to be overdue for just such a review.
Legal arguments support such a view. Pointing out that under the third-party doctrine
“an individual does not have a reasonable expectation of privacy with respect to informa-
tion he voluntarily discloses to a third party, like a bank or a telecommunications carrier,”
Wittes and Chong suggest that the third-party doctrine is ill-suited to the modern situa-
tion in which devices generate data about their users (Wittes & Chong 2014). In a chilling
demonstration of how much information is contained within metadata—the data about
the numbers we call, or where our phone is at a particular moment, who we e-mail and
the subject lines of those messages, our search queries and the websites we visit—Ton
Siedsma, a researcher at the Dutch digital rights foundation Bits of Freedom, allowed an
app on his cellphone to collect such metadata for 1 week (Tokmetzis 2014). The limited
analysis of this information revealed not only Ton’s circles of friends and the like, but also
the types of information included in his search queries. That Ton might have an interest
in bicycles is fairly innocuous, but what if he was searching for information about antide-
pressants or gender reassignment surgery, and these were topics that were in his head, but
he had not—and more importantly did not wish to discuss with others?
Just such a situation is described by Wittes and Lui when alerting us to the fact that “the
privacy that consumers value in practice is not always the privacy that activists devoted
to privacy value on their behalf.” To illustrate the matter, they point out that many people
acquire medical information, salacious images, and more online because “they would
rather be tracked online by commercial vendors than have to face parents, teachers, doc-
tors, or the stern-faced old lady at a news stand” (Wittes & Liu 2015). In a similar vein,
Frances Shen reminds us that what he terms the “privacy panic script” unfolds first with
fear mongering regarding the power of technology, followed by the suggestion that insti-
tutions will use the technology in devious ways, and that current laws are insufficient to
protect the average citizen (Shen 2013). These observations suggest that when advocating
in favor of privacy, humility may be in order.
Given these varied interests, we suggest that explicitly recognizing some of our devices
as TEMs may help us in arriving at a more reasonable state of affairs, especially if we arrive
upon a clearer understanding of what we mean by privacy of thought. The philosopher
Michael Lynch, writing as Amicus Curiae in support of the plaintiffs in American Civil
Liberties Union v. James Clapper, the lawsuit that challenged the legality of the National
17
Security Agency’s bulk phone metadata collection program traces the notion of privacy of
thought back to Descartes and Locke, who both held that:
what identifies your thoughts as your thoughts is that you have “privileged access” to them. This
means at least two things. First, you access them in a way I cannot. Even if I could walk a mile in
your shoes, I cannot know what you feel in the same way you can: you see it from the inside, so
to speak. Second, you can, at least sometimes, control what I know about your thoughts. You can
refrain from telling me the extent of your views and your feelings. (Lynch 2013)
In the context of TEMs, these criteria seem appropriate: if you have a private means of
accessing information on your device that is not available to others, and you have the
means of controlling that access, it seems as if you have demonstrated that, in your view,
it is private. The problem arises, of course, when those very same devices are connected to
others by virtue of the ever-present Internet.
To see how this may play out, it is worth recalling the infamous case of the discount
retailer Target and the pregnant teen. By combining metadata that was packaged, bought,
and sold (online, of course) with analysis of something as innocent as the shopping
behavior of young women, Target was able to predict with high accuracy when women
were in their second trimester of pregnancy (Hill 2012). The commercial objective was to
target these potential customers with ads for diapers, baby clothes, and the like, but when
Target did so, customers felt so invaded that they complained (in this case, it was a father
who only discovered his daughter’s pregnancy through this route). So Target modified
their strategy; instead of sending ads just for diapers, etc., they mixed those ads in with
ads for everyday items unrelated to pregnancy just to prevent the perception that they had
invaded their customer’s privacy.
Similar brinkmanship can be seen in the relationship between Facebook and its users.
In a longitudinal study of 5076 Facebook users between 2005 and 2011, Facebook users
increasingly exhibited privacy-seeking behavior, decreasing the amount of personal data
that they shared publicly. At the same time, the amount of personal information they
revealed privately to so-called connected profiles increased. The unintended result was
that disclosures to “silent listeners” on the network—Facebook itself, third-party apps,
and ultimately advertisers—grew. The authors conclude that these findings “highlight the
tension between privacy choices as expressions of individual subjective preferences, and
the role of the environment in shaping those choices” (Stutzman et al. 2012).
From these examples we can see that the networked nature of our TEMs makes them
particularly vulnerable to intrusions upon privacy of thought. While people may take
steps toward increasing the privacy of their online behavior, the corporate entities at the
other end of the phone, as it were, are continually mining these very same actions in an
effort to enhance their competitive position in the world of commerce. What is lost in
the conversation is that along the way, people may perceive of their devices as extensions
of their minds. We suggest that this implicit tagging of Internet-connected algorithmic
devices as TEMs raises the bar for privacy, qualifying the information within the amalgam
of our brains and our devices as private thoughts.
18 1
Cognitive enhancement
Discussion of the propriety of using advanced neurotechnologies to enhance cognitive
abilities has been among the most protracted of debates in neuroethics (Parens 1998;
Farah et al. 2004; Greely et al. 2008). Ethical arguments from different biopolitical posi-
tions (Reiner 2013) have been waged over a number of issues, but the cardinal concerns
of safety, pressure, distributive justice, and authenticity have dominated (Fitz et al. 2014).
In many ways, the debate is more pragmatic than philosophical, and so we will restrict our
comments regarding the implications of TEMs to the cognitive enhancement debate to a
short outline of the relevant issues.
The debate over cognitive enhancement is somewhat compromised by the observation
that the agents that are available today—drugs and electrical stimulation devices—do not
yield the sorts of enhancements that people seek: effect sizes tend to vary from minimal to
none (Farah 2015; Ilieva et al. 2015). As we have recently suggested, this may be because
attempts to bolster cognitive function from within run up against the hard limits of neu-
robiological reality (Fitz & Reiner 2016). Indeed, we suggest that a better strategy is to
rely upon our TEMs to enhance cognitive function, not only because it is more effective
but because we are already well down the road toward “commingling our cognitive space
with technology.”
The question that remains open, and one that merits further normative and empirical
work in the field, is the degree to which considering TEMs as cognitive enhancers settles
debates that have gone on for over a decade now. The answer is likely to be a mixed bag—
the ubiquity of TEMs might help to dispel the distributive justice concern, but concerns
over safety, pressure, and authenticity now morph into new territory. We predict that
exploring these issues with a new technological lens may assist the field in clarifying how
we should move forward, even if it involves playing catch-up to how we live today.
Holzkamp (Holzkamp 1985). Importantly, in this view social embeddedness goes beyond
the direct private relations between and among individuals, reaching out to the various
social institutions that surround and influence us.
Analogously, the modern world with its increasingly technological surroundings defines
us as technologically embedded beings. Consider that today the trajectory of a life begins
surrounded by reproductive technologies and often ends with a different array of medical
technologies easing us into death. Just try to imagine for a moment the technologies that
are around you right now—from the lightbulb above you, to the heat in the corner, to
the smartphone in your pocket. Perhaps you took a drug this morning to help normalize
some bodily function, or maybe you will use a car or bus or train to move from place to
place, or even have a video-chat with a colleague on a different continent. Indeed, humans
rely on a vast array of technologies, and one might argue that they depend upon them—
some of us more, some less. Such is the modern predicament (Scialabba 2011) that it is
hard to hear silence, that many live in fear of the content of their food, that it has become
a common experience to feel estranged from the natural world. No matter how one evalu-
ates being surrounded by and dependent upon technologies, it is fair to say that we are
increasingly embedded by technologies.
It is no surprise then that some of those technologies engage with our cognitive pro-
cesses. Even more: that they serve as TEMs by functioning as part of the mind that resides
outside of the brain. And as the mind is perceived as perhaps the most intimate part of
us, conceptualizing technologies as extensions of the mind deeply challenges the sense of
who we are as humans. The questions Who am I? Am I my brain? Am I my mind? Am
I my relationships? (Haslam 2004; Rose 2005; Feinberg 2006; Glannon 2009; Burwood
2009; Noë 2009; Brand 2010; Brenninkmeijer 2010; Pardo & Patterson 2010; Reiner
2011) are viewed from a different angle when a person recognizes that technologies serve
as a functional part of the self. Ultimately, with this perspective, humans must find a new
mode of being, and consequently a new mode of understanding ourselves and others. For
if our cognitive processes are not restricted to our biological brains, we need to give seri-
ous consideration to their role in our being.
An important result is that the relationship that people have with those devices merits
much closer attention than they have received to date. We might go as far as arguing that
we need to consider TEMs as new actors on the neuroethical stage. Thus, we call for a
new framework for neuroethics that is informed by philosophy of mind which needs to
reconsider how humans conceive of who they are today: What is at stake when studying
neuroethical questions? What is the “substrate” we are dealing with? If we take the nature
of the intertwinement of modern humans with their surroundings seriously—and we
argue that we should—we cannot any longer focus on the human brain as isolated or, at
most, integrated into a body. The body and the brain are not only in constant interaction
with the environment (Varela et al. 1991; Gallagher 2005; Fuchs 2011; Nagel 2015), they
also constantly make use of their surroundings, of significant and non-significant others,
and of technologies. Thus, in this new framework, neuroethics is not so much concerned
with an organ but ultimately with what makes us human beings, and recognizing the
120 1
impact of technology upon what makes us “us” today matters for the relevant questions
in the field.
References
Adams, F. and Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64.
Adams, F. and Aizawa, K. (2010). Defending the bounds of cognition. In: Menary, R. (Ed.) The Extended
Mind, pp.67–80. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F. (2012). Principles of Biomedical Ethics (7th edn.). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Bering, J. (2006). The folk psychology of souls. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29(5), 453–462.
Brand, C. (2010). Am I still me? Personal identity in neuroethical debates. Medicine Studies, 1(4), 393–406.
Brenninkmeijer, J. (2010). Taking care of one’s brain: how manipulating the brain changes people’s
selves. History of the Human Sciences, 23(1), 107–126.
Burwood, S. (2009). Are we our brains? Philosophical Investigations, 32, 113–133.
Christman, J. (2004). Relational autonomy, liberal individualism, and the social constitution of selves.
Philosophical Studies, 117(1), 143–164.
Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.
Dworkin, G. (1981). The concept of autonomy. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 12, 203–213.
Farah, M.J. (2015). The unknowns of cognitive enhancement. Science (New York, NY), 350, 379–380.
Farah, M.J. and Murphy, N. (2009). Neuroscience and the soul. Science (New York, NY),
323(5918), 1168.
Farah, M.J., Illes, J., Cook-Deegan, R., et al. (2004). Neurocognitive enhancement: what can we do and
what should we do? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 5(5), 421–425.
Farah, M.J., Smith, M.E., Gawuga, C., Lindsell, D., and Foster, D. (2009). Brain imaging and brain
privacy: a realistic concern? Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 21(1), 119–127.
Feinberg, T.E. (2006). Our brains, our selves. Dædalus, 135(4), 72–80.
Fitz, N.S. and Reiner, P.B. (2016). Time to expand the mind. Nature, 531, S9.
Fitz, N.S., Nadler, R., Manogaran, P., Cong, E.W.J., and Reiner, P.B. (2014). Public attitudes toward
cognitive enhancement. Neuroethics, 7(2), 173–188.
Fogg, B.J. (2002). Persuasive Technology: Using Computers to Change What We Think and Do. San
Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.
Frankfurt, H.G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy,
68(1), 5–20.
Friedman, M. (2003). Autonomy and social relationships: rethinking the feminist critique.
In: Autonomy, Gender, Politics, pp.81–97. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fuchs, T. (2011). The brain—a mediating organ. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18, 196–221.
Gallagher, S. (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
Glannon, W. (2009). Our brains are not us. Bioethics, 23(6), 321–329.
Greely, H.T. and Illes, J. (2007). Neuroscience-based lie detection: the urgent need for regulation.
American Journal of Law & Medicine, 33(2–3), 377–431.
Greely, H.T., Sahakian, B., Harris, J., et al. (2008). Towards responsible use of cognitive-enhancing
drugs by the healthy. Nature, 456(7223), 702–705.
Greene, J. and Cohen, J. (2004). For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 359(1451), 1775–1785.
12
References 121
Haslam, N. (2004). Essentialist beliefs about personality and their implications. Personality and Social
Psychology Bulletin, 30(12), 1661–1673.
Haynes, J.-D. and Rees, G. (2006). Decoding mental states from brain activity in humans. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience, 7(7), 523–534.
Hill, K. (2012). How Target Figured Out A Teen Girl Was Pregnant Before Her Father Did. Available
from: http://www.forbes.com/sites/kashmirhill/2012/02/16/how-target-figured-out-a-teen-girl-was-
pregnant-before-her-father-did/4/#583f593d34c6 [accessed March 27, 2016].
Holzkamp, K. (1985). Grundlegung der Psychologie. Frankfurt: Campus-Verlag.
Ilieva, I.P., Hook, C.J., and Farah, M.J. (2015). Prescription stimulants’ effects on healthy inhibitory
control, working memory, and episodic memory: a meta-analysis. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience,
27(6), 1069–1089.
Illes, J. (Ed.) (2006). Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory, Practice, and Policy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Illes, J. (2007). Empirical neuroethics. Can brain imaging visualize human thought? Why is neuroethics
interested in such a possibility? EMBO Reports, 8, S57–S60.
Levy, N. (2007). Rethinking neuroethics in the light of the extended mind thesis. American Journal of
Bioethics, 7(9), 3–11.
Lynch, M. (2013). Brief of Michael P. Lynch as Amicus Curiae in Support of the Plaintiffs,
American Civil Liberties Union v. James R. Clapper. Available from: https://www.academia.
edu/4579430/_The_Privacy_Brief_Amicus_Curiae_Brief_in_Support_of_the_ACLU_vs._NSA.
Mackenzie, C. (2010). Imagining oneself otherwise. In: Mackenzie, C. and Stoljar, N. (Eds.)
Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, pp.124–150.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Menary, R. (2010). The Extended Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Meyers, D. (2005). Decentralizing autonomy: five faces of selfhood. In: Christman, J. and Anderson,
J. (Eds.) Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays, pp.27–55. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Mitchell, T.M., Shinkareva, S.V., Carlson, A., et al. (2008). Predicting human brain activity associated
with the meanings of nouns. Science (New York, NY), 320(5880), 1191–1195.
Nagel, S.K. (2015). Thickening descriptions with views from pragmatism and anthropology. In: Metzinger,
T. and Windt, J.M. (Eds.) Open MIND (Vol. 1), pp.829–839. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nagel, S.K., Hrincu, V., and Reiner, P.B. (2016, May 13–14). Algorithm Anxiety—Do Decision-Making
Algorithms Pose a Threat to Autonomy? Presented at 2016 IEEE International Symposium on Ethics
in Engineering, Science and Technology, Vancouver, BC.
Naselaris, T., Prenger, R.J., Kay, K.N., Oliver, M., and Gallant, J.L. (2009). Bayesian reconstruction of
natural images from human brain activity. Neuron, 63(6), 902–915.
Nedelsky, J. (1989). Reconceiving autonomy: sources, thoughts and possibilities. Yale Journal of Law &
Feminism, 1(1), 5.
Noë, A. (2009). Out of Our Heads: Why You Are Not Your Brain, and Other Lessons from the Biology of
Consciousness. New York: Hill and Wang.
Pardo, M.S. and Patterson, D. (2010). Philosophical foundations of law and neuroscience. University of
Illinois Law Review, 5, 1211–1250.
Parens, E. (1998). Enhancing Human Traits: Ethical and Social Implications. Washington,
DC: Georgetown University Press.
Parens, E. and Johnston, J. (2014). Neuroimaging: beginning to appreciate its complexities. Hastings
Center Report, 44(s2), S2–S7.
12
Pew Research Center (2016). Smartphone Ownership and Internet Usage Continues to Climb in Emerging
Economies. Available from: http://www.pewglobal.org/2016/02/22/smartphone-ownership-and-
internet-usage-continues-to-climb-in-emerging-economies/ [accessed January 31, 2017].
Preston, J.L., Ritter, R.S., and Hepler, J. (2013). Neuroscience and the soul: competing explanations for
the human experience. Cognition, 127(1), 31–37.
Reiner, P.B. (2011). The rise of neuroessentialism. In Illes, J. and Sahakian, B.J. (Eds.) Oxford Handbook
of Neuroethics, pp.161–175. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Reiner, P.B. (2013). The biopolitics of cognitive enhancement. In: Hildt, E. and Franke, A. (Eds.)
Cognitive Enhancement: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, pp.189–200. New York: Springer
Science+Business Media.
Rissman, J., Greely, H.T., and Wagner, A.D. (2010). Detecting individual memories through the neural
decoding of memory states and past experience. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of
the United States of America, 107(21), 9849–9854.
Rose, S.P.R. (2005). Human agency in the neurocentric age. EMBO Reports, 6(11), 1001–1005.
Roskies, A.L. (2007). The illusion of personhood. American Journal of Bioethics, 7(1), 55–57.
Rupert, R.D. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101(8),
389–428.
Rupert, R.D. (2013). Distributed cognition and extended mind theory. In: Kaldis, B. (Ed.)
Encyclopedia of Philosophy and the Social Sciences, pp.209–213. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage
Publications Inc.
Scialabba, G. (2011). The Modern Predicament. Boston, MA: Pressed Wafer.
Shen, F.X. (2013). Mind, body, and the criminal law. Minnesota Law Review, 97, 2036–2175.
Stanovich, K.E. (2009). Distinguishing the reflective, algorithmic, and autonomous minds: is it time for
a tri-process theory. In Evans, J. and Frankish, K. (Eds.) In Two Minds: Dual Processes and Beyond,
pp.55–88. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stutzman, F., Gross, R., and Acquisti, A. (2012). Silent listeners: the evolution of privacy and disclosure
on Facebook. Journal of Privacy and Confidentiality, 2, 7–41.
Tokmetzis, D. (2014). How Your Innocent Smartphone Passes on Almost Your Entire Life to the Secret
Service. Available from: https://www.bof.nl/2014/07/30/how-your-innocent-smartphone-passes-on-
almost-your-entire-life-to-the-secret-service/ [accessed March 27, 2016].
Varela, F.J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human
Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Verbeek, P.-P. (2006). Persuasive technology and moral responsibility toward an ethical framework for
persuasive technologies. Persuasive, 6, 1–15.
Verbeek, P.-P. (2009). Ambient intelligence and persuasive technology: the blurring boundaries between
human and technology. NanoEthics, 3(3), 231–242.
Warren, S.D. and Brandeis, L.D. (1890). The right to privacy. Harvard Law Review, 4(5), 193–220.
Wittes, B. and Chong, J. (2014). Our Cyborg Future: Law and Policy Implications. Center for Technology
Innovation at Brookings. Available from: https://www.brookings.edu/research/our-cyborg-future-
law-and-policy-implications/ [accessed January 31, 2017].
Wittes, B. and Liu, J.C. (2015). The Privacy Paradox: The Privacy Benefits of Privacy Threats. Center
for Technology Innovation at Brookings. Available from: https://www.brookings.edu/wp-content/
uploads/2016/06/Wittes-and-Liu_Privacy-paradox_v10.pdf [accessed January 31, 2017].
Wolpe, P., Foster, K., and Langleben, D. (2005). Emerging neurotechnologies for lie-detection: promises
and perils. American Journal of Bioethics, 5(2), 39–49.
123
Chapter 7
Introduction
An expressed aim of brain–computer interface (BCI) or brain–machine interface (BMI)
research is to develop devices that improve lives of people with disabilities (Hochberg and
Anderson 2012; Shih et al. 2012; Murphy et al. 2016).1 BCIs are integrated input–output
devices that acquire and translate brain signals in order to change physiologic function
or the environment through control of an output device. BCI research has experienced
explosive growth in recent years (Mak & Wolpaw 2009) due to a confluence of advances,
including computational power for modeling brain function, electrode design, neuro-
imaging and electroencephalography (EEG) capabilities, and clinical experience with
implanted neural devices such as deep brain stimulation (DBS). BCI technology is being
envisioned as a way to address unmet or suboptimally met medical needs. BCIs can be
wearable, such as EEG-based devices that detect brain waves through the skull, or implant-
able, such as electrodes inserted into the brain to electrically stimulate or record neuronal
activity. Though there are few current clinical applications of BCI and significant techni-
cal challenges to wider translation remain, implantable and nonimplantable BCI-based
devices promise to be used for a wide range of disorders of movement, affect, sensation,
and cognition (Mak & Wolpaw 2009; Wolpaw & Wolpaw 2012; Soekedar et al. 2014).
Human BCI devices raise interesting ethical questions, some of which have been
explored at the research and policy level:
◆ Privacy of thought (Clausen 2011)
◆ Security of brain data (Denning et al. 2009)
◆ Changes to identity (Goering 2014)
◆ Responsibility for action (Haselager 2013)
◆ Access to expensive technology and post-study obligations to subjects (Schneider
et al. 2012)
◆ Informed consent for research participation (Klein 2016).
Though ethical issues raised by BCI research overlap with those of other neural interven-
tions, such as DBS, neural cell transplantation, and neuropharmacology, the coupling of
124 1
124 Neuromodulation ethics
recorded brain data to output interventions (e.g., electrical, mechanical, molecular, and
sensory-mediated) opens new possibilities for precise and timely modulation of brain
function. A goal for BCI-based applications is to use algorithms to automatically adjust
device function in a closed-loop fashion, substituting machine learning for manual inter-
rogation and adjustment of devices (Hebb et al. 2014). The prospect of closed-loop medi-
cal devices with embedded artificial intelligence raises particularly challenging ethical
questions for BCI research and policy such as determining agency and responsibility for
behavior related to device function (Glannon 2016).
The transition of BCI devices from research into clinical practice raises clinical ethics
challenges as well. A few of these challenges are already beginning to come into view. For
instance, seizure detection and stimulation devices—an early kind of BCI—raise ques-
tions related to predictive, advisory, and automated functionalities (Gilbert 2015). How
will new capabilities affect a patient’s sense of autonomy? What would it mean to over-
rely on such a device? How central to an individual’s autonomy is feeling in control over
a device (Goering 2015)? Such concerns provide a hint of the kinds of ethical questions
that clinicians and patients are likely to face. The development of BCI technology and the
prospect of its wider incorporation into the practice of medicine raise clinical ethics chal-
lenges that are worth trying to anticipate and preemptively address.
The purpose of this chapter is to sketch out some of the clinical ethics challenges of
BCI medicine and to facilitate a discussion about how best to approach these. In the first
section, I give an overview of the kinds of BCI devices that are likely to become a part of
medicine in the near term—devices that target motor, communication, sensation, cogni-
tion, consciousness and affective impairments. This is not meant to be a comprehensive
survey of BCI technology, but to give a glimpse of the current state and ambitions of the
field and the prospect for clinically meaningful devices. In the second section, I explore
some of the ethical issues around consent to BCI-based medical devices. In the third sec-
tion, I discuss some of the ethical challenges of neuromodulation. In the final section,
I argue that looking to an engineering model of medicine for ethical guidance in BCI
medicine is problematic but that a rehabilitation model of medicine holds promise.
may be unnecessary in other kinds of BCIs, for instance, to apply skull surface stimulation
or to control a robotic prosthetic limb or communication speller. The technological and
functional tradeoffs of wearable versus implantable BCI take place against a backdrop of
risks associated with surgical implantation and ongoing care of implanted devices.
The neurophysiologic brain signals used in BCI can be metabolic or magnetic, but cur-
rently the principal type is electrophysiologic (Mak & Wolpaw 2009). Four types of elec-
trophysiologic brain signals are currently being investigated as a basis of wearable BCI
technology (Soekadar & Birbaumer 2015): (1) slow cortical potentials, (2) sensorimo-
tor or motor-related beta rhythms, (3) event-related potentials, and (4) steady-state or
auditory-evoked potentials. Surgically implanted electrodes, on the other hand, whether
strips, grids, or other arrays, can provide brain signal information at a different level, such
as local field potentials, (2) single unit activity, or (3) multiunit activity. The brain signals
can be generated actively, reactively, or passively, depending on whether the user needs
to attend to or respond to a task or whether background cognitive monitoring is involved
(Soekadar et al. 2014). Once the desired brain signal is acquired, the features of the signal
encoding the intent of the user must be extracted, transformed by algorithm into a device
command, and transmitted to a device for execution (Wolpaw et al. 2002).
Potential clinical applications of BCI span a wide range. BCI is currently being explored
for use in controlling computer cursors, wheelchairs, robotic arms, or reanimated limbs
(Mak & Wolpaw 2009). Depending on how widely BCI is defined and how the future of
technological development and acceptance proceeds, BCI devices one day could be per-
vasive in medicine. Near-term clinical uses of BCI can be schematically grouped by func-
tional impairment domains: motor, communication, sensation, cognition, consciousness,
and affect.2 Technology for BCI devices—wearable, implantable, or both—is being devel-
oped currently within each of these domains. In this section, I will briefly give examples of
potential BCI devices being explored in each of these impairment domains.3 It should be
noted that many of these devices exist at an early stage of development, some merely at a
proof-of-principle stage, and whether any of these particular devices will prove clinically
beneficial or commercially viable is an open question.
Motor impairment
Examples of BCI for improving or substituting for impaired motor function include BCI-
controlled exoskeletons, prosthetics, or robotics. Functional electrical stimulation repre-
sents an example of a BCI system for motor control in which EEG signals can be used to
control electrical stimulation of impaired muscle systems, for instance, to facilitate the
grasping motion of a paralyzed hand (Pfurtscheller et al. 2003) or assist in walking (King
et al. 2014). The Braingate system is a well-known example of robotic control using brain-
implanted electrodes. Hochberg and colleagues implanted dense electrode arrays in two
individuals with quadriplegia that allowed them to use local field potentials to control
computer cursors (Hochberg et al. 2006). Other subjects have been able to use devices
with implanted electrodes to control prosthetic limbs (Collinger et al. 2013b).
126 1
126 Neuromodulation ethics
Communication
BCI offers a way to restore or enhance communication in individuals with communica-
tive impairment (Akcakaya et al. 2014). BCI-based devices use (1) slow cortical potentials,
(2) sensorimotor rhythms, (3) event-related potentials, or (4) steady-state visual-evoked
potentials to control communication devices that allow individuals to answer yes/no ques-
tions or select semantic elements, such as letters, words, or phrases (Soekadar & Birbaumer
2015). The first clinically useful BCI allowed two individuals with severe paralysis due
to amyotrophic lateral sclerosis to communicate using slow cortical potentials to move a
computer cursor to select letters (Birbaumer et al. 1999). Individuals who are incompletely
locked-in due to conditions like amyotrophic lateral sclerosis or stroke can communicate
through muscle twitches or eye movements. Such communication can be laborious and
inefficient and individuals can lose these means of communication if their conditions dete-
riorate and they become completely locked-in and unable to communicate through voli-
tional movement at all. BCI communication promises a way to maintain and potentially
restore communication for this and other conditions affecting communication.
An example of BCI for communication is an EEG-based speller for individuals with
locked-in state due to conditions like amyotrophic lateral sclerosis or brainstem stroke
(Chaudhary & Birbaumer 2015). Event-related potentials, such as steady-state evoked
potentials or P300, can allow individuals to communicate by selecting language elements.
As this BCI paradigm is based on an individual focusing on and hence selecting from
language elements from those presented on a screen, such as letters or words, measured
by a P300 or other response, training and cognitive demands involved may be signifi-
cantly less than other BCI communication approaches. Development of spellers that can
be individualized to user neurophysiologic and language patterns and can incorporate
127
lessons from natural language models may substantially improve accuracy and speed of
BCI-based communication (Mainsah et al. 2015).
Sensation
BCI may be a way to bypass, modify, or substitute for impaired or aberrant sensory pro-
cesses (Konrad & Shanks 2010). Sensory neural implants with the widest clinical use
are cochlear implants for sensorineural hearing loss, where direct electrical stimulation
is applied outside the central nervous system to the basilar membrane of the cochlea.
Auditory brainstem implants are a form of BCI that have shown success at restoring
some level of speech recognition in individuals with acoustic nerve damage (Colletti et al.
2009). Visual prosthetics have been developed with electrodes capable of stimulating the
retina, visual cortex, or lateral geniculate body of the thalamus (Cohen 2007).
Stroke is the leading cause of disability worldwide and BCI is emerging as a promising
area of research for stroke-related needs (Soekadar et al. 2015). BCI research after stroke
has focused on (1) bypassing corticospinal pathways damaged by stroke to activate distal
muscles or nerves directly or to control neuroprostheses or (2) facilitating neuroplasti-
city and motor learning for functional motor recovery (Mak & Wolpaw 2009). There is
increasing recognition that sensory feedback is a critical element of stroke recovery and
in control of stroke-related motor prostheses (Patil & Turner 2008).
128 Neuromodulation ethics
acetylcholine) and stem loss of hippocampal volumes, as has been shown in some subjects
with DBS (Sankar 2015; Sankar et al. 2015). Although the clinical significance of cognitive
benefits in this population is far from clear (Nardone et al. 2015), the results suggest that
neurostimulation could be useful. For instance, a BCI device might be used to promote
neuroplasticity for cognitive rehabilitation in combination with future interventions that
slow or stop neurodegenerative processes. Although admittedly speculative, BCI devices
could provide a way to measure substrates of impaired cognition and provide targeted
therapeutic neurostimulation.
Affect
Depression is the most common psychiatric illness, with a lifetime prevalence of nearly
20% (Bromet et al. 2011). Standard pharmacologic therapy and psychotherapy fail to alle-
viate symptoms in a substantial fraction of patients (Warden et al. 2007). Neurostimulation
is an active area of research for treatment-resistant psychiatric disease, including depres-
sion. Electroconvulsive therapy is a well- recognized therapy for treatment- resistant
depression. Newer methods of nonimplantable neurostimulation, such as TMS and tran-
scranial direct current stimulation, have shown modest benefits (George & Aston-Jones
2010). Repetitive TMS received approval from the US Food and Drug Administration
for mild treatment-resistant depression in 2008. DBS has been studied in major depres-
sive disorder, with mixed results. Open-label studies of DBS showed success (Mayberg
et al. 2005; Malone et al. 2009) while two formal clinical trials did not meet primary out-
comes (Dougherty et al. 2015). Differences in psychiatric symptoms across individuals
and within individuals over time have been postulated to explain this discrepancy (Widge
et al. 2017).
BCI-based (closed-loop) DBS offers a way to address the heterogeneity of depression
(Widge 2016). With embedded algorithms designed to automatically adjust stimulation
to need, BCI-based DBS may be a significant improvement on open-loop DBS used in
the failed clinical trials. Rather than employing a one-size-fits-all approach, which may
be responsible for common side effects, such systems could detect real-time fluctuations
in depressive symptoms and individualize stimulation to meet clinical need. The type,
and even the location, of stimulation could be fine-tuned to meet clinical need or neuro-
physiological markers of happiness or quality of life. The potential to further incorporate
machine learning into BCI systems offers a way to not only treat depression in increas-
ingly effective ways but detect patterns of brain activity correlated with depression trig-
gers and intervene before symptoms can take hold.
about whether or when to opt for medical devices. Consent to a medical device is not
an isolated event, but a decisional process situated against a backdrop of relationships
with family, friends, clinicians, and others—and is ethically freighted. What responsibili-
ties and expectations come with accepting a device? Will adoption require a change to
daily routine? Will the device come with direct or ancillary financial or other costs? How
will adopting (or declining) the device change burdens on or relationships with caregiv-
ers? Will having the device engender unwanted expectations of family, clinicians, or even
self? For implanted devices, what are the risks of surgery? What are the alternatives to
or opportunity costs of adopting (or declining) a device? These kinds of ethical consid-
erations are important to the consent process and fall under the provenance of what is
commonly called clinical ethics.
Clinical ethics is a subdiscipline of bioethics concerned with ethical issues arising
within the practice of medicine, such as decisions about diagnosis and therapy (Miller
et al. 1996). Clinical ethics, insofar as it takes the clinical relationship as a focal point,
provides a lens through which to view clinician responsibilities within the consent pro-
cess. A principal responsibility of clinicians is to help patients understand risks associated
with potential interventions. In the case of consent to BCI research, six risk domains
have been identified (Klein 2016). Several of these risk domains—safety, cognitive and
communicative impairment, inappropriate expectations, and privacy and security—are
particularly relevant to clinical adoption of BCI devices as well. It is worth exploring these
risk domains as they pertain to BCI medicine and what responsibilities clinicians have or
will have in helping patients navigate the choice to adopt or decline a BCI.
The first challenge pertains to safety. Even after meeting regulatory standards for
approval, important short-and long-term safety uncertainties will remain with respect to
BCI devices. Just as certain side effects or adverse events are not known or fully appreciated
until after a medication reaches wide clinical use (Klein & Bourdette 2013), so too with
devices. For instance, biocompatibility and durability of implantable electrodes is an ongo-
ing concern as electrodes can fail or lose fidelity over time due to breakdown of electrode
components or to brain tissue reactive processes, such as gliotic encapsulation of elec-
trodes (McGie 2013). Such longevity and long-term reliability uncertainties of BCI systems
are important considerations in the consent process. This is particularly true when weigh-
ing potential benefits against risks of surgical implantation. Some individuals may be will-
ing to undergo neurosurgery and tolerate uncertainties about how long a device will last,
whereas others may have a lower risk tolerance and be willing to pass up potential benefits.
There are safety risks of nonimplantable devices as well. For instance, transcranial direct
current stimulation may cause electrical burns of the scalp. Clinicians have a responsibility
to not only stay abreast of and effectively communicate the current state of known safety
risks, but to explore how safety risks fit with patient values and future plans (Klein 2016).
A second challenge is that of progressive cognitive impairment. BCI may one day
prove useful in stopping, slowing, or reversing pathological processes leading to cog-
nitive impairment, such as Alzheimer’s disease, or in treating noncognitive symptoms
130 1
130 Neuromodulation ethics
in patients with cognitive disorders, such as tremor in patients with Parkinson’s disease
dementia. Consent to BCI therapy in individuals with mild to moderate levels of cog-
nitive impairment will require special attention to decision-making capacity. Do indi-
viduals demonstrate adequate understanding of the risks and benefits of a BCI device?
Do they appreciate what impact adopting a BCI device will or will not likely have on
their symptoms, level of functioning, and quality of life? Can they reason through BCI
as a potential therapeutic option versus other available options? Can individuals make
and express a choice about whether to go forward with or decline a BCI device? Though
assessment of decisional capacity can be less formal and woven into ongoing discussions
between patients, families, and clinicians, more formalized tools are available to assist
with capacity assessments in individuals with known cognitive impairment, such as the
MacArthur Competence Assessment Tool for Treatment (Grisso & Appelbaum 1998).
In addition, multidisciplinary teams that incorporate individuals with relevant expertise,
such as neuropsychologists, nurses, and social workers, can provide more comprehensive
assessment of capacity to consent to BCI therapy. Models of multidisciplinary involve-
ment in the consent process have been developed for DBS (Ford & Kubu 2006).
When decision-making capacity is absent or sufficiently diminished due to cognitive
impairment, clinicians identify and work with appropriate surrogate decision-makers.
While severe cognitive impairment may limit the range of applicable BCI devices, some
BCI devices may still be of benefit. For instance, individuals with dementia can experi-
ence somatic pain that is undertreated in part due to difficulty communicating the expe-
rience of pain to caregivers (Malloy & Hadjistavropoulos 2004). A BCI that senses brain
patterns characteristic of pain and in turn controls a neurostimulation device to treat the
pain could address this problem. In this case, clinicians and surrogates will need to work
together to determine whether BCI is in the overall best interest of patients. The matter
will be more complicated when BCI is proposed as a way to restore cognitive capabilities
in individuals who have lost them. This may require designing consent processes that
make room for a revisiting of the decision to pursue a BCI or how it operates as elements
of decision-capacity progressively improve. Something similar has been suggested with
respect to DBS research in minimally conscious states (Giacino et al. 2012).
BCI may also have adverse effects on cognition. Some individuals with DBS for
Parkinson’s disease, for instance, experience more cognitive decline than would be
expected as a result of the natural course of the disease (Combs et al. 2015). Concerns
about potential cognitive side effects of BCI need to be approached with caution. Not
enough is currently known about long-term cognitive effects of neurostimulation and the
terms “cognition” and “BCI” are exceeding broad and often imprecisely used. It would not
be surprising, however, if BCI devices led simultaneously to beneficial and detrimental
effects on different areas of cognition depending on the type and target location of BCI
and how cognition is measured.
Clinicians will have a responsibility to counsel patients on the range of cognitive effects
of BCI-based therapies. Individuals with impaired communication but normal cogni-
tive capabilities face barriers to meaningful informed consent (Fenton & Alpert 2008).
13
132 Neuromodulation ethics
device for communication may not want every conversation recorded or may want to
dump brain data associated with conversations, perhaps to protect a family member’s feel-
ings or because of embarrassment. The desire to provide individuals with such a sphere
of cognitive privacy may run up against competing interests, such as the need to establish
competency for financial or healthcare decisions. Did the patient ever indicate a desire to
change their last will and testament and give everything to charity? Were the preferences
in their living will consistent (before falling into their current incapacitated state), or does
a BCI record indicate ambivalent feelings? BCI data may become a trove of information
to which parties seek access. The clinician has a role in preparing patients for privacy risks
associated with BCI brain data, even if the scope and available protections of this privacy
are not currently clear.
While it is clear that clinicians have ethical responsibilities to assist patients as they
engage in the consent process for BCI devices, clinicians also have responsibilities after
adoption of a BCI device. A critical feature of BCI technology is the need to moni-
tor and adjust device function over time. This feature of BCI medicine—the need for
neuromodulation—raises its own set of ethical issues (Ford & Henderson 2006; Fukushi
2012). How should the settings of a device be determined? Who determines whether a
device is working well or needs to be adjusted? Who should have a say—patients, families,
clinicians, others—in decisions about neuromodulation? In BCI systems that incorporate
machine learning, when should clinicians or others be able to intervene, say, if patients are
unaware or disagree that a device is malfunctioning?
I felt concern that Sally may have “overshot,” that this new personality was too different from her
old one. She demurred. She said Prozac had let her personality emerge at last—she had not been
alive before taking an antidepressant. Sally insisted I not stop the medication, but I tapered the dose
slightly. (Kramer 1993, pp.147–148, italics added)
134 Neuromodulation ethics
clinicians invoke notions of clinical integrity or the goals of medicine in refusing patient
requests for neuromodulation (Woopen 2012; Schermer 2013)? Other questions relate
to tradeoffs involved in neuromodulation. What is the clinician’s role in advising about
scientific uncertainties of BCI, for instance, if electrodes begin to fail and applying higher
levels of current to overcome encapsulation resistance offers a potential remedy but at an
unknown risk of longer-term tissue damage? Or what if uncertainty exists as to whether
a device is failing or an individual instead is experiencing progression of their disease?
Moreover, how should a clinician counsel about side effects of treatment if a patient and
family disagree about the value of these side effects, for example, increased disinhibition
due to BCI in a previously painfully shy individual like Kramer’s Sally? How might these
questions change if choice points for modulation are obviated by device algorithms that
automatically decide how to adjust device settings? Does this change the obligations of
clinicians to counsel and care for patients with BCI devices? These questions might be
reframed at a more general level: what constitutes responsible neuromodulation?
with subcutaneous interferons in the early 1990s and expanding to a broad range of thera-
pies (Ransohoff et al. 2015). Immunomodulatory therapies involve a tradeoff—in order to
counter the body’s autoimmune attack on the nervous system, a reduction in the ability
of the immune system to perform its normal functions, such as fighting infections (Rizvi
& Coyle 2011), can result. The introduction of one medication, natalizumab, typifies the
immunomodulatory trade-off. When initially introduced, natalizumab demonstrated
significantly better effectiveness at treating MS, but this increased effectiveness came
with a cost: a 1:1000 risk of progressive multifocal leukoencephalopathy, a devastating,
untreatable, and potential fatal brain infection (Clifford et al. 2010). For some patients,
the potential benefits of natalizumab outweigh the rare chance of progressive multifocal
leukoencephalopathy, for others, this is not the case. Patients and clinicians face similar,
though perhaps less stark, tradeoffs with other immunomodulatory therapies.
Immune modulation decisions— whether to start, reduce, escalate, or abandon a
therapy—in turn, raise ethical questions. What is a reasonable tradeoff? What level of
consent is needed? Can a clinician refuse to start therapy, say, if adherence to follow-up
surveillance is likely to be poor? The engineering model of medicine provides one way
to approach these kinds of ethical questions. Clinicians bring technical expertise—the
ability to assess symptoms, note physical signs, examine biomarkers of disease stability
or progression, and effectively communicate information—and patients bring a moral
framework—comprised of their preferences, belief systems, and modes of reasoning. Dan
Brock describes the division of labor at the heart of the engineering model as:
In this approach, both physicians and patients have essential roles in ideal treatment decision mak-
ing. Physicians are to use their knowledge, training, and expertise to provide their patients with a
diagnosis and a prognosis if no treatment is undertaken, together with information about alterna-
tive treatments that might improve the prognosis, including the risks and benefits and attendant
uncertainties of such treatments. Patients articulate their own aims, preferences, and values in
order to evaluate which alternative is best for them. (Brock 1991, p.31)
This division of labor has implications for assignment of moral responsibility. On the
engineering model, the primary obligation of the clinician is to develop technical exper-
tise and to translate this expertise into information for patients. This has led Emanuel and
Emanuel (1992) to describe the engineering model as primarily centered on delivery of
information. This information consists of assessment of the patient’s health, diagnostic
and therapeutic options, and relevant probabilities. The information might even include
the clinician’s assessment of what she takes the patient’s values to be (though without
taking a stand on them). One sees this in discussions of shared decision-making in MS
(Heesen et al. 2011). On this view, whatever subsidiary obligations clinicians may have can
be viewed as deriving from a primary obligation: develop and exercise technical expertise.
On an engineering model, the role of the clinician in neuromodulation is to apply tech-
nical skills to “fix” some dysfunctional aspect of the nervous system. Technical expertise
is problem-oriented. Skills are put to use to solve or fix a particular problem or set of
problems. This orientation centered on fixing is important because it helps structure how
ethical issues are approached and how clinician responsibilities are understood. As an
136 1
136 Neuromodulation ethics
example, consider the individual shown to kick a soccer ball by using a BCI-based exo-
skeleton at the 2016 World Cup in Brazil (Smith 2014). A team of researchers identified a
problem—the inability of an individual with lower extremity paralysis to stand indepen-
dently and kick an object—and developed a plan to solve it. By framing this research in
terms of a single fixable problem (or series of problems) ethical questions that might be
raised about this research inherit this frame. What was the consent process like? Is this
a just use of societal resources? How should the media be utilized to educate the public
about an emerging technology? Questions about consent, justice, responsible conduct of
research, and other matters have their meaning in reference to solving a particular tech-
nical problem: fixing the neural dysfunction that is preventing kicking a soccer ball. As
such, an engineering model provides a simplifying framework for reflecting on the ethical
responsibilities of a “neuromodulationist.”
regaining walking function was not a high priority among individuals with quadriplegia
and paraplegia, whereas restoration of upper extremity and sexual function were. The
value of end-user perspectives in BCI research is beginning to be recognized (Huggins
et al. 2011; Collinger et al. 2013a; Kübler et al. 2015).
The second way in which the fixing frame can distort is in obscuring how problems
addressed by BCI are normatively defined. Take the example of designing a BCI neuro-
prosthetic arm that allows an individual to shake hands (Klein et al. 2015). The character-
istics of handshakes are known to vary across cultures (Dibiase & Gunnoe 2004). What
constitutes a handshake depends on norms and context. A grip that is strong and lingers
may indicate confidence and competence in certain contexts, like a business meeting, but
may be awkward or threatening in others, such as meeting a prospective son-in-law or
daughter-in-law for the first time. That problems might not be definable without reference
to social norms undermines the fixing frame. The promise of a purely technical fix only
makes sense for problems that can be technically defined without remainder, and many of
the functions that BCI devices target will be, at least in part, normatively defined.
The final limitation of the engineering model applied to BCI medicine derives from the
iterative nature of neuromodulation. As discussed earlier, consent to obtain a BCI device
is an important decision, and one that involves the patient and clinician in a discussion
of goals, values, and expected outcomes. A process of shared decision-making is under-
taken. One of the challenges of the engineering model is that while it may be of adequate
fit for the initial decision to get a BCI device, it fits poorly decisions (or iterative consents)
related to ongoing neuromodulation. The clinical benefit of a BCI device will turn to a
great extent on a multitude of decisions about how to modulate the device function over
time. The endpoint around which this modulation occurs is not fixed. An individual may
start out wanting no tremor or no depression but over time develop a more nuanced set
of preferences for BCI function, such as no tremor in church, or no depressive symptoms
related to self-worth. What is important is that the goals of BCI therapy will be under-
determined at initiation of therapy. Patients, clinicians, and family will have to engage
in an iterative practice of values exploration in order to modulate the device function
effectively.
138 Neuromodulation ethics
course of rehabilitation therapy, clinicians help patients reevaluate and reformulate goals
over time in light of these changes. Most BCI devices under development are a form of
assistive technology.
Consider a hypothetical case of Judith, a woman who receives a BCI-based DBS device
for treatment-resistant depression. Judith’s device has electrodes that record neural sig-
nals relevant to depression and uses these to adjust stimulation settings of DBS elec-
trodes. At the outset of therapy, Judith and her clinician decide on the initial setting for
her device. Whenever a certain pattern of activity is detected that correlates with her
depressive symptoms, the DBS electrodes will apply stimulation to return her brain to a
normal state. Over time, Judith and her clinician will reevaluate and adjust her device set-
tings, that is, neuromodulate. What happens if Judith and her clinician disagree on new
settings? Perhaps Judith comes to miss the fluctuations of her pre-device self or feels that
a little dysthymia is helpful for her work as an artist. And maybe her clinician becomes
wary, based on his prior relationship with her that a closed-loop system permissive of
fluctuations may allow her to “spiral down” toward suicide. How should decisions about
neuromodulation be made? What does consent mean in this context?
An advantage of looking to rehabilitation medicine is that it provides an alternative
model of consent for neuromodulation. Purtilo (1988) argues that rehabilitation medi-
cine provides a good example of why the event model of consent is inadequate. Decisions
made in rehabilitation are most often iterative and incremental: as a patient’s condition or
functional capabilities change, therapies are adjusted, often in small ways. For example,
the consent to a rehabilitation program to retrain one’s upper extremity for self-feeding
after a stroke is more accurately understood as a series of decisions that are made over
time and represent small steps. “Today I will agree to work with the physical therapist.”
“Today I will try to move my fingers.” “Today I will ignore spastic pain.” “Today I will try
to grasp an object.” “Today I will try to lift an object.” And so on. These decisions may not
be linear or wholly predictable. They are a process. A process view of consent is a better fit
for the iterative decisions that characterize BCI medicine.
The introduction of clinical BCI devices raises important ethical questions. Some of
these questions will be faced by patients and clinicians as they decide on whether to pur-
sue a BCI device. Other questions will arise in the practice of neuromodulation. How
much control should individuals be given over their cognitive, affective, or motoric life?
When should clinicians abide by or refuse patient requests for device settings? Though
there are unlikely to be easy answers to these questions, it is worth anticipating now the
kinds of ethical issues that patients and clinicians will face as BCI devices come into
greater clinical use and exploring possible resources, such as those found in rehabilitation
medicine, for addressing them.
Acknowledgments
This work was supported by a grant from the National Science Foundation (NSF Award
#EEC-1028725). The views expressed are solely those of the author and do not represent
the views of the NSF.
139
References 139
Notes
1. Although efforts have been made to establish different referents for BCI and BMI, the terms are used
interchangeably in the literature. For instance, some prefer to reserve BMI for neural interfaces con-
trolling robotic or prosthetic devices (Wolpaw & Wolpaw 2012). For the sake of simplicity, BCI will be
used synonymously here.
2. This impairment-based schema has its limitations. For instance, if not put in context it may seem to
reinforce certain questionable dichotomies in our thinking, such as between normal and abnormal
function and able and disabled bodies. In addition, the domains are imperfect in that they are not
comprehensive and in some cases overlap. For instance, does a seizure detection and stimulation BCI
system belong in the motor, sensory, or cognition/consciousness domain? Nonetheless, this rough
grouping maps onto both traditional medical and scientific categories and so is a useful preliminary
framework.
3. The devices and technologies highlighted, both wearable and implantable, give a representative feel for
work in each domain. This is helpful for exploring the ethical issues discussed in this section, even if
the chosen examples are not the most representative technology or are not the closest to translation in
a given domain. No position is taken on the warrant of pursuing wearable versus implantable devices
in any given domain.
4. Veatch juxtaposes the engineering model (unfavorably) to the priestly, collegial, and contractual
models.
5. Medical conditions falling within the scope of neuroimmunology typically include Guillain–Barré
syndrome, myasthenia gravis, central nervous system vasculitis, dermatomyositis, and others, but
multiple sclerosis, an inflammatory demyelinating and neurodegenerative disorder of the nervous sys-
tem, is the paradigmatic example of a neuroimmunological disease.
References
Akcakaya, M., Peters, B., Moghadamfalahi, M., et al. (2014). Noninvasive brain–computer interfaces
for augmentative and alternative communication. Biomedical Engineering, IEEE Reviews, 7, 31–49.
Anderson, K.D. (2004). Targeting recovery: priorities of the spinal cord-injured population. Journal of
Neurotrauma, 21(10), 1371–1383.
Bell, E., Maxwell, B., McAndrews, M.P., Sadikot, A., and Racine, E. (2010). Hope and patients’
expectations in deep brain stimulation: healthcare providers’ perspectives and approaches. Journal of
Clinical Ethics, 21, 112–124.
Birbaumer, N., Ghanayim, N., Hinterberger, T., et al. (1999). A spelling device for the paralysed.
Nature, 398(6725), 297–298.
Brock, D.W. (1991). The ideal of shared decision making between physicians and patients. Kennedy
Institute of Ethics Journal, 1(1), 28–47.
Brody, H. (1997). The physician-patient relationship. Medical Ethics, 2, 75–101.
Bromet, E., Andrade, L.H., Hwang, I., et al. (2011). Cross-national epidemiology of DSM-IV major
depressive episode. BMC Medicine, 9(1), 1.
Chaudhary, U. and Birbaumer, N. (2015). Communication in locked-in state after brainstem stroke: a
brain-computer-interface approach. Annals of Translational Medicine, 3(Suppl. 1), S29.
Clausen, J. (2011). Conceptual and ethical issues with brain–hardware interfaces. Current Opinion in
Psychiatry, 24(6), 495–501.
Clifford, D.B., De Luca, A., Simpson, D.M., Arendt, G., Giovannoni, G., and Nath, A. (2010).
Natalizumab-associated progressive multifocal leukoencephalopathy in patients with multiple
sclerosis: lessons from 28 cases. Lancet Neurology, 9(4), 438–46.
140 1
140 Neuromodulation ethics
Clouser, K.D. (1983). Veatch, May, and models: a critical review and a new view. In: Shelp, E.E. (Ed.)
The Clinical Encounter, pp.89–103. Netherlands: Springer.
Cohen, E.D. (2007). Prosthetic interfaces with the visual system: biological issues. Journal of Neural
Engineering, 4(2), R14.
Colletti, V., Shannon, R.V., Carner, M., Veronese, S., and Colletti, L. (2009). Progress in restoration of
hearing with the auditory brainstem implant. Progress in Brain Research, 175, 333–345.
Collinger, J.L., Boninger, M.L., Bruns, T.M., Curley, K., Wang, W., and Weber, D.J. (2013a). Functional
priorities, assistive technology, and brain-computer interfaces after spinal cord injury. Journal of
Rehabilitation Research and Development, 50(2), 145–160.
Collinger, J.L., Wodlinger, B., Downey, J.E., et al. (2013b). High-performance neuroprosthetic control
by an individual with tetraplegia. The Lancet, 381(9866, pp.557–564.
Combs, H.L., Folley, B.S., Berry, D.T., et al. (2015). Cognition and depression following deep brain
stimulation of the subthalamic nucleus and globus pallidus pars internus in Parkinson’s disease: a
meta-analysis. Neuropsychology Review, 25(4), 439–454.
Denning, T., Matsuoka, Y., and Kohno, T. (2009). Neurosecurity: security and privacy for neural
devices. Neurosurgical Focus, 27(1), E7.
Dibiase, R. and Gunnoe, J. (2004). Gender and culture differences in touching behavior. Journal of
Social Psychology, 144(1), 49–62.
Dougherty, D.D., Rezai, A.R., Carpenter, L.L., et al. (2015). A randomized sham-controlled trial
of deep brain stimulation of the ventral capsule/ventral striatum for chronic treatment-resistant
depression. Biological Psychiatry, 78(4), 240–248.
Elder, G.J. and Taylor, J.P. (2014). Transcranial magnetic stimulation and transcranial direct current
stimulation: treatments for cognitive and neuropsychiatric symptoms in the neurodegenerative
dementias? Alzheimer’s Research and Therapy, 6(9), 74,
Emanuel, E.J. and Emanuel, L.L. (1992). Four models of the physician-patient relationship. Journal of
the American Medical Association, 267(16), 2221–2226.
Fenton, A. and Alpert, S. (2008). Extending our view on using BCIs for locked-in syndrome.
Neuroethics, 1(2), 119–132.
Ford, P.J. and Henderson, J.M. (2006). The clinical and research ethics of neuromodulation.
Neuromodulation: Technology at the Neural Interface, 9(4), 250–252.
Ford, P.J. and Kubu, C.S. (2006). Stimulating debate: ethics in a multidisciplinary functional
neurosurgery committee. Journal of Medical Ethics, 32(2), 106–109.
Freund, H.J, Kuhn, J., Lenartz, D., et al. (2009). Cognitive functions in a patient with Parkinson-
dementia syndrome undergoing deep brain stimulation. Archives of Neurology, 66(6), 781–785.
Fukushi, T. (2012). Ethical practice in the era of advanced neuromodulation. Asian Bioethics Review,
4(4), 320–329.
George, M.S. and Aston-Jones, G. (2010). Noninvasive techniques for probing neurocircuitry and
treating illness: vagus nerve stimulation (VNS), transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) and
transcranial direct current stimulation (tDCS). Neuropsychopharmacology, 35(1), 301–316.
Giacino, J.T., Fins, J.J., Machado, A., and Schiff, N.D. (2012). Central thalamic deep brain stimulation
to promote recovery from chronic posttraumatic minimally conscious state: challenges and
opportunities. Neuromodulation: Technology at the Neural Interface, 15(4), 339–349.
Giacino, J.T., Fins, J.J., Laureys, S., and Schiff, N.D. (2014). Disorders of consciousness after acquired
brain injury: the state of the science. Nature Reviews Neurology, 10(2), 99–114.
Gilbert, F. (2015). A threat to autonomy? The intrusion of predictive brain implants. American Journal
of Bioethics: Neuroscience, 6(4), 4–11.
Glannon, W. (2016). Ethical issues in neuroprosthetics. Journal of Neural Engineering, 13(2), 021002.
14
References 141
Goering, S. (2014). Is it still me? DBS, agency, and the extended, relational me. American Journal of
Bioethics: Neuroscience, 5(4), 50–51.
Goering, S. (2015). Stimulating autonomy: DBS and the prospect of choosing to control ourselves
through stimulation. American Journal of Bioethics: Neuroscience, 6(4), 1–3.
Grisso, T. and Appelbaum, P.S. (1998). MacArthur Competence Assessment Tool for Treatment
(MacCAT-T). Sarasota, FL: Professional Resource Press.
Hansson, S.O. (2007). The ethics of enabling technology. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics,
16(3), 257–267.
Haselager, P. (2013). Did I do that? Brain–computer interfacing and the sense of agency. Minds and
Machines, 23(3), 405–418.
Haselager, P., Vlek, R., Hill, J., and Nijboer, F. (2009). A note on ethical aspects of BCI. Neural
Networks, 22(9), 1352–1357.
Hebb, A.O., Zhang, J.J., Mahoor, M.H., et al. (2014). Creating the feedback loop: closed-loop
neurostimulation. Neurosurgery Clinics of North America, 25(1), 187–204.
Heesen, C., Solari, A., Giordano, A., Kasper, J., and Köpke, S. (2011). Decisions on multiple sclerosis
immunotherapy: new treatment complexities urge patient engagement. Journal of the Neurological
Sciences, 306(1), 192–197.
Herron, J., Denison, T., and Chizeck, H.J. (2015). Closed-loop DBS with movement intention.
In: Proceedings of the 2015 7th International IEEE/EMBS Conference on Neural Engineering (NER),
pp.844–847. Montpellier, France, April 2015
Hochberg, L.R., Serruya, M.D., Friehs, G.M., et al. (2006). Neuronal ensemble control of prosthetic
devices by a human with tetraplegia. Nature, 442(7099), 164–171.
Hochberg, L. and Anderson, K. (2012). BCI users and their needs. In: Wolpaw, J.R. and Wolpaw, E.W.
(Eds.) Brain-Computer Interfaces, pp. 317–323. New York: Oxford University Press.
Holsheimer, J. (2003). Letters to the editor. Neuromodulation, 6(4), 270–2.
Huggins, J.E., Wren, P.A., and Gruis, K.L. (2011). What would brain-computer interface users want?
Opinions and priorities of potential users with amyotrophic lateral sclerosis. Amyotrophic Lateral
Sclerosis, 12(5), 318–324.
King, C., McCrimmon, C., Wang, P., Chou, C., Nenadic, Z., and Do, A.H. (2014). Brain-computer
interface driven functional electrical stimulation system for overground walking: a case report.
Neurology, 82(Suppl. 10), P3–055.
Krames, E.S., Peckham, P.H., Rezai, A.R., and Aboelsaad, F. (2009). What is neuromodulation?
In: Krames, E.S., Peckham, P.H., and Rezai, A.R. (Eds.) Neuromodulation, pp.3–8. San Diego,
CA: Academic Press.
Klein, E. (2016). Informed consent in implantable BCI research: identifying risks and exploring
meaning. Science and Engineering Ethics, 22(5), 1299–1317.
Klein, E. and Bourdette, D. (2013). Postmarketing adverse drug reactions: a duty to report?
Neurology: Clinical Practice, 3(4), 288–294.
Klein, E., Brown, T., Sample, M., Truitt, A.R., and Goering, S. (2015). Engineering the brain: ethical
issues and the introduction of neural devices. Hastings Center Report, 45(6), 26–35.
Kolata, G. (2013, October 27). Of fact, fiction and Cheney’s defibrillator. The New York Times. http://
nytimes.com/2013/10/29/science/of-fact-fiction-and-defibrillators.html [accessed June 25, 2016].
Konrad, P. and Shanks, T. (2010). Implantable brain computer interface: challenges to neurotechnology
translation. Neurobiology of Disease, 38(3), 369–375.
Kübler, A., Winter, S., Ludolph, A.C., Hautzinger, M., and Birbaumer, N. (2005). Severity of depressive
symptoms and quality of life in patients with amyotrophic lateral sclerosis. Neurorehabilitation and
Neural Repair, 19(3), 182–193.
142 1
142 Neuromodulation ethics
Kübler, A., Holz, E., Kaufmann, T., and Zickler, C. (2013). A user centred approach for bringing BCI
controlled applications to end-users. In: Fazel-Rezai, R. (Ed.) Brain-Computer Interface Systems-
Recent Progress and Future Prospects. InTech, DOI: 10.5772/55802. Available from: http://www.
intechopen.com/books/brain-computer-interface-systems-recent-progress-and-future-prospects/
a-user-centred-approach-for-bringing-bci-controlled-applications-to-end-users
Kuhn, J., Hardenacke, K., Lenartz, D., et al. (2015). Deep brain stimulation of the nucleus basalis of
Meynert in Alzheimer’s dementia. Molecular Psychiatry, 20(3), 353–360.
Mainsah, B.O., Collins, L.M., Colwell, K.A., et al. (2015). Increasing BCI communication rates with
dynamic stopping towards more practical use: an ALS study. Journal of Neural Engineering, 12(1),
016013.
Mak, J.N. and Wolpaw, J.R. (2009). Clinical applications of brain-computer interfaces: current state and
future prospects. IEEE Reviews in Biomedical Engineering, 2, 187–199.
Malloy, D.C. and Hadjistavropoulos, T. (2004). The problem of pain management among persons
with dementia, personhood, and the ontology of relationships. Nursing Philosophy, 5(2), 147–159.
Malone, D.A., Dougherty, D.D., Rezai, A.R., et al. (2009). Deep brain stimulation of the ventral
capsule/ventral striatum for treatment-resistant depression. Biological Psychiatry, 65(4), 267–275.
Mayberg, H.S., Lozano, A.M., Voon, V., et al. (2005). Deep brain stimulation for treatment-resistant
depression. Neuron, 45(5), 651–660.
McGie, S.C., Nagai, M.K., and Artinian-Shaheen, T. (2013). Clinical ethical concerns in the
implantation of brain-machine interfaces: Part II: specific clinical and technical issues affecting
ethical soundness. Pulse, IEEE, 4(2), 32–37.
Miller, F.G., Fins, J.J., and Bacchetta, M.D. (1996). Clinical pragmatism: John Dewey and clinical ethics.
Journal of Contemporary Health Law & Policy, 13(27), 27–51.
Mirzadeh, Z., Bari, A., and Lozano, A.M. (2015). The rationale for deep brain stimulation in
Alzheimer’s disease. Journal of Neural Transmission, 123(7), 775–783.
Murphy, M.D., Guggenmos, D.J., Bundy, D.T., and Nudo, R.J. (2016). Current challenges facing the
translation of brain computer interfaces from preclinical trials to use in human patients. Frontiers in
Cellular Neuroscience, 9, 497.
Nardone, R., Höller, Y., Tezzon, F., et al. (2015). Neurostimulation in Alzheimer’s disease: from basic
research to clinical applications. Neurological Sciences, 36(5), 689–700.
Patil, P.G. and Turner, D.A. (2008). The development of brain-machine interface neuroprosthetic
devices. Neurotherapeutics, 5(1), 137–146.
Pfurtscheller, G., Müller, G.R., Pfurtscheller, J., Gerner, H.J., and Rupp, R. (2003). Thought–control
of functional electrical stimulation to restore hand grasp in a patient with tetraplegia. Neuroscience
Letters, 35(1), 33–36.
Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues (2015). Gray Matters: Topics at the
Intersection of Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society, 2. Washington, DC: United States Government.
Purtilo, R.B. (1988). Ethical issues in teamwork: the context of rehabilitation. Archives of Physical
Medicine and Rehabilitation, 69(5), 318–322.
Ransohoff, R.M., Hafler, D.A., and Lucchinetti, C.F. (2015). Multiple sclerosis—a quiet revolution.
Nature Reviews Neurology, 11(3), 134–142.
Rizvi, S.A. and Coyle, P.K. (2011). Clinical Neuroimmunology: Multiple Sclerosis and Related Disorders.
New York: Springer.
Sankar, T. (2015). Alzheimer’s disease: a novel application for deep-brain stimulation? Future Neurology,
10(4), 297–300.
Sankar, T., Chakravarty, M.M., Bescos, A., et al. (2015). Deep brain stimulation influences brain
structure in Alzheimer’s disease. Brain Stimulation, 8(3), 645–654.
143
References 143
Schermer, M. (2013). Health, happiness and human enhancement—dealing with unexpected effects of
deep brain stimulation. Neuroethics, 6(3), 435–445.
Schiff, N.D., Giacino, J.T., Kalmar, K., et al. (2007). Behavioural improvements with thalamic
stimulation after severe traumatic brain injury. Nature, 448(7153), 600–603.
Schneider, M.J., Fins, J.J., and Wolpaw, J.R. (2012). Ethical issues in BCI research. In: Wolpaw,
J.R. and Wolpaw, E.W. (Eds.) Brain-Computer Interfaces, pp. 373–383. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Seel, R.T., Sherer, M., Whyte, J., et al. (2010). Assessment scales for disorders of
consciousness: evidence-based recommendations for clinical practice and research. Archives of
Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, 91(12), 1795–1813.
Shih, J.J., Krusienski, D.J., and Wolpaw, J.R. (2012). Brain-computer interfaces in medicine. Mayo
Clinic Proceedings, 87(3), 268–279.
Silvers, A. (2009). An essay on modeling: the social model of disability. In: Ralston, D.C. and Ho, J.H.
(Eds.) Philosophical Reflections on Disability, pp. 19–36. Netherlands: Springer.
Sjögren, M.J.C., Hellström, P.T.O., Jonsson, M.A.G., Runnerstam, M., Silander, H.C., and Ben-
Menachem, E. (2002). Cognition-enhancing effect of vagus nerve stimulation in patients with
Alzheimer’s disease: a pilot study. Journal of Clinical Psychiatry, 63(11), 972–980.
Smith, S. (2014). Mind-controlled exoskeleton kicks off World Cup. CNN. Available from: http://www.
cnn.com/2014/06/12/health/exoskeleton-world-cup-kickoff/ [accessed May 12, 2016].
Soekadar, S.R. and Birbaumer, N. (2015). Brain–machine interfaces for communication in complete
paralysis: ethical implications and challenges. In: Illes, J. and Sahakian, B.J. (Eds.) Handbook of
Neuroethics, pp.705–724. Netherlands: Springer.
Soekadar, S.R., Cohen, L.G., and Birbaumer, N. (2014). Clinical brain-machine interfaces. In: Tracy,
J.I., Hampstead, B.M., and Sathian, K. (Eds.) Cognitive Plasticity in Neurologic Disorders, pp.347–
362. New York: Oxford University Press.
Soekadar, S.R., Birbaumer, N., Slutzky, M.W., and Cohen, L.G. (2015). Brain–machine interfaces in
neurorehabilitation of stroke. Neurobiology of Disease, 83, 172–179.
Synofzik, M., Schlaepfer, T.E., and Fins, J.J. (2012). How happy is too happy? Euphoria, neuroethics,
and deep brain stimulation of the nucleus accumbens. American Journal of Bioethics: Neuroscience,
3(1), 30–36.
Veatch, R.M. (1972). Models for ethical medicine in a revolutionary age. Hastings Center Report, 2(3), 5–7.
Volkmann, J., Herzog, J., Kopper, F., and Deuschl, G. (2002). Introduction to the programming of deep
brain stimulators. Movement Disorders, 17(S3), S181–S187.
Warden, D., Rush, A.J., Trivedi, M.H., Fava, M., and Wisniewski, S.R. (2007). The STAR* D Project
results: a comprehensive review of findings. Current Psychiatry Reports, 9(6), 449–459.
Widge, A.S., Deckersbach, T., Eskandar, E.N., and Dougherty, D.D. (2016). Deep brain stimulation
for treatment-resistant psychiatric illnesses: what has gone wrong and what should we do next?
Biological Psychiatry, 79(4), e9–10.
Widge, A.S, Ellard, K.K, Paulk, A.C., et al. (2017). Treating refractory mental illness with closed-loop
brain stimulation: progress towards a patient-specific transdiagnostic approach. Experimental
Neurology, 287(Pt 4), 461–472.
Wolpaw, J.R. and Wolpaw, E.W. (2012). Brain-Computer interfaces: Principles and Practice.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Wolpaw, J.R., Birbaumer, N., McFarland, D.J., Pfurtscheller, G., and Vaughan, T.M. (2002). Brain-
computer interfaces for communication and control. Clinical Neurophysiology, 113(6), 767–791.
Woopen, C. (2012). Ethical aspects of neuromodulation. International Review of Neurobiology, 107,
315–332.
14
Chapter 8
Introduction
The human brain contains approximately 84 billion neurons, collectively making trillions
of connections. Fascination with this staggeringly complex organ has long drawn scien-
tists to study the brain. Indeed, advances in neuroscience are emerging at an amazing
rate, supported by investments in science such as the Brain Research through Advancing
Innovative Neurotechnologies (BRAIN) Initiative® (http://braininitiative.nih.gov) that
aims to accelerate the development and application of innovative neurotechnologies to
revolutionize the understanding of the human brain.
The public in developed countries is becoming ever more interested in how the brain
works and how scientists can bring meaningful solutions to those who suffer from dis-
orders of the nervous system, which can be categorized in terms of neurological, mental
health, and substance abuse (NMS) disorders. The disabling features of NMS disorders
stem from dysfunction in neural circuits, but our current tools are unable to identify the
abnormalities in signaling or normalize the circuit dysfunction. Around the world, dis-
ease burden continues to shift from communicable to noncommunicable diseases such as
those in the NMS classification, and from early death to years spent living with a disabil-
ity. Brain-based diseases and disorders comprise a significant share of this toll. In 2010,
mental and behavioral disorders comprised 7.4% of the global burden of disease, stroke
comprised 4.1%, and neurological disorders another 3% (Bloom et al. 2011; Murray et al.
2012). This rising burden causes immense human suffering and poses unprecedented
challenges for healthcare. For example, Alzheimer’s disease not only progressively destroys
essential mental functions like memory but it is also an incredibly costly chronic disease.
In 2015, the cost to American society of caring for Alzheimer’s disease patients totaled
an estimated $226 billion, with half of the costs borne by Medicare. If current trends con-
tinue, by 2050, that cost is estimated to rise to over $1.1 trillion (Alzheimer’s Association
2015). These facts and figures underscore the need for action, and point to the impor-
tance and potential impact of neuroscience research for human health. The problems are
145
Introduction 145
difficult, and more powerful tools and greater fundamental knowledge of the nervous
system are needed to solve them. Modern neuroscience is undergoing a revolution, one
that is propelled by huge leaps in technological capabilities and focused on tool develop-
ment. As Freeman Dyson famously noted (1997), new directions in science are launched
by new tools much more often than by new concepts. That mindset, embodied in the
BRAIN initiative®, will deliver powerful new tools and technologies that fall into two main
classes: those that enable us to interrogate and monitor neural circuit activity, and those
that enable us to modulate it. The ethical and societal issues attached to the medical and
nonmedical use of these technologies are not subtle, nor are they entirely new.
The attempt to discern what a patient is feeling or experiencing is an inherent part of
medicine. There are also nonmedical examples of trying to understand what is unfolding
in someone’s mind. For instance, scientists have long been interested in ferreting out the
neurobiology of lying and deception. Early methods of lie detection rely on nonverbal
cues, such as facial microexpressions and increased perspiration, but these are indirect
reflections of the brain function that is at the core of processing and retelling information
about the world. Modern neuroscience methods have enabled researchers to come closer
to studying that brain function. Functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) measures
brain activity by detecting changes associated with blood flow, and Mohamed and col-
leagues (2006) found that fMRI could be used to discriminate patterns of brain activity
associated with deception from those associated with telling the truth. They observed
that deception triggered activity in brain regions associated with memory encoding and
retrieval, response inhibition (i.e., suppressing the truth), and emotion. Though fMRI has
taken us one step closer to accessing these types of higher-order cognitive functions, the
BRAIN Initiative® holds promise of delivering tools to push this to another level, deliver-
ing both precision and accessibility (i.e., tools that are miniaturized compared to contem-
porary brain scanners, and widely available).
What might this look like in medical practice? As one example, psychiatrists might one
day be equipped with lightweight brain-scanning helmets, which could rapidly, precisely,
and noninvasively measure brain circuit function to aid diagnosis of autism, general-
ized anxiety disorder, post-traumatic stress disorder, manic versus depressive episodes in
bipolar disorder, suicidality, or attention deficit hyperactivity disorder. New tools could
give physicians and researchers ways to objectively measure pain, or assess the circuit
abnormalities underlying epilepsy, cognitive impairment, dystonia, spasticity in cerebral
palsy, and so on. From an ethics perspective, issues around the privacy and use of such
data would be key, as the data will likely contain information linked to multiple core char-
acteristics of the individual. Innovative neural circuit monitoring technologies may pose
new challenges for ethicists and society, since they would far outstrip the current ability to
record brain activity underlying thoughts, mood, and sensations, which is fairly primitive
and not widely in use.
Of course, interrogating brain function is only half of the story. Dysregulated brain
circuits are the most proximal cause of NMS disorders, and from a medical perspec-
tive, modulating brain circuits for health benefit is the basis of all treatments for NMS
146
disorders. Currently, the most common symptomatic treatments are drugs that alter neu-
ral circuit function, but direct electrical modulation of brain circuits is also part of the
therapeutic armamentarium. Following decades of study to identify the circuit abnormal-
ity underlying the motor symptoms of tremor and slowness of movement in Parkinson’s
disease, deep brain stimulation (DBS), in which a patient is implanted with a device to
deliver electrical current focused on specific deep regions of the brain, is now a com-
mon neurosurgical treatment for Parkinson’s disease (DeLong & Wichmann 2015). Major
depressive disorder (often simply referred to as “depression”), a leading cause of disabil-
ity around the world, has been treated to varying degrees of success with different types
of brain stimulation (Murray et al. 2012; Deng et al. 2015). Electroconvulsive therapy,
in which a generalized seizure is induced by delivering electricity directly to the brain,
was originally developed in the 1930s and is still used for patients with severe depres-
sion, as it relatively rapidly elicits high rates of remission (Lisanby 2007). Attempts to
understand the abnormalities in brain circuits that underlie depressed mood have already
given researchers and clinicians brain targets for DBS as an option for treatment-resistant
depression (Mayberg 2009). Beyond electroconvulsive therapy and DBS, researchers are
also focused on noninvasive, subconvulsive methods of brain stimulation for depression,
including transcranial direct current stimulation and transcranial magnetic stimulation.
What all of these techniques have in common is that they are aimed at modulating
brain circuit function, and they vary in their precision in targeting brain circuitry. What
is needed are the tools to both pinpoint the circuit dysfunction that underlies brain disor-
ders and precisely modulate circuit activity to correct this dysfunction. Rendering these
tools noninvasive would decrease risk and increase the number of people who could be
treated, also expanding the pool of research subjects and thereby hastening the pace at
which neuroscience unravels the mysteries of NMS disorders. Noninvasive technologies
also open the door to nonmedical uses as illustrated by the current use of direct current
brain stimulation for a variety of effects. The new circuit modulating technologies raise
the same ethical and societal issues that surround drugs that have the potential to be
mind or brain altering, but the magnitude and precision of the effects may be signifi-
cantly greater. The questions that arise from medical use of the new technologies will be
complicated, but they likely pale in comparison to the questions surrounding nonmedical
uses of neurotechnologies that enable interrogating and modulating the neural circuits of
individuals.
BRAIN Initiative® in April 2013. The BRAIN Initiative® aims to accelerate the develop-
ment and application of new neurotechnologies, empowering researchers to produce a
revolutionary, dynamic picture of the brain that, for the first time, shows how individual
cells and complex neural circuits interact in time and space. A richer understanding of
brain function will inform much-needed progress in diagnosing, treating, and even cur-
ing NMS disorders.
Given this bold goal, the President called for the BRAIN Initiative® to be an “all hands
on deck” effort involving not only US government agencies (currently the National
Institutes of Health (NIH), National Science Foundation (NSF), Intelligence Advanced
Research Projects Activity (IARPA), Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency
(DARPA), and the Food and Drug Administration (FDA)), but also companies, private
research institutes, patient advocacy organizations, state governments, research universi-
ties, philanthropists, and more. Many groups signed on in an enthusiastic response to
this call, even extending internationally. Currently, the Brain Canada Foundation, the
Australian National Health and Medical Research Council, and the Lundbeck Foundation
are NIH BRAIN Initiative® partners. The NIH, NSF, FDA, IARPA, the Kavli Foundation,
Simons Foundation, and the Allen Institute for Brain Science coordinate communication
activities through the BRAIN Initiative® Alliance with affiliates DARPA and the Howard
Hughes Medical Institute at Janelia Research Campus.
To inform scientific planning for the BRAIN Initiative®, NIH established a high-level
working group of the Advisory Committee to the NIH Director (ACD) (http://acd.od.nih.
gov/brain.htm). This working group sought broad input from the scientific community,
patient advocates, and the general public. Their report, released in June 2014 and enthu-
siastically endorsed by the ACD, articulated the scientific goals of the NIH component of
the BRAIN Initiative® and developed a multiyear scientific roadmap for achieving these
goals, including timetables, milestones, and cost estimates (Advisory Committee to the
National Institutes of Health Director (2014). BRAIN 2025: A Scientific Vision outlines
a plan for accelerating technology development for neuroscience, with the intention of
developing and using new tools to acquire fundamental new insights into how the ner-
vous system functions in health and disease. The working group identified the analy-
sis of neural circuits as being particularly suitable for potentially revolutionary scientific
advances. Table 8.1 outlines how the NIH currently organizes scientific programming for
the BRAIN Initiative®.
Circuit technologies Develop tools and technologies for circuit mapping and func-
tional, specifically targeted manipulation of circuit activity
Neural recording and modulation Record and manipulate neural activity with cellular resolution,
at multiple depths and locations across the brain
Human imaging and noninvasive Develop next-generation imaging technologies, and advance
neuromodulation understanding of the relationship between imaging signals and
the underlying brain circuits and cellular activity. Promote the
development, implementation, and integration of innovative
new technologies for human neuroscience research
Understanding circuit function Understand the circuits and patterns of neural activity that give
rise to mental experience and behavior
Training and dissemination Disseminate new neurotechnologies and tools to a wide scien-
tific user base, along with the knowledge required to use them
well
Neuroethics Support neuroethics efforts that can both guide BRAIN
Initiative® research and address ethical dilemmas raised
through advancements in neuroscience
be generated and will challenge current methods of data analysis and intuitive interpre-
tation of meaning. To date, 125 projects have been funded, exceeding an investment of
$130 million USD. These include a systematic inventory of the different cell types of the
brain; targeted genetic and nongenetic approaches for accessing specific cells and circuits;
new and improved capabilities for recording from, and modulating activity of, rapidly
firing collections of neurons; and development of new theories, models, and methods to
analyze complex neural data. Some new tools have already sparked a significant shift in
neuroscience research. For example, optogenetics and chemogenetics are two methods
for cell type-specific modulation; the former uses light and the latter uses engineered
receptor/ligand pairs to control the activity of cells, such as targeted neurons, in living tis-
sue. In contrast to current tools such as DBS or available pharmaceuticals, these tools have
unprecedented spatial and temporal control. They are currently used with much success
in animal models to probe brain circuitry and modulate behaviors such as fear condition-
ing and susceptibility to stress (Haubensak et al. 2010; Perova et al. 2015). The use of these
and other tools to interrogate and modulate circuits in animal studies may soon be used
to study human circuits in ex vivo human brain tissue from surgical biopsies, autopsy
tissue, or cerebral organoids derived from induced pluripotent stem cells. In the future,
149
harnessing these tools to modulate brain circuit function in patients may provide thera-
peutic relief for NMS disorders (for discussion, see Whittle et al. 2014).
Of particular note when considering the potential ethical implications of NIH BRAIN
Initiative® research are current efforts toward understanding human brain function and
treating human brain disorders. To date, the NIH BRAIN Initiative® has funded 14 proj-
ects involving human subjects. These include studies to understand the signals underly-
ing noninvasive imaging modalities, more sophisticated understanding of noninvasive
neuromodulation techniques, and development of novel methods of noninvasive neuro-
modulation. Examples of the latter already studied in humans include focused ultrasound
(Legon et al. 2014), and transcranial magnetic stimulation and direct current stimula-
tion (Deng et al. 2015). In addition, BRAIN Initiative® projects are focused on developing
genetic means to confer electromagnetic sensitivity (Stanley et al. 2016; Wheeler et al.
2016) or chemical sensitivity (Roth 2016) to precise brain circuits.
The NIH is also expanding its portfolio of research with implantable neuromodula-
tion devices, including a new BRAIN Public–Private Partnership Program, which will
connect academic researchers with manufacturers of next-generation invasive devices for
recording and modulation in the human central nervous system. Further, to understand
the unique properties and functions of human neural circuits, the NIH is supporting
research opportunities for studies with neurosurgical patients. This pool of patients com-
prises three types: people who are receiving DBS, people implanted with brain–computer
interfaces, and people with implanted devices that perform activity monitoring for epi-
lepsy control.
One specific project proposes to use DBS to improve the level of consciousness in peo-
ple suffering from severe traumatic brain injuries. Traumatic brain injury (TBI) afflicts
hundreds of thousands of Americans each year, producing chronic cognitive disabilities
that lack effective treatment. Preliminary studies with TBI patients and nonhuman pri-
mates suggest that these cognitive disabilities may be due to disrupted circuit function
in the brain, specifically involving impaired connections between the thalamus and the
frontal cortex (Kinomura et al. 1996; van der Werf et al. 2002; Schiff et al. 2007). Some
investigators are using the latest device technology to deliver DBS to the thalamus, in
hopes of developing a next-generation device for treating cognitive impairment associ-
ated with TBI.
Another project in the area of human imaging aims to develop a completely new, non-
invasive method for measuring brain activity. This work is focused on the feasibility of
sonoelectric tomography, in which ultrasound to tag specific locations in the brain is
combined with conventional scalp electroencephalography to measure electrical activ-
ity. The information can then be used to construct a tomographic map of neuronal cur-
rents, leveraging the millisecond temporal resolution of electroencephalography and the
millimeter spatial resolution of ultrasound. If successful, this would be a powerful next-
generation imaging method, with the capacity not only to map the functions of brain
circuits in healthy individuals, but also for understanding and potentially diagnosing
complex neuropsychiatric disorders.
150
Neuroethical issues
The previously discussed example projects give us some insight into the potential ethi-
cal issues associated with neurotechnology research and development. Importantly,
although we recognize that tools to understand and modulate brain function are and
will continue to be used for a range of purposes, the NIH’s perspective is focused solely
on applications to improve health and reduce illness and disability—that is, medical
applications. Many experts have given much thought to the various relevant ethical
issues, and important scholarship is also stimulated by leadership of the International
Neuroethics Society (a small sampling: Fins 2011; Illes & Bird 2006; Farah 2015;
Sahakian et al. 2015). The NIH has hosted two meetings in Bethesda, MD, bringing
together scientists and ethicists to discuss key issues in neuroethics (proceedings from
these meetings, held in November 2014 and February 2016, can be found on the NIH
BRAIN Initiative® website http://braininitiative.nih.gov/about/newg.htm). Some of
these neuroethical issues are not new—that is, they can be thought of as classic bioeth-
ical issues that are not fundamentally different from those that ethicists and scientists
grapple with in other areas of biomedical research.
For example, new methods for direct stimulation of neurons and neural circuits raise
questions of safety and the acceptable degree of risk for human patients:
◆ What benchmarks should be adopted for testing new methods before they are put to
use with humans, and who should make such decisions?
◆ What level of antecedent evidence is necessary to justify translating preclinical research
into work with human subjects?
◆ When contemplating testing new methods in people who have brain disorders and
diseases, what is the best way to balance decision-making between the patient and
legal surrogate in deciding on an acceptable level of risk?
These important questions are not substantively different from those that would be posed
when considering new methodologies for use in other areas of biomedical research,
except that brain disorders can affect the circuits actually employed in decision-making
and brain circuits uniquely define personhood.
A second classic bioethical issue to consider is the question of incidental findings. Current
brain imaging techniques such as MRI are sufficiently sophisticated that, in the course of
imaging undertaken for the purpose of research, an investigator might unintentionally find
abnormalities or early indicators of disease. Indeed, incidental findings on brain scans with
modern MRI technology are common, and prevalence increases with age (Morris et al.
2009). As neurotechnology research progresses and new methods for deciphering brain
function develop, the domains of such incidental findings will undoubtedly expand. The
question, of course, is what to do with this information, especially if the indicator reveals
an uncertain degree of risk, or the disease or disorder is one for which there is no effective
treatment. One field that has also spurred much thought on this question is genetics. Genes
can be predictive, though often in complex patterns of association that modern science
does not yet fully understand, making prognostication based on genetic testing nuanced
15
Neuroethical issues 151
(Pasic et al. 2013). A further complicating factor, and one that may give a hint of what is to
come for the field of neuroscience, is the growing usage of commercial direct-to-consumer
genetic testing. In December 2013, the Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical
Issues (Bioethics Commission) released its report Anticipate and Communicate: Ethical
Management of Incidental and Secondary Findings in the Clinical, Research, and Direct-to-
Consumer Contexts. The Commission argued that researchers, clinicians, and companies
should expect incidental findings, plan ahead for how to address them, and communicate
with patients or subjects about handling such findings in advance of conducting any tests.
These recommendations echo those made by Illes and colleagues regarding incidental find-
ings in neuroimaging (Illes et al. 2006). The authors argued that disclosure of suspicious
neuroimaging-associated incidental findings to subjects is ethically desirable, though wide
variability exists in such disclosure for the estimated tens of thousands of human subjects
involved in neuroimaging research annually. Even with acknowledgment that disclosure is
desirable, additional questions abound such as whether all neuroimaging studies should
include a physician trained to interpret brain scans, and how to assist vulnerable popula-
tions (e.g., uninsured subjects) in navigating incidental findings.
Beyond such classic bioethical issues exist various ethical questions uniquely associated
with neuroscience research that require careful thought. These questions arise because
the brain is the organ of the mind, and our new neuroscience tools and technologies
provide powerful, unprecedented ways of understanding and modulating brain func-
tion. Such scientific progress must be carefully considered, since it has the potential to
fundamentally alter the understanding of our innate and autonomous sense of self, and
could conflict with our deeply held beliefs about personal volition and responsibility. In
recognition of these concerns, when launching the BRAIN Initiative® in 2013, President
Obama charged his Bioethics Commission to identify proactively a set of core ethical
standards to both guide neuroscience research and address ethical dilemmas raised by
the application of neuroscience research findings. The Commission held public stake-
holder meetings in 2013 and 2014, and issued a two-part report to respond to the rap-
idly emerging and evolving field of neuroscience (Presidential Commission for the Study
of Bioethical Issues 2014, 2015). In the first volume of Gray Matters, the Commission
focused on the importance of integrating ethics into neuroscience research across the
life of a research endeavor. Preemptive integration of ethics into the scientific process
can help guard against ethical setbacks that might undermine research and erode public
support and trust. Thus their recommendation can be succinctly stated as: integration,
not intervention. The European Union’s Human Brain Project (HBP) offers one model
of this approach in action: the HBP has a robust Ethics and Society Programme, which
recognizes the social, ethical, and philosophical implications of HBP-related work, and
aims to recognize concerns early and address them in an open and transparent manner.
Additional recommendations from Gray Matters relate to the importance of integrating
ethics into science education at all levels, the value of including ethicists on scientific
advisory groups, and, from the second volume, specific analysis on the topics of cognitive
enhancement, consent capacity, and neuroscience and the legal system.
152
Conclusion
We have described just some of the issues associated with neurotechnology research
and development that a program of neuroethics can help navigate. The broad and var-
ied neuroethical landscape will require different types of approaches. Some of the issues
are particularly amenable to empirical or normative research. For example, it would be
essential to analyze how participants, participants’ families, and researchers differ in their
perceptions of risk in clinical research with novel neurotechnologies, particularly in stud-
ies with children and cognitively impaired adults. These concrete data could then inform
best practices for the consent process in these studies. Other areas, such as sharing human
clinical research data or managing incidental findings, might benefit from the develop-
ment of guidance documents. In some cases, additional scholarship may be needed, which
could take the form of workshops with extensive discussion and published proceedings.
Going forward, the NIH BRAIN Initiative® will lean heavily on its Neuroethics Division
to consider neuroethics issues and suggest ways to address them. Experts in philoso-
phy, bioethics, psychology, and neuroscience will be consulted to inform future steps.
Additional services may be important, such as providing ethics consultations to funded
researchers working in this space. More broadly, we hope to foster dialogue between
BRAIN-funded researchers and ethicists and their colleagues worldwide, empower sci-
entists’ and clinicians’ consideration of the ethical issues, and urge them to be stewards of
their own work. These efforts will help ensure that neurotechnology research and devel-
opment rests on a solid ethical foundation.
Brain activity forms the physical basis of our humanity and neuroethics provides a
framework for discussing the ethical use of technologies that monitor or modulate the
fundamental features that make us unique as individuals. Society has engaged in a con-
tinuous dialogue over the centuries about accepting, rejecting, or regulating the tools that
15
References 155
spring from science; that focus needs to sharpen on neuroscience as new tools open new
windows into the brain.
Note
1. Editor’s note: an act similar to GINA, the Genetic Non-Discrimination Act, was passed by the
Parliament of Canada in March 2017.
References
Alzheimer’s Association (2015). Alzheimer’s disease facts and figures. Alzheimer’s & Dementia, 11(3),
332–384.
Advisory Committee to the National Institutes of Health Director (2014). BRAIN 2025: A Scientific
Vision. United States Government. Available from: http://braininitiative.nih.gov [accessed March
2, 2016].
Bloom, D.E., Cafiero, E.T., Jané-Llopis, E., et al. (2011). The Global Economic Burden of
Noncommunicable Diseases. World Economic Forum. Available from: http://www.weforum.org/
EconomicsOfNCD [accessed March 2, 2016].
DeLong, M.R. and Wichmann, T. (2015). Basal ganglia circuits as targets for neuromodulation in
Parkinson disease. JAMA Neurology, 72(11), 1354–1360.
Deng, Z.D., McClintock, S.M., Oey, N.E., Luber, B., and Lisanby, S.H. (2015). Neuromodulation
for mood and memory: from the engineering bench to the patient bedside. Current Opinion in
Neurobiology, 30, 38–43.
Dyson, F. (1997). Imagined Worlds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Farah, M.J. (2015). An ethics toolbox for neurotechnology. Neuron, 86(1), 34–37.
Fins, J.J. (2011). Neuroethics, neuroimaging, and disorders of consciousness: promise or peril?
Transactions of the American Clinical and Climatological Association, 122, 336–346.
Haubensak, W., Kunwar, P.S., Cai, H., et al. (2010). Genetic dissection of an amygdala microcircuit that
gates conditioned fear. Nature, 468(7321), 270–276.
Illes, J. and Bird, S.J. (2006). Neuroethics: a modern context for ethics in neuroscience. Trends in
Neuroscience, 29(9), 511–517.
Illes, J., Kirschen, M.P., Edwards, E., et al. (2006). Working Group on Incidental Findings in Brain
Imaging Research. Ethics. Incidental findings in brain imaging research. Science, 311(5762), 783–784.
Lisanby, S.H. (2007). Electroconvulsive therapy for depression. New England Journal of Medicine,
357(19), 1939–1945.
Liu, X., Ramirez, S., Pang, P.T., et al. (2012). Optogenetic stimulation of a hippocampal engram
activates fear memory recall. Nature, 484(7394), 381–385.
Kinomura, S., Larssen, J., Gulyas, B., and Roland, P.E. (1996). Activation by attention of the human
reticular formation and thalamic intralaminar nuclei. Science, 271, 512–515.
Legon, W., Sato, T.F., Opitz, A., et al. (2014). Transcranial focused ultrasound modulates the activity of
primary somatosensory cortex in humans. Nature Neuroscience, 17(2), 322–329.
Mayberg, H.S. (2009). Targeted electrode-based modulation of neural circuits for depression. Journal of
Clinical Investigation, 119(4), 717–725.
Mohamed, F.B., Faro, S.H., Gordon, N.J., Platek, S.M., Ahmad, H., and Williams, J.M. (2006). Brain
mapping of deception and truth telling about an ecologically valid situation: functional MR imaging
and polygraph investigation—initial experience. Radiology, 238(2), 679–688.
156
Morris, Z., Whiteley, W.N., Longstreth, W.T., Jr., et al. (2009). Incidental findings on brain magnetic
resonance imaging: systematic review and meta-analysis. BMJ, 339.
Murray, C.J., Vos, T., Lozano, R., et al. (2012). Disability-adjusted life years (DALYs) for 291 diseases
and injuries in 21 regions, 1990–2010: a systematic analysis for the Global Burden of Disease Study
2010. The Lancet, 380(9859), 2197–2223.
Pasic, M.D., Samaan, S., and Yousef, G.M. (2013). Genomic medicine: new frontiers and new
challenges. Clinical Chemistry, 59(1), 158–167.
Perova, Z., Delevich, K., and Li, B. (2015). Depression of excitatory synapses onto parvalbumin
interneurons in the medial prefrontal cortex in susceptibility to stress. Journal of Neuroscience,
35(7), 3201–3206.
Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues (2013). Anticipate and
Communicate: Ethical Management of Incidental and Secondary Findings in the Clinical,
Research, and Direct-to-Consumer Contexts. United States Government. Available from: https://
bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/node/3183.html [accessed February 12, 2017].
Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues (2014). Gray Matters: Integrative
Approaches for Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society. United States Government. Available from: https://
bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/node/3543.html [accessed February 12, 2017].
Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues (2015). Gray Matters: Topics at the
Intersection of Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society. United States Government. Available from: https://
bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/node/4704.html [accessed February 12, 2017].
Roth, B.L. (2016). DREADDs for neuroscientists. Neuron, 89(4), 683–694.
Sahakian, B.J., Bruhl, A.B., Cook, J., et al. (2015). The impact of neuroscience on society: cognitive
enhancement in neuropsychiatric disorders and in healthy people. Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 370(1677), 20140214.
Schiff N.D., Giacino, J.T., Kalmar, K., et al. (2007). Behavioural improvements with thalamic
stimulation after severe traumatic brain injury. Nature, 448(7153), 600–603. [Erratum in: Nature,
2008, 452(7183), 120.]
Slaughter, L.M. (2008). The Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act: why your personal genetics
are still vulnerable to discrimination. Surgical Clinics of North America, 88(4), 723–738.
Smith, S.M., Nichols, T.E., Vidaurre, D., et al. (2015). A positive-negative mode of population
covariation links brain connectivity, demographics and behavior. Nature Neuroscience, 18(11),
1565–1567.
Stanley, S.A., Kelly, L., Latcha, K.N., et al. (2016). Bidirectional electromagnetic control of the
hypothalamus regulates feeding and metabolism. Nature, 531(7596), 647–650.
van der Werf, Y.D., Witter, M.P., and Groenewegen, H.J. (2002). The intralaminar and midline nuclei
of the thalamus. Anatomical and functional evidence for participation in processes of arousal and
awareness. Brain Research Reviews, 39, 107–140.
Wheeler, M.A., Smith, C.J., Ottolini, M., et al. (2016). Genetically targeted magnetic control of the
nervous system. Nature Neuroscience, 19(5), 756–761.
Whittle, A.J., Walsh, J., and de Lecea, L. (2014). Light and chemical control of neuronal
circuits: possible applications in neurotherapy. Expert Review of Neurotherapeutics, 14(9),
1007–1017.
157
Part II
Chapter 9
Introduction
At the time of publication of the first edition of Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory,
Practice and Policy (Illes 2006), there was focus on the implications of the new neuro-
sciences on questions of self-determination, personal identity, and moral responsibility.
There was also acknowledgment that both genetic and environmental factors were signifi-
cant determinants in the neurocognitive capacity of children to achieve across domains of
academic performance, social adaptations, and socioeconomic ends (Farah et al. 2006).
Early concerns emerged about how this information should be and could be used, and
what implications such information would have on how children should be viewed as
individuals or as members of particular populations vulnerable to prejudicial labeling.
Observational studies in childhood of intellectual quotient, personality, and behav-
ioral inventories date back to early in the twentieth century. Piaget’s work began in the
1920s (Piaget 1926). In addition to characterizing patterns of infancy through child-
hood behavioral development, he also described preliminary findings of normal moral
development (Piaget 1997) based on observations of games play. He was an impor-
tant influence on subsequent generations of developmental investigators including
Lawrence Kohlberg (Kohlberg 1981) who elaborated a highly controversial theory of
moral development in children stratified according to gender. The expected stages of
early infancy and childhood development learned by every pediatrician in the Anglo-
European-American tradition of the twentieth century and the common screening
inventories used in well-child pediatric care all derive from Piaget’s insights. The first
reported collaborative thinking about the intersections of developmental psychol-
ogy and emerging developmental neurosciences occurred in 1989 during a National
Institute of Child Health and Human Development/National Institute of Mental
Health-sponsored meeting in which Adele Diamond brought together developmen-
tal psychologists and neuroscientists (Diamond 1990). Subsequent studies confirmed
observations of variants in executive function in children under a variety of genetic
and environmental influences (Farah et al. 2006). Over the last decade, there has been
160 1
160 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
and healthcare providers have a moral obligation to engage in to assure that this
extraordinary data is not used to oppress further already disadvantaged groups?
3. With the prospect of full understanding of both intrinsic and extrinsic determinants
of the mechanics of brain development in childhood rearing, we presume that inter-
ventions may be devised to normalize brain development and hence psychological
functioning. How do we define normalcy? Would fixing or tweaking neurocogni-
tive function eliminate diversity in personality, temperament, cognitive precocity, or
genius?
As a framework for examining these questions, I will begin with a description of the
concept of the open future of the child (Feinberg 1980). Next will be a discussion of what
is accepted as evolving cognitive competence of children and adolescents, particularly
with respect to self-awareness, insight, and decision-making. The accelerated maturity
of healthcare decision-making among adolescents experiencing lifelong chronic or life-
limiting illnesses, or both, will also be described. Then I will summarize some of the recent
work among neuroscience colleagues on genetic and environmental influences on brain
development and behavior from the prenatal period through adolescence. An account
of the pediatric bioethical theory pertinent to this work will follow, providing a context
for discussion about how neuroscience findings might change how we look at the moral
status and evolving neurocognitive competency of affected children. Finally, I will discuss
the social justice implications and what social strategies ought to be put in place in order
to assure the most open future for not only affected children but also all of our children.
162 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
Feinberg proposed that societies have broad moral obligations to set into place laws
and policies which would assure the future of children’s potential self-determination or
autonomy. Examples include legal prohibitions of physical and emotional abuse, and obli-
gations to avoid risky behaviors that endanger the welfare of children. Thus there are
minimum age standards for permitting cigarette smoking, imbibing of alcoholic bever-
ages, and driving an automobile. Once the minimal legal age of permission is passed,
individuals are free, more or less, to decide for themselves the level of risk they wish to
undertake on their own recognizance. The variations in societal determination of these
minimum ages for specific autonomous functions are an interesting reflection on a given
society’s beliefs about when children actually do come of age, and therefore may take on
the benefits of full autonomy as well as the risks of potential adverse outcomes from those
independent risk-taking behaviors.
In the context of healthcare, this is most frequently taken to mean that parents or other
responsible parties (i.e., caregivers, guardians, and healthcare professionals) are obligated
morally to make healthcare decisions on behalf of the children in their charge which are
most likely to result in the greatest realization of their children’s eventual potential for
self-determination and flourishing. Therefore, parents and caregivers are usually required
to participate in certain public health measures such as childhood immunizations, to pro-
vide adequate nutrition, and to seek healthcare for interval or chronic illnesses.
Nevertheless, particularly in a liberal society, there is wide discretion given to parents/
guardians about the determination of the threshold of obligation toward the usual societal
norms. For instance, in some polities, parents/guardians may forego routine childhood
immunizations for their children on the basis of religious liberty, or often a misplaced
anxiety about the very small risks of vaccines compared with the risks of adverse out-
comes following previously widespread viral diseases such as measles which can be asso-
ciated with risk for death and severe long-term morbidities such as pan-encephalitis.
On the other hand, the concerns of a liberal polity may result in misplaced criticism
about specific treatments of severely cognitively impaired individuals that are intended
to improve the quality of life of those individuals as well as facilitate the caregiving.
One example would be elective sterilization to eliminate risk of pregnancy in cognitively
impaired women, unable to consent to intercourse or to defend against rape. Another
example is the infamous case of the “Pillow Angel,” a profoundly encephalopathic and
neurocognitively diminished child, where growth attenuation treatments were pro-
vided with the intent to facilitate continued home versus institutional care (Gunther
& Diekema 2006). Critics asserted that the Pillow Angel possessed future reproductive
interests which were now foreclosed with the growth attenuation treatments (Liao et al.
2007; Peace & Roy 2014). For many healthcare professionals, as well as their parents, the
notion that a microcephalic child who had been non-ambulatory and in a state of pro-
found static encephalopathy had any particular interests in the future, let alone repro-
ductive interests, is difficult to understand. These examples highlight some of the ethical
tensions within the practical application of the principles embedded in Feinberg’s child’s
open future concept.
163
With this background, then, the new discoveries in pediatric neuroethics bring into
sharp relief some of the problems of self-determination against a background of genetic
and environmental modulation of brain structure and behavior. The new neuroscience
can be interpreted to diminish substantially concepts of free will as well as call into ques-
tion the meaning of personal identity and personal authenticity, and ultimate moral
responsibility for actions. And the question is whether free will and autonomy can be
preserved in the face of the new neuroscience.
164 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
cohort of adolescents who are a part of the University of Southern California Risk Factors
for Antisocial Behavior Twin Study (Baker et al. 2002, 2006, 2013; Yang et al. 2012). In
an endeavor to separate genetic influences from environmental influences on developing
brain structure, 14-year-old twin pairs were studied: monozygotic pairs were compared
with dizygotic pairs, the latter of whom share only one-half of their genetic endowment.
The investigators hypothesized that any environmentally derived differences in cortical
thickness would appear in regions of low heritability (i.e., the motor and sensory cortices).
As it turns out, 80% of interpersonal variations in cortical thickness could be explained
through genetic effects and occurred in later developing areas associated with higher-
order functions in the prefrontal cortex (i.e., fluid intelligence). On the other hand, there
was evidence for environmental malleability in posterior parietal areas associated with
development of spatial attention, topographic information, and language (i.e., capacities
that are determined experientially).
Normal children and adolescents experience a rapid increase in cognitive processing
of sensory, motor, cognitive, and emotional information. These behavioral changes are
associated with changes in brain structure—including synaptic pruning (i.e., controlled
reduction of the number of synapses) and myelination (i.e., increased axonal dimensions)
(Sowell et al. 1999, 2003; Selemon 2013; Houston et al. 2014). In order to characterize
variations from the normal pattern, the investigators (Yang et al. 2015) conducted struc-
tural magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) brain scanning of 14-year-olds and compared
these findings with serial measures of psychopathy with the Childhood Psychopathy Scale
made at ages 9–10, 11–13, 14–15, and 16–18 years. The investigators were interested in
changes in the psychopathy scores over time. They found that higher psychopathy scores
were associated with increased temporal cortical thicknesses, findings specific to adoles-
cents. There were gender-related differences in regional variation in cortical thickness
as well (i.e., female subjects also showed decreased frontal cortical thickness). Increased
psychopathic tendencies over time in individuals, as measured with the Childhood
Psychopathy Scale, were associated with increased temporal cortical thickness. These
changes were more prominent in males versus females. Localization of these structural
anomalies to temporal lobe regions involved in complex social cognition and emotion
are consistent with the observed functional abnormalities in psychopathic tendencies.
Further, these observations are consistent with a neurodevelopmental origin of psychopa-
thy as opposed to or in addition to an experiential model of psychopathy. All the study
subjects were deemed to be healthy, in contrast to well-studied adults who were already
known to have overt psychopathic behaviors (substance abuse, criminality). Therefore,
Yang and colleagues concluded that abnormal cortical development in the temporal lobes
is a likely biomarker of psychopathy in adolescents and may represent delayed maturation,
which is genetically driven, and results in social and moral dysfunction (Yang et al. 2015).
New and continuously improving treatment and neonatal intensive care techniques
have resulted in marked improvement in survival of preterm infants born at lower ges-
tational ages. Adverse neurological injury such as intracranial hemorrhage and isch-
emic injury (periventricular leukomalacia) are known to be associated with poorer
16 1
166 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
common PAH in each woman’s environment for 48 hours. More than 600 women partici-
pated in this phase of the study.
Children exposed to higher levels of PAH in utero showed a variety of neurodevel-
opmental problems at ages 3, 5, and 7 years (Perera et al. 2006, 2008, 2009, 2012). The
investigators then hypothesized that they could identify specific abnormalities in brain
structure associated with prenatal PAH exposure which resulted in the neurodevelop-
mental abnormalities (information processing speed, ADHD) seen in a subset of these
children at ages 7–9 years (Peterson et al. 2015). They performed MRI on a subset of 40
children stratified into above-and below-median in utero PAH exposure. In addition
to the imaging, the Child Behavior Checklist and the Wechsler Scales of Intelligence for
Children (WISC-IV) were administered. The differences between children with low intra-
uterine exposure versus high intrauterine exposure were striking: white matter reductions
were associated with higher PAH exposure, specifically in the left hemisphere. Therefore,
the left hemisphere in utero appears to be more vulnerable to the neurotoxic effects of
PAH. The investigators go on to link these observed changes to what is now known about
the transcriptional pathways that control brain hemispheric structure by week 10 of gesta-
tion. Of interest, the regions of white matter reduction in this cohort of children exposed
to high in utero PAH and who also had ADHD syndrome are qualitatively different
from white matter abnormalities observed in adolescent youth with ADHD syndrome
(Peterson et al. 2015). The authors speculate that environmental neurotoxins produce a
distinct subtype of ADHD.
The investigators recognized some of the implications relating to their study population
of impoverished, principally immigrant peoples and peoples of color in the urban neigh-
borhoods under investigation. However, through careful stratification of study subjects,
they were able to demonstrate independent environmental toxic effects on both brain
structure and neurocognitive function within this population. Therefore, any potential
arguments about intrinsic racial or ethnic differences could be dismissed.
That childhood experiences can modulate developmental functions, behavior and neu-
rocognitive capacity has been amply demonstrated (McLoyd 1998; Rosenzweig 2003;
Noble et al. 2007; Duncan & Magnuson 2012; Kim et al. 2013; Luby et al. 2013). However,
brain structural correlates of the neurocognitive, neurodevelopmental associations with
socioeconomic variables have not previously been demonstrated in any large num-
bers of study subjects. The collaborators of the Pediatric Imaging, Neurocognition, and
Genetics (PING) Study have examined these relationships among more than 1000 indi-
viduals between ages 3 and 20 years (Noble et al. 2015). Previous studies have looked at
brain cortical volume. However, changes in the normal sequence of cortical surface area
change may be more reflective over individual experiences. Normally, in contrast with
cortical volume, cortical surface area increases from infancy through early adolescence,
after which there is progressive shrinkage through middle adulthood. Genetic program-
ming of these changes is modulated by individual experience. Therefore, although nor-
mally cortical thickness decreases into adolescence, and thinness tends to be associated
with greater intelligence, cortical surface area increases with greater intelligence. Against
168 1
168 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
the above-mentioned background, the PING study group made the following observa-
tions: both parental education and family income were associated with increased corti-
cal surface area. Genetic ancestry was not a relevant factor. Subcortical structures, for
example, hippocampal size, are positively associated with parental educational achieve-
ment. Parental educational attainment was found to be linearly associated with cortical
surface area. Specifically, any increment of parental education was associated with a com-
mensurate increase in cortical surface area. The brain regions in question are important
in development of language, executive functions, and memory. Because of the logarith-
mic associations, the lower parental educational attainment and income, the greater the
impact on brain structure.
This study is particularly controversial and therefore it is not surprising that the results
elicited a considerable amount of media attention. The very tight coupling of socioec-
onomic status with brain structure seems to have struck a nerve in mainstream media
and within the greater North American public. Apparently, the specter of shrunken
brains among large segments of our population (i.e., our socioeconomically disadvan-
taged citizens and their children) created significant unrest (King 2015; Mohan 2015).
It is not yet clear whether that concern and unrest are sufficiently long-lasting to result
in significant social policy changes and access to early educational and psychological
interventions.
Common ethical issues emerge across all of these studies. What do the data say about
personal identity? Is identity immutable if associated with structural changes in the brain?
Do all such changes translate to clinically significant abnormalities in information proc-
essing, insight, creativity, and fluid intelligence? How do these variants in brain develop-
ment play against the normal ontogeny of maturation of cognitive processes in children
and adolescents?
A key component for individual rights is the understanding that free will or at least the
possibility or potential for free will is an important determinant of individual person-
hood and worthy moral status. Without the possibility of free will, the concerns within
bioethics about self-determination and respect for autonomy would be irrelevant, mean-
ingless. A discussion about the power of determinism (Rachels 2012) versus the actuality
of free will is well beyond the scope of this chapter, but the dichotomy of determinism (or
more properly, pre-determinism) versus potential for eventual full autonomy is one of the
problems of the now demonstrated morphological aberrations in the brains of the young
throughout childhood.
Returning to Feinberg’s “open future of the child,” while theoretically compelling, much
of pediatric approaches to bioethics have involved pragmatic specifications about how to
implement appropriate decision-making for minors in stewardship for the future mature
individual. There have been at least two significant competing models with some pro-
posed variants.
The most prevalent model in pediatrics is that articulated in the canonical work Deciding
for Others (Buchanan & Brock 1990). For individuals apparently either without compe-
tence or having lost their competence in the neurocognitive sense, surrogates can best
serve their charges by making decisions on their behalf using a “best interests standard”
(BIS) where the parents, or other legitimate responsible parties attempt to determine net
value among alternative choices which balance benefits versus the risks or burdens with
each choice. This standard requires an evaluation of quality of life considerations and the
authors stress that they mean quality of life, as it is significant to the presumed interests of
the individual in question as opposed to the interests of the family or the community at
large that may sway the decision-making toward allocation of either more or less resources.
In other words, decisions on behalf of those deemed unable to decide for themselves should
be made solely on the basis of the worth or consequences of those decisions for those indi-
viduals and not on the basis of the perceived social utility of those individuals.
Although Buchanan and Brock were frequently speaking of individuals severely neu-
rocognitively disabled or those without developmental capacity for decision-making,
depending on how we determine the threshold for neurocognitive incapacity, this surro-
gate decision-making standard could be applied to some individuals now known to have
structural brain anomalies associated with genetic, socioeconomic, or environmental
adverse effects consisting of behavioral anomalies, processing difficulties, and sociopathy.
Further, Buchanan and Brock wrote separately of the specific problem of older children
who demonstrated evolving self-awareness, maturation of abstract reasoning skills, exer-
cise of judgment and insight, and who would have increasing direct interests in their own
healthcare decision-making.
Buchanan and Brock emphasized the priority of the individual’s interests over all other
parties. Therefore, they strictly privileged rights and interests of children/minors over all
other interests including family and community interests.
On the other hand, others have weighed in on behalf of the priority of relationships and
the continuity thereof on whose interests should be first served? Murray speaks eloquently
170 1
170 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
of the importance of the minor child’s place in the tapestry of relationships of the family
and then the social community (Murray 1996). Friedman Ross introduced her concept of
“constrained parental autonomy” (Ross 1998) as a means of bridging the divide between
pure parental prerogative and pure self-interested primacy of their children’s interests
over and above the interests of the parents/family and larger community. Friedman Ross
has contended that childhood autonomy cannot be appropriately expressed by children
due to inadequately developed maturity, lack of insight into consequences of decisions,
and perhaps inadequate foresight or imagination into the future. Therefore, she has stipu-
lated that parents must make all decisions in trust, premised on the requirement that the
constraints that parents must abide by relate to their obligations to provide a minimum of
supportive and protective care which can optimize or at least present the prospect of the
potential for maturation into full autonomous adulthood. Friedman Ross’s interpretation
of the child’s open future is that parents must engage in constraints to their children’s own
choices so as to optimize putative quality of the future child’s life. By doing so, parents
may promote the ongoing health and survival of their children until they can develop
sufficiently mature capacity to be empowered to make their own autonomous decisions.
Two extensive commentaries (Hester 2007; Salter 2012) on the value and utility of the
BIS shed a great deal of light on the pragmatic problems of applying the BIS. Salter has
produced a highly nuanced and detailed description of the BIS in its several versions. She
lists a variety of self-regarding interests ascribed to children including both present and
future interests. The most pertinent of interests of children against the background of
neuroscience are those relating to cognitive-developmental function both in the present
and in the future. Salter is also highly critical of the BIS because of the following prob-
lems: poorly defined terms, standards, and evaluation processes; there appears to be no
uniformly accepted understanding of criteria for determining the best interests resulting
in inconsistent and often too narrow application of the standard to specific cases; finally,
the standard does not allow for adequate respect for the family. Both Salter and Hester
reflect on cases where the specific contexts and circumstances are not amenable to solu-
tion through the BIS. Salter points out clearly that other interested parties, aside from the
child, for example, the healthcare providers and the parents, may not agree or have clarity
about what course of action(s) represent the child’s best interests.
Hester writes of the difficulties of ascribing interests to very young or compromised
infants, or both, because of the lack of any duration of lived experience. Therefore, he
observes that the tendency is to restrict the discussion about the best interest choices for
young infants to either avoiding net harm or to give all priority of decision-making to
parents. He also asserts that parental interests may be connected to but not necessarily
identical to the cultural and social interests of the community at large in the welfare of
infants and children. Therefore, Hester believes that the sources of interests contributing
to decision-making for very young children or children who may be neurocognitively
compromised should be expanded to encompass the larger community. Hester invokes
narrative as a means for ascertaining the relevant stories of the family, the child and the
larger community, which have bearing on healthcare decision-making for the individual
17
child. That is, only by identifying all of the relevant stakeholders can one determine what
are the real best interests for the individual child.
It is clear from these arguments that, as a prevalent/dominant practice in deciding for
children, the BIS can weigh more heavily in the construction of a decision-making future
for children with evidence of neurocognitive compromise or difference. That is, there is
more at stake in potential imposed constraints on the futures of compromised children.
The issues surrounding the emergence of personal identity and how others view the
individual emerging personality continue to be complex and difficult. As a counter to
the ambiguities of the BIS and the problems of recognizing developing individuation in
children, Lindemann has proposed a model of how personal identity is recognized by
others and how the perception of that identity as well as the maintenance of that per-
ception or recognition held over time, enables authenticity of the individual personality
(Lindemann 2014). She has described personhood as a composite of four elements: suf-
ficient mental activity is present to constitute a personality; aspects of the personality are
expressed bodily; others recognize those embodiments as expression of personality; and
others respond to what they perceive. Lindemann then goes on to describe how we see
ourselves and others as specific identities through “a web of stories depicting our most
important acts, experiences, characteristics, roles, relationships, and commitments. This
narrative tissue constitutes our personal identities, which play a crucial role in the prac-
tice of personhood” (Lindemann 2014, p.ix).
What Lindemann emphasizes is that our identities, and by connection, our moral status
as human beings, is determined first by how we are perceived by others, from the time
the gestating mother recognizes her emerging fetus, to the born child and emerging adult.
How individuals are perceived shapes how they view themselves, develop personality, and
how they engage in transactional activities or relationships with others: “Personal identi-
ties function as counters in our social transactions, in that they convey understandings of
what those who bear them are expected to do”(Lindemann 2014, p.ix). That is, how indi-
viduals are perceived results in responses, or reciprocal behaviors that either reinforce the
perceptions, edit those perceptions, eliciting further responses so that the development of
identity and personality is seen in a relational/relationship context. Lindemann does not
directly discuss temperament (perhaps because that is intrinsic). But she does speak about
how the treatment of the other’s identity can be positive—that is, supportive, reinforcing,
stimulating behaviors that lead to flourishing. On the other hand, the treatment of the
other can be negative, and result in the creation of what Lindemann refers to as a damaged
identity (Nelson 2001).
Lindemann’s model is quite potent in the context of identified neurostructural anomalies
in at-risk children and youth for the following reasons: (1) at-risk subjects may embody
abnormal behaviors, or psychopathies, associated with their brain anomalies; (2) how
others perceive and respond to these behaviors can either reinforce negative behaviors or
shape more positive, more functional behaviors within the limits of the individual’s cogni-
tive capacity; and (3) targeted education and training of both at-risk individuals and their
families/community members could, over time, result in sustained alterations of behavior
172 1
172 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
Implicit is the notion that all individuals are deemed to have personal identity and moral
worth. The capabilities 4 through 10 are particularly pertinent to the status of children
with neurocognitive variant or disability. Nussbaum’s prescription, then, is that identi-
fication of socially constructed barriers to expression or experience of these capabilities
ought to allow communities to develop policy and practices which optimize/enhance
capabilities. The Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA) would be an example of the sort
of policy/practice approach endorsed by Nussbaum. She undoubtedly views the ADA as
moving in the right direction, though not as comprehensive as she would like. Nussbaum’s
variant on Sen’s capabilities approach is far more expansive and is not limited to consider-
ations of physical or mental disability but also includes other forms of social and/or eco-
nomic disparity. Recognizing the disproportionate burdens (time, money, labor) on the
part of caretakers of child with varying levels of neuro-disability, Nussbaum extends her
capabilities approach to caretakers and other affiliated personnel who may be recruited
to help with the increased care needs of special needs children. By no means, should
we assume that the increased burden of care involves only those children with the most
severe disabilities. Children with educational and/or social/behavioral disabilities may
also require more resources for education, supervision, and treatment. And Nussbaum
would contend that a just society recognize such needs and accommodate in order that
both at-risk children and their caretakers have flourishing lives:
Capabilities belong first and foremost to individual persons, and only derivatively to groups. The
approach espouses a principle of each person as an end. It stipulates that the goal is to produce
capabilities for each and every person, and not to use some people as a means to the capabilities of
others or of the whole. (Nussbaum 2011, p.35)
Well-being is the key goal in an alternative theory of social justice (Powers & Faden 2006).
The premise is that a sound public health system can ensure a minimum sufficiency of
goods and resources to all members of the society so that well-being can be achieved:
Our theory starts with the assumption that inequalities beget inequalities, and existing
inequalities—in the social determinants of well-being and ultimately in the essential dimensions
of well-being themselves—can compound, sustain, and reproduce a multitude of deprivations in
well-being, bringing some persons below the level of sufficiency for more than one dimension.
(Powers & Faden 2006, p.7)
Powers and Faden assert that the moral imperative of public health practice is not just
regulatory and prescriptive but is also to ensure social justice through allocation and dis-
tribution practices. They have defined well-being as a sufficiency of existence across a
number of dimensions which is similar to but not identical to the capabilities list:
1. Health
2. Personal security
3. Reasoning
4. Respect
5. Attachment
6. Self-determination.
174 1
174 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
They assert that the dimensions interact and that serious insufficiency of even one dimen-
sion tends to influence negatively the other dimensions of well-being too. They do not
equate well-being with absence of disease. They also identify, for some populations, such
as children, specific periods during the life cycle where public allocation decisions are
particularly important to ensure existing and developing well-being. They identify early
infancy and early childhood as periods of great vulnerability in terms of suboptimal
development of reasoning skills that can impair cognitive function lifelong. These are
also periods during the life cycle of great opportunity for interventions that can optimize
practical reasoning skills, above and beyond intrinsic capacity. Because of the priority
assigned to the needs of children by Powers and Faden, they acknowledge that in a public
health system designed to assure the well-being of all its citizens might result in conflicts
of priorities of allocation among subpopulations, for example, children versus the elderly
where there were constraints of resources.
There are always constraints on resources of one sort or another and Powers and Faden
propose strategies using quality of life potential, cost-effectiveness analyses, and cost-
utilization analyses to develop schemes for resource allocation which are fair and still
give priority to children’s needs. This is certainly a refreshing proposition for pediatric
healthcare providers! However, Powers and Faden also stipulate that context is important
in the final allocation decisions—that is, if specific situations place individuals in other
age groups at greater risk to their well-being, then it would be wrong to privilege children
always in terms of allocation of resources. Accounting of all dimensions of well-being
needs to be analyzed closely in order to determine who should be privileged at particular
times and under particular circumstances. On the other hand, children tend to live longer
and therefore a suboptimal well-being state would represent a greater burden to the indi-
vidual as well as the community if the needs of children were not addressed aggressively.
Presumably this stance would apply even more so for children identified to have risk for
poor neurocognitive outcomes.
With these marginally less abstract theories to consider, what we are left with are some
common conclusions: all children are owed optimal services in the form of education,
training, comprehensive care, suitable living conditions, and environments designed to
promote flourishing. Because of the increased burdens associated with providing addi-
tional services to compensate for additional neurocognitive risks, services for support of
families and caretakers should be allocated as well. In concrete terms, neither Nussbaum
nor Powers and Faden provided real descriptions of comprehensive capabilities or social
justice schemes.
Conclusion
Have we made any progress in answering the three questions posed at the beginning of
this paper?
1. How might genetic determinants of brain structure influence social policy to abridge
individual liberty and the individual’s open future?
175
Conclusion 175
2. What are the moral obligations of health researchers and healthcare providers to ensure
that socioeconomic and environmental pollution data not be misconstrued to oppress,
further, already disadvantaged groups by ascribing poorer neurocognitive outcomes to
genetic ancestry?
3. How should normalcy be defined and would correction of neurocognitive function
eliminate diversity in personality, temperament, cognitive precocity, or genius?
For question 1, yes, there are risks of biased perceptions and creation, in Lindemann’s words,
of damaged identities that foreclose many possibilities for remediation through education,
training, and improvement of the rearing environment in childhood. Social and policy
measures which could foster damaged identities are intuitively obvious, such as scapegoat-
ing and restriction of access to appropriate educational and other support services to such
children and their families. On the other hand, we are currently in an era of great libertari-
anism among the families of children who are neurocognitively compromised and fami-
lies are often tremendous advocates on behalf of their special needs children. However,
resources are not distributed at a federal level, but rather at individual states levels, in the
United States, so that access to those resources are certainly not universally available and
are highly variable according to a priori conditions determined by various insurance plans
or state policy. Further, mental health services are notoriously poorly supported.
For question 2, there is no doubt that researchers and clinicians have obligations to
ensure that the data are gathered and reported with sufficient controls so as to eliminate
misconstrual of results and to minimize the possibility of adding social oppression to the
plight of children and families who are less fortunate. Both Peterson and Sowell were able
to implement sufficient controls to disabuse any notions that the neurocognitive impair-
ments observed in their study populations could be ascribed to race, ethnicity or culture.
These are practices that ought to be a part of the design of all such studies.
For question 3, there are no answers yet. This question and all the implications will have
to wait for the next edition of this book.
To conclude, while much of the content of this chapter has been theoretical, there are
some pragmatic interventions that ought to be considered at both individual and societal
levels. They draw upon the different aspects of and strengths of neuroethical inquiry and
methods, and what they can offer looking ahead:
1. Minimization of prenatal exposure to neurotoxins (Lanphear et al. 2005; Mezzacappa
et al. 2011), and of all environmental sources of neurotoxins since adverse effects
on neurofunction are not limited to fetuses or children (Illes et al. 2014; Cabrera
et al. 2016).
2. Focus on maximal educational achievement across all socioeconomic classes for the
purposes of enhancing the likelihood of economic achievement that may ameliorate
the functional consequences of brain growth anomalies among children and adoles-
cents (Diamond & Lee 2011; Schonert-Reichl et al. 2015).
3. Promotion of a societal focus on improving the capabilities of all members of the
polity—whether using the model of Nussbaum or the public health model of Powers
176 1
176 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
References
Baker, L.A., Barton, M., and Raine, A. (2002). The Southern California Twin Register at the University
of Southern California. Twin Research, 5, 456–459.
Baker, L.A., Barton, M., Lozano, D.I., Raine, A., and Fowler, J.H. (2006). The Southern California Twin
Register at the University of Southern California: II. Twin Research and Human Genetics, 9, 933–940.
Baker, L.A., Tuvblad, C., Wang, P., et al. (2013). The Southern California Twin Register at the
University of Southern California: III. Twin Research and Human Genetics, 16, 336–343.
Bishop, S. (1980). Children, autonomy and the right to self-determination. In: Aiken, W. and Lafollette,
H. (Eds.) Whose Child? Children’s Rights, Parental Authority, and State Power, pp.154–176. Totowa,
NJ: Littlefield, Adams & Co.
Buchanan, A.E. and Brock, D.W. (1990). Deciding for Others: The Ethics of Surrogate Decision-Making.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Cabrera, L.Y., Tesluk, J., Chakraborti, M., Matthews, R., and Illes, J. (2016). Brain matters: from
environmental ethics to environmental neuroethics. Environmental Health, 15, 1–5.
Campbell, A.T., Derrington, S.F., Hester, D.M., and Lew, C.D. (2012). Her own decision: impairment
and authenticity in adolescence. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 23, 47–55.
Diamond, A. (1990). Introduction: the development and neural bases of higher cognitive
functions. In: The Development and Neural Bases of Higher Cognitive Functions, pp.xiii–lvi.
New York: New York Academy of Sciences.
Diamond, A. and Lee, K. (2011). Interventions shown to aid executive function development in
children 4 to 12 years old. Science, 333, 959–964.
Duncan, G.J. and Magnuson, K. (2012). Socioeconomic status and cognitive functioning: moving from
correlation to causation. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, 377–386.
Farah, M.J., Noble, K.G., and Hurt, H. (2006). Poverty, privilege, and brain development: empirical
findings and ethical implications. In: Illes, J. (ed.) Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory, Practice,
and Policy, pp.277–287. New York: Oxford University Press.
Feinberg, J. (1980). The child’s right to an open future. In: Aiken, W. and Lafollette, H. (Eds.) Whose
Child? Children’s Rights, Parental Authority, and State Power, pp.124–153. Totowa, NJ: Littlefield,
Adams & Co.
Feinberg, J. (1992). Freedom & Fulfillment: Philosophical Essays. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Gray, J.R. and Thompson, P.M. (2004). Neurobiology of intelligence: science and ethics. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 5, 471–482.
Grisso, T. and Vierling, L. (1978). Minors’ consent to treatment: a developmental perspective.
Professional Psychology, 9, 412–427.
17
References 177
Gunther, D.F. and Diekema, D.S. (2006). Attenuating growth in children with profound developmental
disability: a new approach to an old dilemma. Archives of Pediatrics & Adolescent Medicine, 160,
1013–1017.
Hester, D.M. (2007). Interests and neonates: there is more to the story than we explicitly acknowledge.
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 28, 357–372.
Hester, D.M. (2009). Adolescent decisionmaking, part i: introduction. Cambridge Quarterly of
Healthcare Ethics, 18, 300–302.
Horstkötter, D., Berghmans, R., De Ruiter, C., Krumeich, A., and De Wert, G. (2012). “We are also
normal humans, you know?” Views and attitudes of juvenile delinquents on antisocial behavior,
neurobiology and prevention. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 35, 289–297.
Houston, S.M., Herting, M.M., and Sowell, E.R. (2014). The neurobiology of childhood structural brain
development: conception through adulthood. Current Topics in Behavioral Neurosciences, 16, 3–17.
Illes, J. (Ed.) (2006). Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory, Practice, and Policy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Illes, J. and Racine, E. (2005). Imaging or imagining? A neuroethics challenge informed by genetics.
American Journal of Bioethics, 5, 5–18.
Illes, J. and Raffin, T.A. (2002). Neuroethics: an emerging new discipline in the study of brain and
cognition. Brain and Cognition, 50, 341–344.
Illes, J., Davidson, J., and Matthews, R. (2014). Environmental neuroethics: changing the environment
changing the brain. Recommendations submitted to the Presidential Commission for the Study of
Bioethical Issues. Journal of Law and the Biosciences, 1(2), 221–223.
IOM (2015). Health Literacy: Past, Present, and Future: Workshop Summary. Washington, DC: The
National Academies Press.
Kim, P., Evans, G.W., Angstadt, M., et al. (2013). Effects of childhood poverty and chronic stress on
emotion regulatory brain function in adulthood. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of
the United States of America, 110, 18442–18447.
King, N. (Director) (2015). Socioeconomic Status Could be Affecting Childrens’ Brains. Los Angeles,
CA: American Public Media.
Kohlberg, L. (1981). The Philosophy of Moral Development: Moral Stages and the Idea of Justice (Essays
on Moral Development, Vol. 1). San Francisco:, CA: Harper & Row.
Ladd, R.E. and Forman, E.N. (1995). Adolescent decision-making: giving weight to age-specific values.
Theoretical Medicine, 16, 333–345.
Lanphear, B.P., Vorhees, C.V., and Bellinger, D.C. (2005). Protecting children from environmental
toxins. PLoS Medicine, 2, e61.
Lao, Y., Wang, Y., Shi, J., Ceschin, R., Nelson, M., Panigrahy, A., and Leporé, N. (2016). Thalamic
alterations in preterm neonates and their relation to ventral striatum disturbances revealed by a
combined shape and pose analysis. Brain Structure and Function, 221(1), 487–506.
Liao, S.M., Savulescu, J., and Sheehan, M. (2007). The Ashley treatment: best interests, convenience,
and parental decision-making. Hastings Center Report, 37, 16–20.
Lindemann, H. (2014). Holding and Letting Go. New York: Oxford University Press.
Luby, J., Belden, A., Botteron, K., et al. (2013). The effects of poverty on childhood brain development: the
mediating effect of caregiving and stressful life events. JAMA Pediatrics, 167, 1135–1142.
McLoyd, V.C. (1998). Socioeconomic disadvantage and child development. American Psychologist, 53,
185–204.
Mezzacappa, E., Buckner, J.C., and Earls, F. (2011). Prenatal cigarette exposure and infant learning
stimulation as predictors of cognitive control in childhood. Developmental Science, 14, 881–891.
Mohan, G. (2015). Can money buy yours kids a bigger brain? Los Angeles Times, March 30.
178 1
178 What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future?
References 179
Shonkoff, J.P. and Levitt, P. (2010). Neuroscience and the future of early childhood policy: moving from
why to what and how. Neuron, 67, 689–691.
Sowell, E.R., Peterson, B.S., Thompson, P.M., Welcome, S.E., Henkenius, A.L., and Toga, A.W. (2003).
Mapping cortical change across the human life span. Nature Neuroscience, 6, 309–315.
Sowell, E.R., Thompson, P.M., Holmes, C.J., Batth, R., Jernigan, T.L., and Toga, A.W. (1999).
Localizing age-related changes in brain structure between childhood and adolescence using
statistical parametric mapping. NeuroImage, 9, 587–597.
Weir, R.F. and Peters, C. (1997). Affirming the decisions adolescents make about life and death.
Hastings Center Report, 27, 29–40.
Weithorn, L.A. and Campbell, S.B. (1982). The competency of children and adolescents to make
informed treatment decisions. Child Development, 53, 1589–1598.
Wenar, L. (2013). John Rawls. In: Zalta, E.N. (Ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013
edn.). Stanford, CA.
Wilkinson, D. (2013). Death of Disability?: The “Carmentis Machine” and Decision-Making for Critically
Ill Children. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Yang, Y., Joshi, A.A., Joshi, S.H., et al. (2012). Genetic and environmental influences on cortical
thickness among 14-year-old twins. Neuroreport, 23, 702–706.
Yang, Y., Wang, P., Baker, L.A., et al. (2015). Thicker temporal cortex associates with a developmental
trajectory for psychopathic traits in adolescents. PLoS ONE, 10, e0127025.
180
Chapter 10
Neuroprognostication after severe
brain injury in children: Science fiction
or plausible reality?
Sarah S. Welsh, Geneviève Du Pont-Thibodeau,
and Matthew P. Kirschen
Introduction
Neuroprognostication with regard to functional and cognitive recovery after brain injury
in children is highly complex, and occurs as a continuous, iterative process throughout the
initial resuscitation, acute, and subacute and rehabilitative phases of injury and recovery.
It requires constant and vigilant attention to translation of prognostication to meaningful
action for parents and families making clinical decisions on behalf of their children. This
translation is fraught with the implications for a child’s cognitive and physical potential,
any particular family’s set of goals and acceptable outcomes for that individual child, and
the context driven by personal experience and media exposure within which each family
centers the medical team’s prognostic framework (Racine & Bell 2008).
The spectrum of causes for brain injury in children is broad. For select etiologies, such
as hypoxic-ischemic injury after cardiac arrest or traumatic brain injury, epidemiological
and observational data exist which can guide initial prognostic discussions. For less com-
mon disorders such as infectious or autoimmune encephalitis, sepsis-associated encepha-
lopathy, or status epilepticus, estimating a child’s potential for neurologic recovery can be
far more challenging as the outcomes are less predictable, and dependent on the response
to targeted therapy. A major challenge to accurate and timely prediction of both global
and specific neurologic potential after brain injury in children is the ability of the young,
developing brain to form new neuronal connections and updated structure–function
associations. This process is highly individualized and variable, with the same apparent
injury producing widely different clinical outcomes. Physicians typically have confidence
in their prognostic abilities at the deep ends of the spectrum of injury—they are able to
diagnose brain death and what lies very close to it, and they are comfortable with diagnos-
ing mild injury with normal or near-normal neurologic outcomes—but they struggle to
elucidate the many variations of gray that lie between those two divergent ends.
In this chapter, we utilize a clinical case to outline the phases of injury and recovery
through which a child progresses after sustaining a severe brain injury. Understanding
18
these phases is crucial to elucidating how and where newer technologies may have the
greatest influence on our prognostic capabilities. We describe the potential role of current
technologies, including functional neuroimaging, in neuroprognostication after brain
injury, and examine ethical issues that may arise as these instruments are transitioned
from the research lab into clinical practice. Finally, we envision how current and future
technologies could be applied to improve neuroprognostication accuracy and physician
and family confidence in those assessments.
During the resuscitation phase, which often traverses several hours, pediatric critical care
physicians are methodically and systematically stabilizing critical organ systems includ-
ing the brain. This may require invasive procedures to insert devices for close physiologic
monitoring, CPR, or institution of therapies such as extracorporeal membrane oxygen-
ation (ECMO) for maximal cardiopulmonary support. This is a stressful and anxious time
for both physicians and families. Discussions between medical staff and families during
this tenuous time are typically focused on orientation to the ICU environment, planned
procedures and interventions, and presumed injury severity, although data regarding the
extent of the brain injury is limited often to a clinical exam and an early head comput-
erized tomography (CT) scan. While head CT performed early after injury may fail to
show the full extent of brain injury, loss of gray–white matter differentiation, basilar cis-
tern effacement, and sulcal effacement are in general associated with poor outcome after
pediatric out-of-hospital cardiac arrest (Starling et al. 2015). Similarly, a physical exam
performed during or immediately after resuscitation can be misleading with respect to
the degree and permanence of brain injury. There is often limited time for in-depth dis-
cussions regarding neurologic outcome during an intense resuscitation, especially when
survival is paramount.
Data exist to assist with survival prediction during the resuscitation phase depending
on the etiology of brain injury, and can be further refined based on individual clinical
characteristics (Kessler et al. 2011; Girotra et al. 2013). Additionally, the mortality trend
for pediatric cardiac arrest has been improved over recent years with early recognition
and CPR, emphasis on high-quality resuscitation, and post-resuscitation care (Topjian
et al. 2013). Thus, especially in pediatrics, it is often unclear how long to continue CPR
182
Acute phase
Case scenario, continued: In the PICU, he required mechanical ventilation with high pressures due to
severe lung injury and high-dose vasopressor infusions for hemodynamic support secondary to cardiac
dysfunction. He remained comatose with no response to stimuli and intermittently absent brainstem
reflexes. A head CT scan obtained the following day showed subtle loss of gray–white differentiation
with crowding of the basal cisterns, but no herniation or midline shift. A continuous electroencepha-
logram (EEG) was abnormal, with disorganization, but no epileptiform discharges, and some periods
of preserved sleep architecture.
After surviving the initial resuscitation, patients progress to the acute phase, which typi-
cally lasts for several days. This period of multisystem instability requires close physi-
ologic monitoring and observation, and the institution of therapies aimed at mitigating
and preventing secondary or ongoing brain injury. A complete discussion of these neu-
roprotective and neurorestorative therapies (e.g., therapeutic hypothermia) is beyond the
scope of this chapter, although the neuroprognostication process must account for the
presence and timing of these treatments (Perman et al. 2012). The efficacy of these thera-
pies depends on the etiology of brain injury, and is the subject of many completed and
ongoing clinical trials in adults and pediatrics (Holzer 2002; Nielsen et al. 2013; Moler
et al. 2015).
During this acute phase in the ICU, parents frequently ask probing questions regard-
ing their child’s potential functional and cognitive outcomes (Box 10.1). Will the child
wake up? Will s/he speak, interact, smile, walk? The answers to these questions often
directly guide decisions about care. Intensivists and neurologists partner together dur-
ing this phase to provide information to families regarding the suspected degree of brain
injury, discuss potential treatment options, and ascertain the family values for the child
(Kirschen et al. 2014; Kirschen & Walter 2015). Communicating and managing prog-
nostic uncertainty can be especially challenging during this acute phase (Marcin et al.
1999, 2004).
Information about a patient’s neurologic status during this phase is typically based on
a child’s physical exam, possible head CT, and continuous EEG recordings. The neuro-
logic exam and EEG recordings are often confounded by analgesic and sedative infu-
sions, which are used routinely in the pediatric ICU environment. EEG background and
presence of subclinical seizures have been associated with poor neurologic outcome and
increased mortality after cardiac arrest (Abend et al. 2009; Topjian et al. 2016). More
definitive neuroimaging such as magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) to characterize the
extent of the brain injury is not often feasible during this phase due to the critical nature
of the patient and the inability for safe transport to the scanner suite. Serum biomark-
ers which measure neuronal and astrocyte destruction (e.g., neuron-specific enolase and
183
S100B) have been studied in select pediatric populations, but are not validated or incor-
porated into prognostic algorithms as they are in adults (Topjian et al. 2009; Berger et al.
2010). Clinical characteristics about a child’s cardiac arrest and physiologic data obtained
during the resuscitation and acute phases have also been correlated with survival and
neurologic outcome (Girotra et al. 2013; Topjian et al. 2013, 2014; van Zellem et al. 2015).
Various guidelines exist to assist with neurologic prognosis in patients who remain
comatose after survival from cardiac arrest during this acute phase, although these
have only been developed and validated in adults. For example, in 2006, the American
Academy of Neurology released a sequential algorithm to predict poor neurologic out-
come and thus guide decision-making that focused on the clinical exam, somatosen-
sory evoked potentials, and biomarkers obtained within 72 hours of the arrest, but did
not take into account the advent of targeted temperature management (i.e., therapeutic
hypothermia), EEG assessment, or advanced imaging techniques (Wijdicks et al. 2006).
Thus, the European Resuscitation Council and the European Society of Intensive Care
Medicine issued a revised algorithm in 2014, incorporating the patient’s clinical exam,
EEG, biomarkers, somatosensory evoked potentials, and neuroimaging including CT and
MRI. A poor outcome according to those guidelines is “very likely” if the patient has no
pupillary or corneal reflexes, and bilaterally absent N20 somatosenory-evoked potentials
(SSEPs). A poor outcome is “likely” with the presence of myoclonic status, high neuron-
specific enolase levels, burst suppression or status epilepticus on EEG and/or diffuse
anoxic injury on CT/MRI (even in the absence of abnormalities in pupillary exam or
SSEPs). The algorithm also recommends only initiating prognostic testing after an appro-
priate period post confounders such as hypothermia and residual sedation has elapsed
(Greer et al. 2014; Sandroni et al. 2014; Sandroni & Nolan 2015; Hindle et al. 2015).
184
Subacute phase
Case scenario, continued: Magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) of the brain 72 hours post injury
showed mild signal abnormality in the bilateral thalami with subtle restricted diffusion, indicating
some ischemia in these brain regions. He was extubated 4 days after injury. On exam over the follow-
ing weeks he was non-verbal, lacked purposeful movements, was unable to follow commands, and
had frequent episodes of posturing. Electrocardiogram (ECG) showed a prolonged corrected QT (QTc)
interval, and family history revealed long QT syndrome in a maternal aunt and death by drowning in
a maternal cousin (a prolonged QT interval is a cardiac rhythm abnormality that may be associated
with sudden death).
In the subacute phase of brain injury and recovery, patients typically demonstrate signs
that they will breathe and maintain sufficient hemodynamic stability to survive inde-
pendently of technological support, although some patients require more prolonged
185
pattern of brain injury, with areas of unaffected neural tissue interspersed with the injured
tissue (Fins 2011).
Making the correct clinical assessment of consciousness is essential, as it directly impacts
decisions of care, rehabilitation, and prognostication (He et al. 2014; Bender et al. 2015).
Knowing whether a patient is conscious or aware of their environment certainly plays a
crucial role in families’ decision-making process. Adult physicians commonly utilize the
standardized Coma Recovery Scale-Revised clinical tool to categorize degrees of impaired
consciousness, and in particular, to distinguish the vegetative from the minimally con-
scious patients (Giacino et al. 2004). Making these diagnoses is a very challenging task
for the clinician, as discerning reflexive movements from intermittent and episodic vol-
untary movements can be subjective and dependent on the timing of exam. Furthermore,
patients may suffer from cognitive (aphasia, apraxia) or sensory impairments (auditory
or visual) limiting their ability to interact. The inability to elicit responsiveness does not
necessarily mean that the patient is not conscious. Misdiagnosing patients in vegetative
state when they are in fact minimally conscious has been reported to occur in up to 40%
of cases (Childs et al. 1993; Andrews et al. 1996; Wilson et al. 2002; Schnakers et al. 2009;
Calabro et al. 2016).
Appreciating the wide disparity in adult practitioners’ reliability and accuracy in
diagnosing these disorders makes conferring these diagnoses in pediatric patients that
much more challenging. First, this difficulty in outcome prediction is magnified by any
preexisting chronic neurologic or developmental condition (Kirschen & Feudtner 2012;
Kirschen & Walter 2015). Second, the broad range of normal developmental stages in
childhood further complicates neurologic status assignment, especially for young chil-
dren. And third, clinical exams based on the age and developmental stage of the child
can be incredibly challenging and produce highly variable results, particularly in a child’s
response to painful or uncomfortable stimuli.
In the prior section focusing on prognosticating during the acute phase of injury,
we discussed how physicians often focus on the period of cardiopulmonary instability
as an optimal time to discuss outcome prediction since withholding or withdrawal of
life-sustaining therapies during this window will likely result in death. A large num-
ber of families are unable to make such an irreversible decision during the highly
emotional and stressful initial days after a child’s injury, especially since they are hop-
ing for a better-than-expected outcome. However, this initial period of physiologic
instability is not the only opportunity families have to limit or withhold aggressive
care. Thus, technologies that could enhance prognostic accuracy and certainty during
this subacute phase would continue to be of significant value. They could provide vital
information for a family seeking treatment options aligned with their values for the
child, which may include limiting or withholding care, or proceeding with aggressive
brain-centered rehabilitation. Options for limiting or withholding care may include
removal of an endotracheal or tracheostomy tube that some children still require in
the subacute phase, and discussions regarding goals of care for future illnesses and
hospitalizations. Additionally, for some children who permanently lack conscious
187
also observed in healthy volunteers performing the same task. This patient demon-
strated via fMRI brain activation maps that she was able to understand and respond to
commands (Owen et al. 2006). Monti and colleagues were able to elicit similar responses
in 4 of 23 patients previously diagnosed as being vegetative (Monti et al. 2010). In a
separate study, this team asked a patient that had been in a vegetative state for 5 years
to imagine playing tennis to communicate one answer (e.g., yes) and to imagine mov-
ing around the rooms of his home to communicate the alternative answer (e.g., no).
The patient then correctly answered five personalized questions (e.g., his father’s name)
confirming that he was conscious, and able to successfully recall historical details of his
life (Monti et al. 2010; Owen 2013).
Functional MRI has also shown promising results in predicting functional recovery in
patients clinically diagnosed as being in a vegetative state. The detection of activity in
higher-level associative cortices predicts recovery with 93% specificity and 69% sensi-
tivity (Di et al. 2008). The strength of functional connectivity of whole-brain networks
also correlates with neurologic recovery. A recent study of nearly 100 patients with vary-
ing degrees of impaired consciousness and 34 healthy controls demonstrated a correla-
tion between functional connectivity strength, consciousness, and recovery. Functional
connectivity strength could predict recovery of consciousness with 81% accuracy (Wu
et al. 2015). These studies have identified a population of patients that demonstrate some
evidence of preserved cognitive function, consciousness, and awareness of self and the
environment, but without the ability to communicate with the outside world (Wu et al.
2015). This syndrome, newly termed functional locked-in syndrome, raises the possibility
that some vegetative patients are in fact conscious, aware of their environment, and able
to understand speech.
Ethical considerations
The ramifications of these recent findings are fraught with ethical issues. Such neuroimag-
ing studies suggest that a patient who has clinically been deemed to be in an unresponsive
vegetative state may in fact demonstrate consciousness and be capable of interacting with
their environment. This possibility forces us to question the autonomy and decision-mak-
ing ability of patients with disorders of consciousness. It also raises questions about per-
ceived quality of life, and whether evidence for covert consciousness argues for ongoing
aggressive medical care or compassionate withdrawal of life-sustaining treatments. While
only a small subset of these patients may retain sufficient cognitive neural networks to
perform the types of tasks required in these studies, there is still a significant leap between
imagining motor tasks and answering questions about a person’s past, and demonstrat-
ing adequate understanding to provide informed consent or express a person’s wishes for
complex clinical decision making. If technology were to advance through this gap, could
it be used to assess pain, emotions such as anxiety, fear, or depression, and whether a
patient feels hunger or thirst? If so, perhaps medical teams would more effectively be able
to titrate care to actual patient wishes rather than by proxy.
Prior to transitioning this research-based technology into routine clinical practice, we
as researchers and clinicians must first feel confident that the behavioral stimuli presented
map to known anatomical locations. We must be mindful during this process that normal
structure–function relationships have been developed in the adult population and may
not be directly transferable to the developing brain, or a brain that has begun to func-
tionally reorganize as it recovers from a brain injury. Second, we must be sure that any
particular patient or group of patients will respond to a similar stimulus in a consistent,
replicable manner. Lastly, we currently have no way of understanding whether or not
a meaningful, replicable, and consistent response indicating awareness is predictive of
future functional recovery for any given patient (Wilkinson et al. 2009; Weijer et al. 2014).
Jox and colleagues formatted a deft explanation of this ethical and clinical conundrum
based on three possible outcomes of functional neuroimaging: (1) neuroimaging shows
less evidence of consciousness or awareness than found on clinical exam, which may allow
families to feel more comfortable with limitations or withholding of life-sustaining tech-
nology, but may strain the therapeutic relationship with the clinician if she is more opti-
mistic about the patient’s potential outcome; (2) neuroimaging shows more evidence of
awareness than found on clinical exam, which may on one hand encourage more aggres-
sive treatment, but on the other hand may create false hope for a more complete recovery
or prompt a family to withhold technologic support if there is perceived awareness of pain
or suffering; or (3) neuroimaging shows the same evidence of awareness as clinical exam,
which may also strain the physician-family therapeutic relationship with a perception of
“useless” and expensive testing (Jox et al. 2012). Regardless, as we currently hold neither a
complete understanding of functional neuroanatomy, nor a meaningful ethical construct
of interpreting covert consciousness, we are faced with data that we are unable to reliably
act upon (Lutkenhoff et al. 2015; Kowalski et al. 2015; Wintermark et al. 2015a, 2015b).
190
The field of functional neuroimaging holds great promise to assist with the assess-
ment and potential clinical management of patients with disordered consciousness after
severe brain injury. It may contribute objective data to aid with diagnostic classification
of patients and provide families with a more concrete understanding of a patient’s capa-
bilities. It may have implications for assisting patients with pain management, commu-
nicating wants and needs, and end-of-life decisions of care. Additionally, when repeated
serially after injury, functional imaging may provide crucial information about neuronal
recovery and reorganization over time from brain injury, and could potentially be used to
monitor the response of the brain to medications such as amantadine and zolpidem that
have been shown to produce and accelerating neurologic recovery (Giacino et al. 2014).
care and shared decision-making. A variety of platforms could be used to convey this
information. Dramatic improvements in virtual reality technology have led to the ability
to simulate a 360-degree representation of a space using a head-mounted display and a
mobile phone. These systems have already been applied in medicine and the neurosci-
ences to help physicians and patients enhance their understanding of disease processes
and therapeutic options. For diseases such as multiple sclerosis and migraine headache,
three-dimensional virtual reality systems allow entry into the central nervous system to
visualize how the immune system has become dysregulated and neuronal transmission
impaired. Procedural fields have used these platforms to demonstrate how catheter-based
systems bore through blood clots or deploy stents. One could envision a scenario in
which information gleaned from neuromonitoring and functional neuroimaging tech-
niques could be uploaded onto a virtual reality platform to model a child’s perceptions
and awareness, and allow parents the opportunity to experience this for themselves. How
does the child perceive him-or herself in the ICU? Is there pain? What brings pleasure
or comfort? While this simulated environment may generate intense emotional responses
from parents and family members, it may help clarify how they choose to apply the values
they have for their child when making medical decisions.
Further information about brain function may be available through depth electrodes
that can be surgically implanted in patients after severe acquired brain injury. These elec-
trodes have primarily been used for seizure focus localization in patients being evaluated
for epilepsy surgery, but more recently have been placed in patients after traumatic brain
injury or subarachnoid hemorrhage to screen for subclinical seizures (Claassen et al.
2013; Vespa et al. 2016). Just as signals from these electrodes are more sensitive than rou-
tine scalp EEG to detect some types of seizures, these signals may carry additional infor-
mation about awareness or cognition that could be incorporated into functional models
and prediction algorithms.
By amalgamating these brain-derived signals, one could also create a meaningful
interface that calculates not only the likelihood of overall survival, but answers crucial
questions that could influence clinical decisions during the acute and subacute phases of
injury. Will my child walk again after this injury? Will he or she regain consciousness?
Recognize me? Smile and interact with me? Speak and understand language? For some
parents, answers to these questions, even if delivered with some degree of uncertainty,
would help them make these unfathomable decisions. Finally, the groundbreaking work
with neural control of movement in animals and humans with powered prosthetics may
provide an opportunity to create translational communication devices for children with
disorders of consciousness. Such devices could truly facilitate communication of wants
and desires in patients with covert awareness from brain injury.
These platforms to convert neurally derived signals into tangible reality for physicians
and families are accompanied by considerable ethical considerations. While many of
these technologies are currently in the domain of science fiction, the rapid growth of the
neuroimaging and neuromonitoring fields may make these concepts plausible reality in
the near future. They would require extensive investigation and vetting in the research
192
domain prior to translation into the clinical arena. Additionally, these techniques will not
be without inherent limitations and caveats, and the generated data and user interface
will be susceptible to a wide spectrum of interpretation. Given the power of images and
their influence in medical decision-making, it will be essential that families have a clear
understanding of exactly what they are and are not viewing (Racine et al. 2005, 2006).
Experiencing a virtual tour of their child’s severely injured brain with lack of neural con-
nections, abnormal neurotransmitter levels, and impaired blood flow, may be considered
emotionally manipulative and unethical if used with the intent to encourage withdrawal
of life-sustaining therapies, in the case of, for example, a family with deeply religious
views valuing the preservation of life under any circumstances.
Conclusion
The neuroprognostication process is uncomfortable and anxiety provoking for many phy-
sicians. Conferring an overly optimistic prognosis may result in the prolonged survival of
a neurologically devastated child, while an overly pessimistic prediction may result in a
family withdrawing life-sustaining therapies in a child with a potentially more favorable
neurologic outcome. The challenges associated with outcome prediction are increased
with young children, especially when a child has an underlying neurologic or neurode-
velopmental condition prior to brain injury. Predictions of neurologic outcome should
be evidence-based whenever possible; however, to date, no single clinical exam feature,
laboratory value, biomarker, or neuroimaging finding is highly reliable. Many intensivists
and neurologists have memorable patients for whom initial outcome prediction was inac-
curate, reaffirming both the challenging nature of the process and the incredible adapt-
ability of the pediatric brain after injury.
The patient described in the case scenario survived his drowning and cardiac arrest.
Several experienced physicians counseled the family about his poor prognosis for neuro-
logic recovery given the ischemic injury to his thalami bilaterally, and his failure to make
clinical improvements in the weeks after his injury. After months of intense inpatient
rehabilitation, he has returned to school and is performing near grade level with some
scholastic accommodations. He requires ongoing speech, physical, and occupational
therapies, and has a full-time aid to help with his activities of daily living. His follow-up
MRI showed sequelae of hypoxic-ischemic injury, with abnormal signal in the periven-
tricular white matter and thalami bilaterally and generalized volume loss.
His example is not uncommon. While these types of patients illustrate the diffi-
culty physicians have in accurately predicting functional outcome within the gray
areas between a truly devastating brain injury and mild injury with minimal sequelae,
they are a constant reminder that improved technology is essential to aid the neu-
roprognostic process. Our ability to provide an accurate and timely estimation of
potential neurologic recovery directly impacts decision-making during all phases of
injury. Functional neuroimaging provides a platform that may be able to detect covert
awareness, predict neurologic recovery, and allow seemingly unresponsive patients to
193
References 193
communicate. This technique, however, is often not feasible during the acute phase of
injury due to the patient’s clinical instability. Future directions and technologies for
neuroprognostication may require synthesizing brain-derived signals from multiple
sources and relaying that data to digital platforms easily accessible to physicians and
families. These emerging techniques are on the verge of transforming our perception
and understanding of human consciousness and cognition after severe brain injury.
The associated ethical considerations are immense and should be discussed prospec-
tively with stakeholders from both the medical community and the public. Clinical,
scientific, and ethical caution is needed as these evolving technologies transition from
science fiction to plausible reality.
References
Abend, N.S. and Licht, D.J. (2008). Predicting outcome in children with hypoxic ischemic
encephalopathy. Pediatric Critical Care Medicine, 9(1), 32–39.
Abend, N.S., Topjian, A., Ichord, R., et al. (2009). Electroencephalographic monitoring during
hypothermia after pediatric cardiac arrest. Neurology, 72(22), 1931–1940.
Achard, S., Salvador, R., Whitcher, B., Suckling, J., and Bullmore, E. (2006). A resilient, low-frequency,
small-world human brain functional network with highly connected association cortical hubs.
Journal of Neuroscience, 26(1), 63–72.
Andrews, K., Murphy, L., Munday, R., and Littlewood, C. (1996). Misdiagnosis of the vegetative
state: retrospective study in a rehabilitation unit. BMJ, 313(7048), 13–16.
Ashwal, S., Tong, K.A., Ghosh, N., Bartnik-Olson, B., and Holshouser, B.A. (2014). Application of
advanced neuroimaging modalities in pediatric traumatic brain injury. Journal of Child Neurology,
29(12), 1704–1717.
Bender, A., Jox, R.J., Grill, E., Straube, A., and Lule, D. (2015). Persistent vegetative state and
minimally conscious state: a systematic review and meta-analysis of diagnostic procedures.
Deutsches Ärzteblatt International, 112(14), 235–242.
Berger, R.P., Bazaco, M.C., Wagner, A.K., Kochanek, P.M., and Fabio, A. (2010). Trajectory analysis
of serum biomarker concentrations facilitates outcome prediction after pediatric traumatic and
hypoxemic brain injury. Developmental Neuroscience, 32(5-6), 396–405.
Calabro, R.S., Milardi, D., Cacciola, A., et al. (2016). Moving into the wide clinical spectrum of
consciousness disorders: pearls, perils and pitfalls. Medicina (Kaunas), 52(1), 11–18.
Childs, N.L., Mercer, W.N., and Childs, H.W. (1993). Accuracy of diagnosis of persistent vegetative
state. Neurology, 43(8), 1465–1467.
Claassen, J., Perotte, A., Albers, D., et al. (2013). Nonconvulsive seizures after subarachnoid
hemorrhage: multimodal detection and outcomes. Annals of Neurology, 74(1), 53–64.
Di, H., Boly, M., Weng, X., Ledoux, D., and Laureys, S. (2008). Neuroimaging activation studies in the
vegetative state: predictors of recovery? Clinical Medicine (London), 8(5), 502–507.
Diekema, D.S., Botkin, J.R., and Committee on Bioethics (2009). Clinical report: forgoing medically
provided nutrition and hydration in children. Pediatrics, 124(2), 813–822.
Finley Caulfield, A., Gabler, L., Lansberg, M.G., et al. (2010). Outcome prediction in mechanically
ventilated neurologic patients by junior neurointensivists. Neurology, 74(14), 1096–1101.
Fins, J.J. (2011). Neuroethics, neuroimaging, and disorders of consciousness: promise or peril?
Transactions of the American Clinical and Climatological Association, 122), 336–346.
194
Fins, J.J., Illes, J., Bernat, J.L., Hirsch, J., Laureys, S., and Murphy, E. (2008). Neuroimaging and
disorders of consciousness: envisioning an ethical research agenda. American Journal of Bioethics,
8(9), 3–12.
Giacino, J.T., Kalmar, K., and Whyte, J. (2004). The JFK Coma Recovery Scale-Revised: measurement
characteristics and diagnostic utility. Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, 85(12),
2020–2029.
Giacino, J.T., Fins, J.J., Laureys, S., and Schiff, N.D. (2014). Disorders of consciousness after acquired
brain injury: the state of the science. Nature Reviews Neurology, 10(2), 99–114.
Girotra, S., Spertus, J.A., Li, Y., et al. (2013). Survival trends in pediatric in-hospital cardiac arrests: an
analysis from Get With the Guidelines-Resuscitation. Circulation Cardiovascular Quality and
Outcomes, 6(1), 42–49.
Greer, D.M., Rosenthal, E.S., and Wu, O. (2014). Neuroprognostication of hypoxic-ischaemic coma in
the therapeutic hypothermia era. Nature Reviews Neurology, 10(4), 190–203.
He, J.H., Yang, Y., Zhang, Y., et al. (2014). Hyperactive external awareness against hypoactive internal
awareness in disorders of consciousness using resting-state functional MRI: highlighting the
involvement of visuo-motor modulation. NMR in Biomedicine, 27(8), 880–886.
Hindle, E.M., Dunn, M., Gillies, M., and Clegg, G. (2015). Neuroprognostication following out of
hospital cardiac arrest –a retrospective study of departmental practice. Resuscitation, 94, e5–6.
Holzer, M. (2002). Mild therapeutic hypothermia to improve the neurologic outcome after cardiac
arrest (Hypothermia after Cardiac Arrest Study Group). New England Journal of Medicine, 346(8),
549–556.
Jox, R.J., Bernat, J.L., Laureys, S., and Racine, E. (2012). Disorders of consciousness: responding to
requests for novel diagnostic and therapeutic interventions. Lancet Neurology, 11(8), 732–738.
Katz, D.I., Polyak, M., Coughlan, D., Nichols, M., and Roche, A. (2009). Natural history of recovery
from brain injury after prolonged disorders of consciousness: outcome of patients admitted to
inpatient rehabilitation with 1-4 year follow-up. Progress in Brain Research, 177, 73–88.
Kessler, S.K., Topjian, A.A., Gutierrez-Colina, A.M., et al. (2011). Short-term outcome prediction by
electroencephalographic features in children treated with therapeutic hypothermia after cardiac
arrest. Neurocritical Care, 14(1), 37–43.
Kirschen, M.P. and Feudtner, C. (2012). Ethical issues. In: Abend, N. and Helfaer, M. (Eds.) Pediatric
Neurocritical Care, pp.485–493. New York: Demos Medical Publishing.
Kirschen, M.P. and Walter, J.K. (2015). Ethical issues in neuroprognostication after severe pediatric
brain injury. Seminars in Pediatric Neurology, 22(3), 187–195.
Kirschen, M.P., Topjian, A.A., Hammond, R., Illes, J., and Abend, N.S. (2014). Neuroprognostication
after pediatric cardiac arrest. Pediatric Neurology, 51, 663–668.
Kowalski, R.G., Buitrago, M.M., Duckworth, J., et al. (2015). Neuroanatomical predictors of awakening
in acutely comatose patients. Annals of Neurology, 77(5), 804–816.
Laureys, S., Faymonville, M.E., Degueldre, C., et al. (2000). Auditory processing in the vegetative state.
Brain, 123 (Pt 8), 1589–1601.
Laureys, S., Faymonville, M.E., Peigneux, P., et al. (2002). Cortical processing of noxious
somatosensory stimuli in the persistent vegetative state. NeuroImage, 17(2), 732–741.
Liang, X., Zou, Q., He, Y., and Yang, Y. (2013). Coupling of functional connectivity and regional
cerebral blood flow reveals a physiological basis for network hubs of the human brain. Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 110(5), 1929–1934.
Lutkenhoff, E.S., Chiang, J., Tshibanda, L., et al. (2015). Thalamic and extrathalamic mechanisms of
consciousness after severe brain injury. Annals of Neurology, 78(1), 68–76.
Marcin, J.P., Pollack, M.M., Patel, K.M., Sprague, B.M., and Ruttimann, U.E. (1999). Prognostication
and certainty in the pediatric intensive care unit. Pediatrics, 104(4 Pt 1), 868–873.
195
References 195
Marcin, J.P., Pretzlaff, R.K., Pollack, M.M., Patel, K.M., and Ruttimann, U.E. (2004). Certainty and
mortality prediction in critically ill children. Journal of Medical Ethics, 30(3), 304–307.
Michiels, E., Quan, L., Dumas, F., and Rea, T. (2016). Long-term neurologic outcomes following
paediatric out-of-hospital cardiac arrest. Resuscitation, 102, 122–126.
Moler, F.W., Silverstein, F.S., Holubkov, R., et al. (2015). Therapeutic hypothermia after out-of-hospital
cardiac arrest in children. New England Journal of Medicine, 372(20), 1898–1908.
Monti, M.M., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Coleman, M.R., et al. (2010). Willful modulation of brain activity
in disorders of consciousness. New England Journal of Medicine, 362(7), 579–589.
Nicholas, C.R., Mclaren, D.G., Gawrysiak, M.J., Rogers, B.P., Dougherty, J.H., and Nash, M.R. (2014).
Functional neuroimaging of personally-relevant stimuli in a paediatric case of impaired awareness.
Brain Injury, 28(8), 1135–1138.
Nielsen, N., Wetterslev, J., Cronberg, T., et al. (2013). Targeted temperature management at 33
degrees C versus 36 degrees C after cardiac arrest. New England Journal of Medicine, 369(23),
2197–2206.
Northoff, G. and Heiss, W.D. (2015). Why is the distinction between neural predispositions,
prerequisites, and correlates of the level of consciousness clinically relevant?: Functional brain
imaging in coma and vegetative state. Stroke, 46(4), 1147–1151.
Owen, A.M. (2013). Detecting consciousness: a unique role for neuroimaging. Annual Review of
Psychology, 64, 109–133.
Owen, A.M., Coleman, M.R., Boly, M., Davis, M.H., Laureys, S., and Pickard, J.D. (2006). Detecting
awareness in the vegetative state. Science, 313(5792), 1402.
Perman, S.M., Kirkpatrick, J.N., Reitsma, A.M., et al. (2012). Timing of neuroprognostication in
postcardiac arrest therapeutic hypothermia. Critical Care Medicine, 40(3), 719–724.
Racine, E. and Bell, E. (2008). Clinical and public translation of neuroimaging research in disorders of
consciousness challenges current diagnostic and public understanding paradigms. American Journal
of Bioethics, 8(9), 13–15.
Racine, E., Bar-Ilan, O., and Illes, J. (2005). fMRI in the public eye. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6(2),
159–164.
Racine, E., Bar-Ilan, O., and Illes, J. (2006). Brain imaging: a decade of coverage in the print media.
Science Communication, 28(1), 122–142.
Racine, E., Dion, M.J., Wijman, C.A., Illes, J., and Lansberg, M.G. (2009). Profiles of neurological
outcome prediction among intensivists. Neurocritical Care, 11(3), 345–352.
Roberts, R.M., Mathias, J.L., and Rose, S.E. (2014). Diffusion tensor imaging (DTI) findings
following pediatric non-penetrating TBI: a meta-analysis. Developmental Neuropsychology ,
39(8), 600–637.
Sandroni, C. and Nolan, J.P. (2015). Neuroprognostication after cardiac arrest in Europe: new timings
and standards. Resuscitation, 90, A4–5.
Sandroni, C., Cariou, A., Cavallaro, F., et al. (2014). Prognostication in comatose survivors of cardiac
arrest: an advisory statement from the European Resuscitation Council and the European Society of
Intensive Care Medicine. Resuscitation, 85(12), 1779–1789.
Schiff, N.D., Rodriguez-Moreno, D., Kamal, A., et al. (2005). fMRI reveals large-scale network
activation in minimally conscious patients. Neurology, 64(3), 514–523.
Schnakers, C., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Giacino, J., et al. (2009). Diagnostic accuracy of the vegetative and
minimally conscious state: clinical consensus versus standardized neurobehavioral assessment. BMC
Neurology, 9, 35.
Starling, R.M., Shekdar, K., Licht, D., Nadkarni, V.M., Berg, R.A., and Topjian, A.A. (2015). Early
head CT findings are associated with outcomes after pediatric out-of-hospital cardiac arrest.
Pediatric Critical Care Medicine, 16(6), 542–548.
196
Tomasi, D., Wang, G.J., and Volkow, N.D. (2013). Energetic cost of brain functional connectivity.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 110(33),
13642–13647.
Tononi, G. (2004). An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neuroscience, 5, 42.
Tononi, G. and Koch, C. (2008). The neural correlates of consciousness: an update. Annals of the
New York Academy of Sciences, 1124, 239–261.
Topjian, A.A., Lin, R., Morris, M.C., et al. (2009). Neuron-specific enolase and S-100B are associated
with neurologic outcome after pediatric cardiac arrest. Pediatric Critical Care Medicine, 10(4),
479–490.
Topjian, A.A., Berg, R.A., and Nadkarni, V.M. (2013). Advances in recognition, resuscitation, and
stabilization of the critically ill child. Pediatric Clinics of North America, 60(3), 605–620.
Topjian, A.A., French, B., Sutton, R.M., et al. (2014). Early postresuscitation hypotension is associated
with increased mortality following pediatric cardiac arrest. Critical Care Medicine, 42(6), 1518–1523.
Topjian, A.A., Sanchez, S.M., Shults, J., Berg, R.A., Dlugos, D.J., and Abend, N.S. (2016). Early
electroencephalographic background features predict outcomes in children resuscitated from
cardiac arrest. Pediatric Critical Care Medicine, 17(6), 547–557.
Van Zellem, L., Utens, E.M., Legerstee, J.S., et al. (2015). Cardiac arrest in children: long-term health
status and health-related quality of life. Pediatric Critical Care Medicine, 16(8), 693–702.
Vespa, P., Tubi, M., Claassen, J., et al. (2016). Metabolic crisis occurs with seizures and periodic
discharges after brain trauma. Annals of Neurology, 79(4), 579–590.
Wang, F., Di, H., Hu, X., et al. (2015). Cerebral response to subject’s own name showed high prognostic
value in traumatic vegetative state. BMC Medicine, 13, 83.
Weijer, C., Peterson, A., Webster, F., et al. (2014). Ethics of neuroimaging after serious brain injury.
BMC Medical Ethics, 15, 41.
Wijdicks, E.F., Hijdra, A., Young, G.B., Bassetti, C.L., and Wiebe, S. (2006). Practice
parameter: prediction of outcome in comatose survivors after cardiopulmonary resuscitation (an
evidence-based review): report of the Quality Standards Subcommittee of the American Academy of
Neurology. Neurology, 67(2), 203–210.
Wilkinson, D. (2009). The window of opportunity: decision theory and the timing of prognostic tests
for newborn infants. Bioethics, 23(9), 503–514.
Wilkinson, D. (2011). The window of opportunity for treatment withdrawal. Archives of Pediatrics and
Adolescent Medicine, 165(3), 211–215.
Wilkinson, D.J., Kahane, G., Horne, M., and Savulescu, J. (2009). Functional neuroimaging and
withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment from vegetative patients. Journal of Medical Ethics, 35(8),
508–511.
Wilson, F.C., Harpur, J., Watson, T., and Morrow, J.I. (2002). Vegetative state and minimally
responsive patients –regional survey, long-term case outcomes and service recommendations.
NeuroRehabilitation, 17(3), 231–236.
Wintermark, M., Coombs, L., Druzgal, T.J., et al. (2015a). Traumatic brain injury imaging research
roadmap. AJNR American Journal of Neuroradiology, 36(3), E12–23.
Wintermark, M., Sanelli, P.C., Anzai, Y., et al. (2015b). Imaging evidence and recommendations for
traumatic brain injury: conventional neuroimaging techniques. Journal of the American College of
Radiology, 12(2), e1–14.
Wu, X., Zou, Q., Hu, J., et al. (2015). Intrinsic functional connectivity patterns predict
consciousness level and recovery outcome in acquired brain injury. Journal of Neuroscience,
35(37), 12932–12946.
197
Chapter 11
A true story
A magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) technologist, let’s call her AX, who had been
trained in nonpharmacologic sedation techniques to help her claustrophobic patients
through their tests, needed treatment of her varicose veins. Her vascular specialist was
to use a minimally invasive procedure during which a laser or radiofrequency probe is
inserted in the vein to heat its inner lining and damage the vessel wall so that it closes
off. To ease the sensation, local anesthetic is applied sequentially along the entire course
of the vein from the groin level down to below the knee. AX wanted to be comfortable
and brought with her a colleague who had been trained in the same nonpharmacologic
sedation techniques with which she was familiar. The doctor clearly did not want AX’s
colleague in the procedure room. He kept warning AX that the local anesthetic would
be stinging and burning—repeating the expectations of hurt even after AX asked him to
not use such wording since it was not helpful, and that she was prepared for the proce-
dure. The doctor couldn’t help himself and kept insisting that things would hurt until AX
looked directly at him and told him, “You got this all wrong. I will just experience a deli-
cious sense of tingling.” This had the desired effect and the doctor became and remained
silent. The procedure continued uneventfully and AX was proud of having been able to
help herself.
This short interaction harbors ethics considerations which may even be at odds with
each other depending on whether one analyzes the scenario from the point of moral-
ity ethics, concerning right or wrong behaviors, general societal belief systems, bioethics
used by medical review boards in terms of beneficence/maleficence, risk/liability of vari-
ous approaches, and professional standard of care based on prevailing values and prac-
tices. Further dilemmas arise when beliefs and expectations of patient and healthcare
professional clash with each other and with scientific evidence, societal norms, or observ-
able behaviors. This chapter examines how such interrelationships can shape the experi-
ence of acute pain versus comfort during medical procedures. Can there be gain without
pain? Should there be?
198
Talking about pain
“Will it hurt?” How this question, whether asked or implied, is handled from the point of
view of the recipient and the purveyor of potentially painful stimuli is deeply rooted in
belief systems and cultures of practice. Introducing upcoming stimuli with wording such
as, “This shouldn’t hurt that much,” or “It’s just like a bee sting,” “This is going to be the
worst part,” “A stick and a burn,” or sympathizing, “That wasn’t that bad?” are rampant in
the medical environment and produce the opposite effect—more pain (Blankfield 1991;
Lang et al. 2005; Cyna & Lang 2011). Research has shown that using the word “pain” or
other verbiage with negative emotional content such as “sting” or” burn” will significantly
increase pain and anxiety, even when preceded by “not much” or “little” (Lang et al. 2005).
The mind is only able to call upon the image of something, not of nothing, just as one can
imagine bananas but not no-bananas. Even if I were to tell you not to think of bananas
(or pink elephants), their image and perhaps some appetite for bananas may have come to
mind even though I suggested not to think of such.
Implicitly, the use of such negative suggestions before and during potentially uncomfort-
able procedures is sanctioned by the lack of official guidelines by professional governance
bodies to replace it with more positive suggestions (Blease 2012). One should think that
by inflicting more pain through one action as compared to another less hurtful one vio-
lates the medical ethics principle of nonmaleficence: to do no harm. In clinical practice,
the maleficence potential is to be balanced against the beneficence principle: is the risk of
greater harm justified by a greater good? In the case of negative suggestions this is not the
case, at least not for the patient. So why is the use of negative suggestions so common?
There are various reasons that words and phrases with negative emotional content have
become embedded in the vocabulary of many frontline medical caregivers. For some, it
may be a desire to be perfectly honest with the patient along a general ethical principle
of full disclosure. One procedure nurse once told me she likes to describe the upcom-
ing procedure as more painful since she knows it is not the case and the patient will be
relieved and feel good about the experience (an aspect of beneficence) as well as thank her
for great care (a more questionable motive). Practitioners may truly believe, from training
or experience, that the patient will feel pain and it is only fair to give forewarning. Feeling
it then as a duty to warn the patient of the upcoming hurt and finding confirmation in
the resulting report (more pain than if nothing had been said) will tend to perpetuate the
belief in the need for warning in the future. It may even cause the practitioner to increase
the negatively worded warning thus perpetuating and driving up the spiral of healthcare
provider-induced pain.
Familiarity with routine ways of eliciting a response from patients about their experi-
ence of pain may be another powerful reason that practices do not change. Nurses and
other medical personnel are required to query patients about their pain levels (Joint
Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations 2016). Typically 0–10 pain
scales are used. To make sure patients know about these instruments they may contain
bright red pointers, a bold header such as “Pain Assessment Tool,” and may be prominently
19
posted in the treatment areas. The intent of better pain assessments in the hospital and
ambulatory environment was a good one—to reduce suffering; the choice of advertise-
ment of these instruments in clinical practice, however, may lead to the opposite effect.
There are simple solutions to the beneficence/nonmaleficence equation for this aspect.
One study that assessed whether asking patients instead for their comfort levels after
cesarean section found that this simple change in wording resulted in the women also
reporting their overall postoperative experience as less bothersome or unpleasant com-
pared to those being asked to rate their pain (Chooi et al. 2013). In the clinical trials I was
involved with, we would introduce the customary hospital 0–10 pain scale with the ques-
tion, “How is your comfort level on a scale of 0–10 with 0=no pain at all and 10= worst
possible.” At least this avoided setting an expectation that there should be pain. AX’s story
also highlights what may happen when expectations of pain are at a variance between
healthcare/stimulus provider and recipient thereof. Do patients have a right to their own
experience? Do they, as has happened in the case, have to be convinced that they are
“wrong” and that it will hurt even when they present with a declared set of anodyne skills
in which the provider does not believe or is unfamiliar with? Is it ok to trust the patient’s
perceptions even if they run counter to the provider’s beliefs?
aspects of the Puritan legacy may lead to the consideration of pain as deserved, and
attempts to alleviate suffering as moral weakness (Kilwein 1989). While individuals are
free to choose their actions, the situation becomes ethically more challenging when the
standards of the community or healthcare professionals are forced on individual patients,
and when hurtful approaches are rationalized on moral-ethical grounds.
When an individual who is engaged in researching and learning skills in how to adapt
expectations positively encounters a healthcare professional with a different perception
of what is appropriate (such as AX and the doctor in our story) both may be behaving
morally and true to their convictions even though in this case the patient is subjected to
maleficence based on research evidence. Conversely, when a patient’s beliefs embrace a
high-risk approach, inappropriate in the eye of conventional medicine—such as refusing
blood transfusions or antibiotics for fear of spiritual/religious doom—how much physical
sufferance is acceptable for the higher spiritual good? Lawsuits and ethics boards struggle
over these questions and often there are no good answers. On occasion, it may even be
that the aversion of a professional caregiver to inflict pain at all is in the gray area of what
is ethically justifiable and what is not.
Inflicting pain
Is it ethical to inflict pain? Having been an interventional radiologist all my life, perform-
ing image-guided surgery on mostly awake patients, it is clear that it is sometimes neces-
sary to violate tissue boundaries to be able to proceed with treatment. Even just applying
lidocaine can be interpreted as painful by the patient. Again, belief systems will dictate
whether avoiding potential pain altogether is justifiable, thereby making oneself feel good,
while letting a treatable condition go untreated and endangering a patient’s health or life.
The ethical solution could be to not choose a profession where this may be a dilemma
but there is also an ethical consideration to having only the disinhibited provide care.
Certainly history has sufficient examples of atrocious behavior of physicians for the sake
of science.
What of the dentist who is a soft-hearted individual who will only proceed if the local
anesthetic produces complete numbness? I had the unfortunate experience to observe
this when my husband, who in the beginning cloud of Alzheimer’s, wasn’t able to clearly
distinguish between pressure and hurt when tested with a clanking instrument on a tooth
fragment to be extracted. It was very clear that all would have been fine, based on a prior
visit he had to the same dentist, and with me being there with him. However, the dentist
was so scared that it would hurt that he would not do the extraction and let an underly-
ing abscess smolder for another day until a colleague at a different practice was able to
achieve the goal.
in laboratory animals and is present to varying degrees in humans (Singer et al. 2004;
Goubert et al. 2005; Mogil 2012; Chen et al. 2015). Higher levels of empathy, however, do
not necessarily produce better medical outcomes. In a study with nurses in cardiovascular
units, levels of empathy among the staff did not correlate with patients’ pain perception or
the amount of medication administered (Watt-Watson et al. 2000). Misbeliefs and associ-
ated behavior were independent of the nurses’ levels of empathy.
Seeing another person suffer may result in either withdrawal from the situation to avert
one’s own suffering, or behaviors that may be considered helpful in the given cultural
environment but in themselves can be deleterious. We once had to halt a clinical trial
because patients in the empathic attention control group had significantly more adverse
events than those patients either left alone or supported with guidance in the self-hypnotic
relaxation group (Lang et al. 2008). Review of taped interactions between providers and
patients suggested that increased efforts of being nice likely provided more distraction
from the patient’s own internal coping mechanisms or may have signaled that things were
more risky than perhaps portrayed, keeping adrenergic stimulation up. Thus just feeling
for someone, as desirable, ethical, and humanly noble as this might be, not knowing how
to express it may actually be hurtful.
In the context of this study I recall a taped interaction in which one of the nurses
approached the patient on the procedure table and kindly stroked his hair. The psycholo-
gist on the team pointed out that such an approach should be avoided since it placed the
patient at a child-like level and, in addition, risked potentially evoking past abuse. After
all, we worked in a setting ideally suited to elicit such a memory: a darkened interven-
tional radiology lab with the patient naked under surgical drapes, immobilized, and with
little control while the procedure determined health and well-being. I also recall how dif-
ficult it was to convince the nursing staff that this was not great care and that unsolicited
touching or touching without obtaining permission was inappropriate. It was a case of
reducing the risk of the patient feeling uncomfortable or reliving old trauma versus the
beneficence of good intentions in the hope of improving the experience through touch.
physician identity, or with patients’ levels of pain and anxiety. One might conclude that
local hospital culture or habit was the driving force. This approach bears the risk of over-
medicating individuals whose metabolism and constitution is sensitive to small dosages
of sedatives and analgesics, with possibly fatal or serious adverse effects on breathing and
blood pressure, and undertreating individuals who either experience greater pain and
who need more medication for the same amount of pain relief.
The wide variety in the approach to drug usage for pain management during medi-
cal procedures is not limited to healthcare providers (McDermott et al. 1993) but is also
reflected in patient expectations. Patients risk not to be given enough credence when,
based on their own biases, healthcare professionals expect a different response in terms of
pain severity as the one the patient indicated. Higher than expected pain ratings from the
patient may be interpreted as drug-seeking behavior and withholding of needed medica-
tion, or possibly even as personal offense when the patient indicates pain but refuses drugs.
The medically ethical approach for a caregiver to minimize sufferance would be to be
responsive to the patients’ needs rather than one’s own assumptions. Ethical behavior,
though, relies on rational decisions. Encounters with nursing staff having to perform
repeated painful dressing changes on author Dan Ariely in his youth led him to research
human decision-making in this setting and become a major contributor to the field of
behavioral economics (Ariely 2010). He concluded that humans behave predictably
irrationally—a feature well exploited by the advertising industry. He describes his experi-
ence that the nurses tended to rather quickly rip the bandages off his heavily burnt skin
rather than removing them slowly from the edges. They believed that a short spike in
excruciating pain was better for the patient than a lengthier but less severe approach.
There was no scientific evidence behind the nurses’ behavior who were in general kind
and generous individuals. Even when years later he presented scientific evidence based
on his own experiments that people feel less pain when treatments are carried out with
lower intensity and longer duration, no change in practice ensued. When he asked one of
his more trusted nurses for a reason, she explained that pulling the bandages fast might
be more understandable if it were indeed the nurses’ way of shortening their own tor-
ment. Even after the discussion produced agreement that practice should be changed on
the burn unit, the change never happened. The nurses, with all their experience and true
compassion for their patients, kept misunderstanding the consequences of their behav-
iors and repeatedly made the wrong irrational decisions for their patients.
Pain management goes to the core of the self of healthcare professionals who often
choose their vocations for wanting to help others and the biases emerge along the way
through personal experience, customary behaviors, and social norms in their respec-
tive environments. However, convictions about specific approaches run deep. I had the
opportunity to observe the interpersonal clashes after a hospital merger when staff from
two interventional radiology units had to work together. One team had been used to
injecting relatively large amounts of sedatives and narcotics for procedures, the other
relatively smaller amounts. Nursing staff of the lower-use site would accuse their col-
leagues of being drug pushers and the nursing staff of the higher-use site would return the
203
compliment by accusations of lack of caring. The fact that, as division chief, I introduced
nonpharmacologic adjuncts to pain management only helped insofar as forming an alli-
ance of high-and low-users against this new threat to entrained practice patterns. It took
about half a year and weekly meetings supported by the hospitals’ skilled organizational
development facilitators to arrive at a new common and patient-centered practice.
Societal influence
In years past, most medical procedures and treatments were ordered by a physician and
carried out in an appropriate hospital or office setting with very little consultation with
the patient. What was offered was accepted as necessary, including any accompanying
pain or discomfort. The attitude that the doctor knows best has eroded and the belief that
the healthcare system will provide what is best for the patient has been largely shattered.
Social norms, based on mutual trust between healthcare providers and recipients, are
increasingly being replaced by material norms, expectations of quality outcomes in return
of value for healthcare expenditures.
With healthcare reform in the United States and focus on National Quality Strategies,
patients are being considered more as consumers, clients, and customers (Van Fleet &
Peterson 2016), a concept that is clearly uncomfortable for some healthcare profession-
als (Leng 2015). However, the switch to a consumer’s market has pushed the element
of patient satisfaction into the forefront of various tools that evaluate medical facilities,
including those used by the Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services (CMS) when
weighing reimbursement to hospitals for patient care (Centers for Medicare and Medicaid
Services 2009, 2011). In the United States, patient satisfaction rankings contribute 30% to
the overall quality scores. Hospitals ranking below the 50th national percentile are fined
1–2% of all payments through CMS, which is significant considering hospital margins
commonly range between 1% and 5%.
Pain management and communication play prominently in the US patient satisfac-
tion surveys (Lang et al. 2013). Questions include “How often was your pain well con-
trolled?” “How often did the hospital staff do everything they could to help you with
your pain?” The emphasis on “everything” acknowledges that drugs are not the only way
opening the way to include nonpharmacologic approaches. Effective January 1, 2015, the
Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations clarified its Standard
PC.01.02.07 on managing patient’s pain in that both pharmacologic and nonpharmaco-
logic strategies have a role in the management of pain.
The new emphasis on nonpharmacologic adjuncts is driven in part by the opioid epi-
demic. In 2014, opioids killed more than 28,000 people in the United States alone, with
more than half involving prescription drugs (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention
2016). With greater pressure on medical professionals to see more patients in less time,
it is often easier to prescribe large amounts of narcotics rather than to sit and discuss
what else may work to improve comfort after dental or other surgery and risk a possible
subsequent unreimbursed call or repeat visit of the same patient. Recent laws that attempt
204
Shaping the experience
The proverbial term of the white coat trance, with the associated higher blood pressure
and heart rate is an indication that the medical encounter itself produces a state of height-
ened suggestibility. One can consider the patient to be already in a state of self-hypnosis
205
and being highly susceptible to everything that is said or not being said or the suggestive
power of external cues. Thus, just as any negatively voiced statement or negative sugges-
tion can make the experience worse in the sense of a nocebo, mere avoidance of such
negative suggestions improves the experience, and helpful suggestions can improve the
experience just as the expectations coming with placebo treatment.
Of particular benefit is the fact, as shown in our studies, that shaping the patient’s expe-
rience at the onset of the provider interaction is the critical step and may be all that is
needed, even for procedures that last for hours (Lang et al. 2000, 2006, 2008). The ele-
ments of this process are rapport, relaxation, and reframing in conjunction with aware-
ness of what is said, injection of hypnoidal language, and, depending on the need of the
situation, reading of a formal self-hypnotic relaxation script or comparative unscripted
induction of a relaxed state.
One truly does not know how a patient will experience a stimulus or treatment, and
there is the tendency to project one’s own expectations onto the other person in concor-
dance with one’s own belief system. In going further to assess how the patient’s pain expe-
rience can be improved, we found that the very first step is to establish rapport. Once in
rapport, it makes it much easier to communicate and find the right words spontaneously
and without awkwardness (Marchant 2016). For this reason we place heavy emphasis on
advanced rapport skills when training medical teams in nonpharmacologic calmative and
analgesic techniques (Lang 2012; Norbash et al. 2016).
Advanced rapport skills entail adapting to the patient’s body position, for example,
bending over toward sitting patients, but may also mean adapting to their emotional state,
such as speaking louder or in an agitated manner if they do so, or softer if they are more
subdued and then lead by modeling to a more resourceful state (Lang & Laser 2009). The
same methods are found in some of the sales literature (Boothman 2010) and the question
is often raised during workshops we give to medical professionals whether this would not
be manipulative and therefore unethical.
Often the individuals that object the most to intentional matching with another person
are the ones who do so very naturally on their own. Is it unethical to do something inten-
tionally that one does by natural instinct? The answer will most likely be in the intent of
the outcome, whether to deceive or to help. However, an interesting phenomenon hap-
pens in that regard. People who match each other, whether intentionally or not, are in
rapport and are more open to each other’s suggestions and leads. So even if one may start
with less than best intentions, being so-to-speak willing to walk in the other person’s
shoes may produce a better mutual understanding than intentional lack of matching.
Feelings and external expression thereof are interrelated. For example, the application
of botulinum toxin (Botox®) into the forehead muscles above the nose, mainly done for
cosmetic reasons, has been found to have as a side effect the reduction in depression of
the recipient, giving credence to a facial feedback mechanism on emotion (Wollmer et al.
2014). Furthermore, the facial expression of one person will affect the conversation part-
ner in the sense of an emotional contagion (Hatfield & Cacioppo 1994). What may start as
mimicry or matching ends as feeling in similar ways. If done intentionally, thus one could
206
make another person feel worse, which could ethically be considered as objectionable, or
make the other person feel better. However, when this requires an intentional effort, as we
find in our training, it tends to be interpreted as more manipulative when done to make a
patient feel more resourceful, as compared to when executed without noticing by radiat-
ing off the stress from work and making other people feel equally stressed.
Language
In the interest of full disclosure, consenting and listing of side effects of treatments has to
be honest to enable a person to determine which risk ratio to accept with a treatment as
compared to no treatment or alternative treatment. If done in a collaborative approach,
discussing what will be done to manage potential complications and what omission of
proceeding may evoke with the same conditions, patients can arrive at a decision that feels
right for them (Lang 2014b). After the medical consent is given, full focus on avoidance
of nocebo effects and use of more positive language is in order. How can this be achieved
in practical terms?
Avoiding upfront use of verbiage with negative emotional content is a first step. Use
of neutral statements such as, “I will give you the local anesthetic,” is a further step up
the comfort ladder, and mentioning the likelihood of a reasonably expectable desirable
outcome can help even further, such as, “I will give you the anesthetic and the area should
become numb shortly” (Lang et al. 2005; Dutt-Gupta et al. 2007; Varelmann et al. 2010).
Consider the difference between such a statement and “I will stick you with a needle”
(Lang 2014a).
At the other end of the suggestive spectrum are placebo statements that are known to
the user to be untrue and may constitute a moral dilemma. One of the most impressive
demonstrations of placebo, where need and belief coincide in a powerful combination,
occurred at the warfront in World War II when Henry Beecher ran out of morphine while
treating wounded American soldiers. Desperate to be supportive, nurses would inject
saline, describing it as a potent pain killer. It worked in about 40% of the cases.
With regard to the use of placebo, the American Medical Association urges practitio-
ners to be “extremely thorough in obtaining consent from patients” (American Medical
Association 1997) echoed by the ethics code of the UK General Medical Council equally
insisting on complete openness. Blease argues that medical treatment always occurs in the
framework of interpersonal interactions between staff and patients and is influenced by
the beliefs of those involved in the power of the treatment thus making the term “positive
care effects” more appropriate than “placebo effect” (Blease 2012). “Positive care effects”
may also take away the stigma that some perceive to be associated with a “sugar pill” or an
element of deception. Although the literature suggests that even open labeling of placebo,
for example revealing the placebo nature of a treatment doesn’t interfere with its success
in pain management and can still result in a 50% success rate (Kam-Hansen et al. 2014).
One can see how the element of known deception in some placebo approaches could
interfere with the patient–provider relationship. After all, one really doesn’t know what
207
the patient will experience and thus it is wise to avoid suggesting that something will
not or does not hurt or feel in a particular way. One way around this dilemma is the
use of permissive language leaving options for an outcome, indications that something,
for example, “might happen,” “could happen,” or “would be interesting to notice.” This
approach is often associated with Milton Erickson a psychiatrist and psychologist who
greatly shaped modern hypnosis. The permissive approach avoids the possibility that a
prediction fails and thereby undermines the trust a patient may have in the healthcare
professional. It also adheres to a dictum in my own practice, to leave to the patients the
right to their own experience. On the spectrum between purely neutral descriptors to the
possible integration of stimuli in a deeper hypnotic experience is a language approach
I like to call hypnoidal language. It is still fairly conversational while moving suggestions
up to the next level of desired outcomes. Giving a choice, “Would you prefer the IV on
the right arm or the left arm?” gives the patient a sense of control that otherwise may be
lacking. Double binds target a combination of desired results but leave the perception of
a choice without being authoritarian: “Some people first close their eyes, then they relax;
others first relax then close their eyes.” A sentence using presupposition of outcome in
response to a patient’s complaint may be, “I don’t know when it will stop hurting, in a
minute, in two minutes, in three minutes, or … NOW [emphasized].”
Offering choices for an experience can serve as a distraction by occupying the mind
about what the sensation might be, thereby leading away from the more catastrophizing
expectations, “You might feel some warmth or coolness, and then it should become numb
where it needs to be.” Including confusional elements can further help to take the mind
off spinning around negative recurring thoughts. As such we use in our script or when
announcing injections something like, “You might feel some warmth, or coolness. And
some people even describe a delicious sense of tingling.” The issue is that nobody really
knows how a delicious sense of tingling feels, and the statement is sufficiently surprising
that it helps to end unhelpful interactions, whether when voiced by the healthcare profes-
sional or by the patient, as in the example with AX above. Since AX’s report I have had to
use the “delicious tingling” reference myself once with a surgeon treating me in a similar
scenario and I can attest that it does shut off unwelcome negative suggestions by others.
Should we have asked our doctors’ consent to such confusional induction to reset their
own fears? Having requested them to stop in their unhelpful predictions of discomfort
should have sufficed, and by the time a procedure is started one can assume all partici-
pants are already in a trance-like state.
Procedure hypnosis
Going one step further when guiding patients in nonpharmacologic pain and anxiety
management is to have the patient associate with a pleasant scenario and integrate all
stimuli. This tends to be mostly acceptable as long as it is called imagery, visualization, or
meditation, but beware of using the word that actually would describe it best, “hypnosis,”
a state of focused concentration where awareness of outside stimuli become muted. To
208
Conclusion 209
endoscopies (Arrowsmith et al. 1991) to 8.7 million invasive medical procedures, it is
predicted that 47,000 patients will suffer serious cardiorespiratory complications and
2600 patients will die each year in the United States alone. This number does not take into
account the fatalities in dental offices using IV drug sedation (Yagiela 2001; Bennett et al.
2015). In addition, the cost of patient anxiety poses a considerable burden. The inability
of patients to complete their MRI exams, leaving capacity unused, wastes about $310 mil-
lion USD annually by conservative estimates (Norbash et al. 2016). These losses could be
largely avoided by team training of medical personnel in nonpharmacologic calmative
and analgesic techniques (Lang & Rosen 2002). Here the question of societal ethics clearly
comes into play when considerable sums of healthcare expenditures are wasted because
of preconceived notions. The situation is further aggravated by the fact that rationing of
pain medication now occurs even in prestigious hospitals, mostly without the patient’s
knowledge. A recent article in The New York Times described that all sorts of drugs includ-
ing anesthetics, pain killers, antibiotics, and cancer drugs that may be produced only by
few companies because of poor profit margin, may suddenly become unavailable during
production shortages, and that the practice of doctors of triaging and rationing critical
medications have become the new normal (Fink 2016).
Conclusion
There is ample scientific evidence about the power of words and how small changes in
behavior and wording can make huge differences in terms of medical outcomes and
patient satisfaction. Any change, however small, will likely encounter resistance from
engrained practice patterns often under the guise of the proposal violating prevailing eth-
ics or not being authentic. It can be a dilemma when scientific findings counteract one’s
deepest held beliefs about how another person’s discomfort should be managed or when
one’s own coping mechanisms clash with different preferences of friends or colleagues.
The resulting disagreement becomes even more critical in a patient–provider relationship,
which is inherently unequal. While giving a patient control can be therapeutic in itself for
the patient, giving up control without giving up responsibility can be a challenge for the
healthcare professionals accustomed to a more patriarchal model.
With patients’ empowerment toward expectation of greater patient- centered care
comes the recognition that patient satisfaction is not just a “customer” gimmick. Rather,
it is intertwined with quality in any kind of healthcare system and can enhance patients’
willingness to follow treatment recommendations and save healthcare expenditures.
The hope is that continued documentation of the efficacy of nonpharmacologic calm-
ative and analgesic techniques in well-conducted clinical trials will overcome these hur-
dles and further stepwise integration in medical practice will facilitate the needed culture
change of Western medical practice. The aim is to make gains for all concerned without
unnecessary pains.
210
References
American Medical Association (1997). Opinion 2.075—The Use of Placebo Controls in Clinical Trials.
Available from: http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-ethics/code-
medical-ethics/opinion2075.page? [accessed March 8, 2016].
Ariely, D. (2010). Predictably Irrational, Revised and Expanded Edition: The Hidden Forces that Shape
our Decisions. New York: Harper Perennial.
Arrowsmith, J.B., Gerstman, B.B., Fleischer, D.E., and Benjamin, S.B. (1991). Results from the
American Society for Gastrointestinal Endoscopy/U.S. Food and Drug Administration collaborative
study on complication rates and drug use during gastrointestinal endoscopy. Gastrointestinal
Endoscopy, 37, 421–427.
Atlas, L.Y. and Wager, T.D. (2012). How expectations shape pain. Neuroscience Letters, 520, 140–148.
Atlas, L.Y., Bolger, N., Lindquist, M.A., and Wager, T. D. (2010). Brain mediators of predictive cue
effects on perceived pain. Journal of Neuroscience, 30, 12964–12977.
Bayer, T.L., Coverdale, J.H., Chiang, E., and Bangs, M. (1998). The role of prior pain experience and
expectancy in psychologically and physically induced pain. Pain, 74, 327–331.
Bennett, J.D., Kramer, K.J., and Bosack, R.C. (2015). How safe is deep sedation or general anesthesia
while providing dental care? Journal of the American Dental Association, 146, 705–708.
Blankfield, R.P. (1991). Suggestion, relaxation, and hypnosis as adjuncts in the care of surgery
patients: a review of the literature. American Journal of Clinical Hypnosis, 33, 172–186.
Blease, C. (2012). The principle of parity: the “placebo effect” and physician communication. Journal of
Medical Ethics, 38, 199–203.
Boothman, N. (2010). Convince Them in 90 Seconds or Less: Make Instant Connections that Pay Off in
Business and Life. Chapel Hill, NC: Workman Publishing Company.
Burgstaller, J.M., Schuffler, P.J., Buhmann, J.M., et al. (2016). Is there an association between pain and
magnetic resonance imaging parameters in patients with lumbar spinal stenosis? Spine, 41(17),
E1053–1062.
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (2016). Injury Prevention & Control: Opioid Overdose.
Available from: http://www.cdc.gov/drugoverdose/ [accessed April 16, 2016].
Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services (2009). Roadmap for Implementing Value Driven
Healthcare in the Traditional Medicare Fee-for-Service Program. Available from: http://www.cms.hhs.
gov/QualityInitiativesGenInfo/downloads/VBPRoadmap_OEA_1-16_508.pdf [accessed December
5, 2012].
Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services (2011). Hospital Value-Based Purchasing Program (VBP).
Washington, DC: Medicare Learning Network. Available from: http://www.cms.gov/Hospital-Value-
Based-Purchasing [accessed January 20, 2013].
Chen, J., Li, Z., Lv, Y.F., et al. (2015). [Empathy for pain: a novel bio-psychosocial-behavioral laboratory
animal model]. Sheng Li Xue Bao, 67, 561–570.
Chooi, C.S., White, A.M., Tan, S.G., Dowling, K., and Cyna, A.M. (2013). Pain vs comfort scores after
Caesarean section: a randomized trial. British Journal of Anaesthesia, 110, 780–787.
Cyna, M.A. and Lang, E.V. (2011). How words hurt. In: Cyna, M., Andrew, M.I., Tan, S.G.M.,
and Smith, F. (eds.) Handbook of Communication in Anaesthesia and Critical Care, pp.30–37.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dutt-Gupta, J., Bown, T., and Cyna, A.M. (2007). Effect of communication on pain during intravenous
cannulation: a randomized controlled trial. British Journal of Anaesthesia, 99, 871–875.
Elkins, G., White, J., Patel, P., Marcus, J., Perfect, M.M., and Montgomery, G.H. (2006). Hypnosis to
manage anxiety and pain associated with colonoscopy for colorectal cancer screening: Case studies
and possible benefits. International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 54, 416–431.
21
References 211
Everett, J.J., Patterson, D.R., Burns, G.L., Montgomery, B., and Heimbach, D. (1993). Adjunctive
interventions for burn pain control: comparison of hypnosis and ativan: the 1993 Clinical Research
Award. Journal of Burn Care & Research, 14, 676–683.
Ewin, D.M. and Eimer, B.N. (2006). Ideomotor Signals for Rapid Hypnoanalysis. Springfield, IL: Charles
C. Thomas Publishers.
Faymonville, M.E., Fissette, J., Mambourg, P.H., Roediger, L., Joris, J., and Lamy, M. (1995). Hypnosis
as adjunct therapy in conscious sedation for plastic surgery. Regional Anesthesia, 20, 145–151.
Fink, S. (2016). Drug shortages forcing hard decisions on rationing treatments. New York Times,
January 29.
Goubert, L., Craig, K.D., Vervoort, T., et al. (2005). Facing others in pain: the effects of empathy. Pain,
118, 285–288.
Hashmi, J.A., Kong, J., Spaeth, R., Khan, S., Kaptchuk, T.J., and Gollub, R.L. (2014). Functional
network architecture predicts psychologically mediated analgesia related to treatment in chronic
knee pain patients. Journal of Neuroscience, 34, 3924–3936.
Hatfield, E. and Cacioppo, J. T. 1994. Emotional Contagion (Studies on Emotion and Social Interaction).
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hayashi, K., Ikemoto, T., Ueno, T., et al. (2016). Higher pain rating results in lower variability
of somatosensory cortex activation by painful mechanical stimuli: an fMRI study. Clinical
Neurophysiology, 127, 1923–1928.
Joint Commission On Accreditation Of Healthcare Organizations (2016). Joint Commission Statement
on Pain Management. Available from: https://www.jointcommission.org/joint_commission_
statement_on_pain_management/ [accessed February 8, 2016].
Kam-Hansen, S., Jakubowski, M., Kelley, J.M., et al. (2014). Altered placebo and drug labeling changes
the outcome of episodic migraine attacks. Science Translational Medicine, 6, 218ra5.
Keltner, J.R., Furst, A., Fan, C., Redfern, R., Inglis, B., and Fields, H.L. (2006). Isolating the
modulatory effect of expectation on pain transmission: a functional magnetic resonance imaging
study. Journal of Neuroscience, 26, 4437–4443.
Kilwein, J.H. (1989). No pain, no gain: a Puritan legacy. Health Education Quarterly, 16, 9–12.
Kroger, W.S. and Delee, S.T. (1957). Hypnoanesthesia for cesarean section and hysterectomy. JAMA,
163, 442–444.
Kupers, R., Faymonville, M.E., and Laureys, S. (2005). The cognitive modulation of pain: hypnosis-and
placebo-induced analgesia. Progress in Brain Research, 150, 251–269.
Lang, E.V. (2012). A better patient experience through better communication. Journal of Radiology
Nursing, 31, 114–119.
Lang, E.V. (2014a). How (Not) to Place an IV. Comfort Talk d/b/a/Hypnalgesics, LLC. Available
from: http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=526N-3Xqkwg [accessed February 8, 2016].
Lang, E.V. (2014b). Managing Your Medical Experience: The Information You Need Plus Self-Hyonosis for
Finding Comfort With Your Tests and Treatments. Middletown, DE: Create Space.
Lang, E.V. and Laser, E. (2009). Patient Sedation Without Medication. Rapid Rapport and Quick
Hypontic Techniques. A Resource Guide for Doctors, Nurses, and Technolgists. Raleigh, NC: Lulu.
Lang, E.V. and Rosen, M.P. (2002). Cost analysis of adjunct hypnosis with sedation during outpatient
interventional radiologic procedures. Radiology, 222, 375–382.
Lang, E.V., Chen, F., Fick, L.J., and Berbaum, K.S. (1998). Determinants of intravenous conscious
sedation for arteriography. Journal of Vascular and Interventional Radiology, 9, 407–412.
Lang, E.V., Benotsch, E.G., Fick, L.J., et al. (2000). Adjunctive non-pharmacological analgesia for
invasive medical procedures: a randomised trial. Lancet, 355, 1486–1490.
Lang, E.V., Hatsiopoulou, O., Koch, T., et al. (2005). Can words hurt? Patient-provider interactions
during invasive procedures. Pain, 114, 303–309.
21
Lang, E.V., Berbaum, K.S., Faintuch, S., et al. (2006). Adjunctive self-hypnotic relaxation for outpatient
medical procedures: a prospective randomized trial with women undergoing large core breast
biopsy. Pain, 126, 155–164.
Lang, E.V., Berbaum, K.S., Pauker, S.G., et al. (2008). Beneficial effects of hypnosis and adverse effects
of empathic attention during percutaneous tumor treatment: when being nice does not suffice.
Journal of Vascular and Interventional Radiology, 19, 897–905.
Lang, E.V., Yuh, W.T., Ajam, A., et al. (2013). Understanding patient satisfaction ratings for radiology
services. AJR American Journal of Roentgenology, 201, 1190–1195.
Lang, E.V., Tan, G., Amihai, I., and Jensen, M.P. (2014). Analyzing acute procedural pain in clinical
trials. Pain, 155, 1365–1373.
Leng, S (2015, February). Patients are not customers. Here are 6 reasons why. KevinMD.com. Available
from: http://www.kevinmd.com/blog/2015/02/patients-not-customers-6-reasons.html [accessed
February 8, 2016].
Liossi, C. and Hatira, P. (2003). Clinical hypnosis in the alleviation of procedure-related pain in
pediatric oncology patients. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 51, 4–28.
Liossi, C., White, P., and Hatira, P. (2006). Randomized clinical trial of local anesthetic versus a
combination of local anesthetic with self-hypnosis in the management of pediatric procedure-
related pain. Health Psychology, 25, 307–315.
Marchant, J. (2016). The Cure: A Journey into the Science of Mind Over Body. New York: Crown.
McDermott, V.G.M., Chapman, M.E., and Gillespie, I. (1993). Sedation and patient monitoring in
vascular and interventional radiology. British Journal and Radiology, 66, 667–671.
Meurisse, M., Hamoir, E., Defechereux, T., et al. (1999). Bilateral neck exploration under
hypnosedation. A new standard of care in primary hyperparathyroidism? Annals of Surgery, 229,
401–408.
Mogil, J.S. (2012). The surprising empathic abilities of rodents. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16,
143–144.
Montgomery, G.H., David, D., Winkel, G., Silverstein, J.H., and Bovberg, D.H. (2002). The
effectiveness of adjunctive hypnosis with surgical patients: a meta-analysis. Anesthesia & Analgesia,
94, 1639–1645.
Montgomery, G.H., Bovbjerg, D.H., Schnur, J.B., et al. (2007). A randomized clinical trial of a brief
hypnosis intervention to control side effects in breast surgery patients. Journal of the National
Cancer Institute, 99, 1304–1312.
Norbash, A., Yucel, K., Yuh, W., et al. (2016). Effect of team training on improving MRI study
completion rates and no show rates. Journal of Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 44(4), 1040–107.
Peerdeman, K.J., Van Laarhoven, A.I., Keij, S.M., et al. (2016). Relieving patients’ pain with expectation
interventions: a meta-analysis. Pain, 157, 1179–1191.
Peyron, R., Laurent, B., and Garcia-Larrea, L. (2000). Functional imaging of brain responses to pain.
A review and meta-analysis. Clinical Neurophysiology, 30, 263–288.
Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J., Kaube, H., Dolan, R.J., and Frith, C.D. (2004). Empathy for pain
involves the affective but not sensory components of pain. Science, 303, 1157–1162.
Van Fleet, D.D. and Peterson, T.O. (2016). Improving healthcare practice behaviors. International
Journal of Health Care Quality Assurance, 29, 141–161.
Varelmann, D., Pancaro, C., Cappiello, E.C., and Camann, W.R. (2010). Nocebo-induced hyperalgesia
during local anesthetic injection. Anesthesia & Analgesia, 110, 868–870.
Watt-Watson, J., Garfinkel, P., Gallop, R., Stevens, B., and Streiner, D. (2000). The impact of nurses’
empathic responses on patients’ pain management in acute care. Nursing Research, 49, 191–200.
213
References 213
Weinstein, E.J. and Au, P.K. (1991). Use of hypnosis before and during angioplasty. American Journal of
Clinical Hypnosis, 34, 29–37.
Wollmer, M.A., Kalak, N., Jung, S., et al. (2014). Agitation predicts response of depression to botulinum
toxin treatment in a randomized controlled trial. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 5, 36.
Yagiela, J.A. (2001). Making patients safe and comfortable for a lifetime of dentistry: frontiers in office-
based sedation. Journal of Dental Education, 65, 1348–1356.
214
Chapter 12
Introduction
The powers of placebo are long known. In the popular imagination, placebos have become
synonymous with snake oil, deception and lying, and other nefarious immoral endeavors
(the primary exception being a mother’s kiss to the bumps and bruises of childhood). The
scientific and medical community has assumed a stance that placebos are by definition
inert and their use should be reserved to that of an experimental control; therapeuti-
cally, placebo use is condemned as a transgressive practice and punishable based on the
assumed deception necessary with placebo administration—a breach of ethical conduct.
215
This stance is now being challenged by the emerging scientific evidence demonstrating
that placebos are far from inert as well as by studies revealing widespread, although largely
clandestine, therapeutic use (Sherman & Hickner 2008; Tilburt et al. 2008; Kermen et al.
2010; Rommelfanger 2013a). Perhaps even more surprising is the frequently reported
patient approval of therapeutic use of placebos even under the context of deception
(Lynoe et al. 1993; Fassler et al. 2011; Hull et al. 2013; Pugh et al. 2016). For those who
unequivocally believe deception is immoral, emerging data suggest that placebo effects
can be maintained even without deception (Kaptchuk et al. 2010; Schafer et al. 2015).
Collectively, these new data on placebo require reappraisal.
Placebos in practice
Placebo therapy use is a global phenomenon, and according to some reports, up to 97%
of physicians administer placebo therapeutically (Fassler et al. 2010; Fent et al. 2011;
Meissner et al. 2012; Howick et al. 2013). Fifty percent of US physicians have used pla-
cebo in clinical practice (Sherman & Hickner 2008; Tilburt et al. 2008) for an array of
disorders from gastrointestinal and immune disorders to cancer and neurological disor-
ders (Sherman & Hickner 2008). Placebo treatments include saline, sugar pills, vitamins,
over-the-counter analgesics, antibiotics, and sedatives (Tilburt et al. 2008). Physicians
often describe placebo therapies as “a substance that may help and will not hurt” or “it
is medication” or “it is medicine with no specific effect,” “a medicine not typically used
for your condition but might benefit you,” or might say, “This may help you, but I am
not sure how it works” (Sherman & Hickner 2008; Tilburt et al. 2008). These statements
demonstrate a mode of communicating information that falls somewhere on a spectrum
between acceptable professional norms of oversimplifying treatment descriptions (i.e.,
physician states that a pill is akin to an antibiotic or antihistamine) to deliberate attempts
at verbal misdirection.
Professional values
While placebo therapy has been widely employed across the globe (Hrobjartsson & Norup
2003; Tilburt et al. 2008; Fassler et al. 2010; Fent et al. 2011; Meissner et al. 2012; Howick
et al. 2013), this practice is quite contrary to the values self-professed to be held by profes-
sional medical associations such as the American Medical Association (AMA)—although
the AMA only in 2006 categorically prohibited deceptive placebo use (Bostick et al. 2008;
Blease 2012). Interestingly, no pronouncement has been made by similar global organiza-
tions and the AMA’s stance is by far the most explicit and stringent.
According to the Report of the AMA Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, placebo is
defined as “a substance that the physician believes had no known specific pharmacological
217
activity against the condition being treated” (Bostick et al. 2008, p.58). The Council states
that placebo use with deception “directly conflicts with contemporary notions of patient
autonomy and the practice of shared decision making (Bostick et al. 2008, p.59). Aside
from the harm of violating the patient–physician alliance, the Council argue that patients
may also encounter nocebo effects, adverse side effects rather than the positive effects
associated with placebo use. These statements reveal the inherent professional and con-
ceptual confusion about placebo in two ways. First, the authors warn against placebos as
treatments with no specific pharmacological activity that may be accompanied by legiti-
mate adverse effects, implying that while benefits are somehow fake, the harms are some-
how real. Second, the placebos are defined by the physician’s belief that the placebo has
no known specific pharmacological activity, not characterized or defined by the scientific
evidence that might explain mechanisms of placebo. However, in the concluding state-
ments of the report, the Council states that placebos “may be used in clinical practice to
determine a diagnosis or appropriate treatment in the face of clinical uncertainty,” but that
physicians should avoid deception. The report also recommends that physicians should
avoid placebos, but are nonetheless supported in their attempt to elicit a “placebo-like
effect through the skillful use of reassurance and encouragement … In this way, the physi-
cian builds respect and trust, promotes the patient-physician relationship, and improves
health outcomes” (Bostick et al. 2008, p.60). One may well wonder, which is it? Do pla-
cebos violate the patient–physician relationship and cause harm or do placebos build
respect and trust and improve health outcomes? Perhaps it is no wonder in this linguistic
equivocation that clinicians find themselves in practice clandestinely using placebo.
The AMA has also created explicit guidelines in the form of an Opinion under their
Code of Medical Ethics on the clinical use of placebos. In their Opinion statement there
is one loophole for deception under the condition that the patient is informed at some
point that placebo will be used but that the patient will be blind to the precise timing of
its implementation (AMA 2007). In this case the Opinion appears to sanction a kind of
deception that requires patient ignorance of some details such as timing with the patient’s
approval. Again such an Opinion also highlights lingering ambiguity about the role both
of deception in routine practice and for deceptive placebo use. The AMA Council report
states that “physicians may utilize placebos within their clinical practice without relying
on the act of deception” (Bostick et al. 2008). This statement in the Council Report in
combination with the Opinion seems to suggest that there is some form of acceptable
deception, or appears to suggest that authorized deception is not really deception (Blease
et al. 2016), just like placebos are not really placebos if the physician does not believe they
are, as with the case of active placebos where active agents such as vitamins or off-label
prescriptions are given as placebo.
How and why does the prevalent use of (deceptive) therapeutic placebo prevail even in
the absence of solidarity from professional medical societies? Have physicians betrayed
their oaths to care for patients and to try to make them well or improve their quality of
lives? Is there an ethical framework that would make such a behavior morally permissible?
A consequentialist approach where the ends justify the means seems to explain popular
218
physician use of placebo therapy. A deontological approach championing the duty not to
lie about an inert treatment seems to drive concerns for deception. The result is a rela-
tively widespread use of placebo in a clandestine manner or a compromised use of active
placebos that utilize off-label or reduced doses of real drugs (Sherman & Hickner 2008;
Tilburt et al. 2008; Rommelfanger 2013a). While these arguments around placebo are not
new, the definition and what we know about placebos must be updated with the accumu-
lating body of evidence showing specific neurobiological effects from placebo (Benedetti
2014) as well as the necessity—or lack thereof (Blease et al. 2016)—for deception with
placebo administration. These data will be discussed in “Explanations for placebo effects.”
Just as remarkably absent as the neuroscience data in these ethical evaluative schemas,
is the patient’s voice and her reflections about the use of placebo therapy. These data too
must be incorporated into our future reappraisals of placebo therapy and in determina-
tions of what is best for individual patients.
individual experience and illness. In fact, those who subscribe to such a model are guilty
of reducing the human experience in a way that devalues the individual patient’s sub-
jective experience while over-privileging objective measures. The long-suffering road of
pain researchers who have struggled to find objective measures that can replace subjective
reports of pain demonstrate the downfall of such a strategy.
Another way of conceptualizing placebo is to suggest that placebos are largely effects
of context (Miller & Kaptchuk 2008). So much so, perhaps, that Di Blasi and colleagues
suggest that placebo effects would more appropriately be referred to as “context effects”
(Di Blasi et al. 2001). It would seem that the ritual around the intervention, rather than
the intervention itself, is what determines the placebo effect. Anthropologist Daniel
Moerman advocates for a reconceptualization of placebo effects as meaningful responses,
and in doing so one can avoid the ethical quandaries of both placebo itself and the embed-
ded connotations of deception (Moerman 2002; Moerman & Jonas 2002). With Western
biomedicine, technological interventions are privileged and the placebo is understood as
the non-technological context, somehow a nonspecific variable and background noise.
Placebo effects, in other words, are psychological contamination (Colloca & Benedetti
2005). A discussion of how context impacts learning and expectation associated with pla-
cebo is discussed further in “Mechanisms of placebo.”
Regardless, placebo, conceptualized as nonspecific and subjective phenomena, has
demonstrably specific and objectively measurable effects. Given these demonstrable
effects, should placebos be given more credibility as a viable intervention? Can we over-
come the historical linguistic trappings with placebo and its counterparts? The term pla-
cebo is in grave need of updating and perhaps at best only serves as an anachronistic
placeholder, like thingamajig, a relic of a troubled legacy of misunderstanding.
Mechanisms of placebo
Placebo effects can be thought of in terms of mechanisms of expectation, learning, and
conditioning (Colloca & Miller 2011b). In Colloca and Miller’s model, placebo is a vehicle
for therapy not because of its internal properties, but because they are a collection of
salient signals or symbols. An intervention, whether considered a placebo or not, can-
not be separated from the context in which it is given. Colloca and Miller point out that,
“The patient does not come to the clinical encounter as a blank slate but with a history of
experiences and memories evoked by prior responses to signals related to the milieu of
therapy” (Colloca & Miller 2011b, p.1860). In this sense, placebo effects are not unique
to placebo interventions per se and can happen with any clinical intervention—with or
without physical placebo.
According to a classical conditioning framework, repeated exposure to contextual fac-
tors that coincide with ingestion of a medication—such as visual, tactile, and gustatory
stimuli (unconditioned stimuli)—become associated conditioned stimuli (Pavlov 1927;
Colloca & Miller 2011b). Placebos, as a consequence, are in turn able to elicit condi-
tioned responses in the presence of their conditioned stimuli. For example, were one to
visit a physician’s office and receive pain relief from an injection of an anti-inflammatory
20
drug, a syringe can become the conditioned stimulus—it becomes the symbol for pain
relief. Then future observation of the syringe (or injection from the syringe regardless
of its content) at a doctor’s office may then elicit pain relief for a patient so conditioned
(Montgomery & Kirsch 1997; Colloca & Miller 2011b).
Learning associations for placebo, like any learning, allows for environmental cues or
elements to be connected with social cues. There appear to be several different cues or
conditions that can elicit a placebo response. These include verbal cues, prior experi-
ence, observation, and social learning, each of which lead to expectation and conditioned
learning (Colloca & Miller 2011b). Early studies explored the effect of verbal language on
bronchoconstriction in patients with asthma (Luparello et al. 1968, 1970). When patients
were instructed to inhale a solution (of nebulized saline) and told that the solution was
an allergen, nearly half of the patients demonstrated increased airway resistance. When
the same patients were instructed to inhale the same solution (again of nebulized saline)
and told that the solution was a medicine for asthma, airway bronchoconstriction was
reversed. In an additional study, carbachol, a bronchoconstrictor, was given to patients
who were told that it was a bronchoconstrictor. These patients had greater effects than
when patients were told carbachol was indeed a bronchodilator. In another series of stud-
ies for postoperative pain relief, patients (who were told that a placebo was a potent pain
reliever) were able to reduce their opioid intake more than patients who were told nothing
about the analgesic effect of the placebo or patients who were told that they might receive
a placebo or pain reliever (Pollo et al. 2001). Verbal suggestion also has been shown to
have significant placebo (and nocebo, or negative, unpleasant effects) effects in an experi-
mental model of itch (Van Laarhoven et al. 2011).
One example of conditioning by prior experience was demonstrated by Benedetti and
colleagues. Participants given placebo for migraine relief were able to experience subjec-
tive pain relief accompanied by the same profile of significant biochemical effects (albeit
not as dramatic) of increased growth hormone release and decreased cortisol release
(Benedetti et al. 2003). The placebo was only able to elicit this response after prior admin-
istration of the migraine medication, that is, no effect was seen if placebo was admin-
istered before administration of migraine medication. This effect was also independent
of verbal instructions about the placebo/migraine medication that would have primed
expectations. Similar conditioned placebo responses have been seen with immunosup-
pressors (Goebel et al. 2002, 2005), dopamine agonists (De La Fuente-Fernandez et al.
2001; Benedetti et al. 2004; Lidstone et al. 2010), and benzodiazepines (Petrovic et al.
2005). Conditioned placebo responses have also been modeled in nonhuman animal
studies in mice (Guo et al. 2010) and rats (Zhang et al. 2013; Lee et al. 2015). Interestingly,
in one follow-up study, Guo and colleagues suggest that placebo effects can be trans-
ferred from one domain to another, from pain to emotion in their rodent model (Guo
et al. 2011).
In a recent placebo analgesia study involving rodents, Lee and colleagues attempted to
parse out learning neurophysiology from analgesia physiology (Lee et al. 2015). Rodents
were trained in a conditioned place preference paradigm to associate a place/room with
21
low or high pain induced by heat. Rats then formed an association between the room
cue (one room had a rough floor with a black and white wall and the other room had
black wall with a soft floor) and the pain stimulus following exposure to the room. Given
the choice post training, the rats came to prefer the room that had preceded lower pain
exposure during training. The pain response was measured with hind paw withdrawal to
a stimulus. Longer latencies are associated with lower pain. Administration of the dopa-
mine antagonist haloperidol blocked cue learning preference for the room preceding low
pain exposure. Both dopamine and opioid antagonist naloxone blocked the expression of
placebo analgesia as measured by biomarkers in the ventral tegmental area and nucleus
accumbens. From these data, researchers concluded that dopamine pathways were critical
in the acquisition of association of cues with the placebo response. Corroborating human
study data (Wager et al. 2007), Zhang and colleagues further concluded through direct
microinjections of various subtype opioid antagonists into the rat anterior cingulate cor-
tex, an area associated with registered physical pain, that mu-opioid receptors mediate
placebo analgesia (Zhang et al. 2013).
Prior experience with active drugs or even placebos can influence the magnitude of sub-
sequent placebo responses (Colloca & Benedetti 2006). In one study of placebo analgesia,
two groups of participants were exposed to painful stimuli. In one group, individuals were
told they were given an analgesic agent while the researcher simulated a placebo effect by
surreptitiously reducing the intensity of the painful stimuli. In a second group the inten-
sity of the painful stimuli was not reduced. When both groups were given the placebo
again, but without reduction of painful stimuli, the participants who initially were primed
to believe the placebo was an effective pain reliever by surreptitiously reducing inten-
sity of the painful stimuli in the initial exposure, experienced a greater placebo response.
These placebo responses and the anticipation of analgesia were correlated to activity in
the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex suggesting that anticipation of placebo involves higher-
order cognitive activities such as executive functioning and perception (Lui et al. 2010).
In another study by Lidstone and colleagues, participants with Parkinson’s disease, told
a numerical probability of receiving dopamine therapy while always receiving placebo,
demonstrated significant dopamine release in both the nigrostriatal system that is charac-
teristically impacted in Parkinson’s disease, as well as the mesoaccumbens, a node in the
reward pathway, when the probability was high (75%) (Lidstone et al. 2010). The strength
of expectation by giving participants a numerical expectation value impacted the degree
of dopamine release in both the dorsal striatum associated with therapeutic dopamine
release, and ventral striatum, associated with reward/expectation mediated dopamine
release (Lidstone et al. 2010). Cortical excitability has also been associated with expecta-
tion of treatment (Lou et al. 2013).
Reward learning is the subject of significant study for drug addiction, attention defi-
cit hyperactivity disorder, and basic learning mechanisms. Critical to reward learning is
the recruitment of the ventral striatum (Schultz 2006), a region also thought to underlie
placebo effects (De La Fuente-Fernandez et al. 2004) by moderating salience and expecta-
tion. Dopamine release in the ventral striatum has been identified with placebo analgesia
2
(Scott et al. 2008) as well as in response to the probability of receiving active drug as men-
tioned earlier (Lidstone et al. 2010).
While some scholars have attempted to draw clear distinctions between expectancy
and conditioning (Kirsch 2004; Stewart-Williams & Podd 2004)—that is, conditioning
requires unconscious participation while expectancy may require conscious processing—
it is also recognized by critics (Kirsch 2004) that some form of conditioning likely under-
lies critical aspects of the generation of expectancy. Classical conditioning is also likely to
involve a higher order of cognition in order to form logical and perceptual relationships
between events, stimuli, and representations (Shanks 2010).
Amanzio and Benedetti attempted to dissect components of expectation-based anal-
gesia and conditioning-based analgesia, eliciting recruitment of specific neurophysi-
ological changes related to pain analgesia (Amanzio & Benedetti 1999). In this human
study, expectations of receiving pain relievers that work by two different mechanisms
induced opioid-and nonsteroidal anti-inflammatory drug (NSAID)-mediated pla-
cebo analgesia respectively. However, conditioned responses recruited specific neu-
rophysiological responses dependent on the type of analgesia; morphine-induced
opioid-mediated pain relief was blocked by the opioid antagonist naloxone and
NSAID-mediated analgesia was not blocked by naloxone. Importantly, the research-
ers found that the two components were intertwined and that reduced expectancy. By
telling participants they would receive an NSAID rather than morphine while they
were being given the opioid antagonist that blocks opioid-mediated pain relief, the
conditioned placebo analgesia response was reduced but not eliminated (Amanzio &
Benedetti 1999). In this case, the expectation that the drug was a pain reliever still
resulted in placebo analgesia likely though a specific NSAID-mediated mechanism (as
a conditioned response to the NSAID) that could not be blocked by an antagonist for
another pain reliever (morphine).
Finally, Colloca and Miller note models of social learning for placebo (Colloca &
Miller 2011a), rather than direct first-hand experience as described in the studies previ-
ously described. The magnitude of the placebo response for those who were conditioned
through observing pain relief in another was similar to conditioned placebo responses
via first-hand experience (Colloca & Benedetti 2009). In addition, those participants with
higher empathy scores had greater placebo responses upon observing placebo pain relief.
Another form of social learning with placebo can occur through patient–provider inter-
action. Placebo effects have been shown to be augmented when participants had more
supportive practitioner engagement as enacted though active listening (e.g. repeating
patients’ words and asking for clarification) and attempts to behave in a warm, friendly,
and empathetic (e.g., by saying, “I understand how this could be difficult for you”) way as
well as setting positive expectations (e.g., saying, “I believe this will have a positive impact
for you”) and 20 seconds of thoughtful silence after interventions (Kaptchuk et al. 2008).
It seems the ritual of therapeutic encounters provides a learning mechanism wherein
patients can learn to produce placebo responses through having an interaction with a
healer/clinician (Miller et al. 2009). In this model of “interpersonal healing,” the doctor’s
23
beliefs about the efficacy of treatment can be extremely influential on the patient’s expec-
tation and placebo response to an intervention.
Societal influence and impact of branding can influence placebo effects. In a recent
study on placebo analgesia for migraine, by Kam-Hansen and colleagues, investigators
noted that placebo bottles labeled as “Maxalt” reduced headache severity as well as Maxalt
labeled as placebo (Kam-Hansen et al. 2014). Further placebo, labeled as placebo, was
more effective in reducing headaches than no treatment at all. A recent study exploring
the price attached to a medication for Parkinson’s showed that patients told they were
given expensive medication manufactured at $1500 USD/dose demonstrated a greater
reduction in motor symptoms than patients told they were given cheaper medication
manufactured at $100 USD/dose, both of which were placebos (Espay et al. 2015). Clearly
these placebo effects are modulated both by direct and indirect experience and embedded
meanings in those experiences. In a global study of placebo effects in clinical trials for
pain medications, researchers identified an increasing effect in the United States and only
United States (Tuttle et al. 2015). These effects are stronger in longer and larger trials that
tended to occur in the United States, suggesting the strong influence of cultural values and
meaning of pharmacology on eliciting placebo responses.
Benedetti 1999) and animal models (Nolan et al. 2012) indicating that placebos have
specificity with regard to endogenous neurochemistry.
As noted earlier, studies in human patients suggest that placebo effects utilize reward
pathways in the ventral striatum and that these reward pathways are modulated by
expectation. De la Fuente-Fernandez and colleagues demonstrated in several occasions
through positron emission tomography that placebo can activate the specific nigrostriatal
dopamine system whose degeneration and disruption characterizes Parkinson’s disease,
and greater placebo-induced dopamine release associated with patient-reported clinical
improvement (De La Fuente-Fernandez et al. 2001, 2004). Regardless of whether patients
reported clinical improvement, all participants demonstrated placebo-induced increases
in dopamine in the ventral striatum, an area typically associated with reward functioning
and expectation of rewards (De La Fuente-Fernandez et al. 2004; Schultz 2006). These
studies suggest that while expectation plays a key role in facilitating downstream pla-
cebo effects, the degree of recruitment of the specific relevant biochemical pathway can
impact the perceived therapeutic benefit. Critically, intact top-down cognitive processing
may mediate these placebo effects, as some are lost in patients with Alzheimer’s disease
(Benedetti 2006; Enck et al. 2008).
While many placebo studies have been conducted in pain studies, Parkinson’s disease
allows unique attributes for exploring the biological correlates to the placebo pathway.
For example, with Parkinson’s disease versus pain, treatment responses can be evalu-
ated objectively by the experimenter evaluations of motor performance (Frisaldi et al.
2014). The second unique advantage is that neurophysiological correlates of placebo
response can be measured at the level of the individual brain cell in awake patients by
using electrodes implanted for deep brain stimulation. In a study building on that by
Benedetti and colleagues (Benedetti et al. 2004), Fisaldi and colleagues examined the pla-
cebo response in Parkinson’s disease through single-unit recordings throughout the basal
ganglia (Frisaldi et al. 2014). These studies were critical to connect previous studies that
separately indicated changes in downstream neurophysiology in the subthalamic nucleus
(Benedetti et al. 2004) and the facilitation of this effect mediated by changes in expecta-
tion and reward pathways (De La Fuente-Fernandez et al. 2001). They were able to dem-
onstrate that critical areas affected in Parkinson’s disease, subthalamic nucleus, and the
substantia nigra pars reticulata as well as the ventral anterior thalamus were involved in
the placebo response. Frisaldi and colleagues were also able to compare patterns of activ-
ity between placebo responders and nonresponders (Frisaldi et al. 2014).
In sum, we see the development of an evolving model of placebo (Diederich & Goetz
2008) that suggests that high-order brain regions (such as the prefrontal and cingulate
cortices) modulate pathways involved in expectation and reward processing (such as the
ventral striatum). In turn, changes in these pathways affect disease-specific or condition-
specific pathways—the dorsal striatum in Parkinson disease, the midbrain in modulation
of opioid release for pain relief, and the amygdala and limbic areas to mimic serotonin
reuptake inhibitors in depression (Mayberg et al. 2002). Enck and colleagues postulate
that placebo is a kind of evolved “endogenous healthcare system” (Enck et al. 2008).
25
Deception 225
More recent studies have explored possible biomarkers and genetic polymorphisms
such as enzymes that metabolize catecholamines like catechol-O-methyl transferase, that
would make one more susceptible to placebo responses, the so-called placebome (Hall
et al. 2012, 2015). These studies, along with the notion of placebo effects as a product
of social learning or classical conditioning (even in nonhuman animals), suggest that
placebo responses are biological and evolutionarily conserved (Colloca & Miller 2011a).
Evolutionary psychologist Nicholas Humphrey proposes that typical bodily response to
stressors such as pain or anxiety are counteracted by placebo responses using hope to
counteract pain and anxiety and engaging internal healing mechanisms instead of shut-
ting down (Humphrey 2002). While there is no shortage of future empirical research
needed to further elucidate such mechanisms, this research has moved past its infancy
and warrants more sophisticated integration into practical applications of placebo therapy.
Deception
A seemingly universal tenet of medical ethics is the belief that good practice requires hon-
esty and forbids deceit. The clearest ethical violation of placebo therapy is not necessarily
the use of the placebo itself, but the secreted nature of this use. The use is hidden not just
to the patient, but also from other physicians in the healthcare team.
the answer to this question must be empirically informed. A handful of studies report
actual collected data on patient preferences about placebo treatment. A study of patients
from Sweden revealed that patients were, perhaps surprisingly, stronger (25% of patients)
advocates of deceptive placebo than physicians (7% of physicians) (Lynoe et al. 1993).
In a more recent study, US respondents reported significant acceptance of placebos with
some respondents supportive of deceptive placebo (Hull et al. 2013). It remains unclear
precisely how patients are conceptualizing placebos. In a study by Bishop and colleagues,
while many patients reported supporting placebo usage, particularly if there were per-
ceived beneficial outcomes, those who had negative views of placebo interpreted the
term “placebo” as synonymous with “ineffective” and requiring deception (Bishop et al.
2014). Similar studies will need to be conducted before generalizing results, but these data
should give us pause before categorically prohibiting placebo usage, deceptive or other-
wise, in the name of protecting patient autonomy.
In a paper advocating for “Paternalism and partial autonomy,” O’Neill argued that
deception associated with placebo does not infringe upon patient autonomy because it
does not infringe upon fundamental aspects of care (O’Neill 1984), and Barnehill has
argued that the “fundamental aspects” of care are the purpose of the treatment and that
the mechanism of action is ancillary (Barnhill 2011). Not unlike Barnehill, I have argued,
the deciding factor of what is ancillary information or not should be based on empirical
investigation of patient’s attitudes about placebo administration (Rommelfanger 2013b),
and at the very least determinations of what counts as fundamental should be strongly
informed by such data. A way forward is for medicine to strive for a scenario in which
patients are informed about the nature of placebo and its potential uses rather than purely
relying on patient intuitions (Blease et al. 2016). However, making decisions, that is, joint
care decisions, about whether deceptive or open-label placebo is the appropriate way for-
ward should be informed by patient values.
children and their parents were told that they would receive placebo as a dose extender.
Importantly, they were told that the placebo contained no active pharmaceutical ingredi-
ent. The reduced dose plus placebo was not only more effective than the 50% dose alone,
but also was just as effective as the full optimal dose, once again demonstrating that that
placebo can be used without deception to elicit positive therapeutic results. These find-
ings also suggest placebo need not replace existing treatments, but can also be used to
modify existing treatments—in this case to reduce the dose of medication that is poten-
tially addictive to children.
A common intuition is that once placebo is revealed, it can no longer have its effects.
Schafer and colleagues addressed this topic by first giving participants deceptive topical
cream placebo to elicit the placebo analgesia. Then participants were told explicitly that
the cream was simply petroleum jelly with blue food coloring and participants were even
shown how the placebo cream was prepared (Schafer et al. 2015). Participants continued
to experience placebo-induced analgesia even after being told about and visually seeing
the inert components of the cream, demonstrating that revealing that an intervention is a
placebo, after experiencing placebo effects during blinded administration, does not nec-
essarily impact the placebo’s future ability to elicit positive effects. Taken together, we see
several models of effective non-deceptive placebo therapy applications.
(Benedetti et al. 2011; Bingel et al. 2011). Conversely, describing potential adverse side
effects of interventions can elicit nocebo effects or a higher likelihood of experiencing
those negative side effects (Amanzio et al. 2009). Nocebo has become such a prominent
concern that researchers self-identified as the “placebo competence team” have argued
for a professional imperative to decrease negative expectations of interventions (Bingel &
Placebo Competence Team 2014). This suggests not just open, but conspicuous adminis-
tration of standard drugs may be helpful in augmenting their effects and possibly reduce
adverse effects of drugs where long-term use is detrimental to patient health. These results
also suggest a need for changes in the way informed consent is conceptualized and perhaps
even a need to inform of potential nocebo effects as a consequence of over-informing.
Placebos may become an attractive candidate for personalized therapy and based on pre-
vious studies about expectancy and conditioning. However, it would be imperative to
acknowledge that each patient may have a completely different history and experience
with medication, therapeutic encounters, and series of symbols for understanding their
therapeutic encounters.
To be clear, administration of placebos is not harmless. Deceptive placebos can be
harmful in the case of active or impure substances that are subthreshold doses of medi-
cation. Foddy argues that “placebos are always safe,” and “are sometimes the best treat-
ment” (Foddy 2009). If placebos do have specific physiological effects that could possibly
impact disease pathways then not only are they not inert, but also they could possibly
be contraindicated (Rommelfanger 2013b). If placebo is surreptitiously administered, it
may hamper the rest of the healthcare team’s efforts to address adverse events related to
placebo. Further, as others and I (Freedman 1990; La Vaque and Rossiter 2001; Foddy
2009; Rommelfanger 2013b) have argued, it would be unethical to prescribe placebos in
the place of established successful standards of care or if a better treatment became avail-
able. Placebos need not replace existing successful therapies; they may be able to augment
or supplement existing therapies (Ader et al. 2010; Sandler et al. 2010). Future placebo
research could be directed toward reducing side effects or mitigating addictive potential
of select therapies.
Perhaps one of the greatest potential gains in devoting research to placebo and its
mechanism is to break down silos and move toward perceiving health more holistically.
Current secretive placebo practices can largely be attributed to an entrenched belief in our
medical care system that the mind is somehow separate from the body. Bodily disorders
enjoy the privilege of being legitimate problems and in turn escape the stigma, blamewor-
thiness, and illness invalidation that accompany the stigma of a disorder that is consid-
ered to be psychological (Kendell 2001; Miresco & Kirmayer 2006). Placebo effects have
been similarly dismissed as a phenomenon of the mind, and therefore non-physiological
or nonspecific in origin and illegitimate (Lichtenberg et al. 2004). The emerging neurosci-
ence data suggest the placebo story is more multifaceted. Therefore, a renewed explora-
tion of placebo with these data in mind offers an opportunity to disrupt this division of
mind versus body and provides an opportunity to redress the resulting confusion.
29
References 229
It is also critical to note that the rise of biomedicine has been critiqued as creating an
impractical dichotomy between disease seen as objectively measurable, and illness seen
as the patient’s subjective experience (Kleinman 1988), and there certainly is a danger
of using neuroscience of placebo (Miller & Brody 2011) to reinforce this dichotomy.
Contemporary Western medicine is besotted with biomarkers and biological mechanisms
and some have argued to the detriment of the patient (Kleinman 1988); the patient’s sub-
jective experience of their improvement is confirmation of the measured biological out-
come and not converse.
However, until recently, the perceived improvement or placebo effects reported by
patients were interpreted in the popular imagination as purely subjective and without a
biomarker of their effects, were limited to subjective improvement. The emerging neuro-
physiological correlates to placebo should not be interpreted as neuroscience usurping the
import of social and psychological science, anthropology, or humanities in the conversa-
tion, but should be a reminder that conversations about human health must continue to
be conducted with humility with an openness toward cross-disciplinary discussion and
design. These data invite a broader conversation about the healthcare context, what we
mean by evidence-based medicine, and how we, as a society, balance the value of holistic
patient care.
In some ways, to keep abreast of the emerging data on placebo is extremely threatening
in a healthcare model where physicians are pressured to increase the number of patients
and feel pressures to shorten visits—devaluing the intricacies of the context of the thera-
peutic encounter—to meet productivity quotas in an assembly line style of healthcare
(Konrad et al. 2010). While these financial concerns are legitimate and pragmatic, there
may be a missed opportunity to utilize placebo therapy to minimize unnecessary expen-
ditures. The clear way forward is that placebos become a therapeutic target and a subject
of empirical research—rather than psychological contamination—and a fertile area of
investigation in its own right.
References
Adam, H., Obodaru, O., and Galinsky, A.D. (2015). Who you are is where you are: antecedents and
consequences of locating the self in the brain or the heart. Organizational Behavior and Human
Decision Processes, 128, 74–83.
Ader, R., Mercurio, M.G., Walton, J., et al. (2010). Conditioned pharmacotherapeutic effects: a
preliminary study. Psychosomatic Medicine, 72, 192–197.
Amanzio, M. and Benedetti, F. (1999). Neuropharmacological dissection of placebo
analgesia: expectation-activated opioid systems versus conditioning-activated specific subsystems.
Journal of Neuroscience, 19, 484–494.
Amanzio, M., Corazzini, L.L., Vase, L., and Benedetti, F. (2009). A systematic review of adverse events
in placebo groups of anti-migraine clinical trials. Pain, 146, 261–269.
American Medical Association (2007). Opinion 8.083: Placebo Use in Clinical Practice. American
Medical Association. Available from: http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/
medical-ethics/code-medical-ethics/opinion8083.page? [accessed April 25, 2016].
230
Barnhill, A. (2011). What it takes to defend deceptive placebo use. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal,
21, 219–250.
Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F. (2009). Principles of Biomedical Ethics. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Bendtsen, L., Mattsson, P., Zwart, J.A., and Lipton, R.B. (2003). Placebo response in clinical
randomized trials of analgesics in migraine. Cephalalgia, 23, 487–490.
Benedetti, F. (2006). Placebo analgesia. Neurological Sciences, 27(Suppl. 2), S100–S102.
Benedetti, F. (2014). Placebo effects: from the neurobiological paradigm to translational implications.
Neuron, 84, 623–637.
Benedetti, F., Pollo, A., Lopiano, L., et al. (2003). Conscious expectation and unconscious conditioning
in analgesic, motor, and hormonal placebo/nocebo responses. Journal of Neuroscience, 23, 4315–423.
Benedetti, F., Colloca, L., Torre, E., et al. (2004). Placebo-responsive Parkinson patients show decreased
activity in single neurons of subthalamic nucleus. Nature Neuroscience, 7, 587–588.
Benedetti, F., Carlino, E., and Pollo, A. (2011). Hidden administration of drugs. Clinical Pharmacology &
Therapeutics, 90, 651–661.
Bingel, U. and Placebo Competence Team (2014). Avoiding nocebo effects to optimize treatment
outcome. JAMA, 312, 693–694.
Bingel, U., Wanigasekera, V., Wiech, K., et al. (2011). The effect of treatment expectation on drug
efficacy: imaging the analgesic benefit of the opioid remifentanil. Science Translational Medicine, 3,
70ra14.
Bishop, F.L., Aizlewood, L., and Adams, A.E. (2014). When and why placebo-prescribing is acceptable
and unacceptable: a focus group study of patients’ views. PLoS One, 9, e101822.
Blease, C. (2012). The principle of parity: the “placebo effect” and physician communication. Journal of
Medical Ethics, 38, 199–203.
Blease, C., Colloca, L., and Kaptchuk, T.J. (2016). Are open-label placebos ethical? informed consent
and ethical equivocations. Bioethics, 30(6), 407–414.
Bostick, N.A., Sade, R., Levine, M.A., and Stewart, D.M., Jr. (2008). Placebo use in clinical
practice: report of the American Medical Association Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs.
Journal of Clinical Ethics, 19, 58–61.
Brody, H. (1982). The lie that heals: the ethics of giving placebos. Annals of Internal Medicine, 97,
112–118.
Brody, H., Colloca, L., and Miller, F.G. (2012). The placebo phenomenon: implications for the ethics of
shared decision-making. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 27, 739–742.
Burton, R. (1621). The Anatomy of Melancholy. [Reprinted in 2001 by The New York Review of Books,
New York.]
Colloca, L. and Benedetti, F. (2005). Placebos and painkillers: is mind as real as matter? Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 6, 545–552.
Colloca, L. and Benedetti, F. (2006). How prior experience shapes placebo analgesia. Pain, 124, 126–133.
Colloca, L. and Benedetti, F. (2009). Placebo analgesia induced by social observational learning. Pain,
144, 28–34.
Colloca, L. and Miller, F.G. (2011a). Harnessing the placebo effect: the need for translational research.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 366, 1922–1930.
Colloca, L. and Miller, F.G. (2011b). How placebo responses are formed: a learning perspective.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 366, 1859–1869.
De La Fuente-Fernandez, R., Ruth, T.J., Sossi, V., et al. (2001). Expectation and dopamine
release: mechanism of the placebo effect in Parkinson’s disease. Science, 293, 1164–1166.
231
References 231
De La Fuente-Fernandez, R., Schulzer, M., and Stoessl, A.J. (2004). Placebo mechanisms and reward
circuitry: clues from Parkinson’s disease. Biological Psychiatry, 56, 67–71.
Di Blasi, Z., Harkness, E., Ernst, E., Georgiou, A., and Kleijnen, J. (2001). Influence of context effects
on health outcomes: a systematic review. The Lancet, 357, 757–762.
Diederich, N.J. and Goetz, C.G. (2008). The placebo treatments in neurosciences: new insights from
clinical and neuroimaging studies. Neurology, 71, 677–684.
Dworkin, R.H., Katz, J., and Gitlin, M.J. (2005). Placebo response in clinical trials of depression and its
implications for research on chronic neuropathic pain. Neurology, 65, S7–19.
Enck, P., Benedetti, F., and Schedlowski, M. (2008). New insights into the placebo and nocebo
responses. Neuron, 59, 195–206.
Espay, A.J., Norris, M.M., Eliassen, J.C., et al. (2015). Placebo effect of medication cost in Parkinson
disease: a randomized double-blind study. Neurology, 84, 794–802.
Evers, K. (2007). Towards a philosophy for neuroethics. An informed materialist view of the brain
might help to develop theoretical frameworks for applied neuroethics. EMBO Reports, 8(Spec No.),
S48–51.
Fassler, M., Gnadinger, M., Rosemann, T., and Biller-Andorno, N. (2011). Placebo interventions in
practice: a questionnaire survey on the attitudes of patients and physicians. British Journal of General
Practice, 61, 101–107.
Fassler, M., Meissner, K., Schneider, A., and Linde, K. (2010). Frequency and circumstances of placebo
use in clinical practice –a systematic review of empirical studies. BMC Medicine, 8, 15.
Fent, R., Rosemann, T., Fassler, M., Senn, O., and Huber, C.A. (2011). The use of pure and impure
placebo interventions in primary care—a qualitative approach. BMC Family Practice, 12, 11.
Finniss, D.G., Kaptchuk, T.J., Miller, F., and Benedetti, F. (2010). Biological, clinical, and ethical
advances of placebo effects. The Lancet, 375, 686–695.
Fleurence, R., Selby, J.V., Odom-Walker, K., et al. (2013). How the Patient-Centered Outcomes
Research Institute is engaging patients and others in shaping its research agenda. Health Affairs
(Millwood), 32, 393–400.
Foddy, B. (2009). A duty to deceive: placebos in clinical practice. American Journal of Bioethics, 9, 4–12.
Ford, P.L. (1898). The Writings of Thomas Jefferson. New York: Putnam.
Freedman, B. (1990). Placebo-controlled trials and the logic of clinical purpose. IRB, 12, 1–6.
Frisaldi, E., Carlino, E., Lanotte, M., Lopiano, L., and Benedetti, F. (2014). Characterization of the
thalamic-subthalamic circuit involved in the placebo response through single-neuron recording in
Parkinson patients. Cortex, 60, 3–9.
Goebel, M.U., Trebst, A. E., Steiner, J., et al. (2002). Behavioral conditioning of immunosuppression is
possible in humans. FASEB Journal, 16, 1869–1873.
Goebel, M.U., Hubell, D., Kou, W., et al. (2005). Behavioral conditioning with interferon beta-1a in
humans. Physiology & Behavior, 84, 807–814.
Goetz, C.G., Wuu, J., McDermott, M.P., et al. (2008). Placebo response in Parkinson’s
disease: comparisons among 11 trials covering medical and surgical interventions. Movement
Disorders, 23, 690–699.
Guo, J.Y., Wang, J.Y., and Luo, F. (2010). Dissection of placebo analgesia in mice: the conditions for
activation of opioid and non-opioid systems. Journal of Psychopharmacology, 24, 1561–1567.
Guo, J.Y., Yuan, X.Y., Sui, F., et al. (2011). Placebo analgesia affects the behavioral despair tests and
hormonal secretions in mice. Psychopharmacology (Berlin), 217, 83–90.
Hall, K.T., Lembo, A.J., Kirsch, I., et al. (2012). Catechol-O-methyltransferase val158met
polymorphism predicts placebo effect in irritable bowel syndrome. PLoS One, 7, e48135.
23
Hall, K.T., Loscalzo, J., and Kaptchuk, T.J. (2015). Genetics and the placebo effect: the placebome.
Trends in Molecular Medicine, 21, 285–294.
Howick, J., Bishop, F.L., Heneghan, C., et al. (2013). Placebo use in the United Kingdom: results from a
national survey of primary care practitioners. PLoS One, 8, e58247.
Hrobjartsson, A. and Norup, M. (2003). The use of placebo interventions in medical practice –a
national questionnaire survey of Danish clinicians. Evaluation & the Health Professions, 26, 153–165.
Hull, S.C., Colloca, L., Avins, A., et al. (2013). Patients’ attitudes about the use of placebo
treatments: telephone survey. BMJ, 347, f3757.
Humphrey, N. (2002). Great Expectations: The Evolutionary Psychology of Faith Healing and Placebo
Effect. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kam-Hansen, S., Jakubowski, M., Kelley, J.M., et al. (2014). Altered placebo and drug labeling changes
the outcome of episodic migraine attacks. Science Translational Medicine, 6, 218ra5.
Kaptchuk, T.J., Kelley, J.M., Conboy, L.A., et al. (2008). Components of placebo effect: randomised
controlled trial in patients with irritable bowel syndrome. BMJ, 336, 999–1003.
Kaptchuk, T.J., Friedlander, E., Kelley, J.M., et al. (2010). Placebos without deception: a randomized
controlled trial in irritable bowel syndrome. PLoS One, 5, e15591.
Kendell, R.E. (2001). The distinction between mental and physical illness. British Journal of Psychiatry,
178, 490–493.
Kermen, R., Hickner, J., Brody, H., and Hasham, I. (2010). Family physicians believe the placebo effect
is therapeutic but often use real drugs as placebos. Family Medicine, 42, 636–642.
Kirsch, I. (2004). Conditioning, expectancy, and the placebo effect: comment on Stewart-Williams and
Podd (2004). Psychological Bulletin, 130, 341–343.
Kleinman, A. (1988). The Illness Narratives: Suffering, healing and the Human Condition.
New York: Basic Books.
Konrad, T.R., Link, C.L., Shackelton, R.J., et al. (2010). It’s about time: physicians’ perceptions of time
constraints in primary care medical practice in three national healthcare systems. Medical Care, 48,
95–100.
La Vaque, T.J. and Rossiter, T. (2001). The ethical use of placebo controls in clinical research: the
Declaration of Helsinki. Applied Psychophysiology and Biofeedback, 26, 23–37.
Lee, I.S., Lee, B., Park, H.J., et al. (2015). A new animal model of placebo analgesia: involvement of the
dopaminergic system in reward learning. Scientific Reports, 5, 17140.
Lichtenberg, P., Heresco-Levy, U., and Nitzan, U. (2004). The ethics of the placebo in clinical practice.
Journal of Medical Ethics, 30, 551–554.
Lidstone, S.C., Schulzer, M., Dinelle, K., et al. (2010). Effects of expectation on placebo-induced
dopamine release in Parkinson disease. Archives of General Psychiatry, 67, 857–865.
Lou, J.S., Dimitrova, D.M., Hammerschlag, R., et al. (2013). Effect of expectancy and personality on
cortical excitability in Parkinson’s disease. Movement Disorders, 28, 1257–1262.
Lui, F., Colloca, L., Duzzi, D., et al. (2010). Neural bases of conditioned placebo analgesia. Pain, 151,
816–824.
Luparello, T., Lyons, H.A., Bleecker, E.R., and Mcfadden, E.R., Jr. (1968). Influences of suggestion on
airway reactivity in asthmatic subjects. Psychosomatic Medicine, 30, 819–825.
Luparello, T.J., Leist, N., Lourie, C.H., and Sweet, P. (1970). The interaction of psychologic stimuli
and pharmacologic agents on airway reactivity in asthmatic subjects. Psychosomatic Medicine, 32,
509–513.
Lynoe, N., Mattsson, B., and Sandlund, M. (1993). The attitudes of patients and physicians towards
placebo treatment –a comparative study. Social Science & Medicine, 36, 767–774.
23
References 233
Mayberg, H.S., Silva, J.A., Brannan, S.K., et al. (2002). The functional neuroanatomy of the placebo
effect. American Journal of Psychiatry, 159, 728–737.
Meissner, K., Hofner, L., Fassler, M., and Linde, K. (2012). Widespread use of pure and impure placebo
interventions by GPs in Germany. Family Practice, 29, 79–85.
Mercado, R., Constantoyannis, C., Mandat, T., et al. (2006). Expectation and the placebo effect in
Parkinson’s disease patients with subthalamic nucleus deep brain stimulation. Movement Disorders,
21, 1457–1461.
Miller, F.G. and Brody, H. (2011). Understanding and harnessing placebo effects: clearing away the
underbrush. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 36, 69–78.
Miller, F.G. and Kaptchuk, T.J. (2008). The power of context: reconceptualizing the placebo effect.
Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 101, 222–225.
Miller, F.G., Colloca, L., and Kaptchuk, T.J. (2009). The placebo effect: illness and interpersonal healing.
Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 52, 518–539.
Miresco, M.J. and Kirmayer, L.J. (2006). The persistence of mind-brain dualism in psychiatric
reasoning about clinical scenarios. American Journal of Psychiatry, 163, 913–918.
Moerman, D.E. (2002). The meaning response and the ethics of avoiding placebos. Evaluation & the
Health Professions, 25, 399–409.
Moerman, D.E. and Jonas, W.B. (2002). Deconstructing the placebo effect and finding the meaning
response. Annals of Internal Medicine, 136, 471–476.
Montgomery, G.H. and Kirsch, I. (1997). Classical conditioning and the placebo effect. Pain, 72,
107–113.
Nolan, T.A., Price, D.D., Caudle, R.M., Murphy, N.P., and Neubert, J.K. (2012). Placebo-induced
analgesia in an operant pain model in rats. Pain, 153, 2009–2016.
O’Neill, O. (1984). Paternalism and partial autonomy. Journal of Medical Ethics, 10, 173–178.
Park, L.C. and Covi, L. (1965). Nonblind placebo trial: an exploration of neurotic patients’ responses
to placebo when its inert content is disclosed. Archives of General Psychiatry, 12, 36–45.
Pavlov, I.P. (1927). Conditioned Reflexes: An Investigation of the Physiological Activity of the Cerebral
Cortex. London: Oxford University Press.
Petrovic, P., Dietrich, T., Fransson, P., et al. (2005). Placebo in emotional processing –induced
expectations of anxiety relief activate a generalized modulatory network. Neuron, 46, 957–969.
Pollo, A., Amanzio, M., Arslanian, A., et al. (2001). Response expectancies in placebo analgesia and
their clinical relevance. Pain, 93, 77–84.
Pugh, J. (2015). Ravines and sugar pills: defending deceptive placebo use. Journal of Medicine and
Philosophy, 40, 83–101.
Pugh, J., Kahane, G., Maslen, H., and Savulescu, J. (2016). Lay attitudes toward deception in
medicine: theoretical considerations and empirical evidence. AJOB Empirical Bioethics, 7, 31–38.
Purtilo, R. (1993). Ethical Dimensions in the Health Care Professions. Philadelphia, PA: WB Saunders.
Racine, E., Waldman, S., Rosenberg, J., and Illes, J. (2010). Contemporary neuroscience in the media.
Social Science & Medicine, 71, 725–733.
Rommelfanger, K.S. (2013a). Attitudes on mind over matter: physician views on the role of placebo in
psychogenic disorders. American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience, 4, 9–15.
Rommelfanger, K.S. (2013b). Opinion: a role for placebo therapy in psychogenic movement disorders.
Nature Reviews Neurology, 9, 351–356.
Rose, J.P., Geers, A.L., Rasinski, H.M., and Fowler, S.L. (2012). Choice and placebo expectation effects
in the context of pain analgesia. Journal of Behavioral Medicine, 35, 462–470.
Rosenberg, C.E. (2002). The tyranny of diagnosis: specific entities and individual experience. Milbank
Quarterly, 80, 237–260.
234
Roskies, A.L. (2007). Neuroethics beyond genethics. Despite the overlap between the ethics of
neuroscience and genetics, there are important areas where the two diverge. EMBO Reports, 8(Spec
No.), S52–56.
Sandler, A.D., Glesne, C.E., and Bodfish, J.W. (2010). Conditioned placebo dose reduction: a new
treatment in attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder? Journal of Developmental and Behavioral
Pediatrics, 31, 369–375.
Schafer, S.M., Colloca, L., and Wager, T.D. (2015). Conditioned placebo analgesia persists when
subjects know they are receiving a placebo. Journal of Pain, 16, 412–420.
Schultz, W. (2006). Behavioral theories and the neurophysiology of reward. Annual Review of
Psychology, 57, 87–115.
Scott, D.J., Stohler, C.S., Egnatuk, C.M., et al. (2008). Placebo and nocebo effects are defined by
opposite opioid and dopaminergic responses. Archives of General Psychiatry, 65, 220–231.
Shanks, D.R. (2010). Learning: from association to cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 61,
273–301.
Sherman, R. and Hickner, J. (2008). Academic physicians use placebos in clinical practice and believe
in the mind-body connection. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 23, 7–10.
Spiro, H.M. (1986). Doctors, Patients, and Placebos. London: Yale University Press.
Stewart-Williams, S. and Podd, J. (2004). The placebo effect: dissolving the expectancy versus
conditioning debate. Psychological Bulletin, 130, 324–340.
Tilburt, J.C., Emanuel, E.J., Kaptchuk, T.J., Curlin, F.A., and Miller, F.G. (2008). Prescribing
“placebo treatments”: results of national survey of US internists and rheumatologists. BMJ,
337, a1938.
Tuttle, A.H., Tohyama, S., Ramsay, T., et al. (2015). Increasing placebo responses over time in
U.S. clinical trials of neuropathic pain. Pain, 156, 2616–2626.
Van Laarhoven, A.I., Vogelaar, M.L., Wilder-Smith, O.H., et al. (2011). Induction of nocebo and
placebo effects on itch and pain by verbal suggestions. Pain, 152, 1486–1494.
Wager, T.D., Scott, D.J., and Zubieta, J.K. (2007). Placebo effects on human mu-opioid activity
during pain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 104,
11056–11061.
Yang, Q. and Miller, G. (2015). East-West differences in perception of brain death. Review of history,
current understandings, and directions for future research. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, 12,
211–225.
Zhang, R.R., Zhang, W.C., Wang, J.Y., and Guo, J.Y. (2013). The opioid placebo analgesia is mediated
exclusively through mu-opioid receptor in rat. International Journal of Neuropsychopharmacology,
16, 849–856.
Zubieta, J.K., Bueller, J.A., Jackson, L.R., et al. (2005). Placebo effects mediated by endogenous opioid
activity on mu-opioid receptors. Journal of Neuroscience, 25, 7754–7762.
235
Chapter 13
Introduction
Until the 1970s, rather crude forms of psychosurgery had been used in hundreds of
thousands of mentally ill patients (Valenstein 1986; Diering & Bell 1991; Chodakiewitz
et al. 2015). The abuse of psychosurgery was brought to the public consciousness by Ken
Kesey’s famous novel One Flew Over the Cuckoo’s Nest (Kesey 1964). Due to public criti-
cism and, coincidentally, the development of antipsychotic drugs, psychosurgery was
nearly completely abandoned and forbidden in many countries. Since 1999, after a nearly
30-year hiatus, there is a renaissance of psychiatric neurosurgery in a much more refined
and safer form. Today it is developing quickly as an experimental therapy for medically
refractory psychiatric disorders (Lévèque et al. 2013; Luigjes et al. 2013; Lévèque 2014;
Sun & De Salles 2015) that are not caused directly by identified brain anatomical or func-
tional pathologies, such as brain tumors or epileptogenic tissue, and for which biologi-
cal underpinnings are unknown. Nonetheless, psychiatric neurosurgery is based on the
assumption that certain dysfunctional brain areas or structures play a crucial role in psy-
chiatric disorders, and that lesioning or deactivating them can alleviate psychiatric symp-
toms. For example, the cortico-striato-thalamo-cortical loop is strongly implicated in the
pathogenesis of obsessive–compulsive disorder (OCD). Decreased frontal-striatal control
of limbic structures such as the amygdala might account for the inadequate fear response
seen in OCD patients with fear of contamination (Na et al. 2015). Thus, knowledge of
the interconnected neural circuits underlies hypothesis-driven rationales for choosing
particular targets of neurosurgical intervention (Na et al. 2015).
Many researchers and clinicians expect that modern psychiatric neurosurgery has the
potential to become a safe and effective treatment option for severe, therapy-refractory
psychiatric disorders. According to a recent survey, about 90% of functional neurosur-
geons feel optimistic about the future of psychiatric neurosurgery (Lipsman et al. 2011;
Mendelsohn et al. 2013).
Currently, such psychiatric neurosurgical procedures include deep brain stimulation
(DBS) and ablative neurosurgical procedures. Because DBS is an established therapy for
treatment-refractory Parkinson’s disease, essential tremor and dystonia, and because it is
considered reversible, its experimental use for treating psychiatric disorders was seen as
236
◆ How should researchers and physicians deal with conflicts of interest, for example,
conflicts between research interests and benefits to patients?
◆ Should psychiatric neurosurgery be applied in forensic contexts, for example, to reduce
the risk of re-offense of pedophilic child offenders or violent psychopaths?
Whereas medical ethicists have discussed such questions intensively for DBS, they have
neglected ablative psychiatric neurosurgery. This blind spot is astonishing. Rather than
ignoring the widespread practice of ablative psychiatric neurosurgery, a comprehensive
and differentiated ethical analysis of the pros and cons of the distinct approaches is nec-
essary, which is based on rational evidence, not on fear or hopes or outdated prejudices.
In response, in the rest of this chapter, I provide a continuing overview of the different
techniques of psychiatric neurosurgery and explain their various underlying paradigms
and follow with an overview and comparison of the efficacy and the adverse effects of
the different techniques. Next, I summarize the ethical debate about DBS, and discuss
the neglect in ethics with regard to ablative psychiatric neurosurgery, and conclude with
some preliminary recommendations for the future.
When subcortical motor areas of the basal ganglia and the thalamus are targeted for
treating movement disorders, the chief benefit of DBS over ablative procedures is that
DBS has a lower risk of side effects on speech, swallowing, cognition, and balance (Pepper
et al. 2015). However, the rationale for DBS is less compelling when non-motor areas
are targeted such as for treating psychiatric disorders (Pepper et al. 2015). There is not
much more in favor of DBS “other than it is perceived as nonablative and assumed to be
reversible and more forgiving than lesions, and therefore more acceptable” (Pepper et al.
2015, p.1029). However, many experts doubt that DBS is always reversible and, thus, the
case for DBS is attenuated. In an expert survey conducted by Markus Christen and me,
results showed that about 40% of the participating DBS experts (strongly) disagree with
the statement that DBS is a completely reversible procedure, whereas 43% (strongly) agree
(Christen et al. 2014). The reversibility is questionable because, first, the insertion of the
electrodes might cause irreversible lesions, even with the consequence of death or of per-
manent neurological damage; and second, because the brain will adapt to the stimulation.
Therefore, arguably, the main advantage of DBS is not its reversibility after all, but its
adjustability, that is, that the stimulation parameters like voltage, pulse width, and fre-
quency can be fine-tuned individually to optimize the effect on the target symptoms with
respect to the disease progression over time. Consequently, DBS requires extensive follow-
up for programming and adjusting stimulation parameters, which can only be done by
specialists. Furthermore, the implantable pulse generator (including the battery) has to
be replaced every 3–5 years requiring regular surgeries with full anesthesia. The cost of
DBS device implantation is estimated at $50,000–$120,000 USD. Each battery replace-
ment costs between $10,000 and $25,000 USD (Chodakiewitz et al. 2015). Therefore, the
treatment is both time-consuming and, also in the long-run, very expensive.
the paradigm used in modern functional radiosurgery might be more appropriately cat-
egorized as neuromodulatory rather than ablative (Régis 2013).
Efficacy
Reliable estimation and comparison of the efficacy of the different psychiatric neurosur-
gery procedures remains elusive due to a number of reasons such as publication bias,
methodological heterogeneity, and use of weak methodology of the studies (Müller
S. et al. 2015a).
Publication bias
Due to a strong publication bias in the DBS literature (Schläpfer & Fins 2010), the efficacy
of psychiatric neurosurgery procedures is certainly overestimated. Most reviews consider
only cases published in Anglophone medical journals, and cases with an unfavorable out-
come are often not reported (Schläpfer & Fins 2010). The presumed efficacy of psychiat-
ric neurosurgery procedures is thus very likely an overestimation. The publication bias
might be the explanation for another astonishing phenomenon. A recent review, compris-
ing 22 papers with data from 188 patients and 6 stimulation targets reported responder
rates ranging from 29% to 92%, thus suggesting that DBS is efficacious in ameliorating
treatment-refractory major depression (Morishita et al. 2014). In contrast, however, these
positive results could not be verified in the first two studies that fulfilled scientific quality
241
Efficacy 241
criteria such as randomization, double blinding, and placebo control. Indeed, two ran-
domized, controlled, prospective multicenter studies were discontinued because of inef-
ficacy. These studies had two different targets: (1) the ventral capsule/ventral striatum
(Dougherty et al. 2015) and (2) the subgenual cingulate cortex. Only a short report exists
about DBS in the subgenual cingulate cortex (Cavuoto 2013).
As concerns ablative procedures, there is probably an even stronger publication bias.
Most data on ablative neurosurgery are not published at all, since the procedure is pre-
dominantly applied in clinical practice and not in research. Public websites of private clin-
ics in Asia reveal that ablative neurosurgery for psychiatric disorders is offered there as a
part of clinical routine rather than clinical trials. Recently, Sun and De Salles published a
book with more than 100 previously unpublished ablative psychiatric neurosurgery case
reports from around the world (Sun & De Salles 2015). However, most data in this book
do not contain sufficient detail for consideration in systematic reviews.
Publication bias in psychiatric neurosurgery literature is a fundamental problem that
compromises the systematic evaluation and comparison of the different procedures
(Müller S. et al. 2015a). It also undermines the ethical evaluation, which critically depends
on adequate and objective information of evidence-based risk:benefit ratios.
Methodological weaknesses
Studies published thus far in English-language journals have very small patient num-
bers, most with fewer than ten patients, and so lack of statistical power is thus a major
concern in these studies. Furthermore, most studies are neither placebo-controlled nor
double-blinded, and notably, none of the psychiatric neurosurgery approaches is strictly
evidence-based (Pepper et al. 2015). Observer bias in reporting results also presents
a methodological concern as the evaluation of treatment outcomes have not yet been
24
conducted by independent parties who were not involved in patient selection, surgery, or
follow-up (Pepper et al. 2015).
Despite the positive results of DBS studies in open-label trials, the above-mentioned
failure of two high-quality studies may indicate the typical overestimation of efficacy that
is associated with open-label trials with missing placebo control, and biases due to lack of
blinding and randomization (Morishita et al. 2014). The failure of these studies, however,
does not prove that DBS is in general ineffective for treatment-refractory major depres-
sion. The study of Dougherty and colleagues (Dougherty et al. 2015), for example, had
severe deficits such as a short treatment period (4 months) and unsatisfactory adjustment
of stimulation parameters (Schläpfer 2015). A current study is investigating the slMFB
(Schläpfer et al. 2013) as a DBS target for major depression in a randomized, controlled,
prospective study; the outcome of this study may shed light on the efficacy of DBS for
major depression. For Gamma Knife® radiosurgery, several very small double-blind, ran-
domized controlled trials have been performed thus far (Lévèque et al. 2013).
Rigorous evidence-based comparison of the efficacy of the different psychiatric neu-
rosurgery approaches is not yet possible due to methodological hurdles and publication
bias. Despite these limitations, however, attempts to review efficacy of procedures have
utilized pertinent data, reviews, and a book (Sun & De Salles 2015).
Efficacy 243
For anorexia nervosa, we have reviewed 6 papers comprising 18 patients and three tar-
gets (NAcc, SCC, and VC/VS) (Müller S. et al. 2015b). Remission in terms of normalized
body mass index occurred in 61% of patients, and psychiatric comorbidities improved in
88.9% of the patients as well. However, Sun and colleagues have recently published less
favorable results in which only 20% (3/15) of their patients treated with NAcc DBS showed
improvements in symptoms. The other 80% underwent anterior capsulotomy, which
improved eating behavior and psychiatric symptoms in all patients (Sun et al. 2015).
Another interesting result is the strong reduction of anxiety and depression after
MRgFUS. The mean Hamilton Rating Scale for Depression score improved about 61% at
6 months after treatment, and the mean Hamilton Rating Scale for Anxiety score about
69%. Anxiety and depression improved significantly within 1 week after MRgFUS, and
this improvement was maintained throughout the 6 months (Na et al. 2015).
Comparative efficacy
Pepper and colleagues found greater response rates for OCD patients who underwent
anterior capsulotomy (micro-or radiosurgery) than for patients treated with DBS (62%
versus 52% (response = improvement on Y-BOCS score ≥ 35%) (Pepper et al. 2015).
Additionally, patients who underwent anterior capsulotomy were more likely to go into
remission than DBS patients. This difference in efficacy cannot be explained by group
differences in patient age, symptom severity, or disease duration (Pepper et al. 2015).
A possible explanation is the differential surgical experience. Surgeons have greater expe-
rience with ablation and anterior capsulotomy is more standardized, whereas there is still
a learning curve in the practice of DBS for OCD (Pepper et al. 2015).
Adverse effects
Deep brain stimulation
Adverse effects of DBS are usually differentiated into surgery-related, device-related, and
stimulation-related effects. Because the implantable pulse generator has to be replaced
every 3–5 years, risks of surgery and infection are not limited to the implantation of
the DBS system. Furthermore, infections near the implanted device can always occur.
Furthermore, DBS devices are sensitive to high-energy electrical fields, which can switch
them off or even cause a reset of the device (Na et al. 2015). The adverse effects depend
less on the indication for the intervention; therefore, I recapitulate them in the following
collectively.
Serious adverse events during or shortly after surgery occurred in a few reported cases.
These include intracerebral hemorrhages, which in one case, resulted in a temporary
hemiparesis (Kohl et al. 2014; Morishita et al. 2014; Pepper et al. 2015); intraoperative
seizure; intraoperative panic attack; and cardiac air embolus (Lipsman et al. 2013a).
In several cases, wound infections or inflammation occurred (Kohl et al. 2014; Pepper
et al. 2015).
Several device-related adverse effects have been reported, namely breaks of electrodes,
stimulating leads or extension wires requiring replacement (Kohl et al. 2014; Pepper et al.
2015). Further device-related side effects are dysesthesia in the subclavicular region, feel-
ings of the leads or stimulators (Kohl et al. 2014), or allergy to the pulse generator (Pepper
et al. 2015).
Some patients suffered temporarily from vertigo, olfactory hallucinations, insomnia,
headache, micturition problems, weight loss or gain, long-lasting fatigue, and visual dis-
turbances (Kohl et al. 2014; Pepper et al. 2015). Patients suffering from anorexia nervosa
245
had a particularly high rate of severe complications, namely an epileptic seizure during
electrode programming, further weight loss, pancreatitis, hypophosphataemia, hypo-
kalaemia, a refeeding delirium, cardiological disturbances, and worsening of mood
(Lipsman et al. 2013a).
Several patients had cognitive problems following DBS, particularly forgetfulness and
word-finding difficulties (Pepper et al. 2015). Many patients suffered from stimulation-
induced adverse effects, particularly from depression, anxiety, worsening of OCD, sui-
cidality, panic attacks, fatigue, hypomania, increased libido, and problems at home. In
some cases, these adverse effects were caused either by a change of stimulation parameters
or by battery depletion, and were reversible by respective adjustments (Kohl et al. 2014;
Morishita et al. 2014). Some DBS patients reported feelings of self-estrangement (Gilbert
2013a). A great problem after DBS is the high number of suicides and suicide attempts
(Kohl et al. 2014; Morishita et al. 2014; Pepper et al. 2015).
Adjustability Very high Low (second interven- Low (second inter- Low (second
tion to create another vention to create intervention to
lesion or enlarge the another lesion) to create another
lesion) medium (through lesion) to
a step-by-step medium (through
approach) a step-by-step
approach)
Multiple targets No Yes Yes Not yet done
in a single
session
Reversibility High (exception: No No No
permanent adverse
effects due to
lesions, infections,
bleeding)
Invasive Yes Yes No No
craniotomy
Onset of action Hours to 12 months Days or weeks 6–12 months 1–6 months
Appropriateness No Patients who would Patients: Patients:
for patients with not comply with ◆ who would ◆ who would
special needs long-term follow-up not comply not com-
with long-term ply with
follow-up long-term
◆ for whom follow-up
open surgery is ◆ for whom
precluded open surgery
◆ with higher is precluded
risks of ◆ with higher
anesthesia risks of
◆ with higher anesthesia
infection risks
◆ who must
receive anti-
coagulation
therapy
Time and effort High (single surgery; Medium (single sur- Low (ambulatory Medium (single
of the procedure several days in gery; several days in treatment, single surgery; several
hospital; parameter hospital) session) days in hospital)
adaption)
Long-term Frequent consulta- Not necessary Not necessary Not necessary
treatment tion of specialists
required (parameter
adjustment, regular
device exchange)
(continued)
248
Table 13.1
Table 13.1 Continued
Ethical discussion
Ethical, legal, and social context
The clinical, ethical, legal, and societal issues of psychiatric neurosurgery are strongly
intermingled. The desperate situation of many people with mental disorders, who suf-
fer not only from their disabling condition, but also from stigma, social exclusion, com-
pulsory treatment, and frequently from incarceration, needs to be taken into account.
Thus, development and use of psychiatric neurosurgery has to be considered in a broader
social context, which will undoubtedly impact the development and acceptance of these
new treatment options. Moreover, the context for evaluating neurosurgical developments
also comprises the societal burden of chronic mentally ill patients, the trend of dehospi-
talization, as well as financial and research interests of device producers, hospitals, and
physicians.
Framed within the legal context, national legislation and international law limit the
field of psychiatric neurosurgery. In some countries, for example, ablative neurosurgery
is forbidden. Important legal issues include the admissibility of offering ablative psychi-
atric neurosurgery in general; the admissibility of offering psychiatric neurosurgery to
criminal offenders in jail or forensic psychiatry, particularly, if combined with the offer
of reducing the duration of imprisonment; and the admissibility of treating minors with
psychiatric neurosurgery, particularly, if performed in children with cognitive disabilities
or against the will of a minor (e.g., in cases of anorexia nervosa).
Media reports play a crucial role for the public acceptance or refusal of psychiatric
neurosurgery. The media also influences legal theorists and politicians who are tasked
250
with deciding the admissibility of these procedures. The media in turn are influenced by
success stories from researchers and clinicians, and by diverging statements from bio-
ethicists. Social media disseminate information and opinions rapidly to the traditional
media in addition to the general public. For example, a critical article about psychosur-
gery in China in The Wall Street Journal was published in November 2007. It reported that
thousands of patients had been treated with ablative brain surgery, and in many cases,
in an unethical way. The article reports that this was not done with political intention to
suppress dissenters, but mainly because of profit-interests of physicians. In April 2008,
the Ministry of Health of China issued a strict regulation on neurosurgery for psychiat-
ric disorders that forbids neurosurgical treatments of schizophrenia (Wu et al. 2012). By
contrast, DBS seems to be portrayed over-optimistically in the media, and ethical issues
are largely ignored (Racine et al. 2007; Gilbert & Ovadia 2011). Many DBS researchers are
very aware of the importance of the image of DBS in the media where negative reports on
psychiatric neurosurgery pose a genuine threat to this field.
for two reasons: first, because this debate does not adequately capture the clinical reality
and, second, because it might have negative effects on the patients. If legal theorists take
metaphysical theories about personal identity changes through DBS seriously, then psy-
chiatric advance directives of DBS patients would become invalid. I raised a plea for using
more realistic descriptions in order to capture the different kinds of mental or behavioral
changes following neurosurgery instead of speculating about the metaphysical concept of
personal identity (Müller S. 2014, pp.106–129).
relevant aspects cannot be established (Müller S. et al. 2015a). The authors of a recent
comparative review of DBS and anterior capsulotomy conclude “that the current pop-
ularity of DBS over ablative surgery for OCD is not due to clinical superiority over AC
[anterior capsulotomy], but rather that clinicians and patients find DBS to be more
acceptable” (Pepper et al. 2015, p.1035).
3. The much higher long-term costs of DBS, particularly for long-term treatment, exclude
this option for the majority of patients worldwide.
4. Ablative neurosurgery and Gamma Knife® radiosurgery might avoid several difficult
ethical issues of DBS, which are raised because DBS allows for fine-tuning the mood
and certain personality aspects of patients. If such a fine-tuning is not possible, severe
ethical issues referring to the authority over the stimulation parameters, and to con-
flicts between the patients’ will and the physicians’ attitudes with regard to parameters
that might cause hypomania or addiction are not raised. In particular, Gamma Knife®
radiosurgery does not raise the challenging ethical problem of “inauthenticity” and
the so-called burden of normality syndrome (Wilson et al. 2001; Gilbert 2012), just
because the onset of its effect is delayed for several months (Lindquist et al. 1991; De
Salles and Gorgulho 2015).
Reversibility
The reversibility that has been proclaimed for DBS is presumably the most important
argument that has prevented it from general moral condemnation. Only a few com-
mentators consider psychiatric DBS as a continuation of the discredited historical psy-
chosurgery, whereas the majority highlight the important differences between previous
psychosurgery and DBS with regard to reversibility, invasiveness, adjustability, and ethical
orientation (Müller S. 2014, p.5). The reversibility is the main argument in many state-
ments. For example, in Germany, the working team of ethical review committees has writ-
ten in its recommendation for the appraisal of clinical studies that DBS research projects
are only ethically justifiable if the reversibility of the intervention is guaranteed (Raspe
et al. 2012). The German Association for Psychiatry, Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics
(DGPPN) states in its recently published guidelines for the treatment of OCD that neu-
rolesional or ablative methods have a very controversial history, and should be considered
very critically because of their irreversibility. The authors recommend not using capsu-
lotomy by thermocoagulation or gamma radiation because the risk:benefit ratios were
too negative in comparison with DBS, and because of the sometimes severe, irreversible
side effects (Hohagen et al. 2015). However, this recommendation is based on only one
follow-up study of 25 patients treated with capsulotomy between 1988 and 2000, in which
two patients became sexually disinhibited resulting in one case in a conviction of rape
and in the other case in job loss (Rück et al. 2008). Furthermore, the technique has been
254
significantly refined since then, and the high radiation doses used by Rück and colleagues
(e.g., three bilateral doses of 200 Gy) are not used anymore.
In spite of the broad acceptance of the reversibility argument in favor of DBS, it can be
questioned whether the reversibility of psychiatric neurosurgery is ethically demanded at
all, since generally, a permanent effect of a medical treatment is strongly preferred over
a reversible effect, which requires continuous treatment to maintain the effect. Even in
comparable areas of stereotactic neurosurgery (e.g., for epilepsy or Parkinson’s disease),
reversibility is never demanded, although these interventions often change the patients’
personalities significantly. For these indications, the aim is a permanent cure or relief
and the reversibility of possible adverse effects and personality changes has never been
demanded by ethicists.
I suppose that there are at least three reasons why there is such a strong demand for
reversibility in the case of psychiatric neurosurgery: first, the experimental character of
all procedures and the insecurity about the optimal targets; second, the fear of perma-
nent undesirable personality changes; and third, that some stakeholders consider severe,
therapy-refractory psychiatric disorders as part of the personality or personal identity
instead of considering them as diseases that compromise the personality.
Adjustability
The other main argument that is brought forward for the ethical superiority of DBS
over ablative psychiatric neurosurgery is its adjustability. However, adjustability, in fact,
leads to one of the most challenging ethical problems of DBS, namely that it allows for
fine-tuning the mood and personality properties of patients. This raises difficult ques-
tions, such as the following: Who shall decide about the patients’ mood and personality
traits and according to which criteria? How can the patients’ autonomy be respected
optimally: by giving the patients full power about their stimulation parameters, or by
limiting their power in order to prevent addiction to the stimulation? These difficult
problems, which can cause severe conflicts between patients and physicians, do not
occur after ablative neurosurgery and radiosurgery, just because they do not allow for
fine-tuning.
Recommendations 255
protect against feelings of being manipulated, self-estrangement, and the burden of nor-
mality syndrome (Müller S. et al. 2015a).
The conclusion must therefore be that an absolute superiority of one of the different
methods cannot be established. Each method has a different profile of advantages and dis-
advantages. Furthermore, what counts as an advantage or disadvantage may differ from
patient to patient, and depends on his or her individual situation and condition (Müller
S. et al. 2015a).
Minimal invasiveness
Minimal invasiveness is proclaimed particularly for Gamma Knife® radiosurgery and
for MRgFUS; although even these methods bear some risks for damaging the brain,
these risks are much less than for DBS and microsurgery. With regard to the nonmalefi-
cence principle, the minimal invasiveness speaks in favor of these two methods.
Since the claimed advantages are not advantages in each respect, it would be unjus-
tified to identify any one of the different methods as superior. Therefore, individual
factors should be crucial in decision-making. Which approach is optimal, depends sig-
nificantly on individual medical and nonmedical factors, particularly on the patient’s
general health status, social situation, individual preferences, and individual attitudes
(Müller S. et al. 2015a).
Recommendations
Further research in psychiatric neurosurgery is warranted given the need for effective
therapies for treatment-refractory psychiatric disorders and because of the preliminary
evidence for its efficacy. However, neither the high mortality rates of severe psychiatric
disorders nor their socioeconomic burden can justify therapeutic adventurism. Since
psychiatric neurosurgery has both the goal and the potential to change core features
of the patients’ personalities, these interventions have to fulfill the highest ethical and
scientific standards. The current research practice in this area does not fulfill these stan-
dards in all cases. Therefore, I suggest several protective measures to ensure that psy-
chiatric neurosurgery research proceeds in accord with the ethical demands (Müller S.
2014; Müller S. et al. 2015a, 2015b).
1. Hypothesis-driven interventions
Testable hypotheses on dysfunctional circuits in the different psychiatric disorders should
be rigorously developed and tested (Müller S. et al. 2015b).
2. Cooperation and competition of different approaches
In spite of the competition of the different approaches of psychiatric neurosurgery, they
do also enrich each other mutually. Most of the DBS targets are known from previous
ablative procedures, whereas successful DBS targets could in turn be used to inform abla-
tive procedures. In the long-run, DBS could become the preferable method for exploring
new targets, just because it is largely reversible, whereas well-established targets could
256
Recommendations 257
should not exclude patients who could profit from a given intervention. Although the
criteria should be formulated as general rules, they should also allow for individual excep-
tions (Müller S. & Christen 2011).
7. No compulsory psychiatric neurosurgery
Psychiatric neurosurgery should not be used as a compulsory treatment for adults or
adolescents (even if demanded by their legal guardians). This prohibition is in accor-
dance with the recommendations on psychosurgery of the National Commission for
the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research (1977) and
the consensus paper on stereotactic neurosurgery for psychiatric disorders (Nuttin et al.
2014; Müller S. et al. 2015b).
8. Comprehensive investigation of adverse effects, particularly of sociopsychological sequelae
Since the risk:benefit profile of a therapeutic approach is decisive for recommending it to
patients, research about adverse effects has an important role. Information about psycho-
social and economic consequences of interventions in the brain must be gathered (Müller
S. 2014, p.134).
9. Development of instruments for measuring subtle mental alterations
Since personality changes are a main ethical concern and a central factor of patients’ sat-
isfaction with an intervention, instruments to evaluate even subtle changes should be
developed further (Müller S. 2014, pp.134–135).
10. Long-term, prospective follow-up
Long-term, optimally prospective, follow-up studies are necessary for ensuring study
quality. Nuttin and colleagues recommend that research and clinical protocols should
include support for long-term safety and efficacy studies on psychiatric neurosurgery for
at least 5–10 years of follow-up (Nuttin et al. 2014).
11. Investigation of single cases
Cross-sectional group research does not reveal the different individual trajectories and
provides only limited clues about which factors are most relevant in effecting positive
change for an individual. It is important to study individual outcomes, particularly by
identifying subgroup patterns that can become lost in whole-group analyses (Wilson et al.
2005; Baxendale et al. 2012). Both positive and poor outcomes should be reported sepa-
rately. Particularly cases with unfavorable or unexpected outcome should be investigated,
since they offer extraordinary chances for scientific discovery and improving the tech-
niques used (Christen & Müller S. 2011; Fins et al. 2011; Müller S. 2014, p.133).
12. Comprehensive information for patients
Patients need independent, evidence- based information about risks, benefits, and
chances of different therapy options for decision-making. As we have proposed for DBS
(Müller S. & Christen 2011), a living database should be developed and continuously
updated, ideally for all neurosurgical therapies, with open access for physicians and
patients. It should contain comparative data of single centers about the morbidity, the
258
References 259
Conclusion
Modern psychiatric neurosurgery has the potential to become a further method for treat-
ing otherwise treatment-refractory severe psychiatric disorders. However, to be broadly
accepted in both the medical community and the society, it has to conform to rigorous
scientific and ethical standards.
Acknowledgments
The research of Sabine Müller is funded by the German Federal Ministry of Education
and Research (01 GP 1621A).
Note
1. Written communication of Catherine Gilmore-Lawless, Vice President of Elekta (the only producer of
Gamma Knife®).
References
Andrade, P. and Visser-Vandewalle, V. (2016). DBS in Tourette syndrome: where are we standing now?
Journal of Neural Transmission (Vienna), 123(7), 791–796.
Baxendale, S., Thompson, P.J., and Duncan, J.S. (2012). Neuropsychological function in patients who
have had epilepsy surgery: a long-term follow-up. Epilepsy & Behavior, 23, 24–29.
Baylis, F. (2013). “I Am Who I Am”: on the perceived threats to personal identity from DBS.
Neuroethics, 6(3), 513–526.
Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F. (2013). The Principles of Biomedical Ethics (7th edn.).
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bell, E., Mathieu, G., and Racine, E. (2009). Preparing the ethical future of deep brain stimulation.
Surgical Neurology, 72(6), 577–586.
Bergfeld, I.O., Mantione, M., Hoogendoorn, M.L.C., et al. (2016). Deep brain stimulation of the
ventral anterior limb of the internal capsule for treatment-resistant depression. A randomized trial.
JAMA Psychiatry, 73(5), 456–464.
Breden, T.M. and Vollmann, J. (2006). The cognitive based approach of capacity assessment in
psychiatry: a philosophical critique of the MacCAT-T. Health Care Analysis, 12(4), 273–283.
Bronstein, J.M., Tagliati, M., Alterman, R.L., et al. (2011). Deep brain stimulation for Parkinson
disease: an expert consensus and review of key issues. Archives of Neurology, 68(2), 165–171.
Cavuoto, J. (2013, December). Depressing innovation. Neurotech Business Report. Available from: http://
www.neurotechreports.com/pages/publishersletterDec13.html [accessed May 9, 2016].
Chodakiewitz, Y., Williams, J., Chodakiewitz, J., and Cosgrove, G.R. (2015). Ablative surgery for
neuropsychiatric disorders: past, present, future. In: Sun, B. and De Salles, A. (Eds.) Neurosurgical
Treatments for Psychiatric Disorders, pp.51–66. Dordrecht: Springer.
Christen, M., Ineichen, C., Bittlinger, M., Bothe, H.W., and Müller, S. (2014). Ethical focal points in
the international practice of deep brain stimulation. AJOB Neuroscience, 5(4), 65–80.
Christen, M. and Müller, S. (2011). Single cases promote knowledge transfer in the field of DBS.
Frontiers in Integrative Neurosciences, 5, 13.
Christen, M. and Müller, S. (2012). Current status and future challenges of deep brain stimulation in
Switzerland. Swiss Medical Weekly, 142, w13570.
260
Cook, M., O’Brien, T.J., Berkovic, S.F., et al. (2013). Prediction of seizure likelihood with a long-term,
implanted seizure advisory system in patients with drug-resistant epilepsy. Lancet Neurology, 12,
563–571.
Corripio, I., Sarró, S., McKenna, P.J., et al. (2016). Clinical improvement in a treatment-resistant
patient with schizophrenia treated with deep brain stimulation. Biological Psychiatry, 80(8), e69–70.
De Salles, A. and Gorgulho, A.A. (2015). Radiosurgery for psychiatric disorders. In: Sun, B. and De
Salles A (Eds.) Neurosurgical Treatments for Psychiatric Disorders, pp.217–225. Dordrecht: Springer.
De Zwaan, M. and Schlaepfer, T.E. (2013). Not too much reason for excitement: deep brain stimulation
for anorexia nervosa. European Eating Disorders Review, 21, 509–5011.
Deisseroth, K. (2012). Optogenetics and psychiatry: applications, challenges, and opportunities.
Biological Psychiatry, 71, 1030–2.
Diering, S.L. and Bell, W.O. (1991). Functional neurosurgery for psychiatric disorders: a historical
perspective. Stereotactic and Functional Neurosurgery, 57, 175–194.
Dougherty, D.D., Rezai, A.R., Carpenter, L.L., et al. (2015). A randomized sham-controlled trial
of deep brain stimulation of the ventral capsule/ventral striatum for chronic treatment-resistant
depression. Biological Psychiatry, 78, 240–248.
Dupré, D.A., Tomycz, N., Oh, M.Y., and Whiting, D. (2015). Deep brain stimulation for obesity: past,
present, and future targets. Neurosurgical Focus, 38(6), E7.
Eljamel, S. (2015). Ablative surgery for depression. In: Sun, B. and De Salles, A. (Eds.) Neurosurgical
Treatments for Psychiatric Disorders, pp.87–94. Dordrecht: Springer.
Erickson-Davis, C. (2012). Ethical concerns regarding commercialization of DBS for OCD. Bioethics,
26(8), 440–446.
Fins, J.J., Mayberg, H.S., Nuttin, B., et al. (2011). Misuse of the humanitarian device exemption in
stimulation for obsessive-compulsive disorder. Health Affairs, 30, 2302–2311.
Fisher, C.E., Dunn, L.B., Christopher, P.P., et al. (2012). The ethics of research on DBS for depression.
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1265(1), 69–79.
Focquaert, F. and DeRidder, D. (2009). Direct intervention in the brain: ethical issues concerning
personal identity. Journal of Ethics in Mental Health, 4(2), 1–6.
Franzini, A., Broggi, G., Cordella, R., Dones, I., and Messina, G. (2013). Deep-brain stimulation for
aggressive and disruptive behavior. World Neurosurgery, 80(3–4), S29.e11–14.
Friehs, G.M., Park, M.C., Goldman, M.A., Zerris, V.A., Norén, G., and Sampath, P. (2007). Stereotactic
radiosurgery for functional disorders. Neurosurgery Focus, 23(6), E3.
Gilbert, F. (2012). The burden of normality. Journal of Medical Ethics, 38(7), 408–412.
Gilbert, F. (2013a). Deep brain stimulation for treatment resistant depression: Postoperative feeling of
self-estrangement, suicide attempt and impulsive-aggressive behaviours. Neuroethics, 6(3), 473–481.
Gilbert, F. (2015). A threat to autonomy? The intrusion of predictive brain implants. AJOB Neuroscience,
6(4), 4–11.
Gilbert, F. and Dodds, S. (2013). How to turn ethical neglect into ethical approval. AJOB Neuroscience,
4(2), 59–60.
Gilbert, F. and Ovadia, D. (2011). Deep brain stimulation in the media: over-optimistic portrayals
call for a new strategy involving journalists and scientists in ethical debates. Frontiers in Integrative
Neuroscience, 5, 16.
Gilbert, F., Vranic, A., and Hurst, S. (2013b). Involuntary & voluntary invasive brain surgery.
Neuroethics, 6(1), 115–128.
Giordano, J., Kulkarni, A., Farwell, J. (2014). Deliver us from evil? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics,
35, 73–89.
Glannon, W. (2014a). Neuromodulation, agency and autonomy. Brain Topography, 27(1), 46–54.
261
References 261
Glannon, W. (2014b). Intervening in the psychopath’s brain. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics,
35, 43–57.
Goldberg, D.S. (2012). Justice, population health, and deep brain stimulation. AJOB Neuroscience,
3(1), 16–20.
Greenberg, B.D., Price, L.H., Rauch, S.L., et al. (2003). Neurosurgery for intractable obsessive-
compulsive disorder and depression: critical issues. Neurosurgery Clinics of North America, 14,
199–212.
Hohagen, F., Wahl-Kordon, A., Lotz-Rambaldi, W., and Muche-Borowski, C. (Eds.) (2015). S3-
Leitlinie Zwangsstörungen. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Kesey, K. (1964). One Flew Over the Cuckoo’s Nest. New York: The Viking Press, Inc.
Klaming, L. and Haselager, P. (2013). Did my brain implant make me do it? Neuroethics, 6(3),
527–539.
Kohl, S., Schönherr, D.M., Juigjes, J., et al. (2014). Deep brain stimulation for treatment-refractory
obsessive compulsive disorder: a systematic review. BMC Psychiatry, 14, 214.
Kraemer, F. (2013). Me, myself and my brain implant. Neuroethics, 6(3), 483–497.
Lévèque, M. (2014). Psychosurgery: New Techniques for Brain Disorders. Dordrecht: Springer.
Lévèque, M., Carron, R., and Régis, J. (2013). Radiosurgery for the treatment of psychiatric disorders: a
review. World Neurosurgery, 80(3/4), S32.e1–e9.
Lidz, C.W., Appelbaum, P.S., Grisso, T., and Renaud, M. (2004). Therapeutic misconception and the
appreciation of risks in clinical trials. Social Science & Medicine, 58, 1689–1697.
Lindquist, C., Kihlström, L., and Hellstrand, E. (1991). Functional neurosurgery—a future for the
Gamma Knife? Stereotactic and Functional Neurosurgery, 57, 72–81.
Lipsman, N., Mendelsohn, D., Taira, T., and Bernstein, M. (2011). The contemporary practice of
psychiatric surgery: results from a global survey of North American functional neurosurgeons.
Stereotactic and Functional Neurosurgery, 89, 103–110.
Lipsman, N., Woodside, D.B., Giacobbe, P., et al. (2013a). Subcallosal cingulate deep brain
stimulation for treatment-refractory anorexia nervosa: a phase 1 pilot trial. The Lancet, 381
(9875), 1361–1370.
Lipsman, N. and Glannon, W. (2013b). Brain, mind and machine: what are the implications of deep
brain stimulation for perceptions of personal identity, agency and free will? Bioethics, 27(9),
465–470.
Luigjes, J., de Kwaasteniet, B.P., de Koning, P.P., et al. (2013). Surgery for psychiatric disorders. World
Neurosurgery, 80(3/4), S31.e17–e28.
Mackenzie, R. (2011a). Who should hold the remote for the new me? AJOB Neuroscience, 2(1), 18–20.
Mackenzie, R. (2011b). Must family/carers look after strangers? Post-DBS identity changes and related
conflicts of interest. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 5, 12.
Martínez-Álvarez, R. (2015). Ablative surgery for obsessive-compulsive disorders. In: Sun, B. and De
Salles, A. (Eds.) Neurosurgical Treatments for Psychiatric Disorders, pp.105–112. Dordrecht: Springer.
Mendelsohn, D., Lipsman, N., Lozano, A.M., Taira, T., and Bernstein, M. (2013). The contemporary
practice of psychiatric surgery: results from a global survey of functional neurosurgeons. Stereotactic
and Functional Neurosurgery, 91, 306–313.
Merkel, R., Boer, G., Fegert, J., et al. (2007). Intervening in the Brain: Changing Psyche and Society.
Berlin: Springer Verlag.
Mirzadeh, Z., Bari, A., Lozano, A.M. (2016). The rationale for deep brain stimulation in Alzheimer’s
disease. Journal of Neural Transmission (Vienna), 123(7), 775–783.
26
Morishita, T., Fayad, S.M., Higuchi, M., Nestor, K.A., and Foote, K.D. (2014). Deep brain stimulation
for treatment-resistant depression: systematic review of clinical outcomes. Neurotherapeutics, 11,
475–484.
Müller, S. (2014). Personality and Autonomy in Light of Neuroscience [Cumulative habilitation]. Available
from: http://www.diss.fu-berlin.de/diss/receive/FUDISS_thesis_000000097489 [accessed January
31, 2017].
Müller, S. and Christen, M. (2011). Deep brain stimulation in Parkinsonian patients—ethical evaluation
of cognitive, affective and behavioral sequelae. American Journal of Bioethics, 2(1), 3–13.
Müller, S. and Walter, H. (2010). Reviewing autonomy. Implications of the neurosciences and the free
will debate for the principle of respect for the patient’s autonomy. Cambridge Quarterly of Health
Ethics, (2), 205–217.
Müller, S., Walter, H., and Christen, M. (2014). When benefitting a patient increases the risk for harm
for third persons—the case of treating pedophilic Parkinsonian patients with DBS. International
Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 37(3), 295–303.
Müller, S., Riedmüller, R., and van Oosterhout, A. (2015a). Rivaling paradigms in psychiatric
neurosurgery. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 9, 27.
Müller, S., Riedmüller, R., Walter, H., and Christen, M. (2015b). An ethical evaluation of stereotactic
neurosurgery for anorexia nervosa. AJOB Neuroscience, 6(4), 50–65.
Müller, U.J., Voges, J., Steiner, J., et al. (2013). Deep brain stimulation of the nucleus accumbens for the
treatment of addiction. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1282, 119–128.
Na, Y.C., Jung, H.H., and Chang, J.W. (2015). Focused ultrasound for the treatment of obsessive-
compulsive disorder. In: Sun, B. and De Salles, A. (Eds.) Neurosurgical Treatments for Psychiatric
Disorders, pp.125–141. Dordrecht: Springer.
Northoff, G. (2004). The influence of brain implants on personal identity and personality—a combined
theoretical and empirical investigation in ‘Neuroethics’. In: Schramme, T. and Thome, J. (Eds.)
Philosophy and Psychiatry, pp.311–325. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Nuttin, B., Wu, H., Mayberg, H., et al. (2014). Consensus on guidelines for stereotactic neurosurgery
for psychiatric disorders. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 85(9), 1003–1008.
Pepper, J., Hariz, M., and Zrinzo, L. (2015). Deep brain stimulation versus anterior capsulotomy for
obsessive-compulsive disorder: a review of the literature. Journal of Neurosurgery, 122, 1028–1037.
Racine, E., Waldman, S., Palmour, N., Risse, D., and Illes, J. (2007). “Currents of
hope”: neurostimulation techniques in U.S. and U.K. print media. Cambridge Quarterly of Health
Ethics, 16, 312–316.
Raspe, H., Hüppe, A., Strech, D., and Taupitz, J. (2012). Arbeitskreis Medizinischer
Ethikkommissionen: Empfehlungen zur Begutachtung klinischer Studien. Köln: Deutscher
Ärzte-Verlag.
Régis, J. (2013). Radiosurgery as a modulation therapy! Acta Neurosurgery Supplement, 116, 121–126.
Rosin, B., Slovik, M., Mitelman, R., et al. (2011). Closed-loop deep brain stimulation is superior in
ameliorating Parkinsonism. Neuron, 72, 370–384.
Rück, C., Karlsson, A., Steele, D., et al. (2008). Capsulotomy for obsessive-compulsive disorder. Long-
term follow-up of 25 patients. Archives of General Psychiatry, 65(8), 914–922.
Salgado-López, L., Pomarol-Clotet, E., Roldán, A., et al. (2016). Letter to the Editor: Deep brain
stimulation for schizophrenia. Journal of Neurosurgery, 125(1), 229–230.
Schechtman, M. (2009). Getting our stories straight: self-narrative and personal identity. In: Mathews,
S.J.H., Bok, H., and Rabins, P.V. (Eds.) Personal Identity and Fractured Selves, pp.66–92. Baltimore,
MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Schermer, M. (2011). Ethical issues in deep brain stimulation. Frontiers in Integrative
Neuroscience, 5, 17.
263
References 263
Schläpfer, T.E. (2015). Deep brain stimulation for major depression—steps on a long and winding road.
Commentary. Biological Psychiatry, 78, 218–219.
Schläpfer, T.E., Bewernick, B.H., Kayser, S., Madler, B., and Coenen, V.A. (2013). Rapid effects of deep
brain stimulation for treatment-resistant major depression. Biological Psychiatry, 73, 1204–1212.
Schläpfer, T.E. and Fins, J.J. (2010). Deep brain stimulation and the neuroethics of responsible
publishing: when one is not enough. JAMA, 303(8), 775–776.
Skuban, T., Hardenacke, K., Woopen, C., and Kuhn, J. (2011). Informed consent in deep brain
stimulation. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 5, 7.
Sun, B. and De Salles, A. (Eds.) (2015). Neurosurgical Treatments for Psychiatric Disorders.
Dordrecht: Springer.
Sun, B., Li, D., Liu, W., Zhan, S., Pan, Y., and Lin, G. (2015). Surgical treatments for anorexia nervosa.
In: Sun, B. and De Salles, A. (Eds.) Neurosurgical Treatments for Psychiatric Disorders, pp.175–187.
Dordrecht: Springer.
Tan, D.J., Hope, P.T., Stewart, D.A., and Fitzpatrick, P.R. (2006). Competence to make treatment
decisions in anorexia nervosa: thinking processes and values. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology,
13(4), 267–282.
Tass, P.A. (2003). A model of desynchronizing deep brain stimulation with a demand-controlled
coordinated reset of neural subpopulations. Biological Cybernetics, 89, 81–88.
Torres, C.V., Sola, R.G., Pastor, J., et al. (2013). Long-term results of posteromedial hypothalamic deep
brain stimulation for patients with resistant aggressiveness. Journal of Neurosurgery, 119, S. 277–287.
Valenstein, E.S. (1986). Great and Desperate Cures: The Rise and Decline of Psychosurgery and Other
Radical Treatments for Mental Illness. New York: Basic Books, Inc. Publishers.
Vincent, N.A. (2014). Restoring responsibility. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 8(1), 21–42.
Walter, H. and Müller, S. (2013). Optogenetics as a new therapeutic tool in medicine? A view from the
principles of biomedical ethics. In: Hegemann, P. and Sigrist, S. (Eds.) Optogenetics, pp.201–211.
Berlin: De Gruyter.
Wilson, S.J., Bladin, P.F., and Saling, M.M. (2001). The “burden of normality”: concepts of
adjustment after surgery for seizures. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 70,
649–656.
Wilson, S.J., Bladin, P.F., Saling, M.M., and Pattison, P.E. (2005). Characterizing psychosocial outcome
trajectories following seizure surgery. Epilepsy & Behavior, 6, 570–580.
Witt, K., Kuhn, J., Timmermann, L., Zurowski, M., and Woopen, C. (2013). Deep brain stimulation
and the search for identity. Neuroethics, 6(3), 499–511.
Woopen, C., Timmermann, L., and Kuhn, J. (2012). An ethical framework for outcome assessment in
psychiatric DBS. AJOB Neuroscience, 3(1), 50–55.
Wu, H., Gabriels, L., and Nuttin, B. (2012). Neurosurgery for psychiatric disorders in the People’s
Republic of China. AJOB Neuroscience, 3(1), 56–59.
264
Chapter 14
Introduction
Contemporary formulations of science are increasingly shifting from a top-down model
of expertise toward a more pluralistic approach that encourages the engagement of pub-
lics in the co-creation and governance of science. This conceptualization, in which non-
scientific actors are regarded as agents capable of meaningfully contributing to scientific
debates, evinces a systematic shift from a model of public understanding of science to a
new paradigm marked by public participation in science.
A participatory and egalitarian orientation is central in the field of neuroethics, which
at its core aims to align neurotechnological development with societal values. The brain
is widely regarded as the seat of the mind, and is inextricably linked with abstractions
of individuality and personal identity (Leshner 2005). It is therefore not surprising that
new brain technologies that reside at the intimate frontier of personhood are compelling
widespread public interest and engagement (Illes et al. 2005).
It is the civic duty of neuroscientists and neuroethicists to engage with publics in delib-
eration about the development of new research trajectories (Illes et al. 2005). Not only is
this logical, but it is also socially conscientious to ensure that the publics who bear the
burdens and risks of neurotechnological development are included in dialogue about its
formulation and application. As such, public engagement has been a focal area in the
field of neuroethics since its contemporary inception (Marcus 2002). Ongoing neuroethi-
cal debates about controversial issues including the trade-offs of cognitive enhancement,
implications of brain–computer interfaces on autonomy, and the management of inciden-
tal findings in neuroimaging require the input of both scientists and lay citizens to inform
the field in a sustainable and socially responsible capacity.
Successful civic engagement in science, however, is not without its risks and chal-
lenges. Public engagement may unveil divergence between expert opinion and public
265
debates about science and policy. While social media platforms have only been widely
utilized for less than two decades, their accessibility and global reach have made them
widely impactful in health-information sharing and decision-making. Citizen-generated
content on online platforms is a powerful information tool for health researchers and
policymakers. Indeed, public use of social media platforms has also been the subject
of a growing body of empirical inquiry, with innovative approaches such as web eth-
nographic and infodemiological methodologies that aim to utilize public knowledge to
inform healthcare delivery and science policy (Eysenbach 2009). For example, real-time
infodemiological analyses of Twitter content have been used to track public perspectives
about immunization during the H1N1 epidemic, and respond to public concerns using
risk communication approaches to promote health (Chew & Eysenbach 2010). Publics
also increasingly utilize social media platforms in advocacy efforts. In March of 2014, Josh
Hardy, a 7-year-old boy who suffered a lifethreatening adenoviral infection, was denied
compassionate access to brincidofovir, an antiviral drug that was under investigation in
adult clinical trials. Brincidofovir’s manufacturer, Chimerix, explained that the company
did not have the resources to support a compassionate use program of the antiviral drug.
In response, Hardy’s parents launched a wide-reaching Facebook and Twitter campaign
to pressure both the US Food and Drug Administration and Chimerix to provide access.
Catalyzed by public pressure, Chimerix and the Food and Drug Administration designed
an open-label clinical trial that provided Hardy and 19 other pediatric patients access to
brincidofovir (Goodman 2014).
concluded that lithium carbonate delays the rate of progression of amyotrophic lateral
sclerosis (ALS), an untreatable and invariably fatal neurodegenerative disease. This small
trial, which consisted of a sample of 16 patients who received the experimental interven-
tion and 24 controls followed over a period of 15 months, demonstrated that in contrast
to a 29% incidence of morbidity in the control group, no patient deaths occurred in the
experimental arm (Fornai et al. 2008). Given a scarcity of clinical interventions for ALS
and a limited therapeutic window of opportunity for clinically meaningful intervention,
neurologists began to prescribe lithium off-label. In response to demands for an ongoing
evidentiary basis for the use of lithium, advocates in the ALS community in collaboration
with PatientsLikeMe—an online patient network that aims to connect patients, improve
outcomes, and promote research—initiated a platform for patients who had obtained
lithium off-label to submit data about their usage and outcomes. Data probes included
dosage, weight, and outcome measures on the ALS functional rating scale. Data from 149
treated ALS patients were matched with historical controls in an observational study that
did not replicate the efficacy data suggested by Fornai and colleagues (Wicks et al. 2011).
This patient-led research endeavor contributed to the early termination of clinical trials
due to futility considerations, and spared the ALS community significant divestment of
funds from promising areas of inquiry and opportunity costs for patients.
While numerous academic platforms are dedicated to public participation in science,
and successes in community advocacy are many, public controversies have also revealed
challenges in community engagement. We now direct focus to the case study of the
CCSVI research trajectory, as an example of the challenges of community engagement.
The CCSVI story
Multiple sclerosis (MS) is a chronic and progressive neurological disease of the brain
and the spinal cord that affects more than two million individuals worldwide (Multiple
Sclerosis International Federation 2015). In people with MS, the immune system attacks
myelinated axons in the central nervous system. This causes communication problems
between the brain and the rest of the body that lead to a range of symptoms such as
vision loss, fatigue, pain, sensory loss, spasticity, impaired mobility, and cognitive defi-
cits. Initially these symptoms may fluctuate. However, over time these problems accumu-
late and are often irreversible. Since the 1990s, disease-modifying drugs have decreased
the frequency of developing new symptoms and delayed the onset of progressive decline.
Unfortunately, these treatments only appear to benefit those at the earliest stages of the
disease, and have little impact on improving or reversing chronic symptoms that contrib-
ute to a decrease in quality of life. The unknown etiology of the disease, especially the pro-
gressive forms, presents challenges to finding a cure, and leaves many severely disabled.
Dr. Paulo Zamboni, an Italian vascular surgeon, began to tackle the underlying cause
of MS when his wife was diagnosed with the disease in 1999. His primary area of inquiry,
involving investigation into heavy metal aggregate damage to blood vessels in the leg, led
him to suggest that iron deposits that are caused by narrowed or blocked veins in the neck
268
(cerebrospinal venous insufficiency, or CCSVI) are at the root of the disease. Zamboni
believed that such blockage hinders the efficient removal of blood from the brain and
spinal cord, and causes a build-up of iron that induces inflammation and myelin sheath
attack. Zamboni postulated two hypotheses. First, he proposed that all individuals with
MS have narrowed or blocked veins, and second, that relieving such venous anomalies
using a procedure similar to angioplasty, which he termed liberation therapy, would
cure MS.
To test his first hypothesis, Zamboni performed a cross-sectional study where he looked
to diagnose CCSVI in 65 MS patients and 235 controls using ultrasound and catheter
venography. Indeed, his hypothesis was supported by results that established a strong
association between MS and CCSVI with vein anomalies in virtually the entire MS cohort
and none of the controls (Zamboni et al. 2009a). To test his second hypothesis, Zamboni
conducted an open-label trial of the liberation procedure in 65 patients with MS, who
showed symptomatic improvement, reduced clinical relapses and reduced formation
of new lesions on brain magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) following the procedure
(Zamboni et al. 2009b).
Since 2009, several studies have brought Zamboni’s evidence into question. Scholars
expressed skepticism about Zamboni’s studies, pointing to several limitations in the
methods employed. Indeed, Zamboni’s liberation procedure was not conducted through
a randomized control trial and did not account for a potential placebo effect. Additionally,
patients who experienced the most improvement in Zamboni’s study had the relapsing–
remitting form of MS, where spontaneous remissions in disease activity commonly occur.
Moreover, although a meta-analysis of ultrasound diagnoses of CCSVI suggests an asso-
ciation between vein abnormality and MS (Laupacis et al. 2011), other studies demon-
strate that CCSVI occurs rarely and with similar prevalence among both patients with MS
and in healthy individuals (Doepp et al. 2010; Mayer et al. 2011; Traboulsee et al. 2014).
Commentators believe that the substantial evidence undermining Zamboni’s hypoth-
eses should have been the end of the CCSVI story (Reekers 2012). The cautionary word
of the medical community, however, was seemingly dwarfed by optimistic anecdotes
that amassed publicly accessible domains. Indeed, despite concerns about the validity
of the data that bolstered the liberation procedure in the neurology community, news
of Zamboni’s study catalyzed a media frenzy and showcased a potent account of evi-
dence: the anecdote.
The procedure was widely covered in international newspapers and was also com-
monly featured in television outlets (Favaro & Philip 2009). However, it was publicity
through social media platforms that fueled widespread activism within the MS commun-
ity. Indeed, CCSVI gained significant momentum in the blogosphere: within 2 years of
the publication about the liberation procedure, thousands of people engaged with more
than 500 Facebook groups, pages, and events about the intervention, and over 4000
YouTube videos were dedicated to CCSVI, many documenting the positive experiences
of patients who underwent the procedure (Chafe et al. 2011). These powerful anecdotes
showcased patient accounts before and after the procedure, which not only described the
269
amelioration of their symptoms and improved quality of life, but also demonstrated gains
in function (Mazanderani et al. 2013).
Anecdotal evidence motivated thousands of patients to seek access to CCSVI proce-
dures, and when the intervention was unavailable through their local healthcare provid-
ers, many chose to travel abroad at great personal cost to countries like Costa Rica and
Poland that offered the CCSVI procedure (Snyder et al. 2011). Even in the face of several
severe adverse events linked to CCSVI procedures, including deaths (Alphonso 2010;
Samson 2010), patients persisted in advocacy efforts for access to the invasive procedure.
Advocates continued to publicize personal anecdotes of the therapeutic benefits of the
procedure through social media outlets, organize demonstrations, attack the credibility
of parties that advocated for caution, and question potential conflicts of interest of both
the MS societies and MS neurologists. Steadfast advocacy generated enormous pressures
on granting agencies such as MS societies and government funding bodies in Europe,
Australia, and North America to mobilize additional research on CCSVI. The controversy
became particularly pronounced in Canada, where MS is very prevalent (Pullman et al.
2013). In 2010, the Canadian Institutes of Health Research, the primary government fund-
ing agency for health research in Canada, formed an expert panel in collaboration with
the Canadian MS Society about the CCSVI research agenda. The panel initially advised
that only studies that examine the venous anomaly hypothesis receive funds, a stance that
was also adopted by the United States. But despite expert caution, media pressures contin-
ued to hail the potential of the liberation treatment and reputable media platforms began
to exert political pressure to mobilize funding for CCSVI research (Pullman et al. 2013).
For example, The Globe and Mail, one of Canada’s most circulated newspapers, asserted:
“Canada should fund medical trials of revolutionary treatment for multiple sclerosis, and
not act as if rejection of those trials by an expert panel must be obeyed. This is a political
question, not a purely scientific one” (Globe Editorial 2010).
Critics argue that CCSVI research was mobilized by intense social and political pres-
sure, more so than by sound science (Chafe et al. 2011). Commentators believe that the
CCSVI research trajectory has resulted in the unnecessary expenditure of scarce resources,
divestment of funds from more promising areas of inquiry for MS, and caused signifi-
cant therapeutic opportunity costs, adverse events, and preventable fatalities (Rasminsky
2013). Additionally, the CCSVI experience has contributed to unrealized hopes in the MS
community, the impact of which is yet to be determined. Given these costs, it is essential
that we examine the lessons learned from the CCSVI research trajectory to inform future
public engagement in science and science policy.
mobilized intense public and political pressure to provide access to liberation interven-
tions and invest in their evaluation. Educational initiatives may be needed to address
public evaluation of diverse forms of evidence, particularly in light of the powerful and
readily accessible anecdotes on online fora. The CCSVI experience also emphasizes the
power of the media, particularly newer forms of social media, in influencing science
policy and priority setting in research. Scholarly inquiry should continue to focus on
harnessing the power of social media platforms to foster sustainable support for evidence-
based science. Education about evidence should be a bidirectional effort. Scientists may
reciprocally consider that the contemporary focus on evidence-based medicine some-
times overlooks a wide body of knowledge that has been gleaned from medicine-based
evidence approaches. Indeed, fields such as surgery and oncology have largely seen inno-
vation based on clinical experience. An educational initiative alone, however, would be
a reductionist approach. Indeed, educational approaches do not adequately account for
affective factors, such as hope, that extend beyond a deficit of understanding and exert a
large influence on the decision-making process.
The CCSVI experience brings the delicate nature of hope to the surface—a force that
ubiquitously surrounds biomedical research, and can serve to both mobilize and some-
times hinder successful scientific innovation. Hope largely motivated activism in the
CCSVI context, as it often serves to promote developing biotechnologies. Hope is a nat-
ural and necessary component of technological development, and can also serve as an
adaptive mechanism for managing daily living with serious illness (Groopman 2005;
Kimmelman 2009). Successful community engagement about developing neurotechnolo-
gies will therefore need to address the complexities of hope with key end-users, such as
patients and their families. Clinical conversations about hope may be particularly use-
ful. Neurologists may best serve the interests of their patients by approaching conversa-
tions about hope through a posture of epistemic (knowledge-based) humility: a stance
that acknowledges the uncertainty associated with decision-making in medical care, and
one that also appreciates the lived experience that lends expertise to patients (Ho 2009;
Schwab 2012). Honoring patient hope for therapeutic development while grounding prac-
tical advice in current clinical realities may strengthen collaboration between patients and
their clinicians and support shared decision-making through an emphasis on informed
hope (Reimer et al. 2010; Benjaminy et al. 2015). Conversations through a lens of epi-
stemic humility that privilege openness and understanding over hierarchical assertion
of expertise could also serve to strengthen relationships of trust between patients and
physicians. Indeed, commentators argue that such relationships may have been strained
in the CCSVI context (Pullman et al. 2013; Snyder et al. 2014). Additional research is
necessary to explore the impact of the CCSVI research trajectory on community support
in analogous non-pharmaceutical areas of inquiry that present the possibility for ther-
apeutic development (e.g., stem cell interventions). Such knowledge may be helpful in
understanding the response of communities that have been subject to disappointment
following cycles of hope—a phenomenon that occurs all too often in biomedical research
(Petersen 2009).
271
References 271
Conclusion
Public engagement in science is a central value in the field of neuroethics, and reflects a
commitment to social responsibility and accountability in the process of democratizing
science and policy. A commitment to citizen engagement recognizes the possibility that
public controversies may arise as neuroethical issues are deliberated in the public sphere.
The CCSVI research trajectory illustrates some of the challenges that may arise when
public and scientific agendas diverge. Forging successful partnerships between neurosci-
entists, neuroethicists, and the broader community will require both trust and hope as
well as reciprocity between mutually engaged publics and scholars.
Acknowledgments
The quotation attributed to Globe Editorial was reproduced by kind permission of The
Globe and Mail, Copyright © 2016 The Globe and Mail Inc., http://www.theglobeandmail.
com/opinion/editorials/funding-ms-trials-is-a-decision-that-goes-beyond-expertise/
article1379043/.
References
Alphonso, C. (2010, November 19). Death of MS patient fuels debate over new treatment. The Globe
and Mail. Available from: http://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/national/death-of-ms-patient-
fuels-debate-over-new-treatment/article1314786/ [accessed January 22, 2016].
Benjaminy, S., Kowal, S.P., MacDonald, I.M., and Bubela, T. (2015). Communicating the promise
for ocular gene therapies: challenges and recommendations. American Journal of Ophthalmology,
160(3), 408–415.
Boyd, S.C., MacPherson, D., and Osborn, B. (2009). Raise Shit! Social Action Saving Lives. Black Point,
NS: Fernwood.
27
Boyer, E.L. (1996). The scholarship of engagement. Bulletin of the American Academy of Arts and
Sciences, 49(7), 18–33.
Chafe, R., Born, K.B., Slutsky, A.S., and Laupacis, A. (2011). The rise of people power. Nature,
472(7344), 410–411.
Chew, C. and Eysenbach, G. (2010). Pandemics in the age of Twitter: content analysis of Tweets during
the 2009 H1N1 outbreak. PloS One, 5(11), e14118.
Doepp, F., Paul, F., Valdueza, J.M., Schmierer, K., and Schreiber, S.J. (2010). No cerebrocervical venous
congestion in patients with multiple sclerosis. Annals of Neurology, 68(2), 173–183.
Eysenbach, G. (2009). Infodemiology and infoveillance: framework for an emerging set of public health
informatics methods to analyze search, communication and publication behavior on the Internet.
Journal of Medical Internet Research, 11(1), e11.
Favaro, A. and St Philip, E. (2009). The liberation treatment: a whole new approach to MS. CTV News.
Available from: http://www.ctvnews.ca/the-liberation-treatment-a-whole-new-approach-to-ms-
1.456617 [accessed February 12, 2016].
Fornai, F., Longone, P., Cafaro, L., et al. (2008). Lithium delays progression of amyotrophic lateral
sclerosis. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 105(6),
2052–2057.
Globe Editorial. (2010, September 2). Funding MS trials is a decision that goes beyond expertise. The
Globe and Mail. Available from: http://www.theglobeandmail.com/opinion/editorials/funding-ms-
trials-is-a-decision-that-goes-beyond-expertise/article1379043/ [accessed January 22, 2016].
Goodman, M. (2014). Twitter storm forces Chimerix’s hand in compassionate use request. Nature
Biotechnology, 32(6), 503–504.
Groopman, J. (2005). The Anatomy of Hope: How People Prevail in the Face of Illness.
New York: Random House.
Ho, A. (2009). ‘They just don’t get it!’ When family disagrees with expert opinion. Journal of Medical
Ethics, 35(8), 497–501.
Illes, J., Blakemore, C., Hansson, M.G., et al. (2005). International perspectives on engaging the public
in neuroethics. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6(12), 977–982.
Illes, J., Moser, M.A., McCormick, J.B., et al. (2010). Neurotalk: improving the communication of
neuroscience research. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11(6), 61–69.
Jozaghi, E. (2014). The role of drug users’ advocacy group in changing the dynamics of life in the
Downtown Eastside of Vancouver, Canada. Journal of Substance Use, 19(1–2), 213–218.
Kimmelman, J. (2009). Gene Transfer and the Ethics of First-in-human Research: Lost in Translation.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kowal, S.P., Jardine, C.G., and Bubela, T.M. (2015). ‘If they tell me to get it, I’ll get it. If they
don’t...’: immunization decision-making processes of immigrant mothers. Canadian Journal of Public
Health, 106(4), E230.
Laupacis, A., Lillie, E., Dueck, A., et al. (2011). Association between chronic cerebrospinal venous
insufficiency and multiple sclerosis: a meta-analysis. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 183(16),
E1203–1212.
Leshner, A.I. (2005). It’s time to go public with neuroethics. American Journal of Bioethics, 5(2), 1–2.
Marcus, S.J. (Ed) (2002). Neuroethics: Mapping the Field, Conference Proceedings. Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press.
Mayer, C.A., Pfeilschifter, W., Lorenz, M.W., et al. (2011). The perfect crime? CCSVI not leaving a trace
in MS. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 82(4), 436–440.
Mazanderani, F., O’Neill, B., and Powell, J. (2013). “People power” or “pester power”? YouTube as a
forum for the generation of evidence and patient advocacy. Patient Education and Counseling, 93(3),
420–425.
273
References 273
McCombs, M.E. and Shaw D.L. (1972). The agenda-setting function of mass media. Public Opinion
Quarterly, 36(2), 176–187.
Multiple Sclerosis International Federation. (2015). What is MS? Available from: http://www.msif.org/
about-ms/what-is-ms/ [accessed February 10, 2016].
O’Doherty, K., Burgess, M., and Secko, D.M. (2010). Sequencing the salmon genome: a deliberative
public engagement. Life Sciences Society and Policy, 6(1), 15.
Petersen, A. (2009). The ethics of expectations: biobanks and the promise of personalized medicine.
Monash Bioethics Review, 28(1), 22–33.
Pullman, D., Zarzeczny, A., and Picard, A. (2013). Media, politics and science policy: MS and evidence
from the CCSVI trenches. BMC Medical Ethics, 14(1), 6.
Rasminsky, M. (2013). Goodbye to all that: a short history of CCSVI. Multiple Sclerosis Journal, 19(11),
1425–1427.
Reekers, J.A. (2012). CCSVI and MS: a never-ending story. European Journal of Vascular and
Endovascular Surgery, 43(1), 127–128.
Reimer, J., Borgelt, E., and Illes, J. (2010). In pursuit of “informed hope” in the stem cell discourse.
American Journal of Bioethics, 10(5), 31–32.
Samson, K. (2010). Experimental multiple sclerosis vascular shunting procedure halted at Stanford.
Annals of Neurology, 67(1), A13–15.
Scheufele, D.A. (1999). Framing as a theory of media effects. Journal of Communication, 49(1), 103–122.
Schwab, A. (2012). Epistemic humility and medical practice: translating epistemic categories into ethical
obligations. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 37(1), 28–48.
Snyder, J., Crooks, V.A., Adams, K., Kingsbury, P., and Johnston, R. (2011). The ‘patient’s physician
one-step removed’: the evolving roles of medical tourism facilitators. Journal of Medical Ethics,
37(9), 530–534.
Snyder, J., Adams, K., Crooks, V.A., Whitehurst, D., and Vallee, J. (2014). “I knew what was going to
happen if I did nothing and so I was going to do something”: faith, hope, and trust in the decisions
of Canadians with multiple sclerosis to seek unproven interventions abroad. BMC Health Services
Research, 14(1), 445.
Stilgoe, J., Lock, S.J., and Wilsdon, J. (2014). Why should we promote public engagement with science?
Public Understanding of Science, 23(1), 4–15.
Traboulsee, A.L., Knox, K.B., Machan, L., et al. (2014). Prevalence of extracranial venous narrowing
on catheter venography in people with multiple sclerosis, their siblings, and unrelated healthy
controls: a blinded, case-control study. The Lancet, 383(9912), 138–145.
Wicks, P., Vaughan, T.E., Massagli, M.P., and Heywood, J. (2011). Accelerated clinical discovery using
self-reported patient data collected online and a patient-matching algorithm. Nature Biotechnology,
29(5), 411–414.
Zamboni, P., Galeotti, R., Menegatti, E., et al. (2009a). Chronic cerebrospinal venous insufficiency
in patients with multiple sclerosis. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 80(4),
392–399.
Zamboni, P., Galeotti, R., Menegatti, E., et al. (2009b). A prospective open-label study of endovascular
treatment of chronic cerebrospinal venous insufficiency. Journal of Vascular Surgery, 50(6),
1348–1358.
274
Chapter 15
[A]man does not consist of memory alone. He has feeling, will, sensibi
lities, moral being … And it is here … that you may find ways to touch him.
(A.R. Luria, cited in Sacks 1985, p.32)
Introduction
Neurodegenerative disease can significantly affect the requirements for an ethically
appropriate treatment of an individual. The deterioration of the brain profoundly alters
psychological functioning and capacities, and so profoundly alters the kind of being oth-
ers are called upon to relate to and respond to from the point of view of ethics. Such trans-
formations are easiest to see in cases in which the current preferences and interests of a
patient in a degenerated state come into conflict with the values and choices the person
professed before the neurodegeneration began. Which set of preferences should the care-
giver follow? The answer will be different depending on the ethically relevant metaphysi-
cal and mental properties that the patient still possesses. Thus to resolve such dilemmas
we must get the ethically relevant conceptual distinctions right, but we must also be true
to empirical facts. To the extent that neuroscience has developed a detailed understand-
ing of how various brain disorders undermine psychological functioning and capacity,
it has increasingly become more pertinent to the untangling of such ethical puzzles. The
following case study illustrates the interplay between ethical conceptual analysis and neu-
roscientific findings in the resolution of moral dilemmas that arise in Alzheimer’s disease.
I defend the philosophical view that the immediate interests of an individual cannot
be overridden as long as the individual possesses the capacity to value. In the context of
each particular neurodegenerative disease, this recommendation must be guided by a sci-
entifically informed assessment of when in the course of the disease the capacity to value
could possibly be lost, and when it is likely to be retained. In the case of Alzheimer’s dis-
ease, neuroscientific evidence indicates that the capacity to value is slowly and gradually
weakened, and in some cases may not be completely lost until relatively far along in the
disease’s progression. Similar neuroethical analyses must be carried out for other diseases
and disorders, and will probably yield different results.
275
Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value 275
People who care for Alzheimer’s patients—family members, nursing home providers,
physicians, medical researchers—face such dilemmas routinely, and these dilemmas are
becoming more and more familiar as baby-boomers approach the age of high risk for
Alzheimer’s disease. The particulars of each dilemma may seem unique, but they typi-
cally have the same underlying structure. There is a conflict between the attitudes and
values the patients espoused when they were still healthy and their later interests as peo-
ple afflicted with dementia. The quandary, in a nutshell, is this: should we, in our efforts
to best respect a patient with dementia, give priority to the preferences and attitudes
this person held before becoming demented, or should we follow the person’s present
interests?
Reconceiving well-being
Experiential interests versus critical interests
When we take enhancement of the demented patient’s well-being as the caregiver’s
goal, we need to distinguish two types of prudential interest that the patient may have.
Dworkin labels these two types of interest “experiential” and “critical.” Experiential
interests concern the quality of the person’s experience, his state of mind. We have an
interest in experiencing pleasure, satisfaction, enjoyment, contentment, lack of pain, and
27
Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value 277
so forth; what states of mind count here and how they can be brought about is deter-
mined fully by how these experiences feel to the person in question. But most of us also
have critical interests—interests in doing or having in our lives the things we consider
good and in avoiding the things we consider bad, no matter what sorts of experiences
result from fulfilling these interests. For example, a person’s critical interests may include
being a successful soldier or securing contentment and harmony for his family, however
much stress or anguish the pursuit of these goals may engender.
Experiential interests are inherently time-specific—to satisfy them at a given time,
the person must still espouse them at that time. For instance, it only makes sense to
want to satisfy your experiential interest in having a good time with your guests if at
the time they arrive you will still be interested in enjoying their company. Not so with
critical interests; it may make sense to have your critical interest satisfied even if you
are unaware of its being satisfied, even if you are dead at the time, or unconscious, or
too demented to grasp what your critical interest has been all along. Fulfillment of a
critical interest bears only on the object of that interest. It involves bringing about what-
ever state of affairs the person in question judged good; the fate of the person himself
is not relevant to this, provided that the object of the interest is external to the person.
Thus fulfilling a father’s critical interest in the well-being of his family does not require
his awareness of how well they are doing. This critical interest could be advanced, for
example, by obeying a deathbed promise to take care of his wife and children after he
passes away.
Dworkin readily grants that Alzheimer’s patients, even at late stages of their illness,
can experience pleasures as well as frustrations, and thus have the basis for contem-
poraneous experiential interests. He would interpret the dilemmas under discussion
in this chapter as cases of conflict between these experiential interests and critical
interests that the person professed when he was still healthy (e.g. a conflict between
Mrs. Rogoff ’s experiential interest in continuing the enjoyable storytelling sessions
and her critical interest in not being dependent on her family). And here Dworkin
assumes that, at least in the types of cases he wants to address, the demented patient
is not capable of generating contemporaneous critical interests. From this point, there
follows a very plausible analysis. The fact that the demented patient no longer affirms
critical interests in no way implies that he does not have critical interests. Since such
interests are not inherently time-specific, the prudential importance of satisfying them
may survive the person’s unawareness of their satisfaction, whether due to uncon-
sciousness, dementia, or even death. Thus a demented person who cannot generate
contemporaneous critical interests may still have some of the same critical interests
he professed when he was healthy. And this means that the conflict occurring in our
dilemmas is best described as a conflict between the patient’s ongoing experiential
interests and his ongoing critical interests.
This description helps to clarify how the conflict ought to be resolved. In the case of an
ordinary competent person, when his critical interests (his judgments and values) come
278
into conflict with his experiential interests (what would lead to the optimal state of mind
for him), we do not hesitate to give precedence to his well-considered values and judg-
ments, and we concede that, overall, this is best for him. For example, we would accept
that it is in the best interest of a devoted father to sacrifice his experiential interest in his
current comfort for the sake of the future of his children, or that it is in the best interest
of a patriotic soldier to forgo his experiential interest in a carefree life and sign up for
demanding military training. The case of our demented person turns out to be no dif-
ferent: in his conflict between ongoing experiential and critical interests, it is also best
to privilege the latter. We serve Mrs. Rogoff best by satisfying her critical interest in not
being a burden to her family, at the expense of her experiential interest in enjoying tele-
vision and storytelling.
This analysis stands or falls with the assumption that demented patients no longer
originate critical interests. For if they do—if the conflict in our dilemmas is between the
patient’s contemporarily professed critical interests and the critical interests he professed
before becoming demented—Dworkin’s framework would readily allow that the contem-
porarily professed critical interests ought to take precedence. In this case, the demented
person would be viewed as any other person whose values and commitments change
over time and whose currently professed values are taken to have bearing on what is best
for him.
The idea that a demented person can originate critical interests need not imply that the
person generates brand new critical interests. What matters is whether the person still
has an ongoing commitment to his critical interests. After all, the most likely scenario of
a conflict between a demented person’s current critical interests and his critical interests
from the pre-dementia period is not one in which a person’s demented mind generates
completely new critical interests, but rather one in which dementia causes a person to lose
some of his earlier more complex interests, so that in the new simpler configuration the
remaining interests gain import.
Dworkin defends the claim that the demented cannot generate critical interests as
follows:
[B]y the time the dementia has become advanced, Alzheimer’s victims have lost the capacity to
think about how to make their lives more successful on the whole. They are ignorant of self—not
as an amnesiac is, not simply because they cannot identify their pasts—but more fundamentally,
because they have no sense of a whole life, a past joined to a future, that could be the object of any
evaluation or concern as a whole. They cannot have projects or plans of the kind that leading a crit-
ical life requires. They therefore have no contemporary opinion about their own critical interests.
(Dworkin 1993, p.230)
In contending that demented persons cannot have opinions about their critical interests,
Dworkin presupposes that one needs to have a sense of one’s life as a whole in order to orig-
inate critical interests, a sense that a person may begin to lose relatively early in the pro-
gression of dementia. Dworkin thinks of critical interests as stemming from “convictions
279
Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value 279
about what helps to make a life good on the whole” (Dworkin 1993, pp.201–202). But do
critical interests have to reflect the person’s comprehensive design for the progression of
his life? An alternative view, tacitly embedded in Dworkin, is more plausible.
Critical interests may well be understood to issue from something less grand—simply
from convictions about what is good to have, which do not require the ability to grasp or
review one’s whole life. Dworkin himself describes “opinions about my critical interests”
as “opinions about what is good for me” (Dworkin 1993, p.202), indicating that these are
opinions about values, and that the ability to generate critical interests goes hand in hand
with the ability to value. And it does seem possible for a person to value something at a
given time, without referring this value to his conception of his life as a whole. This pos-
sibility is evident in patients with severe loss of memory and linguistic ability who are still
aware of their decline and deeply regret it. I recently observed a patient who, in response
to a simple question about what he did that day, had great difficulty keeping track of the
sequence of his thoughts and of the sequence of words in the sentence he was composing,
and after several starts and long pauses, said slowly, his voice trembling: “Here you can
see Alzheimer’s at work.” There was no doubt that this man, who had little grip on “his
life as a whole,” nevertheless valued the abilities he could no longer command and was
expressing profound regret.
Understanding values
Intuitively, it is easy to recognize when someone expresses a value—and not merely a sim-
pler attitude such as a craving, a desire, or a wish. But to exhibit more clearly that valuing
need not involve a grasp of one’s life as a whole, let us characterize more systematically
what valuing is and distinguish it from these simpler attitudes, which even Dworkin read-
ily attributes to Alzheimer’s patients.
The main difference between mere desiring and valuing is this: one way to deal with
one’s non-value-laden desires is to try to eliminate them—to try to bring it about that one
does not feel them—but this would not be a satisfactory response to a valuing. A person
could contemplate being free of a mere desire with a sense of relief, but one would always
view the possibility of not valuing something one currently values as an impoverish-
ment, loss, or mistake. We can all recognize clear cases when a strong desire is definitely
not a value—think of a priest eager to rid himself of his sexual desires, or a temporarily
depressed person seeking relief from his persistent wish to hurt himself. Also, even if one’s
attitude toward a desire is more neutral—perhaps one views it only as a nuisance—as long
as one would not mind lacking it, it is still a mere desire. Cravings for specific food items
are paradigmatic cases here. In contrast, when one values something, say, a particular
friendship or a local community, one cannot be indifferent to whether one happens to
value these things or not—a state in which one lacked one’s feelings for one’s friend or
one’s need for a sense of belonging would call for regret.2 We can see this in our patient
mourning the losses caused by Alzheimer’s disease—he would view with horror the pro-
jected future in which he will no longer care about these losses.
280
Thus values have special attributes that do not apply to mere desires: we think that it
would be a mistake to lose our current values—we hold our values to be correct, or at least
correct for us. This means that we can typically give a rationale for why we consider some-
thing valuable or good, usually by situating this value in a larger normative framework.
Also, since values are the sorts of attitudes that we allow could be correct or incorrect,
they are open to criticism and revision. At minimum, there are consistency requirements
on what one can consider good—if one values something and also values its opposite,
one will be under rational pressure to resolve the conflict. For example, if you truly value
a committed relationship, you cannot just as easily value the freedom of a lack of com-
mitment; you may well see the merits of both, but you cannot be fully committed to your
spouse unless you cease to care as deeply about your freedom. In contrast, as a matter of
sheer desire, you may surely remain ambivalent without any rational impetus to settle the
conflict—you may simply keep craving just as strongly the kind of intimacy possible only
in an ongoing partnership as well as the excitement of always being able to walk out and
entice a new partner.
Another mark of valuing as opposed to mere desiring is that a person’s values are
usually entangled with his sense of self-worth: a person values himself in terms of how
well he lives up to his values. Some people pay little attention to their own value, so
what I am now describing is not a necessary condition of having values. However, it
is a sufficient condition: anyone who has a conception of himself, a set of ideals that
he wants to live up to and in virtue of which he assesses his own value, is no doubt a
valuer.
I have isolated two features essential to, or strongly indicative of, valuing: the person
thinks he is correct in wanting what he wants, and achieving what he wants is tied up with
his sense of self-worth. Nothing here suggests that valuing would require a grasp of the
narrative of one’s whole life.
Furthermore, for the purposes of the argument I outlined earlier, Dworkin does not
need to interpret the capacity to generate critical interests as anything more than the so-
specified capacity to value. As we have seen, the backbone of Dworkin’s justification for
disregarding current wishes of patients who can no longer originate critical interests is the
perception that, ordinarily, critical interests take precedence over experiential interests
in determining what is best for a person. But, presumably, critical interests are of such
overriding importance because they stem from the person’s values—because they reflect
the person’s opinion of what is correct for him. And this standing of critical interests is
independent of whether they encompass the person’s design for his life as a whole. For
instance, a devoted father’s critical interest in the well-being of his children overrides his
interest in having optimal experiences, no matter whether he came to value his children
by reflecting on the narrative of his whole life. Thus, to endorse Dworkin’s compelling
argument that deference to current wishes of a demented patient ought to depend on
whether the patient can still originate critical interests, we have no need to understand
critical interests in terms of the person’s grasp of what is good for his life as a whole; we can
281
Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value 281
just trace critical interests to the person’s convictions about what would be good and cor-
rect for him—to the person’s values as understood in the above-mentioned specifications.
Mrs. D’s memory deficiency was rather acute. Since she could not keep track of the passing
time or of her own age, and had severe difficulties forming new memories, Dworkin could
safely assume that she had lost grasp of the narrative of her whole life, that she lacked a
sense of “a past joined to a future.” However, Mrs. D still conducted herself as a valuer. She
often volunteered as a research subject for tests and experiments at the National Institutes
of Health. Although she did not choose to do so through systematic reflection on the
whole trajectory of her life, she clearly felt that this was, for her, the right choice: “That
was the nicety of it, cause I could have said, ‘no,’ but believe me, if I can help me and my
[fellow] man, I would do it” (Sabat 1998, p.46). Her conviction that it would have been a
mistake to say “no” comes across rather starkly here. And she had no need to review her
life as a whole to affirm this conviction. What mattered for her was that this felt right to
her, then and there. One has the sense that Mrs. D was simply enacting a basic part of her
personality, one that had remained relatively intact despite her other impairments.
For a less altruistic example, consider another of Sabat’s interviewees, Dr. B, an
Alzheimer’s patient who scored even lower than Mrs. D on cognitive tests. Like Mrs. D,
he “could not recall the day of the week, the month, or the year” (Sabat 1998, p.41). His
ability to evaluate his life as a whole could not have been better than that of Mrs. D. Yet
he too proved capable of valuing. He became very interested in Sabat’s research project.
Although his grasp of its design was rather rudimentary, he thought of the project as his
“salvation,” as a way to engage, despite his impairments, in something other than “filler”
(Sabat 1998, p.41), in something giving him a mark of distinction. He told Sabat more or
less explicitly that he considered the project right and appropriate: “And you know I feel
a way is that, I feel that this is a real good, big project, and I’m sure you do too. This proj-
ect is a sort of scientific thing” (Sabat 1998, pp.41–42, italics mine). This assessment of
the project went hand in hand with a boost to Dr. B’s sense of pride and self-worth that
ensued from his participation. The impact on his self-esteem was most evident whenever
28
he compared the project to various “filler” group activities at the day care center: “If I’m
working with you, I can—look, I can work in here for 30 times and all that, but in this
group, I’m nothing” (Sabat 1998, p.41, italics mine). That his role in the project could so
alter his self-image demonstrates most poignantly that he valued the project.
Mrs. Rogoff ’s case also demonstrates that the ability to value may outlast the patient’s
grasp of her life as a whole. Her confusion between a television-generated world and
events of her own life easily rules out her having an adequate grasp of her life’s narrative.
However, she does remain a valuer, most clearly when her former reputation as a great
cook is at stake. She invariably becomes upset and agitated seeing Fran usurp the mas-
tery of the kitchen. One day, after Fran made a particularly delicious chicken leg roast,
Mrs. Rogoff insisted that she would cook dinner herself, and asked her granddaughter,
in secret, to buy “a hen with five legs,” clearly in the spirit of one-upmanship with Fran.
At such times, Fran arranges small make-work kitchen tasks that appease Mrs. Rogoff.
Here, as before, the clearest indication of retained values comes from visible effects on the
person’s self-esteem: Mrs. Rogoff ’s self-image suffers whenever she realizes that Fran has
taken over as a culinary expert, and these effects can be mitigated, at least temporarily, by
a semblance of participation in culinary affairs.
Insights from neuroscience
My observations that valuing may be quite independent of grasping the narrative of one’s
life, and that this separation often occurs in Alzheimer’s patients, are also supported by
current findings in neurophysiology and in the neuropathology of Alzheimer’s disease.
The neuronal loss characteristic of Alzheimer’s disease is not distributed evenly in the
cerebral cortex. The disease affects most severely an area of the brain indispensable for
maintaining the sense of one’s life as a whole, but not particularly important for the ability
to value.
In the early stages of Alzheimer’s disease, the neuronal damage affects primarily the
hippocampus. As the damage spreads, the hippocampus continues to be affected much
more severely than other regions of the brain (Geula 1998; Laakso et al. 2000). The hip-
pocampus is of crucial importance in the acquisition and processing of long-term explicit
memory for facts and events. Although it is not involved in short-term memory or in the
eventual storage of long-term memories, the hippocampus nonetheless plays an essential
role in transforming a fresh short-term memory into a lasting long-term memory (Squire
& Zola-Morgan 1991; Riedel & Micheau 2001). Accordingly, while damage to the hippo-
campus affects neither a person’s processing of his immediate experience nor his memo-
ries of events that occurred long before the damage, it causes him to lose track of ongoing
events soon after they happen, so that he typically has no recollection of the previous day
(Squire & Zola-Morgan 1988). Such damage impairs a person’s ability to come back to
a recent thought or memory after a shift of attention to something new (Squire & Zola-
Morgan 1991). These very impairments are, of course, the typical first clinical indications
of Alzheimer’s disease. They are also central to Dworkin’s assessment that Alzheimer’s dis-
ease destroys one’s sense of one’s life as a whole. Damage to the hippocampus alone leaves
283
Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value 283
the person unable to update his autobiographical narrative. As he continually forgets his
immediate past, he loses the sense of “a past joined to a future,” which Dworkin deems
necessary for the ability to formulate critical interests.
However, there is no reason to think that impairment of the hippocampus would oblit-
erate one’s ability to espouse critical interests when this is understood, following my
recommendation, as the ability to value. While removal of the hippocampal formations
leads to the memory defects described previously, it does not otherwise compromise the
patient’s mental functions (Young & Young 1997). Moreover, there is neurophysiological
evidence that other regions of the brain are primarily responsible for interactions of rea-
soning and decision-making processes, especially those concerning personal and social
matters, with feelings and emotions (Damasio 1994). It is damage to these regions that is
most likely to directly compromise a person’s ability to value.
Thus consider Elliot, a patient with brain damage localized in the ventromedial prefron-
tal cortices. He performed normally or even superiorly on a full battery of psychologi-
cal tests (including intelligence, knowledge base, memory, language, attention, and basic
reasoning), and yet was a very poor decision-maker in everyday life (Damasio 1994). He
showed no abnormalities in means-ends reasoning and problem-solving; he was perfectly
able to come up with a full array of options for action in a particular situation as well as to
work out the consequences of each option. As it turned out, his impairment concerned the
ability to choose among the options he could reason through so well. After a full analysis
of all the options he would comment, “I still wouldn’t know what to do!” (Damasio 1994,
p.49). His emotional responses and feelings were severely blunted and this “prevented
him from assigning different values to different options, and made his decision-making
landscape hopelessly flat” (Damasio 1994, p.51). He lacked the very starting points of the
ability to value: he was no longer sufficiently invested in anything; he ceased to care.
The ability that Elliot lacked is the indispensable core of the capacity to value. When you
value something—be it a particular friendship or a local community—your commitment
to these things is first and foremost a form of emotional engagement. You would not call it
“valuing” or “being committed” unless there is some confluence between thinking about
and acting upon what you say you value and your emotional life. True enough, since the
conviction that it is right for you to care about these things and that you would be mis-
taken if you did not care is open to criticism, sophisticated and varied cognitive abilities
are required to develop a robust set of values, values most immune from such criticisms.
But having such convictions in the first place amounts to attaching emotional signifi-
cance to the object of value; it involves having the corresponding emotional attitudes and
reactions, so that some things simply “feel” important to you (Jaworska 1997). Elliot was
unable to value because of the numbing of his affective response.
The neuronal destruction of Alzheimer’s disease eventually reaches the regions of
the brain most responsible for “giving emotional quality to occurrences which renders
them important to the person concerned” (Souren & Franssen 1994 p.52). However, the
destruction and the isolation of the hippocampus are always several steps ahead of the
pathologies in the areas most likely to affect the capacity to value (Braak & Braak 1995).
284
In this section I have chiefly argued that the ability to value is independent of the ability
to understand the narrative of one’s whole life, and that demented people may well retain
the former ability long after they lose the latter. We also saw that, at least when the well-
being of the demented is the focus, Dworkin’s recommendation to disregard the patient’s
current wishes derives from the loss of the former capacity, the capacity to value. Thus,
for a Dworkinian, the threshold capacity level necessary to lend prudential authority to
a person’s current wishes should not be set at the ability to grasp one’s life as a whole, but
rather at the ability to value. As long as the demented person still espouses values, we have
seen no reason to override these in the name of values he professed earlier—Dworkin’s
recommendations do not apply.
Rethinking autonomy
Let us now turn to respect for the patient’s autonomy as the primary goal of those car-
ing for demented patients. How should we now approach our dilemmas? According
to Dworkin, we need to consider whether the demented patient, in his current condi-
tion, still possesses the capacity for autonomy. The rationale here is that respecting
people’s autonomy is morally important only because a human being’s very ability to
act autonomously is morally important. If a person is not even capable of making
autonomous decisions, allowing him to carry out his current wishes would do nothing
to promote his autonomy. As Dworkin sees it, the only way to respect the autonomy of
such patients is to respect their earlier ability to act autonomously; if their autonomous
choices from that earlier time can still be satisfied now, these should be the focus of
respect for autonomy. Of course, choices associated with critical interests are often still
satisfiable, since, as we saw earlier, critical interests can be meaningfully fulfilled at a
time when the person no longer espouses these interests. Thus, for Dworkin, the only
way to respect the autonomy of patients who lost their capacity for autonomy is to
adhere to the critical interests that they professed before this loss. He readily concludes
that the types of demented patients he is interested in lack the capacity for autonomy,
and hence that in order to respect their autonomy one must adhere to their earlier
wishes, wishes that expressed this capacity.
285
Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value 285
The claim that demented patients no longer possess the capacity for autonomy is clearly
pivotal to this part of Dworkin’s analysis. But how plausible is the underlying interpreta-
tion of the capacity for autonomy?
Fundamentals of autonomy
Dworkin describes the capacity for autonomy as “the capacity to express one’s own
character— values, commitments, convictions, and critical as well as experiential
interests—in the life one leads” (Dworkin 1993, p.224). So understood, this is the capac-
ity to be fully in charge of one’s life—to enact one’s own values and convictions in the life
one leads. Demented people may easily lose this capacity, because as they lose the under-
standing of the world around them and become increasingly disoriented, they no longer
know how to translate their values and convictions into appropriate activity in the world.
But suppose that a demented person who still espoused values and convictions received
some help in enacting those values in his environment. Imagine, for instance, a demented
man who values his independence above all else, but who is confused about what he is
still able to do on his own. Were he left to make his own decisions, his choices would
not ultimately enhance his independence, and perhaps would even lead to his harm. But
imagine further that his family makes living arrangements for him that allow a maximum
degree of independence feasible in his predicament. There is an important sense in which
this man is still capable of exercising his capacity for autonomy, of living according to his
convictions and values, albeit with some help in translating ends into means. Thus a pos-
sibility opens up that the capacity for autonomy ought not to be thought of as the capac-
ity to carry one’s convictions into action without external help, a capacity that requires
reasoning through complex sets of circumstances to reach the most appropriate autono-
mous decisions; rather, that the capacity for autonomy is first and foremost the capacity
to espouse values and convictions whose translation into action may not always be fully
within the agent’s mastery.
In his own elaboration of why the demented lack the capacity for autonomy, Dworkin
emphasizes the claim that they have “no discernable even short-term aims” (Dworkin
1993, p.225). Presumably, Dworkin thinks that Alzheimer’s patients cannot have even
short-term aims because as soon as they embark on a course of action they forget what
it was they were doing and are forced to start anew. But he should distinguish between
an inability to form and then remember a plan for fulfilling one’s purposes, and a lack of
a stable set of purposes and preferences. For we can imagine an Alzheimer’s patient who
always wants the same set of things—say, he wants to feel useful and appreciated—and
yet is unable to set up and carry through a plan for achieving any of them, partly because
he cannot figure out the means to his ends, and partly because he cannot keep track of
the steps he is taking. These latter deficiencies seem to be at stake in Dworkin’s claim that
the demented lack the capacity for autonomy, despite his explicit focus on their lack of
consistent purposes.
For Dworkin, Alzheimer’s patients cannot be autonomous because, left to their own
devices, they cannot lead their lives by their own lights. This is largely because they have
286
lost the ability to reason from their preferences to the appropriate decisions and actions—
they have lost the adeptness for means-ends reasoning and planning.
However, there is no good reason to restrict the right to autonomy only to people who
possess these abilities. After all, as the case of Elliot and other patients with prefrontal
brain damage powerfully brings home, the very idea of governing one’s life autonomously
is a complete nonstarter unless the person knows how he wants his life to be governed—
unless he has his own substantive principles or directives for running his life. These prin-
ciples constitute the foundation of autonomy; means-ends reasoning and planning are
mere tools for implementing the principles. Moreover, while having one’s own directives
is indispensable for exercising autonomy, we can well imagine that the tools of means-
ends reasoning and planning could be supplied for the autonomous person from the out-
side. Accordingly, the essence of the capacity for autonomy consists in the ability to lay
down the principles that will govern one’s actions, and not in the ability to devise and
carry out the means and plans for following these principles.3
Dworkin’s analysis, then, focuses on peripheral rather than essential aspects of the
capacity for autonomy. However, to offer a convincing alternative, we must specify more
precisely what the essence of the capacity for autonomy amounts to, and in particular
what counts as one’s own principle or guideline for running one’s life. Presumably this
cannot be just any run-of-the-mill wish or desire, because a person may distance himself
from a mere desire and not recognize it as truly his own.4 So, at the very least, a principle
suitable as a basis for self-governance must be viewed by the person as correct for him.
Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value 287
We can now restate in a more familiar form our earlier finding that the mere laying
down of principles for one’s conduct makes one capable of autonomy. Since such prin-
ciples are values, the very ability to value, even if more instrumental abilities are absent,
supplies the starting points for the exercise of autonomy, and thereby renders the person
capable of autonomy.
Of course, possessing the capacity to value does not guarantee that the person can exer-
cise autonomy to a full degree. Full-blown autonomy involves not only acting on one’s
own principles and convictions, but also the ability to scrutinize these principles and to
revise them in light of critical evaluation, so that they are well articulated and robust. The
capacity to value merely makes possible the most minimal and basic level of autonomy;
other capacities are necessary to further develop and perfect autonomy. All the same,
the capacity to value by itself does, in a very important sense, render a person capable of
autonomy.
But when Ann patiently interviewed him about what he wanted to say, he “spoke halt-
ingly, but passionately, about leaving his career. In garbled phrases he described what he
felt about science and why he was quitting. He needed his colleagues to know why he had
left. He wanted them to know, too, that people with Alzheimer’s are still ‘regular folks’ ”
(Davidson 1997, p.210).
Julian communicated his conviction that it was right for him to care deeply about sci-
ence, and likewise that it was appropriate to give his colleagues an explanation. He was
definitely conveying values here, his authentic ideals. At the same time, he needed Ann’s
help to translate these values into appropriate actions—he could not have figured out on
his own that Ann needed to rewrite his speech and that it would be best if someone else
delivered the speech on his behalf.
There are abundant variations of cases of Alzheimer’s patients who remain valuers
despite severe impairments in their decision-making capacity. On my analysis, these
patients are still capable of fundamentals of autonomy. Accordingly, a caregiver com-
mitted to respect for autonomy must respect these patients’ contemporaneous autonomy.
This is a perfectly coherent goal, albeit respecting the autonomy of such patients usu-
ally requires much more active participation of the caregivers than what is required for
ordinary competent patients. To properly respect the autonomy of many an Alzheimer’s
patient, one must do quite a bit to enhance his autonomy. One must help the person no
longer able to do so on his own to lead his life according to his remaining values, to the
extent that this is still feasible. This involves figuring out how his values would be best
upheld in a reality he no longer fully understands, as well as helping him implement these
solutions in practice. We saw this approach employed by Julian Davidson’s wife, by Mrs.
Rogoff ’s caregiver Fran, and by the researcher working with Dr. B. Sometimes enhancing
a person’s autonomy in this way may even involve going against his explicit choices. Ann
Davidson did not simply allow Julian to try to deliver his jumbled speech, and Fran would
not simply give in if Mrs. Rogoff insisted on cooking a potholder for dinner. The caregiver
must learn to pay attention to the person’s values rather than to her concrete, yet perhaps
ill-informed, selection of options. All the same, as long as the patient is still able to value,
respect for autonomy does not license the caregiver to disregard the patient’s immediate
interests altogether.
In sum, contrary to Dworkin’s assumptions, in the context of dementia, the capac-
ity for autonomy is best understood not as the ability to lead one’s life by one’s lights
when one is left to one’s own devices, and not as a full capacity to make a decision from
the beginning to end, but as the capacity to value—to originate the appropriate bases
for one’s decisions that can then be, if the need arises, partly taken over by others. An
Alzheimer’s patient may be too disoriented to form a life plan or to choose specific
treatment preferences, but as long as he still holds values, he is, in the most basic
sense, capable of self-governance, and this fact about him commands utmost respect.
Autonomy-based recommendations to disregard his contemporaneous interests have
no purchase.
289
Conclusion
No matter whether we emphasize well-being or autonomy of Alzheimer’s patients, we
should approach our dilemmas mindful of Julian Davidson’s insight that many people
with Alzheimer’s disease are still “regular folks.” In some morally very important respects,
many Alzheimer’s patients remain, at least for a time, surprisingly similar to ourselves.
As neuroscience allows us to corroborate, patients moderately afflicted with Alzheimer’s
disease may well remain valuers, and thus retain the essential characteristics by virtue of
which persons and their interests enjoy an exalted moral status.
2016 Postscript
Since I formulated the ideas relayed in this chapter, exciting neuroscience research has
emerged that not only corroborates my key claim that the capacity to care and value is
relatively preserved at least up to the middle stages of Alzheimer’s disease, but also, rather
surprisingly, suggests that the core aspects of this capacity may even be enhanced by the
degeneration typical of Alzheimer’s disease.
This new evidence is tied to a broader finding about the functioning of the brain,
namely, that distinct and often anatomically distant structures in the normal human
brain tend to activate and deactivate together, forming integrated functional units or
networks called intrinsically connected networks (Seeley et al. 2007). The intrinsically
connected network most relevant to Alzheimer’s disease is the so-called default mode
network. Neuronal degeneration characteristic of Alzheimer’s disease (the degen-
eration due to pathological accumulation of tau protein, to be exact) develops early
on in one key node of this network—the hippocampus, as we saw earlier—and then
spreads most prolifically along the pathways of this network (de Calignon et al. 2012;
Raj et al. 2012). In other words, the pattern of the most acute degeneration in a typi-
cal Alzheimer’s brain matches one of the patterns of co-activation found in a normal
human brain (Seeley et al. 2009).
The default mode network supports not only the hippocampal function of transforming
short-term memory into long term memory as emphasized in the original chapter, but
also a broader set of abilities that may be loosely described as “time travel”: the ability to
sequence one’s life as a temporally extended agent—to remember one’s past and to imagi-
natively extend one’s life timeline into the future, for example, through planning—as well
as the broader ability to imaginatively project oneself into an alternative situation or per-
spective, be it the viewpoint of another person or even an alternative spatial perspective
as in some forms of navigation (Buckner & Carroll 2007; Østby et al. 2012). These abilities
are relevant downstream to valuing and caring, insofar as, for example, once you value or
care about another person you are moved to understand their point of view and to plan
for or with them, as their needs dictate. But these abilities are orthogonal to the ability
to value and care about somebody or something in the first place; they merely affect how
well you are able to live up to what you already value and care about. So the finding that
290
Alzheimer’s disease spreads primarily in the default mode network is consistent with my
claim that this trajectory of degeneration spares, at least for a time, the capacity to value
and care.
However, once we look at the brain from the point of view of intrinsically connected
networks, there is more to this story. It turns out that the default mode network is cou-
pled in an interesting way with another intrinsically connected network, known as the
salience network: in a normal human brain, states of high level of activity in the default
network are associated with decreased activity in the salience network and vice versa
(Raichle et al. 2001; Fox et al. 2005). In parallel with this finding, it also turns out that
as the default mode network becomes compromised in Alzheimer’s disease, this corre-
sponds to increased connectivity and activity in the salience network (Zhou et al. 2010).
The salience network plays a central role in social and emotional processing. More spe-
cifically, as the name “salience” suggests, its key function is thought to be isolating what
the cognitive system will pay attention to and allocate more resources to, out of the vast
amount of internal and external information that the brain is bombarded with and pro-
cessing at any given time. The salience network swiftly identifies what is most relevant
and responds accordingly by generating appropriate emotions that recruit other resources
and guide our spontaneous behavior (Seeley et al. 2007). A paradigmatic example of a
well-functioning salience network is a quick pivoting to information relevant to safety
or security when one is absorbed in an unrelated task (e.g., running out of class upon
hearing a fire alarm). However, the network has been conceptualized to have the broader
function of focusing attention and cognitive resources not only on what impacts security
or safety but, more generally, on what is personally relevant, and this maps naturally onto
what one values and cares about. Thus, one would expect that the increased connectivity
and activity in the salience network associated with the progression of Alzheimer’s disease
would result in a heightened emotional attunement to what is important to the person,
in a manner characteristic of valuing and caring. While research in this area is only just
beginning to emerge, Sturm and colleagues have already documented a suggestive result
that emotional sensitivity to the emotions of others (so-called emotional contagion) is
enhanced in mild Alzheimer’s disease compared to normal controls and, perhaps even
more surprisingly, it is further enhanced in moderate Alzheimer’s disease as compared to
mild (Sturm et al. 2013). The increase in emotional contagion was correlated with smaller
volume in the default mode network. These results begin to corroborate the observations
of clinicians and caregivers that some Alzheimer’s patients become more sweet, loving,
and attentive to them as their memory fades.
So far, I have interpreted the finding that connectivity in the salience network increases
as a result of the progression of Alzheimer’s disease as suggestive of an enhancement
of the capacity to care and value, and thus as consistent with my claim that patients
with moderate Alzheimer’s disease possess intact the capacities on the basis of which
we deem persons and their interests worthy of utmost moral respect. Nonetheless, con-
strued differently, this finding may be thought to raise a worry for my account. Might the
increased connectivity in the salience network lead to new cares and values that would be
291
inauthentic in virtue of being mere artifacts of Alzheimer’s disease? If so, the strengthen-
ing of the salience network might be seen not as enhancing the capacity to care and value
but rather as disrupting it in a wayward way. It is one thing if Alzheimer’s disease leads to a
loss of some former values and to a reprioritization of the values that remain (in the man-
ner I discussed earlier), or to a strengthening of some former values, but it is something
quite different if the disease causes values to spring up de novo.
Addressing this issue adequately will need to await a more detailed understanding of
the functioning of the salience network and of the specific ways in which the increased
connectivity associated with Alzheimer’s disease affects the operation of this network.
For example, if the main effect of the increased connectivity is greater attunement to the
emotions of others, this can plausibly be interpreted as an enhancement rather than dis-
ruption of the capacity to value. The attunement to the emotions of others is not, by itself,
a new care or value. Rather, such attunement makes possible a better, more perceptive
and appreciative understanding of other persons—and also of various ideals involving
other persons such as tolerance, justice, etc.—as potential objects of care and value. Thus,
greater attunement to the emotions of others can lead to new cares or values but through
a path that, arguably, is not deviant, since it proceeds via greater appreciation of what the
object of care or value is all about. However, if it turned out that increased connectivity
in the salience network can lead in a more direct way to new cares or values, without the
mediation of any new experience or reasoning, there would be much greater reason to
worry that the capacity to care and value is disrupted.
Acknowledgments
A longer version of this chapter appeared in Philosophy and Public Affairs, Volume 28,
Issue 2, pp.105–38, 1999 (see that version for acknowledgments).
The chapter sans Postscript appeared in Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory,
Practice, and Policy, edited by Judy Illes, pp.87–101, 2005 (https://global.oup.com/aca-
demic/product/neuroethics-9780198567202).
The epigraph at the start of this chapter was reprinted with the permission of Pan
Macmillan via PLSclear, and with the permission of Touchstone, a division of Simon &
Schuster, Inc. from The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat and Other Clinical Tales by
Oliver Sacks. Copyright © 1970, 1981, 1983, 1984, 1985 Oliver Sacks. All rights reserved.
The opinions expressed are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the poli-
cies or positions of the National Institutes of Health, the Public Health Service, or the US
Department of Health and Human Services. Special thanks to Winston Chiong, Katherine
Rankin, and William Seeley for educating me about the science cited in the Postscript,
and to Winston Chiong for comments that partly shaped the Postscript’s content.
Notes
1. This case was reported to me by a family member. To protect the privacy of the patient, I use a fictitious
name. I also do not list the name of my source, but I would like to thank her for her generous help.
29
2. In the case of some (often less central) values, one may anticipate a gradual transformation and loss of
a value without thinking that it would be a mistake. This is not a counterexample to my characteriza-
tion of valuing, because my claim concerns our attitudes to our present espousal of a value: It is part
of valuing something that one would view the possibility of not caring about it here and now as an
impoverishment, loss, or mistake. Imagining a future without the alleged value is a good test for this in
many cases, but it does not work in every case because some values are dependent on context and are
important only at a specific time in one’s life.
3. None of what I say here should be taken to imply that, in a normal case, a person’s own exercise
of means-ends reasoning and planning could be ignored by those aiming to respect his autonomy.
My point is that a person largely incapable of such reasoning may still be able to exercise autonomy,
and not that such reasoning can be taken lightly in an ordinary person who exercises his autonomy
through the use of such reasoning.
4. Some readers may think that this requirement is too stringent, and that the hypothetical individu-
als I go on to describe are still capable of autonomy. If so, it is only easier for me to claim that many
Alzheimer’s patients retain the capacity for autonomy.
5. I speak of a “creature” rather than a “person” here to allow for the view that the ability that my hypo-
thetical creature lacks is essential to personhood.
6. Why this stipulation? If we imagined a creature who was also unable to control his response to a desire,
it would have been easier to see him as lacking the capacity for autonomy. However, I want to show that
our intuition that my imagined creature lacks the capacity for autonomy depends on something else;
even a creature in control of his desires seems to lack the capacity for autonomy if he can never approve
or disapprove of his desires.
References
Braak, E. and Braak, H. (1995). Staging of Alzheimer’s disease-related neurofibrillary changes.
Neurobiology of Aging, 16(3), 271–278.
Buckner, R.L. and Carroll, D.C. (2007). Self-projection and the brain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences,
11(2), 49–57.
Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Putnam.
Davidson, A. (1997). Alzheimer’s, a Love Story: One Year in My Husband’s Journey. Secaucus, NJ: Carol.
de Calignon, A., Polydoro, M., Suárez-Calvet, M., William, C., Adamowicz, D.H., and Kopeikina,
K.J. (2012). Propagation of tau pathology in a model of early Alzheimer’s disease. Neuron, 73(4),
685–697.
Dresser, R. (1986). Life, death, and incompetent patients: conceptual infirmities and hidden values in
the law. Arizona Law Review, 28(3), 373–405.
Dworkin, R. (1993). Life’s Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom.
New York: Knopf.
Fox, M.D., Snyder, A.Z., Vincent, J.L., Corbetta, M., Van Essen, D.C., and Raichle, M.E. (2005). The
human brain is intrinsically organized into dynamic, anticorrelated functional networks. Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 102(27), 9673–9678.
Geula, C. (1998). Abnormalities of neural circuitry in Alzheimer’s disease: hippocampus and cortical
cholinergic innervation. Neurology, 51(Suppl. 1), S18–S29.
Jaworska, A. (1997). Rescuing Oblomov: A Search for Convincing Justifications of Value (Ph.D. thesis).
Harvard University, Cambridge, MA.
293
REFERENCES 293
Laakso, M.P., Hallikainen, M., Hänninen, T., Partanen, K., and Soininen, H. (2000). Diagnosis
of Alzheimer’s disease: MRI of the hippocampus vs delayed recall. Neuropsychologia, 38(5),
579–584.
Østby, Y., Walhovd, K.B., Tamnes, C.K., Grydeland, H., Westlye, L.T., and Fjell, A.M. (2012).
Mental time travel and default-mode network functional connectivity in the developing brain.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 109(42),
16800–16804.
Raichle, M.E., MacLeod, A.M., Snyder, A.Z., Powers, W.J., Gusnard, D.A., and Shulman, G.L. (2001).
A default mode of brain function. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United
States of America, 98(2), 676–682.
Raj, A., Kuceyeski, A., and Weiner, M. (2012). A network diffusion model of disease progression in
dementia. Neuron, 73(6), 1204–1215.
Riedel, G. and Micheau, J. (2001). Function of the hippocampus in memory formation: desperately
seeking resolution. Progress in Neuro-Psychopharmacological and Biological Psychiatry, 25(4),
835–853.
Sabat, S.R. (1998). Voices of Alzheimer’s disease sufferers: a call for treatment based on personhood.
Journal of Clinical Ethics, 9(1), 38–51.
Sacks, O. (1995). The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat and Other Clinical Tales. New York: Summit
Books.
Seeley, W.W., Crawford, R.K., Zhou, J., Miller, B.L., and Greicius, M.D. (2009). Neurodegenerative
diseases target large-scale human brain networks. Neuron, 62(1), 42–52.
Seeley, W.W., Menon, V., Schatzberg, A.F., et al. (2007). Dissociable intrinsic connectivity networks for
salience processing and executive control. Journal of Neuroscience, 27(9), 2349–2356.
Souren, L. and Franssen, E. (1994). Broken Connections: Alzheimer’s Disease, Part I (van der Wilden-
Fall, R.M.J., trans.). Lisse, the Netherlands: Swets and Zeitlinger.
Squire, L.R. and Zola-Morgan, S. (1988). Memory: brain systems and behavior. Trends in Neurosciences,
11(4), 170–175.
Squire, L.R. and Zola-Morgan, S. (1991). The medial temporal lobe memory system. Science, 253(5026),
1380–1386.
Sturm, V.E., Yokoyama, J.S., Seeley, W.W., Kramer, J.H., Miller, B.L., and Rankin, K.P. (2013).
Heightened emotional contagion in mild cognitive impairment and Alzheimer’s disease is associated
with temporal lobe degeneration. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States
of America, 110(24), 9944–9949.
Young, P.A. and Young, P.H. (1997). Basic Clinical Neuroanatomy. Baltimore, MD: Williams and
Wilkins.
Zhou, J., Greicius, M.D., Gennatas, E.D., et al. (2010). Divergent network connectivity changes in
behavioural variant frontotemporal dementia and Alzheimer’s disease. Brain, 133(5), 1352–1367.
294
Chapter 16
A case for anticipation
Recent progress in predictive medicine opens new avenues for the concept of health.
The extensive and idealistic definition given by the World Health Organization in 1946
that: “Health is a state of complete physical, social and mental well-being, and not merely
the absence of disease or infirmity” is no longer pertinent in a world of anticipation where
a biomarker of a disease exists in the absence of any symptom. This is a revolution in
many fields but even more so for neurodegenerative disorders that happen late in a life-
time, making a person’s entire life a period of anticipation.
Among neurodegenerative disorders, Alzheimer’s disease (AD) has gained a special
position during the last 40 years, due to the burden the condition imposes on more than
40 million affected people worldwide. Today’s estimations might only be the beginning, in
fact, since most of the patients are older than 65 years (prevalence of dementia before the
age of 50 years is less than 1 in 4000 with only 30% of cases being attributed to AD), and
projected increases in the prevalence of dementia are higher in developing countries with
young populations (Winblad et al. 2016). Now that we, as a science community, know that
the disease starts two or three decades before any symptoms occur, predictive medicine
may bring forward possibilities for diagnosis or testing. Advances in screening for early
detection may allow for early staging, intervention, and secondary prevention.
Asymptomatic individuals provide the research pool for preventive approaches.
However, is there an interest in diagnosis in the absence of cure? Does no cure mean no
care? Interestingly, results from several European cohort studies have provided evidence
that the age-specific incidence of dementia has decreased in the past 20 years, thereby
raising expectations for preventive interventions (Scheltens et al. 2016). Thus, the related
ethical debate is not about the clinical stages of AD or the timing of interventions where
early appears to be best, but instead, is on the multiple meanings and the impact of pre-
clinical AD diagnosis before the onset of symptoms.
295
Alzheimer’s disease still baffles scientists and tests the boundaries of therapeutic knowl-
edge. Despite undeniable progress, many uncertainties remain, including the cause of
the pathogenic process where the respective roles of amyloid deposition, tau protein, and
other processes of neurodegeneration are not yet understood. The diagnostic criteria of
the International Working Group (IWG) (Dubois et al. 2014) and the National Institute of
Aging and the Alzheimer’s Association (NIA-AA) (Albert et al. 2011) still rely on a clinical
phenotype combined with biomarker information, mainly driven by amyloid and tau. The
preclinical AD concept was initially defined from cognitively unimpaired individuals who
displayed AD brain lesions on postmortem examination. With the development of AD
biomarkers, the concept evolved and preclinical AD (NIA-AA) or at-risk for AD (IWG)
are now considered when these markers are present in a cognitively normal individual. In
addition, individuals known to carry an autosomal dominant monogenic mutation that
will result in the development of full clinical AD are classified as having presymptomatic
AD. These opportunities of anticipation of clinical AD open many questions that range
from basic scientific and technical validity of the biomarkers and methods, toward ethi-
cal issues such as the impact on the individual, family, and society. Similarly challeng-
ing are the ethical issues associated with the set-up of clinical trials with asymptomatic
individuals who will have to consent to a hard-to-bear treatment of unknown efficacy
and unknown potential side effects for a long period, all while living with the status of
preclinical/at-risk AD. Furthermore, while amyloidosis is necessary for an AD diagnosis,
it is not sufficient to reliably predict further progression to a symptomatic stage of disease
given postmortem evidence that demonstrates that a significant proportion of individuals
with typical brain neuropathological AD lesions do not present symptoms of cognitive
impairment (Price et al. 2009). Thus, it is important to understand progression drivers to
determine the proportion of at-risk individuals who will progress to the clinical stage of
AD. Considering the many uncertainties at hand, how then can protocolization for a pos-
sible early detection and the need for adaptation of taking care of individual peculiarities
be reconciled? What are the implications for the family and the workplace? What recon-
figuration of the care relationship and care course do such developments carry?
The short-term therapeutic horizon is further worrisome: effectiveness is not yet
proven. Still, scientists, physicians, and patient organizations agree on the need to
facilitate testing that is as reliable as possible when the first symptoms manifest them-
selves. The precocity of care indeed involves several indisputable advantages. First,
the tested treatments have been proven effective only on patients at the early stage of
AD. Recent clinical trials of three different monoclonal antibodies directed against the
1-42 beta-amyloid peptide (Aß42) (aducanumab, crenezumab, and solanezumab) have
suggested slowing of cognitive decline of early/mild but not moderate AD patients
(Selkoe & Hardy 2016). Second, early care seems to afford economies of scale both
for individuals and the collective. Added to this is the argument that early detection
of the disease could offer patients and their families time to anticipate and look to
the future to consider financial and legal issues, and assert control over the course of
296
their lives that might not have been otherwise considered or desired. To examine the
values and choices that underlie aspirations for anticipation in more detail, I turn to
lessons from other fields of medicine, such as cancer and the identification of high-
risk individuals bearing pathogenic genetic mutations that predispose them to disease.
To conduct this examination, I draw upon fruitful interactions from my work with
a multidisciplinary network of scientists, neurologists, psychologists, philosophers,
representatives of insurance companies, and carers. The effort was carried out under
the auspices of the French national program “Distalz” headed by Professor Philippe
Amouyel, and with the methods established by Professor Emmanuel Hirsch in the
“Espace éthique régional Ile de France” (Forum for Ethics of Care Ile de France), that
became for the occasion “Espace éthique maladies neurodégénératives” (Forum for
Ethics of Neurodegenerative Diseases).
Diagnostic biomarkers
Alzheimer’s disease develops clinically in several stages: a presymptomatic period when
the biological process leading to the disease is active but the patient does not suffer any
disorder, a prodromal phase where the patient suffers from mild cognitive impairment
(MCI), and finally the gradual onset of increasingly severe dementia. In the past, the
diagnosis of AD was based on postmortem neuropathological changes of the brain that
included both positive and negative features. Positive lesions consist of abundant amyloid
plaques and neurofibrillary tangles, and dystrophic neurites containing hyperphosphory-
lated tau protein. Amyloid plaques are found throughout the cortex whereas tangles are
primarily located in limbic and association areas. Early lesions are found in the entorhi-
nal cortex. Later in the progression of the disease, lesions diffuse to the hippocampus,
then association cortex, and finally the primary neocortex. Astrogliosis and activation of
microglia complete this scheme. Negative lesions include losses of neurons and synaptic
elements. Today, biomarkers signal these lesions while the patient is still alive. They are
used to validate the clinical diagnosis and to quantify the level of advancement of the
297
disease through the concentration of the ß-amyloid protein and of the tau protein (total
and under its hyperphosphorylated form) in the cerebrospinal fluid (CSF) and by brain
imaging.
The pathophysiological process of AD has been modeled as a cascade of progressive
neuropathological events initiated by ß-amyloid deposition that is mirrored by a low
level of the CSF Aß42, followed by accumulation of tau (levels increased in CSF) preced-
ing structural brain damage, decreased cerebral glucose metabolism, brain atrophy, and
subsequent functional and cognitive impairments (Jack et al. 2016). Structural magnetic
resonance imaging (MRI) allows brain medial temporal cortex atrophy to be identified,
and rules out intracranial causes of dementia such as meningioma or subdural hema-
toma. Additionally, MRI remains the modality of choice for the assessment of vascular
brain changes, such as white matter hyperintensities, lacunes, and microbleeds that have
gained increasing attention because they are frequent side effects in antiamyloid trials
(Winblad et al. 2016). New techniques of cerebral imaging help to visualize hypome-
tabolism, amyloid plaques, neurofibrillary tangles, and the microglial activation. [18F]
Fluorodeoxyglucose positron emission tomography (FDG PET) reveals focal cerebral
hypometabolism in a very sensible and validated way. A normal FDG PET scan virtually
excludes a diagnosis of neurodegenerative disease. Consequently, FDG PET is increas-
ingly used to follow the disease progression and evaluate the effectiveness of interven-
tions to modify the natural course of the disease. Amyloid PET, namely PET with ligands
for Aβ such as florbetapir, florbetaben, and flutemetamol, which have been approved for
clinical use, has a high negative predictive value since a patient with cognitive impairment
and negative amyloid PET is unlikely to have AD (Jack et al. 2016).
Recent longitudinal studies on subjects without cognitive symptoms at the beginning
of the study have shown that the coexistence of events in the amyloid biological cas-
cade predict brain structural and functional declines (Bateman et al. 2012). Analysis of
natural history in familial AD cases with mutations in the gene coding for the amyloid
protein (APP), or in genes coding for presenilin (PSEN1 or PSEN2) that are the cata-
lytic subunits to the γ secretases enzyme which cleave APP, show that Aß42 levels in
CSF begin to decline 25 years before expected symptom onset (Selkoe & Hardy 2016).
This is followed by the appearance of fibrillar amyloid deposits in the brain, increased
levels of hyperphosphorylated tau in CSF, and progressive brain atrophy (particularly that
of hippocampus) that occur 15 years before the onset of symptoms. Neuronal hypome-
tabolism and short episodes of memory impairments begin 10 years before symptoms
become clinically self-evident. According to current models, mutations in APP, PSEN1,
and PSEN2 genes in familial AD accelerate the generation of fibrillar amyloid deposits,
whereas in sporadic AD, decreased clearance of Aβ associated with other pro-aggregating
conditions might have roles in the accumulation of toxic Aβ species. But most authors
consider that the time course of the disease should be similar in familial and sporadic AD
(Villemagne et al. 2013). This is based on the conceptual framework that β-amyloid and
tau pathologies synergistically potentiate neurodegeneration (Winblad et al. 2016). This
synergistic framework challenges previous AD pathophysiological theories that focused
298
on either ß-amyloid or tau pathologies as the main driving forces of disease progression,
the so-called Baptists and Tauist perspectives respectively. Furthermore, data from ani-
mal models support the synergistic molecular interactions between ß-amyloid and P-tau
peptides, which lead to a downstream toxicity. In a recent survey, Dubois and colleagues
consider that: “AD exists and can be recognized before the onset of cognitive symptoms
when there is little doubt about progression to clinical disease over a short period. This
is the case when both tauopathy (tau PET ligand uptake spread to neocortex or CSF) and
amyloidopathy (PET evidence of AD pattern or CSF measured) are present” (Dubois et
al. 2016, p.297). A key lesson that emerges from such studies is that therapeutic interven-
tions must come soon in the course of the disease and certainly before neuronal lesions
are irreversible.
Interestingly, some authors still consider the amyloid hypothesis as controversial.
Among their arguments are that many of the supporting animal studies used nonphysi-
ologically high concentrations of Aß or transgenic mice significantly overexpress APP
or any other gene. As such, they infer that the amyloid cascade hypothesis provides no
explanation for the silent incubation period of AD and pinpoint the many discrepan-
cies between neuropathological observations and clinical outcomes. In a recent review,
De Strooper and Kerran (2016) suggest a model with three phases, a biochemical phase,
a cellular phase, and the final clinical phase. In the biochemical phase, Aß and tau are
still at the beginning of the pathological process. In the cellular phase, compensatory
mechanisms allow a fragile but long-lasting equilibrium that involves neural networks,
microglia, astroglia, and oligodendrocytes. Finally, during the clinical phase, the system
is overwhelmed and collapses. Thus, they state that “AD is indeed not a biochemical or
molecular problem but a physiological one of disrupted cellular connectivity. The disease
can therefore only be fully understood in the context of the complex cellular interactions
that maintain homeostasis in the brain—i.e., at the level of the neurovascular and glioneu-
ronal units” (De Strooper & Karran 2016, p.612). Consequently, the therapeutic approach
should move from targeting Aß toward a support of the many mechanisms involved in
the cellular phase and allowing compensation: another good reason to make a diagnosis
of AD before the onset of symptoms.
should help to define individuals at higher risk of developing AD and the speed of pro-
gression of the disease (Lacour et al. 2017). Such data might help to set up a rationale
framework for early interventions in the context of anticipation (Peters et al. 2013; Dubois
et al. 2016).
More than 20 genetic loci associated with an increased risk of AD (Karch & Goate
2015) have been identified so far; a few others could have protective effects. The proteins
encoded by these genes belong to pathways involved in the immune system and inflam-
matory responses, for example, the microglia surface receptor TREM2, cholesterol and
lipid metabolism, and endosomal-vesicle recycling. Some factors could be age related.
Identification of these genes is important to understand the pathophysiology of AD since
they probably interact with the core mechanisms of the disease. However, they do not
improve our evaluation of the risk for a given person since most of the reported poly-
morphisms are frequent in the population—more than 30% of the population bear the
allele—and contribute little to the individual risk for AD (Lacour et al. 2017). That said,
APOE4 is different. APOE proteins are involved in cholesterol metabolism and in the
clearance of Aß. The E4 form has a reduced activity in comparison to E2 and E3, and
APOE4 is considered the major genetic risk factor for AD. APOE4 protein expression
has been associated with degeneration of brain blood vessels, leakage of the blood–brain
barrier, and neurodegeneration independent of Aβ. Lifetime risk for AD is more than
50% for APOE4 homozygotes and 20–30% for APOE3 and APOE4 heterozygotes, com-
pared with 11% for men and 14% for women overall irrespective of APOE genotype. Not
only does the frequency matter, but so does age at clinical onset: 68 years in E4 homozy-
gotes, 76 years in E4 heterozygotes, and 84 years in E4 noncarriers (Karch & Goate, 2015).
Consequently, APOE analysis is of importance today to define a population with a clearly
higher risk of AD.
Lifestyle-related factors also influence the age of onset and the delay to progression,
with much evidence concerned with interventions for cardiovascular risk that improve
cognitive health at the population level. In addition, the prevention or treatment of diabe-
tes, obesity, depression, smoking, increasing physical exercise and prevention of mental
inactivity, increasing level of education, and the so-called cognitive reserve, and improv-
ing diet, might result in up to a 30% reduction in dementia incidence (Scheltens et al.
2016). By contrast, the additional presence of a biomarker of tau pathology is associated
with a more rapid progression to clinical AD (Vos et al. 2013).
No marker has been described that indicates a rapid onset of symptoms. However, sub-
jective cognitive decline, defined as the personal sensation of cognitive decline despite
results within healthy limits on cognitive tests, is associated with an increased risk of pro-
gression to dementia, especially when the patient is worried about the decline (Scheltens
et al. 2016). Compared with healthy controls, patients with subjective cognitive decline
have more brain abnormalities, including hippocampal volume loss and hypometabolism.
Some data suggest that an evaluation of the progression speed might be possible in
the future, but the results remain at a population level and are not valid for a given
individual (Vos & Fagan 2016). Most of the available data result from the observation
30
of the progression of the disease in symptomatic patients, either with MCI or pro-
dromal or moderate AD, which might not be informative for asymptomatic patients.
Furthermore, these results need more patients to be really confirmative. One set of evi-
dence correlates patient age with localization of the first lesions: elderly patients with
a predominant limbic form of the disease generally have a slower progression com-
pared to the neocortical form with a hippocampal-sparing type that can be observed
in younger patients. Brain imaging studies have demonstrated that MCI patients with
hippocampal atrophy or temporoparietal hypometabolism as seen on FDG PET, and
CSF Aβ42, invariably developed dementia, whereas those with negative results for all
three parameters almost never did (Vos et al. 2015). Among new biomarkers measur-
able in the CSF are neurogranin and SNAP25 (De Vos et al. 2015). Neurogranin is
a dendritic protein involved in acquisition and consolidation of memory. High CSF
concentrations of neurogranin predict progression to AD in patients with MCI and
correlate with rapid cognitive deterioration. SNAP25 is a presynaptic protein and
its concentrations increase during the prodromal stage. Their value in anticipating
the clinical onset delay remains to be determined, and would require repeated CSF
punctures.
One concern about selecting at-risk individuals for preventive clinical trials is that this
could involve coercive disclosure of unwanted information (Kim et al. 2015). A normative
analysis applying four key ethical criteria—favorable risk:benefit ratio, informed consent,
fair subject selection, and scientific validity—investigated the meaning of blinded enroll-
ment where participants are tested but not told of their risk marker status (Kim et al.
2015). The authors concluded that none of these ethical criteria supports blinded enroll-
ment over transparent enrollment. Furthermore, blinded enrollment protocols have been
criticized ethically for non-respect of the fundamental rights of a person participating in
biomedical research to have access to information. Among arguments to refuse access to
the personal data is the context of research that does not reach the clinical grade of exams
performed in a healthcare program.
Other studies reported that subjects with increased genetic risk for AD (i.e., carriers of
the APOE4 allele who knew their status), more frequently desired to reduce that risk than
did counterparts who learned they were noncarriers. Moreover, the duration of treatment
that is to be undertaken is crucial. A period of 1 year instead of 5 years can change the
game in terms of acceptability. Inclusion in a clinical trial disrupts daily life. For example,
often a person must be available for sampling in a 10-day window. Why would someone
accept such constraints on daily life if not affected by the disease? The rationale that doc-
tors and scientists need information about the long natural history and ongoing process
appears insufficiently justified to many individuals. Furthermore, the needs of biomedical
science and hopes of the prospective subjects who have their own life prospects may not
always align.
Such considerations will be even more important in the context of drug trials with
completely asymptomatic patients. The anticipation of consent is in the air. In North
America, records of individuals who volunteer for clinical trials have been established for
solicitation purposes, not necessarily on genetic bases. In a sense, pre-consent is in play.
Registered individuals decide to volunteer depending on the protocol that is offered. This
type of prearranged consent may be revoked or amended. A conceptual framework for
prevention trials for AD has been proposed (Peters et al. 2013). A first dimension of this
framework focuses on stratification of patients according to their genetic risk for AD and
detection of AD biomarkers. The framework then proposes two gradients that refer to the
risk of developing AD and to a therapeutic risk:benefit ratio. Interestingly, this framework
also considers the critical need to revisit the risk:benefit ratio iteratively during the trial.
The risks that individuals enrolled in an AD clinical trial will face are only beginning
to be known. For example, repeated MRI scans sensitive to microbleeds are mandatory
in clinical trials of antiamyloid drugs to monitor amyloid-related imaging abnormali-
ties (ARIAs) (Arrighi et al. 2016). These include signal hyperintensities on FLAIR (fluid
attenuation inversion recovery) sequences, which are thought to represent edema, and
signal hypointensities on gradient-recalled echo/T2, which are thought to represent hae-
mosiderin deposits, including microhemorrhage and superficial siderosis. ARIAs develop
after removal of amyloid from cerebral microvessels, which leads to endothelial damage,
increased vascular permeability, and leakage of water or blood in the brain parenchyma.
30
Conclusion 303
Are the risks involved in preventing AD justifiable? This has been the current practice
since the middle of the twentieth century. The relationship between myocardial infarction
and high cholesterol was demonstrated around 1955, resulting in prevention strategies
to lower cholesterol. Several tested molecules such as thyroxin and estrogens performed
worse than hypercholesterolemia. Many clinical trials conducted in the 1960s and 1970s
would end up in court today. What risks are justifiable? In the late 1960s, side effects were
tolerated a risk of 1 in 100. Today no company would want to take a risk of 1 in 10,000.
The sensitivity of the public has changed considerably, calling into question which types of
clinical research in AD prevention and early diagnosis should be accepted and which ones
are unethical. Taking into consideration the conceptual framework mentioned previously
(Peters et al. 2013), it seems highly justified to take some risk when uncertainties are low
(i.e., familial AD or two copies of the APOE4 allele) or when the toxicity is low (i.e., diet
or exercise). Regarding AD, everyone should be aware of the risks inherent in the devel-
opment of new treatments, including lawyers and journalists. Biomedical research in the
field of neurodegenerative disorders may necessarily face devastating unexpected effects
such as cases of encephalitis when testing new molecules. Omitting risk is no longer con-
ceivable. We need to inform. Justifying the search every day is to be able to justify the risks
we take. There are several ways to present a risk (absolute risk, relative, over a period) to a
contact, and we must use appropriate words. Dedicated research on such communication
should be developed and investigators will need to conceptualize the process of consent
as being dynamic rather than static (Peters et al. 2013).
Finally, are we studying the right cases? I cannot stress enough the fact that the aver-
age age of onset of dementia is 80 years. In most cases, there is a combination of a
degenerative neurological factor and a vascular factor. However, it is clear that clinical
trials, at present, involve almost only subjects age 70 years or less with few comorbidi-
ties. A question of representativeness of the real disease in clinical experimentation is
indispensable.
Conclusion
Considering the natural history of AD, there are more and more arguments to antici-
pate and try to prevent the onset of the disease. We may consider similarly a better diet,
exercise, and increase of the cognitive reserve. Apart from the rather soft general control
induced on our lifestyle, one might hardly see ethical issues in such early interventions.
Much more complex remains the question of primary prevention and enrollment of at-
risk individuals in clinical trials targeted against amyloid. Multidisciplinary research,
including ethical, legal, and social aspects, is needed to investigate how best to inform
and anticipate reactions of patients, and their families, to the knowledge of their sta-
tus, and how to support individuals undergoing long periods of treatments with high
constraints, unknown risks, and unknown benefits. They should be valued as ordinary
heroes fighting against ignorance that is the main enemy. A new partnership needs to
be set up between at-risk individuals, clinicians, scientists, and society to defeat AD for
once and for all.
304
References
Albert, M.S., Dekosky, S.T., Dickson, D., et al. (2011). The diagnosis of mild cognitive impairment
due to Alzheimer’s disease: recommendations from the National Institute on Aging-Alzheimer’s
Association workgroups on diagnostic guidelines for Alzheimer’s disease. Alzheimer’s & Dementia,
7, 270–279.
Arrighi, H.M., Barakos, J., Barkhof, F., et al. (2016). Amyloid-related imaging abnormalities-
haemosiderin (ARIA-H) in patients with Alzheimer’s disease treated with bapineuzumab: a
historical, prospective secondary analysis. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 87,
106–112.
Bateman, R.J., Xiong, C., Benzinger, T.L., et al. (2012). Clinical and biomarker changes in dominantly
inherited Alzheimer’s disease. New England Journal of Medicine, 367, 795–804.
De Strooper, B. and Karran, E. (2016). The cellular phase of Alzheimer’s disease. Cell, 164, 603–615.
De Vos, A., Jacobs, D., Struyfs, H., et al. (2015). C-terminal neurogranin is increased in cerebrospinal
fluid but unchanged in plasma in Alzheimer’s disease. Alzheimer’s & Dementia, 11, 1461–1469.
Dubois, B., Feldman, H.H., Jacova, C., et al. (2014). Advancing research diagnostic criteria for
Alzheimer’s disease: the IWG-2 criteria. Lancet Neurology, 13, 614–629.
Dubois, B., Hampel, H., Feldman, H.H., et al. (2016). Preclinical Alzheimer’s disease: definition,
natural history, and diagnostic criteria. Alzheimer’s & Dementia, 12, 292–323.
Jack, C.R., Jr., Bennett, D.A., Blennow, K., et al. (2016). A/T/N: an unbiased descriptive classification
scheme for Alzheimer disease biomarkers. Neurology, 87(5), 539–547.
Karch, C.M. and Goate, A.M. (2015). Alzheimer’s disease risk genes and mechanisms of disease
pathogenesis. Biological Psychiatry, 77, 43–51.
Kim, S.Y., Karlawish, J., and Berkman, B.E. (2015). Ethics of genetic and biomarker test disclosures in
neurodegenerative disease prevention trials. Neurology, 84, 1488–1494.
Lacour, A., Espinosa, A., Louwersheimer, E., et al. (2017). Genome-wide significant risk factors for
Alzheimer’s disease: role in progression to dementia due to Alzheimer’s disease among subjects with
mild cognitive impairment. Molecular Psychiatry, 22(1), 153–160.
Peters, K.R., Lynn Beattie, B., Feldman, H.H., and Illes, J. (2013). A conceptual framework and ethics
analysis for prevention trials of Alzheimer disease. Progress in Neurobiology, 110, 114–123.
Price, J.L., McKeel, D.W., Jr., Buckles, V.D., et al. (2009). Neuropathology of nondemented
aging: presumptive evidence for preclinical Alzheimer disease. Neurobiology of Aging, 30,
1026–1036.
Scheltens, P., Blennow, K., Breteler, M.M., et al. (2016). Alzheimer’s disease. The Lancet, 388, 505–517.
Selkoe, D.J. and Hardy, J. (2016). The amyloid hypothesis of Alzheimer’s disease at 25 years. EMBO
Molecular Medicine, 8, 595–608.
Villemagne, V.L., Burnham, S., Bourgeat, P., et al. (2013). Amyloid beta deposition, neurodegeneration,
and cognitive decline in sporadic Alzheimer’s disease: a prospective cohort study. Lancet Neurology,
12, 357–367.
Vos, S.J. and Fagan, A.M. (2016). Alzheimer’s disease biomarker states. Lancet Neurology, 15, 25–26.
Vos, S.J., Xiong, C., Visser, P.J., et al. (2013). Preclinical Alzheimer’s disease and its outcome: a
longitudinal cohort study. Lancet Neurology, 12, 957–965.
Vos, S.J., Verhey, F., Frolich, L., et al. (2015). Prevalence and prognosis of Alzheimer’s disease at the
mild cognitive impairment stage. Brain, 138, 1327–1338.
Winblad, B., Amouyel, P., Andrieu, S., et al. (2016). Defeating Alzheimer’s disease and other
dementias: a priority for European science and society. Lancet Neurology, 15, 455–532.
305
Chapter 17
Introduction
Of the many disorders of the brain, disorders of consciousness are among the most devas-
tating. They have profound implications for whether an individual is considered capable
of experiencing the world, or even considered alive. However, despite the critical implica-
tions, there remains substantial uncertainty about how they are defined and diagnosed,
leading to uncertainty in how these patients are understood and managed. What makes a
person conscious, and how can one person know if another is conscious? What makes a
person dead, and how can one know if another is dead? These questions have challenged
philosophers for centuries. Meanwhile, however, the ability to ethically manage patients
who suffer from disorders of consciousness critically depends upon the answers to these
questions.
Distinguishing between disorders of consciousness has been vital to guiding impor-
tant clinical decisions. However, we argue that disorders of consciousness are not suf-
ficiently distinct to dictate these decisions. After defining each disorder of consciousness
and discussing the decisions that hinge upon the diagnostic distinctions, we will outline
the factors that, upon closer inspection, obscure these distinctions. We argue that the
non-distinct diagnostic boundaries reflect an inherent continuity between disorders of
consciousness. Then we consider a new way of thinking about disorders of conscious-
ness, permitting these diagnoses to more effectively guide decisions. We believe that these
considerations bring clarity to disorders of consciousness, and can improve the ethical
management of patients suffering from them.
Brain death
We will describe each disorder in order of severity, beginning with the most severe. Thus,
the first we will consider is brain death. (Table 17.1) Though not classically included
among other disorders of consciousness—as it is often considered a more severe form
of brain injury with more grave implications—brain death represents a state of disor-
dered consciousness following brain injury. We include it among the other disorders of
consciousness here.
Conceptually, brain death is considered a form of death. Death has been a challenge
to define precisely, and its medical definition has evolved continuously since the 1700s
(Powner et al. 1996). In 1981, neurologist James Bernat built from these concepts to pro-
pose death as the “permanent cessation of functioning of the organism as a whole” (Bernat
et al. 1981, p.390). Bernat argues that the “whole” of an organism consists in the “highly
complex interaction of its organ subsystems,” and “the spontaneous and innate activities
carried out by the integration of all or most subsystems … and at least limited response
to the environment” (Bernat et al. 1981, p.390). Wholeness of an organism can also be
understood through thermodynamic principles: an organism perhaps can be considered
living so long as it employs energy-consuming processes to oppose entropic forces and
maintain homeostasis, thereby preserving itself as an entity distinct from the surrounding
world (Truog 2015).
How does one recognize when an organism has permanently ceased to function as a
whole? In the same year that Bernat offered his conceptual definition of death, the 1981
President’s Commission proposed a legal framework by which this definition could be
recognized, which led to the Uniform Determination of Death Act (Medical Consultants
on the Diagnosis of Death 1981). Under this definition, any individual is considered
dead if he or she has (1) irreversible cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions,
or (2) irreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain, including the brainstem.
The latter criterion comprises the diagnostic criterion for brain death. That is, a person is
thought to meet the conceptual definition of death (the permanent cessation of function-
ing as a whole) if he/she exhibits the irreversible cessation of all brain function. Bernat
argues that the irreversible cessation of all brain functions is sufficient for the permanent
cessation of functioning of the organism of the whole, “because the brain is necessary
for the functioning of the organism as a whole. It integrates, generates, interrelates, and
controls complex bodily activities” (Bernat et al. 1981, p.391).
The diagnostic criterion of brain death as the irreversible cessation of all brain func-
tions was subsequently fleshed out with more specific criteria. In 1995, the American
Academy of Neurology published a set of such criteria (Report of the Quality Standards
307
Vegetative Wakefulness without aware- ◆ Eye opening and closing that appear to follow
state/ ness of self or environment sleep–wake cycles
unresponsive ◆ Incapable of interaction with others
wakefulness ◆ No language comprehension or expression
syndrome ◆ Reflexive behavior only, without any purposeful
behaviors. Behaviors can include:
• Spontaneous breathing
• Move trunk or limbs non-purposefully, arch
back, posturing
• Blink, roving eye movements, nystagmus,
and brief, unsustained visual pursuit
• Move head or eyes briefly toward sound or
movement
• Auditory startle and startle myoclonus
• Grimace to pain
• Yawn, chewing movements,
swallowing saliva
• Reflexive crying, smiling without provoking
stimuli
• Vocalizations without words
• Withdrawal from noxious stimuli
Minimally Wakefulness with partial ◆ Eye opening and closing that appear to follow
conscious state awareness of self or sleep–wake cycles
environment ◆ One or more of the following behaviors on a
reproducible or sustained basis:
• Following simple commands
• Gestural or verbal yes/no responses (regard-
less of accuracy)
(continued)
308 3
Table 17.1 Continued
Source: data from Bernat et al. 1981; Medical Consultants on the Diagnosis of Death to the President’s Commission
for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medical and Biomedical and Behavioral Research 1981; Report of the Quality
Standards Subcommittee of the American Academy of Neurology 1995; Wijdicks et al. 2010 (Brain death); Giacino
et al. 2002; Laureys et al. 2004; Bernat 2006; Posner et al. 2007 (Coma); The Multi-Society Task Force on PVS 1994a;
Giacino 2004; Bernat 2006 (Vegetative state/unresponsive wakefulness syndrome); Giacino et al. 2002 (Minimally
conscious state).
Subcommittee of the American Academy of Neurology 1995; Wijdicks et al. 2010): in
addition to coma (described in more detail later), patients must have an identifiable cata-
strophic brain injury, no confounding conditions (e.g., medical instability, drug toxicity,
hypothermia), absent brainstem reflexes (e.g., pupillary, ocular, facial sensation/motor,
pharyngeal and tracheal reflexes), and apnea (i.e., an absent respiratory drive). Optional
ancillary assessments, which are not required for the diagnosis of brain death, include
a repeat evaluation 6 hours after initial assessment (required by some US states), con-
ventional angiography, magnetic resonance angiography, electroencephalography (EEG),
transcranial Doppler ultrasonography, cerebral scintigraphy, and other technological
assessments. Together, these clinical criteria were proposed as a means of determining
that all functions of the entire brain, including the brainstem, have been irreversibly lost.
Coma
Coma, a component of the diagnostic criteria for brain death, represents the next most
severe disorder of consciousness. To understand the conceptual definition of coma, it
is first important to consider what comprises consciousness. Like death, consciousness
is difficult to define, and so its precise definition has been a matter of debate among
309
philosophers and scientists for centuries. However, there is general agreement that con-
sciousness consists of two primary components: arousal (i.e., wakefulness) and aware-
ness (i.e., the content of experience) (Posner et al. 2007; Laureys et al. 2009). Awareness
requires arousal, in that one must be awake in order to be aware (Posner et al. 2007;
Laureys et al. 2009).1 However, one can be awake without being aware, as in other disor-
ders of consciousness described later in this chapter.
Within this framework, coma is conceptually defined as the total absence of conscious-
ness, where wakefulness, and therefore also awareness, are both lost (Giacino et al. 2002;
Laureys et al. 2004; Posner et al. 2007). Diagnostically, the loss of wakefulness is identified
by the absence of eye opening, either spontaneously or to vigorous sensory stimulation,
and low cortical arousal (e.g., polymorphic delta, burst-suppression) on EEG (Giacino
et al. 2002; Laureys et al. 2004; Bernat 2006; Posner et al. 2007). Behaviorally, comatose
patients exhibit only reflexive and postural responses, without responding to auditory
or visual stimuli (Giacino et al. 2002; Bernat 2006; Posner et al. 2007). These diagnostic
features must persist for more than an hour, to ensure that they are not attributable to a
transient state of unconsciousness, such as syncope or concussion (Laureys et al. 2004).
It should also be noted that, in comparison to the other disorders of consciousness
described here, coma may be a more temporary state, rarely lasting longer than a month,
with most patients dying, regaining consciousness, or progressing to another disorder of
consciousness (Bernat 2006).
Minimally conscious state
Following establishment of the VS/UWS, clinicians recognized that some awake patients
were neither fully unaware (i.e., in a VS/UWS) nor fully aware, exhibiting signs of par-
tial awareness. In 2002, neuropsychologist Joseph Giacino and colleagues proposed a
new diagnostic category to describe such patients, labeled the minimally conscious state
(MCS) (Giacino et al. 2002). The MCS is conceptually defined as a state of preserved
wakefulness with only partial awareness of the self or environment.
In terms of diagnostic criteria, like VS/UWS patients, MCS patients exhibit sleep–wake
cycles through spontaneous eye opening and eye closing. Unlike VS/UWS patients, MCS
patients exhibit awareness of themselves or the environment, albeit only partially and
intermittently. Giacino and colleagues proposed that empirical evidence of such aware-
ness is the reproducible and sustained demonstration of one or more of the following
behaviors: simple command following, answering of yes/no questions, intelligible verbal-
izations, or any other purposeful, non-reflexive behaviors, including appropriate smiling/
crying in response to emotional stimuli, reaching for objects, or eye-tracking a target
(Giacino et al. 2002).
between these various conditions is critical to ensuring that patients are treated ethically.
Two distinctions between these disorders are especially crucial in dictating how patients
are managed: the distinction between brain death and coma, and between the VS/UWS
and MCS.
Thus, for many, determining whether a patient has lost consciousness (as in the VS/UWS)
or retains consciousness (as in the MCS) plays an important role in determining whether
LST is continued.
Second, some have suggested that the presence of consciousness has important impli-
cations for civil rights. Fins, in his book Rights Come to Mind: Brain Injury, Ethics, and
the Struggle for Consciousness, writes that “to my mind, there is nothing more important
than knowing that a patient may be conscious” (Fins 2015, p.201). Fins argues that being
conscious means being entitled to civil rights. Because MCS patients are conscious (albeit
minimally so) he argues that they are therefore entitled to the same civil rights as anyone
else, and that to treat MCS patients otherwise is an act of segregation. Though Fins centers
his arguments on MCS, the implication is that, by virtue of having lost conscious aware-
ness, VS/UWS patients are no longer entitled to that same range of civil rights. If indeed
the presence of consciousness is what dictates a person’s entitlement to civil rights, the
31
distinction between MCS and VS/UWS has major implications for whether patients are
granted or denied these rights.
A third more mundane but still significant implication of this diagnostic distinction is
a humanistic one. To family and loved ones, it matters if a patient is “in there” and aware
of their presence and attempts at communication, which may influence how they inter-
act with the patient (Fins 2015). For clinicians and healthcare providers, knowing that
a patient is conscious, with a quality of life, may encourage them to talk to the patients,
to reposition them, and to provide comfort in other ways. These everyday differences in
how patients are perceived and treated critically depend upon whether they are felt to be
conscious or unconscious, and therefore hinge on the distinction between the MCS and
VS/UWS.
Having acknowledged the inconsistency between the diagnostic criteria and conceptual
definition of brain death, they attempted to solve the problem by proposing a revised
conceptual definition of death. They suggested that death represents the inability to per-
form the “vital work” of the organism as a whole, where “vital work” consists of three
components:
1. [R]eceptivity to stimuli and signals from the surrounding environment.
2. The ability to act upon the world to obtain selectively what it needs.
3. The basic felt need that drives the organism to act as it must, to obtain what it needs. (p.61)
However, this conceptual definition is also problematic (Miller & Truog 2009; Truog
2015). If “vital work” requires conscious awareness (as implied by an “ability to act upon
316 3
the world” and a “felt need”), then VS/UWS patients and perhaps even MCS patients
would be considered dead, a position the Council specifically rejected. If, alternatively,
“vital work” only refers to unconscious bodily functions that respond to the environment
(e.g., mounting an immune response to infection) and interact with the environment in
accordance with the body’s needs (e.g., absorbing oxygen and digesting nutrients), then
the same diagnostic–conceptual discrepancy remains; as described, many patients who
meet the diagnostic criteria for brain death are capable of several such bodily functions.
Thus, the Council’s proposition does not solve the incongruity between the diagnostic
criteria and conceptual definition of brain death.
It is also worth noting that the irreversibility/permanence required of both the over-
arching diagnostic criterion of brain death (the irreversible cessation of brain functions)
and conceptual definition (the permanent cessation of functioning of the organism as
a whole) imposes an additional discrepancy between the diagnostic criteria and con-
ceptual definition of brain death. Irreversibility and permanence are both statements of
prognosis, or predictions for the future. While diagnoses may be associated with certain
prognoses, even with high probability, it is problematic to require a prognosis in the very
conceptual definition of a diagnosis, as doing so theoretically requires a certain predic-
tion of the future. Even if, ignoring the earlier arguments, the diagnostic criteria for brain
death actually reflected the cessation of all brain function or the cessation of all integrated
functioning of the organism, and even if all patients who met the diagnostic criteria for
brain death to date had never recovered those functions, it would still not be absolutely
certain that those diagnostic criteria would predict permanent/irreversible cessation
of those functions in 100% of future cases. Thus, while the diagnostic criteria for brain
death may be associated with an overwhelmingly poor prognosis, the requirement of the
prognosis in brain death’s very definition impossibly demands a prediction of the future,
thereby ensuring that the diagnostic criteria could, in principle, never match the over-
arching diagnostic criterion or conceptual definition with certainty.
To summarize, in order to effectively guide discrete decision-making, the distinction
between brain death and coma must be similarly discrete. Although the diagnostic crite-
ria for brain death and coma are in principle sufficiently discrete, the brain death criteria
do not accurately reflect the conceptual definition of brain death. As it is the conceptual
definition of brain death, as death, that justifies major decisions such as organ procure-
ment, this diagnostic/conceptual discrepancy indicates that the current diagnostic crite-
ria cannot adequately guide these decisions. That is, while one can definitively determine
that a patient fulfills the diagnostic criteria for brain death, as distinct from coma, one
cannot be confident that those diagnostic criteria meaningfully signify death in a way
that justifies organ procurement. We should also note that while we currently focus on
this problem as it pertains to the scientific and medical definition of death, this prob-
lem also extends to alternative religious and cultural definitions of death (Posner et al.
2007). Many, particularly those of orthodox religious groups and those with cultural
roots in Asia and the Middle East, feel that the diagnostic criteria for brain death do not
reflect their personal conceptions of death; in Japan, for example, two types of “death”
317
are commonly recognized—one suitable for patients who wish to be organ donors, and
another for everyone else (Lock 2002). Given the heterogeneity of views on brain death,
US states such as New Jersey and New York have chosen to accommodate religious and
moral objections to brain death testing (Kimura 1991; Posner et al. 2007). Thus, overall,
the diagnostic distinction between brain death and coma does not accurately reflect their
conceptual distinction as death and life, respectively, thus undermining the utility of these
diagnostic distinctions in guiding decisions.
the crux of the diagnostic distinction is that while VS/UWS patients exhibit only reflex-
ive behaviors, MCS patients exhibit both reflexive and purposeful behaviors. The logic
of these diagnostic criteria is that purposeful behaviors reflect volition, which can exist
only in those who are conscious. While this is true, the same logic does not follow
in the absence of these behaviors. Patients are given a VS/UWS if they exhibit only
reflexive behaviors, that is, if they are not observed exhibiting any purposeful behav-
iors. However, first, just because purposeful behaviors are not observed or recognized
does not necessarily mean that purposeful behaviors are absent. Second, the absence
of purposeful behaviors does not necessarily imply the absence of volition. And third,
the absence of volition does not necessarily imply the absence of awareness. We can
imagine many scenarios—patients who are blind, deaf, aphasic, confused, apathetic,
paralyzed, or even intermittently conscious, for example—where conscious patients are
not recognized as such on the basis of observable purposeful behaviors. Thus, in clini-
cally distinguishing VS/UWS from MCS, the absence of evidence is not necessarily the
evidence of absence; the diagnostic criteria for these disorders imperfectly reflect their
conceptual definitions.
Neuroimaging technology has poignantly revealed the danger of assuming that the
absence of purposeful behaviors represents the absence of consciousness. In 2006,
neuroscientist Adrian Owen and colleagues published a study on a 23-year-old woman
who sustained traumatic brain injury after a road traffic accident (Owen et al. 2006).
She continued to demonstrate sleep–wake cycles, but was behaviorally unresponsive,
and so was given the diagnosis of VS/UWS. However, using functional magnetic reso-
nance imaging (fMRI), Owen and colleagues found that she could reliably respond to
commands through fMRI signals. When asked to imagine playing tennis, she exhib-
ited activity in the supplementary motor area, a region associated with planning move-
ment. When asked to imagine walking through the rooms of her house, she exhibited
activity in regions associated with spatial navigation, such as the parahippocampal
gyrus. These activity patterns were indistinguishable from those observed in healthy
individuals. Moreover, these activations did not appear to be reflexive reactions to the
words “tennis” or “house,” but rather intentionally generated; the patient’s responses
lasted up to 30 seconds (longer than would be expected from a transient, automatic
reaction) and only until the experimenters asked her to stop (Hopkin 2006). Another
study found additional patients who, despite being behaviorally unresponsive, were
similarly able to complete this fMRI task (Monti et al. 2010). One of these patients,
who was behaviorally noncommunicative, could correctly answer yes-or-no questions
with this task, imagining one scenario to signal “yes” and the other scenario to sig-
nal “no.” These neuroimaging studies demonstrated that a subset of patients who are
behaviorally unresponsive and meet the diagnostic criteria for VS/UWS in fact do have
conscious awareness, thereby meeting the conceptual definition of MCS, and perhaps
even retaining higher levels of consciousness (Fischer & Truog 2013). These instances
further illustrate a significant discrepancy between the conditions’ diagnostic criteria
and conceptual definitions.
319
Thus, when we try to explain how the whole system behaves, we have to talk about the context of
the whole and cannot get away talking only about the parts. (Gilbert & Sarkar 2000, p.1)
Thus, the definition of life is an inherently wholistic one: life emerges not through inde-
pendently functioning tissues and organ systems, but through the interactions and inte-
gration of those organ systems to produce a whole.2 Importantly, because the whole
must emerge from the interactions of its parts, wholism depends upon emergentism, the
notion that:
properties at one level of complexity (for instance, tissues) cannot be ascribed directly to their com-
ponent parts but arise only because of the interactions among the parts. Such properties that are
not those of any part but that arise through the interactions of parts are called emergent properties.
(Gilbert & Sarkar 2000, p.2)
For example, wetness and temperature can be considered emergent properties of mole-
cules; while an individual water molecule cannot be considered wet or to have a tempera-
ture, it is the larger-scale interaction of many water molecules through which wetness or
temperature emerges. Similarly, life can be considered an emergent property of the inter-
actions between tissues and organ systems, a view endorsed by The President’s Council
on Bioethics, which has written that the integrated functioning of life “is an emergent
property of the whole organism” (The President’s Council on Bioethics 2008, p.40).
Life, so considered, has important implications for death. Given that emergent proper-
ties typically arise gradually out of increasingly complex interactions between constitu-
ent parts, so too do emergent properties disappear gradually from decreasingly complex
interactions. For instance, just as there is no defined number of water molecules above
which wetness appears—wetness emerges gradually out of an increasing number of water
molecules—there is also no defined number of water molecules below which wetness
is suddenly lost. Similarly, just as life emerges gradually from the increasingly complex
interactions of tissues and organ systems (as has been argued in the case of fetal devel-
opment (Gilbert & Sarkar 2000)), so too may death occur continuously, not discretely,
from the loss of those interactions. It should be noted that certain organ systems play a
particularly critical role in sustaining the interactions between organ systems; if the heart
stops beating, the loss of organ interactions, the loss of the organism as a whole, and hence
the death of the organism, occurs more rapidly than if the kidneys stopped functioning.
However, even in the case of cardiac arrest, death can still be understood as the continu-
ous, albeit rapid, cessation of the organ interactions that sustain the emergent property
of life.
Thermodynamic principles have been used to justify the discreteness of the life/death
distinction. An organism perhaps can be considered whole so long as it employs energy-
consuming processes to oppose entropic forces from the surrounding world. Thus,
perhaps at the moment when the entropic forces of the surrounding world exceed the
self-sustaining homeostatic forces of the organism, death can be said to discretely occur.
However, an organism may continue to exist after entropic forces exceed homeostatic
forces, just as beaches persist, while shrinking, after erosive forces exceed the accretive
321
forces. Thus, the moment at which the entropic forces exceed the homeostatic forces
of an organism may merely signify the beginning of dying, with death itself occurring
more continuously as entropic forces erode at the wholeness of the organism. Moreover,
because the entropic forces of the universe can vary in strength—natural disasters and
extreme temperatures may suddenly give way to calm weather—one can imagine scenar-
ios in which, at one moment the entropic forces exceed an organism’s homeostatic forces,
while in the next moment the entropic forces drop below that organism’s homeostatic
forces. It would seem implausible that that organism has died and returned to life, simply
due to variability in environmental forces. Thus, though in many cases it occurs rapidly,
death appears likely to be a fundamentally continuous occurrence.
If death is indeed a continuous occurrence, then no discrete diagnostic criteria can
perfectly segregate all live patients from all dead patients. Selecting discrete criteria for
death would be akin to selecting a number of water molecules below which wetness is
lost: no matter how they are defined, they will oversimplify an inherently continuous
range of conditions as binary categories. Depending on where the criteria are drawn,
some patients will be incorrectly considered dead (when they continue to function par-
tially as a whole), and/or some patients will be incorrectly considered alive (when their
wholeness has been partially lost).
The distinction between consciousness and unconsciousness is likely also a continu-
ous one. Like life, many consider consciousness to be an emergent property of the brain
(Edelman 1999). Philosopher John Searle writes that:
Just as one cannot reach into a glass of water and pick out a molecule and say “This one is wet,” so,
one cannot point to a single synapse or neuron in the brain and say “This one is thinking about my
grandmother.” (Searle 1992, cited in Gilbert & Sarkar 2000, p.2)
Because the diagnostic criteria for MCS includes following simple commands, answer-
ing yes/no questions, smiling/crying in response to emotional content, or reaching for
objects in a goal-directed manner, MCS patients were likely imagined to hear language
and comprehend its meaning, to see objects and perceive their desirability/purpose, and/
or to see people and recognize emotional valence. Awareness of the self also implies a
relatively sophisticated integration of sensation and cognition into a coherent sense of
self. However, one can imagine much more rudimentary forms of awareness: awareness,
for instance, only of color, sounds, or sensations, without awareness of objects or even of
a coherent environment per se, let alone of people, language, or a self. Thus, though the
MCS was created as an intermediary between the VS/UWS and normal consciousness,
the discrete distinction between VS/UWS and MCS may still be too crude, separated
by a continuum of consciousness between complete unawareness and awareness of the
self or environment. As in the distinction of life and death, if the distinction between
consciousness and unconsciousness is indeed a continuous one, then no discrete diag-
nostic criteria for MCS or VS/UWS will perfectly distinguish the conscious from the
unconscious.
be inherently unknowable, for at least three reasons. First, there is no clear “output” of
a person functioning as a whole. For example, the heart has the function of pumping
blood; thus, the functioning of the heart as a whole (i.e., the extent to which its compo-
nent tissues are operating and interacting properly) can be assessed by its cardiac output,
or its ability to effectively pump blood. In contrast, a person has no clear function, and
thus we have no functional output from which to gauge a person’s wholeness. Second,
even if, in theory, there exists some empirical metric—a certain behavior, or a particular
type of physiologic activity—that perfectly corresponds to the functioning of the organ-
ism as a whole, we have no way of identifying or validating it. That is, we could not know
that this metric corresponds to life, because for us to know, we would need to observe a
correspondence between this metric and life, and we have no way of knowing whether
life is present. For us to know that life is present, we would need a metric that perfectly
corresponds to the functioning of the organism as a whole, which traps us in circular-
ity. Third, the required permanence of the cessation of functioning of the organism as a
whole also makes death inherently unknowable, by demanding knowledge of prognosis
(a prediction of the future), as described earlier. Thus, the distinction between life and
death is empirically unknown, and may in principle be unknowable.
The detection of consciousness similarly suffers from an epistemological continuity, as
we have no set of empirical criteria that will perfectly distinguish those aware of the self
or environment from those who are not. Moreover, the line dividing consciousness from
unconsciousness may also be inherently unknowable. The adage that “the only conscious-
ness that we can truly know is our own” (Fins 2015, p.197) reflects the inherent subjectiv-
ity of consciousness. Thus, as in the distinction between life and death, the notion that an
empirical metric could perfectly distinguish consciousness from unconsciousness gener-
ates circularity, as defining such a metric would require us to distinguish consciousness
from unconsciousness in the first place. Thus, even if the distinction between conscious-
ness and unconsciousness is in principle discrete, we do not, and perhaps cannot, have an
empirical way of identifying it with precision.
Given the continuity between these conditions, it is no wonder that the current diagnostic
distinctions between brain death and coma, or between VS/UWS and MCS, do not suc-
cessfully draw discrete delineations. One can imagine, however, why they were intended
to. As described earlier, many significant, discrete decisions, such as whether to withdraw
LST or to procure vital organs for transplantation, hinge upon the conceptual distinctions
between life and death, or consciousness and unconsciousness. The desire to make these
discrete decisions likely drove the diagnostic criteria to become similarly discrete. This is
perhaps most clearly exemplified in the case of organ procurement in brain death. The
very conception of brain death can be traced back to the first heart transplant, conducted
in 1967 in South Africa (Barnard 1967; Truog 2015). The donor for the transplant was
selected on the basis of devastating neurological injury, though she was maintained on a
ventilator (Truog 2015). Recognizing that the criteria for devastating neurological injury
would need to be formalized if organ transplantation was to ethically continue, anesthe-
siologist Henry Beecher organized and chaired a committee to propose the first defini-
tion of brain death (Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School to Examine the
Definition of Brain Death 1968; Truog 2015). Given that the very notion of brain death
was born out of a need to definitively determine when organ procurement was ethical,
it is not surprising that the diagnostic criteria for brain death were made to be discrete.
The drive to establish discrete diagnostic distinctions for these continuous disorders
resulted in different problems in each case. For brain death and coma, the diagnostic
distinction succeeded in being discrete, but failed to reflect their conceptual distinction.
For VS/UWS and MCS, the diagnostic distinction was not discrete, nor did it reflect the
conceptual distinction.
approach best describes the mentality currently adopted, explicitly or implicitly, by the
medical community.
While this type of pretending may seem outlandish, there is indeed legal precedent for
it. Deliberately accepting a discrepancy between an entity’s legal status and its biological
reality for the purpose of the public good—called a legal fiction—can be traced back as
far as the 1893 case of Nix v. Hedden, when the US Supreme Court had to decide whether
a tomato should be considered a fruit or a vegetable (US Supreme Court 1893; Shah &
Miller 2010; Shah et al. 2011; Truog 2015). At the time, a tax was imposed on the impor-
tation of vegetables, and tomato importers argued that they should be exempt from the
tax because tomatoes are technically fruit. The Supreme Court stated that, “Botanically
speaking, tomatoes are the fruit of the vine … But in the common language of the peo-
ple… these are vegetables” (US Supreme Court 1893, p.307), and so determined that
tomatoes should legally be considered vegetables.
There are different types of legal fictions that could apply in the distinctions between
brain death and coma, or between VS/UWS and MCS. The first is a “bright-line fic-
tion,” which refers to creating legally discrete categories by drawing a bright line at a
point along a continuum. An example of a bright-line fiction already established in
medicine and law is that of legal blindness (Shah & Miller 2010). While visual acu-
ity falls along a spectrum, once an individual’s visual acuity falls below 20/200 he or
she is considered legally blind, despite technically retaining limited sight. This legal
classification carries implications for rights (e.g., eligibility for disability benefits)
as well as for restrictions (e.g., driving prohibitions). Thus, while the discrete, legal
definition of blindness does not perfectly correspond to the biological definition of
blindness, this bright line fiction serves an important function in dictating social and
legal decisions.
A second type of legal fiction potentially relevant to disorders of consciousness is the
status fiction, in which A is treated as if it were B (Shah et al. 2011). One example of a well-
established status fiction is that corporations are assigned the same legal status as people
(i.e., corporations are treated “as if they were” people), so that the body of law developed
for people can be applied to corporations. While a corporation is not technically a person,
this legal fiction is helpful in guiding many practical decisions, such as when a corpora-
tion can be sued, and how a corporation can contribute money to a political campaign
(Shah et al. 2011).
Applying these legal fictions to disorders of consciousness would mean either consider-
ing the diagnostic criteria for brain death or VS/UWS to signify death or unconsciousness,
respectively (in the case of a bright line fiction), or treating those who fulfill the diagnostic
criteria for brain death or VS/UWS as if they were dead or unconscious, respectively (in
the case of a status fiction). As described, these forms of pretending can serve useful social
and legal functions. In the case of disorders of consciousness, the fiction that discrete
diagnostic criteria reflect discrete conceptual categories (i.e., of life and death, or of con-
sciousness and unconsciousness), could be useful in guiding discrete decisions that rely
upon these conceptual distinctions.
326 3
But the problem with this approach is: who would we be pretending to? The legal fic-
tions currently established are generally transparent to society and those involved. It is
understood that a corporation is not literally a person, and those who are legally blind
but retain vision understand that they are not literally blind. But in the case of disorders
of consciousness, people could be unfairly misled. If we tell families and surrogates, or
even medical students and physicians in training, that patients are dead if they meet the
criteria for brain death, or are unconscious if they meet the criteria for VS/UWS—as we
often currently do—these groups may not understand the fiction and actual uncertainty
that underlie these statements. They may not understand that such patients are not liter-
ally dead or unconscious. Thus, such fictions could be more deceptive than clarifying,
resulting in incompletely informed decisions. The alternative is to disclose these fictions
to families and surrogates, to tell them that although we consider these patients to be
dead or unconscious (or treat them as such) for legal purposes, we cannot actually be sure
that they are dead or unconscious. In this case, these fictions would cease to effectively
serve as fictions at all, and families and surrogates would need to decide if the diagnostic
criteria themselves are sufficient to justify their decisions, bringing us to a second possible
approach.
We have previously proposed one such criterion for guiding these decisions: interac-
tive capacity, or the ability to receive communicated information and generate a coherent
response (Fischer & Truog 2013, 2015). Under this proposal, a patient should be con-
sidered conscious only if they demonstrate interactive capacity. We have also stipulated
that the patient’s response must be potentially intentional in order to signify interactive
capacity; that is, responses that are inherently non-volitional, even if performed by a con-
scious individual (e.g., automatic brain activity in response to voice or pain), cannot be
considered interactive (Fischer & Truog 2015).
Interactive capacity circumvents the problematic distinction between reflexive and pur-
poseful behaviors by falling safely among the latter, that is, by intuitively signifying con-
sciousness. Fins relays the thoughts of a woman whose mother suffered from a disorder
of consciousness:
[S]he told us why restoring her mother’s ability to communicate was most important to her.
“I think,” she said, “it’s because speech and language are a clear sign that she’s in there.” (Fins
2015, p.199)
Fins elaborates:
Ultimately, communication … helps families know if their loved one is conscious … Although
the only consciousness that we can truly know is our own, in practice we know the consciousness
of others through communication, which is a proxy for the cognitive experience within. Without
communication, others cannot know a patient’s level of awareness … It limits knowledge of the
patient’s current state and their future capabilities. (Fins 2015, p.197)
Along the spectrum of reflexive and purposeful behaviors, interactive behaviors can
be assumed to be purposeful, and thus trusted to signify consciousness. Perhaps this is
because, while spontaneous behaviors without context can be ambiguously interpreted,
behaviors in coherent response to external cues are more likely purposeful. The Turing
test offers an analogous application of the same intuition (French 2000; Stins 2009). In
this test, an examiner enters questions into a computer, and must determine whether the
responses are generated by a human respondent or an automated algorithm. The Turing
test thus assesses an algorithm’s ability to simulate human consciousness based on its
interactivity. Assessing the consciousness of a patient is conceptually similar: one com-
municates to a patient and evaluates whether the responses are sufficiently coherent to
signify consciousness.
In intuitively falling among purposeful, or conscious, behaviors, interactive capacity
solves two problems. First, it serves as a more discrete criterion than the current diagnos-
tic criteria for consciousness. The current criteria require clinicians to determine where
any given behavior falls along the spectrum between reflexive and purposeful behaviors.
As such, a patient whose behavior falls only within this indeterminate spectrum will be
difficult to categorize as either conscious or unconscious. In contrast, because interactive
behaviors are more readily identifiable, deciding whether interactive capacity is present or
absent, rather than whether a behavior is reflexive or purposeful, represents a more dis-
crete diagnostic determination. As such, it can more effectively guide discrete decisions.
329
Second, the intuitiveness with which interactive capacity signifies consciousness reflects
the value we place on interaction. For example, for many, a patient’s ability to interact is
crucial when deciding whether or not to withdraw LST. Fins writes that:
Most decisions to withhold or withdraw care are made when a patient loses consciousness and the
capacity to interact and participate in the decision-making process … It is this loss of conscious-
ness, the ability to interact with the other, that becomes the moral prompt for the conversation
(Fins 2015, p.30)
Given that we often cannot definitively know whether consciousness has been lost, it is
the loss of the “ability to interact” that prompts the conversation to withdraw LST, high-
lighting the value we place on interactive capacity when deciding if someone is conscious.
Fins also relays the thoughts of someone whose loved one suffered from a disorder of
consciousness:
“First of all I wanted her alive and I wanted her to recover, but I didn’t know what I wanted her to
recover the most. And it’s the ability to speak and communicate … ” The restoration of functional
communication was “ … The world.” (Fins 2015, p.197)
Surely the speaker would have wanted the patient to recover awareness, but it is telling
that the speaker chose communication as the most important function to recover. For
many, among the various empirical characteristics that might signify consciousness, it is
interaction that is the most meaningful. It is also worth noting that the current behav-
ioral criteria for the MCS (e.g., following commands, answering yes-or-no questions)
already do center on interactive behaviors, another indication that interactive capacity
intuitively matters to us when determining if another is conscious.
There are additional, more practical advantages to adopting interactive capacity as
a criterion for consciousness. First, whereas the current diagnostic criteria for con-
sciousness pertain specifically to behavior, interactive capacity is more generaliz-
able, and thus can apply to technologically mediated forms of interaction. This is an
important consideration in the context of emerging technologies, such as the fMRI
tasks described earlier, which can demonstrate interactive capacity in patients who
are behaviorally unresponsive. Second, selecting a criterion such as interactive capac-
ity that falls safely among purposeful behaviors prevents tests for consciousness from
becoming overly reductive (Fischer & Truog 2013). After fMRI studies revealed that
behaviorally unresponsive patients could interact through neuroimaging, people began
developing even more sensitive technological biomarkers for consciousness. However,
as these tests began to stray from intuitive conceptions of consciousness (e.g., EEG
responses to auditory stimuli (Faugeras et al. 2011), positron emission tomography
responses to painful stimuli (Boly et al. 2008), fMRI responses to voice (Di et al. 2007),
and correlations between spontaneous fluctuations in fMRI signals (Vanhaudenhuyse
et al. 2010)), they risked over-attributing consciousness to subconscious neural phe-
nomena. Interactive capacity is anchored in an intuitive conception of consciousness,
thereby minimizing the risk of overly reductive tests.
30 3
this way. In 2004, Fins and influential neurologist Fred Plum published an article titled
“Neurological diagnosis is more than a state of mind: diagnostic clarity and impaired con-
sciousness” (Fins & Plum 2004), in which they advocate for the objectivity of the diagnos-
tic criteria for disorders of consciousness. As Fins has argued, “Values should not distort
the clinical reality” (Fins 2015, p.253). This stance has virtue; as mentioned, the variability
in values between people will complicate how we think about disorders of consciousness.
However, given that the “clinical reality” is deeply obscured in disorders of consciousness,
values may indeed be necessary when managing these patients in the face of significant
uncertainty. Indeed, other diagnoses that reflect complex and unknown pathophysiology
have similarly incorporated values. For example, the diagnostic criteria for many psy-
chiatric disorders, such as personality disorders, include significantly impaired function;
what constitutes “function,” let alone what it means to be significantly impaired, will often
depend upon an individual’s values.
Yet, perhaps we should not be thinking about disorders of consciousness in terms of
discrete diagnostic categories at all. If we cannot reliably distinguish between the differ-
ent conceptual states—between life and death, consciousness and unconsciousness—and
if the empirical characteristics we value to make decisions will vary depending on the
person and decision, then any attempt to standardize these criteria will inevitably conflict
with the values of some. Indeed, the current standardized diagnostic criteria for brain
death have already conflicted with the values of certain religious and cultural groups,
leading some states to accommodate objections to brain death testing (Kimura 1991;
Posner et al. 2007). Thus, perhaps instead of focusing on distinguishing between discrete
diagnoses, we should focus on the range of empirical characteristics we can observe about
patients. From there, clinicians may collaborate with families and surrogates, or ideally
may refer to advance directives specified by the patients themselves, to determine which
empirical characteristics matter most for the decisions to be made. This approach will
certainly add complexity and nuance to our understanding of these disorders, but will
also assure that our decisions are made in an intellectually honest and ethical manner.
Disorders of consciousness represent an enigmatic corner of the medical world, chal-
lenging physicians, scientists, philosophers, and ethicists alike. Unlike most other medical
conditions, these disorders degrade our most fundamental attributes—those of life and
consciousness. As such, they are as perplexing as they are critical to understand. These
conditions present profound philosophical and scientific challenges, while also devastat-
ing the lives of patients, families, and loved ones. We have a responsibility to ensure that
these patients are offered the most ethical treatment possible, which will require care-
ful consideration of these complex philosophical problems. While we would like to base
our management of these patients on whether they are alive or dead, or conscious or
unconscious, we often cannot make these distinctions. By accepting the limitations in our
knowledge, we can develop a more honest and thoughtful approach to these disorders and
improve the ethical management of these patients.
3
References 333
Notes
1. Dreaming during rapid eye movement (REM) sleep might appear to violate this relationship, but in
fact REM sleep shares many neuronal characteristics with wakefulness (Steriade et al. 1993).
2. Of note, wholism as applied to life is sometimes called vitalism. However, the term vitalism connotes a
nonmaterial “life force” that enters an organism once whole, a notion largely rejected by the scientific
and medical community.
References
Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death (1968).
A definition of irreversible coma. JAMA, 205(6), 337–340.
Barnard, C. (1967). A human cardiac transplant: an interim report of a successful operation performed
at Groote Schuur Hospital, Cape Town. South African Medical Journal, 1271–1274.
Becker, K.J., Baxter, A.B., Cohen, W.A., et al. (2001). Withdrawal of support in intracerebral
hemorrhage may lead to self-fulfilling prophecies. Neurology, 56(6), 766–772.
Bernat, J. (2006). Chronic disorders of consciousness. The Lancet, 367(9517), 1181–1192.
Bernat, J., Culver, C., and Gert, B. (1981). On the definition and criterion of death. Annals of Internal
Medicine, 94(3), 389–394.
Boly, M., Faymonville, M.E., Schnakers, C., et al. (2008). Perception of pain in the minimally conscious
state with PET activation: an observational study. The Lancet Neurology, 7(11), 1013–20.
Di, H.B., Yu, S.M., Weng, X.C., et al. (2007). Cerebral response to patient’s own name in the vegetative
and minimally conscious states. Neurology, 68(12), 895–9.
Ecker, J. (2014). Death in pregnancy—an American tragedy. The New England Journal of Medicine,
370(10), 889–891.
Edelman, G.M. (1999). Building a picture of the brain. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences,
882(2), 68–89.
Executive Board of the American Academy of Neurology (1989). Position of the American Academy of
Neurology on certain aspects of the care and management of the persistent vegetative state patient.
Neurology, 39, 125–126.
Faugeras, F., Rohaut, B., Weiss, N., et al. (2011). Probing consciousness with event-related potentials in
the vegetative state. Neurology, 77(3), 264–268.
Fins, J.J. (2015). Rights Come to Mind: Brain Injury, Ethics, and the Struggle for Consciousness.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Fins, J.J. and Plum, F. (2004). Neurological diagnosis is more than a state of mind: diagnostic clarity and
impaired consciousness. Archives of Neurology, 61(9), 1354–1355.
Fins, J.J., Miller, F.G., Acres, C.A., Bacchetta, M.D., Huzzard, L.L., and Rapkin, B.D. (1999). End-
of-life decision-making in the hospital: current practice and future prospects. Journal of Pain and
Symptom Management, 17(1), 6–15.
Fischer, D.B. and Truog, R.D. (2013). Conscientious of the conscious: interactive capacity as a threshold
marker for consciousness. AJOB Neuroscience, 4(4), 26–33.
Fischer, D.B. and Truog, R.D. (2015). What is a reflex? A guide for understanding disorders of
consciousness. Neurology, 85(6), 543–548.
French, R. (2000). The Turing test: the first 50 years. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(3), 115–122.
Giacino, J. (2004). The vegetative and minimally conscious states: consensus-based criteria for
establishing diagnosis and prognosis. NeuroRehabilitation, 19, 293–298.
34 3
Giacino, J.T., Ashwal, S., Childs, N., et al. (2002). The minimally conscious state: definition and
diagnostic criteria. Neurology, 58(3), 349–353.
Gilbert, S.F. and Sarkar, S. (2000). Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century.
Developmental Dynamics, 219(1), 1–9.
Gramm, H.-J., Meinhold, H., Bickel, U., et al. (1992). Acute endocrine failure after brain death?
Transplantation, 54(5), 851–857.
Grigg, M.M., Kelly, M.A., Celesia, G.G., Ghobrial, M.W., and Ross, E.R. (1987).
Electroencephalographic activity after brain death. Archives of Neurology, 44(9), 948–954.
Halevy, A. and Brody, B. (1993). Brain death: reconciling definitions, criteria, and tests. Annals of
Internal Medicine, 119(6), 519–525.
Hopkin, M. (2006). “Vegetative” patient shows signs of conscious thought. Nature, 443(7108), 132–133.
Jennett, B. and Plum, F. (1972). Persistent vegetative state after brain damage: a syndrome in search of a
name. The Lancet, 299(7753), 734–737.
Kimura, R. (1991). Japan’s dilemma with the definition of death. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal,
1(2), 123–131.
Lane, A., Westbrook, A., Grady, D., et al. (2004). Maternal brain death: medical, ethical and legal issues.
Intensive Care Medicine, 30, 1484–1486.
Laureys, S., Owen, A.M., and Schiff, N.D. (2004). Brain function in coma, vegetative state, and related
disorders. Lancet Neurology, 3(9), 537–546.
Laureys, S., Boly, M., Moonen, G., and Masquet, P. (2009). Two dimensions of consciousness: arousal
and awareness. Encyclopedia of Neuroscience, 2, 1133–1142.
Laureys, S., Celesia, G.G., Cohadon, F., et al. (2010). Unresponsive wakefulness syndrome: a new name
for the vegetative state or apallic syndrome. BMC Medicine, 8(68), 1–4.
Lock, M. (2002). Twice Dead: Organ Transplants and the Reinvention of Death (Vol. 1). Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press.
Medical Consultants on the Diagnosis of Death to the President’s Commission for the Study of
Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research (1981). Guidelines for the
determination of death: report of the medical consultants on the diagnosis of death to the President’s
Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral
Research. JAMA, 246, 2184–2186.
Miller, F.G. and Truog, R.D. (2009). The incoherence of determining death by neurological criteria: a
commentary on “Controversies in the determination of death”, a white paper by the President’s
Council on Bioethics. Kennedy Institute of Ethics journal, 19(2), 185–193.
Monti, M., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Coleman, M.R., et al. (2010). Willful modulation of brain activity in
disorders of consciousness. New England Journal of Medicine, 362(7), 579–589.
Nair-Collins, M., Green, S.R., and Sutin, A.R. (2015). Abandoning the dead donor rule? A national
survey of public views on death and organ donation. Journal of Medical Ethics, 41, 297–302.
Owen, A., Coleman, M.R., Boly, M., Davis, M.H., Laureys, S., and Pickard, J.D. (2006). Detecting
awareness in the vegetative state. Science, 313, 1402.
Pallis, C. (1983). ABC of brainstem death: the arguments about the EEG. British Medical Journal, 286,
209–210.
Pennefather, S.H., Dark, J.H., and Bullock, R.E. (1993). Haemodynamic responses to surgery in brain-
dead organ donors. Anaesthesia, 48(12), 1034–1038.
Posner, J., Saper, C.B., Schiff, N., and Plum, F. (2007). Plum and Posner’s Diagnosis of Stupor and Coma
(4th edn.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Powner, D.J., Ackerman, B.M., and Grenvik, A. (1996). Medical diagnosis of death in adults: historical
contributions to current controversies. The Lancet, 348(9036), 1219–1223.
35
References 335
Repertinger, S., Fitzgibbons, W.P., Omojola, M.F., and Brumback, R.A. (2006). Long survival following
bacterial meningitis-associated brain destruction. Journal of Child Neurology, 21(7), 591–596.
Report of the Quality Standards Subcommittee of the American Academy of Neurology (1995). Practice
parameters for determining brain death in adults (summary statement). Neurology, 45, 1012–1014.
Robertson, J.A. (1999). The dead donor rule. Hastings Center Report, 29(6), 6–14.
Rodin, E., Tahir, S., Austin, D., and Andaya, L. (1985). Brainstem death. Clinical
Electroencephalography, 16(2), 63–71.
Rubin, E.B. and Bernat, J.L. (2011). Ethical aspects of disordered states of consciousness. Neurologic
Clinics, 29(4), 1055–71.
Sanghavi, D. (2009). When does death start? The New York Times Magazine, December 16.
Schrader, H., Krogness, K., Aakvaag, A., Sortland, O., and Purvis, K. (1980). Changes of pituitary
hormones in brain death. Acta Neurochirurgica, 52(3–4), 239–248.
Searle, J.R. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Shah, S.K. and Miller, F.G. (2010). Can we handle the truth? Legal fictions in the determination of
death. American Journal of Law and Medicine, 36(4), 540–585.
Shah, S.K., Truog, R.D., and Miller, F.G. (2011). Death and legal fictions. Journal of Medical Ethics,
37(12), 719–22.
Shewmon, D. (1998). Chronic “brain-death”: meta-analysis and conceptual consequences. Neurology,
51, 1538–1545.
Steriade, M., McCormick, D.A., and Sejnowski, T.J. (1993). Thalamocortical oscillations in the sleeping
and aroused brain. Science, 262(5134), 679–685.
Stins, J.F. (2009). Establishing consciousness in non-communicative patients: a modern-day version of
the Turing test. Consciousness and Cognition, 18, 187–192.
The Multi-Society Task Force on PVS (1994a). Medical aspects of the persistent vegetative state (1).
New England Journal of Medicine, 330(21), 1499–1508.
The Multi-Society Task Force on PVS (1994b). Medical aspects of the persistent vegetative state (2).
New England Journal of Medicine, 330(21), 1572–1579.
The President’s Council on Bioethics (2008). Controversies in the Determination of Death: A White
Paper by the President’s Council on Bioethics. Washington, DC: The President’s Council on Bioethics.
Truog, R.D. (1997). Is it time to abandon brain death? The Hastings Center Report, 27(1), 29–37.
Truog, R.D. (2007). Brain death—too flawed to endure, too ingrained to abandon. Journal of Law,
Medicine and Ethics, 35(2), 273–281.
Truog, R.D. (2015). Defining death: getting it wrong for all the right reasons. Texas Law Review, 93,
1885–1914.
US Supreme Court (1893). Nix v. Hedden 149 U.S. 304.
Vanhaudenhuyse, A. et al. (2010). Default network connectivity reflects the level of consciousness in
non-communicative brain-damaged patients. Brain, 133, 161–171.
Veatch, R.M. (1993). The impending collapse of the whole-brain definition of death. Hastings Center
Report, 23(4), 18–24.
Wijdicks, E.F.M., Varelas, P.N., Gronseth, G.S., Greer, D.M., American Academy of Neurology.
(2010). Evidence-based guideline update: determining brain death in adults: report of the Quality
Standards Subcommittee of the American Academy of Neurology. Neurology, 74(23), 1911–1918.
Winslade, W.J. (1998). Confronting Traumatic Brain Injury: Devastation, Hope and Healing, New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
36 3
Chapter 18
Introduction
Brain death remains a controversial subject even now, 60 years after the publication of
its original cases. The idea that a person whose brain functions have ceased irreversibly
is dead (despite the continuation of heartbeat, circulation, and visceral organ function
because of respiratory support) is the oldest and most enduring debate in neuroethics.
Notwithstanding its growing acceptance among societies in the developed and develop-
ing world, a trend accompanied by its parallel incorporation into medical practices and
laws, brain death remains inadequately understood by both medical and nursing pro-
fessionals as well as by the general public (Bernat 2006). Within the academy, scholars
continue to debate its conceptual validity (Truog 1997), a dispute amplified by a chorus
of new opponents (Joffe 2010; Nair-Collins 2015). Yet while opponents cite certain valid
conceptual inadequacies of brain death, their critiques for over four decades have not
gained sufficient traction or public support to change prevailing medical practices or laws
(Bernat 2014a).
In the first part of this chapter, I trace the history of brain death by explaining the
technological, medical, and societal factors stimulating its origin and acceptance; discuss
its medical, legal, religious, and social recognition; highlight a few of its controversies,;
examine a recent commission report; and discuss two highly publicized cases that have
reignited debates. In the second part, I provide the conceptual basis for brain death by
analyzing the definition and criterion of death. I offer an analytic framework for a biophi-
losophical account of death that justifies the practice of brain death, pinpoints the areas of
contention, and compares competing concepts of death. I conclude with thoughts about
brain death as a contemporary neuroethical issue and predict the future landscape of the
debate over brain death and the definition of death.
Brain death
Prior to the development of the mechanical ventilator and endotracheal intubation,
human death was a unitary phenomenon. When illness or injury led to the cessation of
heartbeat or breathing, brain function necessarily ceased and all organs lost functioning
37
Brain death 337
irreversibly. It did not matter which of the three vital functions (heartbeat/circulation,
lungs/breathing, and brain) ceased first, their mutual interdependence required that the
others inevitably also ceased within minutes. Physicians declaring death showed that cir-
culation, respiration, and brain functions had ceased by simply examining the patient for
the absence of heartbeat, breathing, responsiveness, and pupillary reactivity to light. Thus,
prior to the 1950s, death always was a unitary phenomenon and its operational definition
was the straightforward cessation of the three vital functions.
With the development of endotracheal intubation, positive-pressure ventilation, and
cardiopulmonary resuscitation in the 1950s, for the first time, the cessation of heartbeat
and breathing could be reversed or supported. It then became possible for a person
to have sustained brain damage so widespread and severe that all brain functions had
ceased irreversibly. Yet, with technological support of breathing and circulation, the
person could be physiologically maintained for a short time, permitting the continua-
tion of spontaneous heartbeat and systemic circulation to visceral organs though not
to the brain. French neurologists, who offered the first detailed descriptions of such
cases, labeled these patients le coma dépassé to indicate that they were in a state beyond
coma (Mollaret & Goulon 1959).1 Over the next decade, physicians began to assert
that these patients were not merely deeply comatose from profound brain damage: they
were dead.
The life status of these patients was ambiguous in the context of the prevailing unitary
understanding of death because they had lost some vital functions but not others. The
traditional unitary concept of death was not equipped to categorize the life status of such
patients because, prior to technological advances in physiological support, such cases
were impossible. A quick survey of their physical examination findings showed that they
had some characteristics traditionally associated with death but not others. Favoring their
classification as dead, they were utterly unresponsive to any stimuli, had no voluntary
or reflex movement, and did not breathe. Favoring their classification as alive, they had
heartbeat and systemic circulation, with intact visceral organ functioning to digest food
introduced into the stomach and to make urine. Achieving consensus on whether such
patients were alive or dead was impossible because they shared features of both states.
Nor could physicians determine whether they were alive or dead until it was first agreed
what death actually meant in the brave new technological world in which respiratory and
circulatory support was possible after these functions had ceased.
In the 1960s, a growing consensus developed among physicians and scholars that these
patients were, in fact, dead. In 1968, a committee of the Harvard Medical School faculty
proposed the first set of clinical criteria to diagnose the emerging concept that they called
brain death (Ad Hoc Committee 1968).2 Although their pioneering work both established
a new criterion of death and influentially fostered its widespread legal and public accep-
tance, their unfortunate choice of the term brain death promoted misunderstanding and
confusion that has persisted to the present.3 The term brain death now has become uni-
versal; it can be found in medical, scientific, scholarly, and legal contexts, has been trans-
lated into many languages, and has entered the public vernacular.
38 3
Brain death 339
nearly all states have adopted the UDDA or a close variant of it. The statute is drafted so
simply and clearly that all attempted legal challenges to brain death statutes in the United
States have failed (Burkle et al. 2011). The UDDA provides:
An individual who has sustained either (1) irreversible cessation of circulatory and respiratory
functions, or (2) irreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem,
is dead. A determination of death must be made in accordance with accepted medical standards.
(President’s Commission 1981)
Although in its concise text, the UDDA does not clarify the relationship between the
circulatory–respiratory and brain criteria, the discussion in Defining Death implies that
the brain criterion is the fundamental criterion of death. In model death statutes pro-
posed by other countries, most notably Canada, the brain criterion is offered within the
statute as the fundamental criterion of death but one that may be tested by physicians at
the bedside in two different ways: by showing the prolonged cessation of circulation and
respiration in patients who are not on ventilators or who will receive CPR, and by show-
ing the irreversible cessation of brain functions in patients who are maintained on ventila-
tors (Law Reform Commission of Canada 1981).6
A few studies have examined the extent of international acceptance of brain death. In
a 2002 survey study by Wijdicks, 80 countries reported medical practices or laws permit-
ting brain death determination (Wijdicks 2002). In a more comprehensive study of 91
countries in 2015, Wahlster and colleagues found that brain death practices were preva-
lent worldwide but with a great variability among testing guidelines and laws (Wahlster
et al. 2015). They found that 70% of countries had established legal provisions for brain
death declaration and that the most powerful predictor of the presence of a lawful proto-
col was a functioning organ donation network. A smaller survey of developed countries
also reported a high rate of brain death acceptance (Gardiner et al. 2012). Thus, despite
academic debates during the past several decades over the conceptual and scientific valid-
ity of equating brain death with human death, during this same time, more countries in
the developed and developing world have permitted or promoted brain death practices.
Thaddeus Pope (2014) comprehensively summarized the current state-by-state legal sta-
tus of brain death in the United States.
Religious acceptance
A second measure of social acceptance is the extent to which a new practice is consistent
with prevailing religious traditions. Whether death determination using a brain criterion
was consistent with the tenets, teachings, and beliefs of the world’s principal religions
has been a documented concern since the first writings on brain death. In early influen-
tial articles, Veith and colleagues asserted that brain death practice was compatible with
the world’s major religious beliefs (Veith et al. 1977a, 1977b). Although their claim was
based on a selective reading of religious opinion, since then, their generalization has been
shown to be mostly true although the actual situation is more complex.
There has been relatively little debate over brain death within Christianity. In
Protestantism, brain death acceptance is essentially universal, even among fundamentalist
341
Brain death 341
sects (Campbell 1999). In Roman Catholicism, acceptance is official but not univer-
sal. Four Vatican Pontifical Councils and Academies charged with studying this issue,
beginning in the 1980s, concluded that brain death was consistent with Roman Catholic
beliefs and teachings (Furton 2002). The Roman Catholic Church Magisterium first took
an official position in 2000, when, in an address to the International Congress of the
Transplantation Society in Rome, Pope John Paul II formally endorsed brain death as
fully consistent with Roman Catholic teachings (Pope John Paul 2000). In response to
questions within the Vatican hierarchy after the death of Pope John Paul, the Pontifical
Academy of Sciences later reaffirmed this position (Pontifical Academy 2007).7
Judaism lacks Roman Catholicism’s top-down ecclesiastical hierarchy that dictates rul-
ings on religious law; instead it relies on learned rabbis and other Talmudic scholars to
interpret contemporary questions in light of ancient Jewish law and teachings. Given the
opportunity for disagreement intrinsic to this method of interpretation, it is not surpris-
ing that a rabbinic debate over brain death persists. In general, Reform and Conservative
Jews accept brain death but the debate over it continues to rage within Orthodox Judaism.
One group of Orthodox Jewish scholars holds that brain death is consistent with Jewish
tradition, citing the writings of Maimonides and Talmudic passages emphasizing the
equivalence of breathing (arising from the brainstem) with life. Opponents counter that
Talmudists correlated the loss of breathing with the loss of heartbeat and therefore brain
dead patients with intact heartbeat remain alive.8
The acceptance of brain death within Islam remains partial and dependent on local
Islamic rulings. Following a fatwah approving brain death determination, the Ullamah
Council in Saudi Arabia confirmed the practice of brain death and permitted it in the
kingdom of Saudi Arabia (Yaqub & Al-Deeb 1996). Yet brain death is not permitted
in several other Islamic societies. The religious basis and varying interpretations of the
acceptability of brain death and the laws governing it among various Islamic countries
have been reviewed recently (Padela et al. 2013; Miller et al. 2014).
Other religious traditions also have addressed brain death. Hindu acceptance of brain
death was the topic of conferences held in Bombay and Madras. In 1993, the Indian leg-
islature enacted the Transplantation of Human Organs Act that contains provisions for
determining brain death (Jain & Maheshawari 1995). In Japan, traditional Shinto and
Buddhist concepts of death requiring cessation of heartbeat and breathing have collided
with technological attempts to Westernize Japanese medicine including the introduction
of brain death and organ transplantation (Lock 1995). Scholarly works, medical and sci-
entific society advocacy, and public debates over the past two decades have led Japanese
society to gradually accept the practices of brain death and deceased donor organ pro-
curement (Lock 2002) but this practice was first supported explicitly in Japanese law only
in 2009 (Aita 2009).
One area in which the prerogatives of religion, law, and public policy overlap is in
the enactment of state laws incorporating religious exemptions for declaring brain
death. In 1991, New Jersey became the first American jurisdiction to enact an exemp-
tion from brain death determination when family members of a patient could show
342 3
that its declaration violated the religious beliefs of the patient (Olick 1991). New York
initially provided administrative regulations accomplishing the same goal that later
became a statutory exemption. Since then, California and Illinois have enacted simi-
lar religious exemptions. New York’s and California’s religious exemption admonishes
physicians also to make reasonable efforts to accommodate moral objections to brain
death. In these states, when the allowable circumstances are verified, physicians can
declare death only by using circulatory–respiratory tests. Given the prevailing varia-
tion in state laws, an important public policy question remains over the extent of the
elasticity of death statutes to accommodate personal religious and moral preferences
before they become incoherent or unmanageable (Brock 1999; Miles 1999; Fry-Revere
et al. 2010).
Brain death 343
commenting that the brain dead person “died” once the ventilator was disconnected
(Racine et al. 2008; Daoust & Racine 2014).
The depth of lay and professional understanding of brain death varies widely (Bernat
2014a). The most rudimentary and common level is intuitive. Many people find it logical
that patients whose brain functions have totally and irreversibly ceased occupy a qualita-
tively different state than those who continue to possess brain functions because the brain
is the master organ and the seat of consciousness and human behavior. This superficial,
intuitive level constitutes a sufficient degree of understanding to allow many people to
accept brain death even though their concept remains only vague and inchoate.
Medical acceptance constitutes a higher level of understanding. Physicians and others
with scientific sophistication may accept brain death because of their greater understand-
ing of the role of the brain in the functioning of the human organism. They may regard
the absence of consciousness, cognition, breathing, circulatory control, and centrally con-
trolled homeostasis as equivalent to death because the remaining bodily functions in a
brain dead patient are only those supported by mechanical devices. They may consider
such patients suitable for organ donation and “as good as dead” even if they remain unde-
cided over whether they are biologically dead.
The most profound level of understanding requires justifying the equivalence of brain
death and human death as a result of a rigorous biophilosophical analysis. This level may
be achieved by conducting an analysis that studies the concept of the human organism
and the meaning of death in our technological era in which organs and organ subsys-
tems, particularly circulation and respiration, can be maintained in modern intensive care
units. This understanding requires appreciating the distinction between the life status of
the human organism and of its component parts. In the next section of the chapter on the
definition and criterion of death, I discuss the biophilosophical justification of the equiva-
lence of brain death and human death and offer my response to criticisms.
Within the practice of death determination, brain death is not unique in generating mis-
understanding or controversy. There remains a raging debate over the exact moment of
death when physicians apply the circulatory–respiratory criterion. This controversy cen-
ters on whether death occurs once circulatory and respiratory functions have ceased irre-
versibly (i.e., they cannot return) or when these functions have ceased permanently (i.e.,
they will not return) as discussed in the second part of this chapter (Bernat 2010a, 2013a).
A recent survey of medical and nursing professionals yielded the surprising finding that
those surveyed felt greater confidence in the accuracy of a brain death determination
than in the accuracy of a circulatory–respiratory death determination (Rodriguez-Arias
et al. 2013).
Several high-profile councils have weighed in on the brain death debate. The most
recent effort, in 2008, by the United States President’s Council on Bioethics yielded a white
paper entitled Controversies in the Determination of Death. Their work was stimulated by
their earlier unpublished study of ethical questions in organ transplantation. The Council
heard testimony from brain death opponents who explained why they believed that the
concept was invalid. Despite acknowledging the shortcoming of relying on the loss of
34 3
integration of bodily subsystems as the conceptual grounds for accepting the equivalency
of brain death as human death, the Council “concluded that the neurological standard
remains valid” (President’s Council 2008, p.x).
Two tragic and highly publicized cases of brain death in the United States refocused
public attention in 2014–2015 and led to controversy. The teenager Jahi McMath was
diagnosed as brain dead following complications after throat surgery but her mother
refused to accept the diagnosis and insisted upon continued treatment even following a
second opinion that agreed with the finding (Magnus et al. 2014). The pregnant Marlise
Muñoz was diagnosed as brain dead but the Texas hospital in which she was admitted
insisted on continuing ventilator treatment against the wishes of her family by claiming
that regulations in the Texas Health and Safety Code mandated treatment in pregnant
women for the welfare of the fetus (Ecker 2014). These cases stimulated much controversy
(and confusion) about the definition, conceptual validity, religious relevance, and legality
of brain death (Gostin 2014). Much of the reporting of these cases by the popular press
compounded the controversy by publishing often incorrect and misleading descriptions
of the medical condition, treatment, and prognosis of both women (Bernat 2014a).9
Even within communities with laws and religions accepting brain death, family mem-
bers of brain dead patients sometimes reject the diagnosis and insist that their loved one
is not really dead and therefore requires continued treatment (Lewis et al. 2016). This was
the tragic situation with McMath even before her mother cited her religious opposition
to brain death. This poignant situation creates a dilemma for physicians caring for such
patients and which requires compassionate and clear communication (Olick et al. 2009).
It is essential for physicians to carefully explain the medical and legal rationale for brain
death, to emphasize its hopelessness, and to clearly distinguish it from coma and other
potentially reversible brain states.
Nevertheless, some families insist on continued treatment, hoping for improvement.
Physicians managing such cases should use their judgment to decide whether or for how
long to acquiesce to this request. Second consultations may be helpful as well as frequent,
empathetic counseling sessions. Valid religious exemption claims should be accommo-
dated to the extent consistent with maintaining good medical practice (Spike & Greenlaw
1995; Orr & Genesen 1997). If the principal barrier to acceptance is emotional, assistance
from chaplains, nurses, social workers, or the hospital bioethics committee may be ben-
eficial (Bernat 2008a). After reviewing several instructive cases, Flamm and colleagues
provided guidelines for physicians to compassionately handle such difficult situations
(Flamm et al. 2014).
the artificial maintenance of respiration and circulation allows portions of the body to
remain alive but that the human organism (“as a whole”) is dead. Those scholars who
advocate that the brain dead person remains alive counter that the brain enjoys no special
status over other organs in a determination of death and that death as a biological phe-
nomenon requires that all organ function must cease as a result of absence of circulation
(Shewmon 2010). Defining what it means to be dead in our technological era, therefore,
is a prerequisite for settling the brain death–human death equivalency argument and
accepting or rejecting the biological foundation of brain death.
During the early era of brain death acceptance, scholars began to offer systematic
analyses of death to show that brain death people were dead. These brain death defense
arguments ultimately progressed to a definition of death argument. In this section, I offer
analytic approaches to the definition and criterion of death and discuss critiques of the
conceptual basis of brain death.
that the mental component cannot be produced merely from the animal component.
Shewmon (2010) elucidated this concept more explicitly: “Reflective self-awareness, uni-
versal concept formation, abstract reasoning, and free will all have properties that tran-
scend spatiality and cannot in principle emerge from a complex electrochemical network.
They therefore derive from an immaterial principle, but nevertheless, one profoundly
oriented to operate in and through a body.” These scholars therefore deny the “reductive”
claim accepted by most cognitive neuroscientists that the mind is solely the product of the
brain without the necessity of an animating spiritual element (Pinker 1997; Koch 2012).
For our paradigm, Gert, Culver, and I require that human beings are only our human
organisms, that self-awareness and other human behaviors are solely emergent functions
of the brain that do not derive from an immaterial principle, and therefore, human death
is the death of the human organism. This approach is consistent with three other elements
of the paradigm: (1) death is fundamentally a biological phenomenon; (2) only organisms
can die; and (3) the biologically univocal usage of the word death requires that it mean
the same thing for humans as for other higher animals such as dogs unimbued with souls.
We regard personhood as a set of psychosocial, legal, moral, and religious attributes of
human beings that arguably may be lost by severe brain injury or illness but cannot die
except metaphorically. In his monograph, Eric Olson (1997) more rigorously defends the
position that human beings are our organisms.
Linda Emanuel (1995) relies too heavily on metaphysics with her claim “there is no state
of death … to say ‘she is dead’ is meaningless because ‘she’ is not compatible with ‘dead.’ ”
The depth of Emanuel’s metaphysical abstraction of death cannot identify a definition or
criterion because it offers nothing to clarify the common usage of the term death. And
as an experienced physician, she obviously does not truly believe that there is no state
of death.
Amir Halevy and Baruch Brody (1993) claim that defining death is impossible because
an organism can reside in a transitional state between life and death that possesses fea-
tures of both states but is congruent with neither state. Using the mathematical model
of fuzzy logic, they postulate that whereas no organism can fully belong to both the sets
of living and dead organisms, because the sets represent mutually exclusive states, some
organisms can reside in a transitional state in which they have some features of each state
but do not fully belong to either the set of living or dead organisms.
Our argument against this position emphasizes the distinction between the ontology of
the life-state of an organism and our ability to accurately determine that state. Because,
as a consequence of technical limitations, we may not be able to conclusively determine
at all times whether a given organism is alive or dead does not mean that it must reside
in a transitional state between alive and dead. The paradigm provides that all organisms
are either dead or alive, but, because of these technical limitations, we may not be able to
make the accurate determination of its life-state in real time but only in retrospect. Future
technological advances will improve the accuracy and timeliness of this determination.
In their mathematical analysis of state discontinuities, Alan and Elisabeth Shewmon
(2004) settled the longstanding debate over whether death is best understood as an
349
event or as a process.12 The Shewmons showed that death must be an event because
of the suddenness and discontinuity of the transition from the states of alive to dead,
given the absence of an intervening state. They agreed that we may not always be able
to identify the precise time of the event, and we may be able to identify it only in
retrospect because of technical limitations. Everyone agrees that the biological phe-
nomena of dying before death and of bodily disintegration after death are processes.
Most scholars, including the Shewmons, now agree with us that death is best viewed
as the event separating the process of dying from the process of bodily disintegration
(Bernat et al. 1981).
The neurologist-philosopher Winston Chiong rejected the idea that death must be
defined before analyzing criteria to measure it (Chiong 2005, 2014). He cited Wittgenstein’s
argument that some common terms, such as games, cannot have uniform definitions that
are based on the possession of an essential meaning shared by all members of the set
because all members of the set in question do not share an essential characteristic. Rather
than communally sharing an essential characteristic, members of the set are related to
each other in various other ways. Chiong claims that death is such a word. He argues that
searching for the essence of the meaning of the word death from which to establish its
definition is futile because there are no conditions that are both necessary and sufficient
for death. He further maintained that defining death is an unnecessary step to provide
a coherent argument supporting the whole-brain criterion of death. He concluded that
our paradigm–definition–criterion–test sequential analytic method therefore should be
rejected.
My late colleague, Bernard Gert, refuted Chiong’s criticism, arguing that Chiong mis-
understood the correct meaning of a definition by accepting a discredited essentialist
concept of a definition (Gert 2006). The effort to choose a definition of death is not to
make explicit the implicit essence of the concept of death but rather to make explicit the
meaning implicit in our consensual and ordinary use of the nontechnical word death.
Gert further pointed out that, given this proper intent of definition, Chiong, perhaps
unknowingly, also relied on a definition of death—though one more diffuse than ours—
in his defense of the whole-brain criterion of death. Therefore, Chiong’s argument reject-
ing definition constituted an invalid criticism of our paradigm–definition–criterion–test
method of analysis that requires starting with what is ordinarily meant by the term death
before choosing its criterion.13
A number of commentators have reported cases of “near-death” experiences to sup-
port their claim that death is not irreversible because, as their experience shows, some
people can return from being dead. The physiological explanation of these personal
narratives is the presence of acute encephalopathies that occur during critical illness
from marked disturbances in brain metabolism (Parnia & Fenwick 2002). Patients with
“near-death” experiences were rescued from death while incipiently dying but were not
dead and therefore did not return from the dead. Despite the poignancy and sincerity
of these subjective accounts (Alexander 2012), they do not negate the axiom that death
is irreversible.
350 3
unity and wholeness. Biological theorists have shown that an organism’s emergent func-
tions are complex phenomena that are difficult to model or predict merely by studying its
isolated parts (Clayton & Kauffman 2006).
Bonelli and colleagues offered a conceptual analysis of the role of the cessation of the
organism as a whole in death (Bonelli et al. 2009). They stated that all life forms possess an
intrinsic unity characterized by four criteria: (1) dynamics, or signs of life, such as metabo-
lism, regeneration, growth, and propagation; (2) integration, the requirement that the life
process derives from the mutual interaction of its component parts; (3) coordination, the
requirement that the interaction of the component parts is maintained within a certain
order; and (4) immanency, the requirement that the preceding characteristics originate
from and are intrinsic to the life form. They identified four criteria that make a life form
an integrated, unified, whole organism: (1) completion, the requirement that an organism
is not a component part of another living entity but is itself an intrinsically independent
and completed whole; (2) indivisibility, the condition of intrinsic unity that no organism
can be divided into more than one living organism; and, if such a division occurs and
the organism survives, the completed organism must reside in one of the divided parts;
(3) self-reference or auto-finality, the characteristic that the observable life processes and
functions of the component parts serve the self-preservation of the whole, even at the
expense of the survival of its parts, because the health and survival of the living whole
is the primary end in itself; and (4) identity, the circumstance that, despite incremental
changes in form and the loss or gain of certain component parts (that even could eventu-
ally result in the exchange of all component atoms), the living being remains one and the
same throughout life (Bonelli et al. 2009). My Dartmouth colleague, Andrew Huang, and
I currently are critiquing and expanding upon Bonelli and colleagues’ formulation.
critical functions of the organism as a whole can be classified as control and executive
functions.
Advocates of “brain death” hold that because most of the critical functions of the organ-
ism as a whole are executed by the brain, irreversible cessation of brain functions elimi-
nates these critical functions and is death (Korein 1978, 1997). Bonelli and colleagues
stated this position most rigorously, arguing that with irreversible cessation of clinical
brain functions (“brain death”), the organism has lost (1) immanency, because its life
processes no longer arise from itself but result from external intensive care support;
(2) auto-finality, because whatever control over the component organ subsystem parts
that remains now is directed at the level of the surviving parts and no longer at the whole;
(3) self-reference, because the continued functioning of its parts no longer supports to
the function of the whole; and (4) completeness and indivisibility, because its separate
component parts and subsystems no longer belong to each other and no longer constitute
a whole. Once an organism has irreversibly lost its totality, completion, indivisibility, self-
reference, and identity, it no longer functions as a whole and is dead (Bonelli et al. 2009).
Brain criterion advocates disagree to some extent on the question of exactly which ele-
ments of the brain’s functioning must cease to be sufficient for death. Higher-brain crite-
rion advocates require the cessation only of the functions of the cerebral hemispheres and
thalami because those structures underlie conscious awareness and the cognitive func-
tions that are the unique characteristics of the human being and whose cessation is death
(Veatch 1975; Gervais 1986). The higher-brain criterion remains popular in the academy
but has not been accepted by any medical society or jurisdiction in the world. The fail-
ure of its acceptance despite decades of argument is because, rather than trying to make
explicit the implicit definition of death that has been obscured by technology, the higher-
brain criterion is a radical redefinition of death. The evidence for this conclusion is that
applying it wrongly labels many patients in coma or vegetative states as dead, despite the
fact that they are considered as alive by societies throughout the world.
Brainstem formulation advocates require only the cessation of functions of the brain-
stem, arguing that the brainstem controls respiration, circulation, and consciousness, and
serves as a through-station for nearly all hemispheric input and output. Further, the clini-
cal tests determining “brain death” examine mostly for brainstem functions (Pallis 1995).
But by not requiring the absence of hemispheric functioning, it permits the unlikely but
possible case of false-positive death determination if awareness were retained despite the
loss of other brainstem functions. The brainstem criterion and the whole-brain criterion
have similar sets of bedside tests but it has been accepted as a criterion of death only by
the United Kingdom and a few other countries.
The prevailing whole-brain criterion of death has been accepted in nearly all juris-
dictions except those that accept the brainstem criterion. The whole-brain criterion
acknowledges that the hemispheres, thalami, hypothalami, and brainstem all contribute
to the critical functions of the organism as a whole, hence the clinical functions con-
trolled by each of these parts of the brain must be abolished for death. But, despite its
categorical name, the whole-brain criterion does not require the cessation of all brain
35
neurons, only a critical number and array (currently unknown) that conduct the clini-
cal functions of the brain underlying the critical functions of the organism as a whole
(Bernat 1998, 2002).
An assessment of the physiological state of the “brain dead” patient shows the contrast
between the technologically maintained and continued life of many component parts of
the organism despite the death of the human organism itself. “Brain death” advocates do
not deny that much of the human organism remains alive because of technological sup-
port, but assert that the body on the ventilator has died because of irreversible cessation
of the clinical brain functions serving the organism as a whole.
Scholars who reject any brain criterion embrace the circulation–respiration criterion.
Alan Shewmon, the intellectual leader of this group, accepts the definition of death as the
cessation of function of the organism as a whole (Shewmon 2010). However, he rejects
any brain criterion because he argues that many functions of the organism as a whole are
operated by the spinal cord and other organs and tissues outside the brain (Shewmon
2001, 2004). Further, he cites cases of “chronic brain death” in whom people declared
brain dead have been treated with circulatory and respiratory support of ventilators and
other therapies to allow their visceral organs to be perfused and oxygenated successfully
for months (Shewmon 1998) or, in one remarkable case, for 16 years (Repertinger et al.
2006). He argues that it is simply counterintuitive to the concept of death that people could
have circulation and visceral organ function maintained for long periods, go through
puberty, or gestate fetuses during this treatment, as have been reported. Shewmon and
other advocates of the circulatory–respiratory criterion claim that the definition of death
therefore is not fulfilled in typical brain death, and instead, death requires the irrevers-
ible cessation of circulation of oxygenated blood to all organs (Shewmon 2001, 2009).
Brain death advocates counter that the definition of death is fulfilled in “brain death” and
that the criterion of irreversible cessation of circulation and respiration, while sufficient
for death, is not necessary. In a paper in preparation, my colleague Andrew Huang and
I rebut Shewmon’s claim.
Although everyone agrees that the irreversible cessation of systemic circulation is suf-
ficient for death, the current controversy over the circulatory criterion surrounds the
question of how long physicians must wait to declare death once circulation (and respira-
tion) have ceased. In cases of circulatory–respiratory death determination in which organ
donation is not being performed, this question is usually inconsequential. Physicians
examine the patient, determine the absence of breathing, heartbeat, responsiveness, and
pupillary light reflexes, and simply declare death at that moment. There is no need to
hurry and physicians usually conduct a leisurely examination without concern about tim-
ing. Death is declared at the completion of the examination.
In cases in which the patient is an organ donor, however, circulatory–respiratory death
determination is an entirely different situation. Here, death determination must be per-
formed as rapidly as possible to minimize warm ischemic damage to the organs to be
transplanted. Conducting a timely death determination in the organ transplantation
donor raises a knotty question: what is the shortest time interval after circulation and
respiration have ceased after which physicians can declare death? This seemingly straight-
forward question has led to considerable controversy and, although a few guidelines have
emerged, remains unresolved.
Many hospitals around the world have established programs of organ donation after
the circulatory determination of death (DCDD), known formerly as nonbeating organ
donation or donation after cardiac death (Bernat et al. 2006). In “controlled” DCDD as
practiced in the United States and Canada, in which the donor is usually a patient with
profound brain damage on a ventilator in an intensive care unit, family members or other
lawful surrogates order withdrawal of life-sustaining therapy (the mechanical ventilator) to
allow the patient to die and also consent for organ donation after death has been declared,
presumably representing the wishes of the patient. Once respiration and circulation stop
following endotracheal extubation, after a mandatory observation period to guarantee
that breathing and circulation will not restart spontaneously (“auto-resuscitation”), the
patient is declared dead and rushed to the surgical suite for organ donation. An analogous
program of “uncontrolled” DCDD is practiced in some European countries, in which the
often previously healthy donor suffers a sudden cardiac arrest, undergoes CPR but cannot
be resuscitated, and is declared dead prior to organ donation (Munjal et al. 2013).
In death declaration of the controlled DCDD donor, the essential question centers on
how long respiration and circulation must be absent before death can be declared. This
interval varies from 2 minutes in the pioneering DCDD protocol at the University of
Pittsburgh Medical Center (DeVita & Snyder 1993), to 5 minutes as recommended by the
US Institute of Medicine (2000) which has been instituted by most US hospitals, to up to
20 minutes in some European countries. The principal requirement is that the duration
chosen must exceed the interval in which auto-resuscitation can occur to be sure that cir-
culation cessation is permanent. This empirical question was addressed in a study of pub-
lished reports of auto-resuscitation after circulatory cessation (Hornby et al. 2010). The
investigators found no cases at all of auto-resuscitation to restored circulation after with-
drawal of mechanical ventilator therapy in the intensive care unit (a situation analogous
35
determination of death requiring only the permanent cessation of those functions. Thus,
the answer to the question of whether the DCDD donor is dead at the moment death is
ordinarily declared in DCDD protocols is “yes” by the medical standard of permanent
cessation but “no” by the biological standard that requires irreversibility. The permanence
standard to determining death has been accepted implicitly in all controlled DCDD pro-
tocols, explicitly by one medical society (American Academy of Pediatrics 2013), and
was recommended by an expert panel advising DCDD programs on standardizing policy
for circulatory death determination in organ donors (Bernat et al. 2010, 2014). Further
scholarly and public policy debate among organ donation stakeholders should clarify if
the clinical standard of permanent cessation of circulation and respiration also should
pertain to death determination in the setting of organ donation (Bernat 2013a).
Future directions
The futures of brain death and the definition of death remain intertwined. The societal
consensus accepting brain death as human death, although described by one critic as
“superficial and fragile” (Youngner 1992), has endured for nearly half a century. One
knowledgeable commentator accurately summarized the state of brain death in the devel-
oped world as “well settled but still unresolved” (Capron 2001). It has been settled to the
extent that societies have enacted more or less uniform laws permitting physicians to use
brain death as a determination of death. But it remains unresolved to the extent that its
opponents validly identify weaknesses in its rationale causing them to reject it and requir-
ing a stronger conceptual defense. As an advocate of brain death, I believe that its most
coherent biophilosophical justification is that the definition of death should be based on
the cessation of functioning of the organism as a whole. But more work needs to be done
to fill in conceptual gaps in the present foundation—particularly in the criteria of the
organism as a whole—that are necessary to more rigorously establish this rationale. My
Dartmouth colleague, Andrew Huang, and I are presently constructing such an argument.
In any analysis of the definition of death or the determination of brain or circulatory
death, it is essential to separate the social desirability and instrumental value of organ
donation (Citerio et al. 2016) from conceptual and policy questions about death determi-
nation. Independent of its utilitarian value, the determination of death must be biologi-
cally accurate and the definition of death must be philosophically plausible and coherent.
Public policies may permit certain agreed upon practical compromises to assure that
medical practices involving organ donation and death determination are workable and
socially acceptable. But these adjustments must be understood by physicians, accepted by
the public, and operationalized into optimal practices of informed consent for the deter-
minations of both brain death and circulatory death, particularly in the context of organ
donation. Current informed consent practices in organ donation appear to be suboptimal
for both brain death (Iltis 2015) and circulatory death (Overby et al. 2015).
It is in this regard that the noncongruence between the medical standards for death
determination and the biological concept of death must be fully appreciated. Medical
357
standards permit physicians to declare death at an earlier moment than the biological
concept would otherwise allow. Primarily for social reasons, physicians routinely declare
death when a person’s vital functions have ceased permanently but at a time before these
functions have ceased irreversibly (Bernat 2013a). As public policy, it is desirable for our
society to rely on accepted medical standards for death determination in both organ
donors and nondonors even though medical standards may not achieve the biologi-
cal standard of death. Stakeholders in organ donation and death determination need to
debate and accept a standard that they conclude is optimal for society. I advocate the per-
manent cessation standard that is implicit in all DCDD protocols and therefore appears
to have achieved widespread acceptance.
An unresolved public policy question remains the extent to which moral or religious
beliefs and personal preferences should influence the medical standards that physicians
will apply in one’s own death determination. This issue has arisen most frequently in
the context of brain death but also could be raised in circulatory death determination
for organ donors. The tension present here is between respect for personal liberties
and the authority of medical practices and societal laws. As is true in most such con-
troversies, differing opinions about the location of the equilibrium point of this ten-
sion result from individual differences in political philosophies, for example, between
communitarianism and libertarianism. A successful public policy needs to identify an
equilibrium point that adequately provides individual liberty rights but does not lead
to social chaos.
Most people intuit the desirability of having uniform standards of brain and circulatory
death determination—whatever they may be—across countries and societies (Choi et al.
2008). Yet, variability in medical practices remains the norm, even in the United States
where expert guidelines on brain death determination have been in effect for over two
decades (Greer et al. 2016). To some extent, this variability results from physicians who
remain unaware of or who refuse to comply with national standards and from hospitals
not enforcing them (Bernat 2008b). Achieving international standardization will be even
more difficult because it must accommodate varying societal mores, religious beliefs, and
medical practice variations (Wahlster et al. 2015). A few medical societies and the World
Health Organization are currently working to try to develop such uniform standards but
it presents a formidable undertaking.
Given the survey data documenting a stubbornly persistent and widespread level of
ignorance about brain death (Siminoff et al. 2004), most people agree that there is a need
to improve public and professional education on concepts and practices of death deter-
mination. Medical professionals need to increase their sophistication about the definition
of death and their knowledge of the concept and determination of brain death. Among
other goals, greater sophistication and knowledge will clarify the true level of support for
the concept of brain death in the medical community that has been hard to assess accu-
rately with current surveys. Better public education should include journalists who write
articles on brain death in the popular press that educate (or mislead) the public and mold
public opinion.
358 3
Finally, there remain gaps in the scientific understanding of incipient dying and death
which, once filled, can inform the development of medical standards for death deter-
mination. For example, we know relatively little about the natural history and precise
time course of how cessation of systemic circulation leads to hypoxic-ischemic neuronal
damage and brain death, particularly, at what moment all brain functions cease and the
point when brain death occurs. Although preliminary observational studies have made
an important contribution to understanding this common phenomenon (Munshi et al.
2015), more such studies need to be conducted.
Notes
1. In their landmark 1959 article from the Claude Bernard Hospital in Paris, Mollaret and Goulon
reported 23 cases of patients with utter coma, apnea, EEG electrocerebral silence, and total brain
necrosis at autopsy (Mollaret & Goulon 1959). They coined the term le coma dépassé (which Prof.
Goluon translated into English as “irreversible or irretrievable coma”) to describe their unprecedented
deep state of coma with no cognitive or vegetative functions (Wijdicks 2011). The article included
the clinical, electroencephalographic, and pathological features of what later would be called “brain
death.” Mollaret and Goulon also discussed ethical and philosophical issues including the boundaries
between life and death and the ethical duty of physicians to continue to support patients in that hope-
less state. Because of the comprehensiveness of their description and discussion, Mollaret and Goulon
are generally credited with describing the first cases of brain death although Lofstedt and von Reis had
done so briefly 3 years earlier (Diringer & Wijdicks 2001).
2. The report of the Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of
Brain Death, misleadingly subtitled “A definition of irreversible coma,” first made the medical and legal
communities and the general public aware of the use of the absence of brain functions to determine
human death. Harvard anesthesiologist and research ethicist, Henry K. Beecher, chaired the commit-
tee. Other members included neurologists Raymond D. Adams, Derek Denny-Brown, and Robert
Schwab; neurosurgeon William Sweet; transplant surgeon Joseph Murray; law professor William
Curran; historian of medicine Everett Mendelsohn; and five others (Wijdicks 2003). The purpose of the
Committee’s report was “to define irreversible coma as a new criterion of death” (Ad Hoc Committee
1968). The Ad Hoc Committee proposed the first examination criteria to certify brain death. These
tests have withstood the test of time and have not been altered significantly in the 49 years since they
were proposed. The four cardinal characteristics of the brain dead patient are: (1) unreceptiveness and
unresponsiveness; (2) no movements or breathing; (3) no reflexes, especially cranial nerve innervated
reflexes; and (4) flat EEG. The tests needed to be repeated after 24 hours to insure irreversibility. They
incorrectly predicted that if the medical community embraced this concept, no change in the law on
death statutes would be required. They correctly asserted that considering the permanent cessation of
all brain functions as death was implicit in the traditional concept of death.
3. The Harvard Medical School Ad Hoc Committee popularized the term “brain death.” This was an
unfortunate choice of terms because it misleadingly implied that only the brain was dead and that
there were two types of death: brain death and ordinary death. The misleading term “brain death”
has contributed to both public and professional persisting misunderstanding (Molinari 1982).
Committee member Murray anticipated this problem and wrote a memo to committee chairman
Beecher in which he pleaded: “The term ‘brain death’ should be eliminated. Death is what we are
talking about, and adding the adjective ‘brain’ implies some restriction on the term as if it were an
incomplete type of death…our charge is to define death…” (Giacomini 1997). But Beecher chose to
retain the term “brain death.”
359
4. When the Health Resources & Services Administration Division of Transplantation of the United
States Department of Health and Human Services empaneled an expert committee to determine
standards for the circulatory determination of death in DCDD organ donors, it explicitly and firmly
barred all membership to and influence from organ transplantation surgeons although these sur-
geons could have contributed useful technical information to the process. See Bernat et al. (2010) and
Bernat et al. (2014).
5. That Kansas became the first state in the United States to amend its death statute to incorporate brain
death has been attributed to the outsize influence of a Kansas neurosurgeon who was friendly with
state legislators and used his powers of personal persuasion to push through the bill (Kennedy 1971).
6. Ironically, Canadian provincial governments chose to ignore their federal council recommenda-
tion to adopt the model statute and, despite its clarity, did not incorporate the model statute into
provincial laws.
7. Despite the papal pronouncement, opponents of brain death remain within Roman Catholicism who
continue to assert that it is inconsistent with Roman Catholic, and even Christian, belief systems.
Most persistent in this area over the past 40 years has been Paul Byrne (Byrne et al. 1979). Yet,
even before the Pope’s pronouncement, it was clear that Byrne’s opinion was marginalized within
Roman Catholic circles. The conservative Roman Catholic bioethics institute, the National Catholic
Bioethics Center (formerly called the Pope John Center), held that Byrne was incorrect and that
brain death was fully consistent with the teachings of Roman Catholicism (Furton 1999). Following
Pope John Paul’s endorsement of brain death in 2000, the Center predicted that the papal pronounce-
ment should quell the disagreement by Byrne and other critics on Roman Catholic religious grounds
(Furton 2002; Haas 2011).
8. The Orthodox rabbi-scientist Moshe Tendler argues that brain death is compatible with Halacha
(historical-traditional Jewish law) because it is the physiological equivalent of decapitation. In the
twelfth century, Maimonides asserted that a decapitated person was immediately dead and that tran-
sient muscle twitches observed in the decapitated body were not signs of life. Tendler and the phy-
sician-talmudist Fred Rosner cite the Talmudic tract, discussed by Rashi, in which it is stated that
breathing, not heartbeat, is the primary sign of life. Therefore, brain death is human death according
to Jewish law (Rosner & Tendler 1989; Rosner 1999). But Orthodox rabbis and Talmudic scholars
David Bleich (1989) and Ahron Soloveichik (1979) reached the opposite conclusion. In emphasizing
the distinction between a sign of death and death itself, they explained that ancient rabbis consid-
ered the cessation of respiration as the cardinal sign of death because it implied a prior cessation of
heartbeat. They concluded that, according to Jewish law, physicians cannot determine death in the
presence of spontaneous heartbeat. Although only the strictest Orthodox sects consistently embrace
this position, it remains the official position in Israel though changes to the Brain Death Act in 2012
permitted brain death determination in some situations and thereafter, brain dead organ donation
increased substantially (Cohen et al. 2012). For learned commentaries on this continuing religious
dispute, see Halachic Organ Donor Society (https://www.hods.org/).
9. The follow-up stories of McMath and Muñoz are instructive. As of February 2017, McMath appar-
ently remains supported on a ventilator somewhere in New Jersey as her mother and her attorneys
try to convince a California judge to reverse her death declaration citing affidavits submitted by
physicians who have examined her stating she is not dead (Winkfield v. Rosen 2015). It is difficult to
objectively know her true condition because, other than these affidavits, her current medical find-
ings are not accessible in the public record. In the Muñoz case, in response to a lawsuit filed by her
husband, a Texas judge ruled that she should be removed from the ventilator because the Texas law
requiring continued life-sustaining therapy to brain-damaged pregnant women for the benefit of the
fetus did not apply to dead women. Her ventilator treatment was then discontinued.
10. Portions of this section were adapted from Bernat (2013b), Bernat (2014b), and Bernat (in press).
360 3
11. See John Lizza’s (2009) anthology of articles relating personhood to death.
12. The classic debate over whether death is a process or an event was conducted in the pages of Science
by Morison (1971) and Kass (1971).
13. Chiong thereafter countered that Gert misunderstood and misrepresented his position. For the latest
chapter on this debate, see the point-counterpoint in (Bernat 2014b) and Chiong (2014). My col-
league, Andrew Huang, and I respond further to Chiong in our manuscript in preparation.
14. Mereology is the branch of philosophy that analyzes the differences between the properties of a whole
and its parts and explores their ontological relationship. The principles of biological mereology hold
the key to understanding the concept of the organism as a whole. See Hovda (2009).
15. Portions of this section were adapted from Bernat (2014b).
References
Ad Hoc Committee (1968). A definition of irreversible coma. Report of the Ad Hoc Committee of the
Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death. JAMA, 205, 337–340.
Aita, K. (2009). Japan approves brain death to increase organ donors: will it work? The Lancet, 374,
1403–1404.
Alexander, E. (2012). Proof of Heaven: A Neurosurgeon’s Journey into the Afterlife. New York: Simon &
Schuster.
American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Bioethics (2013). Policy statement: ethical
controversies in organ donation after circulatory death. Pediatrics, 131, 1021–1026.
Belkin, G.S. (2003). Brain death and the historical understanding of bioethics. Journal of the History of
Medicine and Allied Sciences, 58, 325–361.
Bernat, J.L. (1998). A defense of the whole-brain concept of death. Hastings Center Report, 28(2), 14–23.
Bernat, J.L. (2002). The biophilosophical basis of whole-brain death. Social Philosophy & Policy, 19,
324–342.
Bernat, J.L. (2006). The whole-brain concept of death remains optimum public policy. Journal of Law,
Medicine and Ethics, 34, 35–43.
Bernat, J.L. (2008a). Ethical Issues in Neurology (3rd edn.). Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott Williams &
Wilkins.
Bernat, J.L. (2008b). How can we achieve uniformity in brain death determinations? Neurology, 70,
252–253.
Bernat, J.L. (2010a). How the distinction between “irreversible” and “permanent” illuminates
circulatory-respiratory death determination. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 35(3), 242–255.
Bernat, J.L. (2010b). How autoresuscitation impacts death determination in organ donors. Critical Care
Medicine, 38, 1377–1378.
Bernat, J.L. (2013a). On noncongruence between the concept and determination of death. Hastings
Center Report, 43(6), 25–33.
Bernat, J.L. (2013b). The definition of death. In: Bernat, J.L. and Beresford, H.R. (Eds.) Ethical and Legal
Issues in Neurology. Handbook of Clinical Neurology (3rd Series, Volume 118), pp. 419–435. (Series
Eds. Aminoff, M.J., Boller, F., and Swaab, D.F.). Edinburgh: Elsevier.
Bernat, J.L. (2013c). Controversies in defining and determining death in critical care. Nature Reviews
Neurology, 9, 164–173.
Bernat, J.L. (2014a). Whither brain death? American Journal of Bioethics, 14(8): 3–8.
361
References 361
Bernat, J.L. (2014b). There can be agreement as to what constitutes human death. In: Caplan,
A.L. and Arp, R. (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Bioethics, pp.377–387, 397–398. Chichester,
UK: Wiley-Blackwell.
Bernat, J.L. (in press). Defining death. In: Moreman, C. (Ed.) Routledge Companion to Death and Dying.
London: Taylor & Francis/Routledge.
Bernat, J.L., Culver, C.M., and Gert, B. (1981). On the definition and criterion of death. Annals of
Internal Medicine, 94, 389–394.
Bernat, J.L., D’Alessandro, A.M., Port, F.K., et al. (2006). Report of a national conference on donation
after cardiac death. American Journal of Transplantation, 6, 281–291.
Bernat, J.L., Capron, A.M., Bleck, T.P., et al. (2010). The circulatory-respiratory determination of death
in organ donation. Critical Care Medicine, 38, 963–970.
Bernat, J.L., Bleck, T.P., Blosser, S., et al. (2014). Circulatory death determination in uncontrolled organ
donors: a panel viewpoint. Annals of Emergency Medicine, 63, 384–390.
Bleich, J.D. (1989). Of cerebral, respiratory and cardiac death. Tradition, 24(3), 44–66.
Bonelli, R.M., Prat, E.H., and Bonelli, J. (2009). Philosophical considerations on brain death and the
concept of the organism as a whole. Psychiatria Danubina, 21, 3–8.
Brock, D.W. (1999). The role of the public in public policy on the definition of death. In: Youngner, S.J.,
Arnold, R.M., and Schapiro, R. (Eds.) The Definition of Death: Contemporary Controversies, pp.293–
307. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Burkle, C.M., Schipper, A.M., and Wijdicks, E.F. (2011). Brain death and the courts. Neurology, 76,
837–841.
Byrne, P.A., O’Reilly, S., and Quay, P.M. (1979). Brain death—an opposing viewpoint. JAMA, 242,
1985–1990.
Campbell, C.S. (1999). Fundamentals of life and death: Christian fundamentalism and medical science.
In: Youngner, S.J., Arnold, R.M., and Schapiro, R. (Eds.) The Definition of Death: Contemporary
Controversies, pp.194–209. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press.
Capron, A.M. (2001). Brain death—well settled yet still unresolved. New England Journal of Medicine,
344, 1244–1246.
Capron, A.M. and Kass, L.R. (1972). A statutory definition of the standards for determining human
death: an appraisal and a proposal. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 121, 87–118.
Chiong, W. (2005). Brain death without definitions. Hastings Center Report, 35(6), 20–30.
Chiong, W. (2014). There cannot be agreement as to what constitutes human death: Against definitions,
necessary and sufficient conditions, and determinate boundaries. In: Caplan, A.L. and Arp, R. (Eds.)
Contemporary Debates in Bioethics, pp.388–396, 399–400. Chichester, UK: Wiley Blackwell.
Choi, E.K., Fredland, V., Zachodni, C., Lammers, J.E., Bledsoe, P., and Helft, P.R. (2008). Brain death
revisited: the case for a national standard. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 36, 824–836.
Citerio, G., Cypel, M., Dobb, D.J., et al. (2016). Organ donation in adults: a critical care perspective.
Intensive Care Medicine, 42, 305–315.
Clayton, P. and Kauffman, S.A. (2006). On emergence, agency, and organization. Biology and
Philosophy, 21, 501–521.
Cohen, J., Ashkenazi, T., Katvan, E., and Singer, P. (2012). Brain death determination in Israel: the
first two years experience following changes to the brain death law—opportunities and challenges.
American Journal of Transplantation, 12, 2514–2518.
Daoust, A. and Racine, E. (2014). Depictions of “brain death” in the media: medical and ethical
implications. Journal of Medical Ethics, 40, 253–259.
DeGrazia, D. (2011). The definition of death. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available
from: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/death-definition/ [accessed February 11, 2015].
362 3
DeVita, M.A. and Snyder, J.V. (1993). Development of the University of Pittsburgh Medical Center
policy for the care of terminally ill patients who may become organ donors after death following the
removal of life support. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3, 131–143.
Diringer, M.N. and Wijdicks, E.F.M. (2001). Brain death in historical perspective. In: Widjicks, E.F.M.
(Ed.) Brain Death, pp.5–27. New York: Oxford University Press.
Ecker, J.L. (2014). Death in pregnancy—an American tragedy. New England Journal of Medicine, 370,
889–891.
Emanuel, L.L. (1995). Re-examining death: the asymptotic model and a bounded zone definition.
Hastings Center Report, 25(4), 27–35.
Flamm, A.L., Smith, M.L., and Mayer, P.A. (2014). Family members’ requests to extend physiologic
support after declaration of brain death: a case series analysis and proposed guidelines for
management. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 25, 222–237.
Fry-Revere, S., Reher, T., and Ray, M. (2010). Death: a new legal perspective. Journal of Contemporary
Health Law and Policy, 27(1), 1–75.
Furton, E.J. (1999). Reflections on the status of brain death. Ethics and Medics, 24(10), 2–4.
Furton, E.J. (2002). Brain death, the soul, and organic life. National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly, 2,
455–470.
Gardiner, D., Shemie, S., Manara, A., and Opdam, H. (2012). International perspective on the
diagnosis of death. British Journal of Anesthesia, 108 (S1), i14-i28.
Gert, B. (2006). Matters of life and death. Hastings Center Report, 36(3), 4.
Gervais, K.G. (1986). Redefining Death. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Giacomini, M. (1997). A change of heart and a change of mind? Technology and the redefinition of
death in 1968. Social Sciences in Medicine, 44, 1465–1482.
Gostin, L.O. (2014). Legal and ethical responsibilities following brain death: the McMath and Muñoz
cases. JAMA, 311, 903–904.
Greer, D.M., Wang, H.W., Robinson, J.D., Varelas, P.N., Henderson, G.V., and Wijdicks, E.F.M. (2016).
Variability of brain death policies in the United States. Neurology, 73, 213–218.
Haas, J.M. (2011). Catholic teaching regarding the legitimacy of neurological criteria for the
determination of death. National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly, 11(2), 279–299.
Halevy, A. and Brody, B. (1993). Brain death: reconciling definitions, criteria, and tests. Annals of
Internal Medicine, 119, 519–525.
Hornby, K., Hornby, L., and Shemie, S.D. (2010). A systematic review of autoresuscitation after cardiac
arrest. Critical Care Medicine, 38, 1246–1253.
Hovda, P. (2009). What is classical mereology? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38(1), 55–82.
Iltis, A.S. (2015). Organ donation, brain death and the family: valid informed consent. Journal of Law,
Medicine and Ethics, 43(2), 369–382.
Institute of Medicine (2000). Non-Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation: Practice and Protocols.
Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Jain, S. and Maheshawari, M.C. (1995). Brain death—the Indian perspective. In: Machado, C. (Ed.)
Brain Death, pp.261–263. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Joffe, A. (2010). Are recent defences of the brain death concept adequate? Bioethics, 24(2), 47–53.
Joffe, A., Carcillo, J., Anton, N., et al. (2011). Donation after cardiocirculatory death: a call for a
moratorium pending full public disclosure and fully informed consent. Philosophy, Ethics, and
Humanities in Medicine, 6, 17.
Kass, L. (1971). Death as an event: a commentary on Robert Morison. Science. 173. 698–702.
Kennedy, I.M. (1971). The Kansas statute on death—an appraisal. New England Journal of Medicine,
285, 946–950.
36
References 363
Nakagawa, T.A., Ashwal, S., Mathur, M., et al. (2011). Guidelines for the determination of brain death
in infants and children: an update of the 1987 Task Force recommendations. Critical Care Medicine,
39, 2139–2155.
Olick, R.S. (1991). Brain death, religious freedom, and public policy: New Jersey’s landmark legislative
initiative. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 4, 275–288.
Olick, R.S., Braun, E.A., and Potash, J. (2009). Accommodating religious and moral objections to
neurological death. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 20, 183–191.
Olson, E.T. (1997). The identity of organisms. In: The Human Animal: Personal Identity Without
Psychology, pp.131–135. New York: Oxford University Press.
Orr, R.D. and Genesen, L.B. (1997). Requests for inappropriate treatment based on religious beliefs.
Journal of Medical Ethics, 23, 142–147.
Overby, K.J., Weinstein, M.S., and Fiester, A. (2015). Addressing consent issues in donation after
circulatory determination of death. American Journal of Bioethics, 15(8), 3–9.
Padela, A.I., Arozullah, A., and Moosa, E. (2013). Brain death in Islamic ethico-legal
deliberation: challenges for applied Islamic bioethics. Bioethics, 27, 132–139.
Pallis, C. (1995). ABC of Brainstem Death (2nd edn.). London: British Medical Journal Publishers.
Parnia, S. and Fenwick, P. (2002). Near death experiences in cardiac arrest: visions of a dying brain or
visions of a new science of consciousness. Resuscitation, 52, 9–11.
Pernick, M.S. (1999). Brain death in a cultural context: the reconstruction of death 1967–1981.
In: Youngner, S.J., Arnold, R.M., and Schapiro, R. (Eds.) The Definition of Death: Contemporary
Controversies, pp.3–33. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Pinker, S. (1997). How the Mind Works. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.
Pontifical Academy of Sciences (2007). The Signs of Death. Scripta Varia 110. Vatican City: Pontifical
Academy of Sciences.
Pope John Paul II (2000, August 29). Address of the Holy Father John Paul II to the 18th International
Congress of the Transplantation Society, August 29, Rome. http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_
paul_ii/speeches/2000/jul-sep/documents/hf_jp-ii_spe_20000829_transplants_en.html [accessed
June 4, 2012].
Pope, T.M. (2014). Legal briefing: brain death and total brain failure. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 25(3),
245–257.
President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and
Behavioral Research (1981). Defining Death. Medical, Ethical, and Legal Issues in the Determination
of Death. Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office.
President’s Council on Bioethics (2008). Controversies in the Determination of Death: A White Paper by
the President’s Council on Bioethics. Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office.
Racine, E., Amaram, R., Seidler, M., Karczuska, M., and Illes, J. (2008). Media coverage of the
persistent vegetative state and end-of-life decision-making. Neurology, 71, 1027–1032.
Repertinger, S., Fitzgibbons, W.P., Omojola, M.F., and Brumback, R.A. (2006). Long survival following
bacterial meningitis-associated brain destruction. Journal of Child Neurology, 21, 591–595.
Rodriguez-Arias, D., Tortosa, J.C., Burant, C.J., Aubert, P., Aulisio, M.P., and Youngner, S.J. (2013).
One or two types of death? Attitudes of health professionals towards brain death and donation after
circulatory death in three countries. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 16, 457–467.
Rosner, F. (1999). The definition of death in Jewish law. In: Youngner, S.J., Arnold, R.M., and Schapiro,
R. (Eds.) The Definition of Death: Contemporary Controversies, pp.210–221. Baltimore, MD: Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Rosner, F. and Tendler, M.D. (1989). Definition of death in Judaism. Journal of Halacha and
Contemporary Society, 17, 14–31.
365
References 365
Shah, S.K. and Miller, F.G. (2010). Can we handle the truth? Legal fictions in the determination of
death. American Journal of Law & Medicine, 36, 540–585.
Shewmon, D.A. (1998). Chronic “brain death:” meta-analysis and conceptual consequences. Neurology,
51, 1538–1545.
Shewmon, D.A. (2001). The brain and somatic integration: insights into the standard biological
rationale for equating “brain death” with death. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 26, 457–478.
Shewmon, D.A. (2004). The “critical organ” for the organism as a whole: lessons from the lowly spinal
cord. Advances in Experimental Medicine and Biology, 550, 23–42.
Shewmon, D.A. (2009). Brain death: can it be resuscitated? Hastings Center Report, 39(2), 18–24.
Shewmon, D.A. (2010). Constructing the death elephant: a synthetic paradigm shift for the definition,
criteria, and tests for death. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 35, 256–298.
Shewmon, D.A. and Shewmon, E.S. (2004). The semiotics of death and its medical implications.
Advances in Experimental Medicine and Biology, 550, 89–114.
Siminoff, L.A., Burant, C., and Youngner, S.J. (2004). Death and organ procurement: public beliefs and
attitudes. Kennedy Institute for Ethics Journal, 14, 217–234.
Soloveichik, A. (1979). The Halakhic definition of death. In: Rosner, F. and Bleich, J.D. (Eds.) Jewish
Bioethics, pp.296–302. New York: Sanhedrin Press.
Spike, J. and Greenlaw, J. (1995). Ethics consultation: persistent brain death and religion: must a person
believe in death to die? Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 23, 291–294.
Taylor, R.M. (1997). Reexamining the definition and criterion of death. Seminars in Neurology, 17,
265–270.
Truog, R.D. (1997). Is it time to abandon brain death? Hastings Center Report, 27(1), 29–37.
Veatch, R.M. (1975). The whole brain-oriented concept of death: an outmoded philosophical
formulation. Journal of Thanatology, 3, 13–30.
Veatch, R.M. (1993). The impending collapse of the whole-brain definition of death. Hastings Center
Report, 23(4), 18–24.
Veatch, R.M. (1999). The conscience clause: how much individual choice in defining death can
our society tolerate? In: Youngner SJ, Arnold RM and Schapiro R (eds). The Definition of
Death: Contemporary Controversies. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press: 137–160.
Veith, F.J., Fein, J.M., Tendler, M.D., et al. (1977a). Brain death I. A status report of medical and ethical
considerations. JAMA, 238, 1651–1655.
Veith, F.J., Fein, J.M., Tendler, M.D., et al. (1977b). Brain death II. A status report of legal
considerations. JAMA, 238, 1744–1748.
Wahlster, S., Wijdicks, E.F., Patel, P.V., et al. (2015). Brain death declaration: practices and perceptions
worldwide. Neurology, 84, 1870–1879.
Wijdicks, E.F.M. (2002). Brain death worldwide. Accepted fact but no global consensus in diagnostic
criteria. Neurology, 58, 20–25.
Wijdicks, E.F.M. (2003). The neurologist and the Harvard criteria for brain death. Neurology, 61,
970–976.
Wijdicks, E.F.M. (2011). Brain Death (2nd edn.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Wijdicks, E.F., Varelas, P.N., Gronseth, G.S., and Greer, D.M. (2010). American Academy of Neurology.
Evidence-based guideline update: determining brain death in adults: report of the Quality Standards
Subcommittee of the American Academy of Neurology. Neurology, 74, 1911–1918.
Winkfield v. Rosen. First Amended Complaint for Damages for Medical Malpractice, Case No. Rg
15760730, Superior Court of the State of California for the County of Alameda, filed November
4, 2015.
36 3
Yaqub, B.A. and Al-Deeb, S.M. (1996). Brain death: current status in Saudi Arabia. Saudi Medical
Journal, 17, 5–10.
Youngner, S.J. (1992). Defining death: a superficial and fragile consensus. Archives of Neurology, 49,
570–572.
Youngner, S.J. and Bartlett, E.T. (1983). Human death and high technology: the failure of the whole
brain formulations. Annals of Internal Medicine, 99, 252–258.
367
Part III
Chapter 19
Introduction
Biomedical research enables improvements in diagnosis and treatment of human dis-
eases, and participation in research is the cornerstone of such medical progress. Indeed,
the scholarly beginnings of the bioethics field are often attributed to human rights ques-
tions concerning the ethics of human participation in research, and which have since
influenced every biomedical field from pediatrics (Diekema 2006) to aging (Kim et al.
2001), and genomics (Knoppers 2013) to neurology (Choudhury et al. 2014). The com-
pletion of the Human Genome Project in 2003 brought about paradigmatic shifts in the
nature and conduct of biomedical research. This shift toward data-intensive science is evi-
dent in the ways that analysis, exchange, and reporting now occur increasingly in virtual
(e.g., the cloud commons (Stein et al. 2015)) rather than physical spaces.
The participation of humans in research remains nevertheless a central consideration in
bioethics, and an increasingly complex area for policy development as research becomes
more data intensive and data driven. This is particularly true for the participation of cat-
egorically vulnerable populations in biomedical research—such as minors and incom-
petent adults—who warrant special protections against potential rights violations and
exposure to undue risk or, to undue exclusion and deprivation of the benefits of research.
In this chapter, we provide both a retrospective and prospective analysis of research
involving these two populations with a special focus on the data-intensive sciences such
as genomics and its related “omics” disciplines. In doing so, our analysis adopts what we
term “reverse vulnerability” as one lens through which to examine the ethical intersec-
tionalities between both populations in an effort to better complement governance strate-
gies to the contemporary realities of data-intensive science and data sharing.
The first and second parts of this chapter provide a policy overview of research participa-
tion and the protection of minors and incompetent adults living with dementia. We com-
ment on the practical and theoretical implications of reverse vulnerability to an emerging
area of contemporary policy development: international data sharing. A reinvigorated
370 3
discussion of research participation involving minors and patients living with dementia
necessarily precedes, in our view, policy-making for sharing research data.
Historically, the parens patriae doctrine was the first to legitimize the legal status of
vulnerable persons and the State’s obligation to protect them. This legal doctrine stipu-
lates that the government acts as a guardian of all persons legally incapable of acting on
their own, even in the absence of specific legislation (Griffith 1991). Such State powers
are protective of both property and personal interests, and are usually exercised by the
courts. Both children and incompetent adults are legally presumed to be unable to make
decisions concerning their health, welfare, or involvement in research. It was not until the
Nuremberg Code in 1947, and later the Declaration of Helsinki in 1964, that the interests of
minors and incompetent adults were specifically addressed in medical research.
Ethical principles outlined in the Nuremberg Code emphasized protection through
exclusion, while the Declaration endorsed their inclusion albeit with special protections.
Most countries recognize parents or family members as primary decision-making author-
ities for minors and incompetent adults. Surprisingly, however, neither the 1989 United
Nations (UN) Convention on the Rights of the Child, nor the 2006 UN Convention on
the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (the latter encompassing incompetent adults such
as “those living” with dementia) explicitly addresses their inclusion in research.
From these historically protective stances toward vulnerable populations in research,
international ethics norms evolved to adopt more promotional approaches. The European
Clinical Trials Directive is but one example that testifies to this evolution, which positively
mandates the inclusion of children and incompetent adults in clinical trials in Europe
(European Parliament & the Council of the European Union 2014, s. 32(1)).
Table 19.1 summarizes the Directive, as well as other international ethics guidelines
with specific mention of research involving vulnerable persons.
International ethics guidelines promote the inclusion of incompetent adults in research
as for minors, provided certain special protections. The benefits, either direct or indi-
rect, as a result of their participation justify such inclusion in part, to say nothing of the
fact that certain diseases belong to these groups exclusively. Furthermore, improved stan-
dards of care for conditions earlier or later in life may not otherwise emerge without the
participation of these populations. Data-intensive research involving vulnerable groups,
we argue, must reconcile protective and promotional stances to make way for realistic
and proportional risk analysis and governance. Only then can we facilitate, rather than
obstruct, a future of open science required to advance (personalized) medicine for minors
and patients living with dementia, among others.
Children and minors
The history of children in biomedical research has been (paradoxically) marked by both
grave human rights abuses as well as groundbreaking clinical progress. Their participation
in research has, in turn, long raised ethical concerns. An era of over-protectionism ensued
in the wake of research abuses involving children such as those at the Willowbrook State
371
Table 19.1 International ethics guidelines on the participation of vulnerable persons in medical research
Council for Guideline 15: Research involving vulnerable persons Commentary on Guideline 15:
International When vulnerable individuals and groups are considered for … It is important to recognize that vulnerability involves not
Organizations of recruitment in research, researchers and research ethics commit- only the ability to provide initial consent to participate in
Medical Sciences tees must ensure that specific protections are in place to safe- research, but also aspects of the ongoing participation in
(CIOMS) (2016) guard the rights and welfare of these individuals and groups in research studies. In some cases, persons are vulnerable because
International Ethical the conduct of the research. they are relatively (or absolutely) incapable of protecting their
Guidelines for own interests. This may occur when persons have relative
Health-related or absolute impairments in decisional capacity, education,
Research Involving resources, strength, or other attributes needed to protect their
Humans own interests. In other cases, persons can also be vulnerable
because some feature of the circumstances (temporary or per-
manent) in which they live makes it less likely that others will be
vigilant about, or sensitive to, their interests.
(continued)
372
Table 19.1 Continued
School, Staten Island, New York City, between the late 1950s and early 1970s (Diekema
2006). While the motivation for a protectionist approach was well intentioned, such poli-
cies resulted in children’s near exclusion from biomedical research generally. The con-
sequences of which resulted in a dearth of pediatric-specific therapies (Fernandez et al.
2003), felt even today as standards of care derived from clinical trial findings are often
extrapolated from studies in adults.
Children and adolescents are not miniature adults, but differ both physiologically and
psychologically. Thus, pediatric research is essential to developing treatments that are
safe and effective for children and adolescents, specifically. Advances in pediatric health
research improve the way we understand child and adolescent health, disease, and devel-
opment, and how these are influenced by factors such as genetics and the environment.
Classical tensions related to the involvement of children as vulnerable participants in
research are synthesized in Table 19.2, and include how researchers determine the appro-
priate level of protection, the extent of parental authority and surrogate decision-making,
and gauge the developing autonomy of minors. Transformative biotechnologies such as
next-generation sequencing instantiate these classic tensions, but also shape new chal-
lenges around their responsible deployment and applications in the clinic.
Inclusion
Today, the need to include children and adolescents in research is recognized by inter-
national guidelines such as the United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural
Organisation (UNESCO) Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights pub-
lished in 1997 (s. 5(e)) and 2005 (s. 7), the Council for International Organizations of
Medical Sciences (CIOMS) International Ethical Guidelines for Health-Related Research
Involving Humans (2016, s. 3, 17), and the Council of Europe Convention on Human
Rights and Biomedicine (1997, s. 17(1)(ii)(iii)) and its Additional Protocol (2005, s. 15(1)(i)
(ii)). Indeed, such guidelines generally indicate that vulnerable persons, such as minors,
should be included in research when it is justifiable, when their rights are protected, and
when their safety and well-being have been considered.
Overall, minors can be involved in pediatric research when the research cannot be car-
ried out on adults (World Medical Association (WMA) 2013, s. 20); parental consent, as
well as the minor’s assent (when possible) has been obtained; and the research involves
minimal risk. There is a stronger justification for their inclusion when direct clinical ben-
efit is anticipated (World Medical Association (WMA) 1964, s. 17; Council of Europe
1997, s. 17(1)(ii)(2), 2005, s. 15(2); UNESCO 1997, s. 5(e), 2005, s. 7(b); CIOMS 2002, s.
8–9; CIOMS 2016, s. 17). Other guidelines formulate differently their position that “the
interventions and procedures should be studied in adults first [. . .], unless the necessary
data cannot be obtained without participation of children or adolescents; and the risks
must be minimized and no more than minimal.” However, “when the social value of the
studies with such research interventions and procedures is compelling, and these studies
cannot be conducted in adults, a research ethics committee may permit a minor increase
above minimal risk” (CIOMS, 2016, s. 17).
374
Consent
As children do not have the legal capacity to consent to their own participation in
research, international norms generally state that parental consent or permission of the
authorized legal representative is required (WMA 2013, s. 28; Council of Europe 1997,
s. 6.2, 17(1)(iv), 2005, s. 15(1)(ii); CIOMS 2016, s. 17; UNESCO 2005, s. 7), and that the
best interests of the child should be considered in this decision (UNESCO 2003, 2005).
They furthermore stipulate what information should appear in the consent form so as
to ensure parental consent is fully informed (e.g., the goal and nature of the research,
the potential risks and benefits, the right to withdraw, the protection of privacy and
confidentiality, the compensation for participation) (Council of Europe 1997, s. 5, 2005,
s. 13(2); UNESCO 2005, s. 6(2)). Some guidelines also set more technical requirements,
such as adapting consent language in line with the capacity of parents (Council of
Europe 2005, s. 13(1); UNESCO 2005, s. 6(2)). Although required, the scope of parental
consent can be controversial in particular research contexts. Longitudinal cohort stud-
ies or pediatric biobanking testify to this, where consent to research participation is a
continuous process that may span a lifetime.
Not only should consent be ongoing throughout the research project, but it should be
renewed if significant changes are made to the research protocol (Council of Europe 2005,
s. 24(2)). In addition, the CIOMS also states that, “if children reach the legal age of matu-
rity during the research, their consent to continued participation should be obtained”
(CIOMS 2016, s. 17). The likelihood requiring reconsent are perhaps greatest for longi-
tudinal studies, where child participants eventually reach the age of majority while still
enrolled in the study. A minor’s capacity to consent can thus evolve over time, and during
the course of the research. As a result, this may necessitate the re-contact of minors once
they reach the age of majority, or once they become legally capable of deciding for them-
selves (Knoppers et al. 2016).
Assent of the child
In addition to parental or legal representative consent, applicable norms and policies
surrounding the involvement of children in research consider the emerging maturity
of a child, even if children do not have the legal capacity to consent. The 1998 inter-
national Convention on the Rights of the Child recognizes a child’s right to be heard in
decision-making despite their inability to consent. Specifically, “[a]child who is capable
of forming his or her own views [has] the right to express those views freely in all matters
affecting the child, the views of the child being given due weight in accordance with the
age and maturity of the child” (United Nations General Assembly 1989, s. 12(1)). Thus,
it is equally important for the researcher to obtain the assent of a child who has the
capacity to participate at this level prior to inclusion in research (WMA 2013, s. 28–29;
Council of Europe 1997, s. 6(2), 2005, s. 15(1)(iv); CIOMS 2016, s. 17, 2008, s. 13–14;
UNESCO 2003, s. 8(b)(c), 2005, s. 7(a)). Since 1964, the WMA has adopted this posi-
tion in the Declaration of Helsinki (2013, s. 29), as well as the CIOMS (2016, s. 17),
376
the Council of Europe in the Convention on Biomedicine (1997, s. 6(2)) and its Additional
Protocol (2005).
Despite recognizing the child’s assent dependent on age and maturity, this concept is
not uniformly defined or determined across clinical contexts. The UNESCO Universal
Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights defines assent as the duty to involve a person
who is unable to express consent “[…] to the greatest extent possible in the decision-
making process of consent, as well as that of withdrawing consent” (2005, s. 7(a)). The
International Bioethics Committee of UNESCO identifies the circumstances in which
this involvement should occur in their Report on Consent: individuals unable to consent
“[…] should be involved in the decision-making process according to their age, maturity,
and/or degree of capacity to consent” (2008, s. 164).
In addition to the absence of strict criteria, determining a child’s capacity can also vary
according to the quality or quantity of information given, the research environment, or
the relationship with the researcher or the research team. A change in any of these con-
textual factors could have a significant effect on the child’s capacity as a result, which
may occur at any point throughout the course of a research project. As with consent,
assent is a continuous process that may need to be reconfirmed throughout the duration
of the research, especially in the case of longitudinal studies and, more increasingly with
genomic data sharing that spans years or decades.
Dissent of the child
All norms governing pediatric research state that the opposition of a child to participate
in research (dissent of the child) should be respected (WMA 2013, s. 29; Council of
Europe 1997, s. 6(2), 2005, s. 15(1)(iv); CIOMS 2016, s. 17, 2008, s. 13–14; UNESCO
2003, s. 8(b)(c)), even if parental consent has been obtained. Most international norms,
however, do not provide further guidance on how to formally acknowledge the child’s
dissent. Dissent typically requires a minor to possess the same level of capacity that is
needed for assent. Thus, if the child is too young, too immature, or unable to understand
the nature of the research, his or her dissent may be overridden. The CIOMS (2002), for
example, outlines that the dissent of a minor must be respected, unless, in exceptional
circumstances, research participation is considered the best medical option for a child
or adolescent (s. 17). The return of genetic/genomic results and incidental findings with
next-generation sequencing puts these issues of consent/assent and dissent into sharp
relief, and will be discussed in depth in the following section (“Return of results and
incidental findings”).
Incompetent adults 377
in consideration of the child’s best interests, holds that the potential to return inciden-
tal findings should be addressed at the time that informed consent is obtained (i.e.,
the decision to return results or not should be agreed upon in advance) (Knoppers et
al. 2014a). Incidental findings that are “scientifically valid, clinically useful, and reveal
conditions that are preventable and actionable during childhood should be offered”
(Knoppers et al. 2014a, p.5), while those that relate to an adult-onset disorder should not
be returned, so as to preserve the child’s future autonomy and decision-making ability.
The Statement also confirms that the views of the child or adolescent should be consid-
ered at the time of consent/assent based on his or her age and maturity (Knoppers et al.
2014a), reinforcing the need to respect the child’s evolving decision-making capacities.
In sum, a framework addressing pediatric research exists at the international level. The
principles and guidance, however, typically stem from research ethics norms applicable
in the clinical setting, and which are not always applicable in the data-intensive research
context typified by genomics. The norms included here underscore the need to include
children in research, but do not provide specific guidance on how to manage the evolving
maturity of children and their capacity to consent to research. While it has been estab-
lished that the pediatric population should neither be excluded from medical research
nor considered therapeutic orphans (Shirkey 1968, 1999; Rieder & Hazardous Substances
Committee 2011), amending these international norms to address contemporary ethical
uncertainties, namely in the data-intensive sciences and genomics, is warranted.
Guidance is furthermore lacking with respect to how these uncertainties in the data-
intensive sciences relate to incompetent adults living with dementia. Such persons’ inabil-
ity to consent to research participation is an ethical intersectionality they share with
children and minors. We explore this intersectionality, which we define as “reverse vul-
nerability” in further depth in the next section (“Incompetent adults”).
Incompetent adults
As the global population ages, so too has there been a steady increase in dementia and
dementia-related diseases across high-, middle-, and low-income countries (Brookmeyer
et al. 2007). With nearly 7.7 million new cases per year (World Health Organization
2012, 2016), there is considerable clinical demand (Fox & Petersen 2013; Ngandu et al.
2015) and political pressure for innovative research with curative goals (Department of
Health & Prime Minister’s Office 2013; Canadian Institutes of Health Research 2014).
Timely diagnosis, health-related quality of life, and innovation in new therapies for
patients living with dementia, however, are markedly lacking. Advances in genomics
hold great promise toward improving patient outcomes through drug discovery, eluci-
dating risk reduction strategies, and slowing disease progression. To realize this prom-
ise, research priorities, data governance mechanisms, and alternative frameworks for
consent are needed. In particular, collaboration between dementia research and care,
and improvement in the accessibility of genomic and health data should be promoted
378
across borders. Respect for persons and data protections for patients living with dementia
have both emerged as ethical priorities in turn. Perhaps more acute than in the pediatric
context, the scope of decision-making authority among legally authorized representa-
tives is increasingly becoming a barrier to the sharing of incompetent adults’ research
data.
Inclusion
Similar to minors, the inclusion of incompetent adults living with dementia in research
is protected under international conventions and guidelines summarized in Table 19.3.
While these conventions and guidelines acknowledge that incompetent adults warrant
special protections in research—and some explicitly identify living with dementia as a
hallmark scenario of vulnerability in adults—the guidelines differ in their management
of vulnerability and types of research permissible as determined by level of risk. For
example, the Declaration of Helsinki stipulates that research with vulnerable populations
is “only justified if the research is responsive to the health needs or priorities of this group”
(WMA 2013, s. 20) while the CIOMS guidelines outline a set of criteria for determining
ethically appropriate participation (2016, s. 17). The UNESCO Declaration on Bioethics
and Human Rights (2005) is unique in this regard in two ways. First, it invokes concepts of
both minimal risk as well as minimal burden in rationalizing the participation of vulner-
able groups. Second, the human rights orientation of these guidelines marry the concepts
of personal integrity and best interests standards upon which the decision to participate
in research should be based for groups such as incompetent adults. Legally authorized
representatives (LARs) are the primary shareholders of these best interests on behalf of
incompetent adults, as well as for minors.
Incompetent adults 379
(continued)
380
Table 19.3 Continued
Political Declaration 12(j) Harnessing of scientific research and expertise and realizing the
and Madrid potential of technology to focus on, inter alia, the individual, social
International Plan and health implications of ageing, in particular in developing
of Action on Ageing countries;
(United Nations Second 75(e) Encourage, at all levels, arrangements and incentives to mobilize
World Assembly on commercial enterprises, especially pharmaceutical enterprises,
Ageing 2002) to invest in research aimed at finding remedies that can be pro-
vided at affordable prices for diseases that particularly afflict
older persons in developing countries and invite the World Health
Organization to consider improving partnerships between the pub-
lic and private sectors in the area of health research
86(b) Develop, where appropriate, effective strategies to increase the
level of quality assessment and diagnosis of Alzheimer’s and
related disorders at an early stage. Research on these disorders
should be undertaken on a multidisciplinary basis that meets the
needs of the patient, health professionals and carers;
United Nations Article 7
Principles for Older Older persons should remain integrated in society, participate actively
Persons (United Nations in the formulation and implementation of policies that directly affect
General Assembly 1991) their well-being and share their knowledge and skills with younger
generations.
Article 8
Older persons should be able to seek and develop opportunities for ser-
vice to the community and to serve as volunteers in positions appropriate
to their interests and capabilities.
the severity of their disease. Decision-making capacity may therefore be task, time, and
context dependent.
Taken together, these decisional capacities should be evaluated on a continuous basis,
and a LAR identified early in the dementia trajectory. According to the conventions and
guidelines outlined in Table 19.3, adults living with dementia who are deemed incompe-
tent should be granted the opportunity to assent or dissent to participation in research
before becoming incompetent. A LAR may override a decision in cases where the partici-
pant has not stated an express wish to be involved in research, or when their participation
would constitute greater than minimal risk. Like for children, the best interests standard
varies considerably by jurisdiction and in how it is invoked to justify one’s inclusion or
exclusion from research, particularly if no direct clinical benefit is anticipated. The United
Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2008) safeguards the right to
engage in political, social, and cultural life, which could be interpreted to include partici-
pation in research as an exercise of civic engagement. The Convention protects the rights
to dignity, autonomy, independence, and participation in society. We argue that deci-
sion-making associated with the type(s) of research participation, as well as the sharing of
research data should be considered extensions of the latter participatory right protected
under the Convention.
Researchers are also implicated in the fulfillment of a participant’s best interest, particu-
larly when they express prior wishes related to the return of results/incidental findings
or participation in research generally. As Figure 19.1 illustrates, participants’ wishes may
be unknown. In this case, researchers along with substitute decision-makers are charged
with determining the appropriateness of returning results based on the clinical action-
ability of the result and the participant’s best interest(s).
Figure 19.1 CCMG guidelines for return of results and incidental findings for children and
incompetent adults in research.
38
Summary 383
Summary
As illustrated in this chapter, minors and incompetent adults are considered situationally
vulnerable within a research context. It is as a result of this vulnerability that special pro-
tections in research are justified. The nuances of such vulnerability, however, have impor-
tant implications for laying a responsible governance framework for sharing research
data involving both minors and incompetent adults living with dementia. Lange and col-
leagues have introduced the “situationality concept” for nuancing the typology of vulner-
ability that patients with dementia, and other vulnerable groups with limited cognitive
capacity may experience (Lange et al. 2013). It aligns furthermore with the framing of
vulnerability in the CIOMS (2016) guidelines: “[o]ne widely accepted criterion of vulner-
ability is limited capacity to consent or decline to consent to research participation” (com-
mentary, s. 15). The limitations to capacity can be task, time, or context specific. In this
way, the situational vulnerability that emerges from an inability to consent to research is
a useful ethical intersectionality upon which a policy for genomic data sharing involving
minors and incompetent adults living with dementia can build. Both populations share
task-oriented deficiencies in their capacity to make research participation decisions, but
differ in time-and context-oriented capacities. The decisional capacities of these two pop-
ulations and their substitute decision-makers, as well as the special ethical protections the
research community affords them, differ in their temporal and contextual specificities.
Each component of capacity—time, task, and context—will be next compared for minors
and incompetent adults living with dementia, respectively.
First, the situational vulnerability of minors with respect to decision-making in
research is inversely related to their burgeoning autonomy. The convergence point
heralding the end of minors’ situational vulnerability and societal recognition of their
decision-making ability is legally benchmarked upon reaching the age of majority.
Whereas minors mature out of their situational vulnerability that arises from a tem-
porary inability to consent to research (and in many cases clinical care), incompetent
adults living with dementia can regress into situational vulnerability commensurate with
their cognitive decline. The authors define this phenomenon “reverse vulnerability,” a
compelling ethical consideration when charting the ethics of responsible genomic and
health-related data sharing.
384
Second, in the case of minors, parents are charged with deciding whether, and to what
extent, to share their child’s genomic data. Research suggests parents make this decision
in line with their understanding of informational risks that data sharing poses for their
children today, as they mature into adults, as well as their altruistic intentions to support
further research through secondary data use.
Third, the ethical significance of task-related capacity can be directly compared between
persons living with dementia and minors. That is, the cognitive tasks associated with pro-
viding informed consent to research require the same facilities and reasoning regardless
of whether an incompetent adult person with dementia or a minor makes this decision.
To make a decision to participate in research, a number of task-specific capacities are
required. These include that prospective participants understand the nature and purpose
of the investigation, they acknowledge the roles and activities necessary to participate,
and they appreciate the immediate and future implications of their participation. Singh
(2007), however, proposes a shift in the ethical weight researchers should attribute the
task-specific capacities of vulnerable groups such as children and incompetent adults.
She emphasizes the communicative process, rather than a strictly comprehension-
oriented definition of task-specific capacity is relevant both to clinical and research
decision-making:
Children’s task-specific capacities defy their characterization as vulnerable, incapacitated patients
who are fully dependent on surrogate decision-makers … children must have the capacity to dis-
cuss their understanding of diagnosis and treatment. This understanding need not be correct to
be interesting and informative; therefore the capacity is specific to the task of communication, as
opposed to understanding. (Singh 2007, p.S36)
Finally, surrogate decision-makers charged with ensuring the best interests of minors and
incompetent adults are motivated by different decisional outcomes. These differences can
provide some clarity to the contextual distinction in decision-making capacities between
the two populations. Parents make decisions on behalf of their child temporarily, and
with an overarching motivation to protect as a means of fostering independency in the
future. Care providers or other legally authorized representatives also make decisions
with a chiefly protective aim, yet do so as an exercise of managing the incompetent adult’s
gradual dependency on others.
References 385
elsewhere extensively on the human rights underpinnings of this second ethical imper-
ative (Knoppers et al. 2014b). International support for data sharing resulted in the
founding of which the Global Alliance for Genomics and Health, and adoption of its
Framework for the Responsible Sharing of Genomic and Health-Related Data (Knoppers
2014). Founded on the right of all citizens to benefit from scientific progress (General
Assembly of the United Nations 1948, s. 47), the Framework promotes a positive obliga-
tion on governments to act in respect of this right. For minors and incompetent adults
who require LARs to act on their behalf, data sharing for research that is in their interest
should be encouraged in light of their specific needs. A proportionate risk analysis that
is based on the possible occurrence of real risks and the actual probability of their occur-
rence argues in favor of their inclusion in international data sharing initiatives. In line
with the human rights foundations upon which the Global Alliance was founded, this
chapter contends that the ethical intersectionalities between children and incompetent
adults helps orient research and data governance that is better tailored to the contempo-
rary challenges facing them in the post-genomic era. Policy collaboration and empirical
policy research are needed if vulnerable populations are to continue benefiting from the
fruits of scientific progress made possible through concerted data sharing efforts.
Acknowledgments
The authors wish to thank the Vanier Canada Graduate Scholarship (CIHR), the Canada
Research Chair in Law and Medicine, Ministère de l’Économie, de la Science et de
l’Innovation du Québec, PSR-SIIRI-850 (Canada), the Fond de Recherche du Québec-
Santé, and the Québec Network of Applied Genetic Medicine (RMGA) for their funding
support. The excerpt from Article 12 was reproduced from “Convention on the Rights of
the Child,” by United Nations Human Rights Office of the High Commissioner, © 1989/
1990 United Nations. Reprinted with the permission of the United Nations.
References
Black, B.S., Rabins, P.V., Sugarman, J., and Karlawish, J.H. (2010). Seeking assent and respecting
dissent in dementia research. American Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 18(1), 77–85.
Boycott, K., Hartley, T., Adam, S., et al. (2015). The clinical application of genome-wide sequencing for
monogenic diseases in Canada: position statement of the Canadian College of Medical Geneticists.
Journal of Medical Genetics, 52(7), 431–7.
Brookmeyer, R., Johnson, E., Ziegler-Graham, K., and Arrighi, H.M. (2007). Forecasting the global
burden of Alzheimer’s disease: forecasting the global burden. Alzheimer’s & Dementia, 3(3), 186–191.
Canadian Institutes of Health Research (2014). Second Global Dementia Legacy Event Harnessing the
Power of Discoveries: Maximizing Academia-Industry Synergies. Ottawa, ON: Canadian Institutes of
Health Research.
Choudhury, S., Fishman, J.R., McGowan, M.L., and Juengst, E.T. (2014). Big data, open science and
the brain: lessons learned from genomics. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 239.
Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS) and the World Health
Organization (WHO) (2016). International Ethical Guidelines for Health-Related Research Involving
Humans. Geneva, Switzerland: COMS.
386
Council of Europe (1997). Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine. Oviedo, Spain: Council of
Europe.
Council of Europe (2005). Additional Protocol to the Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine,
concerning Biomedical Research. Strasbourg, France: Council of Europe.
Department of Health and Prime Minister’s Office (2013). G8 Dementia Summit Agreement.
London: Department of Health.
Derse, A. and Spellecy, R. (2015). Ethical and regulatory considerations regarding enrollment of
incompetent adults in more than minimal risk research as compared with children. American
Journal of Bioethics, 15(10), 68–69.
Diekema, D.S. (2006). Conducting ethical research in pediatrics: a brief historical overview and review
of pediatric regulations. Journal of Pediatrics, 149(Suppl. 1), S3–11.
European Parliament and the Council of the European Union (2014). EU Clinical Trials Directive
2001/20/EC., L 269(September 2000), 1–15.
Fernandez, C., Kodish, E., and Weijer, C. (2003). Informing study participants of research results: an
ethical imperative. IRB: Ethics & Human Research, 25(3),12–9.
Fox, N.C. and Petersen, R.C. (2013). The G8 Dementia Research Summit –a starter for eight? The
Lancet, 382(9909), 1968–1969.
Galeotti, F., Vanacore, N., Gainotti, S., et al. (2012). How legislation on decisional capacity can
negatively affect the feasibility of clinical trials in patients with dementia. Drugs & Aging, 29(8),
607–14.
General Assembly of the United Nations (1948). Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Paris: UN
General Assembly.
Griffith, D.B. (1991). The best interests standard: a comparison of the state’s parens patriae authority
and judicial oversight in best interests determinations for children and incompetent patients. Issues
in Law and Medicine, 7(3), 283–338.
Karlawish, J. (2008). Measuring decision-making capacity in cognitively impaired individuals.
Neurosignals, 16(1), 91–98.
Kim, S.Y.H., Caine, E.D., Currier, G.W., Leibovici, A., and Ryan, J.M. (2001). Assessing the
competence of persons with Alzheimer’s disease in providing informed consent for participation in
research. American Journal of Psychiatry, 158(5), 712–717.
Kim, S.Y.H., Appelbaum, P.S., Jeste, D.V., and Olin, J.T. (2004). Proxy and surrogate consent in
geriatric neuropsychiatric research: update and recommendations. American Journal of Psychiatry,
161(5), 797–806.
Kim, S.Y.H., Karlawish, J.H., Kim, H.M., Wall, I.F., Bozoki, A.C., and Appelbaum, P.S. (2011).
Preservation of the capacity to appoint a proxy decision maker: implications for dementia research.
Archives of General Psychiatry, 68(2), 214–20.
Knoppers, B.M. (2013). Genomics: from persons to populations and back again. Genome,
56(10), 537–9.
Knoppers, B.M. (2014a). Framework for responsible sharing of genomic and health-related data. The
HUGO Journal, 8(1), 3.
Knoppers, B.M., Avard, D., Sénécal, K., and Zawati, M.H. (2014b). Return of whole-genome
sequencing results in paediatric research: a statement of the P3G international paediatrics platform.
European Journal of Human Genetics, 22(1), 3–5.
Knoppers, B.M., Harris, J.R., Budin-Ljøsne, I., and Dove, E.S. (2014c). A human rights approach
to an international code of conduct for genomic and clinical data sharing. Human Genetics, 133,
895–903.
Knoppers, B.M., Sénécal, K., Boisjoli, J., et al. (2016). Recontacting pediatric research participants for
consent when they reach the age of majority. IRB: Ethics & Human Research, 38(6)
387
References 387
Lange, M.M., Rogers, W., and Dodds, S. (2013). Vulnerability in research ethics: a way forward.
Bioethics, 27(6), 333–40.
Ngandu, T., Lehtisalo, J., Solomon, A., et al. (2015). A 2 year multidomain intervention of diet,
exercise, cognitive training, and vascular risk monitoring versus control to prevent cognitive
decline in at-risk elderly people (FINGER): a randomised controlled trial. The Lancet, 385(9984),
2255–2263.
Rieder, M.J. and Hazardous Substances Committee (2011). Drug research and treatment for children
in Canada: a challenge. Paediatrics & Child Health, 16(9), 560–561.
Shirkey, H. (1968). Editorial comment: therapeutic orphans. Journal of Pediatrics, 72(1), 119–120.
Shirkey, H. (1999). Editorial comment: therapeutic orphans. Pediatrics, 104(Supplement 3), 583–584.
Singh, I. (2007). Capacity and competence in children as research participants. EMBO Reports,
8(Special Issue), S35–S39.
Stein, L.D., Knoppers, B.M., Campbell, P., Getz, G., and Korbel, J.O. (2015). Data analysis: create a
cloud commons. Nature, 523(7559), 149–151.
Taylor, H.A., Kuwana, E., and Wilfond, B.S. (2015). Is it ethical to enroll cognitively impaired adults in
research that is more than minimal risk with no prospect of benefit? American Journal of Bioethics,
15(10), 64–65.
Thorogood, A., Deschênes St-Pierre, C., and Knoppers, B. M. (2016). Substitute consent to data
sharing: a way forward for international dementia research? Oxford Journal of Law and Biosciences,
Available from: 1–26. http://doi.org/10.1093/jlb/lsw063.
United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organisation (UNESCO) (1997). Universal
Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights. Paris, France:UNESCO.
United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organisation (UNESCO) (2003). International
Declaration on Human Genetic Data. Paris, France:UNESCO.
United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organisation (UNESCO) (2005). Universal
Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights. Paris, France:UNESCO.
United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organisation (UNESCO) (2008). International
Bioethics Committee, Report of the International Bioethics Committee of UNESCO (IBC) on Consent.
Paris, France:UNESCO.
United Nations General Assembly (1989). United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (UN
Document A/RES/44/25). New York: United Nations.
United Nations General Assembly (1991). United Nations Principles for Older Persons, Resolution 46/91
(UN Document A/RES/46/91). New York: United Nations.
United Nations Second World Assembly on Ageing (2002). Political Declaration and Madrid
International Plan of Action on Ageing. New York: United Nations.
Wildeman, S., Dunn, L.B., and Onyemelukwe, C. (2013). Incapacity in Canada: review of laws and
policies on research involving decisionally impaired adults. American Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry,
21(4), 314–325.
World Health Organization (2012). Dementia: A Public Health Priority. Geneva: World Health
Organization.
World Health Organization (2016). Dementia Fact Sheet. Available from: http://www.who.int/
mediacentre/factsheets/fs362/en/ [accessed February 21, 2017].
World Medical Association (2013). Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research
Involving Human Subjects. Amended by the 64 General Assembly, Fotaleza, Brazil. World Medical
Association.
Yarborough, M. (2015). Inconsistent approaches to research involving cognitively impaired
adults: why the broad view of substituted judgment is our best guide. American Journal of Bioethics,
15(10), 66–67.
38
Chapter 20
Introduction
The belief that people are free human beings, able to undertake actions based on will
and desires, is central to much explanation of human behavior and to a broad set of
social practices such as law, ethics, and politics. Indeed, threats to human freedom1
and the ability to act according to individual beliefs and preferences can lead to seri-
ous conflict and is still the object of struggles of oppressed linguistic, ethnic, religious,
and racial minorities throughout the world. It is often stated that there is nothing more
precious than a person’s freedom and this is well reflected in national constitutions
where political freedoms and rights serve as the foundations of social and political
orders. One of the iconic figures of the fight for human freedom in the twentieth cen-
tury, Nelson Mandela, put forth in his famous discourse “No Easy Walk to Freedom”
in 1953 to the African National Congress, in the context of the fight against the regime
of apartheid that “[t]o overthrow oppression has been sanctioned by humanity and is
the highest aspiration of every free man” (Mandela 2011). In a similar mind-frame,
the influential moral and political thinking of the Enlightenment stressed that free-
dom was intrinsic to the definition of humans as social and political beings such that,
in the words of Rousseau, humans had an intrinsic motivation to safeguard freedom
because freedom defines human beings to the point of representing a duty to uphold
this freedom for themselves and for others (Rousseau 1992).2 In a nutshell, freedom
has long been considered intrinsic to what people value in individual and collective
life and constitutes a precondition for the enjoyment of many goods. Accordingly, the
desire to be free has propelled democratic revolutions and social movements through-
out history.
389
Introduction 389
In contrast to this deep commitment to human freedom in the humanities and in society,
and its omnipresence in individual life, domestic affairs, and international relationships,
neuroscience has been heralded as a game-changing field which will radically change
how individuals view themselves, including their beliefs in human freedom. Such changes
have been captured under the concept of a neuroscience revolution (Wolpe 2002), the
idea that neuroscience could reveal another view of humankind which potentially contra-
dicts ordinary, non-scientifically informed views of ourselves. The claim is enormous, as
the reader can easily guess. If freedom is a kind of illusion and human beings are ready to
fight and even die in its name, are they then lured and wronging themselves in pursuing
such a quasi-sacred good?
If the interpretation of some famous studies and neuroscientists is taken seriously, it
would seem to be the case. Starting with the research of Libet in the 1980s (Libet et al.
1982, 1983), a stream of studies has been interpreted to suggest that free will—a basic
descriptor of human freedom that we will come back to in “Behavioral and brain-based
research as a threat to free moral agency”—does not exist. Perhaps human beings have at
best some veto power allowing them to stop an action or thought already initiated by the
brain but nothing much more (Libet et al. 1983). Others have argued that perhaps free
will is simply an illusion (Wegner 2002), albeit a useful illusion which allows us to make
sense of agency, but nevertheless an ill-founded concept, a concept that does not carve
nature at its joints. Perhaps human beings just simply do not have any kind of freedom,
and beliefs in freedom are supported by quirky metaphysics (Haggard, cited in Smith
2011). All these claims merit closer scrutiny, but they set an enormous challenge to the
vast array of social practices that rely on some fundamental beliefs in human freedom.
Adding to the importance of these interpretations of neuroscience research is the fact that
the disqualification of human freedom by neuroscience has become lore in as much as,
for example, the media has conveyed repeatedly that the existence of human freedom has
been invalidated based, for example, on Libet and colleagues’ famous study (Racine et al.
2016). Greene and Cohen have proposed that social practices such as ethics and law be
extensively revised to reflect challenges to human freedom (Greene & Cohen 2004).
In this chapter, we examine some of the basic claims that challenge beliefs in free moral
agency,3 an expression we propose to encompass different abilities4 of the moral agent
often captured with different concepts such as free will, freedom, and autonomy. (These
concepts are often included in the single term of freedom, broadly understood, as already
suggested.) We strive to provide a generous understanding of the underlying points of
views suggesting, for example, that decisions are not made consciously and voluntarily
but are actually predetermined by prior brain activity, as revealed by, for example, readi-
ness potentials. Other research has challenged how conscious and accurate human beings
actually are in making choices and decisions which are believed to be free but are actually
influenced by a host of implicit, nonconscious mechanisms (Bargh & Chartrand 1999).
Although there are methodological caveats to what has been published in neuroscience
with respect to this issue (e.g., about Libet’s research which we and others have scrutinized
(Dubljević 2013; Saigle et al. 2015)), this chapter looks at this problem from a conceptual
390
Freedom, liberty
Ability to choose and benefit from
circumstances allowing the enactment of
one’s choice without coercion.
Free will
Basic ability to envision
options and choose
between them.
choices and preferences, often protected through specific rights in legal parlance such as
freedom of association, freedom of speech, and freedom of religion. For example, whereas
free will may be considered paradoxically to exist even if a choice cannot be enacted, this
usually does not hold true of freedom that entails the actual circumstances allowing the
exercise of one’s freedom. Otherwise said, free will alludes to a more basic ability than
freedom that captures more concrete aspects of choices and decisions. Now the concept
of autonomy, and related concepts like self-determination and self-regulation, designates
an even higher-level or more specific ability to choose or decide as a result of deliberation
and reflection. Usually, there is an emphasis on the fact that the individual came to this or
that choice or decision on his or her own, or that this choice reflects deeply held principles
and values, although this criterion of authenticity is not univocal. According to these
distinctions, the mere act of voting under circumstances where this act is not hindered or
coerced could be an act of freedom, but it may not be autonomous if the choice to vote for
such-and-such candidate has not been the result of a certain kind of deliberate apprecia-
tion of the options available, their implications and consequences, and their alignment
with one’s convictions. And simply having a basic ability to envision options and choose
(having free will) would not entail that a person has the freedom to actually carry out this
choice. For instance, women have the same basic ability to choose according to their pref-
erence among options of government as men, but historically did not have the freedom to
actually carry out this choice. Women have only relatively recently been empowered with
the right to vote, and there are still places where women do not enjoy political freedom.
392
Autonomy requires freedom, which itself requires free will, but free will does not nec-
essarily entail freedom, and freedom does not necessarily lead to autonomy. In our view,
these concepts—distinguished for the sake of clarity here—are interwoven in discussions
about the impact and relevance of behavioral and brain sciences on agency.5 Furthermore,
moral agency is much more than the free or autonomous aspects of attitudes and behavior
of the moral agent. For example, personality and responsibility represent other central
aspects of moral agency although we do not focus on them in this chapter.
Again, as readers may have already envisioned, there are different kinds of claims that
can be made about the impact of behavioral and brain sciences on free moral agency.
A moderate claim could be that what is learned about behavior, decision-making pro-
cesses, including non-conscious processes influencing human psychology, can inform
how behavior is understood, including the kinds of actions described as being free. For
example, an understanding of voting behavior that would exhibit an engagement of the
amygdala, a structure potentially considered “the perceptual or evaluative tool by which
the perceivers form their impressions” (Rule et al. 2010, p.354), does not mean that all
voting behavior is under the control of the amygdala. Different accounts of relational
autonomy have always integrated such moderate claims to revisit standard accounts of
autonomy that originally paid little attention to determinants of choice (Mackenzie &
Stoljar 2000). However, a stronger type of claim could capture statements and interpreta-
tions that suggest that revealing the existence of neurobiological mechanisms underlying
a behavior, a decision-making process or the like, would lead to the conclusion that the
phenomenon is outside the purview of free moral agency. In other words, the behavior
or decision could be considered un-free, determined, lacking any control by the agent,
being completely implicit and inaccessible to conscious awareness in ways that the agent
cannot do anything about how he or she behaves, thinks, or reacts. By and large, the first,
moderate claims are common in most everyday interpretations of what behavioral and
brain sciences mean for human action. However, stronger claims are not uncommon and
are often debated in the media because of their incredible (if true) and sensational impli-
cations (Racine et al. 2016). In the following sections, we illustrate how findings from the
behavioral and brain sciences have been interpreted as challenging different aspects of
free moral agency, notably (1) self-determined action integral to autonomy, (2) conscious
volition involved in free will, (3) conscious control of action required for freedom, and
(4) the sense of self required for autonomous decision making. These are by no means the
only challenges that behavioral and brain sciences have brought to free moral agency or
agency more generally, and we acknowledge that we can only provide an overview to the
reader here.
Libet’s experiments led to diametrically opposed interpretations, with few siding with his
own original middle-ground interpretation (Saigle et al. 2015). These conclusions and
395
interpretations are often taken to have significant implications. Based on Libet’s initial
findings and subsequent research, researchers have claimed that free will is simply an illu-
sion (Wegner 2002). Others have followed Libet’s lead to undertake a series of studies on
the automaticity and unconscious components of behavior (Haggard et al. 2004; Haggard
2005, 2011; Smith 2011) and have concluded that free will does not exist because human
behavior is essentially determined. A commentary in Nature Neuroscience (about a paper
which has supposedly shown that the brain activity was initiated seconds before a deci-
sion) well reflects this strong eliminativist interpretation:
The conscious decision to push the button was made about a second before the actual act but the
team discovered that a pattern of brain activity seemed to predict that decision by as many as seven
seconds. Long before the subjects were even aware of making a choice, it seems, their brains had
already decided. As humans, we like to think that decisions are under conscious control —that we
have free will. Philosophers have debated that concept for centuries, and now Haynes and other
experimental neuroscientists are raising a new challenge. They argue that consciousness of a deci-
sion may be a mere biochemical afterthought, with no influence whatsoever on a person’s actions.
According to this logic, they say, free will is an illusion. “We feel we choose, but we don’t,” says
Patrick Haggard, a neuroscientist at University College London. (Smith 2011, p.24)
(see Brownstein 2016). Many studies have showed that implicit biases can affect social
judgment and behavior independently from the subject’s explicit attitudes. These uncon-
scious and automatic influences, such as implicit racial bias, may be revealed on indi-
rect measures of attitudes (e.g., sequential priming or the Implicit Association Test—see
Brownstein (2016)). The growing research on implicit biases has many upshots, from
chilling (e.g., biases in police shootings of unarmed men of African origin), very practical
(e.g., the well-documented propensity of employers to prefer in-group candidates in job
searches), to the more philosophical (e.g., how can a judgment be trusted once implicit
biased are acknowledged?).
The most important implications of implicit biases in the context of our discussion
stems from the fact that they stand in stark contrast to controlled cognitive processes.
Namely, mental causation is an important theme in many conceptions of free moral
agency—freely willed actions are viewed as actions that are derived from a person’s con-
scious thoughts, whereas actions derived from the unconscious are viewed are unfree
(Baumeister & Monroe 2014). Thus, research into implicit attitudes and the range of
effects they have on judgment and behavior put the understanding of free moral agency
into question. This is exacerbated by data from social psychology and neuroscience,
which shows that prejudices and biases toward out-group members are widespread and
persist in contemporary society (see Amodio 2014). The issue is whether automaticized
behaviors related to, say, sexism, should be thought of as under control of the person in
question. If they unfold in the absence of explicit reasoning, should individuals holding
such attitudes be responsible for them, and for the judgments and behaviors influenced
by their biases? Since there can be unawareness of the impact of a great many cogni-
tive states on behavior, this may lead to a global skepticism about moral responsibility
(Holroyd 2012). However, beyond the global issues of denying moral responsibility, the
fact that implicit biases are pervasive introduces additional constraints to free moral
agency and even forces us to consider ongoing, previously unreflected responsibility in
two ways: responsibility for having implicit attitudes and responsibility for the behavioral
expression of implicit attitudes (Faucher 2016).
mucosal tissues has long been known to immunologists and even before to some vision-
ary scientists like Bernard, Darwin, James, Pavlov, and Lange (Cryan & Dinan 2012).
However, the behavioral and brain sciences have witnessed a plethora of findings sug-
gesting that not only disease states but also, so to speak, ordinary behavior is under the
influence of the microbiota (Neufeld & Foster 2009). The mechanisms through which this
action occurs are being explored (Cryan & Dinan 2012) but include the possible contri-
bution of the gut commensals in the synthesis of neurotransmitters and other microbial
mediators. These mediators then impact homeostasis in the central nervous system, acti-
vation of the hypothalamic–pituitary–adrenal axis (HPA) or stress axis, neuroimmune
response, and neurogenesis by affecting the vagus nerve, involved in the parasympathetic
regulation of many organs, or crossing directly the blood–brain barrier (Sherwin et al.
2016), although other mechanisms could be at stake (Cryan & Dinan 2012).
One of the most intensively investigated areas of brain–gut interaction concerns stress
response and the activity of the HPA axis in which several key observations have showed
clear interactions between the central nervous system and the gut. For example, maternal
separation (a stressor) in rhesus monkeys is associated with changes in the HPA axis but
also affects temporarily the composition of the gut microbiota (Cryan & Dinan 2012).
Long-term effects have also been found in rats and physical stressors (physical restraint)
lead to changes in gut microbiota composition and reciprocally, stress response also
appears to be modulated by microbiota profile (Cryan & Dinan 2012). A few years ago,
a set of landmark studies suggested that the development of the immune system in mice
led to the normalization of the HPA axis. For example, adult germ-free mice showed
an exaggerated stress response in comparison to control animals (Sudo et al. 2004). The
same study showed that colonization of the mice at 6 weeks (early adulthood) reversed
this effect but not in adulthood (8 weeks of life). Additionally, the function of the intes-
tinal barrier can be changed subsequent to stress exposure and can be reversed by the
use of some probiotics (Cryan & Dinan 2012). In addition to effects on the HPA axis, a
series of observations have suggested implications of gut composition and function on
memory, mood, and visceral pain perception (Cryan & Dinan 2012). Of great potential
clinical significance, neurodevelopmental disorders such as autism are associated with gut
dysfunction, although the relationship (causal or correlational) is unclear given that diet
and food intake (as well as use of antibiotics) can differ in individuals affected by autism
(Cryan & Dinan 2012). An association between certain psychiatric conditions (e.g., mood
disorders) and gastrointestinal disorders (e.g., irritable bowel syndrome) has also long
been observed (Neufeld & Foster 2009).
In different headquarters, microbiome7 research is now considered a genuine chal-
lenge to the existence of the self, let alone the self which is free to choose. Kramer
and Bressan (2015), describe human beings as superorganisms where the organisms
constituting the microbiota would have interests of their own, “which need not coin-
cide with ours” (p.464). For example, some behaviors of mammals could be dictated
by the interests of microorganisms to use their hosts to perpetuate their existence.
Rats inflected with toxoplasma lose their fear of cats; the toxoplasma is then able to
398
reproduce sexually instead of asexually in the cat’s intestine, thereby suggesting that
the behaviors of these mammals are instrumentalized by toxoplasma. Similarly, food
cravings and other behaviors and choices of humans could be directed by microor-
ganisms, and could potentially run counter to long-term health and autonomously
deliberated interests. Morar and Beever reviewed such microbiome research and
conclude that it is “producing a radically new understanding of ‘individual’ organ-
isms” (Morar & Beever 2016, p.39). In a nutshell, the human individual should be
more aptly viewed as a “community, but also in recognizing the ways that agency
and autonomy are additionally impacted by microbial interactions” (Morar & Beever
2016, p.40). Accordingly, they criticize standard accounts of autonomy (e.g., moral
agents as having a capacity for self-sufficient, self-determined decisions, i.e., a capac-
ity defined in abstract terms without much understanding or appreciation of deter-
minants of choice) for not taking into account evidence from the biological and
environmental sciences indicating that autonomy is influenced by a host of factors.
They even fault the relational account of autonomy, which was developed explicitly
to incorporate insights on social determinants of choice, as incomplete “to the extent
that it overlooks this deep biological interconnectedness between human individuals
and other organisms” (Morar & Beever 2016, p.41). However, the authors go further
and claim that there is “no reason not to jettison the concept” [of autonomy] “if a
suitable normative replacement for the value that autonomy has traditionally upheld
can be identified” (Morar & Beever 2016, p.42). Otherwise said, microbiome research
and brain–gut interaction radically put into question the understanding of free moral
agency.
To conclude our analysis of threats stemming from behavioral and brain sciences,
different claims have been made to the effect that they bear significant implications
for the understanding of free (moral) agency. If different strands of research are to
be believed, individuals are not free in the sense that they are considered to be. On
the contrary, certain decisions would be heavily influenced by social determinants of
choice, preparatory brain activity such as the readiness potential and neuronal activity
preceding action, implicit biases, and as discovered more recently, the activity of the
microbiota. These insights have been interpreted as threats to free moral agency and
its different facets such as the capacities for self-determined action, conscious volition,
conscious control of action, and the sense of self. In the next section of this chapter, we
discuss two challenges to these claims. First, we highlight their objectivist and essential-
ist assumption toward abilities relevant for free moral agency. Second, we point to their
misplaced devaluation of the normative principle of autonomy and human freedom,
which stresses the value of free moral agency. We propose that a concept of “contextual-
ized autonomy” (e.g., Racine et al. 2017)—which relies on a recognition that autonomy
is a set of agential abilities (see also Dubljević 2013) exercised in context and originat-
ing in the experience of the agent—can integrate the useful insights they describe while
avoiding these two pitfalls.
39
In our eyes, middle-ground positions like Felsen and Reiner’s are hinting at the
genuine promises of the behavioral and brain sciences but fall short from overcoming
explicitly the conceptual barriers to the meaningful integration of behavioral and brain
science knowledge to the theoretical and practical understanding of free moral agency.
Indeed, the discussion remains burdened—we argue—by two common fallacies within
the view of abstracted free moral agency (Figure 20.2a): first, concerning an objec-
tivist and essentialist stance (dualist metaphysics separating starkly the realms of the
subjective and the objective) toward abilities relevant for free moral agency (e.g., free
will, freedom, and autonomy) and second, a misplaced devaluation of the normative
principles that stress the value of free moral agency (e.g., respect for autonomy, respect
for individual rights, and responsibilities) based on behavioral and brain science. We
explain these two tension points and provide a different view informed notably by prag-
matist theory and the concept of “contextualized autonomy” (Dubljević 2013; Racine
& Dubljević 2016; Racine et al. 2017). The first fallacy is resolved by the adoption of a
nonessentialist (nondualistic) metaphysics; the second by taking a distance from pos-
tulating a strong fact–value (is–ought) dichotomy and siding with a description of this
dichotomy as a tension which needs to be resolved in actual moral judgment (see Figure
20.2 for an overview).
(a)
Stance Assumptions Implications
Objectivist,
Free moral essentialist, and dualist Abstract free will, freedom, and autonomy:
agency as an metaphysics Neuroscience undermines the ability for free moral
ability to choose agency because the third-person perspective of
and act without neuroscience challenges the first-person experience
Strong fact–value of being able to choose and act upon the world
constraints or
dichotomy in moral according to those choice and preferences.
undue influence
judgment
(b)
Stance Assumptions Implications
Figure 20.2 Two interpretations of the contribution of behavioral and brain science to the
understanding of free moral agency. (a) Dualist metaphysical interpretation of behavioral and
brain research on free moral agency. (b) Pragmatist interpretation of behavioral and brain
research on free moral agency.
401
from the law of causality (Bargh 2008; Montague 2008), ordinary perspectives on free
will are consistent with a positive definition of freedom as a fluctuating ability to make
a choice, acting consistently with one’s desires, and being reasonably free of constraints
(Baumeister & Monroe 2014). The challenge of determinism to free will is unclear in
lay understandings of free will because being free is viewed as something positive rather
than simply as acting outside the realm of causes. These findings have been supported
by other studies that have looked at ordinary views on free will (Baumeister & Monroe
2014). Otherwise said, the concepts describing free moral agency designate a genuine
first-person experience of free moral agency and serve as an interpretation of these abili-
ties. This sense of free and autonomous agency could be somewhat imperfectly described
and captured by folk terminology, and it could be tricked in different ways as described by
Wegner (2002), but it alludes to a real ability that humans have and robustly attribute to
each other through different established social practices reflected in everyday interactions
and also in social and legal norms.9 As Baumeister (2008, p. 15) writes:
Freedom and choice are woven deeply into the fabric of human relations and activities. If freedom
and choice are completely illusions—if the outcome of every choice was inevitable all along—why
must people agonize so over decisions? Why do they argue and strive so much for the right to
decide (that is, for power and liberty)? Why has so much political, economic, and social struggle
been aimed at increasing freedom if freedom is just an illusion?
This positive account of free moral agency as a set of abilities—and which actually is silent
on the issue of its compatibility or incompatibly with determinism—maps well with the
functions attributed to this concept in daily life. Every time we are able to fulfill basic or
complex actions, we are comforted in our sense of being capable of acting both freely or
autonomously, and, likewise, when we are frustrated in doing so, we experience resistance
to our will and intents. As William James proposed, the feeling of effort and goal-focused
activity “play a role in strengthening the internal sense of the will’s capabilities” (Gray
2007, p.5). If this first-person experience and existence of free moral agency is not first
recognized, then either a person falls into the trap of explaining away free moral agency
(e.g., hard determinism) or reverts to “panicky metaphysics” (Strawson 1962), in order to
account for the basic conditions of free moral agency such as free will. Clearly, the abil-
ity to act freely or autonomously can be jeopardized by a host of factors, but knowledge
about those factors can also facilitate the realization of intents and desires such that the
ability of human beings to act upon the world is not undermined by greater knowledge of
how choices are made. The fact that free moral agency has a subjective and experiential
dimension does not make it less real; and understanding and explaining it through social,
psychological, or biological perspectives does not explain it away. As Dewey, the pre-
cursor of the concept of contextualized autonomy and free moral agency more broadly,
wrote: “we need freedom in and among actual events, not apart from them”10 (Dewey
1922, p.303)—our ability to act upon the world is best understood as a capacity which
uses knowledge of personal, relational, social, biological, and environmental conditions
to actually enact goals and projects (Figure 20.1). The traditional opposition (based on
Kant’s work (Kant 1994)) between freedom and causality is spuriously generated by a
403
metaphysical view, which simply does not take into account seriously the basic subjective
and intersubjective experience of making free and autonomous, and sometimes less free
and autonomous, decisions. Acknowledging that this experience is the first foundation
for the actual existence of free moral agency prevents an interpretation that more knowl-
edge about its conditions actually somehow undermines this experience because the
all-or-none and essentialist objective nature of free moral agency is not posited; rather,
free moral agency describes agent-dependent characteristics which can be diminished
or empowered. This is in line with the veto power interpretation of Libet: some deci-
sions might be unfree, but the power to choose at least some things cannot be reasonably
denied. Thus, empirical data gained about how different contexts can impede free moral
agency becomes valuable knowledge for the moral agent to try to overcome these barri-
ers or, if they are very difficult to surmount, to identify alternative remediation strategies
(e.g., changing the context instead of the agent). In discussions of contextual influences
on free moral agencies, studies similar to those that show that collectivist societies tend to
foster conformity whereas individualist societies tend to reinforce the value of personal
freedom and foster nonconformity, can be factored into the analysis of free moral agency.
Conclusion 405
well as those of fields such as social psychology and sociology (where it is more customary
to speak of “empowerment”) (Perkins & Zimmerman 1995). Freedom presupposes hav-
ing mature powers of volition and the capacity of self-control, but not that it is exercised
all the time (Dubljević 2013). Self-control can be depleted and imperfect, but empiri-
cal research points toward the conclusion that it is undoubtedly present in most adults
(Baumeister et al. 1998; Moller et al. 2006; Vohs et al. 2008).12
Autonomy and free will find their value in experience. And better factual or scien-
tific understanding of the different aspects of free moral agency does not fundamen-
tally undermine the value attributed to them because knowledge does not change the
experience and exercise of free moral agency and its importance. Those claiming that
the behavioral and brain sciences could bring new insights to the understanding of free
moral agency are right, but they are wrong to conclude that ontological revisionism will
be a dominant trend or even should be the dominant trend. It is true that the abilities
described by the concepts of autonomy, freedom, and free will could be re-described in
more accurate normative language. Pragmatist theory does grant and even encourage
the scientific reconstruction of the understanding of physical and psychological realities
(Racine 2013). However, as Dewey warned, contrary to the sweeping reductionism of
positivist and eliminativist neurophilosophy, “it will be a long time before anything of this
sort will be accomplished for human beings [in contrast to physics]. To expel traditional
meanings and replace them by ideas that are products of controlled inquiries is a slow
and painful process” (Dewey 1937, in Gouinlock 1994, p.48). Accordingly, we caution
against the desire to reduce the experience of free moral agency to more rigorous or philo-
sophical language if it leads to expelling important dimensions of the concept, as recent
research does suggest it would be the case if the thinking of the eliminativists is followed
(Monroe & Malle 2010). Meaningful contributions to the understanding of free moral
agency should be understandable through the lenses of different disciplines. Contribution
of diverse disciplines will likely provide enrichments and revisions to self-understanding
and the understanding of other’s behaviors. It would indeed be strange if, like proposed by
Churchland (1981), the behavioral and brain sciences would systematically explain away
the phenomena initially triggering the scientific inquiries. There are cases of ontological
revisions (e.g., phlogiston in chemistry), but it might be more fruitful to expect that most
scientific discoveries in neuroscience and psychology will enrich the understanding of
common-sense (folk psychological) concepts that currently have some traction in indi-
vidual and social life (e.g., law, ethics, and politics).
Conclusion
Neuroscience has been heralded as a game-changing field for its impact on the under-
standing of free human agency. Research in diverse fields examining, for example, social
determinants of choice, brain activity preceding action, implicit biases, and more recently,
the microbiome and its impact on brain function and behavior have all been interpreted
as radically jeopardizing the existence of free moral agency. In this chapter we did not
406
scrutinize the scientific and methodological foundations for such claims, which we have
done elsewhere (Dubljević 2013; Saigle et al. 2015). We tackled another set of issues
related to the conceptual and metaphysical assumptions underlying common interpreta-
tions of behavioral and brain science research. Much possible uptake of the behavioral and
brain sciences with respect to the understanding of free moral agency could be hindered
by strong dualistic metaphysical assumptions as well as dichotomous interpretations of
the fact–value continuum. A resolution can be found in pragmatist theory and recent
research in social psychology. These support the concept of contextualized autonomy that
recognizes explicitly that different aspects of free moral agency originate in a first-person
experience of agency. Moreover, the value placed on the abilities captured by the con-
cept of free moral agency is not necessarily jeopardized by a factual understanding from
the behavioral and brain sciences. In fact, knowledge can also empower moral agency.
Behavioral and brain sciences provide us with important contributions and information
on how free moral agency is limited and could even be seen as a depletable resource.
However, scientific evidence can empower choices by teaching when to conserve limited
resources, and when to undertake or delay decisions.
Acknowledgments
Support for this work comes from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council
(Racine), the Fonds de recherche du Québec–Santé for career awards (Racine), and the
Banting Postdoctoral Fellowships Programme (Dubljević). We extend our thanks to
members of the Neuroethics Research Unit for feedback on previous versions of this man-
uscript. Special thanks to Kaylee Sohng, Simon Rousseau-Lesage, and Roxanne Caron for
editorial assistance in the preparation of this manuscript. Some parts of this chapter have
appeared previously in a short paper by the authors (Racine & Dubljević 2016).
Notes
1. We will introduce a finer-grained distinction between free will, freedom, and autonomy (and their
synonyms), although “freedom” is often used as a generic term to describe these three different
aspects of free moral agency.
2. “Renoncer à sa liberté c’est renoncer à sa qualité d’homme, aux droits de l’humanité, même à ses
devoirs” (Rousseau 1992, p.34).
3. We also thereby acknowledge that there are many different aspects of agency (e.g., authenticity and
responsibility) which we do not tackle since our discussion deals with the issue of freedom in a
general sense and in the context of ethics, hence the qualifier “moral” used throughout even though
some of our points about free agency could be valid beyond the context of ethics.
4. We frequently use the term “abilities” to stress the active dimension of these concepts; the term
“capacities” has a more static connotation and reflects less clearly the context-dependent and agent-
dependent nature of these concepts. However, when the abilities are not engaged, we use “capacities.”
5. The concepts of autonomy, liberty, and free will have been used in different ways. Our conceptualiza-
tion does not obviate other uses. It is simply meant to clarify how we use these terms in this chapter.
The most important idea that is conveyed is the gradual expansion in the substantive commitments
from free will to autonomy. One of us (Dubljević 2013) has used a different designation of the three
407
References 407
distinct levels (basic autonomy, free will, ideal of autonomy), but in this chapter we opted not to use
autonomy twice, so as not to confuse the reader.
6. The tendency to conform is a stable trait with observable neuroanatomical correlates. The upshot
is that not only do some people conform more than others, but that the neuroscience evidence
may actually predict who is more likely to conform and who is more likely to resist such external
influences.
7. In this chapter, we do not draw a strong distinction between the concepts of microbiome and
microbiota.
8. Gert and Duggan (1979, p.197) write: “We are thus in agreement with Moore that the question
whether man has Free Will is best viewed as a question about whether he has a certain power (we
prefer to talk about ability) not as a question about whether what a man has willed to do was the
result of coercion.”
9. The fact that our abilities can be tricked or manipulated does not imply that we do not have them.
Otherwise, visual illusions would suffice to debunk the fact that we have the ability to see, and rely on
sight accurately, at least most of the time.
10. Dewey did not adopt the tripartite distinction (Figure 20.1) but stressed nevertheless how free will
was a limited ability (in contrast to actual freedom).
11. Consider an analogy with slavery: the lack of freedom experienced by slaves does not mean that they
lack appreciation or value of freedom, or that the right to be free has no meaning.
12. Vohs and colleagues equate self-control and self-regulation (which is the literal translation of the
word autonomy) and define it as “the self-exerting control to override a prepotent response, with the
assumption that replacing a response with another is done to attain goals and conform to standards”
(Vohs et al. 2008, p.884). Moller and colleagues, in their self-determination theory make the distinc-
tion between self-control, which is ego-depleting, and self-regulation, which is not ego-depleting
(Moller et al. 2006). “Ego depletion” refers to the phenomenon of diminished ability to enact self-
regulation with repeated efforts, and neuroscience evidence supports the view that relevant capacities
for exertion of control exist (Berkman & Miller-Ziegler 2013; Wagner & Heatherton 2013).
References
Amodio, D.M. (2014). The neuroscience of prejudice and stereotyping. Nature Reviews Neuroscience,
15(10), 670–682.
Asch, S.E. (1955). Opinions and social pressure. Scientific American, 193(5), 33–35.
Bargh, J.A. (2008). Free will is unnatural. In: Baer, J., Kaufman, J.C., and Baumeister, R.F. (Eds.) Are We
Free? Psychology and Free Will, pp.128–154. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bargh, J.A. and Chartrand, T.L. (1999). On the unbearable automaticity of being. American
Psychologist, 54(7), 462–479.
Baron, R.S., Vandello, J.A., and Brunsman, B. (1996). The forgotten variable in conformity
research: impact of task importance on social influence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
71(5), 915–927.
Baumeister, R.F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
3(1), 14–19.
Baumeister, R.F. and Monroe, A.E. (2014). Recent research on free will: Conceptualizations, beliefs, and
processes. In: Zanna, M.P. and Olson, J.M. (Eds.) Advances in Experimental Social Psychology (Vol.
50), pp. 1–52. Burlington, MA: Academic Press.
Baumeister, R.F., Bratslavsky, E., Muraven, M., and Tice, D.M. (1998). Ego depletion: is the active self a
limited resource? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74(5), 1252–1265.
408
Benson, P. (1990). Feminist second thoughts about free agency. Hypatia, 5(3), 47–64.
Berkman, E.T. and Miller-Ziegler, J.S. (2013). Imaging depletion: fMRI provides new insights into the
processes underlying ego depletion. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8(4), 359–361.
Bond, R. (2005). Group size and conformity. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations, 8(4), 331–354.
Bond, R. and Smith, P.B. (1996). Culture and conformity: a meta-analysis of studies using Asch’s
(1952b, 1956) line judgement task. Psychological Bulletin, 119(1), 111–137.
Brownstein, M. (2016). Implicit bias. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available from: http://
plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/implicit-bias/ [accessed March 30, 2016].
Campbell-Meiklejohn, D.K., Kanai, R., Bahrami, B., et al. (2012). Structure of orbitofrontal cortex
predicts social influence. Current Biology, 22(4), R123–R124.
Churchland, P.M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy,
77(2), 67–90.
Cialdini, R.B. and Goldstein, N.J. (2004). Social influence: compliance and conformity. Annual Review
of Psychology, 55, 591–621.
Cryan, J.F. and Dinan, T.G. (2012). Mind-altering microorganisms: the impact of the gut microbiota on
brain and behaviour. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13(10), 701–712.
Dewey, J. (1922). Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology. New York: Holt.
Dewey, J. (1937). An address delivered before the College of Physicians in St. Louis, April 21, 1937,
republished in Gouinlock, J. (Ed.) The Moral Writings of John Dewey, Revised Edition (Great Books
in Philosophy), pp.47–55. Amhert, NY: Prometheus Books.
Dubljević, V. (2013). Autonomy in neuroethics: political and not metaphysical. American Journal of
Bioethics Neuroscience, 4(4), 44–51.
Faucher, L. (2016). Revisionism and moral responsibility for implicit attitudes. In: Brownstein, M. and
Saul, J. (Eds.) Implicit Bias & Philosophy: Volume 2, Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and
Ethics, pp.115–144. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Felsen, G. and Reiner, P.B. (2011). How the neuroscience of decision making informs our conception of
autonomy. American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience, 2(3), 3–14.
Fiske, S.T. (2010). Social Beings: Core Motives in Social Psychology. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Gert, B. and Duggan, T.J. (1979). Free will as the ability to will. Noûs, 13(2), 197–217.
Gilligan, C. (1993). In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Glass, D.C., Siger, J.E., and Friedman, L.N. (1969). Psychic cost of adaptation to an environmental
stressor. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 12(3), 200–210.
Gray, M.T. (2007). Freedom and resistance: the phenomenal will in addiction. Nursing Philosophy,
8(1), 3–15.
Greene, J.D. and Cohen, J. (2004). For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 357(1451), 1117–1785.
Habermas, J. (1968). Technik und Wissenschaft als „Ideologie.” Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Haggard, P. (2005). Conscious intention and motor cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(6),
290–295.
Haggard, P. (2011). Decision time for free will. Neuron, 69(3), 404–406.
Haggard, P., Cartledge, P., Dafydd, M., and Oakley, D.A. (2004). Anomalous control: when ‘free-will’ is
not conscious. Consciousness and Cognition, 13(3), 646–654.
Holroyd, J. (2012). Responsibility for implicit bias. Journal of Social Philosophy, 43(3), 274–306.
Izuma, K. (2013). The neural basis of social influence and attitude change. Current Opinion in
Neurobiology, 23(3), 456-462.
Kant, E. (1994). Fondements de la métaphysique des mœurs. Paris: Delagrave.
409
References 409
Keene, S. (2011). Social bias: prejudice, stereotyping, and discrimination. The Journal of Law
Enforcement, 1(3), 1–5.
Kramer, P. and Bressan, P. (2015). Humans as superorganisms: how microbes, viruses, imprinted
genes, and other selfish entities shape our behavior. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10(4),
464–481.
Libet, B., Wright, E.W., and Gleason, C.A. (1982). Readiness-potentials preceding unrestricted
‘spontaneous’ vs. pre-planned voluntary acts. Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology,
54(3), 322–335.
Libet, B., Gleason, C.A., Wright, E.W., and Pearl, D.K. (1983). Time of conscious intention to act in
relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely
voluntary act. Brain, 106(3), 623–642.
MacKenzie, C. and Stoljar, N. (2000). Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Automony, Agency,
and the Social Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mandela, N. (2011). Nelson Mandela by Himself: The Authorized Book of Quotations.
London: MacMillan.
Mele, A. (2009). Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Milgram, S. (1974). Obedience to Authority. New York: Harper & Row.
Moller, A.C., Deci, E.L., and Ryan, R.M. (2006). Choice and ego-depletion: the moderating role of
autonomy. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32(8), 1024–1036.
Monroe, A.E. and Malle, B.F. (2010). From uncaused will to conscious choice: the need to study,
not speculate about people’s folk concept of free will. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(2),
211–224.
Montague, P.R. (2008). Free will. Current Biology, 18(14), R584–R585.
Morar, N. and Beever, J. (2016). The porosity of autonomy: social and biological constitution of the
patient in biomedicine. American Journal of Bioethics, 16(2), 34–45.
Morse, S. (2006). Brain overclaim syndrome and criminal responsibility: a diagnostic note. Ohio State
Journal of Criminal Law, 3, 397–412.
Morse, S. (2008). Psychopathy and criminal responsibility. Neuroethics, 1(3), 205–212.
Müller, S. and Walter, H. (2010). Reviewing autonomy: implications of the neurosciences and the free
will debate for the principle of respect for the patient’s autonomy. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare
Ethics, 19(2), 205–217.
Neufeld, K.A. and Foster, J.A. (2009). Effects of gut microbiota on the brain: implications for psychiatry.
Journal of Psychiatry & Neuroscience, 34(3), 230–231.
Nissani, M. (1990). A cognitive reinterpretation of Stanley Milgram’s observations on obedience to
authority. American Psychologist, 45(12), 1384–1385.
Perkins, D.D. and Zimmerman, M.A. (1995). Empowerment theory, research, and application.
American Journal of Community Psychology, 23(5), 569–579.
Peterson, C., Maier, S.F., and Seligman, M.E.P. (1995). Learned Helplessness: A Theory for the Age of
Personal Control. New York: Oxford University Press.
Racine, E. (2013). Pragmatism and the contribution of neuroscience to ethics. Essays in the Philosophy
of Humanism, 21(1), 13–20.
Racine, E. (2017). A proposal for a scientifically-informed and instrumentalist account of free will and
voluntary action. Frontiers in Psychology, in press.
Racine, E. and Dubljević, V. (2016). Porous or contextualized autonomy? Knowledge can empower
autonomous moral agents. American Journal of Bioethics, 16(2), 48–50.
Racine, E., Nguyen, V., Saigle, V., and Dubljević, V. (2016). Media portrayal of a landmark
neuroscience experiment on free will. Science and Engineering Ethics. Advance online publication.
doi:10.1007/s11948-016-9845-3
410
Racine, E., Aspler J., Forlini, C., and Chandler, J. (2017). Broadening the lenses on complementary and
alternative medicines in preclinical Alzheimer’s disease: Tensions between autonomy and contextual
determinants of choice. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 27(1), 1–41.
Rousseau, J.-J. (1992). Du Contrat Social. Paris: GF-Flammarion.
Rule, N.O., Freeman, J.B., Moran, J.M., Gabrieli, J.D., Adams, R.B., Jr., and Ambady, N. (2010).
Voting behavior is reflected in amygdala response across cultures. Social Cognitive and Affective
Neuroscience, 5(2–3), 349–355.
Ryan, R.M. and Deci, E.L. (2000). Self-determination theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation,
social development, and well-being. American Psychologist, 55(1), 68–78.
Saigle, V., Dubljević, V., and Racine, E. (2015). The impact of a landmark paper on the concept of free
will: reconsidering the legacy of the Libet et al. EEG experiments. American Journal of Bioethics
Neuroscience, 6(4), 91.
Seligman, M.E.P. (1975). Helplessness: On Depression, Development, and Death. San Francisco, CA: W.H.
Freeman.
Sherwin, E., Rea, K., Dinan, T.G., and Cryan, J.F. (2016). A gut (microbiome) feeling about the brain.
Current Opinion in Gastroenterology, 32(2), 96–102.
Smith, K. (2011). Neuroscience vs philosophy: taking aim at free will. Nature, 477(7362), 23–25.
Strawson, P.F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.
Sudo, N., Chida, Y., Aiba, Y., et al. (2004). Postnatal microbial colonization programs the
hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal system for stress response in mice. The Journal of Physiology,
558(1), 263–275.
Vohs, K.D., Baumeister, R.F., Schmeichel, B.J., Twenge, J.M., Nelson, N.M., and Tice, D.M. (2008).
Making choices impairs subsequent self-control: a limited-resource account of decision making,
self-regulation, and active initiative. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94(5), 883–898.
Wagner, D.D. and Heatherton, T.F. (2013). Self-regulatory depletion increases emotional reactivity in
the amygdala. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8(4), 410–417.
Wegener, J.R., Ludlow, C.E., Olsen, A.J., Tortosa, M., and Wintch, P.H. (2007). Ego depletion: a
contributing factor of hopelessness depression. Intuition, 3, 12–17.
Wegner, D. (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wolpe, P.R. (2002). The neuroscience revolution. The Hastings Center Report, 32(4), 8.
41
Chapter 21
Introduction
Contemporary debates on human enhancement often characterize the notion of enhance-
ment as morally troubling because it undermines some deeply held beliefs concerning
humanity and challenges what some deem as the appropriate use of biotechnologies to
serve human ends. Most techniques and procedures beyond therapeutic aims raise the
eyebrows of many concerned with the potential harmful implications of enhancement
technologies. Fewer people might oppose the enhancement of human physiological and
mental capacities if these techniques address specific diseases and disorders. If the goal of
any intervention is therapeutic, it falls under the purview of medicine. Beyond therapy,
where the aims of enhancement are not well defined, the moral landscape becomes less
clear. To say that human enhancement strives to the betterment of the human condition
or personal fulfillment does not make any normative claim robust enough to justify why
we ought to embrace any type of enhancement. In addition, enhancement is often gauged
against therapy to provide the backdrop necessary to discriminate what belongs to the
domain of medicine and healthcare as well as to provide conceptual clarity. However, the
conceptual distinction between therapy and enhancement has limitations that restrain
our ability to demarcate the types of enhancements that could indeed benefit some
individuals.
In light of these considerations, this chapter considers the use of cognitive enhancers
in healthy individuals with cognitive impairment caused by mental disability, that is, dis-
abled people with limited functioning but who are otherwise healthy and in a stable con-
dition. The use of cognitive enhancers in healthy individuals with cognitive impairment
illustrates the necessity to make more nuanced distinctions when examining the issue of
cognitive enhancement technologies in order to harness their potential clinical benefits
(Jotterand et al. 2015). The main objectives of this analysis are twofold: (1) to outline some
of the problems associated with the attempt to distinguish the concept of enhancement
from therapy. Both concepts assume that an understanding of health and normality is dif-
ficult to establish. I argue that these two concepts cannot be the basis for the assessment of
the use of cognitive enhancers in people with mental impairment because the restoration
of health or the attainment of normality cannot be realized in the case, for instance, of
412
people with cerebral palsy (permanent state); and (2) to show the relevance of the distinc-
tion between two types of enhancement in the attempt to demonstrate why the notion
of human enhancement, if it aims at the improvement of the quality of life of individuals
with mental impairments, might become part of the therapeutic language of tomorrow.
To this end, I introduce the concept of the clinical ideal to justify my claim about the use
of cognitive enhancers in the mentally impaired.
The first section of this chapter examines the various conceptualizations of enhance-
ment found in the literature, especially as outlined by Ruth Chadwick and Nicolas Agar.
These two scholars present helpful categorizations of enhancement that will provide the
basis for the development of the concept of the clinical ideal. Chadwick suggests four
approaches to enhancement helpful to understand how the concept is used in current
debates whereas Agar offers a valuable distinction between the objective ideal and the
anthropocentric ideal. In the second section, building on the work of Agar, I argue that
both ideals have limited clinical relevance and favor the clinical ideal, which allows for
the evaluation of the concept of enhancement in the context of clinical interventions. The
final section looks at the implications of the clinical ideal in relation to the use of cognitive
enhancers in the mentally impaired. I contend that the moral evaluation of enhancement
must take place within the context of the patient’s clinical condition and in relation to the
notion of quality of life.
Contrary to the theoretical nature of these early reflections by Bacon, Descartes, and
de Condorcet, some of the contemporary conceptualizations of human enhancement
can be validated through use of specific technologies, either under development or
already implemented. In current discussions, enhancement usually “characterize[s]
interventions designed to improve human form or functioning beyond what is neces-
sary to sustain or restore good health” (Juengst 1998, p.29). Cognitive enhancement
encompasses “the amplification or extension of core capacities of the mind, using
413
Beyond therapy view Any procedures beyond thera- Some interventions might be viewed
peutic interventions are consid- partly as enhancement and partly as
ered a type of enhancement therapy
Additionality view Enhancement is understood Requires focus on specific capacities
quantitatively: To enhance x is to establish what defines therapy or
to add to, or exaggerate, or enhancement
increase x in some respect Requires focus on particular capaci-
ties for moral evaluation
Improvement view Enhancement is understood Does not provide the criteria neces-
qualitatively: To enhance is to sary to determine what is considered
improve or to make better an improvement
Contingent upon qualitative
judgments
Difficult to assess from a moral
standpoint
Umbrella view Enhancement is assessed case by Too generic and does not provide
case to determine its nature: a proper framework for conceptual
◆ Enhancement may be thera- clarity
peutic (contra the beyond
therapy view)
◆ Enhancement may not
add anything (contra the
additionality view)
◆ Enhancement may not be
an improvement (contra the
improvement view)
Ideals
Objective ideal (Agar) All things being equal, tech- Prudential value of enhancement
nologies that produce greater is based on the degree to which it
enhancements are intrinsically objectively enhances human capacity
more valuable than other tech- Requires setting objective standards
nologies that generate fewer to evaluate levels of enhanced
enhancement outcomes capacities
Anthropocentric ideal Enhancement is evaluated based Assigns value to enhancement
(Agar) on a balance between the instru- relative to human standards and
mental and intrinsic value of the whether or not an enhancement is
enhanced capacity beneficial to the recipient based on
standardized norms
Requires a normative framework
to determine how enhancement
advances the well-being of the
human species within the normal
range of human capacities.
415
Table 21.1 Continued
the context of personal benefits (internal goods) and social benefits (external goods).
Accordingly, the value of enhancement is not contingent upon an evaluative framework
that fosters the maximization of the enhancement of human capacities but rather on the
enhancement of the capacities of a particular individual based on his or her unique per-
sonal goals and values. However, according to Agar, the value of an enhancement is relative
to the degree of prudential value in relation to the objective degree of enhancement within
the normal range of human capacities. Beyond a certain point, he contends, enhancement
becomes highly hypothetical, if not unrealistic, because it lacks objectivity with regard to
its feasibility, and therefore its degree of prudential value decreases due to the uncertainty
of how individuals could potentially be affected negatively by specific enhancements.
The anthropocentric ideal offers a potential way to evaluate the use of cognitive enhanc-
ers in people with mental impairments. Contrary to the objective ideal approach, the
anthropocentric ideal specifically focuses on the established range of normal human
capacities to evaluate the prudential value of particular enhancing technologies. As Agar
puts it: “enhancement beyond human norms encompasses interventions whose purpose
is to boost levels of functioning beyond biological norms” (Agar 2014, p.19). Thus, he
assumes that the normal range of human capacities can be determined based on biologi-
cal attributes of normal functioning, a claim I will challenge in the next section.
While Agar’s distinction is valuable in many ways, I propose a third way of evaluating
enhancement, especially since the objective ideal and the anthropocentric ideal, in my
estimation, have limited clinical relevance. I am proposing what I call the clinical ideal
based on the conceptualization of diseases as clinical problems (Engelhardt 1984).
These criteria characterize a framework based on biostatistical analysis that provides stan-
dards of normal functioning (or healthy states) for which any deviation constitutes a state
of disease. Kass likewise suggests that health, or the absence thereof, is based on biological
standards. Each species displays specific bodily functionalities that can be recognized or
determined by the specificities of its organism (Kass 1985).
Engelhardt, however, rejects the idea that diseased states can be established uniquely in
terms of species-typical levels of species-typical functions. The indeterminateness of the
forces of nature does not allow establishing a taxonomy of disease in relation to the func-
tional organization of the body (Engelhard 1996). In addition, a species, the human spe-
cies for instance, displays a range of characteristic polymorphisms that demands a specific
understanding of what we mean by human nature, its purpose, and its values, which in
turn justify the normality or abnormality of biological attributes (Engelhardt 1996). These
values operate in a proscriptive manner since they inform what behaviors and habits (e.g.,
smoking, unhealthy diet) affect a person’s health and therefore are considered detrimental
to a person’s health. In short, conceptualizations of health and disease are the result of a
complex interaction between values and norms, in addition to biological standards, that
qualify specific understandings of well-being and human flourishing (Engelhardt 1996).
In contrast to a descriptive account of disease, Engelhardt suggests considering diseases
as clinical problems. The focus of clinical medicine is to address questions of pain, expec-
tations concerning human form and grace, physical aptitudes, and mental capacities inso-
far as they affect a person’s ability to achieve specific human goals and ends (Engelhardt
1984). This means that diseases are not considered as abnormalities outside the scope of
what is deemed species-typical levels of species-typical functions. Diseases, as clinical
problems, are contextualized based on the goals, ends, and notions of human flourishing
held by individuals suffering from incapacitating ailments.
Based on the above analysis, I would argue that enhancement cannot be understood
outside a normative framework and therefore without contextualizing enhancement in
relation to notions of human flourishing, goals, and ends debates will remain somewhat
entrenched in ideological positions rather than careful critical enquiry. In addition, as
I stated earlier, my goal is to examine the concept of enhancement within the clinical con-
text. To this end, I suggest that describing the notion of enhancement as a clinical ideal
allows disentangling enhancement from extreme applications such as transhumanism,
and from a narrow explanation based on a normal range of human capacities. In so doing,
I consider the possibility of enhancement as a means to address clinical problems rather
than as a way to promote the agenda of transcending the boundaries of human biology
to achieve a posthuman state. But in order to justify this claim, an important distinction
between two types of enhancement must be made as I show in what follows.
Clinical ideal
To reiterate Agar’s earlier distinction, the objective ideal argues that the prudential value
of enhancement is based on the degree to which it objectively enhances human capac-
ity and therefore adopts a position that demands a set of objective standards to evaluate
levels of enhanced capacities. On the other hand, the anthropocentric ideal assigns value
to enhancement relative to human standards, that is, whether or not it benefits the recipi-
ent of an enhancement based on standardized norms. This approach assumes a norma-
tive framework that determines how enhancement advances the well-being of the human
species.
In contrast to these two ideals, the clinical ideal assigned value to enhancement if it
enhances the physical, mental, and social capacities and the overall quality of life of an
419
individual with mental impairment (baseline disabled) in the context of life (contextual
standards). The clinical ideal facilitates the introduction of the notion of enhancement in
the clinical language without the need to contrast it or oppose it to the notion of therapy. It
limits its scope of considerations to the life of a particular individual whose quality of life
and well-being could be improved by cognitive enhancers. Ordinarily, therapy refers to
the restoration, partial or complete, of the functions of an organism affected by a disease, a
disability, or an impairment using appropriate treatment. Therapy is a useful concept that
helps clinicians determine the scope of medical practice based on established baseline
criteria. In addition, the language of therapy implies an understanding of what a healthy
organism is, and the scope of normal functioning. But providing clear definitions and
conceptual clarity to notions such as health, normality, impairment, and abnormality has
been a notoriously difficult task. Notions of health and normality are concepts that have
evolved, and continue to do, as progress in the biomedical sciences constantly reshapes
the boundaries of what health is or what normal functioning for a biological organism
entails. Health determinants are a complex combination of environmental, social, educa-
tional, and biological factors and therefore the expectation to achieve a healthy status is in
constant flux. That said, the practice of medicine requires the establishment of standards
that will allow practitioners to help their patients achieve the optimization of functioning
established on standards of functionality within the boundaries of human biology.
On the other hand, enhancement #1 refers to the use of the power of biotechnologies
to transcend the normal scope of species-typical human capacities to improve biological
abilities. Therapy is limited to the scope of medicine whereas enhancement #1 applies
to a different domain since its application focuses on healthy individuals who want to
enhance some capacities. Yet, the line of demarcation between what constitutes therapy
and enhancement respectively is increasingly fuzzy because some therapeutic interven-
tions, devices, or drugs have dual effects or, as I point out in this chapter, enhancement #2
could be employed in the context of individuals whose levels of capacities are not consis-
tent with being nondisabled.
these individuals are not competent, if they cannot voice their option, or when clinicians
and family members make claims about the patient’s quality of life. Studies have shown
that there are discrepancies between how patients perceive their quality of life and what
others say about it, especially since patients learn how to cope with illness, find support
elsewhere, and in many instances remain positive about life in general and still find plea-
sure despite their situation (Lo 2000 p.30). Consequently, as Lo rightly states: “quality of
life judgments by others might be inaccurate and biased unless they reflect the patient’s
own assessment of quality of life” (Lo 2000 p.30).
Another important issue to consider is the quality of life of individuals with cogni-
tive impairments. Some authors argue that below a certain level of functionality con-
sidered essential for being a person, individuals cannot experience a meaningful quality
of life and consequently clinical interventions are futile. Others are concerned that such
evaluation of quality of life could lead to the contention that people who do not exhibit
attributes of personhood will be “eliminated” because such lives are deemed “not worth
living” (Schneiderman et al. 1990). The deep disagreement about the nature of the quality
of life of the mentally impaired epitomizes the challenge for its assessment in those who
are baseline disabled. So we need to be cognizant that ultimately the determination of the
quality of life by others remains problematic.
With these considerations in mind, I turn now specifically to the criteria outlining the
boundaries of the quality of life of the mentally impaired when potentially undergoing
cognitive enhancement. The specific aims of the use of cognitive enhancers in people
with mental disabilities include “increase[ing] functioning with a decrease in the need
for health care and daily assistance” and “increase[ing] the individual’s social capacity”
(Jotterand et al. 2015 p.123). Social capacity refers to the ability to increase a person’s
ability to socialize and enter into relationships with others, which includes a broadening
of personal choices, self-expression, and an optimization of how to engage in the world
(Jotterand et al. 2015). Disabled people with mild cognitive impairments who exhibit self-
awareness could benefit from cognitive enhancers with regard to a stronger social lifestyle
and increased independence (Kittelsaa 2014). The case of the severely disabled is more
complex and requires a more nuanced examination.
To make a stronger argument in my analysis, I will use the case of Ashley (often referred
as the Pillow Angel Case). As far as I know, Ashley never underwent interventions
involving cognitive enhancers. This case exemplifies how the use of cognitive enhancers
could improve the quality of life of mentally impaired individuals such as children in a
“permanently unabled state” for which there is no treatment currently available but who
might benefit from enhancement technologies. Of course the assumption here is that
these techniques are safe and efficacious—which I do not intend to assess in this chapter.
My goal is simply to look at enhancement #2 and the implications of its applications in
a real-life case.
Case scenario: Ashley, born in 1997, was diagnosed at the age of 6½ with static encephalopathy, a
condition that keeps the brain of this patient population in a “permanent and unchanging state” and
421
for which there is no treatment. This severe brain disorder kept Ashley “permanently unabled” men-
tally (age of an infant) while her body continued to grow normally. The parents, concerned with the
care of Ashley, made three requests to the Children’s Hospital and Regional Medical Center in Seattle,
Washington. They asked doctors to have Ashley undergo the following three procedures: (1) a hyster-
ectomy (to remove the uterus), (2) the removal of breast buds, and (3) a height attenuation to control
height and weight through hormone therapy. While alert and responsive to her surroundings Ashley
could not walk, sit up, grasp objects, use language or eat.
I will not analyze the case in terms of whether the doctors should proceed with the request
of the parents as other scholars have already examined this case in depth (Gunther &
Diekema 2006). Rather, my intention is to use the case of Ashley to raise the following
question: Does the (hypothetical) improvement of the quality of life of individuals such as
Ashley justify the use of cognitive enhancers?
To answer this question, it is essential to stress that context is crucial in our analysis.
The clinical ideal asserts that any enhancement that improves the quality of life of an
individual with a mental impairment is justified if it takes into account the particular situ-
ation of the person involved. This means that no general claims can be asserted as to the
widespread usage of cognitive enhancers and as to the moral obligation of their use in the
mentally impaired even if it has been proven that enhancers improve their overall quality
of life. The prudential value of enhancement is determined by how clinical procedures—
the degree of enhancement—meet realistic expectations set by the person caring for the
(incompetent) cognitively impaired individual proportionally to the improvement of the
quality of life, to the enhanced physical and mental functionality, and to the increased
social capacity. Such a framework does not require setting any threshold since its goal is
to promote the well-being of the individual subjected to these enhancements.
There is always a danger in using graphics to represent questions of enhancement and
quality of life due to the difficulty in quantifying these concepts. However, the representa-
tion in Figure 21.1 might help visualize the concept of the clinical ideal.
The point here is to make a normative statement about the nature of enhancement with
regard to quality of life. Consider the y-axis as representing quality of life on a scale of
0–10 and the x-axis as representing degrees of enhancement on a scale of 0–10. In addi-
tion, consider this graphic as a visual aid used by the person deciding whether to allow the
use of cognitive enhancers in the mentally impaired under his/her responsibility. While
I recognize that quantification of enhancement and quality of life are difficult to establish,
Figure 21.1 is a graphic representation of the relationship between degrees of enhance-
ment and degrees of quality of life. In an ideal scenario, the clinical ideal suggests that the
increased degree of quality of life must be equal or superior to the degree of increased
enhancement as indicated by the gray arrow. This means that quality of life should take
priority over enhancement to avoid an instrumentation of patients through technologi-
cal interventions. Unless enhancement technologies are safe, the focus should be on the
improvement of quality of life and not on increased capacities. In a nonideal scenario
(degree of enhancement higher than degree of quality of life—see Figure 21.1) where the
improvement of quality of life of an individual requires extensive enhancements, each
42
Clinical Ideal
10
9
8
7
Quality of Life
6
5
4
3
2
1
0
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
Degrees of Enhancement
Figure 21.1 Graphic representation of the relationship between degrees of enhancement and
degrees of quality of life. In an ideal scenario, the clinical ideal suggests that the increased degree
of quality of life must be equal or superior to the degree of increased enhancement as indicated
by the gray arrow.
case must be evaluated on its own facts using ethical guidelines that prevent the use of
enhancement technologies that objectify the patient and promote his or her welfare and
safety.
The clinical ideal does not necessitate setting a normal range of human capacities
because the patient population concerned has a baseline disabled that is outside the nor-
mal range of human abilities. Therefore, any moral assessment as to the acceptability of
an enhancement must be established on the subjective degree of improvement of qual-
ity of life. Furthermore, to protect and maximize the well-being of the recipient of the
enhancement procedure, the degree of enhancement must be equal or superior to the
degree of improved quality of life. In other words, if the degree of enhancement in rela-
tion to a baseline disabled is 4, ideally the degree of quality of life should be deemed to be
4 or higher.
The individualist approach of the clinical ideal is represented in Figure 21.2. It shows
each individual starting at a different stage with regard to how quality of life is experi-
enced or expressed and that the degree of enhancement does not necessarily improve
well-being.
In Figure 21.2, we have three individuals with mental impairment whose quality of life
has been determined to 2 at baseline disabled for person ◆, to 3 at baseline disabled for
person ■, and to 4 at baseline disabled for person ✕. The clinical ideal does not provide
a normative framework within specific parameters other than the fact that enhance-
ments that do not increase quality of life above baseline line should be dismissed. In
addition, quality of life is closely related to the condition of a particular person, how it
is experienced and interpreted. Figure 21.2 reveals that there are different scenarios to
423
6
5
4
3
2
1
0
0 2 4 6 8 10
Degrees of Enhancement
Figure 21.2 Graphic representation of various potential enhancement scenarios: ▲ represents
the clinical ideal where increased degree of quality of life must be equal or superior to the degree
of increased enhancement; ◆ represents the case of a disabled person where increased degree
of enhancement minimally influences quality of life; ◆ represents the case of a disabled person
where increased degree of enhancement decreases quality of life beyond a certain point; ✕
represents the case of a disabled person whereas increased degree of enhancement negatively
impacts quality of life.
consider: in certain cases cognitive enhancement might indeed not improve quality of
life (person ✕), in other cases the magnitude of enhancement only slightly changes the
quality of life (person ◆), whereas in other instances there might be a dramatic improve-
ment of quality of life up to a certain level of enhancement and then a drastic drop (per-
son ◆). This is not a comprehensive list of scenarios nor is it based on empirical data, but
it illustrates that each individual should be treated as a unique case, with specific needs
and a particular experience and expression of well-being.
To summarize, the clinical ideal avoids the challenge of determining the normal range
of human capacities, even in the case of the mentally impaired, or human standards. It
simply states that, with regard to the mentally impaired, the moral evaluation of enhance-
ment #2 can take place within the context of the patient’s clinical condition and in relation
to the notion of quality of life. There is a subjective and evaluative dimension that escapes
any attempt to standardize enhancement #2. The alteration of the physical, mental, and
social capacities of the mentally impaired is justified if it improves the overall well-being
of the patient.
Ethical considerations
It is important to keep in mind that no study on the long-term effects of cognitive
enhancers on healthy subjects has been completed so far and that no accepted ethi-
cal and legal framework has been fully developed for the use of cognitive enhancers.
42
Conclusion
This chapter provides a philosophical justification of the potential clinical use of cognitive
enhancers in the mentally impaired. The concept of the clinical ideal constitutes a pos-
sible approach that takes into account the complexities of clinical work in determining
the overall experience of a patient with mental impairment in terms of expressed and
perceived quality of life, and the interpretation of the notion of enhancement in medi-
cine. While a philosophical justification is a first step toward a hypothetical acceptance
case-by-case of cognitive enhancers in the clinical context, a more robust analysis needs
to take place for the development of ethical guidelines and policies based on sound sci-
ence. Without such analysis, public opinion might be influenced by various stakehold-
ers concerned with the protection of the targeted patient population but might miss the
opportunity to support an endeavor with potential clinical benefits.
References
Agar, N. (2014). Truly Human Enhancement: A Philosophical Defense of Limits. Cambridge, MA: The
MIT Press.
Boorse, C. (1975). On the distinction between disease and illness. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 5, 49–68.
Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.
Boorse, C. (1997). A rebuttal on health. In: Humber, J.M. and Almeder, R.F. (Eds.) What is Disease?,
pp.1–134. Totowa, NJ: Humana Press.
Bostrom, N. (2005). In defense of posthuman dignity. Bioethics, 19, 202–214.
425
References 425
Chapter 22
the relationship between the environment and human health, and the attendant ethical
implications, insufficient attention has been paid to the ethical, social, and legal impli-
cations that arise from environmental impacts and deleterious exposure in terms of
brain and mental health effects.
In this chapter, I introduce environmental neuroethics as an emerging approach at the
intersection of environmental studies, biomedical and social understandings of brain and
mental health, and ethics. In order to make the case that environmental neuroethics is
an important and needed approach, I provide in the next section examples of the various
ways in which environmental exposures impact brain and mental health, both in positive
and negative ways, and explore why those related impacts are a matter of moral concern.
In the last sections I lay out the foundations for a first generation of environmental neu-
roethics and discuss key challenges ahead.
Other metals
Arsenic is yet another neurotoxic heavy metal (Miodovnik 2011). In Japan, in 1955,
arsenic-induced developmental neurotoxicity was reported as a result of consumption of
contaminated dried milk powder. In follow-up studies, infants who survived the poison-
ing had lower IQs and higher rates of severe mental retardation when compared with
control groups (Dakeishi et al. 2006). Other studies have found that arsenic exposure is
associated with declines in verbal learning and memory (Wright et al. 2006), in attention
(Tsai et al. 2003), and in intelligence in school-age children (Rosado et al. 2007).
There is also evidence that manganese (Lucchini et al. 2014) and cadmium (de Burbure
et al. 2006; Rodríguez-Barranco et al. 2014) affect neurological function, either by acting
directly on the brain or alternatively by adversely impacting hormones necessary to main-
tain healthy neurological function (Grandjean 2013; Grossman 2014). When accumu-
lated in excess, copper and manganese can lead to liver failure, which in turn can trigger
hepatocerebral disorders with morphologic changes similar to those seen in Alzheimer’s
disease, and neurological symptoms including parkinsonism1 and cognitive dysfunction
(Butterworth 2010).
Other industrial chemicals with sufficient evidence to suggest neurotoxicity are PCBs.
While PCBs were banned in the 1970s, they remain present in many products and mate-
rials produced before 1979. Various longitudinal studies have examined neurodevelop-
mental outcomes associated with exposure to PCBs, supporting modest associations with
poorer attention (Jacobson & Jacobson 2003), IQ (Stewart et al. 2008), impulse control
(Korrick & Sagiv 2008), and learning skills (Grandjean et al. 2001).
Urban exposures
Another way in which brain and mental health are affected by the environment is through
urbanization which introduces sources of urban pollution as well as toxic social circum-
stances (Bentall & Fernyhough 2008), including stress, fleeting social relationships,
technology-driven remote interactions, higher crime rates, increased social competition,
and wider socioeconomic disparities (Tost et al. 2015). Schizophrenia has the notorious
recognition of being the mental health disorder with the best-examined link regarding
urban birth, urban upbringing, and urban residence (Kelly et al. 2010; van Os et al. 2010).
When compared with rural areas, psychiatric disorders are on average 34% more frequent
in urbanized areas (Peen et al. 2010). A prospective study in Ireland found an incidence
rate ratio of 1.92 for males and 1.34 for females in cities when compared to their rural
431
counterparts (Kelly et al. 2010). Magnetic resonance imaging studies support the idea that
on the functional level the degree of urbanization has implications for the neural social
stress response system, and that the degree of exposure to urban environments is associ-
ated with para-anterior cingulate cortex activation and decreased gray matter volume in
the prefrontal cortex (Lederbogen et al. 2011; Haddad et al. 2015). That finding plausibly
relates to the high incidence of schizophrenia in the cities.
Proximity to noxious facilities
In addition to industry-generated chemicals polluting air and water supplies, simply liv-
ing near to noxious facilities and waste repositories such as mining waste, nuclear plants,
or natural resources extraction sites, can be harmful to brain health (Heiervang et al. 2010;
Rabinowitz et al. 2015). A 2003 study noted that: “wastes from oil refineries can create
health risks to facility workers and surrounding communities... including exposure to heat,
polluted air, noise, and hazardous materials, including asphalt, asbestos, aromatic hydro-
carbons, arsenic, hexavalent chromium, nickel, carbon monoxide, coke dust, hydrogen
sulfide, lead alkyls, natural gases, petroleum, phenol, and silica” (O’Rourke & Connolly
2003). Brain health impacts from exposure to such material can include headaches, psy-
chosis, and peripheral neuropathies (O’Rourke & Connolly 2003; Colborn et al. 2011).
There are associated mental health problems as well. Two studies documented concerns
from residents living in boom town communities in rural Northeastern Pennsylvania and
Texas (Perry 2012; Stedman et al. 2012). They observed feelings of powerlessness, shock,
and disgust among community members as a result of the rapid landscape change from
agricultural and forested to industrial. They also noted stress associated with living within
the vicinity of industrial facilities. Similar findings have been reported for communities
who have experienced oil spills (Gay et al. 2010). There is a condition aptly labeled “eco-
anxiety” which describes a chronic fear of living with the consequences of potentially
unsound environmental practices (Watson 2008).
Extreme weather and changes in landscape
There is considerable evidence that human activities, such as those involved in industrial-
ization and urbanization, are primarily responsible for climate change and the related side
effects of global warming, including extreme weather fluctuations leading to more fre-
quent droughts, deadly heat waves, and more damaging rainstorms, as well as landscape
changes precipitated by the melting of glaciers, coastal flooding due to rising sea levels,
and wildfires (APA Task Force 2011; Resnik 2012).
Climate change impacts on public health have primarily focused on physical health
outcomes, linking changes in availability of food and water quality and quantity to mal-
nutrition and vector-borne diseases, examining increasingly evident and oftentimes more
visible health issues such as respiratory, cardiovascular, and kidney diseases. However,
literature on the impact of climate change on mental health is now emerging (APA Task
Force 2011). For example, research by Cunsolo and colleagues documents the impact of
climate change on the mental health and well-being of Inuit people over time (Cunsolo
Willox et al. 2013). Cunsolo and colleagues demonstrate how temperature increases and
432
the concomitant thinning of the ice layer has prevented the Nunuvut Inuit from engaging
in cultural food procurement practices, such as hunting, as frequently as they had done so
in the past (Cunsolo et al. 2013). This cultural shift was found to be associated with men-
tal health consequences including increased family stress and amplification of previous
traumas and mental health stressors.2 The term solastalgia (Albrecht et al. 2007) describes
a particular distress experienced as a consequence of being deprived of the solace one
derives from contact with one’s native environment. Other research has focused on men-
tal health impacts such as acute and post-traumatic stress disorder, depression, anxiety
disorders, drug and alcohol abuse; higher suicide attempts and completions; and the gen-
eral increased vulnerability of those with preexisting severe mental health issues suffer-
ing from climate change associated loss, disruption, and displacement (Fritze et al. 2008;
Berry et al. 2010, 2011). Clearly, changes in the environment can have important direct
impacts on the mental health and well-being of residents as well as disrupting underlying
determinants of health.
Experience with nature
A deep-seated connection between mental health and the natural world would, from an
evolutionary perspective, be quite plausible. Several cross-cultural studies reinforce this
view. Certain indigenous worldviews see identity, conceptions of the self, and mental
wellness as linked directly and intimately to the environment, and one’s ability to hunt,
trap, fish, forage, and travel on the land, as well as to practice cultural traditions related
to being “on the land” (Kirmayer & Valaskakis 2008; Vukic et al. 2011). This understand-
ing, of the importance of land and land-based activities, highlights connections between
individuals and their environments on well-being and mental health.
A growing body of literature demonstrates that exposure to natural landscapes, or to
their composite features such as flora and fauna, has beneficial effects for child develop-
ment, well-being, mental health, mood, mortality, and recovery from illness (Frumkin
2001; Maas 2006; Haluza et al. 2014). This connection is what David Cumes describes as
“wilderness rapture” (Cumes 1998). That rapture includes feelings of awe, wonder, and
humility, a sense of comfort and connection to nature, and feelings of renewal and vigor.
Although the topic is under-researched, there is evidence associating exposure to natural
environments with restoration from attention fatigue, recovery from stress, feelings of
relaxation, as well as enhanced mental alertness, attention, and cognitive performance
(Bowler et al. 2010; Tost et al. 2015). A large-scale epidemiological study revealed a rela-
tionship between the abundance of green space and human health (Maas 2006). This
finding can be inversely related to the ill-health effects observed in urban settings, as a
key difference between urban and rural settings is the available green space. Although
the neurobiological effects of experiencing nature require further study, the current data
suggests that human contact with nature is more than an aesthetic luxury. This knowledge
has recently been integrated in horticultural therapy and wilderness therapy (Frumkin
43
Enriched environments
Seminal observations in the 1960s on the effect of environments rich in sensory stimuli to
gross brain structures stimulated further research on the influence of enriched environ-
ments to brain function and behavior (van Praag et al. 2000). Nowadays it is recognized
that environmental enrichment profoundly and positively affects the central nervous sys-
tem at the functional, anatomical, and molecular level (Mora et al. 2007; Baroncelli et al.
2010), during critical developmental periods and in adulthood. In turn, this promotes
various plastic responses in the brain, ranging from biochemical parameters to the arbo-
rization of dendrites and neurogenesis (van Praag et al. 2000).
Environmental enrichment improves quality of life by providing a “combination of mul-
tisensory/cognitive stimulation, increased physical activity, enhanced social interactions
and by eliciting natural explorative behaviors” (Baroncelli et al. 2010, p.1093). While envi-
ronmental enrichment studies are largely based on rodent research, they provide insights
for application to humans. The admittedly minimal data from human studies and envi-
ronmental enrichment suggests that a higher level of mental and physical activity reduces
disease risk, including those associated with compromised brain function and cognition
(Kramer et al. 2006; Baroncelli et al. 2010). A study with human subjects revealed that
exercise promotes neurogenesis in the brain, suggesting that new proliferating neurons
might possibly contribute to the effects of exercise on memory and learning (Pereira et al.
2007). Another study with children found environmental enrichment to be somewhat
effective in ameliorating autism symptoms (Woo & Leon 2013). Considering evidence
linking sustained stress with impaired immunity, disease, and neurological changes char-
acteristic of major depressive illness and chronic anxiety disorders, it stands to reason
that stress-reduced environments can positively impact brain health (Crews 2010). These
findings corroborate the need for expanded attention to environmental enrichment para-
digms both for therapy as well as to avert neurological disorders.
affect multiple brain processes (Gómez-Pinilla 2008). Lai and colleagues systemati-
cally reviewed the literature to conduct a meta-analysis of the association between
dietary patterns and depression. They found that a healthy diet—one high in fruit,
vegetables, fish, and whole grains—was significantly associated with reduced likeli-
hood of depression (Lai et al. 2014). Another meta-analysis examined the association
between adherence to a Mediterranean diet and the risks of stroke, cognitive impair-
ment, depression, and Parkinson disease. High adherence to this diet was found to
be associated with reduced risks for ischemic stroke, depression, and mild cognitive
impairment (Psaltopoulou et al. 2013). Diets rich in antioxidants have become increas-
ingly popular as they are linked with positive effects on neural function and might
lower risks of developing age-related neurodegenerative diseases (Joseph et al. 2007).
Finally, studies have shown that probiotics can improve anxiety levels, perceptions
of stress, and mental outlook (Bested et al. 2013). Not surprisingly the production
of neurotransmitters such as serotonin, as well as the function of various neurons, is
highly influenced by the billions of “good” bacteria comprising the intestinal micro-
biota. Although these studies underscore the important effect of dietary factors on the
brain, further work is necessary to determine mechanisms of action and how to best
enhance brain function and mental health.
Social support
The extent and the quality of human social bonds influence positive affect, self-esteem,
recovery, and risk for mental illness (Tost et al. 2015). Seeman and McEwen’s study
provides support for the hypothesis that the positive influence of social environment
features reduces neuroendocrine reactivity (Seeman & McEwen 1996) which in turn
decreases the odds for exaggerated physiological stress responses and negative emo-
tional states (Tost et al. 2015). Laboratory experiments have corroborated the benefits
of social support in managing psychological stress (Chen et al. 2011). As mentioned
in the section on enriched environments, dynamic social interactions are critical, in
particular during childhood between caregivers (particularly parents) and infants.
Parenting behavior has demonstrable long-lasting effects on development. Stable,
supportive, and loving caregiver behavior promotes one’s ability to form trusting and
empathetic social relationships as well as mitigating the detrimental effects of adverse
life effects (Shonkoff 2012). Similarly, when older adults are satisfied with their avail-
able social support, they report a better health status than those who are dissatisfied
(White et al. 2009).
Despite the available evidence, knowledge and understanding as to the effects of envi-
ronmental changes and toxic exposures for brain and mental health is still in its infancy.
Further research is required to gain a more complete understanding of the current and
possible brain health impacts stemming from environmental influences. Given the cur-
rent rapid rate of environmental changes, ongoing study both of risks and resilience
mechanisms offers hope for developing preemptive and therapeutic approaches for brain
and mental health disorders.
436
Brains matters
Environmental neuroethics matters because brain and mental health matter. The brain is
arguably the most complex organ crucial to human well-being. It orchestrates all bodily
functions, is in charge of affective and cognitive capacities of reasoning and decision-
making, and is considered the seat of self-identity, autonomy, and self-narrative. The com-
plicated development of the brain, as well as its plasticity, make it uniquely sensitive to
environmental exposures, especially during development (Grandjean 2013). Such expo-
sures can trigger either adverse or positive effects that can be manifested over a lifetime.
A growing body of evidence suggests that neurological function in the elderly can be
manifestations of exposures from earlier years (Landrigan et al. 2005). Likewise, evidence
suggests that the brains of fetuses, infants, and children are uniquely sensitive to neuro-
toxicants at levels far below those known to harm adults.
Public health
Global impact studies have identified brain and mental health disorders as key contribu-
tors to disabilities and morbidity worldwide. Those disorders have a critical public health,
societal, and economic impact (Prüss-Üstün & Corvalán 2006). Developmental disabili-
ties or developmental delays (including mental retardation, autism, ADHD, and learning
437
disabilities) occur in about one in six children in the United States (Centers for Disease
Control and Prevention 2015). While the impact of the environment on brain and men-
tal health cannot easily be measured and assessed with certainty, cumulative interactive
effects are likely to be profound. Considering the role of the brain in defining a person,
even small deficits can negatively impact mental health.
Policy implications
It is estimated that over 25% of the burden of human illness worldwide can be attributed
to modifiable environmental conditions (Prüss-Üstün & Corvalán 2006). While urban-
ization and industry-precipitated environmental changes are unwittingly creating toxic
environments for brain and mental health, we potentially could modify our lived envi-
ronments to foster brain and mental health. Certain scholars have suggested that shaping
our environments to optimize brain and mental health is likely to be more effective and
less ethically problematic than genetic or pharmaceutical modifications of our capacities
(Levy 2012; Cabrera 2015). In terms of exposures, approximately 200 chemicals have been
found to be neurotoxic in humans (Grandjean & Landrigan 2006). However, thousands
of chemicals commonly found in the environment and in consumer products have not
undergone extensive neurotoxicity testing. Since even low levels of exposure can have
far-reaching brain and mental health effects, prior to entering the market there should
be more rigorous regulation in assessing the neurotoxic profile of chemicals and other
substances (Cranor 2011).
the developing brain more vulnerable to environmental exposures, there are epigenetic
mechanisms through which the dire consequences of environmental exposures are real-
ized in the next generation. In his video “Little Things Matter,” Bruce Lanphear argues that
the widespread and chronic exposure to brain-damaging toxins can lead to an increase
in the number of US children who are mentally challenged, from 6 million to more than
11 million (Canadian Environmental Health Atlas 2014). Thus in terms of environmen-
tal impacts for brain and mental health, the related concerns are intergenerational, and
problematic both from a temporal distributive justice perspective as well as participa-
tive justice’s grounds of equal rights to self-determination in societal decision-making
(Shrader-Frechette 2006). Future generations are, in principle, unlikely to consent to
environmental pollution depletion of natural resources, and other environmental changes
that might pose a risk to their brain and mental health. To this concern, certain schol-
ars make the argument that our choices will cause a different person to exist—the iden-
tity problem—so that future individuals have no moral grounds for lodging complaints
against choices made by the present generation (Parfit 1971). Yet in the ethical assessment
of acts that will impact future generations it does not in fact matter who the members of
the future generation turn out to be. What matters is that future generations will suffer the
consequences of our actions, and as such have serious grounds for complaint. John Rawls’
veil of ignorance concept suggests that any reasonable person, not knowing to which gen-
eration, social class, or intelligence bracket they would belong, would accept as fair the
principle of equal apportionment of risks, resources, and goods (Rawls 1971).
Principles of equality in the distribution of opportunity such as this as well as those
suggested by the advocates of the capability approach seem intuitively fair (Nussbaum &
Sen 1993). Other arguments touch on the notion of a social contract among all genera-
tions. According to this view, as beneficiaries of ancestral legacies, members of present
generations have similar duties to future persons—regardless of whether or not those
future persons can reciprocate their giving; regardless of whether or not the future per-
sons are asked if they wish to receive benefits; and finally regardless of the degree to
which the present persons might know the needs of future generations (Shrader-Frechette
2006, p.102). Minimally, we know that they will require clean water and air to flourish as
human beings. Thus, at the simplest level, regardless of which generation they happen to
belong to, each and every person will have the same opportunity as any other to use and
benefit from resources. There is then a moral duty to provide future generations with
the same level of opportunity as they would have had if the present generation had not
depleted some resources or polluted their environment (Shrader-Frechette 2006, p.103).
This moral duty is recognized in national and international documents, such as the 1972
preamble to the Stockholm Declaration on the Human Environment, which affirms that
humans have “a solemn responsibility to protect and improve the environment for present
and future generations” (United Nations Environment Programme 1972). In the United
States, the first stated goal of the National Environmental Policy Act (NEPA) is to “fulfill
the responsibilities of each generation as trustee of the environment for succeeding gener-
ations” (NEPA 1969). NEPA also states that present generations should not impose undue
439
risks on “a future generation … greater than those acceptable to the current generation”
(NEPA 1969). There are approximately 50 federal statutes in the United States that contain
explicit reference to future generations, many of which aim at preserving some current
benefit for future generations (Shrader-Frechette 2006).
Considering the sensitivity and vulnerability of the brain to environmental exposures,
environmental neuroethics reflects a timely, necessary research trajectory. The focus
and investigation methods put forth by neuroethics provide a meaningful foundation
to address the brain and mental health impacts of environmental change. Neuroethics-
informed perspectives on environmental change and exposure impacts provide a theo-
retically and empirically based understanding of the brain and its relationship with the
environment at the individual, community, and societal level. A neuroethics perspec-
tive also can help to prioritize and rank important environmental change causes, conse-
quences, or responses as well as to make connections to research and concepts from other
social, engineering, and natural science fields. In sum, a neuroethics lens is crucial to
understand the ethical and social consequences of environmental change, to help reduce
the adverse brain and mental health impacts from environmental change, and to enable
effective individual and social adaptation strategies.
clash of different understandings about the environment and its role in promoting or
hindering brain health. Given those complexities, it is a crucial part of environmental
neuroethics to bring together conceptual and methodological frameworks from diverse
disciplines that do not often directly engage, including neuroscience, sociology, environ-
mental science, and ethics (Illes et al. 2014). This drawing together of multidisciplinary
insights launches the field of neuroethics and environmental ethics into broader interac-
tive biomedical and social understandings of environmental change.
There are a variety of frameworks that are relevant to environmental neuroethics, as
illustrated in Box 22.1.
Ethics frameworks
Normative frameworks focused on examining general concepts and principles of ethics,
as well as empirical ethics frameworks focused on moral reasoning, judgment, behavior,
development, and learning, are broad frameworks to explore environmental neuroethics
issues. Van Rensselaer Potter’s global bioethics is another useful normative framework.
Potter’s Global Bioethics (Potter 1988) focuses on integrating biological knowledge with
diverse humanistic knowledge to systematically establish medical and environmental pri-
orities for acceptable survival at a global scale. Rather than viewing neuroethics and envi-
ronmental ethics as separate and distinct entities, within this strategy those two branches
are harmonized to a consensual point, stressing the importance of brain and mental
health consequences of environmental change, as well as the intimate human health and a
healthy environment relationship. Care ethics is another useful framework, capturing the
importance of the environment and human health and well-being relationship. The dis-
tinct relational perspective incorporated by care ethics and feminist approaches acknowl-
edges that an individual’s health and well-being are inextricably linked to the flourishing
of others, of communities, and the natural environment (Held 2006; Slote 2007). The
conceptual contribution frames human beings as “constituted [simultaneously] both as
organisms within systems of ecological relations, and as persons within systems of social
relations” (Ingold 2000, p.3). Such a view is intrinsic to certain indigenous considerations
of an individual’s relationship to their community and ecosystem. A quotation from a
First Nation’s member captures this well: “I am part of an environment and if my environ-
ment suffers I suffer as well.” A relational framework rejects privileging individualistic
values and instead promotes communal values, viewing the individual and community
41
Social justice
A social justice framework considers unequal distribution, in the particular case of envi-
ronmental neuroethics, distribution of exposure to neurotoxicants and environmental
changes differentially impacting various populations in relationship to sociodemographic
determinants, such as income, occupation, education, and ethnicity (Commission on
Social Determinants of Health 2008). Those with lower socioeconomic status generally
have experienced greater exposure to detrimental environmental conditions both within
their homes and as part of their occupations. Minority groups, such as indigenous com-
munities, might suffer greater burdens of exposure if the natural resources they hunt and
fish are contaminated by industries operating near their communities. A social justice
framework additionally takes into consideration vulnerable subpopulations, such as chil-
dren, pregnant women, and the elderly, who due to age, genetics, or health status are
especially susceptible to the effects of environmental exposures. From a social justice
perspective, when making environmental planning decisions, such as choosing where to
build an industrial site, locate a waste dump, or where to establish parks and green areas,
communities and nations have a societal obligation to minimize and mitigate environ-
mental injustices. There is an obligation to better regulate and ensure safety in consumer
products and in the workplace. These decisions should be transparent, democratic, and
fair, and should solicit and take into account in deliberation from those especially vulner-
able to environmental risks (Resnik & Portier 2008).
Environmental justice
A related and important framework is that of environmental justice, which is based
upon the idea that the health and well-being of the members of a community, both
individually and collectively, are a product of the relationship between four interrelated
environments: natural, built, social, and cultural/spiritual (Lee 2002). It represents a
transformative public discourse on what constitutes truly healthy, livable, sustainable, and
vital communities. It expands the discourse concerning public health and environmental
risks to include issues of multiple, cumulative, and synergistic risk. Environmental injus-
tice occurs whenever some individual or group bears disproportionate environmental
risk, has unequal access to environmental goods, such as clean air, or has less opportu-
nity to participate in the environmental decision-making (Shrader-Frechette 2006). In
Western societies, poor and minority people who are disadvantaged in terms of educa-
tion, income, and occupation have been especially affected by environmental injustices,
as they are more likely than affluent Caucasians to live near polluting facilities, eat con-
taminated fish, and be employed at risky occupations. Environmental injustice is wrong
because it presents multiple threats to well-being and health (both for present and future
people), it violates the principle of prima facie political equity, including its components
of distributed and participative justice (Shrader-Frechette 2006), including aspects of
42
human rights to equal protection, due process, consent, and compensation. An environ-
mental justice framework sets the foundations for conducting community-driven science
and holistic, placed-based, systems-wide environmental protection (Lee 2002). It strives
for a more equitable distribution of environmental goods and burdens, while at the same
time it fosters greater public participation in evaluating and apportioning these goods and
burdens (Shrader-Frechette 2006).
Human rights
After World War II, there was international consensus on the need to identify those
activities, conditions, and freedoms that all human beings are entitled to enjoy by virtue
of being human. These are regarded as human rights, and they include political, civil,
social, economic, and cultural rights. Human rights cannot be granted or taken away, the
enjoyment of one right affects the enjoyment of others and they must all be respected.
A human rights framework focuses on ways to establish mechanisms for addressing seri-
ous breaches and promoting national governments’ adherence regarding human rights
obligations. In relation to environmental neuroethics, key human rights to be discussed
would include the right to brain and mental health, to healthy environments, to access to
healthy food and clean water, and equal protection from environmental risks.
43
Social constructionism
According to this theoretical framework, reality cannot be accessed directly; the world
can only be perceived through our understandings. Thus what we know about the world
is socially constructed, and this knowledge is developed, transmitted, and maintained in
social situations. Social construction as a process refers then to how people collectively
and through social interaction perceive and interpret, impose meaning and order on their
world, and shape their shared reality (Berger & Luckmann 1966; Gergen 2001). Our per-
ception of the world, including the environment, is influenced by the underlying culture,
values, and local knowledge, by political and governance processes, by economic oppor-
tunities and costs, as well as by understandings of past experience, the present situation,
and future goals together with appraisals of risk, environmental threat, and environmen-
tal change (see Box 22.1).
Finally, adapting previous work in neuroethics (Marcus 2002), there are five founda-
tional areas (see Box 22.2) in which ethical issues that arise from environmental changes
impacts on brain and mental health can be conceptualized and problematized (Cabrera
et al. 2016).
Considering that environmental neuroethics is a relatively new approach within neu-
roethics, the principles and frameworks suggested here require further elaboration and
analysis; however, they lay a strong foundation to continue interdisciplinary work and
research in this important area.
Conceptual
There are at least two conceptual issues that need to be addressed. The first one deals with
the environment being too broad a concept or too complex as to be the object of discus-
sion for mitigating brain disorders or fostering brain health. While it is true that the envi-
ronment can include many variables, there are ways in which the discussion of how the
environment affects brain and mental health is valuable. One way is to be specific about
the particular aspect of the environment (e.g., physical or social, or air quality). Another
way is to step back from a highly individualized perspective to a relational and interre-
lated one, embracing the underlying complexity and acknowledging how interconnected
brain and mental health is to the environments we grow and live in.
4
A second conceptual challenge has to do with how to distinguish between harm ver-
sus benefit with respect to environmental exposures. These concepts are relative to what
an individual would have been like in the absence of a particular environmental factor.
There is not a straightforward baseline level that would enable classification of a given
environmental factor as being beneficial if it increases brain health above that level and
harmful if it decreases brain health below that level. For many of the environmental fac-
tors already mentioned there seems to be a continuum, and there is not an obvious point
on the continuum that counts as the presumed normal amount of that environmental
factor. What counts as beneficial or harmful environmental exposure, or even what is a
healthy environment, is open to debate and is in need of both more empirical evidence
and normative discussion.
45
Knowledge
There are epistemic challenges. The rigid boundaries among disciplines of knowledge
along with semiautonomous development of knowledge in each field have been long-
standing obstacles to interdisciplinary thinking and practice necessary for integrated envi-
ronmental impact assessment on brain and mental health. This raises questions such as
“What knowledge should be counted in the assessment and how to assess diverse sources
of knowledge?” There is also a relative lack of expertise bridging the different areas that
are needed to obtain a better understanding of the issues involved, and to adequately
project their expertise into the state and national debates (Goldstein et al. 2012). Political
obstacles and time constraints are also a challenge for knowledge creation and dissemina-
tion. Policymakers typically use quantitative risk assessment and benefit–cost analysis in
ways that are not sensitive to social and environmental justice issues.
Methodologies
The comparative dearth in understanding environmental impacts on brain and mental
health has been partly due to methodological challenges in satisfying the scientific rigors of
cause and effect in epidemiology. Useful methodologies, such as population-based studies
that measure subtle effects on neurobehavioral outcomes, are often times challenging to
interpret and costly to conduct (Miodovnik 2011). Evidence linking a particular exposure
to brain health conditions relies on observational epidemiological studies or toxicity test-
ing using animal models, or both. For obvious ethical reasons, experimental studies with
purposeful dosing of substances with potential neurotoxic effects are not conducted in
humans. Therefore, while cause and effect is not proven with any one epidemiology study,
several well-designed studies in different populations, alone or combined with inferential
evidence from animal exposures, can strongly support the likelihood that a given associa-
tion is in fact causal in nature. There are also challenges in terms of accounting for the
long timeframes of onset for many neurological illnesses, distinguishing environmental
impacts from other influences on brain and mental health, and the fact that research on
the brain is a relative latecomer to environmental and health impact studies.
The employment of locally accepted terminology and assessment strategies, study of
the synergistic or additive effects from exposure to mixture compounds, the inefficiency
of traditional research methods to obtain documentation and continuous monitoring of
impacts, for example, in relation to the cumulative effects of contaminants, and the dif-
ficulties in analyzing biomarkers of exposure in human tissue (Cranor 2011) are other
examples of the difficulties ahead.
Evidence
A related challenge is connected to evidence. Different environmental factors may not
appear by themselves to cause any obvious or serious risk for brain and mental health,
and damage might only be detectable from the combination of various chemicals often
after continued exposure, which makes it difficult to assess causality (Grandjean 2013;
46
Grossman 2014). Likewise, while there is widespread agreement that exposing organisms
to environmental toxins at high dose levels constitutes a significant threat to environmen-
tal and public health, low-dose effects continue to be a matter of intense disagreement
among scientists, policymakers, and activist groups (Elliott 2011). There is also the issue
of how to weigh scientific evidence and the role it has in decision-making. Some argue,
for example, that we already have plenty of evidence to support actions aimed at protect-
ing our brain and mental health, while others disagree, adding that the benefits of certain
practices (e.g., use of pesticides) clearly outweigh the possible harms on brain and mental
health. Others have argued that society cannot afford to wait for complete evidence, as the
consequences could be catastrophic and irreversible. An alternative approach endorsed
by a number of commentators and organizations is based on a precautionary principle,
where the idea is that society should take reasonable steps to prevent or mitigate sig-
nificant harm even when scientific evidence is incomplete or contested (Steel 2014). This
leads to a related challenge, that of conflicts of interest.
Risks
Different social actors, based on their different worldviews and values, perceive and han-
dle risks differently (Slimak & Dietz 2006). Risks can be overestimated or underestimated
based on how they are perceived and communicated. Brain and mental health, for exam-
ple, often lack the clearly detectable experience characteristic of other more observable
bodily reactions such as coughing or red eyes resulting from high levels of air pollution,
which could lead to an underestimation of the associated risks.
47
Conclusion 447
Conclusion
Environmental neuroethics aims to identify pragmatic starting points and alternatives
to resolve difficult ethical challenges presented at the intersection of environment and
brain, from strategies to reduce the adverse brain and mental health impacts from envi-
ronmental change and toxic exposures, to policies and strategies to foster healthy envi-
ronments. It provides a platform to discuss different ethical principles and perspectives
at the intersection of environmental change and its impact for brain and mental health,
including issues of beneficence and nonmaleficence (avoiding harm and ensuring welfare
for individuals and communities), social justice, and responsibility. It offers a novel con-
ceptual, normative, and empirical approach, bringing various disciplines together into an
interaction with broader ethical, biomedical, and social understandings of environmental
change and exposures and their role for brain and mental health. The various frameworks
and principles discussed here set the foundation to move forward the first generation of
environmental neuroethics scholarship.
While many challenges lay ahead in the future of environmental neuroethics, it is clear
that the unprecedented consequences for both present and future generations in terms
of environmental impacts on brain and mental health make this new trajectory a needed
and timely one.
Acknowledgments
The author would like to thank Kevin Elliot, Len Fleck, and Libby Bogdan-Lovis for their
insightful comments and for helping with proofreading this chapter.
48
Notes
1. This is the clinical definition of a variety of different underlying pathologies that can cause Parkinson’s-
like symptoms.
2. There is also emerging evidence that chronic stress contributes to depression, post-traumatic stress
disorder, and the development of certain pathologies by accelerating and/or exacerbating preexisting
vulnerabilities.
References
Alavanja, M.C.R., Hoppin, J.A., and Kamel, F. (2004). Health effects of chronic pesticide
exposure: cancer and neurotoxicity. Annual Review of Public Health, 25, 155–197.
Albrecht, G., Sartore, G.M., Connor, L., et al. (2007). Solastalgia: the distress caused by environmental
change. Australasian Psychiatry, 15(Suppl. 1), S95–S98.
APA Task Force (2011). Psychology and Global Climate Change. American Psychological Association.
Available from: http://www.apa.org/science/about/publications/climate-change.aspx [accessed
January 18, 2016].
Baroncelli, L., Braschi, C., Spolidoro, M., Begenisic, T., Sale, A., and Maffei, L. (2010). Nurturing brain
plasticity: impact of environmental enrichment. Cell Death and Differentiation, 17(7), 1092–1103.
Bentall, R.P. and Fernyhough, C. (2008). Social predictors of psychotic experiences: specificity and
psychological mechanisms. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 34(6), 1012–1020.
Berger, P.L. and Luckmann, T. (1966). The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of
Knowledge. London: Penguin Books.
Berry, H.L., Hogan, A., Owen, J., Rickwood, D., and Fragar, L. (2011). Climate change and farmers’
mental health: risks and responses. Asia-Pacific Journal of Public Health, 23(Suppl. 2), 119S–132S.
Berry, H.L., Bowen, K., and Kjellstrom, T. (2010). Climate change and mental health: a causal pathways
framework. International Journal of Public Health, 55(2), 123–132.
Bested, A.C., Logan, A.C., and Selhub, E.M. (2013). Intestinal microbiota, probiotics and mental
health: from Metchnikoff to modern advances: part III—convergence toward clinical trials. Gut
Pathogens, 5(1), 4.
Blas, E., Sommerfeld, J., and Kurup, A.S. (2011). Social Determinants Approaches to Public Health.
Geneva: World Health Organization.
Bowler, D.E., Buyung-Ali, L.M., Knight, T.M., and Pullin, A.S. (2010). A systematic review of
evidence for the added benefits to health of exposure to natural environments. BMC Public Health,
10(456), 1–10.
Butterworth, R.F. (2010). Metal toxicity, liver disease and neurodegeneration. Neurotoxicity Research,
18(1), 100–105.
Cabrera, L.Y. (2015). Rethinking Human Enhancement. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Cabrera, L.Y., Tesluk, J., Chakraborti, M., Matthews, R., and Illes, J. (2016). Brain matters: from
environmental ethics to environmental neuroethics. Environmental Health, 15(20), 1–5.
Calderon-Garcidueñas, L., Azzarelli, B., Acuna, H., et al. (2002). Air pollution and brain damage.
Toxicologic Pathology, 30(3), 372–389.
Calderon-Garcidueñas, L., Reed, W., Maronpot, R.R., et al. (2004). Brain inflammation and
Alzheimer’s-like pathology in individuals exposed to severe air pollution. Toxicologic Pathology,
32(6), 650–658.
Calderon-Garcidueñas, L., Mora-Tiscareño, A., Ontiveros, E., et al. (2008). Air pollution, cognitive
deficits and brain abnormalities: a pilot study with children and dogs. Brain and Cognition, 68(2),
117–127.
49
References 449
Canadian Environmental Health Atlas (2014, November 11). Little Things Matter: The Impact of
Toxins on the Developing Brain. [Online video.] https://youtu.be/E6KoMAbz1Bw [accessed January
29, 2016].
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (2015). Developmental Disabilities. Available from: http://
www.cdc.gov/ncbddd/developmentaldisabilities/index.html [accessed January 29, 2016].
Chen, F.S., Kumsta, R., von Dawans, B., Monakhov, M., Ebstein, R.P., and Heinrichs, M. (2011).
Common oxytocin receptor gene (OXTR) polymorphism and social support interact to reduce
stress in humans. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America,
108(50), 19937–19942.
Colborn, T., Kwiatkowski, C., Schultz, K., and Bachran, M. (2011). Natural gas operations from a
public health perspective. Human and Ecological Risk Assessment: An International Journal, 17(5),
1039–1056.
Commission on Social Determinants of Health (2008). Closing the Gap in a Generation: Health
Equity Through Action on the Social Determinants of Health. Geneva: World Health Organization.
Cranor, C. (2011). Legally Poisoned: How the Law Puts Us at Risk from Toxicants. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Crews, D. (2010). Epigenetics, brain, behavior, and the environment. Hormones, 9(1), 41–50.
Cumes, D. (1998). Nature as medicine: the healing power of the wilderness. Alternative Therapies in
Health and Medicine Journal, 4(2), 1–8.
Cunsolo Willox, A., Harper, S.L., Ford, J.D., et al. (2013). Climate change and mental health: an
exploratory case study from Rigolet, Nunatsiavut, Canada. Climatic Change, 121(2), 255–270.
Cutter, S.L., Boruff, B.J., and Shirley, W.L. (2003). Social vulnerability to environmental hazards. Social
Science Quarterly, 84, 1–20.
Dakeishi, M., Murata, K., and Grandjean, P. (2006). Long-term consequences of arsenic poisoning
during infancy due to contaminated milk powder. Environmental Health, 5(31), 1–7.
Daniels, N. (2008). Just Health. New York: Cambridge University Press.
de Burbure, C., Buchet, J.P., Leroyer, A., et al. (2006). Renal and neurologic effects of cadmium, lead,
mercury, and arsenic in children: evidence of early effects and multiple interactions at environmental
exposure levels. Environmental Health Perspectives, 114(4), 584–590.
Debes, F., Budtz-Jørgensen, E., Weihe, P., White, R.F., and Grandjean, P. (2006). Impact of prenatal
methylmercury exposure on neurobehavioral function at age 14 years. Neurotoxicology and
Teratology, 28(3), 363–375.
Dick, F.D. (2006). Solvent neurotoxicity. Occupational and Environmental Medicine, 63(3), 221–226.
Elbaz, A., Clavel, J., Rathouz, P.J., et al. (2009). Professional exposure to pesticides and Parkinson
disease. Annals of Neurology, 66(4), 494–504.
Elliott, K.C. (2011). Is a Little Pollution Good for You?: Incorporating Societal Values in Environmental
Research. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Elliott, K.C. (2013). Financial conflicts of interest and criteria for research credibility. Erkenntnis,
79(S5), 917–937.
Field, R.A., Soltis, J., and Murphy, S. (2014). Air quality concerns of unconventional oil and natural gas
production. Environmental Science: Processes & Impacts, 16(5), 954–969.
Fritze, J.G., Blashki, G.A., Burke, S., and Wiseman, J. (2008). Hope, despair and
transformation: climate change and the promotion of mental health and wellbeing. International
Journal of Mental Health Systems, 2(1), 13.
Frumkin, H. (2001). Beyond toxicity: human health and the natural environment. American Journal of
Preventive Medicine, 20(3), 234–240.
Gay, J., Shepherd, O., Thyden, M., and Whitman, M. (2010). The Health Effects of Oil
Contamination: A Compilation of Research. Worcester, MA: Worcester Polytechnic Institute.
450
References 451
Illes, J., Davidson, J., and Matthews, R. (2014). Environmental neuroethics: changing the
environment –changing the brain. Recommendations submitted to the Presidential Commission
for the Study of Bioethical Issues. Journal of Law and the Biosciences, 1(2), 221–223.
Ingold, T. (2000). The Perception of the Environment. London: Psychology Press.
Jacobson, J.L. and Jacobson, S.W. (2003). Prenatal exposure to polychlorinated biphenyls and attention
at school age. Journal of Pediatrics, 143(6), 780–788.
Joseph, J.A., Shukitt-Hale, B., and Lau, F.C. (2007). Fruit polyphenols and their effects on neuronal
signaling and behavior in senescence. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences of the United
States of America, 1100(1), 470–485.
Kamel, F. and Hoppin, J.A. (2004). Association of pesticide exposure with neurologic dysfunction and
disease. Environmental Health Perspectives, 112(9), 950–958.
Kelly, B.D., O'Callaghan, E., Waddington, J.L., et al. (2010). Schizophrenia and the city: a review of
literature and prospective study of psychosis and urbanicity in Ireland. Schizophrenia Research,
116(1), 75–89.
Kerti, L. Witte, A.V., Winkler, A., Grittner, U., Rujescu, D., and Flöel, A. (2013). Higher glucose levels
associated with lower memory and reduced hippocampal microstructure. Neurology, 81, 1746–1752.
Kirmayer, L.J. and Valaskakis, G.G. (2008). Healing Traditions. Vancouver, BC: UBC Press.
Korrick, S.A. and Sagiv, S.K. (2008). Polychlorinated biphenyls, organochlorine pesticides and
neurodevelopment. Current Opinion in Pediatrics, 20(2), 198–204.
Kramer, A.F., Erickson, K.I., and Colcome, S.J. (2006). Exercise, cognition, and the aging brain. Journal
of Applied Physiology, 101, 1237–1242.
Lai, J.S., Hiles, S., Bisquera, A., et al. (2014). A systematic review and meta-analysis of dietary patterns
and depression in community-dwelling adults. American Journal of Clinical Nutrition, 99(1),
181–197.
Landrigan, P.J., Sonawane, B., Butler, R.N., Trasande, L., Callan, R., Droller, D. (2005). Early
environmental origins of neurodegenerative disease in later life. Environmental Health Perspectives,
113(9), 1230–1233.
Lanphear, B.P., Hornung, R., Khoury, J., et al. (2005). Low-level environmental lead exposure and
children’s intellectual function: an international pooled analysis. Environmental Health Perspectives,
113(7), 894–899.
Lederbogen, F., Kirsch, P., Haddad, L., et al. (2011). City living and urban upbringing affect neural
social stress processing in humans. Nature, 474(7352), 498–501.
Lee, C. (2002). Environmental justice: building a unified vision of health and the environment.
Environmental Health Perspectives, 110, 141–144.
Levy, N. (2012). Ecological engineering: reshaping our environments to achieve our goals. Philosophy &
Technology, 25(4), 589–604.
Lim, Y.-H., Kim, H., Kim, J.H., et al. (2012). Air pollution and symptoms of depression in elderly
adults. Environmental Health Perspectives, 120(7), 1023–1028.
Lucchini, R.G., Guazzetti, S., Zoni S., et al. (2014). Neurofunctional dopaminergic impairment in
elderly after lifetime exposure to manganese. NeuroToxicology, 45, 309–317.
Luna, F. (2009). Elucidating the concept of vulnerability: layers not labels. International Journal of
Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 2(1), 121–139.
Maas, J. (2006). Green space, urbanity, and health: how strong is the relation? Journal of Epidemiology &
Community Health, 60(7), 587–592.
Marcus, S. (2002). Neuroethics: Mapping the Field. San Francisco, CA: Dana Press.
Marmot, M. (2005). Social determinants of health inequalities. The Lancet, 365(9464), 1099–1104.
Matuszek, S. (2010). Animal-facilitated therapy in various patient populations. Holistic Nursing Practice,
24(4), 187–203.
452
Miodovnik, A. (2011). Environment neurotoxicants and developing brain. Mount Sinai Journal of
Medicine, 78, 58–77.
Mora, F., Segovia, G. and del Arco, A. (2007). Aging, plasticity and environmental
enrichment: structural changes and neurotransmitter dynamics in several areas of the brain. Brain
Research Reviews, 55(1), 78–88.
Needleman, H.L., Gunnoe, C., Leviton, A., et al. (1979). Deficits in psychologic and classroom
performance of children with elevated dentine lead levels. New England Journal of Medicine,
300(13), 689–695.
Needleman, H.L., Schell, A., Bellinger, D., Leviton, A., and Allred, E.N. (1990). The long-term effects
of exposure to low doses of lead in childhood. An 11-year follow-up report. New England Journal of
Medicine, 322(2), 83–88.
NEPA (1969). The National Environmental Policy Act. Available from: https://ceq.doe.gov/laws_and_
executive_orders/the_nepa_statute.html [accessed March 5, 2016].
Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A. (1993). The Quality of Life. Gloucestershire: Peterson’s.
O’Neil, A., Quirk, S.E., Housden, S., et al. (2014). Relationship between diet and mental health in
children and adolescents: a systematic review. American Journal of Public Health, 104, e31–e42.
O’Rourke, D. and Connolly, S. (2003). Just oil? The distribution of environmental and social impacts of
oil production and consumption. Annual Review of Environment and Resources, 28(1), 587–617.
Opler, M.G.A., Buka, S.L., Groeger, J., et al. (2008). Prenatal exposure to lead, δ-aminolevulinic acid,
and schizophrenia: further evidence. Environmental Health Perspectives, 116(11), 1586–1590.
Oreskes, N. and Conway, E.M. (2010). Merchants of Doubt. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing USA.
Parfit, D. (1971). Personal identity. The Philosophical Review, 80, 3–27.
Patterson, C.C. (1965). Contaminated and natural lead environments of man. Archives of Environmental
Health, 11, 344–360.
Peen, J., Schoevers, R.A., Beekman, A.T., and Dekker, J. (2010). The current status of urban-rural
differences in psychiatric disorders. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 121(2), 84–93.
Pereira, A.C., Huddleston, D.E., Brickman, A.M., et al. (2007). An in vivo correlate of exercise-induced
neurogenesis in the adult dentate gyrus. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the
United States of America, 104(13), 5638–5643.
Perrin, M., Opler, M.G., Harlap, S., et al. (2007). Tetrachloroethylene exposure and risk of
schizophrenia: offspring of dry cleaners in a population birth cohort, preliminary findings.
Schizophrenia Research, 90(1–3), 251–254.
Perry, S.L. (2012). Development, land use, and collective trauma: the Marcellus shale gas boom in rural
Pennsylvania. Culture, Agriculture, Food and Environment, 34(1), 81–92.
Peters, A., Veronesi, B., Calderón-Garcidueñas, L., et al. (2006). Translocation and potential
neurological effects of fine and ultrafine particles a critical update. Particle and Fibre Toxicology,
3(1), 1–13.
Petronis, A. and Mill, J. (2011). Brain, Behavior and Epigenetics. New York: Springer.
Potter, V.R. (1988). Global Bioethics. East Lansing, MI: MSU Press.
Prüss-Üstün, A. and Corvalán, C. (2006). Preventing Disease Through Healthy Environments.
Geneva: World Health Organization.
Psaltopoulou, T., Sergentanis, T.N., Panagiotakos, D.B., Sergentanis, I.N., Kosti, R., and Scarmeas, N.
(2013). Mediterranean diet, stroke, cognitive impairment, and depression: a meta-analysis. Annals of
Neurology, 74(4), 580–591.
Public Health Agency of Canada (2011). What determines health? Public Health Agency of Canada,
1–4. Available from: http://www.phac-aspc.gc.ca/ph-sp/determinants/index-eng.php [accessed
January 18, 2016].
453
References 453
Rabinowitz, P.M., Slizovskiy, I.B., Lamers, V., et al. (2015). Proximity to natural gas wells and reported
health status: results of a household survey in Washington County, Pennsylvania. Environmental
Health Perspectives, 123(1), 21–26.
Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Raz, R., Roberts, A.L., Lyall, K., et al. (2014). Autism spectrum disorder and particulate matter air
pollution before, during, and after pregnancy: a nested case–control analysis within the nurses’
health study II cohort. Environmental Health Perspectives, 123(3), 264–270.
Resnik, D.B. (2009). Human health and the environment: in harmony or in conflict? Health Care
Analysis, 17(3), 261–276.
Resnik, D.B. (2012). Environmental Health Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Resnik, D.B. and Portier, C.J. (2008). Environment and Health. Garrison, NY: The Hastings Center.
Roberts, E.M., English, P.B., Grether, J.K., Windham, G.C., Somberg, L., and Wolff, C. (2007).
Maternal residence near agricultural pesticide applications and autism spectrum disorders among
children in the California central valley. Environmental Health Perspectives, 115, 1482–1489.
Rodríguez-Barranco, M., Lacasaña, M., Gil, F., et al. (2014). Environmental research. Environmental
Research, 134(C), 66–73.
Rosado, J.L., Ronquillo, D., Kordas, K., et al. (2007). Arsenic exposure and cognitive performance in
Mexican schoolchildren. Environmental Health Perspectives, 115(9), 1371–1375.
Sagoff, M. (2008). Zuckerman’s dilemma a plea for environmental ethics. Hastings Center Report,
21, 32–40.
Schwartz, B.S., Stewart, W.F., Bolla, K.I., et al. (2000). Past adult lead exposure is associated with
longitudinal decline in cognitive function. Neurology, 55, 1144–1150.
Seeman, T.E. and McEwen, B.S. (1996). Impact of social environment characteristics on
neuroendocrine regulation. Psychosomatic Medicine, 58, 459–471.
Shelton, J.F., Geraghty, E.M., Tancredi, D.J., et al. (2014). Neurodevelopmental disorders and prenatal
residential proximity to agricultural pesticides: the CHARGE study. Environmental Health
Perspectives, 122, 1103–1109.
Shih, R.A., Hu, H., Weisskopf, M.G., and Schwartz, B.S. (2007). Cumulative lead dose and cognitive
function in adults: a review of studies that measured both blood lead and bone lead. Environmental
Health Perspectives, 115(3), 483–492.
Shonkoff, J.P. (2012). Leveraging the biology of adversity to address the roots of disparities in health
and development. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America,
109(Suppl. 2), 17302–17307.
Shrader-Frechette, K.S. (2006). Environmental Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Slimak, M.W. and Dietz, T. (2006). Personal values, beliefs, and ecological risk perception. Risk
Analysis, 26(6), 1689–1705.
Slote, M. (2007). The Ethics of Care and Empathy. New York: Routledge.
Small, G. and Vorgan, G. (2008). iBrain. New York: Harper Collins.
Smith, K.R., Corvalan, C.F., and Kjellstrom, T. (1999). How much global ill health is attributable to
environmental factors? Epidemiology, 10(5), 573–584.
Stedman, R.C., Jacquet, J.B., and Filteau, M.R. (2012). Marcellus shale gas development and new
boomtown research: wiews of New York and Pennsylvania residents. Environmental Practice, 14,
382–393.
Steel, D. (2014). Philosophy and the Precautionary Principle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stewart, P.W., Lonky, E., Reihman, J., et al. (2008). The relationship between prenatal PCB exposure
and intelligence (IQ) in 9-year-old children. Environmental Health Perspectives, 116(10), 1416–1422.
45
Tang, C.Y., Carpenter, D.M., Eaves, E.L., et al. (2011). Occupational solvent exposure and brain
function: an fMRI study. Environmental Health Perspectives, 119(7), 908–913.
Teicher, M.H. and Samson, J.A. (2013). Childhood maltreatment and psychopathology: a case for
ecophenotypic variants as clinically and neurobiologically distinct subtypes. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 170, 1114–1133.
Tost, H., Champagne, F.A. and Meyer-Lindenberg, A. (2015). Environmental influence in the brain,
human welfare and mental health. Nature Neuroscience, 18(10), 1421–1431.
Tsai, S.-Y., Chou, H.Y., The, H.W., Chen, C.M., and Chen, C.J. (2003). The effects of chronic
arsenic exposure from drinking water on the neurobehavioral development in adolescence.
NeuroToxicology, 24(4–5), 747–753.
United Nations Environment Programme (1972). Report of the United Nations Conference on the
Human Environment. Available from: http://www.unep.org/Documents.multilingual/Default.asp?D
ocumentID=97&ArticleID=150 [accessed March 5, 2016].
van Os, J., Kenis, G., and Rutten, B.P.F. (2010). The environment and schizophrenia. Nature, 468(7321),
203–212.
van Praag, H., Kempermann, G., and Gage, F.H., 2000. Neural consequences of environmental
enrichment. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 1(3), 191–198.
Villanueva, C.M., Kogevinas, M., Cordier, S., et al. (2013). Assessing exposure and health consequences
of chemicals in drinking water: current state of knowledge and research needs. Environmental
Health Perspectives, 122, 213–221.
Vukic, A., Gregory, D., Martin-Misener, R., and Etowa, J. (2011). Aboriginal and Western conceptions
of mental health and illness. Pimatisiwin: A Journal of Aboriginal & Indigenous Community Health,
9(1), 65–86.
Watson, S. (2008, October 8). How Eco-anxiety Works. Available from: http://science.howstuffworks.
com/environmental/green-science/eco-anxiety.htm [accessed January 23, 2015].
Weisskopf, M.G., Hu, H., Sparrow, D., Lenkinski, R.E., and Wright, R.O. (2007). Proton magnetic
resonance spectroscopic evidence of glial effects of cumulative lead exposure in the adult human
hippocampus. Environmental Health Perspectives, 115(4), 519–523.
White, A.M., Philogene, G.S., Fine, L., and Sinha, S. (2009). Social support and self-reported health
status of older adults in the United States. American Journal of Public Health, 99(10), 1872–1878.
Windham, G.C., Zhang, L., Gunier, R., Croen, L.A., and Grether, J.K. (2006). Autism spectrum
disorders in relation to distribution of hazardous air pollutants in the San Francisco Bay area.
Environmental Health Perspectives, 114(9), 1438–1444.
Woo, C.C. and Leon, M. (2013). Environmental enrichment as an effective treatment for autism: a
randomized controlled trial. Behavioral Neuroscience, 127(4), 487–497.
Wright, R.O., Amarasiriwardena, C., Woolf, A.D., Jim, R., and Bellinger, D.C. (2006).
Neuropsychological correlates of hair arsenic, manganese, and cadmium levels in school-age
children residing near a hazardous waste site. NeuroToxicology, 27(2), 210–216.
45
Chapter 23
It is for these reasons that the experience of First Nations has become an important
research focus. Environmental change and the development of natural resources have
important implications for the neurological and mental health of both First Nations and
for indigenous people throughout Canada and the rest of the world. While we draw on
findings from other Canadian aboriginal populations, we place First Nations at the center
of this chapter with the understanding that the concerns they share with other popula-
tions are bound together by the global scope of environmental change that is occurring,
and by common experiences under the institutions of Western science and medicine that
have spread their influence across so much of the planet.
In this chapter, we examine past research that intersects studies of the environment,
neurological and mental health, and First Nations experience. We begin with an examina-
tion of vulnerability to diseases of the brain and to environmental change in First Nations
people, and situate these issues within the broader scope of change occurring in their
societies. We examine some of the challenges that exist in conducting research on neu-
rological and mental health with First Nations people, and identify examples of recent
research that has helped create positive relationships between neurological researchers
and First Nations people. We then explore how the corresponding progressions in classi-
cal Western thought and the study of brain and environment contrast with First Nations’
paths of development. We use this analysis to confront the challenges inherent to the con-
vergence of contrasting systems of knowledge, and we address the role that neuroethics
can play in bringing First Nations and Western institutions of science together in protect-
ing the health of the brain.2
This chapter focuses upon First Nations people, and their distinct experiences related to
the environment and brain health. We remain cognizant of the related but distinct experi-
ences of Metis and Inuit peoples in Canada, as well as aboriginal people in other regions.
We acknowledge the need for exploration of the specific issues related to the intersections
between their respective experiences and environmental neuroethics. We also recognize
the diversity of experiences and perspectives that exists both between different groups of
aboriginal people and among the 630 recognized First Nations governments and bands
that are located across Canada.
smell, and taste), which send signals to which the brain responds, and adapts, and which
it ultimately translates into information and knowledge related to a person’s surroundings
and circumstances.
Both perceptions of the environment, and understandings of the brain in relation to
human health and agency, are mediated through cultural frames of reference that define
the boundary between the self and the natural environment, and that shape individuals’
interactions with the environment. These frames of reference include systems of thought
that situate humans as separate from nature (e.g., in traditional Western worldviews) and
perspectives that see the environment and the self as intimately interconnected (such as
traditional First Nations worldviews). Our most fundamental understandings of the rela-
tionship between environment and the brain are thus rooted in culturally situated systems
of knowledge, and are shaped and reshaped through cumulative experience.
Thus, efforts to understand the impact of environmental factors on neurological and
mental health among First Nations people must go beyond a mere acknowledgment of
differences in vulnerability, perspectives, and experiences. Indeed, the fulsome investiga-
tion of this topic involves a broader endeavor. Thoughtful research must reach beyond
the development of “culturally sensitive” programs and regulatory-based research eth-
ics. Between the social dimensions of culture that link humans to the environment, and
the neurological dimensions of environmental impacts on the central nervous system,
is a broad space that spans biological, social, cultural, psychological, and genetic link-
ages between the brain and the environment. As a multidisciplinary field that examines
environmental impacts on brain and mental health, environmental neuroethics seeks to
develop a framework for understanding how new forms of knowledge are produced from
the interaction between Western scientific worldviews and those of First Nations and
other indigenous people.
disorders such as cerebral palsy and autism that are disproportionately prevalent among
other North American aboriginal people remain understudied among Canadian popula-
tions (Di Pietro and Illes 2014).
The need for a better understanding of the environmental impact on First Nations peo-
ple’s neurological and mental health is made more pressing by human-induced global
climate change and ongoing natural resource development activities affecting territories
of First Nations. Across Canada, First Nations are engaged in battles to assert control
over the environment, and to deal with the impact of environmental change on their
brains, bodies, and communities. In the north, for example, the Mikisew Cree and the
Athabasca Chipewyan are confronting ongoing and unknown future health impacts
resulting from oil and gas development in the Albertan tar sands projects (Kelly et al.
2009, 2010; Timoney & Lee 2009; Scarlett et al. 2012). In the east, the Grassy Narrows
and Whitedog First Nations continue to fight the Canadian Government for the release
of information and settlements related to mercury contamination that has negatively
affected their neurological health over the past 70 years (Harada et al. 2011; McQuigge
2012; Crowe 2014). In the west, numerous First Nations are working to understand the
potential future impacts of unconventional natural gas production (known as fracking).
This includes the extraction of gas using hydraulic fracturing processes in the territories
of the Treaty Six First Nations, and the compression and shipment of liquid natural gas
through the territories of the Tsimshian, Haisla, and Squamish First Nations, among oth-
ers (Goodine 2011; Benusic 2013; Jang 2015; Nikiforuk 2015).
These events are occurring within a broader context of change that includes historic
transformation of First Nations traditional territories into industrialized landscapes, and
the more dynamic and unpredictable impacts of global climate change. First Nations
have experienced a more rapid and disruptive trajectory of change than other parts of
the Canadian population with respect to the ways that environmental change has affected
their health and their communities. The gradual industrialization of Western society that
proceeded in step with the evolution of medical science and social adaptation has been
compressed into a short and violent reorganization of life for First Nations people (Barron
1984; Tennant 1990; Young 1994; Furniss 1999; Yazzie 2000). Over the past four centuries
of colonization, First Nations have witnessed the near extinction and recovery of their
population, and the rise of resource industries that have reshaped the land and waters
around them. Throughout this period, First Nations social needs and their traditional
methods of health and healing have been marginalized by Western systems of science,
education, and political control.
For some First Nations, these disruptions have been concentrated into a mere century
of experience, with current generations bearing the direct impact of their lands being
logged, mined, or flooded, and their communities forcibly relocated and reorganized by
the state.3 As these events have unfolded, many First Nations have been cut off from a life
based on harvesting and hunting across vast territories, and forced into life within state-
built modular housing accompanied by reliance upon limited healthcare services and
unfamiliar Western food systems (Gladstone 1953; Tennant 1990; Parsons & Prest 2003;
459
Woolford & Thomas 2011). However, the central focus for this discussion is the implica-
tion that these radical transformations of environment and social organization hold for
the neurological and mental health of First Nations people. Given the persisting deficits in
the health of First Nations people, the need for research on the impact of environmental
change on their brain and mental health has never been higher; yet significant obstacles
remain to be overcome in creating new knowledge in this field.
2013b; Bourque & Willox 2014). The psychological distress experienced as a result of
being deprived of the comfort derived from contact with one’s native environment has
been described as solastalgia (Albrecht et al. 2007).5 While sharing a basis with nostalgia
in the role of sensations of one’s surroundings, solastalgia draws a focus on the role the
environment plays in calming the mind, thus framing responses to drastic changes in the
environment as a form of psychoterratic illnesses that can only be understood with refer-
ence to both environmental and psychological factors (Albrecht et al. 2007).6
Researchers working closely with Inuit people found the mental distress brought about
by environmental change runs deeper than affective states, and is tied to changes in cog-
nition and thinking. Willox and colleagues describe the ecological affect as a set of “prag-
matic and site-specific tracing of infinitely complex ecological arrangements” (Willox
et al. 2013a, p.17). These comprise patterns of thinking and feeling that shape everyday
behaviors, recognition, and information processing that support human interactions with
the environment. Emotions, rather than merely an affective state, embody a response to
environmental stimuli that acts as a necessary and integral form of cognition for guiding
instrumental and social behaviors among Inuit people such as navigation and dietary
decision-making (Willox et al. 2013a). These intimate ties between environment and cog-
nition reveal the blurring of lines between human and nature and between environment
and the mind.
First Nations have been asserting the negative impacts of environmental change on
their lives long before the most recent acknowledgments or discoveries of environmental
impacts on neurological and mental health.7 Meanwhile, researchers continue to work
to understand the linkages between what is classified as affective experience and neuro-
logical health. There are many pieces to the puzzle that defines environmental impacts
on neurological and mental health, but there is an ongoing lack of definitive cause-and-
effect findings to bind these pieces together in a cohesive body of knowledge. However, if
one accepts the premise that the neurological and mental health of First Nations people
has historically been supported by a specific set of physiological, cultural, and cognitive
relationships with the environment, then it stands to reason that upon the reshaping of
the environment, these relationships will be disrupted and negative impacts to brain and
mental health could follow.
research on HIV without permission from the Nuu-chah-nulth people who participated
in the original study (Wiwchar 2004). The same researcher later used the genetic materials
in published research about human migration that contradicted the Nuu-Chah-Nulth’s
historical accounts, causing insult to the band and introducing theories that undermined
their historical claims to their territories. This case has been cited in the fields of phar-
macogenetics, sexual wellness, and genetic ancestry as part of the historical mistrust that
must be overcome by researchers seeking to develop relationships with First Nations pop-
ulations (Lee et al. 2009; Devries & Free 2010; Boyer B.B. et al. 2011).
In other cases, research has been criticized for stigmatizing and attaching essential-
ist judgments to First Nations populations. For example, the thrifty gene hypothesis
attempted to link the high incidence of diabetes among First Nations in Manitoba to
genetic predispositions among hunter-gatherer populations that equipped them to sur-
vive periods of hardship through retention of nutrients, but which resulted in maladap-
tive weight problems under modern Western diets. Like the warrior gene hypothesis
that sought to link risk-taking behavior among Maori people to genetic variants that
affect aggressive behavior, the thrifty gene hypothesis has been criticized for failing to
adequately consider the disruptive impacts of colonization and the social and material
disadvantages suffered by aboriginal people under Western institutions (Abraham 2011;
Gillett & Tamatea 2012).
Even in cases where researchers are quite deliberate about approaching environmental
health issues without imposing value judgments upon the study population, First Nations
can be negatively impacted by the results. For example, research identifying the neuro-
logical health risks of consuming seafood contaminated with methylmercury and other
chemicals can have negative consequences for First Nations. Proof of contamination can
weaken First Nations people’s relationships with the fisheries that form a critical basis
of their culture and identity, and encourage increased reliance upon less healthy dietary
choices in areas where food alternatives are scarce (Wiseman & Gobas 2002; Gilbertson
& Carpenter 2004). The potential consequences of such research place scientific indica-
tors of health at odds with cultural values, and raises ethical questions about the nature of
research that must be explored before analysis even begins.
defining aboriginal health that centers on the practices that comprise positive health and
wellness, and the storytelling techniques that are used to promote and define the wellness
of community members (Hodge et al. 2002).8 Indeed, to bring the study of the brain into
the experience of First Nations people, efforts are needed to understand the dimensions
of their culture and relationships with the environment that define positive neurological
and mental health.
Researchers based in Edmonton, Alberta, focused upon First Nations practices that
support healthy brains in their study of the Cree First Nations’ traditional child-rearing
practices and their impacts on neurological development (Pazderka et al. 2014). The
researchers found correspondence between findings in neuroscience and Cree practices
related to pre-birth nutrition, feeding, and handling of newborns. For example, they
found that Cree practices of carrying infants in traditional leather pouches close to the
body reflects recent findings in Western sciences that indicate such practices support
maternal attachment and social integration, and improve the capacity for handling stress
(Anderson G.C. et al. 2003; Feldman 2011; Pazderka et al. 2014). Such findings suggest
that although First Nations may not commonly speak the technical language of neurology
and medical science in their everyday lives, they have millennia of lived experience that
informs the practices they follow and the relationships they hold with the environment in
order to support the health of their brains.
Engaging First Nations on their own terms in matters of neurological and mental health
requires moving beyond the limits of Western medical science and characterizations of
the brain as merely an infinitely complex system of tissues, chemical reactions, electri-
cal signals, and psychological processes. Native American geneticist Dr. Frank Dukapoo
explains that biological materials that scientists view as merely tissue and personal prop-
erty may be viewed by First Nations as the sacred essence of a person (Dukapoo in Arbour
& Cook 2006, p.155).9 This not only prompts important ethical considerations in rela-
tion to the handling and stewardship of bodily materials (Arbour & Cook 2006; Gillett
& McKergow 2007), but also suggests that those who conduct research on the brain with
First Nations and other indigenous people must question the very nature of that which
they seek to study.
Health researchers working in Australia followed an innovative path to bring studies of
neurological health into alignment with Aboriginal concepts of the brain.10 Rather than
focusing on the physiology of the brain or functioning of the central nervous system,
researchers were able to advance their studies and serve Aborigine needs by focusing on
representations of the brain according to its role in social and cultural processes (D’Abbs
& MacLean 2000). A team of psychologists and psychiatrists collaborated with Aboriginal
artists to create pictures of the brain that depicted different levels of cultural engagement
focusing on stories, family, country, and body. These dimensions corresponded with dis-
tinct dimensions of functional cognition, including memory, socialization, identity, and
motor function (Petrol Link-up 1994; Cohen & Stemmer 2011). The approach assisted in
the development of resources to educate Aborigines about the impacts of specific drugs
on neurological health.
46
Recent research on early-onset familial Alzheimer’s disease with a northern First Nation
in British Columbia provided a similar example of how beneficial partnerships can be
formed by attending to the distinct needs of the study population and recognizing the
complex relationship between traditional beliefs and medical science. Researchers facili-
tated the creation of a community advisory group, and engaged in dialogue with com-
munity members to explore their concerns about the stigmatization of dementia and to
discuss the potential harms and benefits that may come from further examination of the
issue (Stevenson et al. 2013). This engagement assisted in drawing attention to the wider
range of ethical considerations, including concerns about their future ability to obtain
medical insurance, potential stigmatization of families and individuals, and delicate mat-
ters of consent related to determining who speaks for a community when disclosing the
existence of a health problem.
The work also yielded insight into the way that First Nations people integrate tradi-
tional beliefs and information gained through medical science into their understand-
ings of brain disease. Participants in the research drew simultaneously from medical
knowledge and traditional definitions of wellness to explain the illness, demonstrat-
ing the potential for different knowledge systems to converge with positive outcomes
(Cabrera et al. 2015). In turn, the researchers drew on these hybrid understandings to
create educational resources that combined the First Nations narrative and epidemio-
logical data to assist community members in identifying and managing the disease.11
These findings show how aboriginal and Western scientific worldviews can be united,
and that First Nations people need not choose between exclusively traditional and
scientific frames of reference. First Nations people do not reject medical science or
empirical inquiry; they simply do not privilege it above all other ways of knowing, and
seek to reconcile it with the traditional knowledge they have held since time immemo-
rial. Researchers who study issues related to the environment and neurological health
among First Nations must thus come to terms with their entry into a dynamic world
of information exchange within which knowledge is continually being created and
recreated.
Researchers must thus be prepared to discuss phenomena that may not otherwise enter
their field of examination, and be willing to alter their research designs to accommodate
dimensions that First Nations see as important. Definitions of both nature and medicine
must be expanded to embrace First Nations perspectives that include views of the body as
an integrated whole linked with its environment: “It [traditional medicine] looks at all of
you. … Non-traditional looks at that cut on your hand or that ankle you keep spraining,
whereas traditional medicine looks at the whole person” (First Nation Elder in interview
dealing with well-being).
Cajete explains that while Western scientific methods revolve around establishing objec-
tive views to determine “a factual blueprint of the world,” indigenous views emphasize
experience and locate the center of thought and cognition within the interconnectedness
of the body with the environment (Cajete 2000, pp.24–25). And, although the interaction
of body, mind, and environment may not be directly observable through common scien-
tific methods, Huntington reminds us that such experiences must nonetheless be taken
into account when examining the impact of environmental change on indigenous people
(Huntington in Krupnik & Jolly 2002, pp.xxii–xxiii).
The specifics of beliefs of First Nations people about the nature of the environment and
their own bodies and brains may vary from nation to nation and even family to family; the
epistemological foundations of indigenous knowledge systems are not based in central-
ized rational scientific authority, but instead within oral histories, traditional practices,
and ceremonies (Battiste 2002). In light of these considerations, research on environmen-
tal brain impacts with First Nations necessarily becomes a multidisciplinary endeavor
that draws from medical sciences, sociology, anthropology, and other potential contribut-
ing fields.
Beyond the considerations identified earlier in forming trusting relationships between
researchers and First Nations, there are numerous conceptual and methodological chal-
lenges inherent in this field of study. Clearly there are many concepts that defy opera-
tionalization within pure medical research models. For example, the unmeasurable
phenomena that comprise the spirit demands that qualitative inquiry form a central part
of any research effort. In turn, the ability to establish cause–effect relationships becomes
problematic when examining the way that environmental change affects the brain when
the focus shifts to a wider definition of what the brain and body encompass, and when
these parts of a person are viewed as being inseparable from the environment.
One of the most important considerations is that First Nations knowledge cannot be
treated in the same manner as other forms of knowledge, particularly scientific knowl-
edge. In this respect, traditional knowledge is not a currency that is exchanged within
the public domain, and is not subject to the same processes of scrutiny and revision that
characterize peer-reviewed scientific inquiry. Traditional knowledge is often bound in
stories passed down between generations as sacred or private learnings. Knowledge of
the environment and of medicine is often linked to the social and political structure of a
nation, and is interwoven in the bonds of clan and family that give shape to a First Nation
community. Researchers must recognize the importance of incorporating traditional
46
knowledge into their work, but at the same time must understand the local conventions
and customs that accompany engagement with this knowledge. Traditional medicine
does not exist independently as a solution that is introduced to an afflicted body. Instead
it is, like the body and the mind, part of a broader web of experience.
If you look at cultural, even the medicinal parts of Cedar you know? You may get traditional medi-
cine. It’s not just what you swallow or rub on you, because I think the traditional medicine also may
include that whole process of making yourself ready to even go get the bark. Because that’s part
of the healing. So, if you look at traditional healing it’s not just a medicinal sense, you know, it’s a
whole mindset or way of thinking, the healing part of it. (First Nation Elder in interview dealing
with issues of well-being)
First Nations beliefs about the environment and its relationship with health form the basis
of many studies, and several volumes of books would be required to provide a compre-
hensive summary of the respective intricacies found among the many existing nations.
The proliferation of research in this area indicates that Western science has at least begun
to recognize the importance of respecting and integrating First Nations knowledge
into studies of the environment and the brain. However, there remains the delicate and
complex matter of moving beyond acknowledgments of differences in perspectives, to
incorporating First Nations perspective into research models, and addressing the ethical
implications of the knowledge that is produced in these endeavors. That is, how do we
reconcile the belief systems of First Nations people with the normative foundations of
decision-making that lie at the core of neuroethics?
bioethical and moral issues, including those related to the human mind and the environ-
ment. Kant’s assertion of human autonomy continues to form an influential reference
point as scholars debate over the point at which the treatment of biological materials must
include consideration of the personhood of the materials, or how to weigh the auton-
omy of the person against that of the public when forming policies dealing with neuro-
logical enhancements (Racine 2010, pp.131–133; Barker & Beaufort 2013). The friction
between utilitarianism and the alternative methods of evaluating nature forms an endur-
ing point of conflict as society deliberates over issues such as the genetic modification of
food sources and the associated implications for human health (Faunce 2012). Questions
regarding the extent to which the state should enforce the duty of care have arisen when
the right to utilize traditional healing has been pitted against medical positions regarding
the best interests of the patient (McLaren 2015).12 These contemporary debates serve as
a reminder that normative ethics not only express particular frameworks of reason, but
also articulate responses to changes in the world around us and the evolution of society’s
relationship with the state and notions of the self. If we view Kantian deontology and utili-
tarian ethics along with their contemporary manifestations as part of a broader response
to change in society and the world around us, how then might we view the expression of
First Nations ethics? More specifically, how do we understand First Nations ethics in rela-
tion to complicated matters of neurological health as we confront the converging impli-
cations of advancing medical science and a changing environment? We must look more
closely not only at the different traditions from which Western and First Nations respec-
tive notions of ethics arise, but also the conditions within which they have come to be
expressed and defended.
When one seeks to identify the substance of what is referred to as First Nations ethics,
some of the most commonly encountered ideas are respect, balance, interconnectedness,
sustainability, reciprocity, community, and self-determination. Expressions of these ideas
are pervasive within literature that examines environmental and health issues related to
First Nations people (Browne 1995; Wilson 2003; McGregor 2004; Isaak & Marchessault
2008; King et al. 2009; Beckford et al. 2010; Jones et al. 2010). Of course, such values do
not comprise a clear body of normative thought as commonly recognized within Western
society, nor do they provide a clear means of determining how decisions should be made
in relation to issues of environmental impacts on brain and mental health. Indeed, when
one searches for a body of normative ethics within literature on First Nations people, there
is no common body of knowledge to be found among the diversity that comprises this
population. Certainly these concepts are not alien to Western society, and First Nations
are not alone in their valuation of these ideals or their application of these concepts to
ethical matters. However, the way in which these concepts are defined differently between
cultures, and the way in which these concepts have emerged as the primary expressions of
First Nations ethics provides important cues for engaging First Nations in discussions of
environmental impacts on neurological health.
For example, the impact of neurological conditions must be communicated in more
than physiological and cognitive terms. Discussing the impact of environmental change
468
on the brain needs to attend to the way symptoms may be understood as impacts on the
community. At the same time, the emphasis on community needs to be understood as an
effort to reassert the importance of the bonds within and between First Nations families
in response to the Western emphasis on personal autonomy and the individualization of
medical practices as a process that occurs between doctor and patient. Discussing neuro-
logical conditions, environmental change, and the relationships between these issues with
First Nations populations must also attend to the issue of balance. This not only includes
remaining open to different ideas of how balance exists among mind, body, spirit, and
nature, but also understanding the emphasis on balance as a response to Western systems
of human and environmental care that have disrupted First Nations lives.
It is self-determination which provides the most powerful compass point in this
endeavor. The ethics of First Nations are articulated within the context of the assertion
of their aboriginal rights. While the autonomy of the individual forms a central refer-
ence point in ethical debates regarding Western studies of neurological health, it is the
autonomy of each individual nation that is central to First Nations decision-making. First
Nations people deserve to be able to choose their own path as they address impacts on
their brains and bodies, and it is the internal and intimate pathways of decision-making
that occur within their communities, families, and histories that shape the normative
basis of their thought in regard to these matters. These positions are not always for outsid-
ers to know, and the ethical values that are articulated (e.g., balance, interconnectedness)
may only serve as course-corrections or a response to the dominant institutions of science
and health that surround them.
Like that of most other indigenous people, the First Nations experience is forever altered
by the impact of colonialism. When words such as interconnectedness and community
are cited as First Nations ethics, they arise not only as an expression of their ethical foun-
dations, but also as a response to the decisions that have shaped their current circum-
stances. These ethical compass points redirect scientific inquiry to alternative ontologies,
and different targets for study and analysis. Western researchers must remain aware of
how First Nations ethics are expressed in part as a response to the incursion of Western
thought into explaining their lives. Even assumptions of time must be suspended: the
ethic of interconnectedness implies that time may not be linear in their worldview, and
the future and the past remain interconnected. The choices made today may have impacts
on both the future and histories of a First Nation.
These ethical compass points direct researchers toward a broader appreciation of how
First Nations people experience and perceive environmental impacts on the brain. When
seeking guidance on decision-making related to the environment and the health of the
brain, one must be prepared to submit to each First Nation’s distinct flows of ethical pro-
cessing. This may or may not be made visible or shared, and it may vary from group to
group. Close collaboration is required with each individual nation along with a commit-
ment to developing relationships of trust before such knowledge may be shared. Moreover,
there is a need for intellectual flexibility, and a readiness to understand the process of
change First Nations are continuing to experience. Only in this manner can we build
469
bridges between the contrasting ontologies and normative ethics that define approaches
of First Nations and Western institutions to understanding environmental impacts on the
brain as a process of change.
Neuroethics represents a relatively recent shift in the way we consider the brain, and
environmental neuroethics constitutes a new direction in this field. These studies not only
embody advances in science, but also reflect changes in society’s concerns over our rela-
tionships with nature and the way it shapes our lives and our minds. We must not lose
sight of the ongoing changes within our societies that are shaping our ethical reason-
ing. In this sense, the West may have more to gain than First Nations in the bridging of
our respective foundations of knowledge. Over the past 50 years, Western society has
faced a reckoning over the impact of technology and industry on our planet, and we have
collectively struggled to develop normative positions with sufficient power to provoke
the changes necessary to protect our health and that of the environment we rely upon.
While we cannot and should not view First Nations through a romantic lens that casts
them nobly as one-with-the-land, we can benefit from observing the way that they inte-
grate sciences of neurology and the environment with their own understandings of the
brain as they articulate normative positions regarding these matters. The way forward
for environmental neuroethics is to view our engagement with First Nations as a process
of mutual learning, and the co-production of knowledge regarding environment–brain
relationships.
neuroethics acknowledges that studies with First Nations about environmental impacts
on the brain involve co-creation of knowledge that is equally applicable to both First
Nations and Western society; that our cultures and ways of viewing the world are indeed
distinct, but that they are also frequently parallel and driving toward problems of mutual
concern.
For Western scholars, the explicit emphasis on human–nature relationships within First
Nations population creates an object of study, defined by its seemingly stark contrast with
Western notions of separation between society and nature. In turn, this contrast provides
reason to pause and to reconsider the impact of environmental change on the brain and
ethics of environmental care for all. Through the past half century, during which Western
society has come to confront the impacts of environmental change on human health, the
focus has been primarily upon the body. The study of the environment has been shaped
around these concerns. As we confront impacts on the brain, we enter new territory in
our consideration of ethics related to the environment and our use of natural resources.
Notes
1. First Nations people, along with Inuit and Metis, comprise the groups referred to as aboriginal people
in Canada. Inuit include the aboriginal people in the northern and arctic regions of Canada, and Metis
include people with mixed origins that share First Nations and other (generally Western European)
ancestry. First Nations were formerly referred to as Indians, and while this term is still utilized in the
United States, the word Indian is no longer used in Canada to refer to aboriginal people.
2. The pronoun “we” is used extensively throughout this chapter, and its reference to Western society is
by design. Indeed, it identifies a specific audience for this chapter with which not all readers may iden-
tify. However, the use of “we” is done self-consciously by the authors in acknowledgment of the social
and cultural separation of First Nations from the society around them.
3. For many First Nations in British Columbia, for example, the wholesale industrialization of their
forests and the flooding of their traditional lands occurred largely throughout the 1940s to 1960s.
Examples include the Cheslatta and the Tsay Keh Dene, who were both displaced by large hydro-elec-
tric projects accompanied by the expansion of logging and mineral development in their territories.
4. Exceptions to this include severe central nervous system failure as a result of exposure to pollution
at an extreme level, such as the events witnessed in Bhopal, India following the release of toxic gasses
from a pesticide plant in 1984.
5. Solastalgia is taken from the words nostalgia and solace (Albrecht et al., 2007, p.96). Nostalgia, which
was classified as a diagnosable illness until the late nineteenth century, is linked to the attachment of
smells, tastes, and sounds to previous locational and geographic contexts (Hirsch 1992).
6. Albrecht (2011, 2012) defines psychoterratic illnesses as earth-based (terra) mental (psyche) health
states or conditions that are caused by disruption of the conditions that shape people’s feelings and
emotions about nature and space.
7. First Nations have long expressed resistance to colonial impacts on their lands, but it is only in the past
half-century that their voices have received proper legal recognition. Between 1927 and 1950, First
Nations faced legal bans on their ability to mount protests latter half of the twentieth century. Between
1951 and 2000, there were an estimated 616 acts of Aboriginal protest in Canada (Clairmont & Potts
2006, p.20).
8. The term American Indian is the accepted terminology for indigenous people in the United States.
471
References 471
9. Indeed, it should be acknowledged that the infusion of the body with some intangible dimension of
spirit is not exclusive to First Nations. As Pinker (2003) points out, the idea of a physical body indel-
ibly imbued with sacred qualities or a predisposition toward a particular social nature also affects
Western systems of thought and religious belief.
10. The word “Aboriginal” is capitalized when referring to the indigenous people of Australia. The term
“Aborigine” is utilized when referring to a person of Aboriginal ancestry.
11. Resources included information folders that explained risk factors and described experiences
of community members affected by Alzheimer’s disease, and story books aimed at helping chil-
dren understand brain functions and the way that the disease affects community and family
relationships.
12. McLaren provides an account of a young First Nations girl from the Canadian province of Manitoba
who was supported by her parents in refusing potentially life-saving chemotherapy in favour of tra-
ditional healing methods.
References
Abraham, C. (2011, February 25). How the diabetes-linked ‘thrifty gene’ triumphed with prejudice over
proof. The Globe and Mail. Available from: http://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/national/how-
the-diabetes-linked-thrifty-gene-triumphed-with-prejudice-over-proof/article569423/?page=all
[accessed July 15, 2015].
Albrecht, G. (2011). Chronic environmental change: emerging “psychoterratic” syndromes.
In: Weissbecker, I. (Ed.) Climate Change and Human Well-Being, pp.43–56. New York: Springer.
Albrecht, G. (2012). Psychoterratic conditions in a scientific and technological world. In: Kahn, P.H.
and Hasbach, P. (Eds.) Ecopsychology: Science, Totems, and the Technological Species, pp.241–264.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Albrecht, G., Sartore, G.M., Connor, L., et al. (2007). Solastalgia: the distress caused by environmental
change. Australasian Psychiatry, 15(Suppl. 1), S95–S98.
Allan, B. and Smylie, J. (2015). First Peoples, Second Class Treatment: The Role of Racism in the Health
and Well-Being of Indigenous Peoples in Canada. Toronto, ON: The Wellesley Institute.
Anderson, G.C., Moore, E., Hepworth, J., and Bergman, N. (2003). Early skin-to-skin contact for
mothers and their healthy newborn infants. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews, 2, CD003519.
Anderson, R.B. (1999). Economic Development Among the Aboriginal peoples of Canada: The Hope for
the Future. Toronto, ON: Captus Press.
Arbour, L. and Cook, D. (2006). DNA on loan: issues to consider when carrying out genetic research
with aboriginal families and communities. Public Health Genomics, 9(3), 153–160.
Barker, R.A. and de Beaufort, I. (2013). Scientific and ethical issues related to stem cell research and
interventions in neurodegenerative disorders of the brain. Progress in Neurobiology, 110, 63–73.
Barron, F.L. (1984). A summary of federal Indian policy in the Canadian west, 1867–1984. Native
Studies Review, 1(1), 28–39.
Battiste, M. (2002). Indigenous Knowledge and Pedagogy in First Nations Education: A Literature Review
with Recommendations. Ottawa, ON: Apamuwek Institute.
Beckford, C.L., Jacobs, C., Williams, N., and Nahdee, R. (2010). Aboriginal environmental wisdom,
stewardship, and sustainability: lessons from the Walpole Island First Nations, Ontario, Canada. The
Journal of Environmental Education, 41(4), 239–248.
Benusic, M. (2013). Fracking in BC: a public health concern. British Columbia Medical Journal, 55(5),
238–239. Available from: http://www.bcmj.org/council-health-promotion/fracking-bc-public-
health-concern [accessed August 17, 2015].
472
Berry, H.L., Kelly, B.J., Hanigan, I.C., et al. (2008). Rural Mental Health Impacts of Climate Change.
Commissioned Report for the Garnaut Climate Change Review. Canberra, ACT: The Australian
National University.
Block, M.L. and Calderón-Garcidueñas, L. (2009). Air pollution: mechanisms of neuroinflammation
and CNS disease. Trends in Neurosciences, 32(9), 506–516.
Bourque, F. and Willox, AC. (2014). Climate change: the next challenge for public mental health?
International Review of Psychiatry, 26(4), 415–422.
Boyer, B.B., Dillard, D., Woodahl, E.L., Whitener, R., Thummel, K.E., and Burke, W. (2011).
Ethical issues in developing pharmacogenetic research partnerships with American Indigenous
communities. Clinical Pharmacology & Therapeutics, 89(3), 343–345.
Boyer, Y. (2004). First Nations, Métis and Inuit Health Care: The Crown’s Fiduciary Obligation.
[Discussion Paper Series in Aboriginal Health: Legal Issues, No. 2.] Ottawa, ON: National
Aboriginal Health Organization, Native Law Centre, University of Saskatchewan.
Browne, A.J. (1995). The meaning of respect: a First Nations perspective. Canadian Journal of Nursing
Research, 27, 95–109.
Cabrera, L.Y., Beattie, B.L., Dwosh, E., and Illes, J. (2015). Converging approaches to understanding
early onset familial Alzheimer disease: a First Nation study. SAGE Open Medicine, 3,
2050312115621766.
Cabrera, L.Y., Tesluk, J., Chakraborti, M., Matthews, R., and Illes, J. (2016). Brain matters: from
environmental ethics to environmental neuroethics. Environmental Health, 15(1), 20.
Cajete, G. (2000). Native Science: Natural Laws of Interdependence. Santa Fe, NM: Clear Light
Publishers.
Calderon-Garciduenas, L. Reed, W., Maronpot, R.R., et al. (2004). Brain inflammation and
Alzheimer’s-like pathology in individuals exposed to severe air pollution. Toxicologic Pathology,
32(6), 650–658.
Chepesiuk, R. (2009). Missing the dark: health effects of light pollution. Environmental Health
Perspectives, 117(1), A20–A27.
Clairmont, D.H. and Potts, J. (2006). For the Nonce: Policing and Aboriginal Occupations and
Protests. [A Background Paper Prepared for the Ipperwash Inquiry.] Ottawa, ON: Ipperwash
Inquiry.
Cohen, H. and Stemmer, B. (Eds.) (2011). Consciousness and Cognition: Fragments of Mind and Brain.
London: Academic Press.
Crowe, K. (2014, September 2). Grassy Narrows: why is Japan still studying the mercury poisoning
when Canada isn’t? CBC News. Available from: http://www.cbc.ca/news/health/grassy-narrows-
why-is-japan-still-studying-the-mercury-poisoning-when-canada-isn-t-1.2752360 [accessed August
17, 2016].
Csonka, Y. and Schweitzer, P. (2004). Societies and cultures: change and persistence. In: Einarsson,
N., Larsen, J.N., Nilsson, A., and Young, O.R. (Eds.) Arctic Human Development Report, pp.45–68.
Akureyri, Iceland: Stefansson Arctic Institute.
D'Abbs, P. and MacLean, S. (2000). Petrol Sniffing in Aboriginal Communities: A Review of Interventions.
Casuarina, NT: Cooperative Research Centre for Aboriginal and Tropical Health.
De Kluizenaar, Y., Passchier-Vermeer, W., and Miedema, H. (2001). Adverse Effects of Noise Exposure to
Health. Report prepared for the EC Project UNITE by TNO PG. Leiden, the Netherlands: Division
of Public Health.
Devries, K.M. and Free, C. (2010). “I told him not to use condoms”: masculinities, femininities and
sexual health of Aboriginal Canadian young people. Sociology of Health & Illness, 32(6), 827–842.
Di Pietro, N.C. and Illes, J. (2014). Disparities in Canadian indigenous health research on
neurodevelopmental disorders. Journal of Developmental & Behavioral Pediatrics, 35(1), 74–81.
473
References 473
El-Hayek, Y.H. (2007). Mercury contamination in Arctic Canada: possible implications for aboriginal
health. Journal of Developmental Disabilities, 13, 67–89.
Faunce, T. (2012). Governing planetary nanomedicine: environmental sustainability and a UNESCO
universal declaration on the bioethics and human rights of natural and artificial photosynthesis
(global solar fuels and foods). Nanoethics, 6(1), 15–27.
Feldman, R. (2011). Maternal touch and the developing infant. In: Hertenstein, M.J. and Weiss, S.J.
(Eds.) The Handbook of Touch: Neuroscience, Behavioral and Health Perspectives, pp.373–407.
New York: Springer Publishing Company.
Fritze, J.G., Blashki, G.A., Burke, S., and Wiseman, J. (2008). Hope, despair and
transformation: climate change and the promotion of mental health and wellbeing. International
Journal of Mental Health Systems, 2, 13.
Furniss, E. (1999). The Burden of History: Colonialism and the Frontier Myth in a Rural Canadian
Community. Vancouver, BC: UBC Press.
Gilbertson, M. and Carpenter, D.O. (2004). An ecosystem approach to the health effects of mercury in
the Great Lakes basin ecosystem. Environmental Research, 95(3), 240–246.
Gillett, G. and Tamatea, A.J. (2012). The warrior gene: epigenetic considerations. New Genetics and
Society, 31(1), 41–53.
Gillett, G. and McKergow, F. (2007). Genes, ownership, and indigenous reality. Social Science &
Medicine, 65(10), 2093–2104.
Gladstone, P. (1953). Native Indians and the fishing industry of British Columbia. The Canadian Journal
of Economics and Political Science/Revue canadienne d’Economique et de Science politique, 19(1),
20–34. Available from: http://www.jstor.org.ezproxy.library.ubc.ca/stable/10.2307/138471?origin=api
[accessed July 9, 2016].
Goodine, C. (2011, October). Fracking controversy: rethinking the low-carbon label for natural
gas. Canadian Geographic. Available from: https://www.canadiangeographic.ca/article/fracking-
controversy [accessed July 9, 2016].
Grandjean, P. and Herz, K.T. (2011). Methylmercury and brain development: imprecision and
underestimation of developmental neurotoxicity in humans. Mount Sinai Journal of Medicine, 78(1),
107–118.
Grandjean, P. and Landrigan, P. J. (2014). Neurobehavioural effects of developmental toxicity. Lancet
Neurology, 13(3), 330–338.
Haines, A., Kovats, R.S., Campbell-Lendrum, D., and Corvalán, C. (2006). Climate change and human
health: impacts, vulnerability and public health. Public Health, 120(7), 585–596.
Harada, M., Hanada, M., Jajiri, M., et al. (2011). Mercury pollution in first nations groups in Ontario,
Canada: 35 years of Canadian Minamata disease. Journal of Minamata Studies, 3, 3–30.
Hicks, J. (2007). The social determinants of elevated rates of suicide among Inuit youth. Indigenous
Affairs, 4, 30–37.
High, S. (1996). Native wage labour and independent production during the “Era of Irrelevance.”
Labour/le travail, 243–264. Available from http://www.jstor.org.ezproxy.library.ubc.ca/stable/
10.2307/25144044?origin=api [accessed August 17, 2016].
Hirsch, A.R. (1992). Nostalgia –a neuropsychiatric understanding. Advances in Consumer Research, 19,
390–395.
Hodge, F.S., Pasqua, A., Marquez, C.A., and Geishirt-Cantrell, B. (2002). Utilizing traditional
storytelling to promote wellness in American Indian communities. Journal of Transcultural Nursing,
13(1), 6–11.
Illes, J., Davidson, J., and Matthews, R. (2014). Environmental neuroethics: changing the
environment—changing the brain. Recommendations submitted to the Presidential Commission for
the Study of Bioethical Issues. Journal of Law and the Biosciences, 1(2), 221–223.
47
Isaak, C.A. and Marchessault, G. (2008). Meaning of health: the perspectives of Aboriginal adults
and youth in a northern Manitoba First Nations community. Canadian Journal of Diabetes, 32(2),
114–122.
Jackson, D.D. (2011). Scents of place: the dysplacement of a First Nations community in Canada.
American Anthropologist, 113(4), 606–618.
Jang, B. (2015, July 9). Five First Nations join forces to assess environmental impact of LNG exports.
The Globe and Mail. Available from: http://www.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-
news/energy-and-resources/five-first-nations-join-forces-to-assess-impact-of-bc-lng-exports/
article25388272 [accessed July 9, 2016].
Jones, R., Rigg, C., and Lee, L. (2010). Haida marine planning: First Nations as a partner in marine
conservation. Ecology and Society, 15(1), 12.
Kant, I. (1785). Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals.
Kelly, E.N., Short, J.W., Schindler, D.W., et al. (2009). Oil sands development contributes polycyclic
aromatic compounds to the Athabasca River and its tributaries. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences of the United States of America, 106(52), 22346–22351.
Kelly, E.N., Schindler, D.W., Hodson, P.V., Short, J.W., Radmanovich, R., and Nielsen, C.C. (2010). Oil
sands development contributes elements toxic at low concentrations to the Athabasca River and its
tributaries. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 107(37),
16178–16183.
King, M., Smith, A., and Gracey, M. (2009). Indigenous health part 2: the underlying causes of the
health gap. The Lancet, 374(9683), 76–85.
Klotz, O. (1914). Pulmonary anthracosis—a community disease. American Journal of Public Health,
4(10), 887–916.
Krupnik, I. and Jolly, D. (2002). The Earth is Faster Now: Indigenous Observations of Arctic
Environmental Change. [Frontiers in Polar Social Science.] Fairbanks, AK: Arctic Research
Consortium of the United States.
Kuhnlein, H.V., Receveur, O., Muir, D.C.G., Chan, H.M., and Soueida, R. (1995). Arctic indigenous
women consume greater than acceptable levels of organochlorines. The Journal of Nutrition,
125(10), 2501.
Lee, S.S.J., Bolnick, D.A., Duster, T., Ossorio, P., and TallBear, K. (2009). The illusive gold standard in
genetic ancestry testing. Science, 325(5936), 38.
Lehti, V., Niemelä, S., Hoven, C., Mandell, D., and Sourander, A. (2009). Mental health, substance use
and suicidal behaviour among young indigenous people in the Arctic: a systematic review. Social
Science & Medicine, 69(8), 1194–1203.
MacDonald, J.P., Ford, J.D., Willox, A.C., and Ross, N.A. (2013). A review of protective factors and
causal mechanisms that enhance the mental health of indigenous circumpolar youth. International
Journal of Circumpolar Health, 72, 21775.
McAlpine, D. and Araki, S. (1958). Minamata disease an unusual neurological disorder caused by
contaminated fish. The Lancet, 272(7047), 629–631.
McGregor, D. (2004). Coming full circle: indigenous knowledge, environment, and our future. The
American Indian Quarterly, 28(3), 385–410.
McLaren, L. (2015, January 21). Makayla Sault: whose rights are served when a little girl dies? Special to
The Globe and Mail. Available from: http://www.theglobeandmail.com/life/parenting/whose-rights-
are-served-when-a-little-girl-dies/article22562573/ [accessed August 18, 2015].
McMichael, A.J. (2003). Climate Change and Human Health: Risks and Responses. Geneva: World
Health Organization.
McMichael, A.J., Woodruff, R.E., and Hales, S. (2006). Climate change and human health: present and
future risks. The Lancet, 367(9513), 859–869.
475
References 475
McQuigge, M. (2012, June 4). Two Ontario first nations still plagued by mercury poisoning: report. The
Globe and Mail. Available from: http://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/politics/two-ontario-first-
nations-still-plagued-by-mercury-poisoning-report/article4230507/ [accessed August 17, 2015].
Masuda, J.R. and Garvin, T. (2006). Place, culture, and the social amplification of risk. Risk Analysis,
26(2), 437–454.
Mills, C.A. (1943). Urban air pollution and respiratory diseases. American Journal of Epidemiology,
37(2), 131–141.
Murata, K., Weihe, P., Budtz-Jørgensen, E., Jørgensen, P.J., and Grandjean, P. (2004). Delayed
brainstem auditory evoked potential latencies in 14-year-old children exposed to methylmercury.
Journal of Pediatrics, 144(2), 177–183.
Nikiforuk, A. (2015, January 10). Fracking industry shakes up northern BC with 231 tremors. TheTyee.
ca. Available from: http://thetyee.ca/News/2015/01/10/Fracking_Industry_Shakes_Up_Northern_
BC/[accessed August 17, 2015].
Northern Brain Injury Association (2015). First Nations. http://nbia.ca/first-nations-brain-injury/
[accessed August 17, 2015].
Parsons, R. and Prest, G. (2003). Aboriginal forestry in Canada. The Forestry Chronicle, 79(4), 779–784.
Available from: http://pubs.cif-ifc.org.ezproxy.library.ubc.ca/loi/tfc?open=2003#id_2003 [accessed
August 17, 2015].
Passchier-Vermeer, W. and Passchier, W. F. (2000). Noise exposure and public health. Environmental
Health Perspectives, 108(Suppl. 1), 123.
Patz, J.A., Campbell-Lendrum, D., Holloway, T., and Foley, J.A. (2005). Impact of regional climate
change on human health. Nature, 438(7066), 310–317.
Pazderka, H., Desjarlais, B., Makokis, L., et al. (2014). Nitsiyihkâson: the brain science behind Cree
teachings of early childhood attachment. First Peoples Child & Family Review, 9(1), 53–65.
Petrol Link-up. (1994). Australian Government Department of Health and Aging, and Menzies School
of Health Research. Available from: http://resources.menzies.edu.au/download/Sniffing_and_the_
Brain.pdf [accessed July 15, 2015].
Pinker, S. (2003). The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. Chicago, IL: Penguin.
Pinkerton, E. (1987). The fishing-dependent community. In: Marchak, M.P., Guppy, N., and McMullan,
J.L. (Eds.) Uncommon Property: The Fishing and Fish-Processing Industries in British Columbia,
pp.293–325. Toronto, ON: Methuen Publications.
Racine, E. (2010). Pragmatic Neuroethics: Improving Treatment and Understanding of the Mind–Brain.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ray, J.G., Vermeulen, M.J., Meier, C., Cole, D.E., and Wyatt, P.R. (2004). Maternal ethnicity and risk
of neural tube defects: a population-based study. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 171(4),
343–345.
Raz, R., Roberts, A.L., Lyall, K., et al. (2015). Autism spectrum disorder and particulate matter air
pollution before, during, and after pregnancy: a nested case–control analysis within the Nurses’
Health Study II Cohort. Environmental Health Perspectives, 123(3), 264–270.
Rose, N. and Abi-Rached, J.M. (2013). Neuro: The New Brain Sciences and the Management of the Mind.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Russell, W.T. (1924). The influence of fog on mortality from respiratory diseases. The Lancet, 204(5268),
335–339.
Scarlett, A.G., West, C.E., Jones, D., Galloway, T.S., and Rowland, S.J. (2012). Predicted toxicity of
naphthenic acids present in oil sands process-affected waters to a range of environmental and
human endpoints. Science of the Total Environment, 425, 119–127.
Schaefer, T.W. (1907). The contamination of the air of our cities with sulphur dioxide, the cause of
respiratory disease. Boston Medical and Surgical Journal, 157(4), 106–110.
476
Smylie, J., Kaplan-Myrth, N., McShane, K., and Nation, P.F. (2008). Indigenous knowledge
translation: baseline findings in a qualitative study of the pathways of health knowledge in three
indigenous communities in Canada. Health Promotion Practice.
Stanbury, W.T. (1973). Indians in British Columbia: level of income, welfare dependency and poverty
rate. The British Columbian Quarterly, 20, 66–78. Available from: http://ojs.library.ubc.ca/index.php/
bcstudies/issue/view/140 [accessed July 15, 2015].
Stevenson, S., Beattie, B.L., Vedan, R., Dwosh, E., Bruce, L., and Illes, J. (2013). Neuroethics,
confidentiality, and a cultural imperative in early onset Alzheimer disease: a case study with a First
Nation population. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 8(1), 15.
Stout, R., Stout, T.D., and Harp, R. (2009). Maternal and Infant Health and the Physical Environment of
First Nations and Inuit Communities: A Summary Review. Winnipeg, MB: Prairie Women’s Health
Centre of Excellence.
Sullivan, A. and Brems, C. (1997). The psychological repercussions of the sociocultural oppression of
Alaska native peoples. Genetic, Social, and General Psychology Monographs, 123(4), 411–440.
Takeuchi, T., Kambara, T., Morikawa, N., Matsumoto, H., Shiraishi, Y., and Ito, H. (1959). Pathologic
observations of the Minamata disease. Pathology International, 9(S1), 769–783.
Talbott, E.O., Arena, V.C., Rager, J.R., et al. (2015). Fine particulate matter and the risk of autism
spectrum disorder. Environmental Research, 140, 414–420.
Tennant, P. (1990). Aboriginal Peoples and Politics: The Indian Land Question in British Columbia, 1849–
1989. Vancouver, BC: UBC Press.
Timoney, K.P. and Lee, P. (2009). Does the Alberta tar sands industry pollute? The scientific evidence.
The Open Conservation Biology Journal, 3, 65–81.
Van Oostdam, J., Gilman, A., Dewailly, E., et al. (1999). Human health implications of
environmental contaminants in Arctic Canada: a review. Science of the Total Environment,
230(1), 1–82.
Wheatley, B. and Wheatley, M.A. (2000). Methylmercury and the health of indigenous peoples: a risk
management challenge for physical and social sciences and for public health policy. Science of the
Total Environment, 259(1), 23–29.
Willox, A.C., Harper, S.L., Edge, V.L., Landman, K., Houle, K., and Ford, J.D. (2013a). The land
enriches the soul: on climatic and environmental change, affect, and emotional health and well-
being in Rigolet, Nunatsiavut, Canada. Emotion, Space and Society, 6, 14–24.
Willox, A.C., Harper, S.L., Ford, J.D., et al. (2013b). Climate change and mental health: an exploratory
case study from Rigolet, Nunatsiavut, Canada. Climatic Change, 121(2), 255–270.
Willox, A.C., Stephenson, E., Allen, J., et al. (2015). Examining relationships between climate change
and mental health in the Circumpolar North. Regional Environmental Change, 15(1), 169–182.
Wilson, K. (2003). Therapeutic landscapes and First Nations peoples: an exploration of culture, health
and place. Health & Place, 9(2), 83–93.
Wiseman, C.L. and Gobas, F.A. (2002). Balancing risks in the management of contaminated First
Nations fisheries. International Journal of Environmental Health Research, 12(4), 331–342.
Wiwchar, D. (2004, December 16). Nuu-chah-nulth blood returns to west coast. Ha-Shilth-Sa. Canada’s
Oldest First Nations Newspaper, 31(25). Available from: http://www.igb.illinois.edu/sites/default/
files/Wiwchar%202004%20Nuu-chah-nulth.pdf [accessed July 15, 2015].
Woolford, A. and Thomas, J. (2011). Genocide of Canadian First Nations. Genocide of Indigenous
Peoples, 8, 61–86.
Yazzie, R. (2000). Postcolonial colonialism. Reclaiming Indigenous voice and vision. In: Battiste, M.
(Ed). Reclaiming Indigenous Voice and Vision, pp.39–49. Vancouver, BC: UBC Press.
Young, T.K. (1994). The Health of Native Americans: Toward a Biocultural Epidemiology.
New York: Oxford University Press.
47
Chapter 24
Introduction
Drug addiction is a severe problem for public health, systems of justice, and for the func-
tioning of societies worldwide. Views of addicted people vary widely between and even
within countries. Perspectives range from seeing them as medically ill to having the sta-
tus of moral pariahs. Since possession of addictive drugs other than tobacco or alcohol
is a criminal offense within many jurisdictions, addiction to many drugs is de facto a
crime. In this chapter, I use insights that have emerged from neuroscience and psychol-
ogy in the last two decades to examine the predominant medical model of drug addiction
as a form of behavior that has escaped volitional control, that is, compulsive drug use
despite significant negative consequences. This model is codified in the fifth edition of the
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-5) (American Psychiatric
Association 2013) and similarly in the tenth edition of the International Classification of
Diseases (ICD-10) (World Health Organization 1992). I contrast this view of addiction
with what might be called a moral model, which sees the behavior of the addicted person
as reflecting a series of bad choices that could be brought under volitional control with
appropriate effort. These contrasting views have significant ethical and pragmatic impli-
cations for how societies hold addicted people responsible for their behavior and how
they treat them.
Addiction is an apt subject for neuroethical analysis because (1) it problematizes the
concepts of volition and responsibility, which are central concerns for neuroscience, phi-
losophy, law, and ethics; and (2) because enough is known scientifically about addiction
to ground the discussion in a reasonable, if still incomplete body of knowledge. Addiction
is a topic about which too many ungrounded inferences and assertions are made. My brief
scientific discussion is a byproduct of mechanistic neurobiological analyses performed
for other reasons. The pursuit of neurobiological mechanisms is partly driven by a desire
for greater understandings of nature as well as human self-understanding. However, as
with essentially all other medically significant conditions, mechanistic investigations of
478
addiction are also meant to yield knowledge that will ultimately prove actionable for pre-
vention and treatment.
Compulsion
Short of being externally coerced or psychotic, what can it mean to say that a person can-
not control his or her consciously planned behaviors? What does society make of a person
who has suffered dire health consequences from smoking tobacco, understands the health
risks perfectly well, states a credible intention to stop smoking, repeatedly tries to cut
down, but repeatedly resumes smoking? How do we interpret the behavior of an opioid
user who had entered a treatment facility under the threat of losing his job and spouse,
who soon after release from the facility (where he initially suffered painful withdrawal
symptoms, and later participated seriously in psychotherapy and rehabilitative services),
steals money from his spouse, buys heroin, prepares it for self-injection, and consumes it?
Are these individuals likely to be lying glibly about their intentions to abstain? Are they
weak-willed, heedlessly seeking pleasure or oblivion rather than effectively confronting
urges to smoke tobacco or use drugs? Or is there a convincing alternative explanation for
their behavior that can be grounded in the concepts of compulsion and loss of control that
dominate medical description of addiction?
Much is now known about neural mechanisms of decision-making and control of behav-
ior and how these mechanisms can be altered long term by addictive drugs. Nonetheless,
addicted individuals, such as those briefly described in the vignettes, often attract moral
condemnation, and if caught breaking the law for possessing illegal drugs or commit-
ting illegal acts to obtain them, may face severe sanctions. Attribution of the continuing
drug use of addicted people to weak will or some kind of moral failure remains a potent
factor in social, policy, and legal spheres. For example, in 1988 the Supreme Court of
the United States decided two related cases, Traynor v. Turnage and McKelvey v. Turnage
(1988), upholding the denial of a petition of two veterans by the Veterans Administration
(VA) in the United States. The veterans had asked the VA to extend the usual 10-year limit
on educational benefits because they suffered from complications of alcoholism, which,
they argued, was a medical illness. Extensions had previously been granted to veterans
who, because of other illnesses, had been unable to use their benefits during the allotted
10 years’ time. The Court, however, upheld the denial of an extension, with the majority
finding that the VA was reasonable in defining alcoholism as willful misconduct.
In contrast to the Court’s decision, the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association
2013) defines drug addiction as compulsive drug use despite significant negative conse-
quences. Loss of control over drug use may be evidenced, inter alia, by multiple unsuc-
cessful attempts to cut down. Those who doubt that addicted individuals have truly lost
control of their behavior and, like the Court, see it instead as willful misconduct, at least
implicitly construe human decision-making to be a conscious process of deliberation that
weighs costs and benefits (Heyman 2010). Based on such a model, a decision to use drugs
would represent a conscious choice of gratification or relief from distress over the risk of
479
Compulsion 479
exacerbating drug-related harms and perhaps committing illegal acts. In this model, a
decision to abstain from drug use, and thus to forego the pleasure or relief gained by drug
taking, might result from the incorporation of salient new information or recent aversive
experiences that tilt the decisional scales against continued drug taking (Heyman 2010).
Those skeptical of the idea that addicted people cannot control their substance use
have pointed out that seeking and using drugs often requires meticulous planning, first
to gain necessary resources and then drugs; may be played out over time, giving ample
opportunity for users to inhibit prepotent drug-seeking impulses; and requires signifi-
cant cognitive and behavioral flexibility given real-world obstacles to obtaining drugs,
especially when they are illegal or must be used furtively. Moreover, addicted people,
except when intoxicated or experiencing significant withdrawal symptoms, may act in
a rational manner, might at times display insight into their condition, and can typically
control most other aspects of their behavior—unlike individuals with florid psychosis,
dementia, or delirium who would seem to be better candidates for the descriptor, lack of
control. A salient example of individuals who for the most part exhibit rationality outside
the sphere of their drug habit are tobacco smokers—at least in part because tobacco is
legal and not intoxicating—but to varying degrees, users of other drugs have periods of
rational control of behavior.
Opposition to medical models of addiction is also grounded in pragmatic concerns.
Medical models can be construed as decreasing incentives for recovery by appearing to
explain away drug use as uncontrollable and providing a rationalization for being unable
to abstain, (Satel 1999; Satel & Lillienfeld 2013). Concerns have been raised, in addition,
about a trend toward medicalizing all forms of deviance in society (Conrad & Schneider
1992). After all, criminality is a form of deviance that, like addiction, has identifiable
familial (presumably partly genetic), developmental, social, and contextual risk factors,
yet it is not included in the DSM-5. Those concerned about what they see as creeping
medicalization of all deviance also express concern about the placement of compulsive
gambling in the same chapter with drug addiction in the DSM-5, and about arguments
being made to further broaden the concept of behavioral addiction (Robbins & Clark
2015) based on shared risk factors and shared neural mechanisms. In fact, some scientists
and clinicians have been arguing for the inclusion as addictions in future DSM editions of
compulsive sex, compulsive shopping, compulsive use of the internet, and perhaps excess
eating associated with obesity (Volkow et al. 2013).
The idea that human decision-making, including the choices made by addicted people,
represent conscious deliberations that yield freely chosen goals and actions, is consis-
tent with ubiquitous human intuitions that are sometimes described as folk psychology
(Morse 2008). Upon introspection, human beings intuit a self that has experiences, makes
decisions, and causes bodily actions. Thus folk psychology and systems of justice hold
that human beings act for reasons. This view is entirely contradicted by neurobiology,
which finds no evidence for anything like a self that possesses decisional capacity and
causes behavior. What have been found instead are diverse neural mechanisms—opaque
to introspection—that contribute to different aspects of decision-making and that control
480
behavior. It appears that one of the outputs of the circuitry that controls action is the
experience—but not the fact—of a self that authors our behavior (Wegner 2002, 2003;
Haggard 2008). Without resorting to evolutionary “just so” stories, it can safely be posited
that cognitive and behavioral mechanisms were selected in evolution by their adaptive-
ness and survival value, not by their ability to capture objective truth.
Actions can be conceptualized as ranging from reflexes, which are the most stimulus
bound, to volitional acts in which external stimuli act only indirectly and do not directly
determine the timing or nature of the act (Gold & Shadlen 2007; Haggard 2008). A par-
tially overlapping way of parsing actions (which excludes simple reflexes) is to rank at one
extreme, actions that arise wholly from unconscious processing and at the other, actions
that reflect conscious, goal-oriented, deliberative decisions. However, decision-making is
more complex than might be implied by these extremes. For example, voluntary action
that might, on the evidence of introspection, appear to spring entirely from conscious,
deliberative decision-making, is also invariably dependent on rapid, unconscious, parallel
processing by neural circuits with access to such information as previously stored values
(Gallagher et al. 1999; Xie & Padoa-Schioppa 2016), social stereotypes (Dunham et al
2013; Stolier & Freeman 2016), and ingrained behavioral tendencies. The decision-maker
cannot be directly aware of this processing, or of the neural mechanisms that control
motor outputs (Dayan 2007; Glockner 2007; Gold & Shadlen 2007; Koechlin & Hyafil
2007; Kable & Glimcher 2009; Cisek & Kalaska 2010; Custers & Aarts 2010). While such
work is focused on general aspects of mechanisms underlying decision-making, it has
profound implications for addiction. The process of becoming addicted is one in which
drug taking begins as a volitional pursuit of such goals as pleasure, facilitation of social
behavior, or relief from distress, but mediated by processes that will be described, devolves
into behavior in which drug seeking becomes automatic, stimulus bound, extremely dif-
ficult to inhibit, and divorced from goals.
Some specific genetic loci associated with smoking and nicotine dependence have
been identified in part because the behavior is legal, making research participation more
straightforward, and in part because it is relatively easy to know how many cigarettes
a person has smoked per day. Pointing to the complexity of addiction risk, different
genes have been associated with smoking initiation, smoking dependence, cessation, and
smoking-associated diseases such as lung cancer (Thorgeirsson et al. 2010). Significant
efforts to discover specific genes associated with different stages of drug use among other
drug classes are currently under way. This research is being pursued because identifi-
cation, with certainty, of specific disorder-associated genomic variants provides solid
biological clues to pathogenesis, and hopefully molecular targets for preventive or thera-
peutic interventions.
Reward circuitry
The drive to obtain natural rewards such as food, water, social interactions, and mat-
ing opportunities is required for the survival of free-living animals and their species
(Kelley & Berridge 2002). Rewards can be operationally defined as stimuli that elicit
approach and appetitive behaviors; they also increase the probability that behaviors
aimed at obtaining them will be repeated, that is, rewards are positively reinforc-
ing. A specialized brain reward circuity that is conserved across mammalian evolu-
tion plays the central role in the ability of an organism to successfully obtain and
consume or consummate innately programmed rewards and learn about and pursue
new ones. This circuitry is comprised of neurons that synthesize and release the neu-
rotransmitter dopamine and that project from the ventral tegmental area (VTA) of
the midbrain to forebrain regions involved in motivation, emotion, and important
aspects of cognition, notably the nucleus accumbens (NAc), amygdala, hippocampus,
and prefrontal cortex. A separate cluster of midbrain dopamine neurons that proj-
ect from the substantia nigra to the caudate and putamen facilitate motor learning
that results in efficient reward seeking and consummatory behaviors. Reward circuitry
has been extensively characterized in the brains of multiple mammals including mice,
rats, several nonhuman primate species, and based on noninvasive methods such as
functional brain imaging, in humans as well (Breiter et al. 1997; Diederen et al. 2016).
Reward circuitry, which leads to appetitive and approach behaviors and amygdala-
based and other circuits that produce aversion and avoidance, confer valuation and
valence on experiences encountered in the world, and undergird decision-making and
control of behavior. Maladaptive functioning of reward circuitry plays a central role in
many human ills. Excessive stimulation of reward circuity is central to drug addiction
(Hyman et al. 2006; Nestler et al. 2015; Pascoli et al. 2015), to compulsive gambling
and other impulsive behaviors (Dagher & Robbins 2009; Robbins & Clark 2015), and
perhaps to obesity (Kenny 2011). Underactivity of reward circuitry likely contributes
to the anhedonia (inability to experience pleasure) and behavioral inertia that charac-
terize depression (Ferenczi et al. 2016).
483
Dopamine release in reward circuitry does not serve as the internal representation of
pleasure as once was hypothesized, but as a learning signal that shapes behavior to max-
imize further rewards and thus the likelihood of survival (Schultz et al. 1997; Schultz
2006). In their basal (unstimulated) state, dopamine neurons exhibit a pattern of slow
tonic firing. When a reward is encountered unexpectedly, these neurons fire a brief phasic
burst of action potentials, producing a transient increase in synaptic dopamine in the
forebrain. For example, an encounter with natural rewards such as palatable foods or
mating opportunities causes VTA neurons to fire phasically (Kelley & Berridge 2002).
Important insights into the function of dopamine came from electrophysiologic record-
ings of dopamine-releasing neurons in nonhuman primates, and later from rats and
mice undergoing classical (Pavlovian) conditioning (Schultz et al. 1997; Schultz 2006).
Animals readily learn to associate a previously neutral stimulus (e.g., a light) with delivery
of reward when the stimulus reliably precedes reward over several trials. In the monkey
studies by Schultz et al. (1997, 2006), appearance of highly palatable juice or food (an
unconditioned stimulus—a natural reward) elicits phasic dopamine neuron firing and
thus a transient increase in dopamine release. Once the animal—or as was later estab-
lished a human subject studied by noninvasive neuroimaging—learns that the new stimu-
lus (e.g., light) predicts reward, the dopamine neurons no longer fire phasically when
the reward (unconditioned stimulus) appears, but rather at the appearance of the light,
which has become a conditioned stimulus (i.e., predictive of reward). If an new stimulus is
introduced (e.g., a tone), that reliably precedes the light, which in turn predicts the juice,
dopamine neurons fire phasically in response to the tone, but no longer to the light or to
reward delivery (Schultz et al. 1997; Schultz 2006). If the reward is omitted at the time
when it was predicted by learned cues, there is a pause in dopamine neuron firing (i.e., a
punishment signal). There is convergent evidence from many experiments (together with
computational models), which make a strong case that dopamine neurons respond to
errors in prediction about the availability of reward (Schultz 2006). They fire phasically at
the first and therefore unpredicted appearance of a conditioned stimulus or reward. They
fire only at their basal tonic rate when a cue or reward is encountered that has been fully
predicted (i.e., when there is nothing more to learn) and pause when an expected reward
is less than expected or omitted. The effect of increased synaptic dopamine is to initiate
a set of molecular and cellular processes that consolidate learning about the predictive
significance of cues and produce long-lived alterations in behavioral responses to reward-
associated cues. A critical mechanism by which dopamine alters functional outputs of the
forebrain is by facilitating long-term changes in the strength of synaptic communication
between target neurons with the result that neural circuitry is altered long term (Berke &
Hyman 2000; Hyman et al. 2006; Luescher & Malenka 2011).
Acting in the NAc, dopamine binds reward-associated stimuli to motivation, thus
imbuing the cue with what has been called incentive salience (Robinson et al. 2005). The
result is that the cue gains the ability to motivate pursuit and consummatory behavior.
Within orbital prefrontal cortex, dopamine updates the representation of rewards and
their relative valuation; neural processes within the orbital prefrontal cortex establish a
48
common currency that permits an organism to choose among possible goals that may
differ both qualitatively and quantitatively (Gallagher et al. 1999; Montague et al. 2004;
Schoenbaum et al. 2006; Xie & Padoa-Schioppa 2016). In the caudate and putamen, pha-
sic dopamine release supports motor learning that binds cues predictive of reward to
action. Motor learning involving the caudate and putamen requires repetition (i.e., prac-
tice), but eventually becomes highly efficient, smooth, automatic, and resistant to forget-
ting. Examples include learning to ride a bike, learning to touch-type, or a baseball player
learning to throw a fastball. In the case of direct pursuit of rewards, such as obtaining food
under conditions of scarcity or intense competition, automatic recognition of predictive
cues and speedy, efficient engagement in hunting, or foraging might make the difference
between survival and starvation. While this last description may call up visions of animals
in the wild, they apply also to modern humans when, because of crop failure, conflict, or
extreme economic mismanagement, shops are empty and food is unavailable.
Well-learned action repertoires typically remain goal directed, but become automatized,
highly efficient, and largely independent of conscious control. For example, fluent deliv-
ery of a well-rehearsed lecture by a professor or a well-practiced gymnastic routine during
an athletic competition are initiated in a goal-directed manner but, once begun, unfold
without conscious consideration of each word, gesture, or bodily movement. Under path-
ological conditions, however, behaviors of varying complexity from tics to extended rou-
tines may be activated by environmental or internal cues independently of, and even in
contravention of a person’s goals. Such deeply ingrained habits, which may become quite
stereotyped, are highly resistant to conscious control (Graybiel 2008). Examples of com-
mon, relatively simple, stereotyped habits include compulsive nail biting and compulsive
hair pulling (trichotillomania). Automatized behaviors and even deeply ingrained habits
can be interrupted by a salient, unexpected event or a failure such as losing one’s place
while delivering a lecture or speech or falling during a well-practiced gymnastic routine;
this results in a marked increase in arousal and attention, and a transient gain in behav-
ioral flexibility (e.g., to find one’s place or right oneself) before returning to the routine.
Thus the addicted person who sees a uniformed policeman standing where he expects to
see his drug dealer does not zombie-like try to buy drugs from the policemen, but aborts
the plan and seeks out drugs elsewhere. Under such circumstances, the addicted person
often suffers intense drug craving (Tiffany 1990).
It may seem counterintuitive based on what we think we know about ourselves, but the
actions of dopamine in tuning motivation, cognition, and behavior toward future rewards
are unavailable to conscious introspection. The basis of consciousness remains a deep
scientific mystery, but the properties of conscious cognition are well studied. Among its
attributes, consciousness is a remarkable, but capacity limited, serial processor of infor-
mation. Conscious deliberative decision-making is slow and effortful relative to uncon-
scious decision-making processes. In a complex, rapidly moving world in which survival
often depends on speed and efficiency, it is unsurprising that decision-making and con-
trol of behavior are served by rapid, massively parallel unconscious processing that has
access to multiple sources of relevant information (Dayan 2007; Cisek & Kalaska 2010).
485
Addictive drugs 485
Addictive drugs
Addictive drugs are chemically diverse and interact with different molecular targets in
the nervous system (Nestler et al. 2015). Based on their chemical differences, these drugs
exert diverse physiological and behavioral effects. For example, amphetamines are stim-
ulants, that is, they increase arousal. At lower doses, amphetamines enhance cognitive
performance; and at higher doses they produce euphoria, but may also cause anxiety and
insomnia. Alcohol, in contrast, is a depressant; it is anxiolytic at low doses, and degrades
cognitive and motor performance with higher, intoxicating doses. Despite their differ-
ences in mode of action in the brain, all addictive drugs share the property of causing
dopamine release from VTA neurons and thus activating reward circuitry. Psychotropic
drugs such as selective serotonin reuptake inhibitor antidepressants that do not cause sig-
nificant dopamine release are not addictive. Even drugs that produce physical withdrawal
symptoms (physiological dependence) are not considered addictive unless they produce
compulsive behavior.
In a metaphorical sense, addictive drugs can be likened to Trojan horses in the brain.
All addictive drugs mimic one or another endogenous neurotransmitter that can directly
or indirectly increase synaptic dopamine. Cocaine is structurally similar enough to dopa-
mine itself that it binds the dopamine transporter that normally clears dopamine from
synapses. However, cocaine is different enough structurally from dopamine that it blocks
the transporter without entering it. The result of cocaine blockade of the dopamine trans-
porter is a buildup of dopamine in synapses to very high levels. Opiates, nicotine, alcohol,
and cannabinoids mimic different neurotransmitters and act on different receptors in the
brain, but by diverse mechanisms, all of them indirectly cause dopamine release (and in
the case of opiates also exert independent rewarding effects) (Nestler et al. 2015).
Why do addictive drugs have an advantage over natural rewards, and, in vulnerable indi-
viduals, crowd out other, more adaptive goals? It is because addictive drugs activate reward
circuits directly by pharmacologic action, independently of experience and despite their lack
of any homeostatic or reproductive benefit. Such drugs reliably cause significant dopamine
release and thus a positive reward prediction signal. As drug use is repeated under the initial
influence of pleasure seeking, relief of distress, or social forces, the resulting grossly abnormal
dopamine signal potently consolidates the motivational power of drug-associated cues, patho-
logically excessive valuation of drug taking, and drug seeking and consummatory behavioral
repertoires (Montague et al. 2004; Schoenbaum et al. 2006; Everitt & Robbins 2016).
An additional advantage that addictive drugs have over natural rewards is that phar-
macologically induced dopamine release masks the results of disappointing or aversive
experiences. Thus biting into a rotten fruit would create, among other effects, a dopa-
mine pause, which might devalue that kind of fruit. This is not the case for drugs that
directly release dopamine. For example, if the inhalation of tobacco smoke causes painful
coughing or shortness of breath in a chronically ill smoker, nicotine still causes dopamine
release as a pharmacologic action mediated by nicotinic acetylcholine receptors. Despite
the smoker’s actual aversive experience, forebrain circuits still receive a signal that rein-
forces tobacco use (Redish 2004).
486
As individuals progress from repetitive drug use to addiction, action patterns involved
in drug seeking and drug taking become habitual: drug-associated cues gain the ability
to activate automatized drug-seeking behaviors in a manner that is increasingly indepen-
dent of the person’s goals (Berke & Hyman 2000; Everitt & Robbins 2005, 2016). Cue-
dependent activation of ingrained drug-seeking habits helps explain why an addicted
person continues to take drugs, even when late in the course of addiction, tolerance to
drugs and damage to health may have sapped all pleasure from the experience of using
them and may even be aversive. When such habitual drug seeking is delayed or foiled
(e.g., by unavailability or by attempts to cut down), intense drug craving often occurs,
increasing the motivation to find and use drugs (Tiffany 1990). Craving is so characteris-
tic of addicted individuals as to be listed among the DSM-5 diagnostic criteria (American
Psychiatric Association 2013).
unrelated to a person’s goals, becomes extremely difficult to interrupt for any extended
period of time.
Some implications of the scientific model for moral responsibility and legal culpability 489
large numbers obtain only modest benefits, if any. As in the case of many severe chronic
and relapsing human ills, especially those that affect the brain, progress has been slow. In
the case of addiction, the search for better treatments has been hampered by low levels
of interest on the part of pharmaceutical companies based, in part, on concerns about
retaining addicted people in clinical trials and in part about the likelihood of reimburse-
ment given the often tenuous state of health insurance for this stigmatized population.
The most important reason to investigate neurobiological mechanisms of addiction is
to gain deeper understandings that will yield biomarkers and effective treatments. One
early example of a treatment that has come from research on basic mechanisms is the
use of long-acting opiate antagonists that diminish drug craving across multiple classes
of addictive drugs (Lee et al. 2016). These are proving a useful tool in treatment, but as
noted, much more is needed.
A challenging problem is how to convince addicted individuals to accept treatment—a
problem that is exacerbated by the dearth of drug treatment slots in most countries and
the limitations on insurance payments. The foregoing discussion is consistent with the
experience of many families and many clinicians. Information alone is rarely adequate;
rather, sustained efforts at persuasion and some level of coercion are often required. Given
the power of cues and stress to elicit drug seeking, opportunities to succeed in getting an
addicted person to treatment may be transient—thus the limitation of treatment slots and
insurance coverage are particularly unfortunate. Challenging and frustrating in addition,
as in the second of the opening vignettes, are relapses after treatment. Given what we
know of addiction, relapses are not surprising, nor should they be the occasion to give
up on the addicted person. Based on what we know of the power and persistence of the
underlying neural mechanisms, many attempts are often needed before an addicted per-
son can achieve a sustained remission.
Application of the medical model does not mean, however, that all sanctions would be
inappropriate. Rationales for punishment in most systems of justice include a combina-
tion of retributivist and consequentialist goals. Retribution expresses the moral outrage
of society about a crime and is meant to assuage the moral emotions of victims and of
society more broadly. Consequentialist goals include deterrence of future crime by the
perpetrator and by setting an example, deterrence of other potential perpetrators; inca-
pacitation of dangerous individuals; and rehabilitation of the person being punished. The
medical model of addiction does not militate against consequentialist goals of punish-
ment, but explains why punishment often fails to end drug use. Moreover, if one goal of
punishment is to protect society from the considerable harms wrought by drug use and
addiction (including the profoundly negative effects of black markets), it can be asked
whether incarceration in prison, which has been so common in the United States in
recent decades, is beneficial to society, or whether alternative sanctions—a complex mat-
ter that cannot be discussed within the limits of this chapter—might better serve society’s
pragmatic goals. The medical model suggests that retribution makes no sense with respect
to addicted individuals given the constraints its underlying pathologies put on volitional
control, and on the ability of addicted persons to respond to moral condemnation. The
moral model in systems of criminal justice, combined with stigmatization of addicted
people and outrage against them, has produced a period of harsh punishment, notably in
the United States, which has a significant percentage of its population serving long prison
sentences for drug-related crimes, even when nonviolent.
Some legal scholars argue that moral responsibility and legal culpability can almost
always be determined at the level of psychological evidence and that neuroscience has
nothing to add (Morse 2006). This is because the factors that matter for determinations
of mens rea are the capacities and especially the rationality of accused persons at the
time that they committed an illegal act, and, they argue, facts about brain anatomy or
brain function do not directly address these issues (Morse 2006). Such views create some-
thing of an impasse between the law and neuroscience, since the neuroscience view would
argue that the apparent rationality of the addicted person is illusory: the person can plan
to gain and take drugs, but is not in control of his or her motives.
Significant challenges remain if neuroscience is to effectively influence systems of jus-
tice and social policy more broadly. The mechanistic picture of addiction, which I have
reviewed here, has ultimately been constructed out of many hundreds of individual stud-
ies. The majority of these studies are based on animal models rather than humans because
of the inviolability of the human brain to intrusive experimentation in life. In addition,
given the serious limitations of current noninvasive imaging and neurophysiological
technologies, neural correlates of addiction—assuming these were better defined from
basic studies—cannot be convincingly demonstrated for any given individual to a court,
parole officer, or medical personnel. Even if published neuroimaging studies were more
convincingly replicated than at the present time, it would still not be possible to deter-
mine the degree to which any specific person had been deprived by addiction of volitional
control—and courts must deal with individuals, not with diagnostic classes. Perhaps at
491
some future time, there will be convincing biomarkers that will provide a clear measure of
the severity of a given person’s loss of volitional control, but none exist today.
That might be the end of the matter for now, except that many scientists share the view
that the moral model of addiction has often tilted courts and especially their sentencing
practices toward injustice by overstating the degree to which addicted people can control
their actions in accordance with the law. Certain courts and legal scholars—those more
anxious about letting the guilty go free than about punishing the innocent—may also be
concerned that symptoms of addiction, like symptoms of all physically invisible disabili-
ties and disorders, such as mental illnesses and early-stage neurodegenerative disorders,
might be feigned and impairments of decision-making and behavioral control overstated
by defendants. These concerns notwithstanding, and understanding full well that today
the severity of compulsion in any individual person cannot be objectively determined, it
is still the case that mainstream scientific understandings converge on the view that drug
seeking and drug taking by addicted individuals reflects severely impaired volitional con-
trol and markedly diminished ability to conform behavior to rational goals. Indeed, the
moral model of addiction, based in folk psychological intuition, is inconsistent with scien-
tific understandings both of normal decision-making (Dayan 2007; Glockner 2007; Gold
& Shadlen 2007; Koechlin & Hyafil 2007; Kable & Glimcher 2009; Cisek & Kalaska 2010;
Custers & Aarts 2010) and the pathological decision-making and behavior of addicted
people (Berke & Hyman 2000; Redish 2004; Montague et al. 2004; Everitt & Robbins 2005;
Hyman et al. 2006; Hyman 2007; Ersche et al. 2016; Everitt & Robbins 2016). The only
way out of this impasse at this point in history is for the scientific investigation of addic-
tion to continue to advance, with greater focus on humans, as opposed to animal models,
and to engage more effectively with judges, legal scholars, and policymakers—both to
understand their concerns and constraints, and to provide honest views of the state of the
science. The most to hope for and energetically pursue are effective treatments that inter-
rupt the progression of addiction and provide realistic and reliable alternatives to systems
of criminal justice.
Conclusion
In this chapter I have described a scientific model of addiction that, while still incomplete,
captures evidence-based views of many neurobiologists and psychologists. Understandings
of neurobiological mechanisms that underlie both healthy functioning and pathological
conditions such as addiction will deepen over time, especially with recent technological
advances that, inter alia, have made analysis of genetic risk factors feasible. I have probed
the implications of a neurobiological model of addiction for attributions of moral respon-
sibility and legal culpability, contrasting it with a widely influential moral model that is
grounded in folk psychology. The moral model lacks a scientific basis, but given its origin
in the potent, if misleading, human intuition of a self that is free to make decisions and
exert agency, this model has enormous persuasive power. In contrast, scientific formula-
tions that appeal to complex and invisible neural mechanisms do not automatically influ-
ence public views of addiction or other neural pathologies that affect behavior; nor do
they necessarily change the views lawmakers or courts, who are often sensibly skeptical
of moving too rapidly on such claims. If scientific understandings of behavior are to con-
tribute to more just societies, it is not enough for the science to advance. More specifically,
understandings that are grounded in animal models must be convincingly translated to
the human situation, and the disease state must be made “visible” through well-validated
and convincing markers. As noted, perhaps most convincing to important lay audiences
493
References 493
References
American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders
(5th edn.). Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.
Belin, D., Berson, N., Balado, E., Piazza, P.V., and Deroche-Gamonet, V. (2011). High-novelty preference
rats are predisposed to compulsive cocaine self-administration. Neuropsychopharmacology, 36,
569–579.
Berke J.D. and Hyman, S.E. (2000). Addiction, dopamine, and the molecular mechanisms of memory.
Neuron, 25, 515–532.
Breiter, H.C., Gollub, R.L., Weisskoff, R.M., et al. (1997). Acute effects of cocaine on human brain
activity and emotion. Neuron, 19, 591–611.
Caplan, A. (2008). Denying autonomy in order to create it: the paradox of forcing treatment upon
addicts. Addiction, 103, 1919–1921.
Cisek, P. and Kalaska, J.F. (2010). Neural mechanisms for interacting with a world full of action choices.
Annual Review of Neuroscience, 33, 269–298.
Conrad, P. and Schneider, J.W. (1992). Deviance and Medicalization: From Badness to Sickness,
Expanded Ed. St. Louis, MO: Mosby.
Custers, R. and Aarts, H. (2010). The unconscious will: how the pursuit of goals operates outside of
conscious awareness. Science, 329, 47–50.
Dagher, A. and Robbins T.W. (2009). Personality, addiction, dopamine: insights from Parkinson’s
disease. Neuron, 61, 505–510.
Dayan, P. (2007). The role of value systems in decision making. In: Engel, C. and Singer, W. (Eds.) Better
Than Conscious? Decision Making, the Human Mind, and Implications for Institutions, pp.51–70.
Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press.
Diederen, K.M., Spncer, T., Vestergaard, M.D., Fletcher, P.C., and Schultz, W. (2016). Adaptive
prediction error decoding in human midbrain and striatum facilitates behavioral adaptation and
learning efficiency. Neuron, 90, 1127–1138.
Dunham, Y., Chen, E.E., and Banaji, M.R. (2013). Two signatures of implicit intergroup
attitudes: developmental invariance and early enculturation. Psychological Science, 24, 860–868.
Ersche, K.D., Gillian, C.M., Simon Jones, P., et al. (2016). Carrots and sticks fail to change behavior in
cocaine addiction. Science, 352, 1468–1471.
Everitt, B.J. and Robbins, T.W. (2005). Neural systems of reinforcement for drug addiction: from
actions to habits to compulsion. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 1481–1489.
Everitt, B.J. and Robbins, T.W. (2016). Drug addiction: updating actions to habits to compulsions ten
years on. Annual Review of Psychology, 67, 23–50.
Fenno, L., Yizhar, O., and Deisseroth, K. (2011). The development and application of optogenetics.
Annual Review of Neuroscience, 34, 389–412.
Ferenczi, E.A., Zalocusky, K.A., Liston, C., et al. (2016). Prefrontal cortical regulation of brainwide
circuit dynamics and reward-related behavior. Science 351, 42–54.
Gallagher, M., McMahan, R.W., and Schoenbaum, G. (1999). Orbitofrontal cortex and representation
of incentive value in associative learning. Journal of Neuroscience, 19, 6610–6614.
Glockner, A. (2007). How evolution outwits bounded rationality. The efficient interaction of automatic
and deliberate processes in decision making and implications for institutions. In: Engel, C. and
49
Singer, W. (Eds.) Better Than Conscious? Decision Making, the Human Mind, and Implications for
Institutions, pp 259–284. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Gold, J.I. and Shadlen, M.N. (2007). The neural basis of decision making. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 30, 535–574.
Goldstein, R.Z. and Volkow, N.D. (2011). Dysfunction of the prefrontal cortex in addiction: neuroimaging
findings and clinical implications. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 12, 652–669.
Graybiel, A.M. (2008). Habits, rituals, and the evaluative brain. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 31,
359–387.
Haggard, P. (2008). Human volition: towards a neuroscience of will. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9,
934–946.
Hall, W., Capps, B., and Carter, A. (2008). The use of depot naltrexone under legal coercion: the case
for caution. Addiction, 103, 1922–1924.
Heyman, G.M. (2010). Addiction: A Disorder of Choice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hser, Y.I., Hoffman, V., Grella, C.E., and Anglin, M.D. (2001). A 33-year follow-up of narcotics addicts.
Archives of General Psychiatry, 58, 503–508.
Hyman, S.E. (2007). The neurobiology of addiction: implications for voluntary control of behavior.
American Journal of Bioethics, 7, 8–11.
Hyman, S.E., Malenka, R.C., and Nestler, E.J. (2006). Neural mechanisms of addiction: the role of
reward-related learning and memory. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 21, 565–598.
Kable, J.W. and Glimcher, P.W. (2009). The neurobiology of decision: consensus and controversy.
Neuron, 24, 733–745.
Kelley, A.E. and Berridge, K.C. (2002). The neuroscience of natural rewards: relevance to addictive
drugs. Journal of Neuroscience, 22, 3306–3311.
Kenny, P.J. (2011). Reward mechanisms in obesity: new insights and future directions. Neuron, 69,
664–679
Koechlin, E. and Hyafil A. (2007). Anterior prefrontal function and the limits of human decision-
making. Science, 318, 594–598.
Koob G. (2008). A role for brain stress systems in addiction. Neuron, 59, 11–14.
Lee, J.D., Friedman, P.D., Kinlock, T.W., et al. (2016). Extended-release naltrexone to prevent opioid
relapse in criminal justice offenders. New England Journal of Medicine, 374, 1232–1242.
Luescher, C. and Malenka RC. (2011). Drug-evoked synaptic plasticity in addiction: from molecular
changes to circuit remodeling. Neuron, 69, 650–63.
Merikangas, K.R., Stolar, M., and Stevens, D.E., (1998). Familial transmission of substance use
disorders. Archives of General Psychiatry, 55, 973–979.
Miller E.K. and Cohen, J.D. (2001). An integrative theory of prefrontal cortex function. Annual Review
of Neuroscience, 24, 167–202.
Montague, P.R., Hyman, S.E., and Cohen, J.D. (2004). Computational roles for dopamine in
behavioural control. Nature, 431, 760–767.
Moreno, M., Economidou, D., Mar, A.C., et al. (2013). Divergent effects of D2/3 receptor activation
in the nucleus accumbens core and shell on impulsivity and locomotor activity in high and low
impulsive rats. Psychopharmacology (Berlin), 228, 19–30.
Morse, S.J. (2006). Brain overclaim syndrome. Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law, 3, 397–412.
Morse, S.J. (2008). Determinism and the death of folk psychology: two challenges to responsibility from
neuroscience. Minnesota Journal of Law, Science, and Technology, 9, 1.
495
References 495
Nestler, E.J., Hyman, S.E., Holtzman, D., and Malenka, R.J. (2015). Molecular
Neuropharmacology: Foundation for Clinical Neuroscience. New York: McGraw Hill.
Pascoli, V., Terrier, J., Hiver, A. and Luscher, C. (2015). Sufficiency of mesolimbic dopamine neuron
stimulation for the progression to addiction. Neuron, 88, 1054–1066.
Redish, A.D. (2004). Addiction as a computational process gone awry. Science, 306, 1944–1947.
Robbins, T.W. and Clark, L. (2015). Behavioral addictions. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 30, 66–72.
Robins, L.N., Helzer, J.E., and Davis, D.H. (1975) Narcotic use in southeast Asia and afterward. An
interview study of 898 Vietnam returnees. Archives of General Psychiatry, 32, 955–961.
Robinson, S., Sandstrom, S.M., Denenberg, V.H., and Palmiter, R.D. (2005). Distinguishing whether
dopamine regulates liking, wanting, and/or learning about rewards. Behavioral Neuroscience, 199,
336–341.
Satel, S.L. (1999). What should we expect from drug abusers? Psychiatric Services, 50, 861.
Satel, S. and Lillienfeld, S.O. (2013). Brainwashed: The Seductive Appeal of Mindless Neuroscience.
New York: Basic Books.
Schoenbaum, G., Roesch, M.R., and Stalnaker, T.A. (2006). Orbitofrontal cortex, decision-making and
drug addiction. Trends in Neurosciences, 29, 116–124.
Schultz, W. (2006). Behavioral theories and the neurophysiology of reward. Annual Review of
Psychology, 57, 87–115.
Schultz W., Dayan P., and Montague, P.R. (1997). A neural substrate of prediction and reward. Science,
275, 1593–1599.
Shaham, Y., Erb, S., and Stewart, J. (2000). Stress-induced relapse to heroin and cocaine seeking in
rats: a review. Brain Research. Brain Research Reviews, 33, 13–33.
Stolier, R.M. and Freeman, J.B. (2016). Neural pattern similarity reveals the inherent intersection of
social categories. Nature Neuroscience, 19, 795–797.
Sullivan, P.F., Daly, M.J., and O’Donovan, M. (2012). Genetic architectures of psychiatric disorders: the
emerging picture and its implications. Nature Reviews Genetics, 13, 537–551.
Thorgeirsson, T.E., Gudbjartsson, D.F., Surakka, I., et al. (2010). Sequence variants at CHRNB3-
CHRNA6 and CYP2A6 affect smoking behavior. Nature Genetics, 42, 448–453.
Tiffany, S.T. (1990). A cognitive model of drug urges and drug-use behavior: role of automatic and
nonautomatic processes. Psychological Review, 97,147–168.
Traynor v. Turnage and McKelvey v. Turnage (1988). 485 US 535; 108 S. Ct. 1372.
Tsuang, M.T., Lyons, M.J., Eisen, S.A., et al. (1996). Genetic influences on DSM-III-R drug abuse and
dependence: a study of 3,372 twin pairs. American Journal of Medical Genetics, 67, 473–477.
Valenstein, E. (1986). Great and Desperate Cures: The Rise and Decline of Psychosurgery and Other
Radical Treatments for Mental Illness. New York: Basic Books.
Volkow, N.D., Wang, G.J., Tomasi, D., and Baler, R.D. (2013). The addictive dimension of obesity.
Biological Psychiatry, 73, 811–818.
Walker, D.M., Cates, H.M., Heller, E.A., and Nestler, E.J. (2015). Regulation of chromatin states by
drugs of abuse. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 30, 112–121.
Wallis, J.D. (2007). Orbitofrontal cortex and its contribution to decision-making. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 30, 31–56.
Wegner, D.M. (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wegner, D.M. (2003). The mind’s best trick: how we experience conscious will. Trends in Cognitive
Science, 7, 65–70.
496
Wolf, M.E. (2016). Synaptic mechanisms underlying persistent cocaine craving. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 17, 351–365.
World Health Organization (1992). The ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioural Disorders.
Geneva: World Health Organization.
Xie, J. and Padoa-Schioppa, C. (2016). Neuronal remapping and circuit persistence in economic
decisions. Nature Neuroscience, 19, 855–861.
497
Chapter 25
Introduction
It has been two decades since Alan Leshner, then director of the US National Institute on
Drug Abuse (NIDA), published his seminal paper in Science declaring that “addiction is
a brain disease, and it matters” (emphasis added) (Leshner 1997). According to Leshner,
the chronic use of addictive substances flicked a neurochemical switch in the brain that
made it very difficult for addicted people to stop using drugs. The brain disease model of
addiction (BDMA) professed to explain the high rates of relapse among people treated
for addiction.
Leshner was not simply outlining the empirical case for why drug addiction is a brain
disease; he was laying the groundwork for a clinical and policy agenda to transform the
way in which addiction was treated by healthcare professionals, policymakers and leg-
islators, and the general public. He argued that the BDMA would deliver more effective
medical treatments for addiction that would be covered by health insurance and thereby
be more readily accessible to addicted people (Leshner 1997). The brain disease view was
also intended to convince a skeptical public that addiction was a real psychiatric disorder
and that addicted people suffered from a condition that warranted more humane medi-
cal treatment, rather than being morally weak or bad people who should be punished
either via incarceration or informally through stigmatization and social discrimination.
These changes in public understanding, he argued, would lead to a greater investment in
addiction treatment services and less reliance on punitive approaches to drug use and
addiction.
Over the last 20 years, Nora Volkow, current NIDA director, and others have expanded
this agenda. They have appealed to a growing body of neuroimaging research that argues
that the brains of people with an addiction have been hijacked by their drug (Dackis &
O’Brien 2005; Baler & Volkow 2006). This view has been very influential, particularly in
the United States, given that NIDA funds over 85% of addiction research. In 2014, Michael
Botticelli, then acting and now director of the US Office on National Drug Control Policy,
declared “decades of research have demonstrated that addiction is a brain disorder—one
498 4
that can be prevented and treated” (Botticelli 2014). The BDMA has also been widely
promoted in leading science journals (Volkow & Li 2004; Volkow et al. 2016a) and was
endorsed in an editorial in the UK journal, Nature (Editorial 2014). The American Society
of Addiction Medicine has also recently redefined addiction as a “primary, chronic dis-
ease of brain reward, motivation, memory, and related circuitry” (American Society of
Addiction Medicine 2011).
The notion that the brains of addicted individuals have been so altered to prevent them
from choosing not to use their drug of addiction has significant ethical implications. It
has been used to:
◆ justify the use of greater coercion or mandated treatment to support those who lack
the autonomy to make decisions to support themselves (Caplan 2008)
◆ suggest that addicted people lack the decision-making capacity to freely consent to
research or treatment that involves the administration of their drug of addiction
(Charland 2002; Cohen et al. 2002), or its agonist (Carter & Hall 2008a)
◆ support the use of invasive and high-risk interventions such as brain surgery (e.g.,
deep brain stimulation or ablative psychosurgery) to correct the brain dysfunction that
is believed to underpin addiction (Krack et al. 2010; Luigjes et al. 2012).
We have addressed these important ethical implications of a brain disease model else-
where (Carter & Hall 2008a, 2008b, 2011; Hall et al. 2008; Carter et al. 2011). In this chap-
ter, we examine the evidence supporting the claim that addiction is a brain disease and
we assess whether this view has lived up to its promises. We also examine recent research
on the impact that a BDMA has had on (1) public views of people with an addiction, and
specifically whether it has reduced addiction-related stigma; (2) the way that people with
an addiction view their own behavior and drug use, or engage in treatment; and (3) public
health policies to reduce the harms of drug use. We explore a reframing of neuroscience
research of addiction that takes into account the impact that the repeated use of addictive
drugs has on the brain while ensuring that we apply these insights in ways that optimize
public health policies to reduce the harms of drug use and addiction.
Cingulate gyrus
Striatum
Prefrontal
cortex
Substantia nigra
Nucleus
accumbens
Ventral tegmental area
Figure 25.1 Projections from the midbrain to the nucleus accumbens (NAcc) and forebrain.
Dopaminergic neurons from the ventral tegmental area (VTA) and substantia nigra project to
the central reward area, the NAcc, and to the cortical areas primarily responsible for making
decisions, such as whether to use drugs (e.g., the prefrontal cortex (PFC), and the anterior
cingulate gyrus (aCG)).
Reproduced with permission of Annual Review of Neuroscience, Volume 29, Issue 1, Steven E. Hyman, Robert C.
Malenka, Eric J. Nestler, ’Neural Mechanisms of Addiction: Role of Reward-Related Learning and Memory’,
pp. 565–598, DOI: 10.1146/annurev.neuro.29.051605.113009 © by Annual Reviews, http://www.annualreviews.org.
chronic drug use acting on the brains of genetically vulnerable individuals produces
addiction (Kendler et al. 2012).
BDMA (e.g., Volkow & Li 2004; Dackis and O’Brien 2005; Volkow & Koob 2015; Volkow
& Morales 2015; Volkow et al. 2016a). In these articles they assert that addiction is a
chronic, relapsing brain disease that hijacks behavior; any qualifications are relegated to
supplementary material (Volkow et al. 2016b).
This acknowledgment has important implications for how clinicians, healthcare profes-
sionals, and policymakers discuss addiction and argue for its treatment and policies. We
believe that advocates of the BDMA cannot continue to equate the lifetime prevalence of
addictive disorders with the prevalence of the severe and chronic addictive disorders that
appear to fit the BDMA. Nor can they argue for policy initiatives and treatment interven-
tions that assume that the majority of addicted individuals are suffering from a chronic
and relapsing disease that robs them of their ability to control their drug use. Although
they state that the BDMA only applies to a minority of individuals with the most severe
forms of addiction (Volkow et al. 2016b), Volkow and colleagues still cite estimates of the
prevalence of lifetime and past year addiction from epidemiological surveys as if these
were estimates of the prevalence of addiction of sufficient severity to make a brain disease
a plausible hypothesis (Volkow et al. 2016a).
epidemiological evidence reviewed in the previous section (“How strong is the evidence
for a brain disease model of addiction?”).
Neuroimaging studies of addiction are typically case–control studies that report
statistically significant differences in brain function and structure between groups of
severely addicted and nonaddicted people. These averaged differences do not reflect all
addicted people—many addicted individuals will not display these deficits while some
nonaddicted controls will. These studies also do not tell us whether addiction is a cause
or a consequence of differences in brain structure (Ersche et al. 2013). Differences in
patterns of activation in brain scans between addicted and nonaddicted people also
do not prove that drug use in people with an addiction is compulsive (Hyman 2007).
The fact that reduced activity in frontal brain regions is modestly correlated with self-
reported craving does not demonstrate that drug use is driven by impulses that are
irresistible.
Volkow and colleagues acknowledge that neuroimaging technologies have been unable
to distinguish between addicted and nonaddicted individuals, but optimistically place
this failure at the feet of current technological limitations, a lack of understanding of how
the human brain works, and the complexity of the neurobiological changes triggered by
drugs and the heterogeneity of substance use disorders (Volkow et al. 2016b). However,
this failure may also reflect the fact that there are other important psychological and social
factors at play in addiction. In the absence of acknowledgment of this failure, the role
played by the brain in individual outcomes is overestimated.
While we know from twin and adoption studies that addiction runs in families and that
genetics accounts for a significant portion of this risk, this pattern of risk is not explained
by a small number of specific genetic or molecular pathways. Very large numbers of alleles
are involved in the susceptibility to addiction and individually they are weak predictors
of addiction risk (Kendler et al. 2012). Risk scores based on multiple risk alleles do not
predict addiction risk any better than simple family history information (e.g., number of
smoking parents) (Gartner et al. 2009). Risk involves a complex and unpredictable inter-
action between genetics and environmental events, as well as a possible constellation of
gene–gene and epigenetic effects.
Our analysis suggests that the neuroscience research does not uncritically support the
more modest version of the BDMA. We next examine whether the BDMA has delivered
the clinical, social, and policy benefits promised and propose an alternative account of the
relevance of neuroscience research to addiction.
Twenty years on: Has the brain disease model of addiction delivered? 503
role that these outcomes have played in garnering support for the BDMA, it is worth ask-
ing whether the BDMA has lived up to its promise.
construct that involves several elements. Structural stigma can lead to institutionalized
discrimination that deprives individuals with certain disorders of effective healthcare.
Social stigma involves the interpersonal victimization or discrimination against an indi-
vidual that may discourage someone from seeking treatment. It can also exacerbate inter-
nalized or self-stigma, a collection of negative attitudes toward oneself that can lead to a
loss of self-esteem and poorer health behaviors, such as continued or escalated drug use
to escape negative thoughts and feelings.
A major benefit claimed for the BDMA is that its public acceptance will reduce
stigma and discrimination against people with addictions. A similar hope has long
been expressed in mental health more generally (Pescosolido et al. 2010; Sartorius
2010). The optimistic assumption is that the public will be more accepting of people
with mental illnesses, such as depression and addiction, if they can be convinced that
these are the result of biological, specifically neurobiological changes that produce
the aberrant behavior, and hence that their sufferers have real diseases (Pescosolido
et al. 2010).
Proponents of the BDMA do not provide sufficient evidence to support this claim and
have ignored a growing body of social science survey evidence that suggests otherwise.
Numerous social science surveys have found that increased acceptance of a biological
basis for schizophrenia and alcohol dependence has had minimal impact on stigmatiza-
tion, and may in fact increase rather than decrease stigma (Angermeyer & Matschinger
2005; Pescosolido et al. 2010; Reavley & Jorm 2011; Kvaale et al. 2013). One large study of
the attitudes of US citizens over a 10-year period found that while acceptance of neuro-
biological and genetic causes of addiction and schizophrenia, two of the most highly stig-
matized mental illnesses, increased substantially over this period, stigmatizing attitudes
were unchanged. Some research suggests that addicted individuals often see the BDMA as
adding to the stigma that they experience by reinforcing public fears that their behavior is
an uncontrollable consequence of permanent changes in their brains. We have also found
mixed support for the BDMA among Australian clinicians who treat addiction (Bell et al.
2014; Carter et al. 2014).
Reduced stigmatization and discrimination against people with an addiction is a desir-
able outcome, but we doubt that acceptance of a BDMA will achieve this. Stigma is a
complex construct that involves a range of different stakeholders (e.g., clinicians, policy-
makers, the public, and the individual), each of whom will require a specific and targeted
approach to reduce stigma and its negative consequences (Corrigan et al. 2014). There
is a growing realization that alternative approaches are needed to reduce the stigma of
mental illness, such as those employed by the nonprofit organization Bring Change 2
Mind, that target emotional processes to reduce social distance and fear (Corrigan et al.
2007; Corrigan & Shapiro 2010; Sartorius 2010). Future campaigns will need to identify
evidence-based ways of reducing social distance and fear, rather than relying on plausible
but misplaced suppositions that simply educating the public about the impact of drug use
on the brain will reduce stigma.
50
Twenty years on: Has the brain disease model of addiction delivered? 505
These positives were offset by views about the potentially adverse impacts of the BDMA
on the treatment and drug use of a subpopulation of addicted individuals. The concern
was that it could hinder addicted individuals’ behavior change, reduce their willingness
to enter treatment, undermine their ability to reduce drug use, and provide them with an
excuse for not changing their behavior (Bell et al. 2014). These results are consistent with
findings from a recent study of opioid-dependent individuals receiving opioid substitu-
tion treatment (Netherland 2011).
research budget, 41% was allocated to basic and clinical neuroscience and 17% to phar-
macotherapies (NIDA 2014). Social and public health research forms a small part of the
24% allocated to epidemiological research (NIDA 2014). A National Academy of Science
committee highlighted in 2001 that the National Institutes of Health had seriously under-
invested in drug policy evaluation (National Research Council 2001). In a recent response
to criticisms of the policy payoffs of the BDMA, Volkow and colleagues explicitly stated
the greater need for even further investment in the search for medical treatments of
addiction, despite acknowledging the failure to develop new effective treatments (Volkow
et al. 2016b). No mention was made of increasing investment in public policy research.
It is important to emphasize that clinical treatment and population-level approaches
are not mutually exclusive; we are not arguing for either one or the other. The obser-
vation that science should not ignore the very significant benefits of population-level
approaches does not preclude the need to identify more effective treatments for addicted
people. Society can, and should, look for more effective medical treatments of addiction.
But this should not be at the expense of maintaining attention to more broadly effective
population-level approaches for reducing drug use and preventing harm (Hall et al. 2015).
We would like to see greater advocacy for increasing access to existing treatments rather
than for a BDMA that is of uncertain utility and acceptability to the people who are sup-
posedly its chief beneficiaries.
Volkow and colleagues claim that the BDMA has contributed to at least two policy
milestones in recent years: (1) passing of the Mental Health Parity and Addiction Equity
Act as part of the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act that ensures that addiction
treatment is covered by medical insurance; and (2) justification for increasing the drink-
ing age to 21 years (Volkow et al. 2016b). It is difficult to assess whether the BDMA led to
the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act as part of US nationalized healthcare per
se, however. A fair appreciation of the factors that contributed to the passage of this Act
would require social and historical research on the drivers of this policy change.
drug use and addiction, and is not a major influence on our concern for people with an
addiction (Meurk et al. 2016a).
Originators and current proponents of the BDMA uphold the forced choice of the
1990s, namely, that rejection of addiction as a chronic, relapsing brain disease equates
to an acceptance of the moral view of addiction according to which addicted people can
simply stop using (Leshner 1997; Volkow & Koob 2015). Critics can accept that there is
value in neurobiological and genetic research on addiction but still reject the narrow view
that addiction is a brain disease and be skeptical that promoting this view will overcome
many of the limitations in the treatment of addicted individuals in society. As we have
outlined already, we do not believe that telling people with an addiction that they have a
brain disease that involves persistent rewiring of their brain that drives them to drug use
will necessarily lead to better health outcomes.
It has recently been claimed that there is a consensus view among scientists and clini-
cians that addiction is a brain disease (American Society of Addiction Medicine 2011;
Editorial 2014). There has been little empirical research to test this claim. In a small study
of Australian neuroscientists and clinicians, less than one-third strongly endorsed the
BDMA. A more reasonable and modified argument for the relevance of neurobiology
to addiction would involve arguing that addiction can be, but is not always, a chronic,
relapsing disorder; that people who develop chronic forms of addiction often require sus-
tained treatment to become and remain abstinent; that this treatment often has to address
the biological effects of sustained heavy drug use on brain and body; and that drug treat-
ments can certainly assist in withdrawing from drugs and in maintaining abstinence after
cessation of use. This view makes it clearer that the drug treatment of addiction is often
only the beginning in addressing the many challenges that addicted people face in recov-
ering and remaining abstinent, namely, securing useful employment, making friends who
are not drug users, repairing damaged family relationships, and overcoming the stigma
and social consequences of having a criminal record.
Conclusion 509
exercise, brain training, or cognitive exercises, to rewire and relearn more adaptive habits
(Lewis 2015).
Conclusion
The chronic, relapsing brain disease model seems most plausible when used to describe
the minority of severely addicted people who fail to quit using drugs and who present
themselves, or are coerced by others, into treatment in middle adult life. These individu-
als comprise a minority of those who meet diagnostic criteria for addiction. The BDMA
cannot be used to describe the vast majority of individuals who receive an addiction diag-
nosis at some point during their lives.
We conclude that the BDMA has also not delivered on its promises. We are yet to see
substantially more effective treatments for drug addictions and the impact of the BDMA
in reducing stigma and improving access and funding to appropriate treatment services
has been modest. We share many of the hopes of those who advocate for the BDMA, such
as the delivery of more effective treatment and less punitive responses to addicted people.
But addiction is a complex biological, psychological, and social disorder that requires
a combined clinical and public health approach (Carter & Hall 2012). The search for
technological cures of addiction should not distract from increasing access to currently
available psychosocial and drug treatments for addiction, which the majority of addicted
individual are still unable to access, or developing simpler, cheaper, and more efficient
population-based policies that discourage the whole population from smoking tobacco,
drinking heavily, or abusing illicit drugs.
Our rejection of the BDMA should not be misinterpreted as a defense of the moral
model of addiction (Carter & Hall 2012) or the denial of the value of neuroscience.
Neuroscience research on addiction has provided useful insights into the neurobiology of
decision-making, motivation, and behavioral control. These insights help to understand
how chronic use of addictive drugs can impair cognitive and motivational processes and
may partially explain why some people are more vulnerable than others to developing
an addiction. The challenge for all addiction researchers is to incorporate the emerging
insights of neuroscience research into those provided by economics, epidemiology, soci-
ology, psychology, and political science so the harms caused by drug misuse and all forms
of addiction can be reduced.
Neuroscience research can be extremely persuasive. It can influence expectations of
the clinical effectiveness of treatments (Racine et al. 2007) and the understanding of the
self in health and disease (Racine et al. 2010; Rose N.S. & Abi-Rached 2013). Care is
needed in how clinicians, policymakers, and other relevant stakeholders communicate
the results of neuroscience research on addiction (Satel & Lilienfeld 2013). It should not
be assumed that messages about diseased brains will always lead to increased treatment-
seeking and reduced drug use. Messages about neuroscience research must be tailored to
individuals to foster better choices and health outcomes and avoid negative consequences.
This requires evidence on how addicted individuals interpret this research. More work is
510 5
References
Ahmed, S.H. (2010). Validation crisis in animal models of drug addiction: beyond non-disordered drug
use toward drug addiction. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 35, 172–184.
Ahmed, S.H. (2012). The science of making drug-addicted animals. Neuroscience, 211, 107–125.
Ahmed, S.H., Lenoir, M., and Guillem, K. (2013). Neurobiology of addiction versus drug use driven by
lack of choice. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 23, 1–7.
Alexander, B.K., Coambs, R.B., and Hadaway, P.F. (1978). The effect of housing and gender on
morphine self-administration in rats. Psychopharmacology, 58, 175–179.
American Society of Addiction Medicine (2011). Public Policy Statement: Definition of Addiction (Long
Version). Chevy Chase, MD: American Society of Addiction Medicine.
Angermeyer, M.C. and Matschinger, H. (2005). Labeling–stereotype–discrimination. An investigation
of the stigma process. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology, 40, 391–395.
Bachman, J.G., Wadsworth, K.N., O’Malley, P.M., Johnston, L.D. and Schulenberg, J. (1997). Smoking,
Drinking, and Drug Use in Young Adulthood: The Impacts of New Freedoms and New Responsibilities.
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Baler, R.D. and Volkow, N.D. (2006). Drug addiction: the neurobiology of disrupted self-control.
Trends in Molecular Medicine, 12, 559–566.
Bell, S., Carter, A., Mathews, R., Gartner, C., Lucke, J., and Hall, W. (2014). Views of addiction
neuroscientists and clinicians on the clinical impact of a “brain disease model of addiction”.
Neuroethics, 7, 19–27.
Botticelli, M. (2014). National Blueprint for Drug Policy Reform Released Today in Roanoke, VA. Office
of National Drug Control Policy Media Release.
Buchman, D.Z., Skinner, W., and Illes, J. (2010). Negotiating the relationship between addiction, ethics,
and brain science. AJOB Neuroscience, 1, 36–45.
Caplan, A. (2008). Denying autonomy in order to create it: the paradox of forcing treatment upon
addicts. Addiction, 103, 1919–1921.
Carter, A. and Hall, W. (2008a). Informed consent to opioid agonist maintenance
treatment: recommended ethical guidelines. International Journal of Drug Policy, 19, 79–89.
Carter, A. and Hall, W. (2008b). The issue of consent in research that administers drugs of addiction to
addicted persons. Accountability in Research, 15, 209–225.
Carter, A. and Hall, W. (2011). Proposals to trial deep brain stimulation to treat addiction are
premature. Addiction, 106, 235–237.
Carter, A. and Hall, W. (2012). Addiction Neuroethics: The Promises and Perils of Neuroscience Research
on Addiction. London: Cambridge University Press.
Carter, A., Bell, E., Racine, E., and Hall, W. (2011). Ethical issues raised by proposals to treat addiction
using deep brain stimulation. Neuroethics, 4, 129–142.
Carter, A., Mathews, R., Bell, S., Lucke, J., and Hall, W. (2014). Control and Responsibility in Addicted
Individuals: What do Addiction Neuroscientists and Clinicians Think? Neuroethics, 7, 205–214.
Chapman, S. and MacKenzie, R. (2010). The global research neglect of unassisted smoking
cessation: causes and consequences. PLoS Medicine, 7, e1000216.
Charland, L.C. (2002). Cynthia’s dilemma: consenting to heroin prescription. American Journal of
Bioethics, 2, 37–47.
51
References 511
Cohen, M.J.M., Jasser, S., Herron, P.D., and Margolis, C.G. (2002). Ethical
perspectives: opioid treatment of chronic pain in the context of addiction. Clinical Journal
of Pain, 18, S99-S 107.
Corrigan, P.W. and Shapiro, J.R. (2010). Measuring the impact of programs that challenge the public
stigma of mental illness. Clinical Psychology Review, 30, 907–922.
Corrigan, P.W., Larson, J., Sells, M., Niessen, N., and Watson, A. C. (2007). Will filmed presentations
of education and contact diminish mental illness stigma? Community Mental Health Journal, 43,
171–181.
Corrigan, P.W., Druss, B.G., and Perlick, D.A. (2014). The impact of mental illness stigma on
seeking and participating in mental health care. Psychological Science in the Public Interest,
15, 37–70.
Cunningham, J.A., Sobell, L.C., and Chow, V.M. (1993). What’s in a label? The effects of substance
types and labels on treatment considerations and stigma. Journal of Studies on Alcohol, 54, 693–699.
Dackis, C. and O’Brien, C. (2005). Neurobiology of addiction: treatment and public policy
ramifications. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 1431–1436.
Davies, J.B. (1998). Pharmacology versus social process: competing or complementary views on the
nature of addiction? Pharmacology & Therapeutics, 80, 265–275.
Dejong, W. and Blanchette, J. (2014). Case closed: research evidence on the positive public health
impact of the age 21 minimum legal drinking age in the United States. Journal of Studies on Alcohol
and Drugs, Supplement, 108–115.
Doran, C.M., Hall, W.D., Shakeshaft, A.P., Vos, T., and Cobiac, L.J. (2010). Alcohol policy reform in
Australia: what can we learn from the evidence. Medical Journal of Australia, 192, 468–470.
Editorial (2014). Animal farm. Nature, 506, 5.
Ersche, K.D., Williams, G.B., Robbins, T.W., and Bullmore, E.T. (2013). Meta-analysis of structural
brain abnormalities associated with stimulant drug dependence and neuroimaging of addiction
vulnerability and resilience. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 23, 615–624.
Feltenstein, M.W. and See, R.E. (2008). The neurocircuitry of addiction: an overview. British Journal of
Pharmacology, 154, 261–274.
Gartner, C.E., Barendregt, J.J., and Hall, W. (2009). Multiple genetic tests for susceptibility to smoking
do not outperform simple family history. Addiction, 104, 118–126.
Hall, W., Madden, P., and Lynskey, M. (2002). The genetics of tobacco use: methods, findings and
policy implications. Tobacco Control, 11, 119–124.
Hall, W., Capps, B., and Carter, A. (2008). The use of depot naltrexone under legal coercion: the case
for caution. Addiction, 103, 1922–1924.
Hall, W. and Gartner, C. (2011). Ethical and policy issues in using vaccines to treat and prevent cocaine
and nicotine dependence. Current Opinion in Psychiatry, 24, 191–196.
Hall, W., Carter, A., and Forlini, C. (2015). The brain disease model of addiction: is it supported by the
evidence and has it delivered on its promises? The Lancet Psychiatry, 2, 105–110.
Heyman, G. (2009). Addiction: A Disorder of Choice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hyman, S.E. (2007). The neurobiology of addiction: implications for voluntary control of behavior.
American Journal of Bioethics, 7, 8–11.
Hyman, S.E., Malenka, R.C., and Nestler, E.J. (2006). Neural mechanisms of addiction: the role of
reward-related learning and memory. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 29, 565–598.
Kalant, H. (2010). What neurobiology cannot tell us about addiction. Addiction, 105, 780–789.
Kendler, K.S., Chen, X., Dick, D., et al. (2012). Recent advances in the genetic epidemiology and
molecular genetics of substance use disorders. Nature Neuroscience, 15, 181–189.
512 5
Kilmer, B., Nicosia, N., Heaton, P., and Midgette, G. (2013). Efficacy of frequent monitoring with swift,
certain, and modest sanctions for violations: insights from South Dakota’s 24/7 sobriety project.
American Journal of Public Health, 103, e37–e43.
Kincaid, H. and Sullivan, J.A. (2010). Medical models of addiction. In: Ross, D., Kincaid, H., Spurrett,
D., and Collins, P. (Eds.) What is Addiction?, pp.353–376. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kleiman, M. (2009). When Brute Force Fails: How to Have Less Crime and Less Punishment. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Koob, G.F. and Le Moal, M. (2006). Neurobiology of Addiction. New York: Academic Press.
Koob, G F., Lloyd, G.K., and Mason, B.J. (2009). Development of pharmacotherapies for drug
addiction: a Rosetta Stone approach. Nature Reviews Drug Discovery, 8, 500–515.
Kosten, T.R., Domingo, C.B., Shorter, D., et al. (2014). Vaccine for cocaine dependence: a
randomized double-blind placebo-controlled efficacy trial. Drug and Alcohol Dependence,
140, 42–47.
Krack, P., Hariz, M.I., Baunez, C., Guridi, J., and Obeso, J.A. (2010). Deep brain stimulation: from
neurology to psychiatry? Trends in Neurosciences, 33, 474–484.
Kvaale, E.P., Haslam, N., and Gottdiener, W. H. (2013). The “side effects” of medicalization: a meta-
analytic review of how biogenetic explanations affect stigma. Clinical Psychology Review, 33,
782–794.
Lam, D.C.K., Salkovskis, P.M., and Warwick, H.M.C. (2005). An experimental investigation of the
impact of biological versus psychological explanations of the cause of “mental illness”. Journal of
Mental Health, 14, 453–464.
Leshner, A.I. (1997). Addiction is a brain disease, and it matters. Science, 278, 45–47.
Lewis, M. (2015). The Biology of Desire: Why Addiction is Not a Disease. New York: Scribe Publications.
Lingford-Hughes, A.R., Welch, S., Peters, L., and Nutt, D.J. (2012). BAP updated guidelines:
evidence-based guidelines for the pharmacological management of substance abuse, harmful
use, addiction and comorbidity: recommendations from BAP. Journal of Psychopharmacology, 26,
899–952.
Luigjes, J., van den Brink, W., Feenstra, M., et al. (2012). Deep brain stimulation in addiction: a review
of potential brain targets. Molecular Psychiatry, 17, 572–583.
McLellan, A.T., Lewis, D.C., O’Brien, C.P., and Kleber, H.D. (2000). Drug dependence, a chronic
medical illness: implications for treatment, insurance, and outcomes evaluation. JAMA, 284,
1689–1695.
Merikangas, K.R. and Risch, N. (2003). Genomic priorities and public health. Science, 302, 599–601.
Meurk, C., Hall, W., Morphett, K., Carter, A., and Lucke, J. (2013). What does “acceptance” mean?
Public reflections on the idea that addiction is a brain disease. Biosocieties, 8, 491–506.
Meurk, C., Fraser, D., Weier, M., Lucke, J., Carter, A., and Hall, W. (2016a). Assessing the place of
neurobiological explanations in accounts of a family member’s addiction. Drug and Alcohol Review,
35(4), 461–469.
Meurk, C., Morphett, K., Carter, A., Weier, M., Lucke, J., and Hall, W. (2016b). Scepticism and hope in
a complex predicament: people with addictions deliberate about neuroscience. International Journal
of Drug Policy, 32, 34–43.
Miller, P., Carter, A., and De Groot, F. (2012). Investment and vested interests in neuroscience research
of addiction: Why research ethics requires more than informed consent. In: Carter, A., Hall, W., and
Illes, J. (Eds.) Addiction Neuroethics: The Ethics of Addiction Research and Treatment, pp. 278–301.
New York: Elsevier.
Moyers, T.B. and Miller, W.R. (1993). Therapists’ conceptualizations of alcoholism: Measurement and
implications for treatment decisions. Psychology of Addictive Behaviors, 7, 238.
513
References 513
National Institute on Drug Abuse (2014). Fiscal Year 2015 Budget information—Congressional
justification for National Institute on Drug Abuse. Rockville, MD: National Institute on Drug Abuse.
National Research Council (2001). Informing America’s Policy on Illegal Drugs: What We Don’t Know
Keeps Hurting Us. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Netherland, J. (2011). “We haven’t sliced open anyone’s brain yet”: Neuroscience, embodiment and the
governance of addiction. In: Pickersgill, M. and Van Keulen, I. (Eds.) Sociological Reflections on the
Neurosciences (Advances in Medical Sociology, Volume 13), pp. 153–177. Bingley, UK: Emerald
Group Publishing Limited.
Nutt, D. and Lingford-Hughes, A. (2008). Addiction: the clinical interface. British Journal of
Pharmacology, 154, 397–405.
Pescosolido, B.A., Martin, J.K., Long, J.S., Medina, T.R., Phelan, J., and Link, B. (2010). “A disease
like any other?”: a decade of change in public reactions to schizophrenia, depression, and alcohol
dependence. American Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 1321–1330.
Phelan, J.C., Yang, L.H., and Cruz-Rojas, R. (2006). Effects of attributing serious mental illnesses to
genetic causes on orientations to treatment. Psychiatric Services, 57, 382–387.
Pierce, J.P., Gilpin, E.A., Emery, S.L., White, M.M., Rosbrook, B., and Berry, C. C. (1998). Has the
California tobacco control program reduced smoking? JAMA, 280, 893.
Racine, E., Waldman, S., Palmour, N., Risse, D., and Illes, J. (2007). “Currents of
hope”: neurostimulation techniques in U.S. and U.K. print media. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare
Ethics, 16, 312–316.
Racine, E., Waldman, S., Rosenberg, J., and Illes, J. (2010). Contemporary neuroscience in the media.
Social Science and Medicine, 71, 725–733.
Reavley, N.J. and Jorm, A.F. (2011). Stigmatizing attitudes towards people with mental
disorders: findings from an Australian National Survey of Mental Health Literacy and Stigma.
Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry, 45, 1086–1093.
Reske, M. and Paulus, M.P. (2011). A neuroscientific approach to addiction: ethical issues. In: Illes,
J. and Sahakian, B. (Eds.) Oxford Handbook of Neuroethics, pp. 177–202. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Robins, L.N. (1993). Vietnam veterans’ rapid recovery from heroin addiction: a fluke or normal
expectation? Addiction, 88, 1041–1054.
Rose, G. (1992). The Strategy of Preventive Medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rose, N.S. and Abi-Rached, J.M. (2013). Neuro: The New Brain Sciences and the Management of the
Mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sartorius, N. (2010). Short-lived campaigns are not enough. Nature, 468, 163–165.
Satel, S. (1998). For addicts, force is the best medicine. Wall Street Journal, January 6.
Satel, S. (1999). The fallacies of no-fault addiction. Public Interest, 99, 52–67.
Satel, S. and Lilienfeld, S.O. (2013). Brainwashed: The Seductive Appeal of Mindless Neuroscience.
New York: Perseus Books Group.
Satel, S. and Lilienfeld, S.O. (2014). Addiction and the brain-disease fallacy. Frontiers in Psychiatry,
4, 141.
Varney, S.M., Rohsenow, D.J., Dey, A.N., Myers, M.G., Zwick, W.R., and Monti, P.M. (1995). Factors
associated with help seeking and perceived dependence among cocaine users. American Journal of
Drug and Alcohol Abuse, 21, 81–91.
Volkow, N. and Baler, R. (2014). Addiction science: uncovering neurobiological complexity.
Neuropharmacology, 76, 235–249.’
Volkow, N.D. and Koob, G. (2015). Brain disease model of addiction: why is it so controversial? The
Lancet Psychiatry, 2, 677–679.
514
Volkow, N.D. and Li, T.-K. (2004). Drug addiction: the neurobiology of behaviour gone awry. Nature
Reviews. Neuroscience, 5, 963–970.
Volkow, N.D. and Li, T.-K. (2005). Drugs and alcohol: treating and preventing abuse, addiction and
their medical consequences. Pharmacology & Therapeutics, 108, 3–17.
Volkow, N.D. and Morales, M. (2015). The brain on drugs: from reward to addiction. Cell, 162,
712–725.
Volkow, N.D., Fowler, J.S., Wang, G.J., Swanson, J.M., and Telang, F. (2007). Dopamine in drug abuse
and addiction: results of imaging studies and treatment implications. Archives of Neurology, 64,
1575–1579.
Volkow, N.D., Fowler, J.S., Wang, G.J., Baler, R., and Telang, F. (2009). Imaging dopamine’s role in drug
abuse and addiction. Neuropharmacology, 56(Suppl. 1), 3–8.
Volkow, N.D., Wang, G.-J., Fowler, J.S. and Tomasi, D. (2012). Addiction circuitry in the human brain.
Annual Review of Pharmacology and Toxicology, 52, 321.
Volkow, N.D., Koob, G.F., and McLellan, A.T. (2016a). Neurobiologic advances from the brain disease
model of addiction. New England Journal of Medicine, 374, 363–371.
Volkow, N.D., Koob, G.F., and McLellan, A.T. (2016b). Supplement to: Neurobiologic advances from
the brain disease model of addiction. New England Journal of Medicine, 374(4), 363–371. Available
from: http://www.nejm.org/doi/suppl/10.1056/NEJMra1511480/suppl_file/nejmra1511480_
appendix.pdf [accessed February 9, 2017].
Vrecko, S. (2010). Birth of a brain disease: science, the state and addiction neuropolitics. History of the
Human Sciences, 23, 52–67.
Walker, M.J. (2010). Addiction and self deception: a method for self control? Journal of Applied
Philosophy, 27, 305–319.
White, V., Hill, D., Siahpush, M. and Bobevski, I. (2003). How has the prevalence of cigarette smoking
changed among Australian adults? Trends in smoking prevalence between 1980 and 2001. Tobacco
Control, 12, ii67.
Xu, Z., Hou, B., Gao, Y., He, F. and Zhang, C. (2007). Effects of enriched environment on morphine-
induced reward in mice. Experimental Neurology, 204, 714–719.
51
Chapter 26
Introduction
Concussion is a short-term disturbance in neurological function that is the result of a
traumatic impact to the head. The term is sometimes used interchangeably with mild
traumatic brain injury (MTBI). The Concussion in Sport Group has called concussion
“a complex pathophysiological process affecting the brain, induced by traumatic biome-
chanical forces,” which reflects a “functional” disruption to the brain rather than “struc-
tural” damage (McCrory et al. 2013).
The Centers for Disease Control has estimated that up to 3.8 million sports-related
concussions occur in the United States alone each year, but these events are significantly
under-reported (Daneshvar et al. 2011). It is a common injury in many body contact
sports and its prevalence in this arena has recently garnered attention because of concerns
about the possible long-term effects of these injuries. The focus of this chapter is on con-
cussion injuries in body collision sports. It addresses ethical issues that arise in the diag-
nosis of concussion, debates about the longer-term consequences of repeated concussion
injuries, and the design and implementation of policies that aim to prevent and manage
concussion injuries that occur in the course of sporting matches.
Concussion in football codes
Some football codes exhibit high levels of risk of concussion because they involve repeated
heavy collisions between participants who are running at speed directly at each other. The
prevalence of concussion in amateur and professional Australian Rules football (Makdissi
et al. 2009) and rugby league (Hinton-Bayre et al. 2004) are among the highest of any con-
tact sports. At the high school and collegiate level in the United States, American football
has the highest participation rate among sports and the highest rate of concussion per
thousand playing hours (Daneshvar et al. 2011).
Concussion management policies have become a major priority worldwide for sports
that involve frequent collisions between participants because repeated head trauma has
been associated with long-term cognitive impairments (Guskiewicz et al. 2005), mental
516 5
health problems (Guskiewicz et al. 2007), and some forms of neurological degeneration
(Omalu et al. 2005; McKee et al. 2009, 2013, 2014). Traumatic brain injury (TBI) is the
leading cause of death and disability among children and young adults worldwide, and
approximately one-fifth of all TBI cases occur during sports participation.
Concussion management guidelines have been developed by a number of groups in
an effort to either prevent concussion or to improve its management. These include the
American Academy of Neurology (Giza et al. 2013) and Concussion in Sport Group
(McCrory et al. 2009, 2013). Although procedures for identifying concussion have been
formally implemented in many sports, clinicians are still confronted with conceptual,
empirical, and ethical uncertainty in diagnosing and managing concussion (McNamee
et al. 2016).
Challenges in diagnosis
Diagnosis can be a challenge because there is a long list of potential symptoms and signs
of concussion that reflect disruptions to normal cognition, motor functioning, or affect.
These include, for instance, amnesia, loss of balance, blurred vision, confusion, dizziness,
feeling “in a fog,” or being more emotionally labile. There is no consensus on when a
diagnosis of concussion should be made and there are no specified necessary and suf-
ficient symptoms for the diagnosis, not even the seemingly obvious loss of consciousness
(McNamee et al. 2016).
Brief diagnostic tools have been developed to identify concussion but there is no defini-
tive “concussion test” and so a concussion diagnosis always reflects a clinician’s judgment.
These conceptual uncertainties have the potential to undermine the reliability and valid-
ity of a diagnosis of the presence or absence of concussion. They also affect the validity of
epidemiological data on the prevalence of concussion in different sports, with the likeli-
hood that many cases of concussion go unrecognized.
there is sufficient evidence for a causal relationship between moderate to severe TBI and
Alzheimer’s and Parkinson’s-related dementia. There is also an association between these
conditions and mild TBI when there has been a loss of consciousness (Bazarian et al.
2009). This includes evidence from a large-scale prospective study which found that mild
TBI was an independent risk factor for dementia (Lee et al. 2013). Prospective cohort
studies also find that severe, moderate, and mild TBI are associated with an increased risk
of developing depression (Fann et al. 2004).
There are fewer studies of the specific risks of concussion in athletes but epidemio-
logical studies of players of collision sports have reported similar findings to the studies
of TBI in the general population. Former American footballers who have suffered three
or more concussions reported more mild cognitive impairment, memory problems, and
depression than players without such a history. Retired football players also have an ear-
lier age of onset of Alzheimer’s disease than peers in the general population (Guskiewicz
et al. 2005, 2007) and are three times more likely to die prematurely from neurodegenera-
tive diseases than the general population (Lehman et al. 2012).
The available epidemiological evidence is sufficient to justify prudential policies to
reduce the incidence of concussion in body collision sports. Instead, in the United States,
these policies have been delayed by a narrow debate on whether the cumulative effects of
repeated concussion cause a specific condition known as chronic traumatic encephalopa-
thy (CTE)—a degenerative brain disease in which neurofibrillary tangles of tau protein
are deposited in the brain—that was first described in boxers in the 1920s. Interest in
CTE among American footballers increased after a 2005 postmortem neuropathological
study of a former National Football League (NFL) player found evidence of the condition
(Omalu et al. 2005). Since then, several groups have reported signs of CTE in postmortem
studies of the brains of several dozen former American footballers and a smaller number
of former rugby players and wrestlers (Omalu et al. 2010; McKee et al. 2014).
People who show neuropathological evidence of CTE often reported dementia-like
symptoms, disturbed memory and mood, increased impulsiveness and aggression, and
an increased risk of suicide (McKee et al. 2014). The prevalence of CTE in football players
and other collision sport athletes is unknown but the seriousness of the condition and
high public profile of some of its sufferers have placed the condition at the center of a con-
tentious debate in the United States that has echoes in other countries such as Australia.
The evidence for the hypothesis that repeated head trauma causes CTE comes from
postmortem evidence of the disorder in players with a history of repeated head trauma.
Proponents of the CTE hypothesis assume that the disorder is so rare and so clearly
related to repeated head trauma that these cases are sufficient to establish a causal rela-
tionship. Critics (Gardner et al. 2014) counter that there is no epidemiological evidence
that CTE is more common among football players than in the general population and no
evidence to rule out the role of factors other than concussion, such as genetic vulnerability
to dementia, alcohol and other drug use, and risky behavior outside football. The most
recent consensus statement about such injuries by the 4th International Conference on
Concussion in Sport held in Zurich, November 2012 (McCrory et al. 2013) stated that: “a
518 5
cause and effect relationship has not as yet been demonstrated between CTE and concus-
sions or exposure to contact sports.”
Well-designed, independent, and credible research studies are essential to decide
whether CTE is caused by repeated concussions and head injuries in athletes. But this
shortcoming in the literature on CTE should not detract attention from the larger epide-
miological literature that strongly suggests that repeated head injuries increase the risk of
cognitive impairment, depression, and dementia, whatever the underlying pathological
mechanism.
including concussion. If this stance were taken, then collision sports could argue that
participants play at their own risk and therefore must accept responsibility for any future
health problems that may arise (Partridge & Hall 2015).
If the “play at your own risk” stance were adopted then sporting bodies would need to
ensure that players autonomously decide whether or not to play after being fully informed
about the risks of participation. This would require (1) management of the potential for
coerced consent and the conflicts of interest among players, coaches, trainers, and doctors
that may lead them to circumvent concussion management; and, (2) full acknowledgment
and disclosure of the risks of repeated head injuries by sports governing bodies.
The implicit assumption of current management policies seems to be that the risk of
concussion cannot be eliminated from American football, rugby league, and Australian
Rules football. The goal of these policies is therefore on managing specific instances
of concussion. There are no policies to prevent players from suffering repeated head
trauma during their playing careers. This stance is arguably at odds with the professed
claims of the governing bodies of these sports that they give a high priority to protect-
ing players.
These minimalist policies have often been justified by skepticism about the claim that
concussions can cause serious long-term neurological harm in general and CTE in par-
ticular. Sporting officials have used uncertainty about the causal relationship to delay act-
ing on their professed ethical obligation to protect players from repeated head injuries.
For instance, some medical officers employed by, and researchers with professional links
to, the AFL have described the evidence on the long-term risks of multiple concussions as
“anecdotal” and overhyped by the media (Lane 2012, 2016). In 2012, for example, when
the Chief Medical Officer of the International Rugby Board (IRB) was asked whether
repeated concussions could cause long-term brain damage, he responded (McDermott
and Hichens 2012): “The answer is: it is possible. But at the moment there is no clear
evidence—there are some isolated cases suggesting it could—but there is no clear evi-
dence that repeated concussions lead to long term brain damage.”
In 2014 the Director of the AFL Medical Officers Association (Dr. Hugh Seward) also
characterized evidence on the link between sports-related concussions and brain injury
as circumstantial (Carlisle 2014).
If there was proof that repeated head trauma caused a degenerative condition such as
CTE this would be a strong reason for collision sports to implement policies to prevent
repeated head injuries. But uncertainty about whether a causal relationship between CTE
and repeated concussion has been used to delay “major changes in the play or manage-
ment of sports” (McKee et al. 2014). By avoiding acting until there is proof of causation
for CTE, sports governing bodies have ignored the epidemiological evidence that justifies
prudent measures to prevent repeated head injuries. In doing so, they have arguably failed
to honor their professed commitment to protecting the health and safety of their players.
There are probably a number of reasons for these delaying tactics, namely, that concus-
sion is seen as an inherent feature of many collision sports because many fans enjoy see-
ing fit athletes engage in bodily collisions; and that no sports administrator or fan would
520 5
like to believe that repeated concussions can produce brain injuries because accepting
this would require major changes in the way their sports are played. As with similarly
motivated reasoning about the evidence on climate change, skepticism about the evidence
for CTE has been used to justify inaction. This may be changing. In March 2016, an NFL
executive was prepared to concede for the first time a “link between football and CTE”
(Bieler 2016)—it remains to be seen how this change of mind will influence concussion
management in collision sports around the world.
For example, neither the NRL nor the AFL prohibits same-day return to play for muscu-
loskeletal injuries.
Previously in both leagues, team doctors were only encouraged not to allow concussed
players to return to the field if they still had symptoms of concussion. It is clear that in the
past, many players who suffered concussion continued to play for the remainder of the
match even after being examined by a team doctor. Given recent concerns about the long-
term implications of repeated head trauma, it is worrying that some former players have
reported suffering multiple concussions in the same match on several occasions during
their career (McDermott & Hichens 2012).
Efforts to improve compliance with this rule have focused on increasing awareness
of the injury and educating coaching and medical staff on how to manage it. Important
ethical and social issues pose significant barriers to the proper identification and man-
agement of concussion in many sports at the professional and community level (ama-
teurs and juniors) (Partridge 2014; Partridge & Hall 2014). Lack of awareness may
only be one reason for noncompliance with concussion guidelines. Conflicts of inter-
est between doctors, players, and teams may be a more substantial obstacle to their
adherence.
The decision to allow a concussed athlete to return to play is one of the most con-
tentious in sports medicine (Kaye & McCrory 2012). Autonomy in decision-making,
informed consent to participate in risky activities, coercion, and competing interests of
key decision-makers all present difficulties when diagnosing and managing concussion—
particularly in the case of junior athletes (Dunn et al. 2007). And there is little guidance
on how key stakeholders should navigate these ethical issues.
In professional sports, the emergence of the “team doctor” (Polsky 1998) has trans-
formed the doctor–patient relationship into a triad: doctor–patient–team (Dunn et al.
2007). A team’s interest in winning may conflict with the welfare of an injured player
when decisions are made about whether he is fit to play after injury. These issues are not
confined to professional sport: they may present even greater difficulties in community
level sport where other key stakeholders (e.g., coaches, parents) also have a duty of care
toward junior athletes (Gilbert & Johnson 2011).
Severe concussion usually renders a player unable to continue playing but footballers
may recover from many of the symptoms of milder cases during a match. Without a “con-
cussion exclusion rule” these players have been allowed to stay on, or go back onto the
field, and play at the risk of incurring further injury and complications. Some coaches
may not want a player to continue after suffering a concussion, but there are examples of
coaches allowing players to continue playing despite suspected concussion. In some cases,
it may be in the team’s interests of winning to prevent a potentially concussed player from
being assessed (e.g., if there are no other substitute players available), if the match is very
close, or if a particularly important team player is involved.
In surveys, sports physicians often report pressure from coaches (and injured players)
to clear the injured players for a rapid return to play despite the risks to their welfare
(Anderson & Gerrard 2005; Price et al. 2012). For example, Anderson and Gerrard (2005)
52 5
interviewed sports physicians in New Zealand and found that conflicts of interest were
one of the ethical issues team doctors had the most trouble managing.
Team doctors also report pressure from coaches to return concussed players to the field
on the same day. The implementation of a concussion exclusion rule would reduce this
pressure because it would require players to remain on the sideline for the remainder of
the match after receiving a diagnosis of concussion. However, this rule could affect team
doctors’ clinical decisions as to whether a played has been concussed. A revealing insight
into these tensions was given by a rugby league team doctor early in 2012 on the British
Journal of Sports Medicine blog after the Australian NRL instigated a “concussion exclu-
sion rule” (see Box 26.1) (Orchard 2012).
In this case, the team coaching staff prioritized team goals over player health by tell-
ing the doctor that if he “didn’t examine the player, then the rules would allow him to
continue.” In practice, a team doctor could be prevented from examining a potentially
concussed player if the sports trainer who initially assesses the player fails to refer him to
a doctor at a coach’s direction. The attitude of the coaching staff described in the blog post
describes this situation.
The first point in Box 26.1 describes the tension created between the team doctors, the
team, and the NRL by the concussion guideline. When the doctor says that “I am going
to be pulling players out of the game who I have been comfortable letting continue for
many years,” he refers to the previous policy of allowing concussed players to continue
playing, if their symptoms had resolved. Under the most recent guidelines, the NRL has
taken this clinical judgment out of the hands of team doctors. While this may accord
with the views of some sports physicians, others may see it as an unwelcome intrusion
into their clinical practice that reflects a lack of confidence in their management of their
players. Concussion can sometimes be difficult to identify and there is still uncertainty
about the threshold for diagnosing concussion, but the team doctor in Box 26.1 was aware
that the concussion exclusion rule may “hurt our team’s chances of winning” and so felt
uncomfortable.
The second point raised in Box 26.1 is the worrying possibility that team doctors may
avoid assessing players if a diagnosis of concussion may hurt their team’s chances of win-
ning. If this happens, then concussed players could be put at risk of further injuries—the
very outcome the guidelines were intended to prevent.
The third point in Box 26.1 is that team doctors may re-label concussion as “being
dazed” or “traumatic migraine” to enable a concussed player to continue playing.
This runs the serious risk of delaying appropriate and timely treatment of concussion.
Furthermore, because their injury would not be recorded as a concussion, the footballer
would not be included in prospective epidemiological studies of how concussed players
fare. Good data about the long-term consequences of concussion is essential for better
management. Ironically, before the “concussion exclusion rule” there was less pressure to
re-label concussion as something more benign because concussed players whose symp-
toms had resolved were permitted to continue (Orchard 2012).
Important questions remain about how to implement concussion management guide-
lines in ways that avoid nonadherence by team doctors. These questions include the
following:
◆ What are the implications of concussion management guidelines for autonomy in
decision-making by athletes, clinicians, parents, and coaches?
◆ How is decision-making about concussion affected by coercive influences to continue
playing exerted on athletes by coaches, clinicians, parents and other stakeholders?
◆ How do we reconcile the competing ethical obligations among athletes, coaches, and cli-
nicians when making decisions about the diagnosis and management of concussion?
◆ Does simply informing athletes (or parents of junior athletes) about the short-and
long-term risks of suffering concussion make the athlete (or parent) responsible for any
future adverse health outcomes?
◆ Is there still a moral obligation on team doctors or sports governing bodies to prescribe
how concussions must be managed, and to make paternalistic decisions for athletes in
their own best interests in some cases?
◆ Can athletes (or parents of junior athletes) give full and informed consent in accepting
the risks of participating in sports with high rates of concussion when the evidence
about the long-term harms of such injuries is incomplete?
524 5
by the self-appointed Concussion in Sport Group some of whose members have serious
ethical issues of conflicts of interest.
First, the companies that market these tools, particularly ImPACT and CogState, have
funded or undertaken many of the studies that have been published in the academic lit-
erature in support of the clinical utility of their products. Often these studies have been
coauthored by owners or employees of the company, by researchers who have received
research funding from the company, or by consultants to the company. Second, some of
these researchers have been authors of the guidelines recommending the routine use of
these tests. In the Consensus Statements on Concussion in Sport that have supported NP
testing:
◆ only industry-funded studies were cited in support of the value of NP tests for
concussion
◆ the industry funding of these studies was not disclosed in the consensus document
◆ some panel members have had direct links to the companies that own these NP tests
but these links have not always been declared
◆ these documents do not cite research undertaken by independent researchers that
raise doubts about the reliability and utility of these NP tests.
Some of the authors of the Consensus Statements who have links to NP testing companies
have advised professional sporting leagues in the United States and Australia to adopt
these tests. These leagues have subsequently mandated the use of these NP tests for all
players—most notably, the NFL, the AFL, and, the NRL.
Major conflicts of interest arise when recommendations are made by a panel that
includes members with financial and professional links to companies that sell computer-
ized NP tests for concussion management. Without regulations to declare and manage
conflicts of interest, it may be difficult to ascertain when special interests have improperly
influenced a decision. Could we be confident that a panel without any links to the com-
panies that market computerized NP tests would have made the same recommendations?
A major concern about their reliance on evidence from industry-linked research is
that companies may simply not report studies that fail to support their products, as has
happened in the past with the reporting of clinical trials by pharmaceutical companies.
For example, systematic reviews that have compared neutrally sponsored drug trials with
those sponsored by the pharmaceutical industry have found that the latter are much more
likely to favor the company’s product (Lexchin et al. 2003). Investigator bias may be even
more likely when the investigators include owners and employees of the company.
Industry funding may also determine the questions that are asked and answered, often
with the future marketing of the product in mind. This may bias the literature toward
publication of results that are favorable to the funder’s product, again as has been noted in
the pharmaceutical field with selective publication of the results of clinical trials. The fact
that the Consensus Statements relied on industry-sponsored evaluations of NP testing
raises concerns that recommendations to use particular products have not been based on
an unbiased appraisal of the evidence. The same concerns apply when sporting leagues
526 5
establish their own concussion advisory groups whose members have links to computer-
ized NP testing companies. How can sports governing bodies be sure that they received
unbiased advice about the use of these products?
If independent assessment of these tests support the claims made by their designers,
then no harm will have been done. But if these tests are not as useful in evaluating and
managing concussion as their proponents claim, then athletes could be mistakenly diag-
nosed as “fit” to return to play and suffer additional concussions that produce longer-
lasting forms of cognitive impairment.
In 2013, Resch and colleagues published a review of computerized NP tests for con-
cussion including the ImPACT and CogState tools (Resch et al. 2013). They concluded
that: “Although many of the studies reviewed demonstrate suboptimal reliability and
validity, computerized testing is widely used in concussion management at all competi-
tive levels … development, marketing and sales appear to have outpaced the clinical
evidence base.”
A high priority should be given to developing evidence-informed policies to manage
concussions in sports. This should be done in ways that reduce the potential effects of
conflicts of interest when those who design these tests make recommendations about
their use and can by virtue of their positions also control the research that evaluates their
effectiveness in reducing concussion.
Conclusion
Ethical issues can be important obstacles in the proper identification and manage-
ment of concussion in sport. And yet despite the proliferation of published concus-
sion management guidelines by professional groups over the last decade, there has
been little guidance for stakeholders in how to navigate and resolve many of these
issues. In the past, concussions in collision sports were often overlooked by players,
coaches, team doctors, fans, and administrators. Describing a concussed player as
having “gone to Disneyland” or “having their bell rung” reflects how concussion
has often been spoken about in a nonserious way that downplays the potentially
serious nature of the injury. The legacy of past policies and attitudes is a culture
within many sports that sees concussion as a trivial injury, with participants who
succumb to concussion being viewed as weak or not team players. In the past it
was not uncommon for coaches, doctors, teammates, and the players themselves to
continue playing after a concussion if it were physically possible—a stark contrast
to the “no same-d ay return-to-play” policy adopted by many sports today. Despite
increasing evidence that repeated concussions are associated with long-term cogni-
tive and neurological sequelae, this legacy is not easily erased. Participants com-
monly encounter covert and overt forms of coercion to continue playing after a
concussion at all levels of competition. What is best for the concussed player (sit-
ting out) may not be what is best for the team (winning). In professional sports in
particular, the lucrative rewards on offer mean that players, coaches, team doctors,
527
References 527
and sports governing bodies may find that they have competing loyalties when it
comes to concussion management. These conflicts of interest have often been over-
looked or tolerated, and vigilance is required to ensure that conflicts of interest do
not undermine the health and welfare of athletes. Sporting leagues would do well to
explore managing some of these issues through the use of independent doctors who
are not affiliated with particular teams.
Experts in sports medicine, neurology, and the neurosciences may also find they have
conflicts of interest when it comes to concussion. The need to find better ways of identi-
fying and managing concussion has presented a large commercial opportunity for clini-
cians and researchers, and led to a preponderance of neurogadgets aiming to address
these issues. But we need to ensure that in the pursuit of commercial opportunity, the
marketing of these products does not outpace the evidence for their utility, reliability, and
validity. Furthermore, there are professionally lucrative opportunities to consult for, or
conduct research for, multimillion (or multibillion)-dollar sports leagues. Clinicians and
researchers should ensure that they properly disclose these affiliations when publishing
work in the area or treating athletes.
Acknowledgments
Sincere thanks to Sarah Yeates for her assistance in formatting this chapter.
References
Anderson, L.C. and Gerrard, D.F. (2005). Ethical issues concerning New Zealand sports doctors.
Journal of Medical Ethics, 31(2), 88–92.
Aubry, M., Cantu, R., Dvorak, J., et al. (2002). Summary and agreement statement of the first
International Conference on Concussion in Sport, Vienna 2001. British Journal of Sports Medicine,
36(1), 6–7.
Bazarian, J.J., Cernak, I., Noble-Haeusslein, L., Potolicchio, S., and Temkin, N. (2009). Long-term
neurologic outcomes after traumatic brain injury. Journal of Head Trauma Rehabilitation, 24(6),
439–451.
Bieler, D. (2016, March 14). In stunning admission, NFL official affirms link between football and CTE.
Washington Post. Available from: https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/early-lead/wp/2016/03/14/
in-stunning-admission-nfl-official-affirms-link-between-football-and-cte/ [accessed May 14, 2016].
Carlisle, W. (2014, June 22). Concussion games. ABC Radio National Background Briefing. Available
from: http://www.abc.net.au/radionational/programs/backgroundbriefing/-v2/5497562#transcript
[accessed May 14, 2016].
Crawley, P. (2014, March 13). Wake-up call: rugby league concussion culture “has to change” says
head doctor. The Daily Telegraph. Available from: http://www.dailytelegraph.com.au/sport/nrl/
wakeup-call-rugby-league-concussion-culture-has-to-change-says-head-doctor/story-fni3fbgz-
1226852942110 [accessed May 14, 2016].
Daneshvar, D.H., Nowinski, C.J., McKee, A.C., and Cantu, R.C. (2011). The epidemiology of sport-
related concussion. Clinics in Sports Medicine, 30(1), 1–17.
Dunn, W.R., George, M.S., Churchill, L., and Spindler, K.P. (2007). Ethics in sports medicine.
American Journal of Sports Medicine, 35(5), 840–844.
528 5
Fann, J.R., Burington, B., Leonetti, A., Jaffe, K., Katon, W.J., and Thompson, R.S. (2004). Psychiatric
illness following traumatic brain injury in an adult health maintenance organization population.
Archives of General Psychiatry, 61(1), 53–61.
Fleminger, S., Oliver, D.L., Lovestone, S., Rabe-Hesketh, S., and Giora, A. (2003). Head injury as a risk
factor for Alzheimer’s disease: the evidence 10 years on; a partial replication. Journal of Neurology,
Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 74(7), 857–862.
Gardner, A., Iverson, G.L., and McCrory, P. (2014). Chronic traumatic encephalopathy in sport: a
systematic review. British Journal of Sports Medicine, 48(2), 84–90.
Gilbert, F. and Johnson, L.S.M. (2011). The impact of American tackle football-related concussion in
youth athletes. AJOB Neuroscience, 2(4), 48–59.
Giza, C.C., Kutcher, J.S., Ashwal, S., et al. (2013). Summary of evidence-based guideline
update: evaluation and management of concussion in sports: report of the Guideline
Development Subcommittee of the American Academy of Neurology. Neurology, 80(24),
2250–2257.
Graves, A.B., White, E., Koepsell, T.D., et al. (1990). The association between head trauma and
Alzheimer’s disease. American Journal of Epidemiology, 131(3), 491–501.
Guo, Z., Cupples, L.A., Kurz, A., et al. (2000). Head injury and the risk of AD in the MIRAGE study.
Neurology, 54(6), 1316–1323.
Guskiewicz, K.M., Marshall, S.W., Bailes, J., et al. (2005). Association between recurrent concussion
and late-life cognitive impairment in retired professional football players. Neurosurgery, 57(4),
719–726.
Guskiewicz, K.M., Marshall, S.W., Bailes, J., et al. (2007). Recurrent concussion and risk of depression
in retired professional football players. Medicine and Science in Sports and Exercise, 39(6), 903–909.
Harmon, K.G., Drezner, J.A., Gammons, M., et al. (2013). American Medical Society for Sports
Medicine position statement: concussion in sport. British Journal of Sports Medicine, 47(1), 15–26.
Hinton-Bayre, A.D., Geffen, G., and Friis, P. (2004). Presentation and mechanisms of concussion in
professional rugby league football. Journal of Science and Medicine in Sport, 7(3), 400–404.
Kaye, A.H. and McCrory, P. (2012). Does football cause brain damage? Medical Journal of Australia,
196(9), 547–549.
Lane, S. (2012). US Concussion Study May Not Apply to AFL: Doctor. Available from: http://www.smh.
com.au/afl/afl-news/us-concussion-study-may-not-apply-to-afl-doctor-20120603-1zq6h.html
[accessed May 14, 2016].
Lane, S. (2016). Concussion Problem Overblown: AFL Expert Paul McCrory. Available from: http://www.
theage.com.au/afl/afl-news/nfl-concussion-problem-overblown-afl-expert-paul-mccrory-20160406-
go0ctx.html#ixzz45CM8W9VA [accessed May 14, 2016].
Lee, Y.K., Hou, S.W., Lee, C.C., Hsu, C.Y., Huang, Y.S., and Su, Y.C. (2013). Increased risk of dementia
in patients with mild traumatic brain injury: a nationwide cohort study. PloS One, 8(5), e62422.
Lehman, E.J., Hein, M.J., Baron, S.L., and Gersic, C.M. (2012). Neurodegenerative causes of death
among retired National Football League players. Neurology, 79(19), 1970–1974.
Lexchin, J., Bero, L.A., Djulbegovic, B., and Clark, O. (2003). Pharmaceutical industry sponsorship
and research outcome and quality: systematic review. BMJ (Clinical Research Ed.), 326(7400),
1167–1170.
Lye, T.C. and Shores, E.A. (2000). Traumatic brain injury as a risk factor for Alzheimer’s disease: a
review. Neuropsychology Review, 10(2), 115–129.
Makdissi, M., McCrory, P., Ugoni, A., Darby, D., and Brukner, P. (2009). A prospective study of
postconcussive outcomes after return to play in Australian football. American Journal of Sports
Medicine, 37(5), 877–883.
529
References 529
McCrory, P., Johnston, K.M., Meeuwisse, W., et al. (2005). Summary and agreement statement of
the 2nd International Conference on Concussion in Sport, Prague 2004. British Journal of Sports
Medicine, 39(4), 196–204.
McCrory, P., Meeuwisse, W., Johnston, K.M., Dvorak, J., Aubry, M., Molloy, M., and Cantu, R. (2009).
Consensus Statement on Concussion in Sport: the 3rd International Conference on Concussion in
Sport held in Zurich, November 2008. British Journal of Sports Medicine, 43(Suppl 1), i76-i84.
McCrory, P., Meeuwisse, W.H., Aubry, M., et al. (2013). Consensus Statement on Concussion in
Sport: the 4th International Conference on Concussion in Sport held in Zurich, November 2012.
British Journal of Sports Medicine, 47(5), 250–258.
McDermott, Q. and Hichens, C. (2012, May 14). Hard knocks. ABC TV Four Corners. Available
from: http://www.abc.net.au/4corners/stories/2012/05/10/3499950.htm [accessed May 14, 2016].
McKee, A.C., Cantu, R.C., Nowinski, C.J., et al. (2009). Chronic traumatic encephalopathy in
athletes: progressive tauopathy after repetitive head injury. Journal of Neuropathology and
Experimental Neurology, 68(7), 709–735.
McKee, A.C., Stein, T.D., Nowinski, C.J., et al. (2013). The spectrum of disease in chronic traumatic
encephalopathy. Brain, 136(1), 43–64.
McKee, A.C., Daneshvar, D.H., Alvarez, V.E., and Stein, T.D. (2014). The neuropathology of sport. Acta
Neuropathologica, 127(1), 29–51.
McNamee, M.J., Partridge, B., and Anderson, L. (2016). Concussion ethics and sports medicine. Clinics
in Sports Medicine, 35(2), 257–267.
Molgaard, C.A., Stanford, E.P., Morton, D.J., et al. (1990). Epidemiology of head trauma and
neurocognitive impairment in a multi-ethnic population. Neuroepidemiology, 9(5), 233–242.
Muratore, R. (2012). The need to tackle concussion in Australian football codes. Medical Journal of
Australia, 197(3), 146.
Nemetz, P.N., Leibson, C., Naessens, J.M., et al. (1999). Traumatic brain injury and time to onset of
Alzheimer’s disease: a population-based study. American Journal of Epidemiology, 149(1), 32–40.
NRL (2012). NRL Mailbox: Player Safety and Concussions. Available from: http://www.nrl.com/nrl-
mailbox-player-safety-and-concussions/tabid/10874/newsid/66477/default.aspx [accessed May
14, 2016].
Omalu, B.I., Dekosky, S.T., Minster, R.L., Kamboh, M.I., Hamilton, R.L., and Wecht, C.H. (2005).
Chronic traumatic encephalopathy in a National Football League player. Neurosurgery, 57(1), 128–
134; discussion 128–134.
Omalu, B.I., Hamilton, R.L., Kamboh, M.I., Dekosky, S.T., and Bailes, J. (2010). Chronic traumatic
encephalopathy (CTE) in a National Football League Player: Case report and emerging medicolegal
practice questions. Journal of Forensic Nursing, 6(1), 40–46.
Orchard, J. (2012). Concussion: how do we reconcile risk-averse policies with risk-taking sports? BJSM
Blog. Available from: http://blogs.bmj.com/bjsm/2012/03/15/concussion-how-do-we-reconcile-risk-
averse-policies-with-risk-taking-sports/ [accessed May 14, 2016].
Partridge, B. (2014). Dazed and confused: sports medicine, conflicts of interest, and concussion
management. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, 11(1), 65–74.
Partridge, B. and Hall, W. (2014). Conflicts of interest in recommendations to use computerized
neuropsychological tests to manage concussion in professional football codes. Neuroethics,
7(1), 63–74.
Partridge, B. and Hall, W. (2015). Repeated head injuries in Australia’s collision sports highlight ethical
and evidential gaps in concussion management policies. Neuroethics, 8(1), 39–45.
Polsky, S. (1998). Winning medicine: professional sports team doctors’ conflicts of interest. Journal of
Contemporary Health Law and Policy, 14(2), 503–529.
530
Price, J., Malliaras, P., and Hudson, Z. (2012). Current practices in determining return to play following
head injury in professional football in the UK. British Journal of Sports Medicine, 46(14), 1000–1003.
Resch, J.E., McCrea, M.A., and Cullum, C.M. (2013). Computerized neurocognitive testing in the
management of sport-related concussion: an update. Neuropsychology Review, 23(4), 335–349.
Salib, E. and Hillier, V. (1997). Head injury and the risk of Alzheimer’s disease: a case control study.
International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 12(3), 363–368.
Shively, S., Scher, A.I., Perl, D.P., and Diaz-Arrastia, R. (2012). Dementia resulting from traumatic
brain injury: what is the pathology? Archives of Neurology, 69(10), 1245–1251.
White, P.E., Newton, J.D., Makdissi, M., et al. (2014). Knowledge about sports-related concussion: is
the message getting through to coaches and trainers? British Journal of Sports Medicine, 48(2),
119–124.
531
Chapter 27
History
Introduction
The historical relationship between the brain and military spans many cultures, conti-
nents, and centuries. From the age-old use of stimulants, depressants, intoxicants, and
hallucinogens—including cannabis, coca, cocaine, and others—to today’s pharmaceuti-
cals and sophisticated brain–machine interfaces (BMIs), humankind has long studied and
altered neurological functions to enhance mental and physical performance in warfare.
Some of the same pharmacological and electronic neuroengineering breakthroughs that
are being developed for use in medicine, including military medicine to treat neurologi-
cal and psychiatric wounds of war, can also be employed within dual-use initiatives to
facilitate or augment warfighter capabilities, or both. Additionally, in the United States at
least, security agencies are increasingly addressing ways to leverage findings from neu-
roscience to enhance intelligence operations, including the acquisition, analysis, and use
of diverse types and levels of information (Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group 2014,
2015; Giordano & Wurzman 2016).
Despite numerous success stories and persistently high hopes for the ways that brain
science can be used in national security and intelligence operations, fundamental ten-
sions between the goals of science and security riddle the history of US military and
intelligence neuroscience research with case studies in ethics, law, and policy. Whereas
national security relies on secrecy to maximize strategic, technological surprise, science
is an inherently public enterprise characterized by transparency and peer review. Security
agencies, moreover, focus on the ever-present immediacy of security threats, while sci-
ence slowly tests and aggregates truths over time. History shows that an unfortunate
result of these conflicts of values can manifest as unethical experimentation on human
532 5
subjects and the deployment of technologies before being scientifically and ethically vali-
dated as safe and effective. And yet, as described by the Collingridge dilemma, the prac-
tical and ethical consequences of technological innovation may be unpredictable until
widely deployed; by then, however, it may be too late to put the proverbial genie back in
the bottle (Collingridge 1980).
The dual-use nature of national security neuroscience applications represents a funda-
mental tension in the science–security relationship. In the context of scientific research
and the development and deployment of technology, scholars and policymakers use the
term “dual-use” to refer to two separate, but interrelated, dichotomies. One meaning indi-
cates that the research and/or use of a given technology may be intended to achieve either
benevolent or malevolent ends, whereas the second refers to science and technology with
both military and civilian uses (Evans 2014). Ongoing work, in both the United States
and the European Union, addresses the historical uses of the term “dual-use” in order to
clarify its meaning and implications.
Numerous science and technological developments for medical and other civilian uses
have been adopted and incorporated for security and defense purposes (e.g., chemical and
biological agents, among others). Moreover, under what is referred to as reverse dual-use,
many innovations used and taken for granted in civilian medicine—and daily life—have
trickled down from, or were developed in pursuit of, military applications (e.g., ther-
mographic medical imaging and the Internet). With increasing momentum of the brain
sciences, and growing interest in and dedication to the use of neurocognitive science for
national security purposes, researchers, regardless of nationality, should be aware of both
explicit dual-use research of concern (DURC), and the potential for any brain science to
be viable and of value to security and defense agendas.
How should these tensions be managed and by whom? A 2003 Nature editorial admon-
ished applied neuroscientists to consider the intentions of their military funders and to
speak out (Editorial 2003). Does the “silence of the neuroengineers” that the editorial
alleged persist? Recently, a concerned group of neuroscientists developed a document to
establish a pledge to proscribe active participation in brain research that is explicitly to be
used for military purposes (Bell 2014).
But can the goals that stand behind such a pledge be realized? After all, any published
research could be utilized to develop information, techniques, and methods in military
settings and operations. A study published in 2015 suggests that neuroscientists are far
more likely to consider their colleagues’ work of dual-use potential than their own (Kosal
& Huang 2015). Ethical, legal, and social analysis of the science–security partnership
receives scant attention in the academic world and government bureaucracy, allowing the
military–and intelligence–industrial complex to churn along largely unfettered by the
concerns that make national security and neuroscience a prime target for neuroethical
critique. Perhaps a first question is: How did we get here?
Since the mid-nineteenth century, government agencies and advisory bodies have been
periodically created to assess and direct science and technology policy issues as they
relate to military operations and national security. In the United States, President Lincoln
53
History 533
established the National Academy of Sciences to advise the Union on weapons purchasing,
among other pressing technological issues. During World War I, the National Research
Council was formed in an attempt to apply civilian science to the preparation for and
waging of war. At that time, however, the military was reluctant to integrate findings from
the academy. World War II marked the transition of US foreign policy from isolation-
ism to a garrison state, a nation perennially militarized and engaged in conflict (Lasswell
1941). In 1945 the US presidential science advisor Vannevar Bush informed President
Harry S. Truman that science represented an essential component of US national defense,
one that the government must support, stating: “it has become clear beyond all doubt
that scientific research is absolutely essential to national security” (Bush 1945). Bush went
on to cite the critical advantages provided by radar and then-secret anti-rocket devices.
Only a few months later, his point was bolstered by the results of the Manhattan Engineer
District, popularly known as the Manhattan Project, that caused the Japanese Imperial
Government to sue for peace. Implicit in Bush’s description of science as “an endless fron-
tier” was its dual-use nature, crucial for civilian as well as military purposes. Notably,
in charging the former provost of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT) to
prepare his report, US President Franklin Delano Roosevelt wrote in 1944 that “[n]ew
frontiers of the mind are before us” (Roosevelt 1944).
Ever since the outset of the Cold War, US national security policy has called for techno-
logical superiority over all adversaries, not merely parity. In 1950, the National Security
Council officially recognized the importance of the science–security partnership, declar-
ing: “it is mandatory that in building up our strength, we enlarge upon our technical
superiority by an accelerated exploitation of the scientific potential of the Unites States
and our allies” (Nitze 1950). Following this recognition of the importance of innova-
tion and technological surprise, a full-fledged military–academic complex emerged
and remains an essential element of today’s university funding portfolio. Reacting to
the Soviet Union’s launch of Sputnik, the first Earth-orbiting satellite, in 1958 President
Dwight Eisenhower founded the Advanced Research Projects Agency (now known as
the Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA); one of a number of such
ARPAs), tasked with the development of rockets and weather satellites among its first
projects. DARPA’s mission was and remains that of “keeping the United States out front
when it comes to cultivating breakthrough technologies for national security rather than
in a position of catching up to strategically important innovations and achievements of
others” (DARPA 2016).
DARPA’s most celebrated achievement, the development of the Internet, is proving
useful in various BMI projects and integrating head-mounted displays to web-access
for augmented reality. Since at least the early 2000s, DARPA has contracted with many
university-and medical school-based neuroscientists to pursue projects of interest.
According to one estimate, by fiscal year 2011 DARPA was funding at least $240 million
USD in cognitive neuroscience studies (Kosal, quoted in Moreno 2012, p.53). In 2014, the
presidential administration proposed to double, in fiscal year 2015, the $100 million USD
federal investment in DARPA, the National Institutes of Health, and the National Science
534 5
Foundation, key participants in the federal Brain Research through Advancing Innovative
Neurotechnologies (BRAIN) Initiative® (White House 2014).
Although DARPA has played a significant role in development and testing of innova-
tive neuroscience techniques and technologies that can be translated into both military
and civilian use, other US military agencies have also been, and are increasingly engaged
in brain research. The Office of Naval Research (ONR) has sponsored a number of proj-
ects that have focused on enhancing warfighter performance. Through such work, ONR
seeks to “[e]nhance individual and team decision-making and combat effectiveness” by
optimizing biological efficiency and performance (Office of Naval Research: Science &
Technology n.d. a). Additionally, the agency’s Computational Neuroscience Program
supports the development of neurologically inspired microcircuitry (Office of Naval
Research: Science & Technology n.d. b). Replicating in silico the structural and func-
tional bases of the algorithmic computations of the brain could enhance the scientific
understanding of the relationship between brain and cognition. In addition, the US
Department of Defense directly engages brain research through broad-agency announce-
ments and contracts that solicit university-based projects. For example, in 2003, MIT
received $500 million USD and Johns Hopkins University was awarded approximately
$300 million USD in Department of Defense grants and contracts. Of course, not all of
these efforts have proven to be fruitful. One especially colorful effort by the US Army in
the 1980s involved an attempt to determine whether extrasensory perception and psy-
chokinesis could aid in the training of “warrior monks” who could “remotely view” sites
without ever having been physically present in them or seen them in images, and even
cause animals to collapse at will (Druckhman & Swets 1988).
More sober efforts have been reflected in advisory reports from the National Research
Council commissioned by agencies including the Army and the Defense Intelligence
Agency during the early 2000s (National Research Council 2008; National Research
Council (US) Committee on Opportunities in Neuroscience for Future Army Applications
2009). These reports included recommendations for the military and intelligence com-
munity to identify and pursue neurotechnologies that could be developed for opera-
tional use. This was prescient, for while a 2008 US National Academies Report, Emerging
Cognitive Neuroscience and Related Technologies, was somewhat cautious in its view of the
operational utility of brain science, subsequent reports, including a number of Pentagon
white papers, have acknowledged that neuroscientific techniques and technologies have
high potential for operational use in a variety of security, defense, and intelligence enter-
prises (Air Force Studies Board, 2008; Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group 2010, 2012a,
2012b, 2012c, 2013, 2015). These papers also advocated the need to address current and
near-term ethical, legal, and social issues (ELSI) generated by such use. A subsequent
report by the National Academies in 2014, Emerging and Readily Available Technologies
and National Security: A Framework for Addressing Ethical, Legal, and Societal Issues,
reflected this view, and the importance of ethical engagement (Chameau et al. 2014). At
present, operationally viable products of brain science include microbiological agents,
toxins, drugs, and devices (Wurzman & Giordano 2014). Certain microbiological agents,
53
History 535
toxins, and chemicals are regulated and restricted by international policies, conven-
tions, and treaties, such as DURC policies, and the Biological and Toxin and Weapons
Convention (BTWC), and Chemical Weapons Convention (CWC). Therefore, this chap-
ter will focus upon research and use of drugs and devices that are not constrained by
these regulations, and which have been, and remain viable for use in defense and security
initiatives on an international scale.
Enhancement/therapy
Drugs
Warfighters have long used myriad substances both to fortify performance of military
tasks and to cope with the horrors of war. Alertness, wakefulness, and focus—key decision-
making capacities of a warfighter—have been enhanced for centuries. An ephedrine-
containing herb stimulated the senses of guards on China’s Great Wall, just as coca leaves
did for Incan fighters. Bavarian soldiers received cocaine from their officers, and amphet-
amines have been used by warfighters since World War II (Moreno 2012). Referred to as
“go pills,” amphetamines came to the attention of the public in 2003 when US Air National
Guard pilots, allegedly enhanced by go pills, accidentally bombed Canadian troops in
Afghanistan (Shanker & Duenwald 2003).
Warfighters have even used hallucinogens and intoxicating combinations of psychoac-
tive herbs to enhance their combat effectiveness, or at least the appearance of ferocity.
Turks reportedly used opium to enhance wartime bravery in the 1500s (Lewin 1998).
Consumption of Amanita muscaria, a psychoactive and hallucinogenic mushroom, may
have facilitated the “berserker” rage characteristic of Viking raids, though scholars remain
divided on the veracity of this claim (Fabing 1956; Høyersten 2015). South African tribal
warriors smoked dagga, a type of cannabis, in combination with the consumption of
other herbs to enhance fearlessness and insensitivity to pain (Kamienski 2016, pp.29–30).
Not only have warfighters used substances to enhance capacities to engage in combat,
the history of warfare is rich with examples of warriors using substances to disengage from
combat. Homer’s Odyssey famously described the consumption of nepenthe by warriors
who quickly forgot their wartime sorrows (Kamienski 2016, pp.29–30). During the US
Civil War, the term “soldier’s disease” became synonymous with opiate addiction, likely
as a result of the widespread use of opiate analgesics among warfighters (Miller 2013).
Deployment to Vietnam correlated with an uptick in warfighter narcotic use and addic-
tion, at least in part used for escapism (Robins et al. 1975). More recently, US warfighters
have used “no go pills” to calm the mind and induce rest in preparation for, or in recovery
from, combat (Golub & Bennett 2013). These interventions foreshadow ongoing research
on drugs like propranolol, which could ultimately enable warfighters to disengage from
combat without having formed traumatic memories (Donovan 2010).
Devices
The history of neuromodulation via electricity and magnetism also dates back centuries, if
not millennia. Scribonius Largus, an ancient Roman physician, wrote the earliest known
536 5
History 537
In 2002, Nature published results of a DARPA study that created the “roborat,” a
remote-controlled rodent that utilized BMI technology. Scientists implanted electrodes in
the rat’s brain and in real time controlled its locomotion through complex mazes (Talwar
et al. 2002). Scientists equivocate on whether such research actually advances the aims
of medical prostheses, but DARPA’s interest was different: the roborat could be sent into
dangerous scenarios to detect mines, clear bombs, or identify survivors among rubble.
More recently, scientists have created “cyborg beetles” whose flight characteristics can be
remotely controlled (Sato et al. 2015). Such studies also raise ethical issues about the use
and purpose of animals in such research. There is a nuanced general consensus that the
public interest in animal studies performed for biomedical research may outweigh animal
autonomy, but such sentiments are less clear when biomedical research is directed toward
furthering military goals (Quigley 2007).
Other national security-funded animal BMI studies are more directly oriented toward
therapeutic objectives. Around the same time as the roborat studies, scientists equipped
monkeys with BMIs attached to robotic arms and successfully trained the primates to
articulate and control the prostheses using neurological output from their brains (Lebedev
2006). This research could revolutionize prosthetics, both for warfighters and civilians.
Since then, BMIs have also facilitated human neurological control of a mouse cursor,
which could allow paraplegic patients to regain control and physical autonomy in their
lives (Simeral et al. 2011). Current DARPA research seeks to complete the feedback loop
between the brain and prostheses, not only granting the brain direct control over a robotic
limb but also returning tactile feedback, such as pressure and temperature, from sensors
in the prosthesis to the user’s brain (DARPA 2015).
An early twenty-first century DARPA program, AugCog (short for “augmented cogni-
tion”), sought to fully integrate, at the neurological level, a warfighter’s cognitive capaci-
ties and sensory perceptions with his or her combat vehicle environment (Cummings
2010). As computers monitor working memory, attention, executive function, and sen-
sory input, the warfighter would be prompted in real time with information about cogni-
tive load. This kind of biofeedback could help a warfighter manage his or her neurological
resources; it might even bring into conscious awareness one’s own subconscious recogni-
tion of danger, prompting the warfighter’s attention to threats before they would have
been identified naturally (Szondy 2012). Though in name AugCog no longer exists, simi-
lar research continues. Giordano and Dando provide current overviews of neuroscience
and technology that is being studied, considered, developed, and used in national secu-
rity, intelligence, and defense (Giordano 2014c; Dando 2015).
testing tools and techniques of the brain sciences in and for security and defense agendas
around the world. As shown in Table 27.1, these include (but are not limited to) Australia,
Canada, China, consolidated efforts of the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO)
member nations, India, and Russia.
In the main, brain science is primarily being used in international military and security
contexts:
◆ for medical purposes
◆ to optimize operational training and performance in military and intelligence
personnel
◆ to study (and perhaps develop) nonlethal and lethal weapons (e.g., chemical and
microbial agents and toxins, and neurotechnologic devices) (Giordano 2014b).
The 2014 report of the National Academies asserted that the research, development, and
use of brain science in international military and security scenarios represent a significant
and growing concern. In the United States and most Western nations, governmentally
funded neuroscience programs adhere to DURC policies, in keeping with the general
constructs of the BTWC and CWC. But such control can also create a dilemma: on the
one hand, it creates parameters for the conduct of brain science in participatory states;
on the other, it can create opportunities for other nations or even nonstate actors to
take advantage of these constraints to gain a competitive edge toward attaining power.
What’s more, international policies and treaties don’t guarantee cooperation, and studies
and applications of brain science don’t have to be covert. As previously noted, the cur-
rent BTWC and CWC do not restrict pharmaceutical formulations of neurotropic drugs
for medical use, or neurotechnologies (e.g., neurostimulatory or modulatory devices);
exemptions for biomedical experimental purposes and/or shields of commercial propri-
etary interests and intellectual property can subvert inquiry into the dual-use or military
applications of brain science (Giordano 2016).
Addressing ethical issues
Military medicine can generate particular ethical circumstances and implications (e.g.,
conflicting military and medical duties; exigencies of battlefield conditions). However,
brain research and the application of new techniques and technologies in military medi-
cine evoke many of the same ethical issues, questions, and steps toward resolution as in
civilian contexts. Also, several fundamental questions and issues about the type(s), extent,
limit(s) and effects of neurological assessment and augmentation of military personnel
can be viewed and addressed in much the same ways that these approaches are dealt with
in civilian settings. There is continued discussion about the potentially coercive nature
and non-consented conduct of biomedical research in the military, discussions that stem
in large part from awareness of past ethical transgressions.
But, as matter of fact, illustration of such transgressions both in the military, and more
widely in biomedical research, have fortified the stringency of responsible practices in
the conduct of research in—and for—the military, at least in the United States, Canada,
540
Table 27.1 Representative international research programs in neuroscience and neurotechnology for national security
Country Major research institutions and Research themes Example research projects and initiatives
funding resources
Australia Defense Science and Technology Group Transcranial direct-current ◆ Evaluating the index of cognitive activity as a measure of men-
(previously DSTO, now DSTG) stimulation (tDCS) tal workload.
◆ Transferring training for battle management systems: From
Land Human Services branch leads group on Artificial intelligence (AI)
Cognition and Behavior and machine cognition simulators to the real world.
◆ Evaluating longitudinal impacts of combat expo-
Centre for Cognitive Work and Safety Analysis Cognitive enhancement/
sure: Neurocognitive, psychological and biological outcomes.
Office of the Chief Defense Scientist performance
◆ Analyzing sleep characteristics of a small Australian Army popu-
Chemical Warfare Agent Laboratory Network Sleep deprivation studies lation and the effect of sleep deprivation on their simulated
driving performance.
Defense Materials Technology Centre
◆ Defining usability of command and control technology while
accumulating sleep loss.
◆ Reducing psychological dependency on ideological groups.
◆ Analyzing cognitive work beyond human factors and engineer-
ing: Application to military doctrine and strategy development.
◆ Evaluating non-invasive brain stimulation: Opportunities and
implications for the Australian Defense Force (ADF).
◆ Determining the importance of cognitive neuroengineering and
computational neuroscience for defense.
Canada National Research Council Canada Biotechnology Sleep and circadian cycles ◆ Novel ligands of prothrombin as inhibitors of blood and extra-
Research Institute (NRC-BRI) Working memory vascular coagulation.
◆ Human factors engineering (HFE) support to Canadian soldier
Defense Research and Development Canada Blood brain barrier-related
(DRDC), particularly the Toronto, Valcartier and systems.
topics
◆ Department of National Defense (DND) and SickKids work-
Suffield locations
Human factors, decision- ing together to better diagnose post-traumatic stress disorder
Defense and Security Research Institute making, and team/group (PTSD) and mild traumatic brain injury (mTBI).
Director General Military Personnel Research & behavior ◆ The future Canadian soldier and enhancement of human per-
Analysis Performance enhancement formance: Research meets policy.
◆ Inflammatory cytokine and chemokine profiles are associated
Pharmacokinetics
with patient outcome and the hyperadrenergic state following
PTSD acute brain injury.
541
◆ Hyperbaric stress in divers and non-divers: Neuroendocrine and
psychomotor responses.
◆ Thromboelastographic study of psychophysiological
stress: A review.
◆ Do framing effects reveal irrational choice?
China National Natural Science Foundation of China “Bio-chips” and ◆ Determining how perceptual learning modifies the functional
Ministry of Science and Technology (MOST) biotechnology specializations of visual cortical areas.
◆ Evaluating minocycline ameliorates hypoxia-induced blood-
Institute of Neuroscience (ION) of the Chinese Trauma
brain barrier damage by inhibition of HIF-1α through SIRT-3/
Academy of the Sciences (CAS) Neurodegeneration
PHD-2 degradation pathway.
Chinese Society for Neuroscience Tumor biology ◆ Creating CGCG clinical practice guidelines for the management
Second Military Medical University Pain and analgesia of adult diffuse gliomas.
◆ Evaluating meCP2 plays an analgesic role in pain transmission
Third Military Medical University Drug abuse and addiction
through regulating CREB/miR-132 pathway.
Fourth Military Medical University in Xi’an ◆ Learning to memorize: Shedding new light on prefrontal
Institute of Neurosciences functions.
◆ Analyzing medial prefrontal activity during delay period contrib-
Zhujiang Hospital, Institute of Neuromedicine
utes to learning of a working memory task.
Partners
◆ Evaluating high-angular diffusion MRI in reward-based psychiat-
Beijing Society for Neuroscience ric disorders.
Neuroscience Research Institute, Peking University ◆ Determining if PKMζ might be a potential target for the treat-
ment of aging-related cognitive impairment, suggesting a
IDG/McGovern Institute for Brain Research at
potential therapeutic avenue.
Peking University
◆ Analyzing functions and mechanisms of microglia/macrophages
Beijing Normal University, National Key Laboratory in neuroinflammation and neurogenesis during stroke.
of Cognitive Neuroscience and Learning
East China Normal University – School of
Psychology and Cognitive Science
The Translational Neuroscience Center of West
China Hospital of Sichuan University
(continued)
542
Table 27.1 Continued
Country Major research institutions and Research themes Example research projects and initiatives
funding resources
Germany Defense laboratories: Bundeswehr Institutes—part Biological agent research ◆ Developing methods and measures to identify relevant charac-
of a “Medical Academy” network PTSD teristic parameters in military workplaces with high cognitive
Institute of Microbiology (InstMikroBioBw) demands.
Cognitive performance
◆ Researching the pathophysiology of mild form of neurological
Center for Aerospace Medicine of the Airforce optimization
decompression sickness.
German Society for Cognitive Science ◆ Analyzing spatial and temporal phylogenesis for the verification
of biological agents using tick-borne encephalitis virus.
◆ Developing new therapies for nerve agent poisoning: From in
vitro models to clinical use.
◆ Evaluating brain activity in soldiers with combat-related PTSD.
◆ Detecting molecular markers in the cerebellum after traumatic
brain injuries (TBI).
India Defense Research and Development Organisation Effects of high altitude ◆ Differentiating neural activation for camouflage detection task
(DRDO) Effects of environmental in field-independent and field-dependent individuals: Evidence
Defense Institute of Psychological Research stress from fMRI
◆ Analyzing the neuroprotective role of L-NG-nitroarginine methyl
DIPAS –Defense Institute of Physiology and Allied Radiation neurobiology
ester (L-NAME) against chronic hypobaric hypoxia with crowd-
Sciences Biological/chemical agent ing stress (CHC) induced depression-like behaviour.
DRDE –Defense Research and Development research ◆ Analyzing the neuroprotective role of intermittent hypobaric
Establishment hypoxia in unpredictable chronic mild stress-induced depression
Institute of Nuclear Medicine and Allied Sciences in rats.
(INMAS) ◆ Evaluating the elevated pulmonary artery pressure and brain
natriuretic peptide in high-altitude pulmonary edema-suscepti-
ble non-mountaineers.
◆ Evaluating neural activation patterns in self deceivers.
◆ Comparing (11)C-methionine and (18)F-fluorodeoxyglucose
positron emission tomography-computed tomography scans in
evaluation of patients with recurrent brain tumors.
◆ Identifying critical path in strategic domains using fuzzy cogni-
tive maps.
543
Israel Israel Institute for Biological Research (IIBR) Therapeutics for CNS/PNS ◆ Evaluating rapid brain MRI based on temporal sparsity
Subsidiary: Life Science Research Israel disorders exploitation.
◆ Analyzing novel bifunctional hybrid small molecule scavengers
Israel Ministry of Defense, Directorate of Defense Nanotechnology
for mitigating nerve agent toxicity.
R&D Neurodegeneration
◆ Evaluating solvent effects on the reactions of the nerve
Affiliates PTSD agent VX with KF/Al2O3: Heterogeneous or homogeneous
Israel National Nanotechnology Initiative Medical diagnostic decontamination?
techniques ◆ Analyzing the attenuation of sarin-induced brain damage in
Ministry of Science, Technology, and Space
rats by delayed administration of midazolam.
Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Zlotowski Protein and enzyme synthe-
◆ Determining if rivastigmine is a safe pretreatment against nerve
Center for Neuroscience sis and engineering
agents poisoning? A pharmacological, physiological and cogni-
Vaccines and tive assessment in healthy young adult volunteers.
pharmaceuticals ◆ Acute and long-term ocular effects of acrolein vapor on the
eyes and potential therapies
◆ Improving functional recovery after experimental traumatic
brain injury via inosine.
North Korea Pyongyang Bio-Institute Anthrax (hypothesized) N/A
Biological agents,
neurotoxins
Russia Russian Foundation for Advanced Research Neurotechnology ◆ Evaluating whether intracortical microinjections may cause
Projects Integrated biosystems spreading depression and suppress absence seizures.
◆ Analyzing a Bayesian classifier for brain–computer interface
Laboratory of Neurotechnology Perception and Memory, perception, and
Recognition with focus areas based on mental representation of movements.
recognition
◆ Activating brain structures by fMRI data when viewing the
Russian Academy of the Sciences Public health and safety video clips and recall of shown actions.
Institute of Higher Nervous Activity Neurotrauma ◆ Determining whether two-faced nitric oxide is necessary for
30th Central Scientific Research Institute, Ministry both erasure and consolidation of memory.
of Defense ◆ Evaluating the influence of the working memory load on the
spatial synchronization of prestimulus cortical electrical activity
State Research Center of Virology and
during recognition of facial expression.
Biotechnology (VECTOR)
◆ Analyzing the mechanisms of orientation sensitivity of human
vision system. Part II: neural patterns of early processing of
information about line orientation.
◆ Evaluating stress reactivity and stress-resilience in the patho-
genesis of depressive disorders: Involvement of epigenetic
mechanisms.
(continued)
54
Table 27.1 Continued
Country Major research institutions and Research themes Example research projects and initiatives
funding resources
United Defense Science and Technology Laboratory Next-generation neuro- ◆ Analyzing R-Cloud human capability SOR—From safety net to
Kingdom Porton Down pharmacology including augmented cognition: Using flexible autonomy levels for on-
nootropic agents line cognitive assistance and automation.
Centre for Defense Enterprise
◆ Initiatives on:
Transcranial stimulation (DC
University of Kent (academic partnership) • Adaptive technologies
and magnetic)
• Human factors
Synthetic biology
• Understanding and influencing human behavior
Machine-augmented • Human performance and protection
cognition • Evaluating the cognitive systems project
Neuro-prostheses
Also interests in: neurotox-
ins, virtual reality, trauma,
social and behavioral
influence
54
United Kingdom, and European Union (Gross & Carrick 2013). There are still uncertain-
ties regarding responsible conduct of research in those countries that employ differing
codes of ethics, and what this portends both for research subjects and for the outcomes of
such research and the capabilities of power incurred. Further questions arise if and when
considering the use of brain science in settings and situations that are explicitly relevant to
warfare, such as warfighter augmentation and the development and use of neuroweapons,
and intelligence operations.
Casebeer has proposed a normative framework for neuroethical address of issues
fostered by neuroscience research and its translation, which although primarily ori-
ented toward military and civilian medicine, can be applied, and is nonetheless useful
to national security, intelligence, and defense agendas (Casebeer 2014). This has been
expanded to engage neuroethicolegal and social risk-assessment and mitigation para-
digm, in which defined steps, queries, and framing constructs are employed to determine
if and how specific uses of neuroscience and neurotechnologies give rise to ethical issues
(Giordano et al. 2014; Giordano 2015). Critical to this approach is consideration of con-
texts of application. An undergirding question is whether neuroethical issues of brain
science in contexts of national security and defense are best addressed in accordance with
military ethics, ethics relevant to enterprises in the public domain, or some other system
or ethical toolkit. It could be argued that ethics are ethics, but ethics provide systematic
analysis and articulation of moral actions relevant to the specific goals, values, and tasks
defined by and within communities of use even though the underlying principles are the
same. This “telic” approach is not an attempt at veiled consequentialism, or mere ethical
relativism, but rather, is ethical realism. It asks: What are the ends (i.e., the telos) of the
profession, and how is the good to be attained and upheld in both end(s) and the means
entailed toward their achievement?
On this realist view, the professional ethics of the military should define the focus,
scope, and conduct of any and all its constituent scientific and technological enterprises.
Just war theory, jus ad bellum, may substantiate using neuroscience and neurotechnol-
ogy (or any science and technology) in national security, intelligence, and defense, in
accordance with ethical precepts that define the need for aggressive actions. The premise
is that war is a horror to be abhorred and avoided, but realistically may sometimes be nec-
essary. Defined criteria attempt to discern if and how such conflict might be prevented,
restrained, and made more humane.
In this latter regard, precepts for fair conduct of conflict (i.e., jus in bello) might define
whether and ways that neuroscience and technologies may be employed within warfare,
or to prevent warfare. But particular attention should be paid to the precept of no means
malum in se, which proscribes the use of methods and weapons that violate some con-
sensus construct of harm (e.g., chemical weapons), or that may be uncontrollable (e.g.,
biological and nuclear weapons), or both of these. This remains a gray zone: as noted pre-
viously, while some domains of brain science fall within the purview of the current BTWC,
CWC, and DURC policy, others such as neurotechnologies do not. Thus, as brain science
both continues to advance and to be assessed for use within national defense agendas,
546
it will be important to address (1) whether extant and new neuroscientific techniques
and technologies can incur harms relative to considerations of means malum in se, and
(2) whether neurotechnologies fall under mandate constraints of biological weaponry.
An underlying issue is the ethics of power, specifically power exercised to preserve
communal values and a way of life. The mission of national security and defense is to
protect the ideals, objectives, and integrity of a state. Like any cutting-edge tool, brain
science can afford an actor’s defined advantage in leveraging relative balances of power
in deterrence and influence. Furthermore, although in a free state the values of the polis
are reflected in its politics, totalitarian regimes often inflict and enforce values of a power
estate upon the polis. This gives rise to questions of relative good: what one state deems to
be right and just may not necessarily be the same for other states. Formal, contemporary
constructs of jus ad bellum define grave, public evil such as “aggression or massive viola-
tion of the basic human rights of … populations” as substantive grounds to justify hostile
action (i.e., war). If this is the case, should neuroscientific techniques and technologies be
part of the armamentarium?
In light of these considerations, it is important to regard “the good” in a variety of
dimensions, as security and defense operations represent state-level enterprises that are
executed and exert influence in an international milieu. Such a view moves beyond the
somewhat narrow confines of military ethics, and brings neuroethical and legal con-
sideration of brain science in national defense agendas into a broader social context.
Consistent with core precepts of other international deliberations upon the use of various
implements in military and defense operations, such consideration would need to evalu-
ate the ways that brain science should or should not be studied, developed, and employed.
In many ways, these considerations reflect more general concerns about both unknown,
unanticipated, and possibly uncontrollable effects of nascent science and technology, and
the sociocultural manifestations and responses generated by the use or misuse of such
techniques and technologies (Giordano & Benedikter 2012; Giordano 2014b). Key ques-
tions include whether the use of certain neuroscientific and technological approaches
incurs greater or lesser risks and harms than other methods of intelligence, security, and
defense, and what limits should be applied to any possible development and use of brain
science in defense initiatives (Tractenberg et al. 2014).
Based upon the activities and results of other international conventions (e.g., the
BTWC, CWC, and Geneva Convention) that have sought to govern military methods and
weapons, we have speculated that such deliberation could lead to two possible outcomes.
The first is a move to ban or restrict any research or use of brain science that is applicable
to military operations. However, this would be difficult, if not impossible, in that existing
brain research can be used for military purposes, and, as we have previously noted in this
chapter, many countries already have directly subsidized military and defense enterprises
of brain research. Thus, unless a ban was universal, restricted research and development
by some could afford opportunities for others to exploit scientific and technological bal-
ances of power (Forsythe & Giordano 2011). The second, and we believe more plausible,
possibility is to work to establish realistic criteria for development and use of specific
547
remains classified, and so public discussion, while necessary, must be carefully engaged
(Giordano et al. 2010). We believe that it is vital to inform the public about the reality and
growing potential for brain science to be used in security, intelligence, and defense opera-
tions, so as to foster broad social awareness.
Indeed, it is the social impact of the use and misuse of brain science in military and
security operations that gives rise to ethical and legal issues. Thus, we do not see mili-
tary and civilian silos of ethicolegal deliberation and guidance as being wholly separate.
Current intramural efforts at various national agencies dedicated to examining current
and future ELSI are commendable. And while it is important to elucidate the ethical issues
that arise in and from such research and its use, ethics alone are not sufficient. Ethics must
inform and lead to the formulation of policies and regulations that guide and govern
what aspects of brain science are studied and employed in these contexts (Dando 2007;
Moreno 2012). The growing potential for the use of novel drugs and devices of brain
science will prompt re-examination and revision of current categorizations, caveats, and
constraints. As we have stated in prior work, it is undeniable that neuroscience is, and
will be, employed in security and defense agendas (Moreno 2012; Wurzman & Giordano
2014). Our hope is that the knowledge and capabilities it confers will be used to prevent
or mitigate violence, reduce conflict, and foster peace.
Acknowledgments
The authors gratefully acknowledge the research and editorial assistance of Celeste Chen
and Kira Becker, and the ongoing collaboration of the Strategic Multilayer Assessment
Group of the Joint Staff of the Pentagon. Aspects of this this work were supported in part
by funding from the Lawrence Livermore National Laboratory (JG) and Office of Naval
Research (JG).
Disclaimer
The work presented in this chapter is solely that of the authors and does not necessarily
represent the perspectives of the United States Department of Defense, Defense Advanced
Research Projects Agency (DARPA), or Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group of the
Joint Staff of the Pentagon.
References
Abney, K., Lin, P., and Mehlman, M. (2014). Military neuroenhancement and risk assessment.
In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and Defense: Practical Considerations,
Neuroethical Concerns, pp.239–248. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Air Force Studies Board (2008). Emerging Cognitive Neuroscience and Related Technologies. Washington,
DC: National Academies Press.
Bell, C. (2014). Why neuroscientists should take the pledge: a collective approach to the misuse of
neuroscience. In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and Defense: Practical
Considerations, Neuroethical Concerns, pp.227–238. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
549
References 549
Benedikter, R. and Giordano, J. (2012). Neurotechnology: new frontiers for European policy. Pan
European Networks: Science & Technology, 3, 204–207.
Bush, V. (1945). Science: the endless frontier. Transactions of the Kansas Academy of Science (1903–),
48(3), 231–264.
Casebeer, W.D. (2013). Plenary Testimonial Presented to US Presidential Commission for the Study of
Bioethical Issues. Available from: https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/node/2779.html
[accessed February 19, 2017].
Casebeer, W.D. (2014). A neuroscience and national security normative framework for the twenty
first century. In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and Defense: Practical
Considerations, Neuroethical Concerns, pp.279–284. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Chameau, J.-L, Balhaus, W.F., and Lin, H.S. (2014). Emerging and Readily Available Technologies and
National Security: A Framework for Addressing Ethical, Legal, and Societal Issues. Washington,
DC: National Academies Press.
Coffey, RJ. (2008). Deep brain stimulation devices: a brief technical history and review. Artificial
Organs, 33(3), 208–220.
Collingridge, D. (1980). The Social Control of Technology. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Committee on Opportunities in Neuroscience for Future Army Applications, National Research
Council of the National Academies (2009). Opportunities in Neuroscience for Future Army
Applications. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
Cummings, M.L. (2010). Technology impedances to augmented cognition. Ergonomics in Design,
18(2), 25–27.
Dando, M. (2007). Preventing the Future Military Misuse of Neuroscience.
New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
Dando, M. (2012). Bioterror and Biowarfare: A Beginner’s Guide. Oxford: OneWorld Publications.
Dando, M. (2015). Neuroscience and the Future of Chemical-Biological Weapons.
New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
DARPA (2015, April 23). HAPTIX Starts Work to Provide Prosthetic Hands with Sense of Touch.
Available from: http://www.darpa.mil/news-events/2015-04-23 [accessed January 4, 2016] [accessed
January 4, 2016].
DARPA (2016). Where the Future Becomes Now. Available from: http://www.darpa.mil/about-us/
timeline/where-the-future-becomes-now [accessed January 4, 2016].
Donovan, E. (2010). Propranolol use in the prevention and treatment of posttraumatic stress disorder
in military veterans: forgetting therapy revisited. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 53(1), 61–74.
Druckman, D. and Swets, J.A. (Eds.) (1988). Enhancing Human Performance: Issues, Theories, and
Techniques. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
Editorial (2003). Silence of the neuroengineers. Nature, 423(6942), 787. Available from: http://www.
nature.com/nature/journal/v423/n6942/full/423787b.html [accessed January 11, 2016].
Evans, NG. (2014). Dual-use decision making: relational and positional issues. Monash Bioethics
Review, 32, 268–283.
Fabing, H.D. (1956). On going berserk: a neurochemical inquiry. American Journal of Psychiatry,
113(5), 409–415.
Farwell, J. (2014). Issues of law raised by the developments and use of neuroscience and
neurotechnology in national security and defense. In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National
Security and Defense: Practical Considerations, Neuroethical Concerns, pp.133–166. Boca Raton,
FL: CRC Press.
Ferguson, J.R. (2000). Biological weapons and US law. In: Lederberg, J. (Ed.) Biological
Weapons: Limiting the Threat, pp.81–91. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
50
Foc.us (2015). Focus Take Charge®—Foc.us Electrical Brain Stimulators. Available from: http://www.foc.
us [accessed February 8, 2017].
Forsythe, C. and Giordano, J. (2011). On the need for neurotechnology in the national intelligence and
defense agenda: scope and trajectory. Synesis: A Journal of Science, Technology, Ethics and Policy,
2(1), 5–8.
Fregni, F. and Pascual-Leone, A. (2007). Technology insight: noninvasive brain stimulation in
neurology—perspectives on the therapeutic potential of rTMS and tDCS. Nature Clinical Practice
Neurology, 3(7), 384.
Giordano, J. (Ed.) (2014a). Neurotechnology in National Security and Defense: Practical Considerations,
Neuroethical Concerns. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Giordano, J. (2014b). Neurotechnology, global relations and national security: Shifting contexts
and neurothical demands. In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and
Defense: Practical Considerations, Neuroethical Concerns, pp.1–10. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Giordano, J. (2014c). The human prospect(s) of neuroscience and neurotechnology: domains of
influence and the necessity—and questions—of neuroethics. Human Prospect, 4(1), 1–18.
Giordano, J. (2015). A preparatory neuroethical approach to assessing developments in
neurotechnology. AMA Journal of Ethics, 17(1), 56–61.
Giordano, J. (2016, May). The neuroweapons threat. Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists. Available
from: http://thebulletin.org/neuroweapons-threat9494 [accessed February 8, 2017].
Giordano, J. and Benedikter, R. (2012). An early—and necessary—flight of the Owl of
Minerva: neuroscience, neurotechnology, human socio-cultural boundaries, and the importance of
neuroethics. Journal of Evolution and Technology, 22(1), 14–25.
Giordano, J. and Wurzman, R. (2016). Integrative computational and neurocognitive science and
technology for intelligence operations: horizons of potential viability, value and opportunity.
STEPS: Science, Technology and Engineering Policy Studies, 4, 32–37.
Giordano, J., Casebeer, W., and Sanchez, J. (2014). Assessing and managing risks in systems neuroscience
research and its translation: A preparatory neuroethical approach. Paper presented at 6th Annual
Meeting of the International Neuroethics Society, Washington, DC.
Giordano, J., Forsythe, C., and Olds, J. (2010). Neuroscience, neurotechnology and national
security: the need for preparedness and an ethics of responsible action. AJOB Neuroscience,
1(2), 1–3.
Golub, A. and Bennett, A.S. (2013). Introduction to the special issue: drugs, wars, military personnel,
and veterans. Substance Use & Misuse, 48, 796.
Gross, M.L. and Carrick, D. (Eds.) (2013). Military Medical Ethics for the 21st Century.
New York: Ashgate.
Hamilton, R., Messing, S., and Chatterjee, A. (2011). Rethinking the thinking cap: ethics of neural
enhancement using noninvasive brain stimulation. Neurology, 76(2), 187–193.
Horvath, J.C., Forte, J.D., and Carter, O. (2015). Quantitative review finds no evidence of cognitive
effects in healthy populations from single-session transcranial direct current stimulation (tDCS).
Brain Stimulation, 8(3), 535–550.
Høyersten, J.G. (2015). Manifestations of psychiatric illness in texts from the medieval and Viking era.
Archives of Psychiatry and Psychotherapy, 2, 57–60.
Kamienski, L. (2016). Shooting Up: A Short History of Drugs and War. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Kappenmann, E., Bikson, M., and Giordano, J. (Eds.) (2016, March). Mechanisms and Effects of
Transcranial Direct Current Stimulation. US Air Force Office of Scientific Research Report.
Kosal, M.E. and Huang, J.Y. (2015). Security implications and governance of cognitive neuroscience.
Politics and the Life Sciences, 34(1), 93–108.
51
References 551
Lanzilao, E., Shook, J., Benedikter, R., and Giordano, J. (2013). Advancing neuroscience on the
21st century world stage: the need for—and proposed structure of—an internationally relevant
neuroethics. Ethics in Biology, Engineering and Medicine, 4(3), 211–229.
Lasswell, H.D. (1941). The Garrison State. American Journal of Sociology, 46(4), 455–468.
Lebedev, M.A. and Nicolelis, M.A.L. (2006). Brain-machine interfaces: past, present and future. Trends
in Neurosciences, 29(9), 536–546.
Lewin, L. (1998). Phantastica: A Classic Survey on the Use and Abuse of Mind-Altering Plants.
New York: Inner Traditions/Bear & Co.
McCreight, R. (2014). Brain brinksmanship: devising neuroweapons looking at battlespace, doctrine
and strategy. In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and Defense: Practical
Considerations, Neuroethical Concerns, pp.115–132. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Miller, R.J. (2013). Drugged: The Science and Culture Behind Psychotropic Drugs. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Moreno, J.D. (2012). Mind Wars. New York: Bellevue Literary Press.
National Research Council. (2008). Emerging Cognitive Neuroscience and Related Technologies.
Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.
National Research Council (US) Committee on Opportunities in Neuroscience for Future Army
Applications (2009). Opportunities in Neuroscience for Future Army Applications. Washington,
DC: National Academies Press. Available from: http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/books/NBK207975/.
Nitsche, M.A. and Paulus, W. (2000). Excitability changes induced in the human motor cortex by weak
transcranial direct current stimulation. Journal of Physiology, 527(3), 633–639.
Nitze, P. (1950). NSC 68: United States Objectives and Programs for National Security. In: May, E. (Ed.)
American Cold War Strategy: Interpreting NSC 68, pp.31–32. Boston, MA: Bedford/St. Martins (1993).
Office of Naval Research: Science & Technology (n.d. a). Code 34: Warfighter Performance Department.
Available from: http://www.onr.navy.mil/Science-Technology/Departments/Code-34.aspx [accessed
April 15, 2016].
Office of Naval Research: Science & Technology (n.d. b). Computational Neuroscience Program.
Available from: http://www.onr.navy.mil/Science-Technology/Departments/Code-34/All-
Programs/human-bioengineered-systems-341/Computational-Neuroscience.aspx [accessed
April 15, 2016].
Parent, A. (2004). Giovanni Aldini: from animal electricity to human brain stimulation. Canadian
Journal of Neurological Sciences, 31, 576–584.
Priori, A., Berardelli, A., Rona, S., Accornero, N., and Manfredi, M. (2008). Polarization of the human
motor cortex through the scalp. Neuroreport, 9(10), 2257–2260.
Quigley, M. (2007). Non-human primates: the appropriate subjects of biomedical research? Journal of
Medical Ethics, 33(11), 655–658.
Robins, L.N., Helzer, J.E., and Davis, D.H. (1975). Narcotic use in Southeast Asia and afterward.
Archives of General Psychiatry, 32(8), 955–961.
Roosevelt, F.D. (1944, November 17). Letter to Vannevar Bush. Available from: https://www.nsf.gov/
about/history/vbush1945.htm#letter [accessed April 15, 2016.
Sato, H., Vo Doan, T.T., Kolev, S., et al. (2015). Deciphering the role of a coleopteran steering muscle
via free flight stimulation. Current Biology, 25(6), 798–803.
Shanker, T. and Duenwald, D. (2003, January 19). Bombing error puts a spotlight on pilots’
pills. The New York Times. Available from: http://www.nytimes.com/2003/01/19/us/threats-
and-responses-military-bombing-error-puts-a-spotlight-on-pilots-pills.html [accessed April
15, 2016].
Shook, J.R. and Giordano, J. (2014). A principled, cosmopolitan neuroethics: considerations for
international relevance. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 9, 1.
52
Shook, J.R. and Giordano, J. (In press). Assessing performance enhancement before neuroethical
evaluations. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience.
Shook, J.R., Galvagni, L., and Giordano, J. (2014). Cognitive enhancement kept within
contexts: neuroethics and informed public policy. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 8, 1–8.
Simeral, J.D., Kim, S.P., Black, M.J., Donoghue, J.P., and Hochberg, L.R. (2011). Neural control of
cursor trajectory and click by a human with tetraplegia 1000 days after implant of an intracortical
microelectrode array. Journal of Neural Engineering, 8(2), 1–24.
Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group, Joint Staff/J-3. (2010). Neurobiology of Political Violence: New
Tools, New Insights. Washington, DC: The Pentagon.
Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group, Joint Staff/J-3. (2012a). Neurobiological & Cognitive Science
Insights on Radicalization and Mobilization to Violence: A Review. Washington, DC: The Pentagon.
Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group, Joint Staff/J-3. (2012b). Cyber on the Brain: The Effects of
CyberNeurobiology & CyberPsychology on Political Extremism. Washington, DC: The Pentagon.
Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group, Joint Staff/J-3. (2012c). National Security Challenges: Insights
from Social, Neurobiological, and Complexity Science. Washington, DC: The Pentagon.
Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group, Joint Staff/J-3. (2013). Topics in Operational Considerations on
Insights from Neurobiology on Influence and Extremism. Washington, DC: The Pentagon.
Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group, Joint Staff/J-3. (2014). Leveraging Neuroscientific and
Neurotechnological Developments with Focus on Influence and Deterrence in a Networked World
(Revised). Washington, DC: The Pentagon.
Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group, Joint Staff/J-3. (2015). Social and Cognitive Neuroscience
Underpinnings of ISIL Behavior and Implications to Strategic Communication, Messaging, and
Influence. Washington, DC: The Pentagon.
Szondy, D. (2012, September 20). DARPA’s CT2WS Technology Uses “Mind Reading” to Identify Threats.
Available from: http://www.gizmag.com/tag-team-threat-recognition-technology/24208 [accessed
April 15, 2016].
Tabery, J. (2014). Can (and should) we regulate neurosecurity? Lessons from history. In: Giordano,
J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and Defense: Practical Considerations, Neuroethical
Concerns, pp.249–258. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Talwar, S. K., Xu, S., Hawley, E.S., Weiss, S.A., Moxon, K.A., and Chapin, J.K. (2002). Rat navigation
guided by remote control. Nature, 417, 37–38.
The President’s Council on Bioethics (US) and Kass, L. (2003). Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the
Pursuit of Happiness. New York: Harper Perennial.
Tractenberg, R.E., FitzGerald, K.T., and Giordano, J. (2014). Engaging neuroethical issues generated
by the use of neurotechnology in national security and defense: toward process, methods and
paradigm. In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and Defense: Practical
Considerations, Neuroethical Concerns, pp.259–278. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Tyler, W.J. (2010, September). Remote control of brain activity using ultrasound. Armed with Science.
Available from: http://science.dodlive.mil/2010/09/01/remote-control-of-brain-activity-using-
ultrasound/[accessed April 15, 2016].
UK ECT Review Group. (2003). Efficacy and safety of electroconvulsive therapy in depressive
disorders: a systematic review and meta-analysis. The Lancet, 361(9360), 799–808.
Ukueberuwa, D. and Wassermann, E.M. (2010). Direct current brain polarization: a simple,
noninvasive technique for human neuromodulation. Neuromodulation, 13(3), 168–173.
53
References 553
White House (2014). Fact Sheet: Over $300 Million in Support of the President’s BRAIN Initiative.
Available from: https://obamawhitehouse.archives.gov/sites/default/files/microsites/ostp/brain_fact_
sheet_9_30_2014_final.pdf [accessed February 14, 2017].
White, S.E. (2008). Brave new world: neurowarfare and the limits of international humanitarian law.
Cornell International Law Journal, 41, 177–210.
Wurzman, R. and Giordano, J. (2014). NEURINT and neuroweapons: neurotechnologies in
national intelligence and defense. In: Giordano, J. (Ed.) Neurotechnology in National Security and
Defense: Practical Considerations, Neuroethical Concerns, pp.79–114. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
54
Chapter 28
its accessibility for the average person (Bucchi 2008). Over time, the process of science
communication broadened and came to include multiple types of stakeholders. In his
famous 1881 public experiment, French chemist Louis Pasteur demonstrated the concept
of vaccination by injecting a group of livestock with an anthrax vaccine, while another
group remained unvaccinated. Farmers, doctors, veterinarians, physiologists, politicians,
and reporters all witnessed the inoculations. The science experiment was successful: all
unvaccinated animals died and all inoculated animals survived. The public experiment
was successful as well: the engagement powerfully demonstrated the value of research
and discovery.
In more recent years, the dissemination of scientific knowledge has grown increas-
ingly complex as once-broad fields of research have become specialized and academic
journals have become the standard for publication of new research findings. In 1985, a
report on the public’s knowledge of science commissioned by the Royal Society urged
scientists to “Learn to communicate with the public, be willing to do so, and consider
it your duty to do so” (Royal Society 1985). However, many years later, scientist com-
municators are seen by their peers as less serious than their less-communicative coun-
terparts: researchers understand the need to communicate broadly, but there is a stigma
attached to those who actively pursue public engagement. A 2006 survey by the Royal
Society on “factors affecting science communication by scientists and engineers” found
that while 74% of Royal Society members surveyed had participated in “at least one
science communication or public engagement activity in the past 12 months,” in inter-
views researchers revealed that “public engagement activity was seen by peers as bad
for their career,” and that “public engagement was done by those who were ‘not good
enough’ for an academic career.” This view that public engagement is detrimental to a
person’s scientific career was especially damaging for junior and women researchers. In
the same survey, 20% of respondents agreed that scientists who engage with the public
are less well regarded by other scientists (Royal Society 2006); 64% of scientists sur-
veyed that the need to spend more time on research was a barrier to engaging in public
engagement activities. Known as “The Sagan Effect” for Dr. Carl Sagan who popularized
science on television for lay audiences in the 1970s and 1980s, this belief that scien-
tists who pursue media and public engagement opportunities are less serious and less
focused on research persists in modern academia, despite being directly at odds with
society’s need to have an educated and informed populace who trusts and sees the value
in scientific research.
Despite these real and perceived barriers in science communication, a 2014 Public
Attitudes to Science Ipsos Mori poll found that 72% of citizens in the United Kingdom
agree with the statement “it is important to know about science in my daily life”; 90% of
those same people stated that they believe that scientists make an important contribu-
tion to society (Ipsos MORI 2014). The public desire for scientific knowledge is very
high, even as overall science literacy appears to be threatened by the inscrutable, top-
down nature of academic publishing. There is a clear disconnect between the goals of
science communication and science literacy in the general population. According to the
56
same poll, nearly 30% of respondents believe that science is speculative, and that “sci-
entific research is never or only occasionally checked by other scientists before being
published,” illustrating the important gap in knowledge about the process of scientific
discovery.
To increase public trust in science, and to improve science literacy, researchers and lay
communicators alike have put forward models of knowledge translation. Earlier mod-
els, such as the deficit model, emphasized the transfer of knowledge in one-way and
one-time processes, such as popularization of science through books. In recent decades,
there has been much discussion and criticism of this top-down dissemination model
(Gregory & Miller 2000; Wilsdon & Willis 2004). As the multidirectional nature of sci-
ence communication emerged, the dialogue model was put forward, proposing a two-
way, iterative process focused on consultation and the recognition and discussion of the
implications of scientific discoveries (Bucchi 2008). In a shift driven by the urgency of
fully engaging lay audiences in research, emerging models of science communication
emphasize engagement between disciplines as well as with the general public. In the
participation model, knowledge is co-produced; multidirectional communication takes
place between all stakeholder groups with the goal of having all parties participate in
shaping the agenda.
As these models evolve, so does the environment in which science communication
takes place. The last century has seen an exponential increase in the specialization of
science. Neuroscience, for example, now comprises dozens of specialties, each with their
own methods, experimental designs, and terminologies. In addition to this specialization,
neuroscience is also becoming increasingly multidisciplinary, with contributions from
engineering, computer science, social sciences, psychology, and ethics, to mention just a
few. As science broadly and neuroscience specifically become increasingly both special-
ized and multidisciplinary, new challenges arise, such as the lack of training in translating
difficult concepts to lay audience (Illes et al. 2009) and the need to effectively translate
across disciplines at the expert level.
Social media
Social media platforms allow for content to be created and modified on an ongoing basis,
and as such have transformed information-sharing from the passive consumption of top-
down dissemination to active engagement with multidirectional, peer-based exchange.
Extensive conversations about dementia are taking place on social media platforms.
59
From one 24-hour period in February 2012, for example, we captured 9200 unique tweets
(Robillard et al. 2013). We used a customized content analysis methodology (Robillard
et al. 2013) to characterize the following features of Twitter posts: (1) users contributing
to this volume of activity on Twitter, (2) websites that are linked to in the tweets, and
(3) thematic content of the tweets.
In answer to the first question, we collected and analyzed publically available data fields
for freely contributed user information. We found that health professionals were the larg-
est group contributing to the conversation. Of the sample, 17% were from this cohort of
individuals operating in all realms of healthcare such as medicine, pharmacy, and nurs-
ing. News groups and commercial organizations also contributed important proportions
of tweets (news: 10%; commercial: 10%). Care services facilities, journalists, patients and
their families, and researchers represented the remaining groups of sources of tweets.
We answered the second question by analyzing the links to third-party websites con-
tained within the text of tweets and found that 50% of the links redirected to an article
hosted on a news site, such as BBC News or CBC News. This finding suggests that while
new media provides unprecedented opportunity for engagement with information, at the
present time popular platforms such as Twitter still rely heavily on traditional media to
create and host content, at least for topics related to dementia.
To answer the third research question, we conducted a content analysis of the text of
tweets. Although researchers themselves were relatively low contributors in the sample
studied, their findings certainly made their way into the tweets: 48% referred to a specific
research study, and of these, 76% were about peer-reviewed, original research. Especially
intriguing was the way that different tweets from different users described the same
research study: for example, an abstract from the 2012 American Academy of Neurology
Annual Meeting entitled “Walking Speed, Handgrip Strength and Risk of Dementia
and Stroke: The Framingham Offspring Study” was featured in a tweet that read “Fast
walking speed and a strong grip in middle age may help predict dementia risk.” Another
tweet based on the same abstract read “Slow walking ‘predicts dementia.’ ” Similarly,
the research described in an article published in the Journal of the American Medical
Association Neurology in 2012 entitled “Sleep Quality and Preclinical Alzheimer Disease”
was tweeted both as “Disturbed sleep is associated with preclinical signs of Alzheimer’s
disease, researchers found” and as “Study shows sleep prevents Alzheimer’s.” In the case
of both these examples about walking speed and sleep, the first tweet harnessed the 140
available characters to provide an accurate representation of the research and used cau-
tious vocabulary designed to mitigate false hopes; the second tweet leans closer toward
misleading and sensationalized oversimplifications.
Science discoveries and advances in biotechnologies that relate to the brain are often
hyped in the media: their benefits exaggerated and their risks minimally discussed. These
overly positive representations of neuroscience and neurology findings can lead to ethical
conflict when they are responsible for the generation of false hopes in potentially vul-
nerable readers. Many different factors contribute to this problem along the entire pro-
cess from scientific discovery to publication: on the one hand, scientists face pressures
560
to appeal to funders, the industry, and to the public; on the other, journalists and media
institutions must put forward newsworthy content to drive profit (Bubela et al. 2009).
With the rise of Internet marketing, headline writers at traditional media outlets have
been put into a position where they must compete with new media aggregators and digi-
tal sales channels for a limited share of Internet users’ attention in an increasingly satu-
rated online space. This has led to headlines tailored specifically to generate an emotional
response in readers in order to entice them to click through to read more. In a 2016
study on science news headlines, researchers found that “although tentativeness is part
and parcel of communicating science, popular science journalism employs epistemic
modality strategically to mix reporting with predicting, recounting with speculating and
evidentiality with possibility (Molek-Kozakowska 2016)”. While the phenomenon of hype
in neuroscience communication has been observed in traditional media (Caulfield and
Rachul 2011; Caulfield and McGuire 2012), it can be further fueled by the format of social
media platforms, for example, those that require very short descriptions of shared con-
tent, such as Twitter. For example, a recent analysis of the discussion about stem cells
and Parkinson’s disease or spinal cord injury on Twitter showed that research was at the
forefront of the discussion but that the majority of tweets were either positive or neutral in
tone and that there was very little discussion of risks (Robillard et al. 2015a). One concern
with sensationalized neuroscience findings is that this would facilitate the early adoption,
use, and promotion of unproven interventions (Ryan et al. 2010). Another consequence
of overly simplified headline-driven science communication is that expertise is diluted
to the point where researchers’ authority over their subject matter appears questionable,
reducing public trust in scientists and institutions (Fischoff 2013), or fueling the increase
of trust in trends like homeopathy or natural health alternatives with no scientific validity
or clinical endorsement.
Websites
Over half of the 65-years-and-older demographic uses the web specifically to seek health
information. To examine the quality of the available information, we applied a quality
evaluation tool to a sample of articles about the prevention of Alzheimer’s disease. We
retrieved 290 articles through a location-independent keyword search on Google, the
most used search engine in North America. The evaluation tool is an original adaptation
of previous work by Chumber and colleagues (Chumber et al. 2015), Sandvik (Sandvik
1999), and the JAMA benchmarks developed by Silberg and colleagues (Silberg et al.
1997). It consists of six weighted criteria for a maximum score of 28: (1) authorship,
(2) attribution, (3) conflict of interest, (4) currency, (5) complementarity, and (6) tone.
The articles scored across the full range of quality, but we distinguished two clear tails
of the distribution: articles that rated poorly (score: 4–11) and those that rated highly
(score: 24–27). Three main characteristics separated the low-and high-quality arti-
cles: conflict of interest, attribution of claims, and tone. The presence of an endorsement
or commercial advertisement of a product or service within an otherwise informational
article about the prevention of Alzheimer’s disease signaled conflict of interest. This
561
important ethical concern was identified in 20% of the sample. None of the highest scor-
ing articles contained this feature. We found that scientific claims were attributed to gen-
eral research (broad, unverifiable claims using research words, such as “research studies
show that … ,” 60% of the articles), specific studies (58%), and quotes from doctors (30%);
many articles contained more than one type of attribution. High-quality articles were
more likely to cite a specific study that could be traced back by the researcher. Finally, the
tone of recommendations differed across the sample. We found strong recommendations,
unequivocal language, and little discussion of alternatives or limitations to the featured
prevention strategies in 22% of the articles. Only 13% presented both balanced advice
with cautious vocabulary, and discussed the limitations of the research supporting the
claims.
As online behaviors have been shown to influence offline behaviors, poor commu-
nication about dementia but also about advances in neuroscience and neurology more
broadly may lead to decision-making toward negative health outcomes. For example, a
study by Walji and colleagues showed that one-quarter of websites about three popular
herbal supplements contained recommendations that, if followed, would lead directly to
physical harms (Walji et al. 2004). Of particular concern is the industry around com-
plementary and alternative medicines for brain conditions ranging from depression to
Alzheimer’s disease. Dietary supplements and homeopathic remedies for a number of
conditions are readily available for purchase on the Internet and promoted through social
media. Palmour and colleagues examined websites about dietary supplements specifically
for Alzheimer’s disease and found that only 16% of these sites contained peer-reviewed
evidence to support the claims about the benefits of the products (Palmour et al. 2014).
While the notion of autonomy in health decision-making favors empowerment and
accessibility to varied sources of information, an ethical conflict arises when the available
resources are so greatly varied in quality.
Self-assessments
Online self-assessments are available for a wide variety of brain-related conditions
including depression, anxiety, migraines, as well as neurodegenerative conditions such
as Alzheimer’s disease. They are also becoming increasingly popular as measured by the
proportion of Internet users who report going online specifically to establish whether
they or someone they know suffer from a medical condition. Today, that number is more
than 30% (Fox 2013). No doubt, self-assessments for brain-related conditions may result
in benefits for the target users: they may feel empowered, they can access information
when traditional health services are difficult to reach, and they may become motivated
to seek medical advice or self-monitor for preventive purposes (Trustram Eve & de Jager
2014). However, the limited oversight of technology-assisted self-assessments may also
adversely lead to inaccurate self-diagnosis and treatment (Lovett et al. 2012). Users may
misinterpret graphic displays of risk and associated terminology (Johnson & Shaw 2012),
and select inappropriate actions that lead to negative health consequences (Waters et al.
562
2009; Lovett et al. 2012). These risks are exacerbated in the case of Alzheimer’s disease for
which no broadly effective treatments exist.
In 2015, we (Robillard and colleagues) published the results of the first study to our
knowledge to evaluate online self-assessments for Alzheimer’s disease. We studied 16
tests available on high-traffic websites (Robillard et al. 2015b) for criteria related to scien-
tific validity such as test–retest reliability, ethical features such as conflict of interest, and
human–computer interactions features such as usability. We found that most tests in our
sample were not scientifically valid and failed to deliver meaningful information about
Alzheimer’s disease or other dementias in an ethically sound and user-friendly way, with
no test scoring excellent across all criteria evaluated. Expert ratings for human–computer
interaction items were variable, with ratings in the acceptable range for clarity of instruc-
tions and quality of the visuals (e.g., contract, font size) and lower ratings for the detecting
of invalid performances and accommodations for varying levels of computer knowledge.
Expert ratings for ethics-related factors were the lowest, and ranged from very poor
to poor across most criteria. Despite the fact that the tests resembled legitimate medi-
cal interventions, the informed consent process was either lacking or overly dense. In
response to the wealth of available information online and to concerns with both DTCA
and informed consent in the digital age, Bal and Brenner ask “Has the Internet made
informed consent obsolete?” (Bal & Brenner 2015). Indeed, the digital age has shifted
how patients educate themselves about their conditions, the available conventional but
also alternative treatments, and the risks and benefits associated with each option. While
informed consent was initially designed in the context of a system whereby the physician
is the primary source of health information, a recent survey found that 91% of physicians
surveyed have seen patients who made inquiries about information they found online
(Kim J. & Kim S. 2009). When writing about informed consent in the online environment
more broadly, for example with regard to personalized advertising and behavior tracking,
Friedman and colleagues state: “To date, informed consent is woefully understudied by
the online community and underused as a means of cultivating trust online,” and call for
research into the development of principles to implement consent in the online environ-
ment (Friedman et al. 2000). As the medical community shifts toward new channels of
communication about brain health, it becomes imperative to consider how information
and misinformation acquired through online and mobile platforms will impact the ethi-
cal duty to obtain informed consent for both online interventions and those delivered in
the clinic.
Similarly, for most tests, language around privacy and confidentiality of the data
that were entered as part of the test-taking process was either absent or incorpo-
rated into lengthy terms of agreement. In Canada, the Freedom of Information and
Protection of Privacy Act was enacted in the 1980s “to govern the collection, use and
disclosure of personal information by organizations in a manner that recognizes both
the right of individuals to protect their personal information and the need of organi-
zations to collect, use or disclose personal information for purposes that a reasonable
person would consider appropriate in the circumstances” (Office of the Information
563
and Privacy Commissioner 1983). The Act protects the personal information of pri-
vate citizens and limits disclosure of personal information by organizations or pub-
lic bodies; however, this protection extends only to information stored on Canadian
servers. Other jurisdictions may offer different or no protection for personal data.
Without protective legislation in place, personal data may be vulnerable to third-
party sale, subpoena, or theft.
In the United States, the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act (GINA) (United
States 2008) protects private citizens from discrimination by employers or insurers
based on genetic information, and builds upon the Health Insurance Portability and
Accountability Act (HIPPA) (United States 2004) and related privacy rules. The intention
of these privacy rules was meant to protect individuals’ private health information, but
there is no guideline or legislation in place to ensure privacy of personal health informa-
tion given voluntarily via non-healthcare commercial entities, such as websites.
Terms of agreement may be vague in detailing how personal data may be used, and
because this is relatively new legal terrain, it is unclear in many jurisdictions whether user
agreements for web services and products are legally binding or if the terms themselves
are ethically sound.
All 16 tests in our sample rated either very poorly or poorly with regard to conflicts of
interest. For example, one of the self-assessments for dementia in the sample consisted
of a number of questions about daily activities, behaviors, and risk factors. However, all
possible combinations of answers yielded the same result: a strongly worded warning
about a severe risk of developing Alzheimer’s disease, followed by a recommendation to
purchase three different supplements from the online store of the website. In this case, a
predatory marketing strategy masqueraded as a self-test aimed at providing meaning-
ful information regarding one’s risk of developing dementia. Though not all conflicts of
interests uncovered in our studies were so deeply problematic, they all had the poten-
tial to compromise the quality of the information offered to a vulnerable segment of the
population, especially as older adults may experience difficulties with the identification
of trustworthy information (Castle et al. 2012). In turn, information that is unbalanced,
biased, or of poor quality may compromise personal autonomy and prevent meaningful
decisions for brain health.
Looking to the future
“In the 16th century,” writes Robert Lucky, “science progressed at the pace of the postal
system. Often it would take six months for one scientist to learn of the ongoing results of
another. It took even more time for scientists to build on one another’s accomplishments”
(Lucky 2000). As the ability of scientists to communicate more efficiently has improved,
so has the ability to uncover the mysteries of the brain and behavior. In parallel, the rate
of discovery has advanced together with technology, with publication rates in scientific
journals increasing by nearly 5% per year (Larsen & von Ins 2010). The benefit of moving
from a top-down to a participatory model of neuroscience communication in a process
564
Over 30 years later, the recommendations of the Royal Society’s 1985 report for
scientists to consider science communication a duty are still very relevant. Looking
to the future, all scholars in the life and social sciences must include in these recom-
mendations to keep pace with the rapidly evolving communications landscape and
embrace the conversation about brain, health, and ethics that is taking place on inter-
active platforms (Table 28.1). In the balance of the benefits and risks of new com-
munication channels lies a significant opportunity for scientists to engage with the
public about neuroscience and neuroethics, and to join forces in developing priorities
for the future.
(continued)
56
Table 28.1 Continued
Acknowledgments
J.M.R would like to acknowledge all co-authors who contributed to this published work,
research assistant Tanya Feng at the National Core for Neuroethics, University of British
Columbia, for her work on the analysis of websites about the prevention of Alzheimer’s
disease, and all members of the Robillard lab for their contributions to the development
of the online health information quality evaluation tool.
References
Bal, B.S. and Brenner, L.H. (2015). Medicolegal sidebar: informed consent in the information age.
Clinical Orthopaedics and Related Research, 473, 2757–2761.
Benigeri, M. and Pluye, P. (2003). Shortcomings of health information on the Internet. Health
Promotion International, 18, 381–386.
Blakemore, C. (2002). From the “public understanding of science” to scientists' understanding of the
public. In Marcus, S.J. (Ed.) Neuroethics: Mapping the Field, pp.211–221. New York: Dana Press.
Block, G., Sternfeld, B., Block, C.H., et al. (2008). Development of Alive! (A Lifestyle Intervention
Via Email), and its effect on health-related quality of life, presenteeism, and other behavioral
outcomes: randomized controlled trial. Journal of Medical Internet Research, 10, e43.
Bubela, T., Nisbet, M.C., Borchelt, R., et al. (2009). Science communication reconsidered. Nature
Biotechnology, 27, 514–518.
Bucchi, M. (2008). Handbook of Public Communication of Science and Technology. Abingdon: Routledge.
Castle, E., Eisenberger, N.I., Seeman, T.E., et al. (2012). Neural and behavioral bases of age differences
in perceptions of trust. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of
America, 109, 20848–20852.
Caulfield, T. and McGuire, A. (2012). Athletes’ use of unproven stem cell therapies: adding to
inappropriate media hype? Molecular Therapy, 20, 1656–1658.
Caulfield, T. and Rachul, C. (2011). Science spin: iPS cell research in the news. Clinical Pharmacology &
Therapeutics, 89, 644–646.
Chumber, S., Huber, J., and Ghezzi, P. (2015). A methodology to analyze the quality of health
information on the internet the example of diabetic neuropathy. The Diabetes Educator, 41, 95–105.
567
References 567
Cline, R.J.W. and Haynes, K.M. (2001). Consumer health information seeking on the internet: the state
of the art. Health Education Research, 16, 671–692.
Corner, L. and Bond, J. (2004). Being at risk of dementia: fears and anxieties of older adults. Journal of
Aging Studies, 18, 143–155.
Eysenbach, G., Powell, J., Kuss, O., and Sa, E.R. (2002). Empirical studies assessing the quality of health
information for consumers on the world wide web: a systematic review. JAMA, 287, 2691–2700. 1.
Fischhoff, B. and Scheufele, D.A. (2013). The science of science communication. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 110(Suppl. 3), 14031–14032.
Fox, S. (2013). Health Online 2013. Washington, DC: Pew Research Center’s Internet & American Life
Project.
Friedman, B., Khan Jr, P.H., and Howe, D.C. (2000). Trust online. Communications of the ACM,
43, 34–40.
Gollust, S.E., Wilfond, B.S., and Hull, S.C. (2003). Direct-to-consumer sales of genetic services on the
Internet. Genetics in Medicine, 5, 332–337.
Gregory, J. and Miller, S., 2000. Science in Public: Communication, Culture, and Credibility. Cambridge,
MA: Basic Books.
Hawn, C. (2009). Take two aspirin and tweet me in the morning: how Twitter, Facebook, and other
social media are reshaping health care. Health Affairs (Millwood), 28, 361–368.
Idriss, S.Z., Kvedar, J.C., and Watson, A.J. (2009). The role of online support communities: benefits of
expanded social networks to patients with psoriasis. Archives of Dermatology, 145, 46–51.
Illes, J. (Ed.) (2006). Neuroethics: Defining the Issues in Theory, Practice, and Policy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Illes, J., Kann, D., Karetsky, K., et al. (2004). Advertising, patient decision making, and self-referral
for computed tomographic and magnetic resonance imaging. Archives of Internal Medicine, 164,
2415–2419.
Illes, J., Moser, M.A., McCormick, J.B., et al. (2009). Neurotalk: improving the communication of
neuroscience research. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 61–69.
Ipsos MORI (2014, March). Public Attitudes to Science 2014. Available from: https://www.ipsos-mori.
com/researchpublications/researcharchive/3357/Public-Attitudes-to-Science-2014.aspx [accessed
April 16, 2016].
Jacques, J. and Raichvarg, D. (1991). Savants et ignorants: Une histoire de la vulgarisation des sciences.
Paris: Seuil.
Johnson, C.M. and Shaw, R.J. (2012). A usability problem: conveying health risks to consumers on the
Internet. AMIA Annual Symposium Proceedings, 2012, 427–435.
Kim, E.-H., Coumar, A., Lober, W.B., and Kim, Y. (2011). Addressing mental health epidemic among
university students via web-based, self-screening, and referral system: a preliminary study. IEEE
Transactions on Information Technology in Biomedicine, 15, 301–307.
Kim, J. and Kim, S. (2009). Physicians’ perception of the effects of internet health information on the
doctor–patient relationship. Informatics for Health and Social Care, 34, 136–148.
Kortum, P., Edwards, C., and Richards-Kortum, R. (2008). The impact of inaccurate Internet health
information in a secondary school learning environment. Journal of Medical Internet Research,
10, e17.
Larsen, P.O. and von Ins, M. (2010). The rate of growth in scientific publication and the decline in
coverage provided by Science Citation Index. Scientometrics, 84, 575–603.
Lovett, K.M., Mackey, T.K., and Liang, B.A. (2012). Evaluating the evidence: direct-to-consumer
screening tests advertised online. Journal of Medical Screening, 19, 141–153. 1.
Lucky, R. (2000) The quickening of science communication. Science, 289(5477), 259–64.
568
References 569
United States (2009). The Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act of 2008 (GINA). Washington,
DC: US Department of Labor, Employee Benefits Security Administration.
van Uden-Kraan, C.F., Drossaert, C.H.C., Taal, E., Seydel, E.R., and van de Laar, M.A. (2009).
Participation in online patient support groups endorses patients’ empowerment. Patient Education
and Counseling, 74, 61–69.
Vance, K., Howe, W., and Dellavalle, R.P. (2009). Social internet sites as a source of public health
information. Dermatologic Clinics, 27, 133–136, vi.
Walji, M., Sagaram, S., Sagaram, D., et al. (2004). Efficacy of quality criteria to identify potentially
harmful information: a cross-sectional survey of complementary and alternative medicine web sites.
Journal of Medical Internet Research, 6.
Wangberg, S.C., Andreassen, H.K., Prokosch, H.-U., Santana, S.M.V., Sørensen, T., and Chronaki,
C.E. (2008). Relations between Internet use, socio-economic status (SES), social support and
subjective health. Health Promotion International, 23, 70–77.
Waters, E.A., Sullivan, H.W., Nelson, W., and Hesse, B.W. (2009). What is my cancer risk? How
internet-based cancer risk assessment tools communicate individualized risk estimates to the
public: content analysis. Journal of Medical Internet Research, 11, e33.
World Health Organization (n.d.). Neurology and Public Health. Available from: http://www.who.int/
mental_health/neurology/en/ [accessed April 16, 2016].
Wilsdon, J. and Willis, R. (2004). See-Through Science: Why Public Engagement Needs to Move
Upstream. London: Demos.
Wolfe, S.M. (2002). Direct-to-consumer advertising—education or emotion promotion? New England
Journal of Medicine, 346, 524–526.
Zulman, D.M., Kirch, M., Zheng, K., and An, L.C. (2011). Trust in the internet as a health resource
among older adults: analysis of data from a nationally representative survey. Journal of Medical
Internet Research, 13.
570
Chapter 29
Introduction
For better and worse, biomedical explanations of human behavior, including genetic and
neuroscientific explanations, seem to affect public perceptions of a person’s moral and
legal responsibility for that behavior. This effect flows from the tendency to regard a per-
son’s biological constitution as given and largely fixed and, crucially, as a causal contribu-
tor to that person’s behavior. In other words, the perception seems to be first that a person
has no control over the origin and little control over the continuation of that essential bio-
logical nature, and second, that this biology determines or at least predisposes a person to
a particular behavior. Because the person has little control over any of this, the person is
perceived to have diminished responsibility for that behavior. As I will discuss, the extent
to which this pattern of thought holds true, and the circumstances in which it does so, are
both still matters of debate.
The purpose of this chapter is to consider the hypothesis that neurobiological
accounts of behavior will affect the law, not just in the criminal context, but also in
how disability is defined in the law. The chapter first presents a very short overview of
some of the ways that neurobiology may affect judgments of criminal responsibility,
in order to explore the importance of control in assessing responsibility as well as the
countervailing impulse to control and supervise those who are judged to be dangerous
and incapable of controlling themselves rather than unwilling to do so. The chapter
then proceeds to explain how control and responsibility for one’s condition affects the
concept of disability and the social willingness to offer support and protection. Finally,
examples drawn from the treatment in human rights law of contested conditions like
addictions to gambling, sex or the Internet, and nicotine are used to illustrate the man-
ner in which medicalization and, where possible, neurobiological explanations, have
been used to try to suggest that the conditions constitute disabilities that ought to be
accommodated rather than punished.
571
Introduction 571
The positive consequences of this phenomenon lie in the reduction of blame for socially
disfavored behavior and traits and increased willingness to forgive and to help. However,
the negative consequences flow from the corollary of the idea that the person’s behavior
is explained by biological factors beyond his or her control, namely that the person is a
faulty biological mechanism lacking self-control. In other words, the person is viewed
as falling within a different biological category than other people, and furthermore, the
person must be supervised or controlled if the disfavored behavior poses a threat. The
particular mix of these reactions will likely vary from case to case, and the impulse to
help may be swamped by the more negative reactions for behaviors that are perceived as
particularly dangerous.
These are general reactions documented and discussed in the study of mental
health stigma, biopolitics, and many other fields. In recent years, they have been
increasingly discussed in the law. Since the questions of self-control, responsibility,
and moral blameworthiness are of central importance in ascribing criminal respon-
sibility and selecting the appropriate social response, a large literature has developed
regarding the effect of behavioral genetics and neuroscience on criminal responsi-
bility. The research has been both empirical, attempting to determine the likely or
actual impact on moral reasoning and judgment, and also normative, arguing about
whether, when, and how this evidence ought to affect moral reasoning and judgment
in the context of criminal justice.
But these questions certainly do not exhaust the potential legal ramifications of genetic
and neuroscientific explanations of human behavior. The questions of responsibility and
self-control are important not just for affixing legal liability for harmful actions; they also
turn out to be fundamental to social solidarity. People who are perceived to be in control
of, and therefore responsible for their problems are much less likely to be perceived as
having disabilities that are deserving of support in the form of financial assistance and
protection from discrimination. This is particularly the case for psychiatric or behavioral
conditions, as opposed to physical disabilities.
A review of the manner in which the brain disease concept has been used to repel blame
and to support claims to solidarity and protection in relation to a multitude of different
highly stigmatized behavioral conditions (e.g., schizophrenia, depression, addiction, and
obesity) over the years reveals these patterns of thought and their political significance.
Of course, the framing of these conditions as a biomedical disease is itself contested. The
neurodiversity movement, for example, pushes back against the biomedical model of dis-
ability. It accepts biological essentialism and indeed crafts a group identity around the
biological difference, but rejects the pejorative framing of the difference as a disease or
disorder. The broader concept of the social construction of disability, which continues to
battle the biomedical model of disability, locates the negative consequences of a physical
or mental difference in the intolerant and inflexible social environment rather than within
the person him-or herself. While these movements have succeeded to some extent, much
of the law remains firmly within the biomedical model.
572
To some extent this is an old story. The pressure to medicalize various conditions in
order to fend off blame and judgment and to elicit support is not new, and operates even
where neither genetic nor neurobiological causal factors can be identified. Even a psychi-
atric diagnosis offers something in this ideological battle. However, there is evidence that
the public tends to assign more control and therefore more blame to a person for his or
her behavior when it is explained in psychiatric rather than organic terms. In other words,
the brain-based account is likely to be a more potent force in reducing blame assigned to
those with stigmatized and disfavored behaviors and conditions.
A final dimension in this exploration of the ideological impact of neurobiological
explanations of behavior is the question of self-fulfilling prophecies. If people are pushed
to claim a lack of self-control in order to ward off blame and judgment, or to claim a right
to social support, are we in fact forcing them into that corner? The potentially dispirit-
ing and anti-therapeutic effects of brain disease models of mental illness and addictions
have been pointed out many times. In the legal context, the analogue to this concern is
that biological deterministic explanations of criminal behavior may be demotivating and
may undermine rehabilitation and reintegration. Similarly, a disability definition built on
establishing a lack of control over the condition may itself be disabling because it under-
mines a person’s motivation and sense of control.
At the sentencing hearing, convicted offenders frequently point to factors that suggest
diminished capacity in order to try to reduce their degree of responsibility and thus the
moral blameworthiness of their acts. For example, offenders may point to mental disor-
ders that, while insufficient to render a person non-criminally responsible, may serve to
reduce the moral blameworthiness of their actions and the severity of the sentence that is
viewed as appropriate (Ruby 2004, para. 5.246; R. v. Belcourt 2010).
At the same time, causal explanations for the criminal behavior that suggest diminished
capacity may increase the perception that an offender is out of control and a risk to the
public. A sentence reflects many objectives, including not just retributive punishment
proportionate to the degree of moral blameworthiness but also a range of consequen-
tialist objectives including the protection of the public. Where prospects for rehabilita-
tion are considered to be poor, a heavy sentence may be viewed as necessary for public
safety even if moral blameworthiness is lowered due to diminished capacity. This double
effect—the reduction of moral blameworthiness, which would reduce the length of the
sentence, along with an increased perception of dangerousness, which might increase the
length of the sentence—has been termed the “double-edged sword” of neurobiological
causal explanations of criminal behavior (Aspinwall et al. 2012). To the extent that neuro-
biological explanations invite the conclusion of a “broken brain” that erodes self-control
and is unlikely to be amenable to treatment, the outcome on sentence may depend upon
the circumstances (e.g., the perceived riskiness of the offender or the type of offence in
question).
An example of these countervailing impulses is the sentencing decision in the case of
R. v. Obed (2006). Obed was sentenced to 10 years of imprisonment for a violent sexual
assault. At the sentencing hearing, the judge considered evidence regarding Obed’s cha-
otic and abusive childhood, as well as evidence of brain damage associated with prenatal
alcohol exposure. The judge clearly felt that these factors meant that Obed had dimin-
ished responsibility for his crime. Yet, the judge also noted that there was neither a good
treatment for Obed’s brain damage nor good prospects for rehabilitation. The judge con-
cluded that the predominant consideration in selecting the sentence was the protection of
the public (Obed 2006, para. 54). At the conclusion of the sentence, the judge addressed
the offender directly in a way that clearly shows the tension between retribution and con-
sequentialism in a case of diminished capacity due to brain damage:
Mr. Obed before you go. I don’t know what more to say to you. I feel almost helpless in one way by
the inability of the court in being able to do something that would offer you some form of reha-
bilitation. This is the first case I’ve ever had where I felt that rehabilitation was not a realistic factor.
I hope that somehow the Federal or Provincial authorities will take a hard look at this FASD [fetal
alcohol spectrum disorder] phenomenon. I hope, as well, that you become the person that they
rally around and work with and see if somehow, some of this damage … Dr. Rosales says that it’s
irreversible and that the brain no longer develops after a certain point. That’s what we know right
now … Five years, two year from now maybe we’ll know a whole lot of different things. Maybe in
a couple of years from now we can actually go inside the brain and reorganize things. I don’t know.
I just hope in your case, because this is one of those cases that to me falls somewhere between total
responsibility and diminished responsibility and I don’t know really … But I refuse to be without
574
hope and in your case I hope that something comes along that can focus on you and help you with
this … You’re not that old that further research can’t have a profound effect on you and I would
hope that you do benefit from such future research. In any event, in the meantime, I have to protect
society from your violent behaviour. I have to protect people from you, even from behaviour that
you don’t know you’re going to commit yet. (R. v. Obed 2006, para. 78)
With the development of behavioral genetics, particularly the identification of gene vari-
ants thought to be associated with an increased risk for impulsive violence, as well as neu-
roimaging that is looking for structural and functional correlates of particular behavioral
abnormalities such as psychopathy, there has been an increase in interest in how such
biological evidence might be used in the criminal justice context. Among the questions
posed are the extent to which this evidence is being used in criminal cases, and the issue
of how it is or should be affecting assessments of criminal responsibility and the selection
of the appropriate responses to offending. Of course, evidence related to mental disor-
der has long been presented to criminal courts. The more novel question posed by these
emerging forms of biologically focused accounts of behavior is whether they are more
likely or not than the more typical psychiatric diagnoses to reduce attributions of control
and blame.
While the research results are inconsistent so far, there are intriguing studies that do
suggest that the effects of neurobiological explanations sometimes differ from those of
psychiatric explanations of criminal behavior.
Aspinwall and colleagues surveyed a group of nearly 200 American state trial judges
and found that evidence supporting a neurobiological cause of an offender’s psychopathy
reduced the sentence imposed as well as the extent to which the psychopathy was viewed
as an aggravating factor (Aspinwall et al. 2012). The judges considered a vignette in which
a psychiatrist provided expert testimony that a man who committed a violent assault was
a psychopath. Half of the participants also received the expert testimony of a neurobiolo-
gist who presented a neurobiological explanation of the psychopathy. The participants
were able to provide explanatory comments on their responses. One judge wrote that
“[t]he evidence that psychopaths do not have the necessary neural connections to feel
empathy is significant. It makes possible an argument that psychopaths are, in a sense,
morally ‘disabled’ just as other people are physically disabled” (Aspinwall et al. 2012,
p.847). The neurobiological explanation of psychopathy appears to have reduced per-
ceived moral blame but at the same time may have increased the perception of increased
dangerousness. Another judge wrote that “[p]sychopathy may make the defendant less
morally culpable, but it increases his future dangerousness to society. In my mind, these
factors balance out” (Aspinwall et al. 2012, p.848).
Fuss and colleagues repeated with a group of German judges a version of the study
conducted by Aspinwall and colleagues (Aspinwall et al. 2012; Fuss et al. 2015). They
presented the judges with a vignette in which an expert provided a psychiatric diagnosis
of psychopathy. Half also received expert testimony from a neurobiologist explaining psy-
chopathy as a genetically driven developmental condition and indicating that the offender
had the gene in question. Fuss and colleagues found that the neurobiological explanation
57
slightly reduced the judgment of legal responsibility, but it did not significantly affect
the prison sentence imposed (Fuss et al. 2015). The presentation of the neurobiological
evidence by the prosecution did greatly increase the decision to order involuntary com-
mitment in a psychiatric hospital, which could lead to a longer detention time.
There have also been studies of public reactions to biological explanations of behav-
ior. Monterosso and colleagues surveyed the public to see whether scientific explana-
tions of undesirable behavior reduced perceived culpability (Monterosso et al. 2004).
They looked at four types of undesirable behavior: setting fire to a building, killing a
store clerk over a disagreement, overeating, and consistent failure to follow through on
plans. They found that physiological explanations were more likely to lead to reduced
judgments of culpability than socioenvironmental explanations in all four cases. For
example, in the case of the man who killed the store clerk, attributions of culpability
were lower where the explanation given for his behavior was a greatly elevated amount
of a particular brain chemical versus the experience of severe and brutal abuse as a
child. The physiological explanations also elicited lower scores on a composite measure,
showing reduced judgments of voluntariness, greater sympathy, greater mitigation of
blame, more positive treatment, and greater likelihood that the participants themselves
would behave in the undesirable way if the explanatory condition were true of them
(Monterosso et al. 2004, p.150).
Monterosso and colleagues speculated that the Western perception of the person is
dualistic, and the mind (or soul) and body are perceived as two separate forces inde-
pendently capable of bringing about behavior (Monterosso et al. 2004, p.154). Further,
behavior tends to be perceived as voluntary or “owned by the self ” only when it flows
from the mind (or soul), and where one force is operating it is perceived as denying the
causal efficacy of the other. They suggest that this explains “why, in our vignettes, when a
physiological explanation was given, participants tended to view the body as the cause of
the behaviour and motivations as less relevant, with the result that the behaviour was per-
ceived as less voluntary” (Monterosso et al. 2004, p.155). They suggest that this manner of
thought may lead to reduced space for intentional agency as the physiological behavioral
sciences advance.
There is also research questioning whether biological explanations of criminal behav-
ior will affect judgments of responsibility. Scurich and Appelbaum (2015) failed to find
an effect of biological (genetic and neurobiological) explanations of wrongful behavior
on public decisions about punishment. They suggest several possible explanations. First,
ordinary people may regard biological predisposition as only one influence on behavior,
and one that is not necessarily the prime determinant of the behavior in a given con-
text. Second, they suggest that these explanations might activate countervailing concerns
about dangerousness, which negate any mitigating impact on punishment.
In sum, the evidence is presently mixed on the question of whether or when bio-
logical explanations of criminal behavior produce different perceptions of control and
responsibility than psychosocial explanations. Nonetheless, some of the experimen-
tal evidence suggests such an effect in both public and judicial decision-making. The
576
ultimate effect on punishment decisions may be slight for serious offences, however,
given that perceptions of dangerousness may increase at the same time as perceived
culpability decreases.
reasonable efforts to facilitate the accommodation by, for example, participating in a reha-
bilitation program:
When an alcoholic employee has failed to respond to multiple rehabilitation efforts and there is no
objective evidence that further efforts at accommodation would be likely to succeed, it is generally
concluded that the employee has been accommodated to the point of undue hardship. (Kellogg
Canada Inc v. Bakery, Confectionary, Tobacco Workers & Grain Millers 2006)
Many of these legal instruments do not provide particularly precise definitions of disabil-
ity, meaning that the list of specific impairments that fall within the scope of entitlements
to support or protection from discrimination evolves over time and remains uncertain in
some cases (Law Commission of Ontario 2009, pp.10–11). It is this area of uncertainty
that may ultimately be influenced by emerging neurobiological explanations of stigma-
tized behavior and conditions. As noted in the section “Perceived control, responsibil-
ity, and social solidarity,” attribution theory predicts that conditions and behaviors that
are seen to fall outside personal control are more likely to generate reactions of social
solidarity—willingness to provide support and protection from discrimination.
The political and economic significance of the definition of disability is clear. As the
Law Commission of Ontario (2009, p.11) puts it, claimants seek “the label of ‘disability’
in order to access benefits and supports, while institutions [withhold] the label in order
to maintain program standards.” Other institutional actors may also use the definition of
disability strategically, inappropriately finding disabilities where this will generate higher
funding allocations (Law Commission of Ontario 2009, p.12). Others police the bound-
ary of disability to ward off what they perceive as inappropriate attempts to appropriate
resources that should be made available to those whose impairments they consider more
genuinely disabling. For example, Gilbert and Majury cite the argument that a legal claim
lodged by an infertile couple that the exclusion of a form of infertility treatment from
provincially funded health care discriminated on the basis of disability (i.e., infertility)
“appropriated a disability rights discourse [in order] to gain access to resources and ser-
vices forged by earlier efforts at advocating very different disability issues” (Gilbert &
Majury 2006, p.112). Of course the use of models that attract social sympathy and sup-
port will be taken up by others seeking a similar response, a pattern revealed by the use
of the concept of addiction to describe other compulsive behaviors unrelated to drugs or
alcohol, including compulsive behavior related to food, the Internet, and sex.
The medicalization of a condition tends to support its inclusion within the scope of dis-
ability for legal purposes, although this is not invariably the case. The biomedical model
of disability—the dominant understanding of disability for much of the twentieth cen-
tury, and still the dominant public conception of disability—is reflected in many laws. For
example, access to disability benefits is largely defined in biomedical terms and eligibil-
ity for benefits is verified by medical professionals (Law Commission of Ontario 2009,
p.17). As a result, the development of a biomedical conception of a condition is often
a key requirement to accessing the protections available by law. It is not strictly neces-
sary that this conception involve a known biological etiology to qualify as a disability for
579
legal purposes, because the human rights laws cover both physical and mental disabili-
ties. However, the claim to inclusion as a disability and to social solidarity is strength-
ened where there is a lack of control over a disabling condition, which biological causal
explanations of the condition suggest more persuasively than do psychological causal
explanations.
Drug and alcohol dependency and addiction are considered disabilities under human
rights legislation (Canadian Human Rights Act s.25; Ontario Human Rights Commission
2014). Thus, the exclusion of people with drug and alcohol dependency or addiction
from eligibility for disability benefits constituted discrimination on the basis of dis-
ability (Ontario v. Tranchemontagne 2009). The human rights jurisprudence now com-
monly refers to drug and alcohol dependency and addiction as a disease of the brain (e.g.,
Milazzo v. Autocar Connaisseur Inc. 2003), a framing that has been in the ascendant since
the early 1970s (Vrecko 2010, p.58).
The path forged by drug and alcohol addictions toward a neurobiological disease model
is now being emulated in relation to a range of other compulsive behaviors. As Vrecko
(2010, p.54) puts it, “[p]ersonal, social and legal issues associated not only with drugs, but
with a range of compulsive and problematic behaviours—including criminal offending,
spending and debt, gambling and obesity—are coming to be represented as, at least in
part, problems of the molecular body and brain.” Canadian legal cases reveal the manner
in which neurobiology is being adopted in the legal context to reduce perceptions of con-
trol and moral blameworthiness for this broader range of stigmatized behavior.
Disability claims involving addictions to gambling, nicotine, sex, and the Internet are pre-
sented in the following sections. While nicotine addiction has been medicalized for some
time, warranting its own section—“Nicotine-related disorders”—within the Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, fourth edition (DSM-IV) section on “Substance-
related disorders” (American Psychiatric Association 2000, p.264), gambling addiction has
recently been reclassified because of neurobiological evidence. Pathological gambling was
formerly classified in the DSM-IV as an “impulse control disorder” (American Psychiatric
Association 2000 p.312.31) and was reclassified in the DSM-5 within the section on
“Substance-related and addictive disorders” (American Psychiatric Association 2013). The
notes on the section indicate that gambling disorder has been added because of “evidence
that gambling behaviors activate reward systems similar to those activated by drugs of
abuse and produce some behavioral symptoms that appear comparable to those produced
by the substance use disorders” (American Psychiatric Association 2013).
As for addictions to sex and the Internet, official psychiatric diagnoses are not yet
recognized. As the notes on gambling disorder in the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric
Association 2013) state:
Other excessive behavioral patterns, such as Internet gaming, have also been described, but the
research on these and other behavioral syndromes is less clear. Thus, groups of repetitive behav-
iors, which some term behavioral addictions, with such subcategories as “sex addiction,” “exercise
addiction,” or “shopping addiction,” are not included because at this time there is insufficient
580
peer-reviewed evidence to establish the diagnostic criteria and course descriptions needed to iden-
tify these behaviors as mental disorders.
Gambling addiction
Gambling addictions typically arise in legal cases in one of two contexts. First, they are
raised as explanations for criminal behavior (e.g., stealing from an employer to finance
gambling). The judicial reactions to this type of argument are mixed, perhaps reflecting
the degree of perceived lack of self-control in specific cases. Second, they are raised to
try to challenge dismissal from employment. In these employment grievances, the argu-
ment made is that the gambling addiction is a disability and so the wrongful behavior like
stealing from the employer merits less severe disciplinary measures and in fact may even
require an employer to accommodate the employee’s disability by, for example, reassign-
ing the employee to a position in which theft will not be possible. Courts and arbitrators
have not been very receptive to these arguments. Despite attempts to frame gambling
addiction as a brain disorder, they remain suspicious that the condition necessarily entails
a sufficient lack of self-control to relieve a person from responsibility. Furthermore, the
accommodations requested may be perceived as unreasonable.
The case of R. v. Smith (2015) involved a woman who pleaded guilty to stealing from
her employer to finance her gambling. At the sentencing, the defense tendered evidence
that pathological gambling was now classified as an addiction in the DSM-5 because of
“[b]rain imaging studies and neurochemical tests [that] have provided compelling evi-
dence that gambling activates reward systems in the brain much the same way that drugs
and alcohols do,” and that it generates “physiological cravings and the experience of being
‘high’ or in an altered state of consciousness similar to the experience of substance depen-
dence” (Smith 2015, para. 48).
The defense expert also indicated that, as with substance addiction, gambling addicts
also experienced craving and loss of control, and that although “[t]he neurobiology asso-
ciated with behavioural and substance addictions overlap but are not identical … there is
also convincing research indicating common genetic factors including heritable pheno-
types that underlie substance abuse and gambling disorders” (Smith 2015, para. 49).
The judge considered precedents in which gambling addictions were cited as mitigat-
ing factors at sentence, one of which was R. v. Horvath (1997), in which a distinction was
drawn between pathological and compulsive gambling (R. v. Horvath 1997, para. 81).
The court in Horvath had accepted the medical model of pathological gambling and con-
cluded that it reduced moral blame:
The offences were the products of a distorted mind—a mind seriously diseased by a disorder now
recognized by the medical community as a mental disorder. The acts committed at the command
of that mind were not acts of free choice in the same sense as are the acts of free choice of a normal
mind. A pathological gambler does not have the same power of control over his or her acts as one
who does not suffer from that complex disease. Accordingly, where those acts constitute criminal
offences, the moral culpability—moral blameworthiness—and responsibility are not of the same
order as they would be in those cases where the mind is not so affected.
581
However, the judge in Smith was not ultimately persuaded that Smith had a condition that
undermined her self-control, and so rejected the argument that her gambling problem
should mitigate personal responsibility:
People with serious mental disorders cannot, through sheer willpower and resolve, rid themselves
of their afflictions. In notable contrast, once Ms. Smith’s crime was discovered and she resolved to
stop gambling, she was able to do so without apparent difficulty and with lasting results. If only it
were so easy for the mentally disordered. (R. v. Smith 2015, para. 92)
In the employment context, employees dismissed for theft sometimes bring grievances
on the basis that the disciplinary measure was unfair because the behavior was caused by
a disability—pathological gambling—that had subsequently been addressed. The role of
demonstrable biological etiology in buttressing such a claim is revealed in an older case,
in which the arbitrator considered the claim for reinstatement and drew a distinction
between so-called easy cases in which there was a clear physical reason for the wrongful
conduct, and the more common cases where there are no physical reasons for it (Canada
Safeway Ltd. 1999):
In the former category would fall cases where there is an identifiable physical reason for aberrant
conduct. An easy example is where an employee had a brain tumor [that] caused improper conduct
such as violence or theft. If it can be shown that the brain tumor was a direct contributor to the
aberrant conduct and that it has now been cured, most employers and arbitrators would reinstate
the employee. The most common cases that seem to arise do not deal with clearly identifiable physi-
cal problems such as a brain tumor, rather they most often deal with alcohol addiction, drug addic-
tion and, more recently, gambling addiction. Even in these cases there is a tendency to characterize
the "condition" as an illness. Often much of the evidence will be led for that purpose. (para. 62)
The arbitrator then went on to say it wasn’t absolutely necessary to establish a “recogniz-
able condition” or “true illness,” but there must be a condition that leads to the improper
behavior and it must be one that essentially removes self-control from the employee:
Again using the brain tumor example, it may be concluded that the employee was acting as an
automaton and was not responsible whatever for his or her conduct. On the other hand, even
if a gambling or alcohol addiction is established, and it is established that but for the condition
the aberrant conduct, such as theft, would not have occurred, it still may be concluded that the
grievor possesses sufficient responsibility for his or her actions so that a substitution of penalty
is not appropriate. This is precisely what occurred in the SaskTel case where it was accepted that
the grievor had a pathological or compulsive gambling addiction and that it contributed to his
acts of theft but it was concluded that he was still responsible because he had been fully aware of
his problem and he was fully aware of the avenues open to him to have his problem dealt with. In
other words, the mere existence of an addiction does not in itself explain or justify serious aberrant
conduct. There are many people with alcohol, narcotic and gambling addictions but a very small
number of those people steal money. (para. 66)
Similar reasoning has been subsequently followed in a range of other labor arbitrations
involving pathological gambling. For example, in Manitoba v. Manitoba Government and
General Employees’ Union (2005), the arbitration panel doubted that gambling addiction
made the decision to steal involuntary, despite evidence that gambling addictions “hijack
the brain” (paras. 48, 59, 85).
582
In the US context, Tovino (2015) writes about another way in which the neurobiologi-
cal conceptions of pathological gambling may affect benefits entitlements and protection
from discrimination. While her example does not have to do directly with how biological
causal explanations affect judgments of control and responsibility, it does suggest another
way in which the legal treatment of disabilities may be affected by neurobiological con-
ceptions of disability. Tovino (2015) observes that the neurobiologically driven reclas-
sification of pathological gambling as a form of addictive behavior in the DSM-5 may
support the argument that it should no longer fall within the category of “impulse control
disorders” for the purposes of health insurance in Nevada, which excludes that category
from coverage but includes coverage for substance-related conditions (drug and alcohol
use disorders). She also predicts that neurobiological advances may lead to challenges
to certain exclusions from the scope of anti-discrimination laws. For example, Title I of
the ADA excludes people engaging in the use of illegal drugs from protection against
discrimination in employment (Tovino 2015, p.723). However, those who have engaged
in drug rehabilitation programs and are not currently using illegal drugs are protected.
Title I of the ADA also specifically excludes from employment discrimination protection
“compulsive gambling,” and several other impulse control disorders, but does not include
a similar proviso protecting those who have been successfully treated. Tovino (2015) sug-
gests that the evolving understanding of compulsive gambling may permit a stakeholder
to argue that gambling disorder should be treated more like alcohol or drug use disorders
under antidiscrimination laws.
The example of gambling addictions sheds some light on the effect of neurobiological
explanations of behavior on the concept of disability. Although brain-based evidence may
help to support the idea that someone may become addicted to the act of gambling, this
may not be sufficient where the disfavored behavior is the upstream activity of stealing in
order to finance the compulsive behavior. Unlike the following examples of nicotine and
Internet sex addiction where the disfavored behavior that is being punished is the com-
pulsive behavior itself, in pathological gambling it is not the gambling but the stealing that
is being punished. In these cases, decision-makers appear to doubt that the compulsion to
gamble necessarily made the theft sufficiently involuntary to reduce blame. Nevertheless,
the invocation of neurobiological evidence supports the idea that it is being used in an
attempt to suggest lack of self-control and responsibility, and may also have other effects
on disability rights protections through the shifting classification of various conditions.
Nicotine addiction
Although nicotine addiction is a medicalized condition, the case law on whether it is a
disability is mixed. The focus of the dispute is the degree of loss of voluntary self-control.
In McNeill v. Ontario Ministry of the Solicitor General and Correctional Services (1998),
an inmate challenged a smoking ban in a detention center on the basis that it discrimi-
nated against him on the basis of disability. He argued that addiction to drugs and alco-
hol were recognized as disabilities for the purposes of human rights protections and that
addiction to tobacco should similarly be recognized as a disability. The Ontario Court
583
of Justice ruled that smokers do not have a “mental or physical disability.” The Court
held that “[a]ddiction to nicotine is a temporary condition that many people voluntarily
overcome, albeit with varying levels of difficulty related to the strength of their will to dis-
continue smoking,” and that “smoking and the addiction that often accompanies it does
not interfere with a person’s effective physical, social and psychological functioning, the
results that often characterize addiction to alcohol” (para. 29). The court also observed
sarcastically that the claimant “was in a position to do something about the discrimina-
tion of which he complained. He could forego his frequent attendances at the Wellington
Detention Centre” (para. 31).
Other courts have rejected the idea that nicotine addiction is a disability for the
purposes of the antidiscrimination provisions of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms
(R. v. Ample Annie’s Itty Bitty Roadhouse 2001; Yellowknife (City) v. Denny 2004). The
judge in Yellowknife wrote that an addiction to smoking:
may be a mental or physical disability by somebody else’s definition, but not pursuant to section 15
[of the Charter]… Smokers can successfully overcome their addiction. Help is close at hand. There
is nothing discriminatory in the [non-smoking] by-law. If it has a purpose or effect that addresses
the issue of addiction, it is a positive, rehabilitative by-law that should be welcomed by the public at
large, including those so addicted. (paras. 56–60)
[H]is almost total dismissal of the pharmacological effects of nicotine on the brain is not sup-
ported by the experts in the field. He implicitly recognized this when, after much painful cross-
examination, he admitted that nicotine does, in fact, have a pharmacological effect on the brain. He
stated that nicotine binds to receptors in the brain, thus causing “brain changes.” … Such changes
do not mean that the brain is damaged, in his view, because they are not permanent. He cited a
study … showing that the brains of people who quit smoking “return to normal” after twelve weeks.
That this indicates that the smoker’s brain was, therefore, not “normal” while he was smoking seems
not to have been considered by him. (Letourneau 2015, paras. 161–162)
The plaintiffs’ expert, on the other hand, described nicotine dependence as a brain dis-
ease, and characterized the user as a “slave” who had lost “freedom of action” (Letourneau
2015, paras. 172–173). The companies’ experts energetically disputed this, arguing that
nicotine use does not remove freedom of action, as is clearly demonstrated by the many
people who have quit smoking (Letourneau 2015, para. 173).
The Court ultimately found that “nicotine affects the brain in a way that makes contin-
ued exposure to it strongly preferable to ceasing that exposure. In other words, although
it can vary from individual to individual, nicotine creates dependence. That is the point”
(Letourneau 2015, para. 179). The judge also noted that tobacco dependence was listed as
a psychiatric disorder in the DSM-5, and the marketing of a dependence-inducing prod-
uct could be the basis of a product liability claim (Letourneau 2015, paras. 183–184). As a
result, those who started smoking at a time when the addictive and harmful properties of
tobacco were known were held partly responsible, but the others who were already depen-
dent when the harms became known were not at fault (Letourneau 2015, paras. 829–830).
58
Although the sample size does not permit firm conclusions about the role of neurobiol-
ogy on the concept of disability, these cases suggest a number of points. First, medicaliza-
tion is not in itself sufficient to guarantee that a condition will be recognized as a disability
for legal purposes. In some of these cases, the effort to deflect blame and to claim accom-
modation of a disability was unsuccessful because the claimant was perceived to retain
some control over the condition. The invocation of neurobiological explanations of nico-
tine addiction seems to help to produce a more sympathetic response to the difficulties of
smokers, as the cases of Cominco and Letourneau reveal. Finally, the legal context appears
to matter. There seems to be a greater willingness to support the claimant where the other
side is profiting in some way from the claimant’s alleged addiction (as in the product
liability case in Letourneau), than there is in cases where a party is being asked to accom-
modate the claimant’s alleged addiction.
Another case involving an employee fired for pornography use at work contrary to
acceptable use policies was Interior Health Authority (South Similkameen Health Centre)
v. Hospital Employee’s Union (RP Grievance) (2013). The employee argued that he had the
condition of “sexually compulsive behaviour regarding viewing pornography,” and that
the employer was obligated to make reasonable accommodation of his disability. There
was supporting evidence provided in this case by a clinical social worker, accepted as
an expert for the purpose of making diagnoses under the DSM-IV. The expert acknowl-
edged that sexual compulsivity was not a diagnosis under the DSM-IV and so no claim
about a diagnosis was advanced, but he did proceed to provide evidence that RP ranked
in the moderate to severe range of compulsive pornography use on a Sexual Addiction
Screening Test and an Internet Sex Screening Test. The arbitrator rejected the claim say-
ing that, in the absence of expert medical or psychiatric evidence supporting the existence
of such a condition, she was “unable to conclude that there exists a disability of ‘sexually
compulsive behavior regarding viewing pornography’ ” (paras. 57–59). She went on fur-
ther to note that the employee’s behavior did not resemble an addiction since he did not
appear to have “an irresistible drive to view pornography, or any loss of control” (para.
60). Instead, he timed his pornography consumption to times when work was slow.
In Seneca College v. Ontario Public Service Employees Union (Discharge Grievance)
(2002), a college professor pleaded guilty to child pornography offences after he was caught
using the student computer lab to download child pornography. When his employer fired
him for this behavior, he argued that his pathological Internet use was the result of a men-
tal disorder, and that there was an obligation under the Ontario Human Rights Code to
accommodate this disability. He further argued that he had paid a penalty in the criminal
courts, and that termination of his employment was too harsh a response by the employer
in the circumstances. The arbitration panel rejected his suggestion that he had “a type of
impulse control disorder that took the form of pathological attraction to internet pornog-
raphy,” because the evidence showed he did have control:
The grievor through his own testimony indicated that his activity in searching out and viewing
Internet pornography was both selective and controlled, suggesting that he could exercise self
restraint if he chose to do so. (para. 16)
There was an intriguing dissent by the panel member nominated by the union. The mem-
ber said that even though his condition did not fit the “accepted medical model of psy-
chiatric disorders” in the DSM-IV, the medical community does recognize compulsive
behavior. The member noted that this was a person who turned to the Internet to escape
from reality due to difficult life circumstances, and asked “[h]ow is that different from
those who turn to alcohol, drugs, gambling and other forms of escapism? The difference,
this member submits, is our own personal view on the morality of the issue and of course,
legality of the issue” (para. 26). Because other employees are given time off to “fight their
own personal demons” the grievor also should have been given this opportunity and been
awarded severance even if reinstatement was not possible due to the breach of the funda-
mental responsibilities of his teaching position (paras. 26–30).
587
Conclusion 587
The Internet sex addiction cases demonstrate the importance of an accepted medical
diagnosis. Even where expert medical evidence is provided, its weight may be discounted
by the lack of a generally accepted condition, as occurred in Interior Health Authority
(2003) case. The cases also hint at the possibility of a backlash against those who are per-
ceived to be in control of a condition yet are attempting to deny control and responsibility
by invoking a disability. Where this claim is not believed, blame may be aggravated by the
perception of failure to properly take responsibility and the lack of remorse.
Conclusion
A common theme in discussions of law and neuroscience is that behavioral, genetic,
and neuroscientific explanations of behavior will affect judgments of causal control and
responsibility. The suggestion is that people tend to interpret these explanations deter-
ministically to a greater extent than other types of causal explanations of behavior, such
as environmental or psychological factors. Of course, all behavior involves the brain, and
pointing out this fact does not settle the question of whether society should hold someone
legally responsible for it. Legal practice and social psychology seem to show that people
are sensitive to a person’s perceived control over disfavored behaviors or symptoms, and
assign blame and punishment to those who are perceived to have the capacity to control
them and are therefore responsible for them.
This effect has been most often explored in the criminal context, where the impact
of behavioral genetics and neuroscience on retribution are being actively researched.
However, this does not exhaust the possible legal effects of the manner in which people
link brain explanations to a lack of control and to diminished responsibility. The willing-
ness to recognize a behavioral condition as a disability, entitling a person to social assis-
tance and protection from discrimination, also is sensitive to perceived control.
A review of cases in which emerging forms of behavioral addictions are claimed as dis-
abilities reveals a complex picture. Brain-based explanations are sometimes used in an
attempt to emulate the successful reframing of drug and alcohol addiction as a disease of
the brain. However, this in itself does not seem to be enough to succeed in legal claims.
Decision-makers often question whether self-control is sufficiently diminished to excuse
the behavior in question. Furthermore, claimants may be punished for failing to take
responsibility and to show remorse when they ascribe behavior to a condition over which
they are perceived to retain at least some control.
As research continues to elucidate the underlying biological mechanisms involved in
behavioral control, it seems likely that human rights lawyers and complainants will adopt
this evidence in relation to stigmatized conditions not yet firmly accepted as disabilities.
An additional way that neuroscience research may alter the legal response to disabilities
is by developing novel treatments based on greater understanding of the biology of behav-
ior. Since claimants are expected to participate in attempts to make reasonable accommo-
dation of their disabilities under human rights law, claimants may find themselves under
pressure to adopt these new treatments.
58
There are potential negative consequences, familiar from the literature on human rights
theory and the sociological literature on medicalization, to the framing of behavioral
problems as matters of biology or physiology. They deflect attention from other social or
environmental conditions that are also causal contributors, and so may weaken attempts
to make broader responses to behavioral conditions. Furthermore, while it is understand-
able why people may seek to attribute causal control for socially disfavored behavior to
biological mechanisms beyond their control, might this not also undermine their actual
self-control in a self-fulfilling way? Future research looking specifically at the law and
legal institutions could fruitfully explore these and other themes to help societies incor-
porate neuroscientific explanations of human behavior.
Acknowledgments
The author gratefully acknowledges the research assistance of Tijana Potkonjak and
Hilary Bond, as well as the financial support of the Bertram Loeb Research Chair and the
Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.
References
American Psychiatric Association (2000). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (4th
edn., text rev.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.
American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (5th
edn.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.
Aspinwall, L.G., Brown, T.R., and Tabery, J. (2012). Science, 337, 846–849.
Canada Safeway Ltd. and RWDSU (MacNeill) Re [1999] S.L.A.A. No. 1 (Sask. Labour Arbitration).
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada
Act 1982 (UK), 1982, c 11.
Cominco Ltd. v. United Steelworkers of America, Local 9705, [2000] B.C.C.A.A.A. No. 62 (QL) Para. 179.
Corrigan, P.W. (2000). Mental health stigma as social attribution: implications for research methods
and attitude change. Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice, 7(1), 48–67.
Corrigan, P., Markowitz, F.E., Watson, A., Rowan, D., and Kubiak, M.A. (2003). An attribution model
of public discrimination toward persons with mental illness. Journal of Health and Social Behavior,
44(2), 162–179.
Criminal Code. R.S.C. 1985 c. C-46.
Esses, V.M. and Beaufoy, S.L. (1994). Determinants of attitudes toward people with disabilities. Journal
of Social Behavior and Personality, 9(5), 43–64.
Fischer, J.M. and Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fuss, J., Dressing, H., and Briken, P. (2015). Neurogenetic evidence in the courtroom: a randomized
controlled trial with German judges. Journal of Medical Genetics, 42, 730–737.
Gilbert, D. and Majury, D. (2006). Infertility and the parameters of discrimination discourse. In: Pothier,
D. and Devlin, R. (Eds.) Critical Disability Theory: Essays in Philosophy, Politics, Policy, and Law,
pp.285–304. Vancouver, BC: UBC Press.
Human Rights Code, R.S.O. 1990, c. H.19.
Interior Health Authority (South Similkameen Health Centre) v. Hospital Employee’s Union (RP
Grievance) [2013] B.C.C.A.A.A. No. 44.
589
References 589
Invista (Canada) Co., Kingston Site v. Kingston Independent Nylon Workers Union (Asselstine
Grievance) [2013] O.L.A.A. NO. 38.
Kellogg Canada Inc. v. Bakery, Confectionary, Tobacco Workers & Grain Millers, Local 154-G (Fickling
Grievance), [2006] O.L.A.A. No. 375 at 60.
Kvaale, E.P., Haslam, N., and Gottdiener, W.H. (2013). The ‘side effects’ of medicalization: a meta-analytic
review of how biogenetic explanations affect stigma. Clinical Psychology Review, 33, 782–794.
Law Commission of Ontario (2009). The Law as it Affects Persons with Disabilities: Preliminary
Consultation Paper, Approaches to Defining Disability. Available from: http://www.lco-cdo.org/en/
disabilities-threshold-paper [accessed February 11, 2017].
Lee, A.A., Laurent, S.M., Wykes, T.L., Kitchen Andre, K.A., Bourassa, K.A., and McKibbin, C.L.
(2014). Genetic attributions and mental illness diagnosis: effects on perceptions of danger, social
distance, and real helping decisions. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology, 49, 781–789.
Letourneau v. JTI-MacDonald Corp. 2015 QCCS 2382.
Love, T., Laier, C., Brand, M., Hatch, L., and Hajela, R. (2015). Neuroscience of internet pornography
addiction: a review and update. Behavioral Sciences, 5(3), 388–433.
Manitoba Government and General Employees’ Union v. Manitoba (M.W. Grievance) [2013] M.G.A.D.
No. 10 at para. 81.
Manitoba v. Manitoba Government and General Employees’ Union 2005 MGAD No. 14.
McNeill v. Ontario Ministry of the Solicitor General and Correctional Services [1998] O.J. No. 2288
(Ont. Ct. J.—Gen Div.).
Monterosso, J., Royzman, E.B., and Schwartz, B. (2004). Explaining away responsibility: effects of
scientific explanation on perceived culpability. Ethics & Behavior, 15(2), 139–158.
Milazzo v. Autocar Connaisseur Inc. 2003 CHRT 37.
Mueller, P.K., Houser, J.A., and Riddle, M.K. (2010). Regarding disability: perceptions of protection
under the Americans with Disabilities Act. Research in Social Science and Disability, 5, 159–180.
Ontario (Director, Disability Support Program) v. Tranchemontagne (2009) O.R. (3d) 327, aff ’d 2010
ONCA 593.
Ontario Human Rights Commission (2014). Policy on Preventing Discrimination Based on Mental
Health Disabilities and Addictions. Available from: http://www.ohrc.on.ca/en/policy-preventing-
discrimination-based-mental-health-disabilities-and-addictions [accessed February 11, 2017].
Penney, S. (2012). Impulse control and criminal responsibility: lessons from neuroscience. International
Journal of Clinical and Health Psychology, 35, 99–103.
R. v. Ample Annie’s Itty Bitty Roadhouse (2001) O.J. No. 5968 (Ont. C.J.).
R. v. Belcourt 2010 ABCA 319.
R. v. H.T. 2010 MBPC 8.
R. v. Obed 2006 NLTD 155.
R. v. Smith 2015 BCSC 1267.
R. v. Horvath [1997] S.J. No. 385 (Sask. C.A.).
Roach, K. (2012). Criminal Law (5th edn.). Toronto, ON: Irwin Law Inc.
Ruby, C.C. (2004). Sentencing (6th edn.). Markham, ON: Butterworths.
Seneca College v. Ontario Public Service Employees Union (Discharge Grievance [2002] O.L.A.A.
No. 415.
Tovino, S.A. (2015). Will neuroscience redefine mental injury? Disability benefit law, mental health
parity law, and disability discrimination law. Indiana Health Law Review, 12(2), 695–728.
United Nations General Assembly (2007). Convention on the Rights of Persons with
Disabilities: Resolution/Adopted by the General Assembly, 24 January 2007. [UN Document A/RES/
61/106.] New York: United Nations.
590
Van Oorschot, W. (2000). Who should get what, and why? On deservingness criteria and the
conditionality of solidarity among the public. Policy and Politics, 28(1), 33–49.
Vrecko, S. (2010). Birth of a brain disease: science, the state and addiction neuropolitics. History of the
Human Sciences, 23(4), 52–67.
Weiner, B. (1993). On sin versus sickness: a theory of perceived responsibility and social motivation.
American Psychologist, 48(9), 957–965.
Weiner, B., Perry, R.P., and Magnusson, J. (1988). An attributional analysis of reactions to stigmas.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 55(5), 738–748.
Weiner, B., Osborne, D., and Rudolph, U. (2011). An attributional analysis of reactions to poverty: the
political ideology of the giver and the perceived morality of the receiver. Personality and Social
Psychology Review, 15(2), 199–213.
Yellowknife (City) v. Denny 2004 NWTTC 2.
591
Chapter 30
Introduction
Neuroethics, alongside the other neuro-disciplines, has largely been developed within
high-income Western countries. This is not surprising, given that neuroscience is an
expensive research endeavor that has mostly been undertaken in academic institutions
based in these locations, and given that the conceptual framework of neuroethics is
related to work in areas such as bioethics and neurophilosophy, which have also most
often been pursued in this high-income Western context. Conversely, an electronic search
of the research literature at the intersection of “neuroethics” and “low-income or middle-
income countries” reveals vanishingly few publications, although there is certainly clear
recognition of the importance of issues surrounding neuroethics and globalization
(Lombera & Illes 2009; Giordano 2013).
Global mental health is another recently defined field of intellectual and practical
endeavor, which has emphasized that although the majority of research on mental dis-
orders takes place in high-income Western countries, the vast bulk of the world’s people
with mental disorders live in low-and middle-income countries (LMICs) (the so-called
10:90 research gap) (Becker & Kleinman 2012; Patel 2012). Researchers in global mental
health have not only emphasized the research gap, but they have also brought attention
to the treatment gap; in LMICs, there are significant barriers to accessing and scaling up
effective treatments (Wang et al. 2007; Andrade et al. 2013). Conversely, an electronic
search of “global mental health” and “neuroscience” yields relatively few publications at
this intersection, although there is a growing emphasis on the need for both implementa-
tion and discovery science in LMIC contexts (Collins et al. 2011; Stein et al. 2015).
This chapter makes the argument that despite their different histories and trajectories,
neuroethics and global mental health have a good deal in common, and there is much
to be gained from an ongoing dialogue and interaction between these fields. There are
a number of important areas of overlap between neuroethics and global mental health,
including (1) a naturalist and empirical approach, (2) a concern with both disease and
with well-being, (3) a concern with human rights and with patient empowerment—
intersections which have previously been reviewed (Stein & Giordano 2015). Each
of these areas of overlap is considered in more detail throughout this chapter, and an
592
ensure that these are made fully explicit, that these are rigorously discussed and debated,
and that adaptation of different constructs and approaches across different contexts is
done in a sensitive and appropriate way.
Both neuroscience and global mental health can usefully contribute to the debate about
the nature and boundaries of mental disorder and mental well-being. Community survey
data have emphasized, for example, that respondents who do not meet threshold criteria
for presence of disorder, but who have subclinical symptoms, nevertheless suffer from a
great deal of impairment (Kessler et al. 2003). While absenteeism is a major cost, the bur-
den due to presenteeism also requires recognition (Beddington et al. 2008). Delineation
of the boundaries between illness and disease partly reflects the availability and costs
for treatment; thus the introduction of generic statins led to a lowering of definitions
of hypercholesterolaemia (Kessler et al. 2003). Similarly, in the area of mental disorders
and mental health, both conceptual and empirical work is needed to address optimally
the delineation of disorders, and to answer fully the questions of when and how best to
intervene in a global context (Stein 2008; Stein et al. 2013). We can expect that novel
opportunities to improve individual and societal flourishing will become an increasingly
prominent topic for debate and practice (Shook & Giordano 2014).
on the importance of equitable relationships between researchers from the global North
and South (Fricchione et al. 2012).
Important concerns can be raised about these foci of neuroethics and of global mental
health. There is an argument which emphasizes that human rights should not be thought
of as a natural kind but rather that such constructs are bound to specific times and places
(Donnelly 2013); there is a view that to understand and evaluate an ethical issue, concepts
of human rights need to be augmented with additional constructs such as “duty” and
“virtue” (Benatar 2006); and there is a position that the right to mental healthcare may not
always be the most appropriate approach to ensuring optimization of mental health ser-
vices (Glover-Thomas & Chima 2015). Some critics have emphasized the risk of including
patient perspectives merely for the sake of political correctness (Spitzer 2004), and there
are certainly limits to the effectiveness of social inclusion as a sole treatment for those suf-
fering from mental disorders. There is a need for careful conceptual and empirical work
on issues such as the stigmatization of mental disorder, in order to ensure that responses
to mental illness fully recognize its reality and its consequences, but at the same time, do
not unfairly discriminate against those who suffer from these conditions.
Indeed, in response to such concerns, there is much room for neuroethics and global
mental health to contribute in a collaborative way. Although they come from quite dif-
ferent perspectives, each emphasizes the growing role of the patient in mental healthcare,
and each strongly values the autonomy of the individual in deciding on what health-
care to access and how. Each is also, however, aware of important limits to autonomy;
sometimes those with serious mental illness are hospitalized against their will, and some-
times consumers use neurotechnologies, including psychotropic agents, in harmful ways.
Rigorous theoretical and empirical work is needed in order to ensure the optimization
and maximization of human rights and consumer empowerment in the area of clinical
neuroscience. As the agenda of global mental health research, including work on discov-
ery and implementation science, gives increasing impetus to studies of mental health and
mental disorders in LMICs, so there will be a need to increase attention to neuroethical
issues arising in these settings, and to the promotion of responsible policies (Shook and
Giordano 2014).
Analogously, global mental health is very much aware that most psychology research
is undertaken on Westernized, educated, industrialized, rich, and democratic (WEIRD)
populations (Henrich et al. 2010). It is also crucially aware of how mental disorders pres-
ent differently in different contexts, of how there are multiple different explanatory mod-
els of mental disorder, and of how these can impact the course of treatment (Kleinman
1991; Stein 1993; Kirmayer 2006). Whereas clinical neuroscience has focused on biologi-
cal diversity, global mental health has emphasized the importance of cultural and social
diversity.
Once again, some concerns can perhaps be raised in this area. Science, including the
field of genetics, does not always have a good track record of celebrating diversity, and it is
crucial to bear in mind those times when neuroscience and psychiatry have had an igno-
minious and deplorable past (Weiss & Lambert 2011; Zeidman 2012). At the same time,
there are perhaps potential risks in not providing neuroscientific and psychiatric treat-
ments when these can relieve suffering. In the current era, recognition of past excesses has
led to a strong focus on the avoidance of over-medicalization. At the same time, in certain
contexts, medicalization is entirely appropriate (Stein & Gureje 2004).
Neuroethics and global mental health can again perhaps develop a mutually enrich-
ing research agenda in this area. It is important, for example, to understand fully our
genetic diversity by employing global populations in the study of normal and abnormal
behavior. There is a strong argument that the inclusion of African populations is needed
to delineate fully the genetic risk factors for mental disorders, and that the exclusion of
African populations from such studies may potentially lead to exclusion from the positive
benefits of certain kinds of research (e.g., not fully understanding pharmacogenetics of a
particular psychotropic drug) (Dalvie et al. 2015). Indeed, the study of global populations
may yield crucially important lessons for neuroscience and for psychiatry (Patel 2010;
Patel & Saxena 2014).
Conclusion
Neuroethics and global mental health have strikingly different origins and trajectories.
The former has focused mainly on new and specialized technologies being introduced
into high-income countries, while the latter has focused on primary care interventions
and their scale-up in LMICs. At the same time, these fields also share a number of impor-
tant concerns and approaches. There has been relatively little conversation between neu-
roethics and global mental health to date; this chapter argues that collaboration between
these fields may be useful in advancing a number of key areas of work and of debate. Our
hope is that lessons from global neuroscience may impact positively on the development
and articulation of an internationally sensitive, relevant, and valuable neuroethics.
Such a conversation and collaboration between neuroethics and global mental health
may be important in ensuring ongoing progress in advancing a naturalist and empiri-
cal approach to mental disorders, in addressing both disease and wellness in the mental
health context, in maintaining an ongoing focus on the importance of human rights and
597
References 597
References
Altman, D.G. and Bland, J.M. (1995). Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence. BMJ, 311, 485.
Andrade, L.H., Alonso, J., Mneimneh, Z., et al. (2013). Barriers to mental health treatment: results
from the WHO World Mental Health surveys. Psychological Medicine, 1–15.
Becker, A.E. and Kleinman, A. (2012). An agenda for closing resource gaps in global mental
health: innovation, capacity building, and partnerships. Harvard Review of Psychiatry, 20, 3–5.
Becker, A.E. and Kleinman, A. (2013). Mental health and the global agenda. New England Journal of
Medicine, 369, 1380–1381.
Beddington, J., Cooper, C.L., Field, J., et al. (2008). The mental wealth of nations. Nature, 455,
1057–1060.
Benatar, D. (2006). Bioethics and health and human rights: a critical view. Journal of Medical Ethics,
32, 17–20.
Buniak, L., Darragh, M., and Giordano, J. (2014). A four-part working bibliography of
neuroethics: part 1: overview and reviews –defining and describing the field and its practices.
Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 9, 9.
Collins, P.Y., Patel, V., Joestl, S.S., et al. (2011). Grand challenges in global mental health. Nature,
475, 27–30.
Dalvie, S., Koen, N., Duncan, L., et al. (2015). Large scale genetic research on neuropsychiatric
disorders in African populations is needed. EBioMedicine, 2, 1259–1261.
Darragh, M., Buniak, L., and Giordano, J. (2015). A four part working bibliography of
neuroethics: part 2: neuroscientific studies of morality and ethics. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities
in Medicine, 10, 1.
Davidson, L. and Strauss, J.S. (1995). Beyond the biopsychosocial model: integrating disorder, health,
and recovery. Psychiatry, 58, 44–55.
DiEuliis, D. and Giordano, J. (2016). Neurotechnological convergence and big data: a “force multiplier”
toward advancing neuroscience. In: Collmann, J. and Matei, S. (Eds.) Ethical Reasoning in Big Data:
An Exploratory Analysis, pp.71–80. New York: Springer.
Donnelly, J. (2013). Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (3rd edn). Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Farah, M.J., Illes, J., Cook-Deegan, R., et al. (2004). Neurocognitive enhancement: what can we do and
what should we do? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 5, 421–425.
Fricchione, G.L., Borba, C.P., Alem, A., Shibre, T., Carney, J.R., and Henderson, D.C. (2012). Capacity
building in global mental health: professional training. Harvard Review of Psychiatry, 20, 47–57.
Fulford, K.W. (2011). The value of evidence and evidence of values: bringing together values-based and
evidence-based practice in policy and service development in mental health. Journal of Evaluation in
Clinical Practice, 17, 976–987.
Giordano, J. (2013). Ethical considerations in the globalization of medicine –an interview with James
Giordano. BMC Medicine, 11, 69.
598
References 599
Patel, V. and Thornicroft, G. (2009). Packages of care for mental, neurological, and substance use
disorders in low-and middle-income countries: PLoS Medicine Series. PLoS Medicine, 6, e1000160.
Patel, V., Saraceno, B., and Kleinman, A. (2006). Beyond evidence: the moral case for international
mental health. American Journal of Psychiatry, 163, 1312–1315.
Prince, M., Patel, V., Saxena, S., et al. (2007). No health without mental health. Lancet, 370, 859–877.
Racine, E. (2008). Which naturalism for bioethics? A defense of moderate (pragmatic) naturalism.
Bioethics, 22, 92–100.
Remien, R.H., Mellins, C.A., Robbins, R.N., et al. (2013). Masivukeni: development of a multimedia
based antiretroviral therapy adherence intervention for counselors and patients in South Africa.
AIDS and Behavior, 17, 1979–1991.
Sahakian, B.J. and Morein-Zamir, S. (2011). Neuroethical issues in cognitive enhancement. Journal of
Psychopharmacology, 25, 197–204.
Sahakian, B.J., Bruhl, A.B., Cook, J., et al. (2015). The impact of neuroscience on society: cognitive
enhancement in neuropsychiatric disorders and in healthy people. Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 370, 20140214.
Sandel, M.J. (2004). The case against perfection: what’s wrong with designer children, bionic athletes,
and genetic engineering. Atlantic Monthly, 292, 50–54, 56–60, 62.
Savulescu, J. (2006). Justice, fairness, and enhancement. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences,
1093, 321–338.
Schaefer, G.O., Kahane, G., and Savulescu, J. (2014). Autonomy and enhancement. Neuroethics, 7,
123–136.
Shook, J.R. and Giordano, J. (2014). A principled and cosmopolitan neuroethics: considerations for
international relevance. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 9, 1.
Shook, J.R. and Giordano, J. (2016). Neuroethics beyond normal: performance enablement and self-
transformative technologies. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 25, 121–140.
Silove, D. (1999). The psychosocial effects of torture, mass human rights violations, and refugee
trauma: toward an integrated conceptual framework. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 187,
200–207.
Spitzer, R.L. (2004). Good idea or politically correct nonsense? Psychiatric Services, 55, 113.
Stein, D.J. (1993). Cross-cultural psychiatry and the DSM-IV. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 34, 322–329.
Stein, D.J. (1998). Philosophy of psychopharmacology. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 41,
200–211.
Stein, D.J. (2008). Philosophy of Psychopharmacology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stein, D.J. (2012a). Positive mental health: a note of caution. World Psychiatry, 11, 107–109.
Stein, D.J. (2012b). Psychopharmacological enhancement: a conceptual framework. Philosophy, Ethics,
and Humanities in Medicine, 7, 5.
Stein, D.J. and Giordano, J. (2015). Global mental health and neuroethics. BMC Medicine, 13, 274.
Stein, D.J. and Gureje, O. (2004). Depression and anxiety in the developing world: is it time to
medicalise the suffering? Lancet, 364, 233–234.
Stein, D.J., Xin, Y., Osser, D., Li, X., and Jobson, K. (2002). Clinical psychopharmacology
guidelines: different strokes for different folks. World Journal of Biological Psychiatry, 3, 64–67.
Stein, D.J., Lund, C., and Nesse, R.M. (2013). Classification systems in psychiatry: diagnosis and global
mental health in the era of DSM-5 and ICD-11. Current Opinion in Psychiatry, 26, 493–497.
Stein, D.J., He, Y., Phillips, A., Sahakian, B.J., Williams, J., and Patel., V. (2015). Global mental health
and neuroscience: potential synergies. Lancet Psychiatry, 2, 178–185.
Summerfield, D. (2013). “Global mental health” is an oxymoron and medical imperialism. BMJ,
346, f3509.
60
Wang, P.S., Angermeyer, M., Borges, G., et al. (2007). Delay and failure in treatment seeking after first
onset of mental disorders in the World Health Organization’s World Mental Health Survey Initiative.
World Psychiatry, 6, 177–185.
Weiss, K.M. and Lambert, B.W. (2011). When the time seems ripe: eugenics, the annals, and the subtle
persistence of typological thinking. Annals of Human Genetics, 75, 334–343.
Yamin, A.E. and Rosenthal, E. (2005). Out of the shadows: using human rights approaches to secure
dignity and well-being for people with mental disabilities. PLoS Medicine, 2, e71.
Zeidman, L.A. (2012). Re: neuroscience in Nazi Europe part I: eugenics, human experimentation,
and mass murder. Can J Neurol Sci. 2011; 38:696–703. Canadian Journal of Neurological Sciences,
39, 400.
601
Part IV
Epilogue
602
603
Chapter 31
gold standard Coma Recovery Scale-Revised (Giacino et al. 2004), the colorful visuals
of neuroimaging captured media attention and generated academic discourse. Although
neuroimaging was inferior as a diagnostic tool, it was far more spectacular because only
a nonbehavioral metric could reveal a dissociation between overt and covert signs of
consciousness. This discordance, born of technological advance, prompted neuroethi-
cal reflection about what should be done for those who might have a life of the mind
(Naccache 2006).
Halfway technologies
As neuroscience began to unravel what the great Canadian neurosurgeon Wilder Penfield
(1976; Fins 2008b) called the “mystery of the mind”, the revelations were accompanied
by both angst and hope. People thought forever gone might literally be trapped in their
heads, deprived of community and communication (Fins 2015), isolated and alone. And
it also suggested the seemingly impossible. Might those stranded somehow be rescued?
Once again neuroethics becomes concerned with its recurring theme of technology. If
technology reveals a problem, might it not also resolve it? That is, could neurotechnology
help address the isolation of those recently identified as suffering from cognitive motor
dissociation and reintegrate them into community through the restoration of functional
communication? And of course, this effort has begun with the use of neuroprosthetics like
deep brain stimulation (DBS) (Schiff et al. 2007), drugs (Giacino et al. 2012), and neuro-
imaging paradigms to communicate with the severely injured brain (Giacino et al. 2014).
It would seem to be a neat resolution to our problem with technology. One technology
creates an ethical challenge only for another to solve it. But if it were that simple, it would
be impoverishing. We would risk falling prey to Leon Kass’s (2003) critique of modern
bioethics with its penchant for a technological quick fix of complex problems, reducing
human experience to engineering solutions that truncate the lived experiences of affected
communities. He warns that:
To a society armed with biotechnology, the activities of human life may come to be seen in purely
technical terms, and more amenable to improvement than they really are. Or we may imagine
ourselves wiser than we really are. Or we may get more easily what we asked for only to realize it is
vastly less than what we really wanted. (Kass 2003)
A self-critique 605
brain science solely through the prism of technology is both clinically incomplete and
normatively thin.
A self-critique
While neuroscience is nurtured by the scientist’s curiosity, neuroethics should help
ensure that the quest discovery is more than a science project. The stakes are higher
than that and the work has to be understood in a broader humanistic context in which
the purpose and telos of technological advance is well articulated. Short of that, neuro-
ethics will be a hollow, self-justifying framework, one prone to misdirection, distrac-
tion, and even abuse.
This is not a trivial statement. To be more than just the handmaiden of technological
advance, neuroethics needs to examine the uses of instrumentality. But asking such ques-
tions can be a challenge. It is all too easy to be seduced by an emergent ability to manipu-
late the chemistry of a synapse or alter current flow through a circuit. The explanatory
power of these maneuvers can be overwhelming, especially when they achieve an elusive
(and often dramatic) therapeutic need. Such success can be blinding, especially when
ancient nihilism about brain-based disorders is replaced by a fledgling optimism. When
this happens, the technological can easily become triumphant, obscuring important ethi-
cal considerations too easily pushed into the shadows caused by a glaring success, making
it all the more difficult to question success.
Indeed, a thoughtful commentator can be thought a Philistine when even broach-
ing concerns about the purpose and limits of emerging technologies in the wake of an
important discovery. But question we must, lest we fall prey to what the bioethicist Daniel
Callahan (1996) has termed “scientism” by which he suggests a “non-falsifiable faith in the
capacity of science not simply to provide reliable knowledge but also to solve all or most
human problems, social, political, and economic.”
Callahan critiques science as a member of what he describes the “loyal opposition”
(1996) committed to, but still questioning its goals. His skepticism about the sweep of sci-
ence is wise and prudent, especially in an age of discovery that we live today. But I would
add a friendly amendment to his critique. Such skepticism is essential to, and not counter
to, good science itself.
This was known to Isadore I. Rabi, who was awarded the Nobel Prize for physics for
his work on nuclear magnetic resonance, essential to modern neuroimaging. When
asked why he became a scientist, he reportedly responded that he became a scien-
tist because of his mother’s influence upon him, even though that was not her intent.
Instead of asking him, as all the other Jewish mothers in Brooklyn did, whether he had
learned anything in school, Mrs. Rabi would query him about methods. She’d ask him
if he had asked a “good question.” Rabi attributes this focus to his becoming a scientist
(Sheff 1988).
60
Rabi, better than most, understood that it was not certainty about our answers but our
ability to question that leads us forward. So while discovery is cause for celebration, these
moments also call for humility and careful deliberation. When we do this we are not dis-
loyal to the scientific enterprise but rather squarely in its best traditions.
Sustaining success
Humility even in moments of scientific triumph is prudent because success is no guar-
antee of sustained progress. Despite the spectacular advances we have seen in the past
decades, much of which is recounted in this volume, barriers to progress remain (Fins
et al. 2012). One critical challenge is the proverbial “valley of death,” a phrase used to
describe the premature demise of promising proof-of-principle efforts for lack of funding
that bridges the perilous terrain, typically between government funding and that of ven-
ture capital or pharma or device companies (Finkbeiner 2010). When this happens, good
ideas linger on the sidelines.
This challenge is a profound one for two types of what one might call messy innova-
tion. The first is for emerging drugs and devices aimed at conditions that do not con-
stitute a ready market and thus do not attract capitalization. While the Orphan Drug
Act of 1983 (Orphan Drug Act of 1983), has helped to ease some of the US Food and
Drug Administration’s (FDA’s) regulatory barriers for such drugs (and to a lesser extent
devices under the aegis of the “Orphan Products Board,” now the FDA Office of Orphan
Products Development (FDA 2016) and the more recently constituted Center for
Devices and Radiological Health (FDA 2015)), there is no provision to address the fis-
cal challenges that can doom promising research lingering between basic science fund-
ing streams and underwriting from conventional market sources. Moreover, there are
distinct challenges for device development for orphan conditions versus the promotion
of pharmacological approaches to therapy (Fins et al. 2011a; Mokhtarzadeh et al. 2016).
The challenge of ongoing support is even more complicated when basic neurosci-
ence research is predicated upon having access to devices and to devices of greater and
greater sophistication needed for experimental work. This has been an ongoing chal-
lenge in the realm of neuromodulation where DBS may not always be readily available
to investigators by their manufacturers. Device makers may withhold access to devices,
or their rights of reference required for regulatory approval, because of concerns about
liability when they are used in experimental trials, cost, or in order to maintain a
competitive advantage of one sort or another (Mokhtarzadeh et al. 2016). This can be
highly problematic because devices like DBS are not only therapeutic agents but pro-
bative agents (Fins 2012) that can help map circuits essential to the understanding of
systems neurobiology, and ultimately the creation of a three-dimensional brain map
or connectome (Fins and Shapiro 2013). When these devices are unavailable, tools of
discovery are taken out of the hands of the scientist, disadvantaging all and imperiling
access to the fruits of neuroscience.
607
In sum, while the future is bright for neuroscience, success is not assured. Economic
forces, the commodification of new ideas through patenting (Fins 2010a; Fins and Schiff
2010a; Fins et al. 2011b), and the all too human quest for notoriety can distort the central
ethos of scientific discovery.
While the line can be blurred between restoration and enhancement, and nonclinical
applications are inevitable, I believe that it is normatively appropriate and politically
useful to cast neurotechnology in the service of those who are sick, injured, or suffering
from a neuropsychiatric condition. This will maintain the broad societal consensus and
provide a platform for translational discovery that will be good for basic and clinical
neuroscience. In short, by prioritizing the clinical instrumentality of emerging neuro-
technologies, neuroethics can minimize contention, provide comfort to those afflicted
with neuropsychiatric conditions, and foster scientific advance both at the bench and
the bedside.
But mine is not solely a clinical appeal. It is a broader one grounded under the broad
banner of human rights, specifically the civil and disability rights of individuals with neu-
ropsychiatric conditions (Fins 2010b, 2015). As a physician, and as a humanist, I believe
that such a prioritization is just and fair. Directing emerging neuro-instrumentality to
the remediation of conditions that cause physical or mental distress, constrain liberty,
or compromise a person’s ability to participate in human community helps to equalize
opportunity for those who suffer from life’s most malignant conditions.
And beyond the effects of these therapies on the well-being of individuals, as a class,
people with neuropsychiatric conditions have a long history of marginalization and dis-
crimination. We only need turn to the history of medicine and consider the legacy of the
asylum for those with psychiatric conditions (Rothman 1971) or the more modern neu-
ronal segregation of those with severe brain injury that I have described in my work (Fins
and Hersh 2011; Fins 2013, 2015), to appreciate that these populations have been under-
served by medicine and society at large. Emerging neurotechnologies have the potential
to even that score and restore functional status and equanimity to those burdened by
these conditions, though of course technology can only be part of any solution to such
complex social problems.
Toward a rights agenda
Viewing neuroethics through this prism of rights both distances it from Callahan’s “sci-
entism” (1996) and brings it closer to a sad, but important, truth about neuropsychiatric
conditions and their treatment in society. Historically, those with neuropsychiatric condi-
tions have been marginalized by society. Whether it is paralysis or a movement disorder
that makes mobility a challenge or cognitive or psychiatric conditions that require insti-
tutional care, diseases of the brain and mind can lead to the segregation of affected indi-
viduals and their sequestration from others in society, much as racism of the Jim Crow,
American South segregated individuals because of race.
Legal scholar Timothy Cook (1991) has written of the historic confluence between atti-
tudes toward the disabled and racism. He observed that, “The Jim Crow system estab-
lished after Plessy and the government-supported, systematic segregation of persons with
disabilities during precisely the same time were no mere coincidence of historical events.
The historical record abounds with evidence that disability discrimination emanated
609
from the same attitudes and prejudices fomenting at the turn of the century regarding
race.” (Cook 1991).
Although the Americans with Disability Act (Americans with Disability Act 1990) and
the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (United Nations
General Assembly 2007) both call for the maximal integration of individuals with dis-
ability into civil society, this legacy of segregation and marginalization has been difficult
to overcome, much less acknowledge or recognize as a problem. Bias toward these popu-
lations remains, and individuals with neuropsychiatric conditions continue to suffer, as
former US Surgeon General David Satcher (2000) noted, from profound health dispari-
ties and substandard care. More recently, Jaffe and Jimenez (2015) have written of health
disparities in rehabilitation medicine.
My own research examining the treatment of individuals with disorders of conscious-
ness reveals a class, of mostly young people, segregated in chronic care facilities designed
for the aged with degenerative conditions. There they struggle for services, a credible
diagnosis, and are denied needed rehabilitation (Fins 2013, 2015). Collectively these
omissions can deprive these individuals of the possibility of returning to their homes and
families, often robbing them of fundamental rights, such as the right to remain part of
their communities.
Of course sometimes, the burden of injury or illness makes institutional care neces-
sary. But increasingly, and expectantly, neurotechnology might make this less necessary,
providing opportunities for people with disabilities to be more routinely integrated into
society with the help of neuroprostheses. This is more than wishful thinking. If society
takes stock of what neurotechnology has done and promises to achieve in the next decade,
this aspiration can be viewed as more than a promissory note.
Neurotechnology is beginning to lift the burden of neuropsychiatric maladies and ame-
liorate many conditions. To name but a few notable examples . . . The work of engineers like
P. Hunter Peckam (Moss et al. 2011), Miguel Nicolelis (2012), and others have provided
mobility to those with paralysis. John Donoghue and Leigh Hochberg (Hochberg et al.
2012), and Andrew Schwartz (Collinger et al. 2013) have even begun to broach the locked-
in-state giving individuals mobility with brain–computer interfaces. Our team’s efforts
with thalamic DBS helped an individual in the minimally conscious state speak for the first
time in 6 years and eat food by mouth (Schiff et al. 2007). Bart Nuttin’s (1999) pioneering
use of DBS for obsessive–compulsive disorder and Helen Mayberg’s for depression (2005)
have begun to bring relief to those whose conditions were refractory to pharmacologic
and conventional therapy. And beyond invasive technologies, neuroimaging—as exempli-
fied by Monti et al. (2006)—has the potential to serve as a communication channel in the
setting of what appeared to be the vegetative state but was in fact, a patient with apparent
cognitive motor dissociation in the minimally conscious state (Fins and Schiff 2010b).
What all these technologies have in common is the possibility of reintegration, bring-
ing people with motor, cognitive, or psychiatric disabilities back into the room, back into
civil society by ending the sequestration caused by both their illness and society’s treat-
ment of their disability. When I consider how the active neuroimaging paradigm used by
610
Monti et al. (2006) liberated a conscious individual from cognitive motor dissociation,
I am reminded of that famous image of Nelson Mandela (1994) when he returned to
Robben Island and the place of his decades-long imprisonment and peered out of the bars
that had kept him captive.
In the context of our efforts using thalamic DBS in the minimally conscious state, neu-
roprosthetics have helped to restore voice, and with the restoration of functional com-
munication a person severed from his family was able to rejoin his community. Note the
resonant cognates: communication makes the return to community possible (Schiff et al.
2007; Fins 2015).
Each of these efforts is a story of liberation and reintegration into civil society. While
work with thalamic DBS in the minimally conscious state is not an established therapy
and remains in the realm of proof of principle (Schiff et al. 2009), I believe that it, and the
aforementioned examples of technological innovation, are emblematic of the construc-
tive role that neurotechnology might come to play in securing rights for those left too
long on the margins by neuropsychiatric conditions. It also suggests how neuroprosthetic
technology might become the centerpiece of an emerging rights agenda for patients with
neuropsychiatric disabilities (Schiff et al. 2007).
Beyond providing direct assistance to patients in need, this confluence of neuroethics
and the law will also help expand neuro-law scholarship beyond its current purview with
its focus on criminal law, culpability, and the credibility of evidentiary information (The
MacArthur Foundation n.d.), to broader considerations of how a human rights perspec-
tive can help inform the future of neuroscience and neuroethics (Fins 2016; Wright & Fins
2016), and become an important tool for civil rights advocacy to advance health in the
twenty-first century (McGowan et al. 2016).
Neurotechnology as heuristic
A refrain … returning to my original argument that if neuroethics was a distinct ethics, it
would be as an ethics of technology, we have seen here that not only has neurotechnology
like neuroimaging pointed us to a technical solution, but that it also pointed to arguments
beyond itself, making us appreciate that society was willfully disregarding the needs of
members of its citizenry and ignoring their right to be more fully integrated into civil
society. This is surely a question that transcends technology, and it would be a mistake
to resort to technology for its solution. But we would also be mistaken not to be grateful
to technology as a heuristic that allows society to better apprehend dimensions of our
reality that heretofore had been obscure and unrecognized. While neuroscience does not
provide an easy answer to our questions, it does help us pose new and sometimes deeply
disturbing questions. For that, we should be grateful.
Acknowledgments
The author is grateful to Amy B. Ehrlich and Cathleen A. Acres for their comments, and
Jennifer Hersh for editorial assistance, and acknowledges the Jerold B. Katz Foundation
61
References 611
for its support of the Consortium for the Advanced Study of Brain Injury (CASBI) at Weill
Cornell Medical College and Rockefeller University and an NIH Clinical & Translational
Science Center Award (UL1-RR024966) to Weill Cornell Medical College.
References
Americans with Disability Act of 1990. Public Law 101-336. 104 stat. 328 (1990).
Bardin, J.C., Fins, J.J., Katz, D.I., et al. (2011). Dissociations between behavioural and functional
magnetic resonance imaging-based evaluations of cognitive function. Brain, 134(3), 769–782.
Callahan, D. (1996). Calling scientific ideology to account. Society, 33(4), 14–19.
Collinger, J.L., Wodlinger, B., Downey, J.E., et al. (2013). High-performance neuroprosthetic control by
an individual with tetraplegia. The Lancet, 381(9866), 557–564.
Cook, T.M. (1991). The Americans with Disability Act: the move to integration. Temple Law Review, 64,
393–470.
FDA Center for Devices and Radiological Health (2015). 2014–2015 Strategic Priorities. Available
from: http://www.fda.gov/downloads/AboutFDA/CentersOffices/OfficeofMedicalProductsandTobacco/
CDRH/CDRHVisionandMission/UCM431016.pdf [accessed July 11, 2016].
FDA Office of Orphan Products Development (2016). Developing Products for Rare Diseases
& Conditions. (Updated March 30, 2016.) Available from: http://www.fda.gov/ForIndustry/
DevelopingProductsforRareDiseasesConditions/ucm2005525.htm [accessed July 11, 2016].
Finkbeiner, S. (2010). Bridging the Valley of Death of therapeutics for neurodegeneration. Nature
Medicine, 16(11), 1227–1232.
Fins, J.J. (2003). From psychosurgery to neuromodulation and palliation: history’s lessons for the ethical
conduct and regulation of neuropsychiatric research. Neurosurgery Clinics of North America, 14(2),
303–319.
Fins, J.J. (2005). Rethinking disorders of consciousness: new research and its implications. The Hastings
Center Report, 35(2), 22–24.
Fins, J.J. (2007). Border zones of consciousness: another immigration debate? American Journal of
Bioethics-Neuroethics, 7(1), 51–54.
Fins, J.J. (2008a). Neuroethics & neuroimaging: moving towards transparency. American Journal of
Bioethics, 8(9), 46–52.
Fins, J.J. (2008b). A leg to stand on: Sir William Osler and Wilder Penfield’s “Neuroethics.” American
Journal of Bioethics, 8(1), 37–46.
Fins, J.J. (2010a). Deep brain stimulation, free markets and the scientific commons: is it time to revisit
the Bayh-Dole Act of 1980? Neuromodulation, 13, 153–159.
Fins, J.J. (2010b). Minds apart: severe brain injury. In: Freeman, M. (Ed.) Law and Neuroscience, Current
Legal Issues (Vol. 13), pp.367–384. New York: Oxford University Press.
Fins, J.J. (2011). Neuroethics and the lure of technology. In: Illes, J. and Sahakian, B.J. (Eds.) Handbook
of Neuroethics, pp.895–908. New York: Oxford University Press.
Fins, J.J. (2012). Deep brain stimulation as a probative biology: scientific inquiry & the mosaic device.
AJOB Neuroscience, 3(1), 4–8.
Fins, J.J. (2013). Disorders of consciousness and disordered care: families, caregivers and narratives of
necessity. Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, 94(10), 1934–1939.
Fins, J.J. (2015). Rights Come to Mind: Brain Injury, Ethics and the Struggle for Consciousness.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Fins, J.J. (2016, May 10) Bring them back. AEON. Available from: https://aeon.co/essays/thousands-of-
patients-diagnosed-as-vegetative-are-actually-aware [accessed 12 July 2016].
612
Fins, J.J. and Hersh, J. (2011). Solitary advocates: the severely brain injured and their surrogates.
In: Hoffman, B., Tomes, N., Schlessinger, M., and Grob, R. (Eds.) Transforming Health Care
from Below: Patients as Actors in U.S. Health Policy, pp.21–42. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers
University Press.
Fins, J.J. and Schiff, N.D. (2010a). Conflicts of interest in deep brain stimulation research and the ethics
of transparency. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 21(2), 125–132.
Fins, J.J. and Schiff, N.D. (2010b). In the blink of the mind’s eye. The Hastings Center Report,
40(3), 21–23.
Fins, J.J. and Shapiro, Z.E. (2013). Deep brain stimulation, brain maps & personalized medicine: lessons
from the human genome project. Brain Topography, 27(1), 55–62.
Fins, J.J., Schlaepfer, T.E., Nuttin, B., et al. (2011a). Ethical guidance for the management of conflicts
of interest for researchers, engineers and clinicians engaged in the development of therapeutic deep
brain stimulation. Journal of Neural Engineering, 8(3), 033001.
Fins, J.J., Mayberg, H.S., Nuttin, B., et al. (2011b). Neuropsychiatric deep brain stimulation research
and the misuse of the humanitarian device exemption. Health Affairs (Millwood), 30(2), 302–311.
Fins, J.J., Dorfman, G.S., and Pancrazio, J.J. (2012). Challenges to deep brain stimulation: a pragmatic
response to ethical, fiscal and regulatory concerns. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences,
1265, 80–90.
Fins, J.J., Pohl, B., and Doukas, D. (2013). In praise of the humanities in academic medicine: values,
metrics and ethics in uncertain times. Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics, 22, 355–364.
Giacino, J.T., Kalmar, K., and Whyte, J. (2004). The JFK Coma Recovery Scale-Revised: measurement
characteristics and diagnostic utility. Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, 85(22),
2020–2029.
Giacino, J.T., Whyte, J., Bagiella, E., et al. (2012). Placebo-controlled trial of amantadine for severe
traumatic brain injury. New England Journal of Medicine, 366(9), 819–826.
Giacino, J.T., Fins, J.J., Laureys, S., and Schiff, N.D. (2014). Disorders of consciousness after acquired
brain injury: the state of the science. Nature Reviews Neurology, 10, 99–114.
Hochberg, L.R., Bacher, D., Jarosiewicz, B., et al. (2012). Reach and grasp by people with tetraplegia
using a neurally controlled robotic arm. Nature, 485(7398), 372–375.
Illes, J. and Sahakian, B.J. (Eds.) (2011). Handbook of Neuroethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jaffe, K.M. and Jimenez, N. (2015). Disparity in rehabilitation: another inconvenient truth. Archives of
Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, 96: 1371–1374.
Kass, L.R. (2003). Foreword. In: President’s Council on Bioethics, Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and
the Pursuit of Happiness, p.xvii. New York: Harper Perennial.
The MacArthur Foundation Research Network on Law and Neuroscience (n.d.). Available at: http://
www.lawneuro.org [accessed July 11, 2016].
Mandela, N. (1994). Long Walk to Freedom. New York: Little, Brown and Company.
Mayberg, H.S., Lozano, A.M., Voon, V., et al. (2005). Deep brain stimulation for treatment-resistant
depression. Neuron, 45(5), 651–660.
McGowan, A.K., Lee, M.M., Meneses, C.M., Perkins, J., and Youdelman, M. (2016). Civil rights laws as
tools to advance health in the 21st century. Annual Review of Public Health, 37, 185–204.
Mokhtarzadeh, M., Eydelman, M. and Chen, E. (2016). Challenges and opportunities when developing
devices for rare disease populations. Expert Opinion on Orphan Drugs, 4(5), 457–459.
Monti, M.M., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Coleman, M.R., et al. (2010). Willful modulation of brain activity
in disorders of consciousness. New England Journal of Medicine, 362(7), 579–589.
613
References 613
Moss, C.W., Kilgore, K.L., Peckham, P.H. (2011). Training to improve volitional muscle activity in
clinically paralyzed muscles for neuroprosthesis control. Conference Proceedings of the Annual
International Conference of the IEEE Engineering in Medicine and Biology Society, 2011, 5794–5797.
Naccache, L. (2006). Is she conscious? Science, 313(5792), 1395–1396.
National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research
(1977). Use of psychosurgery in practice and research: report and recommendations of National
Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Federal
Register, 42(99), 26318–26332.
Nicolelis, M.A. (2012). Mind in motion. Scientific American, 307(3), 58–63.
Nuttin, B., Cosyns, P., Demeulemeester, H., Gybels, J., and Meyerson, B. (1999). Electrical stimulation
in anterior limbs of internal capsules in patients with obsessive-compulsive disorder. The Lancet,
354(9189), 1526.
Orphan Drug Act of 1983. Public Law 97–414. 96 Stat. 2049 (1983).
Osler, W. (1919). The Old Humanities and the New Science: An Address before the Classical Association,
Oxford. London: John Murray.
Owen, A.M., Coleman, M.R., Boly, M., et al. (2006). Willful modulation of brain activity in disorders of
consciousness. Detecting awareness in the vegetative state. Science, 313(5792), 1402.
Penfield, W. (1976). Mystery of the Mind: A Critical Study of Consciousness and the Human Brain.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rothman, D. (1971). The Discovery of the Asylum: Social Order and Disorder in the New Republic.
New York: Little Brown.
Satcher, D. (2000). Executive summary: a report of the surgeon general on mental health. Public Health
Reports, 115(1), 89–101.
Schiff, N.D., Rodriguez-Moreno, D., Kamal, A., et al. (2005). fMRI reveals large scale network
activation in minimally conscious patients. Neurology, 64, 514–523.
Schiff, N.D., Giacino, J.T., Kalmar, K., et al. (2007). Behavioral improvements with thalamic stimulation
after severe traumatic brain injury. Nature, 448(7153), 600–603.
Schiff, N.D., Giacino, J.T., and Fins, J.J. (2009). Deep brain stimulation, neuroethics and the minimally
conscious state: moving beyond proof of principle. Archives of Neurology, 66(6), 697–702.
Sheff, D. (1988, January 19). Izzy, did you ask a good question today? The New York Times. Available
from: http://www.nytimes.com/1988/01/19/opinion/l-izzy-did-you-ask-a-good-question-today-
712388.html [accessed July 12, 2016].
Thomas, L. (1974). The Lives of a Cell: Notes of a Biology Watcher. New York: The Viking Press.
UN General Assembly (2007). Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities. Available
from: http://www.un.org/disabilities/convention/conventionfull.shtml [accessed July 12, 2016].
Wright, M.S. and Fins, J.J. (2016). Rehabilitation, education, and the integration of individuals with
severe brain injury into civil society: towards an expanded rights agenda in response to new insights
from translational neuroethics and neuroscience. Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law, and Ethics,
16(2), 233–288.
614
615
Author Index
616 Author Index
Author Index 617
618 Author Index
Author Index 619
620 Author Index
Author Index 621
622 Author Index
Author Index 623
624 Author Index
Author Index 625
626 Author Index
Author Index 627
628 Author Index
Schweitzer, P. 460 Slote, M. 440
Schweser, F. 16 Small, G. 432
Scialabba, G. 119 Smith, C.F. 99
Sclove, R. 9 Smith, E.E. 55
Scott, D.J. 222 Smith, K. 395
Scullard, P. 557 Smith, K.R. 427, 580
Searle, J.R. 321 Smith, M.E. 413
Secen, J. 19 Smith, P.B. 393
See, R.E. 498, 499 Smith, S. 136
Seel, R.T. 127 Smith, S.M. 38, 153
Seeley, W.W. 289, 290 Smylie, J. 462
Seeman, T.E. 435 Snow, C.P. 8
Sekihara, K. 31 Snyder, J. 269, 270
Selemon, L.D. 165 Snyder, J.V. 354
Seligman, M.E.P. 404 Soekadar, S.R. 123, 124, 125, 126, 127
Selkoe, D.J. 297, 300 Soloveichik, A. 359
Selters, W.A. 31 Song, T.M. 558
Sen, A. 438 Souren, L. 283
Sénécal, K. 5, 6 Sowell, E.R. 165
Shadlen, M.N. 480, 491 Spearman, C. 20
Shafer, J.P. 37 Spellecy, R. 378
Shah, N.J. 17 Spiegel, D.P. 19
Shah, S.K. 325, 342 Spike, J. 343
Shaham, Y. 487 Spiro, H.M. 223
Shanker, T. 535 Spitzer, R.L. 594
Shanks, D.R. 222 Sporns, O. 20, 33
Shanks, T. 127 Sproul, A.A. 6
Shapiro, J.R. 504 Squire, L.R. 282
Shaw, D.L. 265 Stables, J. 84
Shaw, R.J. 561 Stam, C.J. 26, 32
Sheff, D. 605 Stanbury, W.T. 456
Shelton, J.F. 429 Stanford Medicine 91
Shen, F.X. 115, 116 Stanley, S.A. 149
Sherman, R. 215, 216, 218, 225 Stanovich, K.E. 109
Sherwin, E. 397 Starling, R.M. 181
Shewmon, A. 346, 347, 348, 353 Stedman, R.C. 431
Shewmon, D. 315, 353 Steel, D. 446
Shewmon, E. 346, 348 Stein, D.J. 591–614
Shih, J.J. 123, 428 Stein, L.D. 369
Shirkey, H. 377 Steinsbekk, K.S. 62
Shively, S. 516 Stejskal, E.O. 38
Shonkoff, J.P. 172, 435 Stemmer, B. 463
Shook, J. 538, 594, 595 Stephan, B.C.M. 55
Shores, E.A. 516 Steriade, M. 333
Shrader-Frechette, K.S. 426, 438, 439, 441, 442, 446 Stevenson, S. 464
Silberg, W.M. 560 Stewart, P.W. 430
Silove, D. 594 Stewart-Williams, S. 222
Silvers, A. 135 Stilgoe, J. 266
Sime, W.E. 84 Stins, J.F. 328
Simeral, J.D. 537 Stockard, J.J. 31
Siminoff, L.A. 357 Stolier, R.M. 480
Singer, T. 200 Stolyar, N. 392
Singh, I. 384 Stout, R. 460
Singh, V. 17 St Philip, E. 268
Siu, A.L. 93 Strategic Multilayer Assessment Group 534
Sivashanker, K. 72 Strauss, J.S. 593
Sjögren, M.J.C. 127 Strawson, P.F. 402
Skloot, R. 5, 7 Sturm, V.E. 290
Skuban, T. 250 Stutzman, F. 117
Slaughter, L.M. 153 Sudlow, C. 55
Slimak, M.W. 446 Sudo, N. 397
629
Author Index 629
630 Author Index
Author Index 631
Subject Index
ablative microsurgical procedures see neurosurgery, preclinical Alzheimer’s disease diagnosis 294–304
ablative microsurgical procedures preventive clinical trials 301–3
addiction self-assessments 562
animal models of 483, 498–9 see also dementia, demented patients
high rates of recovery 501 amblyopia
concept, describing other compulsive event-related, parametric fMRI 18–19
behaviors 578–80 localizing neuropathology 18–19
drugs Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA) 577
abnormal dopamine signal 485 amphetamines, enhancement therapy 535
advantage over natural rewards 485–6 amyloid-related imaging abnormalities
dependency and 578–9 (ARIAs) 302
individual differences in liability and risk of amyloidosis
drug use 480–2 antiamyloid drugs 300, 302
gambling, neurobiology claimed/adopted in legal beta-amyloid protein 22, 295–8
context 579, 580–2 clinical trials, monoclonal antibodies 295
impaired agency 491–2 analytic framework sharing 8–11, 10t
medical model see brain disease model of anorexia nervosa
addiction (BDMA) ablative procedures 243
moral model 477, 489, 490, 491, 492, 509 deep brain stimulation (DBS) 242
nicotine 582–5 anterior limb of the internal capsule (ALIC) 242
persistence of relapse risk 487–8 antiamyloid drugs 300, 302
public views of addiction, stigma, and antiviral drugs, compassionate access 266
discrimination 503–4 Apple, Health Kit 81
punishment and 490, 492 arsenic intoxication 428
scientific model 477–93 arterial spin labeling, estimates of cerebral blood flow
implications for moral responsibility and legal rates 16
culpability 490–1 attention deficit hyperactivity disorder 167
implications for understanding placebo therapy 226–7
behavior 488–90 attribution theory 576, 578
see also brain disease model of addiction (BDMA) auditory brain stem implants, speech
adolescents recognition 127
consent issues 73 auditory brainstem response (ABR) 30–1
social media, cyberbullying 70–9 auditory event-related potentials 30–2
vulnerability and homelessness 70–9 auditory steady-state response (ASSR) 30–1
advance directives 258 AugCog (augmented cognition) 537
aging, advice in a digital world 558 autism, gut dysfunction 397
air and water pollution 430 autism spectrum disorders and social media 73–4
Albertan tar sands projects 458, see also First autonomy
Nations Canada constrained parental autonomy 170
alpha-synuclein, Parkinson’s disease 23 deception of placebo therapy 225–7
alpha-theta-gamma (ATG) switch, thalamocortical definition 407
processing 41 demented patients 284–9
Alzheimer’s disease ethics of deep brain stimulation (DBS) 250
antiamyloid drugs and amyloid-related imaging extended mind hypothesis (EMH) 112–15, 124
abnormalities 300, 302 free moral agency and 392
case study 275 free will 169
competing theoretical perspectives 275–6 microbiome research and 398
costs of care, US 144 notes 291–2
genetic risk 302 personality-changing interventions 251
hippocampal function 289–91 standard model 399
634
634 Subject Index
Subject Index 635
636 Subject Index
Subject Index 637
638 Subject Index
Subject Index 639
640 Subject Index
Subject Index 641
642 Subject Index
Subject Index 643
UN Office of the High Commissioner 374t vulnerability, youth, and homelessness 70–9
UN Principles for Older Persons 380t
UN Second World Assembly on Ageing 380t water pollution 430
UNESCO Declaration on Bioethics and Human wearable and mobile health technology 80–107
Rights 372t, 378 authentic living 98–100
unresponsive wakefulness syndrome 185 case study: mental health apps 92–7
urban pollution 430 classifications 82–7
US Department of Health & Human Services 5 consent 90–1
US National Institute on Drug Abuse (NIDA) 497 democratization of healthcare 91–2
US National Institutes of Health BRAIN see BRAIN ethical considerations 87–92
Initiative® (US National Institutes of Health) examples 81
functionalities 84–6
vaccination, Pasteur, Louis and 555 privacy and confidentiality 88–90
value purposes 82–3
capacity to 276–8 usage profiles 86–7
understanding values 279–84 see also brain–computer interface (BCI) medicine
vegetative state (unresponsive wakefulness westernized, educated, industrialized, rich, and
syndrome) 185, 309–10 democratic (WEIRD) populations 596
vestibular schwannomas (aka acoustic neuromas) 31 white coat trance 204
volitional control 392, 491, 495 whole genome sequencing 4–5
brain–computer interface (BCI) medicine wholism 333
and 126 World Medical Association (WMA), vulnerable
conscious vs free and determined 394, 401, 405 individuals, research 371t, 373
escaped 477, 480 worried well 593
minimally conscious state (MCS) and 318
neural basis 394 youth homelessness 76–9
64
645
64
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654